Burgess Math Model Modality
Burgess Math Model Modality
Burgess Math Model Modality
John Burgess is the author of a rich and creative body of work which
seeks to defend classical logic and mathematics through counter-
criticism of their nominalist, intuitionist, relevantist, and other critics.
This selection of his essays, which spans twenty-five years, addresses
key topics including nominalism, neo-logicism, intuitionism, modal
logic, analyticity, and translation. An introduction sets the essays in
context and offers a retrospective appraisal of their aims. The volume
will be of interest to a wide range of readers across philosophy of
mathematics, logic, and philosophy of language.
JOHN P. BURGESS
CAMBRIDGE UNIVERSITY PRESS
Cambridge, New York, Melbourne, Madrid, Cape Town, Singapore, São Paulo
Cambridge University Press has no responsibility for the persistence or accuracy of urls
for external or third-party internet websites referred to in this publication, and does not
guarantee that any content on such websites is, or will remain, accurate or appropriate.
Dedicated to the memory of my sister
Barbara Kathryn Burgess
Contents
Preface page ix
Source notes xi
Introduction 1
PART I MATHEMATICS 21
1 Numbers and ideas 23
2 Why I am not a nominalist 31
3 Mathematics and Bleak House 46
4 Quine, analyticity, and philosophy of mathematics 66
5 Being explained away 85
6 E pluribus unum: plural logic and set theory 104
7 Logicism: a new look 135
vii
viii Contents
12 Translating names 236
13 Relevance: a fallacy? 246
14 Dummett’s case for intuitionism 256
‘‘Numbers and ideas’’ was first delivered orally as part of a public debate at
the University of Richmond (Virginia), 1999. Ruben Hersh argued for the
thesis ‘‘Resolved: that mathematical entities and objects exist within the
world of shared human thoughts and concepts.’’ I argued against. It was
first published in a journal for undergraduates edited at the University
of Richmond (England), the Richmond Journal of Philosophy, volume 1
(2003), pp. 12–17. (There is no institutional connection between the
universities of the two Richmonds, and my involvement with both is
sheer coincidence.)
‘‘Why I am not a nominalist’’ was first delivered orally under the title
‘‘The nominalist’s dilemma,’’ to the Logic Club, Catholic University of
Nijmegen, 1981. It was first published in the Notre Dame Journal of Formal
Logic, volume 24 (1983), pp. 93–105.
‘‘Mathematics and Bleak House’’ was first delivered orally at a sympo-
sium ‘‘Realism and anti-realism’’ at the Association for Symbolic Logic
meeting, University of California at San Diego, 1999. The other symposiast
was my former student Penelope Maddy, and the Dickensian title of my
paper is intended to recall the Dickensian title of her earlier review,
‘‘Mathematics and Oliver Twist’’ (Maddy 1990). First published in
Philosophia Mathematica, volume 12 (2004), pp. 18–36.
‘‘Quine, analyticity, and philosophy of mathematics’’ was first delivered
orally at the conference ‘‘Does Mathematics Require a Foundation?,’’
Arché Institute, University of St. Andrews, 2002. Identified in its text as
a sequel to the preceding item, this paper circulated in pre-publication
draft under the title ‘‘Mathematics and Bleak House, II.’’ First published in
the Philosophical Quarterly, volume 54 (2004), pp. 38–55.
‘‘Being explained away’’ is a shortened version (omitting digressions on
technical matters) of a paper delivered orally to the Department of
Philosophy, University of Southern California, 2004. (I wish not only to
thank that department for the invitation to speak, but especially to thank
xi
xii Source notes
Stephen Finlay, Jeff King, Zlatan Damnjanovic, and above all Scott
Soames for their comments and questions, as well as for their hospitality
during my visit.) It was first published in the Harvard Review of Philosophy,
volume 13 (2005), pp. 41–56.
‘‘E pluribus unum’’ evolved from a paper ‘‘From Frege to Friedman’’
delivered orally at the Logic Colloquium of the University of
Pennsylvania and the Department of Logic and Philosophy of Science
at the University of California at Irvine. It was first published in
Philosophia Mathematica, volume 12 (2004), pp. 193–221. (I am grateful
to Harvey Friedman for introducing me to his recent work on reflection
principles, to Kai Wehmeier and Sol Feferman for drawing my attention
to the earlier work of Bernays on that topic, and to Penelope Maddy for
pressing the question of the proper model theory for plural logic, which
led me back to the writings of George Boolos on this issue. From
Feferman I also received valuable comments leading to what I hope is
an improved exposition.)
‘‘Logicism: a new look’’ was first delivered orally at the conference
marking the inauguration of the UCLA Logic Center, and later (under a
different title) as part of the annual lecture series of the Center for
Philosophy of Science, University of Pittsburgh, both in 2003. It has not
previously been published.
‘‘Tarski’s tort’’ was first delivered orally at Timothy Bays’ seminar on
truth, Notre Dame University, Saint Patrick’s Day, 2005. It was previously
unpublished. The paper should be understood as dedicated to my teacher
Arnold E. Ross, mentioned in its opening paragraphs.
‘‘Which modal logic is the right one?’’ was first delivered orally at the
George Boolos Memorial Conference, University of Notre Dame, 1998. It
was first published in the Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic, volume 40
(1999), pp. 81–93, as part of a special issue devoted to the proceedings of
that conference. Like all the conference papers, mine was dedicated to the
memory of George Boolos.
‘‘Can truth out?’’ was first delivered orally under the title ‘‘Fitch’s para-
dox of knowability’’ as a keynote talk at the annual Princeton–Rutgers
Graduate Student Conference in Philosophy, 2003. It was first published
in Joseph Salerno, ed., New Essays on Knowability, Oxford: Oxford
University Press (2007). The paper originally bore the epigraph ‘‘Truth
will come to light; murder cannot be hid long; a man’s son may, but at the
length truth will out’’ (Merchant of Venice II: 2). Thanks are due to Michael
Fara, Helge Rückert, and Timothy Williamson for perceptive comments
on earlier drafts of this note.
Source notes xiii
‘‘Quinus ab omni naevo vindicatus’’ was first delivered orally to the
Department of Philosophy, MIT, 1997. It was first published in Ali
Kazmi, ed., Meaning and Reference, Canadian Journal of Philosophy
Supplement, volume 23 (1998), pp. 25–65. (The present paper is a com-
pletely rewritten version of an unpublished paper, ‘‘The varied sorrows of
modality, part II.’’ I am indebted to several colleagues for information used
in writing that paper, and for advice given on it once written, and I would
like to thank them all – Gil Harman, Dick Jeffrey, David Lewis – even if
the portions of the paper with which some of them were most helpful have
disappeared from the final version. But I would especially like to thank
Scott Soames, who was most helpful with the portions that have not
disappeared.)
‘‘Translating names’’ was first published in Analysis, volume 65 (2005),
pp. 96–204. I am grateful to Pierre Bouchard and Paul Égré for linguistic
information and advice.
‘‘Relevance: a fallacy?’’ was first published in the Notre Dame Journal of
Formal Logic, volume 22 (1981), pp. 76–84. Its sequels were Burgess (1983c)
and Burgess (1984b).
‘‘Dummett’s case for intuitionism’’ was first published in History and
Philosophy of Logic, volume 5 (1984), pp. 177–194. The paper originally bore
the epigraph from Chairman Mao ‘‘Combat Revisionism!’’ I am indebted
to several colleagues and students for comments, and especially to Gil
Harman, who made an earlier draft of this paper the topic for discussion at
one session of his summer seminar. Comments by editors and referees led
to what it is hoped are clearer formulations of many points.
Introduction
ABOUT ‘‘ R E A L I S M ’’
A word on terminology may be useful at the outset, since it is pertinent
to many of the papers in this collection, beginning with the very first.
The label ‘‘realism’’ is used in two very different ways in two very different
debates in contemporary philosophy of mathematics. For nominalists,
‘‘realism’’ means acceptance that there exist entities, for instance natural
or rational or real numbers, that lack spatiotemporal location and do not
causally interact with us. For neo-intuitionists, ‘‘realism’’ means acceptance
that statements such as the twin primes conjecture may be true independ-
ently of any human ability to verify them. For the former the question of
‘‘realism’’ is ontological, for the latter it is semantico-epistemological. Since
the concerns of nominalists and of neo-intuitionists are orthogonal, the
double usage of ‘‘realism’’ affords ample opportunity for confusion.
The arch-nominalists Charles Chihara and Hartry Field, for instance,
are anti-intuitionists and ‘‘realists’’ in the neo-intuitionists’ sense. They do
not believe there are any unverifiable truths about numbers, since they do
not believe there are any numbers for unverifiable truths to be about. But
they do believe that the facts about the possible production of linguistic
expressions, or about proportionalities among physical quantities, which in
their reconstructions replace facts about numbers, can obtain independ-
ently of any ability of ours to verify that they do so. Michael Dummett, the
founder of neo-intuitionism, was an early and forceful anti-nominalist, and
though he calls his position ‘‘anti-realism,’’ he and his followers are ‘‘real-
ists’’ in the nominalists’ sense, accepting some though not all classical
existence theorems, namely those that have constructive proofs, and agree-
ing that it is a category mistake to apply spatiotemporal or causal predicates
to mathematical subjects.
On top of all this, even among those of us who are ‘‘realists’’ in both
senses there are important differences. Metaphysical realists suppose, like
1
2 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
Galileo and Kepler and Descartes and other seventeenth-century worthies,
that it is possible to get behind all human representations to a God’s-eye
view of ultimate reality as it is in itself. When they affirm that mathematical
objects transcending space and time and causality exist, and mathematical
truths transcending human verification obtain, they are affirming that such
objects exist and such truths obtain as part of ultimate metaphysical reality
(whatever that means). Naturalist realists, by contrast, affirm only (what
even some self-described anti-realists concede) that the existence of such
objects and obtaining of such truths is an implication or presupposition of
science and scientifically informed common sense, while denying that
philosophy has any access to exterior, ulterior, and superior sources of
knowledge from which to ‘‘correct’’ science and scientifically informed
common sense. The naturalized philosopher, in contrast to the alienated
philosopher, is one who takes a stand as a citizen of the scientific com-
munity, and not a foreigner to it, and hence is prepared to reaffirm while
doing philosophy whatever was affirmed while doing science, and to
acknowledge its evident implications and presuppositions; but only the
metaphysical philosopher takes the status of what is affirmed while doing
philosophy to be a revelation of an ultimate metaphysical reality, rather
than a human representation that is the way it is in part because a reality
outside us is the way it is, and in part because we are the way we are.
My preferred label for my own position would now be ‘‘naturalism,’’ but
in the papers in this collection, beginning with the first, ‘‘realism’’ often
appears. Were I rewriting, I might erase the R-word wherever it occurs; but
as I said in the preface above, I do not believe in rewriting when reprinting,
so while in date of composition the papers reproduced here span more than
twenty years, still I have left even the oldest, apart from the correction of
typographical errors, just as I wrote them. Quod scripsi, scripsi.
This collection begins with five items each pertinent in one way or
another to nominalism and the problem of the existence of abstract entities.
The term ‘‘realism’’ is used in an ontological sense in the first of these,
‘‘Numbers and ideas’’ (2003). This paper is a curtain-raiser, a lighter piece
responding to certain professional mathematicians turned amateur philo-
sophers who propose a cheap and easy solutions to the problem. According
to their proposed compromise, numbers exist, but only ‘‘in the world of
ideas.’’ Since acceptance of this position would render most of the profes-
sional literature on the topic irrelevant, and since the amateurs often offer
unflattering accounts of what they imagine to be the reasons why profes-
sionals do not accept their simple proposal, I thought it worthwhile to
accept an invitation to try to state, for a general audience, our real reasons,
Introduction 3
which go back to Frege. The distinction insisted upon in this paper,
between the kind of thing it makes sense to say about a number and the
kind of thing it makes sense to say about a mental representation of a
number (and the distinction, which exactly parallels that between the two
senses of ‘‘history,’’ between mathematics, the science, and mathematics, its
subject matter) is presupposed throughout the papers to follow.
Some may wonder where my emphatic rejection of ‘‘idealism or con-
ceptualism’’ in this paper leaves intuitionism. The short answer is that I
leave intuitionism entirely out of account: I am concerned in this paper with
descriptions of the mathematics we have, not prescriptions to replace it with
something else. Intuitionism is orthogonal to nominalism, as I have said,
and issues about it are set aside in the first part of this collection. I will add
that, though I do not address the matter in the works reprinted here, my
opinion is that Frege’s anti-psychologistic and anti-mentalistic points raise
some serious difficulties for Brouwer’s original version of intuitionism, but
no difficulties at all for Dummett’s revised version. Neither opinion should
be controversial. Dummett’s producing a version immune to Fregean
criticism can hardly surprise, given that the founder of neo-intuitionism
is also the dean of contemporary Frege studies. That Brouwer’s version, by
contrast, faces serious problems was conceded even by so loyal a disciple as
Heyting, and all the more so by contemporary neo-intuitionists.
But notion of class brings with it difficulties of its own, leaving many
hesitant to admit these alleged entities.
The suggestion of Boolos (in my own notation) was to replace singular
quantification 8U or ‘‘for any class U of sets . . .’’ over classes by plural
quantification 88uu or ‘‘for any sets, the u’s . . .’’ and Uz or ‘‘z is a member
of U’’ by z / uu or ‘‘z is one of the u’s,’’ thus yielding a formulation in
which the only objects quantified over are sets:
One may even take a further step and make the notion x uu or ‘‘x is the
set of the u’s’’ primitive, with the notion y 2 x or ‘‘y is an element of x’’ being
defined in terms of it, as 99uu(x x uu & y / uu) or ‘‘there are some things
that x is the set of, and y is one of them.’’ Such a step was actually taken in
a paper by Stephen Pollard (1996) some years before my own, of which
I only belated became aware, along with Shapiro (1987) and Rayo and
Uzquiano (1999).
The idea taken from Bernays was that an approach incorporating a
so-called reflection principle can provide a simpler axiomatization than
the standard approach to motivating the axioms of ZFC, and permit the
derivation of some further so-called large-cardinal principles that are
widely accepted by set theorists, though they go beyond ZFC. The original
Bernays approach had the disadvantage of involving ‘‘classes’’ over and
above sets, and of requiring a somewhat artificial technical condition in the
formulation of the reflection principle. Boolos’s plural logic was subject to
the objection that, like any version or variant of second-order logic, it lacks
a complete axiomatization. I aim to show how the combination of Boolos
with Bernays neutralizes these objections.
10 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
9X 8xðXx $ fðxÞÞ
8X 8Y ð8zðXz $ YzÞ ! ðfðX Þ $ fðY ÞÞÞ
8X 8Y ðX ¼ Y $ 8zðXz $ YzÞÞ:
Russell showed that a paradox arises in this system, and also introduced the
idea of imposing a restriction of predicativity on the comprehension axiom,
assuming it only for formulas f(x) without bound class variables. Russell
proposed a great many other changes, and his overall system diverged greatly
from Frege’s. Heck was the first to consider closely what would happen if one
made only the one change just described, and he showed that the resulting
system, though weak (and in particular consistent) is strong enough for the
minimal arithmetic embodied in the system known in the literature as Q to
be developed in it. So a bare minimum of mathematics can be developed on
a predicative logicist basis in the manner of Frege. (More technical details as
to what can be accomplished along these lines are provided in my book
Fixing Frege (Burgess 2005b). Since the book and the paper were written
there have been important advances by Mihai Ganea and Albert Visser.)
Introduction 11
Russell’s version of logicism was opposed by Brouwer’s intuitionism and
also by Hilbert’s formalism. The latter was consciously modeled on instru-
mentalist philosophies of physics, according to which physical theory is a
giant instrument for deriving empirical predictions, though theoretical
terms and laws in physics in general do not admit direct empirical defi-
nitions or meaning. Hilbert’s philosophy of mathematics can be repre-
sented by a simple proportion:
computational : mathematics :: empirical : physics.
The connection between the Jeffrey idea and the Heck idea is that
predicative logicism provides enough mathematics to connect the basic
computational facts that figure in the Hilbert proportion with the logical
facts that figure in the Jeffrey proportion. So, though predicativist logicism
falls far short of the whole of mathematics it would be possible to regard it
as providing the data for mathematics.
The question I raise about all this is whether the engine is doing any real
work: do sophisticated mathematical theories (such as standard Zermelo–
Frankel set theory or the proposed Boolos–Bernays set theory) actually
make available any more logical ‘‘predictions’’ in the way sophisticated
theories in physics make available more empirical predictions? I show how
(and in what sense) certain results of Julia Robinson and Yuri Matiyasevich
in mathematical logic yield an affirmative answer to this question. (More
technical details are provided in a forthcoming paper ‘‘Protocol Sentences
for Lite Logicism.’’)
12 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
Logical necessity was originally what modal logicians had generally meant
the box symbol to represent, and I believe that Quine was entirely correct
in asserting that with that understanding of the symbol, quantifying into
modal contexts makes no sense. Quine’s complaint was that to make non-
trivial sense of 9x&Fx one must make sense of so-called de re modality, of
the notion of an open sentence Fx being necessarily true of a thing, and this
is impossible (or at any rate, has not been done by the proponents of
quantified modal logic) if ‘‘necessarily true’’ is to mean ‘‘true by virtue of
meaning.’’ For a thing, as opposed to an expression denoting a thing, has
not got a meaning for anything to be true by virtue of. Truth by virtue of
meaning is an inherently de dicto notion, applicable to closed sentences.
Quine underscored his point by illustrating the difficulty of reducing de re
to de dicto modality. One can’t say &Fx is true of the object b if and only
if &Ft is true, where t is a term denoting b, because &Ft may be true for
some terms denoting the object and false for other terms denoting the
same object.
The early response of modal logicians to Quine’s critique, by which
I mean the responses prior to Kripke’s ‘‘Naming and necessity’’ (1972),
involved an appeal, not to a distinction between metaphysical and logical
modality, but rather to (purely formal ‘‘semantics’’ and/or to) the magical
properties of Russellian logically proper names. In simplest terms, the
‘‘solution’’ would be that &Fx is true of b if and only if &Fn is true,
where n is a ‘‘name’’ of b, it being assumed that if &Fn is true for one
name it will be true for all. I believe this line of response is a total failure,
Introduction 15
and anyone acquainted with the views of Mill ought to have been aware
that it must fail. For it will be recalled that Mill, before Russell, held that
a name has only a denotation, not a connotation. He also held, like the modal
logicians who identified & with truth by virtue of meaning, that all necessity
is verbal necessity, deriving from relations among the connotations of
words. What those responding to Quine ought to have remembered is
that, having committed himself to those two views, he inevitably found
himself committed to a third view, that there are no individual essences: ‘‘all
Gs are Fs’’ may be necessarily true because being an F may be part of the
connotation of G, but ‘‘n is an F ’’ cannot be necessarily true, because n has
no connotation for being an F to be part of. Positing Millian/Russellian
‘‘names’’ may permit the reduction of de re to de dicto modality, where the
relevant dicta involve such names, but only at the cost of depriving de dicto
modality, where again the dicta involve such names, of any sense – so long
as one continues to read & as truth by virtue of meaning.
What is now the fashionable view evaluates the early responses to Quine
much more positively than I do, when it does not outright read Kripke’s
ideas back into earlier texts. That Quine was right as against his early critics
is the view that I, going against fashion, defend in ‘‘Quinus ab omni naevo
vindicatus’’ (1998). The origin of the curious title is explained in the article.
Closely linked with the issue of metaphysical versus logical necessity is
the question of the status of identities linking proper names, as in
‘‘Hesperus is Phosphorus.’’ This question has been the topic of an immense
body of literature in philosophy of language. Like Kripke, I on the one
hand reject descriptivist theories of proper names, but on the other hand
equally reject ‘‘direct reference’’ theories. I am attracted to a third view
based on distinguishing two senses of ‘‘sense,’’ mode of presentation versus
descriptive content, a view rather tentatively (and certainly non-polemically)
put forward in connection with Kripke’s Puzzling Pierre problem in
‘‘Translating names’’ (2005).
But returning for a moment to ‘‘Quinus,’’ since some readers like nothing
better than polemics between academics, and others like nothing less, all
potential readers should be informed in advance that ‘‘Quinus’’ is as polem-
ical as anything I have ever written (though much of the polemic is relegated
to footnotes), and several degrees more so than anything else in this collec-
tion. Even the explanation why the paper is polemical must itself inevitably
be somewhat polemical, and so I will relegate it to a parenthetical paragraph
which those averse to polemics may skip, along with the paper itself.
(My paper is explicitly a response to a paper by Ruth Barcan Marcus
from the early 1960s, but it is also implicitly a response to a widely
16 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
circulated letter by the same writer from the middle 1980s, discussed in the
editorial introduction to Humphreys and Fetzer (1998). This letter is the
original source for the claim that Kripke’s ideas were taken without
acknowledgment from the early Marcus paper. The response to such
allegations is that Kripke could not have stolen his ideas from the indicated
source, since neither those important and original contributions nor any
others were present there to be plagiarized. In my paper I do not mince
words in presenting this defense. Marcus’s insinuations are more directly
addressed in my paper (Burgess 1996). The contents of her letter, with
elaborations but without acknowledgment of that letter as a source, reap-
pear in the work of one of its many recipients, Quentin Smith. His version
is addressed in my paper (Burgess 1998a).)
Mathematics
1
1 REALISM VS NOMINALISM
1
The classical expression of the anthropological view is that of White (1947). For a recent endorsement by
a mathematician, see Hersh (1997), a book that makes a professional philosopher’s hair stand on end.
Numbers and ideas 25
Conceptualist and idealist views, however, were subjected along with
other nineteenth-century views to a scathing critique by the late nineteenth-
century German mathematician and philosopher Gottlob Frege.2 Largely as
a result of that critique, the anthropological view today has virtually no
adherents among professional academic philosophers. Its rejection is one of
the rare cases of general agreement and consensus on an issue in philosophy.
Precisely because there is such general agreement, philosophers seldom
stop to explain, in language more modern than Frege’s, just what is wrong
with the view that so many anthropologists, sociologists, psychologists,
mathematics educators, and even mathematicians have found attractive. It
is this task of explanation that I will be undertaking in the present essay,
using an example of a kind that definitely would not have been used by Frege.
2 BIGFOOT
Let us begin by considering the proposition that Bigfoot, also known as the
Sasquatch – a cousin of the Abominable Snowman or Yeti – exists in the
realm of shared human ideas and concepts. Now certainly there is some-
thing in the neighborhood that exists in the realm of shared human ideas
and concepts, namely, the shared human idea or concept of Bigfoot. This is
the idea of a large, hairy, humanoid creature inhabiting the wilder parts of
the Pacific Northwest, from northern California to British Columbia.
There are even people who claim to have sighted individual Bigfeet, and
to have formed ideas of these individuals, even to the point of giving them
names like ‘‘Harry’’ or ‘‘Harriet.’’ The idea of an individual Bigfoot
includes the traits that are common to all Bigfeet according to the general
idea of Bigfoot, but also more specific elements: for instance, Harry is male
and Harriet is female. These ideas of individual Bigfeet are less widely
shared than the idea of the species, but we may suppose they are at least
shared among members of the International Society for Cryptozoology,
who take a special interest in such things.
The majority view among zoologists is that there do not, in fact, exist any
large, hairy, humanoid creatures, and that the alleged sightings of Harry,
Harriet, and other individual Bigfeet were either illusions or hoaxes. But I ask
you to join me in assuming, just for the moment, that the majority is wrong,
and that creatures of the kind indicated, including Harry and Harriet, do
exist. On this assumption, I will argue, two things should be clear.
2
See Frege (1884), English translation by Austin (1960). The critical portions (the part of the book
relevant to the present essay) are reprinted in Benacerraf and Putnam (1983).
26 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
The first is that Harry, Harriet, and other large, hairy, humanoid
creatures inhabiting the wilder parts of the Pacific Northwest are very
different sorts of things from shared human ideas and concepts, and in
particular are very different sorts of things from the ideas and concepts of
Harry, of Harriet, and of Bigfoot in general. They differ in absolutely
fundamental respects, for instance, in their location in space and time.
Let us consider space, for instance. (Similar considerations would apply
to time.) It is not clear whether or where a shared human idea or concept
should be thought of as located in space, but presumably if it is located
anywhere, it is located where the human beings who share it are located.
Thus if the International Society for Cryptozoology holds its annual
convention on the banks of Loch Ness, the idea of Bigfoot in general,
and the ideas of Harry and Harriet in particular, are located mainly in
Scotland. Harry, Harriet, and the rest of their kind, however, are still
located in Washington or Oregon or thereabouts. The creatures cannot
be the ideas, because the two are located in different places.
The creatures differ from the ideas also in respect of how many of them
there are. People have ideas of Harry, Harriet, and several more Bigfeet that
have allegedly come into contact with human beings; but there are supposed to
be, according to the minority view I have asked you to assume for the moment,
more Bigfeet than just these: more individuals like Harry and Harriet than
there are shared human ideas of individual Bigfeet. So again the creatures
cannot be the ideas, since there are more of the former than of the latter.
A second point I hope will be clear is that it is the flesh-and-blood
creatures, not the ideas, that are the Bigfeet. The term ‘‘Bigfoot’’ refers to
the inhabitants of the wilds of Washington and Oregon, not to the contents
of the minds or brains of the cryptozoologists assembled in Scotland. If we
wish to refer to the latter, we must use some other expression than the word
‘‘Bigfoot,’’ such as the phrase ‘‘the idea of Bigfoot.’’
In short, on the minority view, according to which the flesh-and-blood
creatures do exist, the following is the case: Bigfeet, being flesh-and-blood
creatures, are not ideas, and are more numerous than the ideas of them and
located in a different place from those ideas.
3 NUMBERS
Are things any different on the majority view? It is when one assumes that
there are no such flesh-and-blood creatures that some are tempted to say
that the Bigfoot in general, or Harry and Harriet in particular, are human
ideas. I think this temptation should be rejected.
Numbers and ideas 27
Let me say straightaway that it would be pointless to object to someone
expressing disbelief in Bigfoot by saying, ‘‘Bigfoot exists only in the imagina-
tion of the credulous,’’ or something of the sort. Someone might well say this –
I might well say it myself, for that matter, when not talking philosophy – and
mean it only as a manner of speaking, as a way of saying ‘‘Bigfoot doesn’t exist
at all, though some credulous persons imagine that it does.’’ The proposition I
want to consider, however, is that Bigfoot literally does exist, but only in the
realm of shared human ideas and concepts, where, according to the anthro-
pological view, numbers also have their being.
To indicate the reasons why I reject this proposition, suppose the
population of some endangered forest or swamp species falls until there
is only one left. So long as this one surviving flesh-and-blood or wood-
and-sap organism lives, considerations of the kind already adduced in the
case of Bigfoot indicate that it is the only member of the species, and it is
not an idea, from which it follows that the members of the species are
not ideas.
Now suppose this last survivor also perishes. Are we now to say that the
species still has members, but that the members of the species are now
ideas? Should we say that the species has not become extinct but rather has
undergone a metamorphosis, transcending its former carnal or xyline
nature, and taken on a conceptual essence: that its members have cast
aside their fleshly or wooden bodies, and are now made of whatever ideas
are made of? Should we say that the species has undertaken a migration,
abandoning the woods or marshes that were once its home, and occupying
now instead a niche in the minds or brains of human subjects?
It seems to me about as plain as anything can be in philosophy – where
admittedly things are never as plain as they are in some other disciplines –
that this is not what we should say, and that the correct way to describe the
situation is by saying that creatures of this animal or plant species simply no
longer exist at all, though of course human ideas about them do exist, and
may perhaps continue to exist as long as the human species does.
Likewise in the case of Bigfoot. If the forest creature exists, then Bigfoot is
that forest creature, and is something very different from an idea. If the forest
creature does not exist, then Bigfoot is, so to speak, even more different from
an idea: for in that case Bigfoot is nothing, while the idea is at least something,
and what could be more different than something and nothing?
The case is the same, I maintain, with our shared human ideas and
concept of number in general, and of individual numbers such as one or
two or three. (Again the individual ideas contain whatever is contained in
the general idea, plus additional distinguishing elements. We no longer
28 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
imagine, as did the Pythagoreans, that two is female and three is male, but,
for instance, two is even and three is odd.)
These ideas are clear enough, I maintain, to indicate that one, two, three,
and the other numbers, if they exist at all, do not have the same sort of
spatial or temporal features as human ideas, and above all are more
numerous than human ideas could possibly be.
Taking first issues of time and place, mathematics is used throughout
science, and mathematical objects and entities are referred to in all its
branches, including those like cosmology that deal with times and places
very remote from any inhabited by human beings. Are we to say that a
cosmologist’s estimates of the relative numbers of heavy and light elements
at a certain stage in the early evolution of the universe must be wrong,
because there were no numbers at all back then, no human beings having
yet evolved to create them? Surely not.
And then there is the matter of infinity. It is a crucial feature of the
concept of the number system that it has infinitely many elements, that
there are infinitely many numbers. But surely human beings have formed
ideas or concepts of only finitely many of them. There simply are not
enough human ideas and concepts for each number to be one. Some
numbers at least must therefore either enjoy a mode of existence different
from that of any human idea, as realists maintain, or else must simply fail to
exist, as nominalists hold. And is it not preposterous to maintain that while
one of the pair realism or nominalism gives the correct account of mathe-
matical existence in the case of some numbers, conceptualism is correct for
the rest? Surely the question of the existence and nature of numbers has a
uniform answer, and if conceptualism fails in any case, then it must fail in all.
Such, then, are some of the principal reasons why I and almost all profes-
sional philosophers of mathematics reject conceptualism, and consider the
only real issue to be that between nominalism and realism. This last issue is
far too large to be thrashed out here, but I do wish to say a word about it,
and in particular about the character of the realist position, which very often
tends to be misrepresented. Nominalists do not believe in numbers because
they cannot see them (or see any visible effects caused by them), and tend to
represent their opponents as claiming that they can see them.
According to an old story, Plato was once lecturing in his Academy on
his Forms, and was speaking of the forms of ‘‘tableness’’ and ‘‘cupness.’’
Diogenes the Cynic interrupted and said, ‘‘O Plato, I see the table and the
Numbers and ideas 29
cup, but the tableness and the cupness I do not see.’’ To this Plato replied,
‘‘Very naturally, Diogenes, since you have eyes, by which material things
are perceived, but lack Intellect, by which the forms are seen.’’3
Nominalists tend to represent their opponents as Platonists, maintain-
ing that if numbers do not emit electromagnetic radiation to which the eye
is sensitive, then they must be emitting something else, perhaps noetic rays,
which can be sensed by some other organ, perhaps the pineal gland. This,
however, is a misrepresentation of realism. Or at least, I have never known
a single realist who was in any meaningful sense a Platonist.
What is actually the case is that anti-nominalists take much more
seriously than nominalists the thought that mathematics is a human crea-
tion, since mathematics is a body of theory expressed in language, and
language is a human creation.
Now creating a language involves creating certain rules for its use.
Among these is, I believe, a rule to the effect that tense and date are not
to be applied to mathematical existence assertions. One can say ‘‘There
exist infinitely many prime numbers,’’ but to ask ‘‘How many of them
already existed in 1000 B C E , or during the Cenozoic Era?’’ is to commit a
kind of grammatical solecism.
Nominalists say they are opposed to the view that numbers are ‘‘eternal,’’
existing ‘‘outside of time.’’ But to say that numbers are ‘‘eternal’’ is a
misleadingly Platonistic way of putting the simple negative grammatical
fact of the inapplicability of tense distinctions in mathematical contexts.
That simple grammatical point is all the realist really believes about the
‘‘timelessness’’ of number.
(By contrast with the case of the numbers themselves, it makes perfect
sense to ask whether the idea or concept of prime number had emerged by
1000 B C E – the issue involved would be that of the interpretation of certain
Babylonian tablets and Egyptian papyri – and it makes perfect sense to
assert that it had not emerged in the Age of the Dinosaurs. This difference
between the ‘‘timeless’’ numbers proper and datable ideas of them was one
of the points I was arguing in rejecting conceptualism.)
Likewise, there are certain rules or standards as to what counts as
adequate or sufficient to establish or prove a mathematical existence
theorem, and by these rules Euclid’s theorem on the existence of infinitely
many prime numbers is as well-established as anything can be.
The nominalists assume that they have an understanding of what it
would be for a mathematical object or entity to exist that is independent
3
See the life of Diogenes the Cynic in Diogenes Laertius (1925).
30 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
of ordinary mathematical standards of sufficient proof, by reference to
which understanding they can criticize the ordinary mathematical stand-
ards. So-called realism is really just skepticism about the existence of any
understanding of what ‘‘existence’’ means in mathematics that is independ-
ent of ordinary mathematical standards for evaluating existence proofs.
The nominalist denies the existence of numbers, while the realist denies
that the nominalist understands what is meant by ‘‘existence’’ as applied to
numbers.
Thus the realists think the nominalists are confused. But realists and
nominalists agree that the conceptualists are confused, and while I cannot
hope to have convinced anyone by the foregoing very brief remarks that the
realists are right as against the nominalists, I hope I have convinced some of
you that realists and nominalists are right in their common opposition to
conceptualism.
2
INTRODUCTION
The sum of the divisors of 220 is 284, and the sum of the divisors of 284 is
220. The Pythagoreans spoke of numbers so related as being amicable. I do
not know how this ancient teaching should be taken, but surely nobody
nowadays, except perhaps a stray numerologist or two, would imagine that
numbers are literally capable of forming friendships. A number is just not
the sort of thing that can enjoy a social life. And this is but the least of a
number’s lacks.
A number lacks a position in space, such as tables, chairs, and other
material bodies possess. It lacks dates in time, such as dreams, headaches,
and other contents of minds possess. It lacks all visible, tangible, audible
properties. In a word, it is abstract.
Disbelievers in numbers and other abstract entities or ‘‘universals’’ have
come to be called nominalists. Nominalism has always attracted philoso-
phers of the hard-headed, no-nonsense type. But does it not conflict with
modern science, which speaks the language of abstract mathematics?
1 INSTRUMENTALIST NOMINALISM
The nominalist does not presume to restrict the scientist. The scientist may use
Platonistic class constructions, complex numbers, divination by inspection of
entrails, or any claptrappery that he thinks may help him get the results he
wants. But what he produces then becomes raw material for the philosopher,
whose task is to make sense of all this: to clarify, simplify, explain, interpret in
understandable terms . . . Nominalism is a restraint the philosopher imposes on
himself, just because he feels he cannot otherwise make real sense of what is put
before him. (Goodman 1956, objection vii)
3 HERMENEUTIC NOMINALISM
If we take everyday beliefs at face value, then we must conclude that natural
numbers are posits of common sense dating from prehistoric times. If we
take physics even halfway literally, then we must conclude that science has
been committed to complex numbers for well over a century. According to
Why I am not a nominalist 35
hermeneutic nominalism, this is all illusion. General relativity theory may
seem to make statements about vector-valued functions. Quantum
mechanics may seem to make statements about linear operators. But, in
fact, no physical theory asserts or presupposes the existence of such mathe-
matical objects; no branch of science actually posits or commits itself to the
existence of abstract entities.
Hermeneutic nominalism is thus a thesis of a type that has recently been
described by Saul Kripke:
The philosopher advocates a view in patent contradiction to common sense.
Rather than repudiating common sense, he asserts that the conflict comes from
a philosophical misinterpretation of common language – sometimes he adds that
the misinterpretation is encouraged by the ‘‘superficial form’’ or ordinary speech.
He offers his own analysis of the relevant common assertions, one that shows that
they do not really say what they seem to say. (Kripke 1976, p. 269)
4 REVOLUTIONARY NOMINALISM
It is one thing to observe that matters could equally well have been
arranged otherwise than they currently are. It is quite another thing to
urge that a rearrangement would constitute an improvement. To say that
the British convention of driving on the left-hand side of the road is no
worse than our own convention of driving on the right-hand side is not to
advance a criticism of our traffic laws.
‘‘Science,’’ Putnam tells us, lives ‘‘extremely happily on the rich diet of
impredicative sets’’ (1971, p. 56). The work of Chihara and Field suggests
that science could survive on more meager fare, on a diet of inscription-
possibilities or of spatiotemporal regions. But would science be healthier
after such a change of menu?
Why I am not a nominalist 37
When scientists abandoned caloric fluid and luminiferous ether, it was
because they had discovered alternative theories that were empirically
superior, of wider scope and greater accuracy in predicting the results of
observations and experiments. Now the alternative theories concocted by
Chihara and Field cannot be claimed to be empirically superior to current
theories, for they have been designed to be empirically equivalent.
Will it be urged that those alternatives are somehow pragmatically
superior? Their awkward and ungainly character makes it difficult to
claim that they are more convenient and efficient as systematizations of
the data of experience. Will it be urged that, despite their unnatural and
artificial character, they somehow contributed to clarity, simplicity, intelli-
gibility, and the like, in ways that matter to working scientists? Something
of the sort must be urged if a nominalistic revolution in science is to be
motivated.
The proviso, ‘‘in ways that matter to working scientists,’’ is crucial, if a
mere instrumentalist opposition to science is to be avoided. It is pointless
and futile to urge a revolution in the practice of physicists motivated only by
considerations appealing only to philosophers of a certain type. Physicists
are too well aware of the dismal historical record of philosophical interfer-
ence in science to accept such dictation from outsiders.
Now the avoidance of ontological commitments to abstract entities does
not seem to have won recognition in the scientific community as being in
itself a goal of the scientific enterprise on a par with scope and accuracy,
and convenience and efficiency, in the prediction and control of experi-
ence. It seems, on the contrary, a matter to which most working scientists
attach no importance whatsoever. It seems distinctively and exclusively a
preoccupation of philosophers of a certain type. Thus Goodman is able to
cite only a few linguists who are nominalistically inclined, and not one
physicist:
Paucity of means often conduces to clarity and progress in science as well as
philosophy. Some scientists indeed – for example, certain works in structural
linguistics – have even imposed the full restriction of nominalism upon themselves
in order to avoid confusion and self-deception.
One would search the physics journals in vain for any expression of nomi-
nalistic qualms and scruples, of reluctance and hesitancy to use mathematical
apparatus, of suspicion that such ‘‘Platonistic claptrappery’’ as complex
numbers may be a source of ‘‘confusion and self-deception.’’
The proposed nominalistic revolution in physics can be scientifically
motivated only by showing that the avoidance of ontological commitments
38 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
to abstract entities would somehow serve indirectly to advance us toward
some more recognizably scientific goals. For my own part, I cannot discern
any such scientific benefits to be expected from the proposed revolution,
while I do discern a couple of non-negligible costs.
First, any major revolution involves transition costs: the rewriting of
textbooks, redesign of programs of instruction, and so forth. A reform
along the lines of Chihara (1973) would involve reworking the mathematics
curriculum for science and engineering students, avoiding impredicative
methods in favor of predicative parodies that are harder to learn and not so
easy to apply.
A reform along the lines of Field (1980) would involve reworking the
physics curriculum, so that each basic theory would initially be presented
in qualitative rather than quantitative form. A course on measurement
theory would have to be crammed into the already crowded study plan, to
explain and justify the use of the usual numerical apparatus. This is
educational reform in precisely the wrong direction: away from applica-
tions, toward entanglement in logical subtleties.
Second, the physicist who puts on nominalistic blinders may be unable
to see certain potentially important paths for the development of science. I
have in mind here not an inevitable logical consequence of nominalistic
revolution, but a likely psychological consequence. Chihara (1973, p. 209)
promises that he will recant his nominalism should some future physical
theory turn out to require mathematical objects indispensably. But the
danger I have in mind is that if science goes nominalist today, that future
theory may simply never be discovered. Yuri Manin has noted this point in
connection with intuitionism:
Unfortunately, it seems that it is these ‘‘extremes’’ – bold extrapolations, abstractions
which are infinite and do not lend themselves to a constructivist interpretation –
which make classical mathematics effective. One should try to imagine how much
help mathematics could have provided twentieth century quantum physics if for the
past hundred years it had been developed using only abstractions from ‘‘constructive
objects.’’ Most likely, the standard calculations with infinite dimensional represen-
tations of Lie groups which today play an important role in understanding the
microworld, would simply never have occurred to anyone. (Manin 1977, pp. 172–3)
(Mention of quantum mechanics should remind us that it is unclear
whether the methods of Chihara and Field are adequate even for present-
day science in its entirety. For Chihara the problem is a minor one, and
could probably be solved by adopting a somewhat stronger system of
predicative analysis than the particular weak system Rx he favors. For
Field, the problem is a major one, for he has given us no idea how he
Why I am not a nominalist 39
proposes to treat quantum theory, which differs radically (owing to its use
of infinite-dimensional apparatus and to its statistical character) from the
one theory he does treat in detail, Newtonian gravitational theory.)
But I need not enlarge on the costs for present-day and future physics of a
nominalistic revolution. Surely the burden of proof is on the revolutionary,
who proposes a drastic departure from our thus far eminently successful
policy of ontological tolerance in common sense and scientific theory
construction. Until it is shown that nominalism offers physical science
some substantive advantages, I for one am prepared to dismiss its revolu-
tionary proposals as motivated only by medieval superstition (‘‘Ockham’s
razor’’) and fastidious bigotry (cf. Goodman 1964, objection viii).
Chihara and Field have gone a long way toward constructing nominal-
istic alternatives empirically equivalent and pragmatically only slightly
inferior to our current scientific theories. Their work suggests that an
ontology of abstracta may be one feature of those current theories that is
merely conventional, in the best sense of the word (that of David Lewis
1969). This suffices to cast considerable doubt on some more extreme
versions of realism.
It does not suffice to cast doubt on moderate versions of realism, which
merely observe that our current theories seem to invoke abstracta and that
we do not yet have reasons to abandon those theories. For to characterize
some feature of our present ways of doing things (in scientific theorizing or
in driving) as conventional is not in itself to criticize that feature. And
Chihara and Field have not come close to constructing nominalistic alter-
natives that are manifestly superior (empirically or pragmatically) to our
current scientific theories.
CONCLUSION
APPENDIX
Informally this says: however long a tally you could ever write down, I
could write down a still longer one such that . . . Here we have the idea
behind the approach to arithmetic in Chihara (1973).
Chihara’s approach builds on the work of predicativists (specifically, Hao
Wang), mathematical constructivists somewhat more liberal than intui-
tionists. Predicativists accept uncritically classical arithmetic (theory of
natural, or equivalently rational, numbers) but in analysis (theory of real
numbers, or equivalently of sets of natural numbers) they accept only what
is definable. To begin with, they accept those sets of natural numbers that
are definable by purely arithmetical conditions, conditions quantifying
only over natural numbers. These are the order zero sets. Next they accept
those sets of natural numbers that are definable by conditions quantifying
over natural numbers and order zero sets. These are the order one sets. And
so on, through higher and higher orders. (Just how high to go is a delicate
question.) A surprisingly large portion of classical mathematics can be
‘‘parodied’’ within this framework, as the survey by Feferman (1977)
shows. Intuitively, it is plausible that a theory of definable sets should be
reducible to arithmetic plus truth-predicates, with quantification over
definable sets being replaced by quantification over the code numbers of
their defining conditions, and the membership relation replaced by the
relation ‘‘n is the code number of a formula with one free variable that is
true of m.’’ The details can be worked out, and we get a reduction of
predicative analysis to something that has already been shown to be
nominalistically reinterpretable. Chihara’s account of the application of
mathematics in science is illustrated by Figure 2.1.
While scientific theories are formulated mathematically in terms of
sharply defined functions, at least in the overwhelming majority of
Why I am not a nominalist 43
Empirical Basic scientific
conditions theory
define formulated for
FUZZY Idealization SHARP
FUNCTION FUNCTION
Theorems of
analysis
Information about
Consequences of
FUZZY
scientific theory:
FUNCTION
information about
hence information
Approximation SHARP
about empirical
FUNCTION
situation
Figure 2.1
Conservation Theorems
theorems
⇓ of
analysis
Figure 2.2
Why I am not a nominalist 45
versions of its consequences involves a ‘‘Platonistic’’ detour: from qualitative
basic theory by measurement theory to quantitative basic theory, thence by
theorems of analysis to quantitative consequences, and thence by measure-
ment theory again to qualitative consequences, as in Figure 2.2.
It is, however, theoretically possible, though practically inconvenient, to
avoid the introduction of mathematics, to avoid the detour through the
quantitative and abstract:
the conclusions we arrive at by these means are not genuinely new, they are already
derivable in a more long-winded fashion . . . without recourse to the mathematical
entities. (Field 1980, pp. 10–11)
for these purposes [‘‘problem solving’’] the usual numerical apparatus is a practical
necessity. But it is a necessity that the nominalist has no need to forgo: he can treat
the apparatus . . . as a useful instrument for making deductions from the nominal-
istic system that is ultimately of interest; an instrument which yields no conclusions
not obtainable without it, but which yields them more easily. (Field 1980, p. 91)
These claims are supported by appeal to conservation theorems from proof
theory (the most important being perhaps one due to Scott Weinstein).
3
1 ‘‘ N O M I N A L I S M ’’ AND ‘‘ R E A L I S M ’’ 1
Nominalism is a large subject. In our book (Burgess and Rosen 1997) my
colleague Gideon Rosen and I distinguished a negative or destructive side
of nominalism, which tells us not to believe what mathematics appears to
say, from a positive or reconstructive side, which aims to give us something
else to believe instead. We noted that there were a few nominalists who
contented themselves with the negative side, conceding that mathematics is
useful, insisting that what it appears to say is not true, and letting it go at
that, without attempting any reconstrual or reconstruction of mathe-
matics. We expressed some surprise that there were not more such destruc-
tive nominalists, since as compared with reconstructive nominalism,
destructive nominalism has what Russell in another context called ‘‘the
advantages of theft over honest toil’’; and if nothing else was clear from the
work of Hartry Field, Charles Chihara, Geoffrey Hellman, and other
reconstructive nominalists whose work we surveyed, it was clear that the
amount of honest toil that would be required for a nominalistic reconstrual
or reconstruction of mathematics would be quite considerable.
Today, a couple of years after publication, it is beginning to seem that
the main achievement of our book will have been to provide a decent burial
for the hard-working, laborious variety of nominalism. For almost every-
thing that has come forth since from the nominalist camp has represented a
light-fingered, larcenous variety, which helps itself to the utility of math-
ematics, while refusing to pay the price either of acknowledging that what
mathematics appears to say is true, or of providing any reconstrual or
reconstruction that would make it true. The usual label for this variety of
1
I have decided to keep this paper in the form in which it was originally written for oral delivery,
adding footnotes to supply citations of the literature, and for clarification at a few points where
experience has shown misunderstanding of my intended sense may be likely.
46
Mathematics and Bleak House 47
nominalism is ‘‘[mathematical] fictionalism.’’2 Not only has fictionalism
become the most widely pursued form of nominalism, but even some
former anti-nominalists have been wavering or drifting in its direction,
including even the author of one of the most eloquent early criticisms,
‘‘Mathematics and Oliver Twist.’’ I will take the liberty, therefore, of
substituting ‘‘fictionalism’’ for the ‘‘nominalism’’ label in the official title
of our symposium.
While I am at it, I had better say something about the ‘‘realism’’ as well.
It is an even larger subject, since there is hardly any bit of philosophical
terminology more diversely used and overused and misused than the R-
word. There seems to be a systematic difference between the way in which
the word is understood by many of those who describe themselves as
‘‘realists’’ and the way in which it is understood by most of those who
describe themselves as ‘‘anti-realists.’’ For many professed ‘‘realists,’’ realism
amounts to little more than a willingness to repeat in one’s philosophical
moments what one says in one’s scientific moments, not taking it back,
explaining it away, or otherwise apologizing for it: what we say in our
scientific moments is all right, though no claim is made that it is uniquely
right, or that other intelligent beings who conceptualized the world differ-
ently from us would necessarily be getting something wrong. For many
professed ‘‘anti-realists,’’ realism seems rather to amount to a claim that
what one says to oneself in scientific moments when one tries to under-
stand the universe corresponds to Ultimate Metaphysical Reality; that it is,
so to speak, a repetition of just what God was saying to Himself when He
was creating the universe.
The weaker position might be called anti-anti-realism, and the stronger
position capital-R Realism. Quine says somewhere that his ‘‘realism’’ and his
‘‘pragmatism’’ are reconciled by his ‘‘naturalism.’’ This is a hard saying, but I
think it can be explained along the following lines. First, ‘‘realism’’ here
means anti-anti-realism: the refusal to apologize while doing philosophy for
what is said while doing mathematics or science. Second, ‘‘pragmatism’’
2
In earlier publications I called this stance ‘‘instrumentalism,’’ while Rosen called it ‘‘constructive
nominalism,’’ by analogy with van Fraassen’s ‘‘constructive empiricism.’’ (Incidentally, though van
Fraassen is best known for his fictionalism about unobservable physical entities, he is also a fictionalist
about abstract mathematical entities.) However, the analogous positions in other areas of philosophy
(e.g. modality) are today generally called ‘‘fictionalist,’’ and on this ground Rosen adopted the
‘‘fictionalist’’ label, and I now follow him. Unfortunately, there has been another use of ‘‘fictionalist’’
in philosophy of mathematics, by Hartry Field and his students, for whom it includes all rejectionist
views, all views that hold that standard mathematics is false, whether fictionalist in our sense or
reconstructive. This usage seems to be out of alignment with the usage of ‘‘fictionalism’’ in other areas
of philosophy, and for that reason to be avoided.
48 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
means rejection of capital-R Realism, rejection as unjustified of any claim
that mathematics and science give us a God’s-eye view of capital-R Reality.
Third, ‘‘naturalism’’ means adherence to a conception of epistemology as an
inquiry conducted by citizens of the scientific community examining science
from the inside, rather than an inquisition conducted by philosophers
foreign to science judging science from the outside.
And the reconciliation? Naturalism teaches us to look at our scientific,
philosophical, and other forms of intellectual endeavor as activities of bio-
logical organisms with cognitive capacities that, though extensive, stop well
short of omniscience. As such, none of these endeavors can succeed in
achieving a God’s-eye view of Reality. And therefore there is no reason to
apologize for one of them, science, failing to achieve such a view, and every
reason not to suppose that another of them, philosophy, could do better.
Should I, therefore, replace ‘‘realism’’ by ‘‘naturalism’’ in the title of our
symposium? No, for unfortunately ‘‘naturalism’’ too has been used and
overused and misused in multiple senses. In particular, while in Quine’s
sense naturalism abstains from imposing philosophical constraints on
science, there is another equally widespread but diametrically opposed
conception in which ‘‘naturalism’’ consists precisely in imposing such a
philosophical constraint, namely, the constraint that no entities are to be
assumed that do not stand in natural cause-and-effect relations with us. So
I will just replace ‘‘realism’’ by ‘‘anti-fictionalism,’’ making the title of our
symposium come down to this: ‘‘fictionalism in philosophy of mathe-
matics: pro and con.’’
2 LITERARY GENRES
To begin with the pro side, it is impossible to quarrel with the proposition
that mathematics is in some respects like fiction. For indeed, anything is like
anything else, in some respect. I even think the comparison may be illumi-
nating, as to the nature of fiction, or rather, as to some of the questions
philosophers raise about fiction, and in particular about the status of
fictional characters. The hard-headed view is that they just do not exist.
Another view is that they are abstract entities of some sort or other. Yet
another view is that they are mental entities. Now the view that mathe-
matical entities are mental entities, though a perennial favorite of amateur
philosophers, has been in disrepute among professional philosophers since
Frege’s trenchant critique of psychologistic philosophies of mathematics
more than a hundred years ago. I think that fiction is enough like mathe-
matics to suggest that the view that fictional entities are mental entities is
Mathematics and Bleak House 49
equally dubious. For example, one problem for mentalistic theories of
mathematical entities is that there are too many such entities for minds to
have created each one; and a little reflection shows that the situation is
similar with fiction: a novelist may write of the doings of a vast army with
thousands of officers and myriads of soldiers, while in fact describing only a
couple of dozen of them individually. But I am straying from our topic,
which was supposed to be what, if anything, comparison with fiction can
show us about mathematics, and not the reverse.
Reverting to that topic, then, I have said on the one hand that it can
hardly be denied that mathematics is like fiction in some respects, most
obviously in consisting of large bodies of manuscript and printed and now
electronic writing. On the other hand, it must be said that there is a sense in
which mathematics is clearly non-fiction: there is a well-established prac-
tice of classifying writing as ‘‘fiction’’ and ‘‘non-fiction,’’ and setting aside
attempted theoretical definitions and analyses, attending rather to the
criteria by which in actual practice such classifications are made, clearly
mathematics counts as non-fiction. The compilers of the New York Times
best-seller list will never put any mathematical work, however wonderful,
at the top of the fiction column, and not just because nothing even by
Andrew Wiles will ever sell like Stephen King. Nor will any librarian
catalogue, say, the Proceedings of the Cabal Seminar as an ‘‘anthology of
short stories based on the characters created by Georg Cantor.’’ Now of
course misclassifications are sometimes made, and mischievous hoaxes and
pious frauds sometimes succeed, but these represent mistakes in applying
general criteria to specific cases. I do not think it even makes sense to
suggest that the general criteria are themselves mistaken, and it seems
unquestionable that by those criteria mathematical writing is not literally
fictional writing: mathematics is not in all respects the same as fiction.
So the question is: in which respects is mathematics like, and in which
respects is it unlike, fiction? That in part depends on the species of the
genus fiction one considers. The first species one thinks of will probably be
the novel, and comparison with novels is in fact common among professed
fictionalists and their critics, as with Oliver Twist, mentioned earlier. There
has been, however, a minority – including especially the late Leslie Tharp3 –
who have preferred a comparison with mythology. In a slightly different
vein, Steve Yablo, in an interesting paper,4 has suggested a comparison with
metaphor. Metaphor of course is not a genre of fiction but a figure of
3
Rescued from oblivion in Chihara (1989).
4
The reference was to an on-line version, but the paper has since appeared in print as Yablo (2000).
50 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
speech, and I think that to speak as Yablo does of a metaphor running on
for volumes and volumes and volumes is to stretch the concept of ‘‘meta-
phor’’ well beyond breaking point. But perhaps much of the content of
Yablo’s suggestion could be preserved if we took the comparison to be
between mathematics and parables or fables.
Be that as it may, I believe the comparison with fables is the most apt of
the candidates I have considered, and comparison with novels the least so.
Novels almost always are attributable to identifiable individual authors:
Proust or Flaubert, Trollope or Dickens. Some fables are attributable to
such authors, Lafontaine for instance; others are traditional. Mathematics
also consists of both traditional elements and elements with identifiable
authors. Novels are almost always unique. Fables tend to be retold over and
over in variant versions by different writers, so that we have Aesop’s
version, Lafontaine’s version, and many latter-day retellings of the fox
and the crow, for instance. Mathematics likewise gets retold by textbook
writer after textbook writer. The characters in one novel seldom reappear in
another, and even those who do reappear, like Swann or Palliser, do so only
in comparatively few stories, all by the same author. This is so with some
characters of fable, but many, like the clever fox, reappear in whole cycles of
tales. The same mathematicalia, p and e, the sine and cosine functions, 0
and 1 and 2 and so on, reappear through whole libraries of mathematical
works. Again, characters encountered in novels are generally of the same
species as those encountered in daily life, while those in fables are, as one
dictionary definition reminds us, beings of a different order: ‘‘animals that
talk and behave like human beings.’’ Mathematics, too, has objects even
more unlike those of any other subject, and it is for precisely that reason
that there is thought to be a philosophical problem about them.
Yet more important is the matter of application, which in literature
typically takes the form of a ‘‘message.’’ The fable typically though not
invariably has a ‘‘moral,’’ while to demand one of the novel is virtually the
definition of Philistinism. I am reminded in this connection of what
Nabokov says in his posthumously published lectures about Bleak House
and its supposed concern with reform of the Court of Chancery.
At first blush it might seem that Bleak House is a satire. Let us see. If a satire is of
little aesthetic value, it does not attain its object, however worthy that object may
be. On the other hand, if a satire is permeated by artistic genius, then its object is of
little importance and vanishes with its times while the dazzling satire remains, for
all time, as a work of art. So why speak of satire at all? . . . Such cases as Jarndyce
did occur now and then in the middle of the last century although, as legal
historians have shown, the bulk of our author’s information on legal matters
Mathematics and Bleak House 51
goes back to the 1820s and 1830s so that many of his targets had ceased to exist by
the time Bleak House was written. But if the target is gone, let us enjoy the carved
beauty of the weapon. (Nabokov 1980, p. 64)
The question of applications is crucial in the case of mathematics, because
though it would be a kind of Philistinism to demand that every piece of
mathematics have one, many do; and it is precisely because many do that
many philosophers have opposed nominalism, this being the least com-
mon denominator of all ‘‘indispensability arguments.’’
Still more important, however, is a feature common to all genres of
fiction. The most important single respect in which fictionalists hold
mathematics to be like novels or fables or whatever is in being a body of
falsehoods. In particular the existence theorems of mathematics are sup-
posed to be untrue: these say there exist, for instance, prime numbers
10
greater than 1010 , whereas according to mathematical fictionalists, and
indeed all nominalists, there are no such things as numbers at all.5
3 NON-LITERAL LANGUAGE
7
The term ‘‘hermeneutic fictionalism’’ was taken as the title for a large-scale study by Jason Stanley
(2001), which pursues at length a number of the points to be made below, and many more also,
through several different areas of philosophy where fictionalism has become fashionable. In an
alternative terminology, hermeneutic reconstructive nominalism and hermeneutic non-reconstructive
nominalism are called content hermeneuticism and attitude hermeneuticism respectively. This
terminology is used in Rosen and Burgess (2005).
Mathematics and Bleak House 53
asking, ‘‘What is the value of your investigation of p, since irrational
numbers do not exist?’’ Suppose a nominalist philosopher today were to
say to Wiles, ‘‘What’s all this fuss about your proving there are no natural
numbers x, y, z > 0 and n > 2 such that xn þ yn ¼ zn? Since there are
no numbers at all, a fortiori there are none satisfying that equation.’’8
I imagine most mathematicians would be contemptuous of this speech and
most philosophers – even most nominalist philosophers – embarrassed by it.
According to another story, G. E. Moore famously once argued along
something like the following lines: he held up his hands and said, ‘‘As you
can see, here are two human hands. Since human hands are material bodies
in the external world, there exists an external world of material bodies.’’
Suppose an anti-nominalist philosopher today were to hold up his hands
and say, ‘‘As you can see, the number of my hands is two. Since the number
two is an abstract entity, abstract entities exist.’’ Would not most mathe-
maticians be baffled and bewildered by this argument, and would not most
philosophers – even anti-nominalist philosophers – balk and boggle at it?
On the one hand, objections to what mathematicians and others would
ordinarily say about mathematical entities on the grounds of their alleged
non-existence are regarded with scorn, while on the other hand, purported
proofs of their existence are viewed with suspicion. Yablo argues that this
double attitude is explicable if we assume that mathematical assertions are
meant non-literally, as fiction, or rather, in this preferred terminology, as
metaphor. For that would make both objections on the grounds that they
are not literally true, and attempts to prove that they are literally true,
equally off the mark in opposite directions. As I said earlier, I think Yablo’s
argument ultimately relies on the same kind of consideration as Chihara’s,
namely, mathematicians’ puzzlement at or repudiation of philosophical
theses and arguments about the existence of the entities they study. I also
think the positions of Chihara and Yablo ultimately involve similar mis-
takes about the nature and meaning of ‘‘commitment’’ and ‘‘literalness.’’
Let me begin with commitment. The reason Quine and others have
spoken of the ‘‘commitment’’ of mathematical, scientific, and everyday
thought to mathematical and other abstract entities, is precisely because
they did not want to speak of mathematicians’ or scientists’ or lay-persons’
‘‘assertions’’ of or ‘‘beliefs’’ in the existence of such entities. Mathematicians
qua mathematicians do address questions about whether there are prime
10
numbers greater than 1010 , but they generally do not spend much time
talking, and presumably do not spend much time thinking, about the
8
This example is from a talk by the late George Boolos.
54 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
question whether there are any such things as numbers at all: hence the
inappropriateness of speaking of their ‘‘assertions’’ or ‘‘beliefs’’ about such
questions. Quine’s claim was that they are committed to an affirmative
answer to this question, because what they do assert and believe, that there
10
are prime numbers greater than 1010 , implies that there are prime numbers
and therefore that there are numbers, and it has this implication whether or
not they ever acknowledge it, and indeed even if they repudiate it, when
talking philosophy rather than mathematics.
Now for literalness. Quine does allow that someone might say, ‘‘There are
10
prime numbers greater than 1010 ’’ and yet not be committed to its impli-
cations. For one could say it and not really mean it, or not really believe it,
whether or not one were capable of articulating what it is that one does mean
and believe when saying it. One could say it and not intend it to be
understood ‘‘literally.’’ But what does this mean? If the function of the
word ‘‘literal’’ were to indicate the presence of something positive, some extra
enthusiasm perhaps, then it would indeed be very doubtful whether mathe-
10
maticians who assert that there are prime numbers greater than 1010 mean
it ‘‘literally.’’ But I suggest that the function of the word is in actual fact less
to indicate the presence of something positive than to indicate the absence of
something negative: roughly what in the legal phrase is called ‘‘mental
reservation and purpose of evasion.’’ If this is so, then what is in actual fact
very doubtful is whether mathematicians who assert that there are prime
10
numbers greater than 1010 intend their assertion only as something ‘‘non-
literal.’’ To do that, they would have to be more philosophically self-
conscious than they appear to be. To put the matter another way, the
‘‘literal’’ interpretation is not just one interpretation among others. It is the
default interpretation. There is a presumption that people mean and believe
what they say. It is, to be sure, a defeasible presumption, but some evidence is
needed to defeat it. The burden of proof is on those who would suggest that
people intend what they say only as a good yarn, to produce some actual
evidence that this is indeed their intention.9
9
To mean what one says literally is simply to mean what one says, just as to be a genuine antique is
simply to be an antique. The force of ‘‘literally’’ is not to assert that one is doing something more
besides, but to deny that one is doing something else instead: meaning something other than what one
says, as when one speaks metaphorically, hyperbolically, elliptically, or otherwise figuratively. One
does not have to think anything extra in order to speak literally: one has to think something extra in
order to speak non-literally. Such, at any rate, is the not uncommon view of the meaning of ‘‘literal’’ to
which I subscribe. For more on this point, see Searle (1979). Assuming this point, the hypothesis that
someone is writing or speaking literally is the hypothesis that nothing more is going on than meets the
eye or the ear: the null hypothesis about covert intentions. In the text I call it the default hypothesis,
since I take it there is a defeasible presumption in favor of null hypotheses in general. In the specific
Mathematics and Bleak House 55
And I submit that the fact that mathematicians tend to be perplexed by
and dubious about philosophical argumentation over the existence of
mathematical entities – the ‘‘frog and mouse battle’’ as Einstein once called
a specific instance of such debate – and even the fact that mathematicians
who are badgered with skeptical questions by skeptical philosophers can be
got to make skeptical noises, are not very good evidence. In this connec-
tion, I remember reading an interview in Scientific American some years
back with Murray Gell-Man, who explained that in his original paper on
the quark hypothesis he avoided claiming that quarks were real in order to
avoid trouble with ‘‘philosophers.’’ This self-censorship perhaps does not
say much for Gell-Man’s courage – Galileo, after all, did not recant until he
was ‘‘shown the instruments’’ – but it is rather revealing as to how we
philosophers are viewed by some of our scientific colleagues, and suggests
that there may be serious difficulties with the methodology of pestering
scientists for opinions on philosophical issues to which they may have given
little or no thought, and accepting their answers as indicative of their
intentions in putting forward the affirmations that they do put forward
when philosophers leave the scene and let them get back to work.
4 CONTRASTING CASES
case of the null hypothesis about meaning, there is the additional consideration, not mentioned in the
text, that word-meaning and speaker-meaning, though distinct, are not independent. It would be
impossible for words to mean what they do if everyone always used them to mean something else, and
difficult for them to mean what they do unless most people most of the time use them to mean that, so
that a randomly chosen person at a randomly chosen time probably means what he or she says.
56 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
among philosophers proper, including positions that regard all of mathe-
matics as just a good yarn, or merely a great game.
Certainly the bulk of Hilbert’s own results, beginning with his basis
theorem, were meaningless or ‘‘ideal’’ statements according to his official
philosophy. The topological work, and notably the fixed-point theorem,
which established Brouwer’s reputation among mathematicians, is largely
false or meaningless according to his intuitionist principles. There is of
course always a question, whenever someone says something in one context
and takes it back in another, whether we should regard the original
affirmation as merely pretense and the subsequent denial as revealing the
person’s real opinion, or whether contrariwise we should regard the cere-
mony of recantation as play-acting, and the real opinion the one expressed
originally. But I think that in the case of the field marshal of the batrachians
and the generalissimo of the rodents we may conclude on the basis of their
extensive philosophical writings that they did indeed mean much of what
they said in their mathematical work as ‘‘non-literal’’ or ‘‘fictitious’’ in some
sense. My earlier point was that in the case of the overwhelming majority of
mathematicians there is no such evidence that unspoken philosophical
caveats accompany their mathematical assertions.
The other case I wish to mention is that of the mathematician who, for
instance, asserts on one page that there is only one non-cyclic group of
order four, and on the next page that among the subgroups of some larger
group there are three non-cyclic groups of order four. How can there be
three of them if there is only one of them? That is a mystery whose solution
is that the assertion of uniqueness was not meant literally, but rather
involved a figure of speech, namely ellipsis: ‘‘unique’’ was elliptical for
‘‘unique up to isomorphism,’’ and what is really meant is that all non-
cyclic groups of order four, including the three that turn up as subgroups of
the larger group alluded to, are isomorphic to each other. This isomor-
phism is, of course, what the proof of ‘‘uniqueness’’ proves.
The difference between such cases of mathematicians locally meaning
this or that form of expression as one or another kind of figure of speech,
and the hermeneutic fictionalist’s claim that mathematicians globally mean
none of what they say literally, is that there is evidence within what
mathematicians say while engaged in mathematical research or teaching, to
indicate, for instance, that the claim of uniqueness of the Klein four-group
is intended to be understood as pertaining not literally to uniqueness, but
to uniqueness up to isomorphism. For one thing, if a student who had not
yet learned all the relevant idioms and usages were to raise a question, the
mathematician would explain. Owning up to the non-literal character of
Mathematics and Bleak House 57
the uniqueness assertion is something the mathematician does on the job,
not just when interrupted and pestered by skeptical philosophers, or after
hours pursuing some philosophical hobby.
To be sure, it is also possible in this particular example that the
mathematician just does not know what ‘‘unique’’ means, like the mer-
chant whose advertisement I once saw, who claimed that ‘‘Every item in the
store is unique, and many are one-of-a-kind.’’ But there are other classes of
examples of local non-literalness. Indeed, my discussion of the case of
uniqueness assertions is largely inspired by Stewart Shapiro’s discussion
of one extensive class of such cases,10 mathematicians’ frequent use of
dynamic language, as if the functions, for instance, were moving mathe-
matical objects around, changing one mathematical object into another,
and so on – a manner of speaking to which, as Shapiro notes, Plato already
objected. I think again, with Shapiro, that there is good evidence within
what mathematicians say while engaged in mathematical research or teaching
for taking this particular kind of language to be meant non-literally. But
the presence of evidence in this case again contrasts with the comparative
absence of evidence for the hermeneutic fictionalist’s global claim that all
kinds of mathematical language are meant ‘‘non-literally.’’
5 UNDECIDABLE QUESTIONS
10
In public talks since the later 1970s and in Shapiro (1997).
58 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
This similarity would seem to provide less than no support to the
hermeneutic view that mathematicians do intend their mathematical asser-
tions as fictions. After all, mathematicians were making mathematical
assertions for centuries before Gödel, in blissful ignorance of any incom-
pleteness or incompletability phenomena, and even while confidently
asserting that ‘‘in mathematics there is no ignorabimus’’ and ‘‘wir müssen
wissen, wir werden wissen.’’ So the fact that fiction rather obviously leaves
many questions undecided would seem to be a powerful argument for the
conclusion that mathematicians were not thinking of their science as a
branch of creative writing. By contrast, the observation that mathematics
resembles fiction in respect of incompleteness might well be thought to
provide support for the revolutionary view that philosophers should regard
mathematical assertions as fictions. At any rate, the observation often is
cited in support of such a position.
To this sort of observation there are two kinds of response: a more specific
and a more general. The more specific notes that, even if we accept that
Gödelian theorems do show that there are fundamental reasons of mathe-
matical principle why some mathematical questions must remain forever
undecided, this by no means establishes a dividing line with mathematics
and novels, fables, and so on, on the one side, and scientific and common-
sense thought on the other side. For are there not, to begin with, also
fundamental reasons of physical principle why some physical questions
must remain forever undecided? The second law of thermodynamics suggests
the growth of entropy will blur the historical record to the point where many
facts about the past will become irrecoverable. General relativity suggests
information may be swallowed up by black holes and hidden from us forever
beyond their horizon. And then there is quantum mechanics. On top of all
this, there are the apparently undecidable questions that arise wherever there
is vagueness, which is just about everywhere except mathematics. But these
considerations are doubtless familiar, and I need not enlarge on them here.
What I want to consider instead is another line of response, suggesting
that even if it were distinctive of mathematics among what pass for sciences
to present us with unanswerable questions, it would be doubtful that this
feature should be taken as a criterion for distinguishing fiction from fact.
More generally, the other line of response I wish to consider – one vaguely
analogous to Hume on miracles – suggests that it is virtually always more
doubtful that philosophy has arrived at the correct understanding of
‘‘truth’’ or ‘‘existence’’ or what have you, than that what well-established
mathematical, scientific, and commonsense principles tell us are facts are
fantasies, or that what they tell us exists is a phantasm.
Mathematics and Bleak House 59
Revolutionary mathematical fictionalism is an ‘‘error theory,’’ offering a
‘‘correction’’ to mathematics, and especially to mathematical existence
theorems, much as Brouwer once offered an intuitionistic ‘‘correction’’ to
his own Brouwer Fixed Point Theorem.11 At the same time, it is offering a
‘‘correction’’ to science insofar as it is formulated mathematically. The line
of response against such philosophical ‘‘corrections’’ to mathematics and
science that I want to consider is the one expressed in the Credo of my
colleague David Lewis. Rosen and I quoted it in our book, and I will not
quote it again here; but for those who have not read it, its point is that,
given the comparative historical records of success and failure of philoso-
phy on the one hand, and of mathematics on the other, to propose
philosophical ‘‘corrections’’ to mathematics is comically immodest.
And indeed, the historical record of philosophical ‘‘corrections’’ to
mathematics and science from Bellarmine’s ‘‘correction’’ of Galileo – an
early form of fictionalism or ‘‘constructive empiricism’’ – onwards, has
been pretty dismal. One argument against revolutionary fictionalism is
thus just that, given the historical record, on simple inductive grounds it
seems extremely unlikely that philosophy can do better than mathematics
in determining what mathematical entities exist, or what mathematical
theorems are true, and much more likely that for the (n þ 1)st time,
philosophy has got the nature of truth and existence wrong.
6 INTERMINABLE DEBATE
11
The theorem can be found in Brouwer (1976) and the ‘‘correction’’ in Brouwer (1975).
60 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
To begin with, Carnap notes, as so many others have since, and as I did
above, that the question whether there exist any such things as numbers at
all is one that is never raised by the mathematicians themselves (while
doing mathematics), but only by philosophers (including such few pro-
fessional mathematicians as are also amateur philosophers, when doing
philosophy rather than mathematics). And the most salient fact Carnap
notes about the debate among philosophers is that it goes on and on and on
without ever being settled. The philosophical issue of nominalism and
realism is in this respect like Jarndyce and Jarndyce.
There is an apparent difference in that in Dickens’ novel the parties to
the lawsuit were finally driven mad by the interminable legal wrangling,
whereas few philosophers have been driven over the edge by the issue of
nominalism and realism. But then philosophers are not really in the
position of the suitors. Rather, as Rosen put it when we were once
discussing the matter, ‘‘We’re the lawyers.’’ Of course, in Dickens’ novel,
even the lawyers eventually stopped arguing the case: the case ended
when the entire value of the estate had been eaten up by legal costs,
and there was no money left to pay any more lawyers. So far we philoso-
phers are still being paid, and even to some slight degree paid attention,
and perhaps there is no immediate danger of the value of the estate running
out in our case. Still, Carnap thought that the endless litigation with
no sign of settlement approaching was an indication that something was
badly wrong.
His analysis of the situation was rather complex, and had three strands:
there is a positive phase with two aspects, plus a negative phase. Let me take
the elements one at a time. The two aspects of the positive phase can be
brought out by comparing Carnap’s position on the one hand with that of
one of Yablo’s targets, Crispin Wright, and on the other hand with that of
all nominalists’ target, Quine.
Wright once propounded an argument against nominalism roughly as
follows: I have as many fingers as toes; but as everyone who understands the
concept of ‘‘number’’ knows, to say that I have as many fingers as toes is
equivalent to saying that the number of my fingers equals the number of
my toes; but to say this presupposes that there is such a thing as the number
of my fingers or toes; hence the number ten exists. What the Carnapian
agrees with in this argument is the recognition that concepts come with
rules for their employment, some of which entail affirmative answers to
certain existence questions, so that one has only two choices: either one
rejects the concept, in which case the existence questions cannot even be
asked; or else one accepts the concept, in which case one immediately gets
Mathematics and Bleak House 61
affirmative answers to those existence questions. One cannot ask the
question and answer it in the negative. One is compelled to accept certain
existence assertions, if one accepts the concept, or the ‘‘framework’’ to
substitute Carnap’s term for Wright’s.
One is not, however, compelled to accept every concept that might be
proposed. In response to criticism by Hartry Field, Wright acknowledged
this point, and in subsequent rounds of debate he and his colleague Bob
Hale have attempted to formulate a general principle that would enforce
acceptance of the concept involved in many though not all cases, including
the particular case relevant to Wright’s original argument, that of the
concept of ‘‘number.’’12 So far they have not come up with a general
principle that has commanded any very widespread support, and the
Carnapian view would be that it is a mistake to attempt to enforce the
acceptance of concepts by a priori arguments.
Quine, and along with him Hilary Putnam at one stage in the evolution
of his views, urged a very different sort of reason for accepting the existence
of numbers (or other abstract mathematical entities to which numbers
could be ‘‘reduced’’). According to Quine, we must (alas, with the greatest
reluctance!) resign ourselves (ah, that it should have come to this!) to
accepting (unbidden and unwelcome!) mathematical entities, because
(most regrettably and unfortunately!) mention of them seems (would
that it were not so!) to be an unavoidable requirement (how cruel a
necessity!) in formulating scientific theories. What Carnap agrees with in
this argument is that the ultimate grounds for accepting the concept
‘‘number’’ is the role it plays in formulating scientific theories, together
with the role scientific theories in turn play in much of our life.
Quine’s argument invites two kinds of objections. On the one hand, there
are the reconstructive nominalists who question that mention of mathemat-
ical entities really is an unavoidable necessity after all. It is the large con-
cessions to nominalism made in the anti-nominalist argument of the ex-
nominalist Quine that invite this sort of objection. On the Carnapian view,
by contrast, a ‘‘framework’’ of mathematical entities is not something to
which we grudgingly resign ourselves because it is a necessary evil, but
something we gratefully adopt because it is an enormous convenience; and
there is no suggestion that if mathematical entities by hook or crook or
somehow could be eliminated, then they should, and hence no invitation to
nominalists to go looking for hooks and crooks.
12
See Hale and Wright (2001), especially ‘‘Responses to Critics.’’
62 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
On the other hand, there are objections of the kind especially voiced by
Charles Parsons (1980, p. 150), roughly to the effect that Quine’s argument
does not do justice to the seeming obviousness of elementary arithmetic, and
makes acceptance of ‘‘two plus two is four’’ or ‘‘the number of my hands is
two’’ depend on recondite and abstruse considerations about whether it is
possible to formulate general relativity without referring to tensors, or
quantum mechanics without reference to linear operators. Such objections
are invited by Quine’s refusal to acknowledge any ‘‘conceptual’’ truths, even
conditional ones, and his insistence that all knowledge ‘‘faces the tribunal of
experience’’ as a whole. By contrast, on the Carnapian view, the seemingly
obvious simple statements about the number two just mentioned are taken
to be immediate, given the relevant concept or framework, and consider-
ations of the larger role of that framework in science are only relevant to
explaining why the framework, as well as whatever comes thus immediately
with it, is classified as non-fiction rather than fiction. Moreover, to repeat,
what is important about the larger role in science is merely that it would be
very inconvenient in practice not to use mathematical language, and not that
detailed scrutiny of the most sophisticated theories shows it to be wholly
impossible in principle to do without such language.
It is against the background of this two-sided positive account, accord-
ing to which there are both a local a priori element, the rules constitutive of
the concept, and also a global pragmatic element, motivating acceptance
of the concept, that Carnap attempts to account for the interminability of
philosophical debate between nominalists and anti-nominalists. What is
missing, according to Carnap, when philosophers debate whether numbers
exist – not whether they exist according to standard mathematics, or whether
it is convenient to speak and think as if they existed, but whether they really
exist – is any framework providing rules for assessing assertions of onto-
logical metaphysics about what italics-added really or capital-R Really
exists, in the way that the framework of number-language determines
that ‘‘I have as many hands as feet’’ is a sufficient condition for ‘‘The
number of my hands equals the number of my feet.’’ Or to put the matter
another way, the ontologists are treating the practical question whether to
accept the framework of number-language, to which only considerations of
convenience and the like are genuinely germane, as if it were a theoretical
question of a kind that can only be asked within a preexisting conceptual
framework. Or to put the matter yet another way, and as briefly as possible,
the debate never ends because there is not only a lack of agreement between
the two sides as to what the right answer to the question is, but also a lack of
agreement between the two sides, and for that matter even among those on
Mathematics and Bleak House 63
the same side, about what counts as a relevant consideration for or against one
or another answer to the question.13
7 MEANINGLESS QUESTIONS
I suspect the reason Carnap’s presentation of the case failed to convince was
largely that he was too much identified with the infamous ‘‘empiricist
criterion of meaningfulness,’’ which certainly has by now been consigned,
if not to the rubbish bin, then at least to archives, where it may be studied
by historians of philosophy, but where it no longer influences current
philosophical debate. According to this criterion – which among other
things sits rather poorly with a recognition of Gödelian phenomena – the
absence of agreed empirical and/or logical criteria for what counts for or
against one or another ontological hypothesis renders argumentation for
these theses meaningless, a kind of nonsense poetry without the poetry.
Instead of a comparison of mathematics with the work of Charles Dickens
or George Elliot, we have here a comparison of philosophy of mathematics
with the work of Lewis Carroll or Edward Lear: it makes the same amount
of sense, though it is less entertaining. Carnap was notorious for the
provocative claim that the issue of nominalism and realism, the ‘‘problem
of universals,’’ is a ‘‘pseudo-problem.’’ This Carnapian thesis is much
stronger than, for instance, the Ludovician claim that induction suggests
it is less likely that philosophy has now solved the problem of universals in a
way that shows mathematics to be in error, than that philosophy has once
again failed to solve the problem. Moreover, the Carnapian thesis implies
or presupposes other very large and controversial claims.
Let me elaborate. One very traditional sort of way to try to make sense of
the question of the ultimate metaphysical existence of numbers would be to
turn the ontological question into a theological question: did it or did it not
happen, on one of the days of creation, that God said, ‘‘Let there be
numbers!’’ and there were numbers, and God saw the numbers, that they
were good? According to Dummett, and according to Nietzsche – or my
13
As mentioned in the review (Burgess 2001), there is a superficial appearance of similarity between
Carnap’s view and that of Mark Balaguer, especially as in Balaguer (1998, pp. 158–79), who maintains
that the question of the existence of numbers is ‘‘factually empty.’’ Really, there is a deep difference
between the two positions, since Balaguer does not distinguish two questions as Carnap does. Like
10
someone who thought that the plain, literal meaning of ‘‘Prime numbers greater than 1010 exist’’ was
1010
‘‘Prime numbers greater than 10 are ingredients of ultimate metaphysical Reality,’’ Balaguer
declines to join Carnap in answering, ‘‘Yes, of course,’’ to the question, ‘‘Do numbers exist?’’ If
doubters as well as deniers of numbers are counted as nominalists, then his refusal to return an
affirmative answer to the question whether numbers exist makes Balaguer a kind of nominalist.
64 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
perspective on Nietzsche – this is the only way to make sense of questions
of ontological metaphysics. The Carnapian claim that ontological meta-
physics is meaningless is roughly equivalent to the conjunction of
this Nietzsche–Dummett thesis, ‘‘realism makes sense only on a theistic
basis,’’ with analytic atheism, the thesis that theological language is mean-
ingless. Both these theses are highly controversial: analytic atheism was
explicitly rejected even by outspoken agnostics like Russell, and the
Nietzsche–Dummett thesis is rejected by many philosophers in Australia
who regard themselves as simultaneously ‘‘realists’’ in some strong sense,
and ‘‘physicalists’’ in some sense equally strong.
I myself believe, like Russell, that analytic atheism is false, and suspect,
contrary to the Australians, that the Nietzsche–Dummett thesis is true. If as
I believe the theological question does make sense, and if as I suspect it is
the only sensible question about the italics-added real or capital-R Real
existence of numbers, then I would answer that question in the negative;
but then I would equally answer in the negative the question of the Real
existence of just about anything. For as has been said elsewhere, everything
we have learned about our processes of cognition points in the direction of
the conclusion that even other intelligent creatures, to say nothing of an
Omniscient Creator, would or might well have patterns of language and
thought very different from ours, recognizing categories of objects very
different from those we recognize, or perhaps not even having a category of
‘‘objects’’ at all, if they used a language without a category of nouns, as well
they might.
Since I do not wish to claim that the absence of empirical meaning is
tantamount to the absence of all meaning, where Carnap would put
forward a categorical negative, ‘‘These questions are meaningless,’’ I only
put forward a rhetorical question, ‘‘What are these questions supposed to
mean?’’ But I do agree with Carnap that the question of the Real existence
of mathematical entities does lack empirical meaning, and while I do not
think this settles the question of nominalism, I think it does have an
important bearing on the question of how much mathematics is like
novels, fables, and other forms of fiction.
For consider the question whether, say, the works of Carlos Castañeda
or Rigoberta Menchù are non-fiction or fiction: are they eye-witness
reportage of magic or tragic occurrences, or merely novels masquerading
as anthropology or autobiography? In these cases, we know very well what
it would have looked like for the events in Menchù’s book to have occurred,
and in this age of cinematic special effects, we can even say the same for
Castañeda’s books. By contrast, as regards the question of the ultimate
Mathematics and Bleak House 65
metaphysical Reality of numbers, we have absolutely no idea of what
difference it would make to how things look; or rather, we have a very
strong suspicion that it would make no difference at all. This is what is
meant by having an empirically meaningful question in one case, and an
empirically meaningless question in the other.14
I think that in view of this radical difference between mathematics and
novels, fables, or other literary genres, the slogan ‘‘mathematics is a fiction’’
is not very appropriate, and the comparison of mathematics to fiction not
very apt. My conclusion is that, whatever may remain to be said for or
against nominalism, about whether we should or should not call ourselves
‘‘nominalists,’’ we should not call ourselves ‘‘fictionalists.’’
14
In other words, I mean no more by saying that the choice between two views is ‘‘empirically
meaningless’’ than that the two views themselves are empirically equivalent. Thus understood, it is
a trivial truism that there is no empirically meaningful difference between any given theory T, and
the fictionalist alternative T * according to which everything observable happens as if theory T were
true, though it is not. What would be highly non-trivial would be the claim that the difference
between T and T * is meaningless tout court et sans phrase. But that would only follow from empirical
meaninglessness assuming a discredited empiricist criterion of meaningfulness.
4
1 TWO SENSES OF ‘‘ F O U N D A T I O N S O F M A T H E M A T I C S ’’
Does mathematics requires a foundation?1 The first thing that must be said
about the question is that the expression ‘‘foundations of mathematics’’ is
ambiguous. Let me explain.
Modern mathematicians inherited from antiquity an ideal of rigor,
according to which each mathematical theorem should be deduced from
previously admitted results, and ultimately from an explicit list of postu-
lates. It also inherited a further ideal according to which the postulates
should be self-evidently true. During the great creative period of early
modern mathematics, there were and probably had to be many departures
from both ideals. But during the century before last, as mathematicians
were driven or drawn to consider less familiar mathematical structures,
from hyperbolic spaces to hypercomplex numbers, the need for rigor was
increasingly felt, and higher standards were eventually instituted. But while
the ideal of rigor may be claimed to have been realized, the ideal of self-
evidence was not.
Considering only the ideal of rigor, the working mathematician’s under-
standing of its requirements, of what is permissible in the way of modes of
definition and modes of deduction of new mathematical notions and
results from old, is largely implicit. Logic, which investigates such matters,
and fixes explicit canons, is a subject in which the algebraist, analyst, or
geometer need never take a formal course. Nor are mathematicians in
practice much concerned with tracing back the chain of definitions and
deductions beyond the recent literature in their fields to the ultimate
1
This question was the title of the Arché Institute conference, August 12–15, 2002, where a preliminary
version of this paper was first delivered. I would like to thank the leadership of the institute and local
organizers of the affair, and especially Crispin Wright and Fraser MacBride, for making my
participation both possible and pleasurable, and my fellow participants for valuable feedback on
the preliminary draft.
66
Quine, analyticity, and philosophy of mathematics 67
primitives and postulates. But there is a place, and one even may go so far as
to say a need, for someone to investigate the choice of postulates, and what
differences a different choice would make. It is these kinds of investiga-
tions, when carried out by mathematical means, that in standard classi-
fications of the branches of mathematics are called ‘‘logic and foundations.’’
Or rather, that label is applied to the kind of investigation just mentioned
plus any other research that can fruitfully apply the same methods.
This, then, is the first and weaker of two senses in which the term
‘‘foundations’’ is used. There will be a need for ‘‘foundations of mathe-
matics’’ in this first sense so long as mathematicians continue to adhere to
an ideal of rigor, and – despite hype from some popularizers about ‘‘the
death of proof ’’ – that would mean for the foreseeable future.
But there is a second and stronger sense, in which one would speak of a
‘‘foundation’’ for mathematics only if, in addition to the ideal of rigor, the
ideal of self-evidence or something like it were realized. Though I have
listed this sense second, it is presumably older, since it is only if something
like the ideal of self-evidence is realized that the metaphor implicit in the
word ‘‘foundations’’ is appropriate. Postulates with something like self-
evidence would provide the firm foundations of the edifice of mathematics,
and this firmness together with the firmness of the rigor by which new
results are built upon old would guarantee the firmness of the higher
stories. This picture is merely the application to mathematics of the picture
offered by epistemological ‘‘foundationalism,’’ according to which the
edifice of knowledge is to be built up from a secure and privileged basis
by secure and privileged means.
Mathematicians have learned to live with the absence of self-evident
postulates, of ‘‘foundations,’’ and in this sense passively acquiesce in the
proposition that foundations (in the foundationalist sense) are not
required. Many philosophers remain more troubled by the situation, and
in consequence either lapse into nominalist, constructivist, or other here-
sies, rejecting orthodox mathematics, or involve themselves in programs to
provide the missing foundations.
For a very familiar specific instance of the distinction between two senses
of ‘‘foundations,’’ we may consider the result we have been taught to call
Frege’s theorem, namely, the deducibility of the basic laws of arithmetic
from the postulate we have been taught to call Hume’s principle, according
to which, if there are as many of these as of those, then the number of
the former is equal to the number of the latter. Uncontroversially Frege’s
theorem is a major contribution to foundations of mathematics in the first
and weaker sense, which is concerned with logical relationships between
68 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
postulates and theorems, without too much concern over the status of the
postulates. But there has been a controversy, involving the late George
Boolos and the nominalists on one side, and some of the St Andrews school
on the other, over the status of Hume’s principle, and over whether Frege’s
theorem can provide a foundation for mathematics in the second and
stronger sense.
On one view, Hume’s principle is analytic, Frege’s theorem does provide
such a foundation for arithmetic, and the challenge is to find a way of
providing a similar foundation for more of mathematics. On the other
view, Frege’s theorem does not provide a foundation, and Hume’s princi-
ple is either a synthetic truth, or an untruth. What I want to do here is to
elaborate a third or intermediate position, according to which Hume’s
principle is analytic, but still does not provide a foundation for arithmetic
in the sense of foundationalist epistemology. Naturally this presupposes a
notion of analyticity in which a statement may be analytic but nonetheless
need not be self-evident or a logical consequence of self-evident statements,
or anything of the sort. In sketching the intermediate position I will be
mainly concerned to sketch a conception of analyticity with this feature.
My starting point will be, as my title suggests, the thought of the late
W. V. Quine. His work, by the way, provides another illustration of the
distinction between the two senses of foundations. Quine was, in his
generation, a significant contributor to ‘‘logic and foundations’’ in the
first sense. (I heard it said, by one of my fellow speakers at a memorial
meeting, that asked about his standing on one occasion, he described
himself as ‘‘captain of the B-team’’; and this seems quite a just estimate.)
But Quine was also famously a paradigmatic opponent of epistemological
foundationalism, and the author of the best-known rival to the architec-
tural metaphor. According to Quine, knowledge is not a building but a
web, more or less fixed at the edges by the attachment of observation
sentences to sensory evidence, but underdetermined as to how we spiders
should spin the middle portions, including mathematics, which lies some-
where very near the center.
My reexamination of Quine will be a sequel to an earlier reexamination
of Carnap, entitled ‘‘Mathematics and Bleak House’’ (Burgess, 2004b).
I even thought of entitling the present paper ‘‘Mathematics and Bleak
House II,’’ though in the end I was deterred from doing so when I found
myself having only one occasion to refer to the Dickens novel, mentioning
the police investigator in it, one Bucket, who was for a generation2 the
2
Until the appearance of Sherlock Holmes.
Quine, analyticity, and philosophy of mathematics 69
canonical fictional detective in the English-speaking world. The concern of
my earlier paper with the Dickensian title was to re-evaluate Carnap’s
classic ‘‘Empiricism, semantics, and ontology’’ (Carnap 1950). Here I wish
to consider Quine’s reply, ‘‘Carnap’s views on ontology’’ (Quine 1951a) and
more particularly the famous paper of a few months earlier on which that
reply was based, ‘‘Two dogmas of empiricism’’ (Quine, 1951b).
To put the matter very roughly, Quine argued in replying to Carnap
that the position of Carnap presupposed the analytic-synthetic distinction,
the first of the two dogmas Quine took himself to have refuted. Like some
other recent commentators,3 I dissent from the common view that Quine
clearly vanquished Carnap in their exchange. To put matters very roughly
again, my claim will be that Quine almost needs to recognize a notion of
analyticity – and also that he can recognize such a notion, without betray-
ing his core philosophical principles.
2 QUINIANISM VS PLATONISM
Before I examine the differences between Quine and Carnap, I wish to con-
sider what divides them both from the nominalists. And before I consider
what divides them from the nominalists, I wish to consider what Quine,
Carnap, and many nominalists have in common that divides them from
anyone who would really deserve to be called a ‘‘Platonist’’ in anything like a
traditional sense. I will begin with a sympathetic description of – I do not
pretend it is anything like an argument for – a Quinian world-view.
It was the ambition of Galileo, Kepler, and other worthies of their era, by
close reading of the book of nature, to discover the very intentions of its
great Author in writing it; or, to vary the metaphor, to produce a plan of
the universe faithfully reproducing the blueprint used by its great Architect
in constructing it. For Quine, this is a hopeless ambition: no science
produced by human beings can provide a God’s-eye view of the universe,
and this should be evident almost as soon as one begins to view the human
knower as an object of scientific study.
When human knowers are so viewed, human knowledge, including
especially scientific theorizing, is seen as the product of certain organisms
3
Let me in particular cite two useful unpublished works, the Princeton senior thesis of Tom Dixon
‘‘Separating Semantics from Empiricism and Ontology,’’ and the doctoral dissertation of Inga
Nayding, ‘‘Positing Existence.’’ Both see less difference between Quine and Carnap than perhaps
the two saw between themselves, and both attempt, each in his or her own way, to narrow the
difference still further. I derived encouragement from their example, even though my own way of
attempting to narrow the difference is not quite theirs.
70 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
in a certain environment, seeking to fulfill certain needs. Beavers build
dams; people first construct hydrological theories, and only then construct
dams (unless, having also constructed ecological theories, they decide not to
construct the dams after all). Scientific theories make intelligible patterns
in the environment as we experience it, and in favorable cases make it
possible to influence (or warn us not to try to influence) the course of that
experience. But what science can make intelligible in our experience, and
how it can make it so, inevitably depends on the nature of our intellects,
and what kinds of experience we are capable of. Thus scientific theory,
product of a certain organism in a certain environment, will inevitably be
the way it is in part because that environment, the universe, is the way it is,
and in part because the organisms, ourselves, are the way we are: there is no
reason to suppose intelligent extraterrestrials, with very different kinds of
sensory experience and very different intellects, would produce the same
scientific theories we have.
For that matter, there is not much reason to believe that even if we
ourselves had it to do all over again we would come up with the very same
theories we have. Thus scientific theories are the way they are partly
because the universe is the way it is, partly because we are the way we
are, and partly because of a third factor: partly because the interaction
between the universe and ourselves has gone the way it has. But if our
theories as they are thus differ from what they might equally well have been
had history gone slightly differently, and differ even more from what the
theories of alien creatures might be expected to be like, then a fortiori they
must differ greatly from the ‘‘theories’’ of an omniscient Creator, and the
ambition of gaining a God’s-eye view of the universe must be unrealizable.
Such is the Quinean picture at the highest level of generality.
To descend to a level of slightly greater specificity, one feature of the way
our intellects work is that language is crucial to scientific thought, and our
language exhibits a comparatively limited range of grammatical forms. In
particular, our scientific theories run very much to sentences of the
noun–verb, subject–predicate, object–property type. As we employ sen-
tences of this type over and over in different contexts and with different
functions within scientific theorizing, our scientific theories will be posit-
ing over and over again different kinds of objects with different kinds of
properties.
To be a little more specific still, all this applies the mathematical
apparatus deployed in our scientific theories. Starting with the use of
numerals as adjectives, we have found that to bring out certain patterns a
shift to using them as nouns is required, and so natural numbers have been
Quine, analyticity, and philosophy of mathematics 71
posited. After long speaking only of relations of proportions among geo-
metric magnitudes, we have found it immensely convenient, if not practi-
cally indispensable, to shift to speaking of ratios of magnitudes as objects,
and as objects that can be added and multiplied, and so real numbers have
been posited. Later we have found useful a transition from speaking of real
numbers (plural) with certain properties to speaking of the set (singular) of
such real numbers, thus positing sets as single objects constituted by
pluralities of objects.
We thus end up speaking of different kinds of numbers, sets, functions,
and so forth in sentences of the same grammatical form as ones about
medium-sized dry goods, even though these sentences occupy very differ-
ent positions and roles in the body of our knowledge. ‘‘Septimus is a prig’’
and ‘‘Seventeen is a prime,’’ for instance, have similar grammatical or
logical forms, but very different epistemological positions. The best way
to verify the former would be to locate Septimus in space and time and
interact with him causally: he may sit near us and speak, sending sound-
waves to our ears, by which we detect his priggishness. The number
seventeen does not do anything analogous. It does not sit in Cantor’s
paradise and shine N-rays on our pineal glands, by which we detect its
primality. That arithmetical property is checked by quite different means.
This feature of our actual scientific theories is perhaps one they need not
have had. Whether or not we could have managed to do without any non-
spatial, non-temporal, causally inactive, causally impassive mathematical
objects at all – the partial success of programs of nominalistic reconstruc-
tion of mathematics suggests that in principle this might have been
possible, though examination of the details suggests that in practice it
might not have been feasible – there is no strong reason to suppose that
if we had it to do all over again we would end up with the very same kinds of
mathematical objects. As for the scientific theories of space aliens, not only
is there no strong reason to suppose they would involve distinctive mathe-
matical objects, but what is more, there is no strong reason to suppose they
would involve objects at all, since there is no strong reason to suppose space
aliens would have a language that involved nouns. The Chomskians
maintain that universal grammar is species specific, and in combinatory
and predicate-functor logics we get at least a vague and dim image of what a
language with a grammar radically unlike ours might be like. And as for the
‘‘theories’’ of a Deity, ‘‘we see but through a glass, darkly.’’
Thus Quine – and in this Carnap would surely join him – can concede
to the nominalist that the (particular kinds of) mathematical objects that
figure in our current scientific theories are there largely because of the way
72 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
we are (and the way our interaction with the universe has gone) rather than
because of the way the universe is. The positing of numbers may be
extremely convenient and in practice even indispensably necessary for us,
but theories that involve such posits cannot be claimed to give a God’s-eye
view of the universe, to reflect ultimate nature of metaphysical reality, or
anything of the sort.
3 QUINIANISM VS ‘‘ F I C T I O N A L I S M ’’
What Quine – and again Carnap would surely be with him – will not
concede to the nominalist is that any of this gives us any reason at all to
reject current science and mathematics. It gives us no reason why we should
perform, on entering the philosophy seminar room, a ceremony of abjura-
tion, recanting what we habitually say outside that room, when engaged in
scientific work or in daily life. No theory of ours can give a God’s-eye view
of the universe: ‘‘the trail of the human serpent’’ will be over all. But the fact
that any particular theory fails to deliver a reflection of the ultimate nature
of metaphysical reality, uncontaminated by any contribution from us, is no
special grounds for complaint against that particular theory. If there are
grounds for complaint, it is against the human condition.
And thus Quine is willing to speak inside the philosophy room in the
same terms in which he speaks outside it, neither taking back, nor explain-
ing away, nor apologizing for, the use of number-laden or set-laden
language. Rather he is willing to reiterate in his capacity as philosopher
the theorems of mathematics and theories of science. To apply the words
used by the great Scottish philosopher in a somewhat different context,
‘‘Nothing else can be appealed to in the field, or in the senate. Nothing else
ought ever to be heard of in the school, or in the closet.’’4
Here we have direct opposition to the most common kind of nominalist
today. They do take back in their philosophical moments what they assert in
their scientific moments. And for most of them, that is about all they do by
way of expression of their nominalist allegiances: few nominalists any more
are involved in active programs for reconstructing science on a number- and
set-free basis. This kind of inactive nominalism is generally called ‘‘fiction-
alism’’5 and in my earlier paper on Carnap it was the contrast between his
4
David Hume, ‘‘On the practical consequences of natural religion, or, Of a particular providence and
a future State,’’ in Enquiry Concerning the Human Understanding, Part XI.
5
The label is also used by some activists like Hartry Field, whose views I am leaving to one side in the
present discussion.
Quine, analyticity, and philosophy of mathematics 73
views and fictionalism that was my topic. Much that I said there about
Carnapian anti-fictionalism applies also to Quinian anti-fictionalism, and I
will recapitulate briefly.
The first thing to be said against ‘‘fictionalism’’ is that the label is
remarkably ill chosen. To say, for instance, that Victorians regarded Bleak
House as fiction, is among other things to say that when Victorians were in
need of the services of a good detective, they did not waste any time looking
for Bucket. They did not use the contents of the novel as a guide to
practice.6 The label ‘‘fictionalist’’ for the dominant contemporary variety
of nominalism is ill chosen because those nominalists who apply the label to
themselves do not in fact regard current mathematically formulated ordi-
nary and scientific lore and theory in the same way they regard the
productions of Dickens or other novelists. They do use such lore and such
theory as a guide to practice.
The analogy ‘‘fictionalists’’ cite ought to be, not with works of imagi-
native literature, but with scientific theories that are regarded as no more
than useful approximations to more complex but truer theories, known or
remaining to be developed. An architect, for instance, designing a modest
private residence, will obviously have to take into account the topography
of the site, the fact that some points on the site are at a higher elevation
above sea level than others, but generally will not take into account the
curvature of the earth, or the fact that points at the same elevation do not lie
on a perfect plane. To this extent, the architect is using as a guide to
practice the primeval theory that the earth is flat, though no architect today
believes any such thing.
Here is a case where a theory is rejected, a theory is not believed, and yet
that theory is not regarded as fiction, as a work of creative writing, but
rather is used as a guide to practice, is employed for practical purposes. The
analogy the mislabeled ‘‘fictionalists’’ ought to be citing is with such cases,
with uses of flat-earth geography when we know the earth is round, or of
Newtonian gravitational theory when we know it is only an approximation
to Einsteinian general relativity, or indeed of this last when we know it
needs a quantum correction, though we do not as yet have a developed
theory of quantum gravity.
But the citation of such examples soon makes evident a serious disanalogy
between the attitude of the nominalist and that of the scientist or engineer
who makes use of a theory known to be only a simplified approximation.
6
At least not in the way they would have used it as a guide had they thought it non-fiction: for all
I know, some readers may have been stirred by it to work for reforms in the Court of Chancery.
74 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
This can be brought out by considering an architectural firm suddenly given
a commission for a much larger project than the private homes that are all
they had built before. They would need to take into account the fact they had
been ignoring, that the earth is round, and recalculate whether it is safe to
ignore its curvature on the new and larger scale on which they would be
working. If the project were as vast as the Very Large Array,7 clearly they
could not get away with treating the earth’s surface as flat, they way they can
in building a house on a half-acre lot. For projects of intermediate size, they
would have to think at least for a moment about the question, or ask some
consulting engineer whether flat-earth geography can still be trusted. And
the engineer would base the calculation on round-earth geography: just how
far flat-earth theory can be trusted for architectural purposes is something
that is estimated in terms of round-earth theory.
The situation is similar in all cases of technical and everyday applications
of theories that are not really accepted in the sense of being not really
believed. The scientific and technical application of an approximation is
always framed by some kind of estimate of how good the approximation is,
obtained from some more accurate and credible theory, whether fully
developed or still a work in progress.
The situation is quite dissimilar in the case of the nominalists’ attitude
towards mathematics, pure and applied. Here there is no question of the
untruth of ordinary and scientific theories ever being relevant to practical
questions. Nor is there any nominalistic alternative theory present in the
background, or being sought. Rather, ‘‘fictionalism’’ became the dominant
form of nominalism in the 1990s largely as a result of disappointment with
the search for nominalist alternatives to standard mathematical formula-
tions of scientific theories in the 1980s. The dissimilarity and disanalogy
I have been describing marks nominalism as a non-, un-, or anti-scientific,
and distinctively philosophical concern. For a Quinean, this feature – a
willingness to say that some formulation is acceptable in everyday and all
scientific contexts, however theoretical, but still not acceptable in the
philosophy seminar room – would mark nominalism of the contemporary
kind as involving a species of old-fashioned alienated epistemology as
opposed to the ‘‘naturalized’’ epistemology Quine promoted.
Now, though I cannot discuss Carnap at length here, I believe that the
position he held by the 1950s was not fundamentally different in this respect
7
An arrangement of radio dish-antennas spread out over twenty miles or more, used for radio
astronomy.
Quine, analyticity, and philosophy of mathematics 75
from that I have just associated with the name of Quine. Thus, just as Quine
and Carnap and ‘‘fictionalists’’ are all agreed that our current science, partly
owing to its being mathematically formulated, does not present a God’s-eye
view of the universe, so also Quine and Carnap agree that the nominalist
suggestion that current science should therefore be regarded as only a
‘‘useful fiction’’ is to be rejected.
To put the matter another way, the ‘‘fictionalist’’ nominalist considers
that, even when we have answered in the affirmative whether an apparatus
of numbers and/or other mathematical objects does or will figure in the
best physical theory, there remains a further question, whether numbers
really exist, which they answer in the negative. Quine and Carnap agree in
doubting that there is any intelligible question of this form.
4 QUINIANISM VS CARNAPIANISM
Thus the issue between Quine and Carnap on one side, and ‘‘fictionalist’’
nominalism on the other side, is over the intelligibility or appropriateness
of the question, ‘‘Science and common sense aside, are there really num-
bers?’’ The issue between Quine on one side and Carnap on the other can
also be represented as a difference over whether or not a certain question
arises, or more precisely, over whether such a question as, say, ‘‘If I have as
many fingers as toes, is the number of my fingers equal to the number of
my toes?’’ arises in more than one sense. Carnap famously thought there
were two senses to such a question, internal and external to the ‘‘linguistic
framework’’ of number – or, as I will say, to the ‘‘concept’’ of number –
where Quine took there to be only one question.
Taking the concept of number for granted – as the Carnapian is justified
in doing, since the questioner has used the term ‘‘number’’ in framing the
question – the question admits an immediate positive answer: that if
one has as many fingers as toes, then the number of one’s fingers is the same
as the number of one’s toes, is something that ‘‘comes with’’ or ‘‘is part of ’’
the concept, and in this sense is analytic. This is the first, ‘‘internal’’ way of
taking the question.
But there is another, ‘‘external’’ way of taking it. Perhaps in asking the
question what the questioner really means to do is to raise the issue whether
we should accept the concept of number. The ‘‘material mode’’ formula-
tion, which has the appearance of presupposing the concept of number,
may be misleading in this respect. Perhaps what is really being questioned
is, put in the less misleading ‘‘formal mode,’’ simply this: is the concept of
‘‘number’’ to be accepted?
76 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
This question is certainly one the Carnapian is willing to discuss, and the
answer to this external question will take longer to give than did the answer
to the internal question. What the Carnapian will insist is that in discussing
why we accept the concept of ‘‘number,’’ questions about the correspond-
ence of that concept to a feature of ultimate metaphysical reality are out of
order. The considerations the Carnapian advances will rather be broadly
speaking ‘‘pragmatic.’’
Thus, for Carnap, the immediate affirmative answer is justified by
appeal to linguistic considerations (by the consideration that Hume’s
principle or something like is analytic); by contrast, the further question
why to accept that concept takes longer to answer, and the ultimate
affirmative answer is justified largely by appeal to pragmatic considerations
(by the consideration of the utility of mathematical formulations in scien-
tific theory). Quine, rejecting the analytic–synthetic distinction, cannot
recognize that there are two questions here.
I have said that I belong to the minority who are not so sure Quine
scored a victory in his debate with Carnap; but what I want now to say is
that if he did score a victory, it was a pyrrhic one. For in rejecting the
distinction between the two ways of taking the question, Quine seems to
deprive himself of any justification for giving it an immediate affirmative
answer. For Quine the answer is ultimately affirmative, to be sure, but his
right to give this answer seems to depend on the whole long story, involving
pragmatic considerations, that has to be told to answer Carnap’s second
question. And this lays Quine open to the objection raised especially by
Charles Parsons, that his account of matters cannot do justice to the felt
obviousness of elementary mathematics. (He acknowledges the existence of
the feeling, but has no apparatus with which to explain it.)
I myself consider this type of objection so serious that a Quinian ought
to want to be able to endorse some notion of analyticity that would allow
an immediate affirmative answer, ‘‘Yes, that’s analytic,’’ or ‘‘Yes, that’s just
part of the concept.’’ It may be an exaggeration to say Quine needs a notion
of analyticity if his position is to be at all plausible, since other means by
which an immediate affirmative answer could be justified have not been
explored; but certainly the most obvious means would be to accept some
notion of analyticity.
(Note that ‘‘fictionalists’’ have no trouble returning, with their fingers
crossed, an immediate affirmative answer to the question, which they will
retract upon entering the philosophy seminar room. Then they will claim
that all they meant was, ‘‘Yes, that’s part of the usual fairy tale,’’ or ‘‘Yes,
that’s how the traditional legend goes.’’)
Quine, analyticity, and philosophy of mathematics 77
8
‘‘Problems and changes in the empiricist criterion of meaning’’ (Hempel 1950) immediately followed
Carnap (1950), ‘‘Empiricism, semantics, and ontology,’’ in the same issue of the same journal.
9
I intend ‘‘laws of logic’’ to be neutral here as between what would correspond in a formal system to
axioms and what would correspond to rules. That there would have to be at least one rule is the lesson
of Quine (1936).
78 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
any conception, and again on Quine’s, we are supposed to be able to grasp
the connection between observational terms and predicates and observable
objects and properties. What remains to be considered are theoretical terms
and predicates that are non-logical but also non-observational.
Here the obvious candidate for a surveyable, graspable something asso-
ciated with an item of vocabulary would be some core theory, some basic
laws. For a theoretical term generally is learnt along with a batch of related
theoretical terms, and along with a batch of basic laws involving the given
term and those other terms. The surveyable, graspable, body of basic laws
does in at least one obvious sense guide subsequent usage of the term, and if
one calls this surveyable, graspable, usage-guiding body a meaning, then it
can be said that the basic laws that are members of that body are part of the
meaning of the theoretical term, or part of the concept expressed by that
term, and in that sense analytic.
Now already this fall-back notion of analyticity differs appreciably from
more traditional notions of analyticity, and cannot do all the same work.
Notably, to call something ‘‘analytic’’ in this sense is not at all to call it
unproblematic. What is analytic must be accepted if the concept is accepted,
but then perhaps the concept should not be accepted!10 The basic laws may,
after all, be internally inconsistent, either obviously so, as with Prior’s ‘‘tonk,’’
or less obviously so, as with Frege’s infamous law V.11 Or the basic laws may
have implications clashing with the results of observation. Or the term and
concept may simply be otiose, creating clutter and doing no useful work.
For a Quinian, the fact that the analytic need not be unproblematic
would not be an unwelcome feature. For certainly Quine wants to be able
to say that there is a question whether one should accept a given concept or
not, though indeed such questions are to be resolved by pragmatic consid-
erations, and not on the basis of whether or not the concept corresponds to
an ingredient of ultimate metaphysical reality. To concede that, say,
Hume’s principle, is analytic in the indicated sense would permit Quine
to join Carnap in giving an immediate affirmative answer to the question
whether the number of my fingers is the same as the number of my toes,
10
An alternative closer to the traditional notion would be to count as part of the meaning of the term
only such laws as have the form of an equation or a biconditional and the status of an abbreviatory
definition. But as Quine correctly points out, the same equation or biconditional may have the status
of a definition in one exposition and lack it in another.
11
In such a case, where there is a word, a more or less definite list of basic laws, and an inconsistency in
that list, should we say that there is a concept, but it is an inconsistent and therefore unacceptable
one, or that there simply is no concept? I follow the former usage, but have found some other
philosophers very strongly attached to the latter. I consider this a purely verbal issue in the sense of
‘‘purely verbal issue’’ to be discussed below.
Quine, analyticity, and philosophy of mathematics 79
while still doing justice to the thought that somehow its pragmatic role in
scientific theorizing is relevant to the question why we regard Riemann’s
On the Hypotheses Which Lie at the Foundations of Geometry as a contribu-
tion to science, and Dickens’ Bleak House (finished just the year before) as a
contribution to art.
This rather untraditional notion of analyticity would in fact seem to be
just what Quine should want, if he is to be able both to remain faithful to his
core philosophical principle that the ultimate grounds for regarding mathe-
matics or anything else as non-fiction rather than fiction are pragmatic, and
also to explain the felt obviousness of elementary arithmetic. And yet Quine
will accept neither this nor any other analytic–synthetic distinction.
And why not? Why does Quine reject the kind of theory of meaning
I have just been very abstractly and very vaguely describing? Well, he does
not discuss that particular kind of theory specifically, but he thinks he has
reasons for rejecting any theory of meaning at all. He allows that if the
notion of synonymy, or sameness of meaning, could be made sense of, then
meanings could be admitted, being identifiable, if all else fails, with
equivalence classes of expressions under the equivalence relation of syno-
nymy. He allows that synonymy can be made sense of in terms of analy-
ticity, and vice versa. But he famously denies that either of the two can be
made sense of in a scientifically acceptable way.
But as the earliest replies to ‘‘Two dogmas’’ recognized, Quine in making
his case is taking for granted some not-uncontroversial assumptions about
what is scientifically acceptable in a linguistic or other psychological
inquiry. As Grice and Strawson (1956) put it, he is assuming that only
some kind of ‘‘combinatorial’’ or ‘‘behavioral’’ account could make a
linguistic or psychological posit respectable. Quine’s general complaint
about analyticity, as applied to the particular kind of picture of analyticity
vaguely sketched above, amount to just this: that there is no clear combi-
natorial or behavioral criterion for distinguishing which laws count as
‘‘basic’’ and therefore ‘‘constitutive of the meaning’’ of a term, and which
count as ‘‘non-basic’’ and ‘‘additional to the meaning’’ of the term.
The assumption that there would have to be such a criterion before the
notion could be respectable and acceptable is just an instance of the same
behavioristic assumptions that notoriously led Quine to write that ‘‘differ-
ent persons growing up in the same language are like different bushes
trimmed and trained to take the shape of identical elephants. The anatom-
ical details of twigs and branches will fulfill the elephantine form differ-
ently from bush to bush, but the overall outward results are alike’’ (Quine
1960, p. 8). The canonical objection to this assumption is given in
80 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
Chomsky’s devastating review of Skinner’s Verbal Behavior (Chomsky,
1959): children’s language grows to resemble that of their parents with
strikingly little input. The resemblance between the two bushes cannot be
simply the result of their being trimmed the same way, because the garden-
ers have done very little trimming.
The conclusion is that if one is to get anywhere thinking about language,
one is going to have to learn to think outside the Skinner box. The brain is
not an organ for cooling the blood, and one is not going to get anywhere
trying to understand the complex relations between sensory input and
behavioral output simply by seeking correlations between the two, treating
everything going on in-between in the brain and elsewhere as a black box.
Nor can one wait until neuroscience finds the relevant physical structures
inside the skull before bringing them into psychological theorizing.
Without some theorizing in advance, one would not even know what to
look for inside the skull, any more than, without Mendel’s positing
‘‘factors’’ and formulating laws of heredity in terms of these, would one
have known what to look for in seeking the physical basis of heredity.
Theoretical posits, including meanings of a kind that bring with them a
distinction between analytic and synthetic, must be allowed even if they are
not directly manifested in observable behavior – provided that they play a
useful role in explaining the phenomena of language and thought.
This, no doubt, most philosophers today will grant, and Quine’s failure
to grant it dates his classic paper more than any other feature. And yet, even
granting that behaviorism of any kind, logical or substantial or methodo-
logical, is to be rejected, and that non-behaviorist programs positing
meanings are to be not just tolerated but even encouraged, there is still
this much to be said for Quine’s skepticism about meanings: no stable
consensus in favor of any one such program has as yet emerged among
either linguists or philosophers. There is nothing that could be called a
body of accepted scientific conclusions about meaning or analyticity that
workers in other areas, such as philosophy of mathematics, can draw upon
and apply to their concerns. And this being so, the question retains some
interest whether a notion of analyticity can be developed without introduc-
ing unobservable theoretical posits, and without stepping outside the
boundaries within which Quine confined himself.
6 QUINIANISM VS INTUITIONISM
12
The allusion is to the double negation interpretation, by which classical ‘‘either / or’’ becomes
intuitionistic ‘‘not neither / nor,’’ and to the modal interpretations, by which intuitionistic
‘‘either / or’’ becomes classical ‘‘it is constructively provable that either / or.’’
13
Witness the immense literature spawned by Michael Dummett’s neo-intuitionism, for instance.
14
Quine (1970, p. 81). Two pages later it says that ‘‘he may not be wrong in doing so,’’ meaning that the
reasons or motives for deviations from classical logic must be examined, though Quine in fact
ultimately rejects them on pragmatic grounds. Quine’s position in these passages seems not far from
conceding that the intuitionistically unacceptable classical laws, say, may be called ‘‘analytic’’
provided that term is not taken to imply ‘‘unproblematic’’ or ‘‘incorrigible.’’ This contrasts with
his official view in Chapter 7 of the same work.
Quine, analyticity, and philosophy of mathematics 83
over the law, it would be helpful for the minority or perhaps even both sides to
stop using the term or at least to attach some distinguishing modifier to it. Such
basic statements would then count as analytic.15 This proposal makes the
notion of analyticity vague, a matter of degree, and relative to interests and
purposes: just as vague, just as much a matter of degree, and just as relative
to interests and purposes, as ‘‘helpful.’’ But the notion, if vague, and a
matter of degree, and relative, is also pragmatic, and certainly involves no
positing of unobservable psycholinguistic entities, and for these reasons
seems within the bounds of what a Quinian could accept.
There is no denying that utility of the notion is limited by its vagueness,
and yet I think there are some non-trivial cases that are comparatively if not
absolutely clear. The intuitionist case just discussed is one of them, and
I think that the case of greatest interest in the present context, Hume’s
principle, is another. That is to say, I think Hume’s principle can be called
analytic in the sense that it would be helpful if ‘‘fictionalists’’ would stop
saying things like ‘‘I grant that if numbers exist then Hume’s principle is
true of them, but I don’t grant that numbers exist,’’ and instead just
abandoned (inside the philosophy seminar room) the use of the term
‘‘number’’ (with the usual exception of use in negative existentials and in
indirect discourse), and said instead, ‘‘I don’t grant that use of ‘number’ is
accepted, though I grant that if it is accepted, it should be used in accord-
ance with Hume’s principle.’’
What is the difference here? Well, the first formulation tends to turn
discussion in the direction of the question, ‘‘Do numbers exist?’’ And this is
a question that cannot usefully be debated between anti-nominalists and
nominalists, since there is simply no agreement at all between them as to
what would constitute a relevant consideration in favor of or against the
statement that numbers exist. (It was in connection with this point that in
my earlier paper I alluded to the interminable lawsuit Jarndyce and Jarndyce
in Dickens.)
By contrast, much as in the intuitionist case, the second formulation
tends to turn discussion in the direction of issues about what makes it
appropriate or inappropriate to accept a given concept (in a philosophical
as opposed to a scientific context). Though, again as in the intuitionist case,
there is no guarantee that thus turning from the object level to the meta-
level of discourse will result in convergence of opinion, an airing of differ-
ences at the meta-level can at least somewhat clarify why there seems to be
15
As would their logical consequences, at least in contexts where, in contrast to the examples above,
there is no disagreement over logic.
84 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
so little chance of achieving agreement at the object level, and debate over
the criteria of acceptability of concepts does not seem as wholly futile as
does debate at the object level, where it seems impossible for either side to
do more than argue in a (vicious or virtuous) circle.
I will not press the point, however, but will leave it to the reader to
ponder. What I want to do instead, before closing, is to consider one all-
too-obvious complaint about the notion of analyticity proposed. The
proposed notion of ‘‘analyticity’’ seems, in its relativity and vagueness, as
well as in its failure to imply unproblematicity, so different from traditional
ones as to make it unhelpful to use the traditional term for it, or at least
unhelpful to use that term without some distinguishing modifier. Hence
by my own principles I ought at least to add a qualifying adjective. Let me
therefore do so, and close by commending to Quinians and non-Quinians
alike a notion that may be called that of the pragmatic analytic.
5
2 REVOLUTIONARY RUMBLINGS
1
Lest footnotes and bibliography become longer than the paper proper, I will refer the reader to the
long list of references at the end of Burgess and Rosen (1997) for the full titles and bibliographical data
of the relevant works of all the various authors alluded to in passing here, from Alston to Zermelo.
Exceptions must be made in the case of two more recent authors whom Rosen and I did not discuss
in our book. One is Yablo, whom Rosen does discuss in Rosen and Burgess (2005). (My role in
producing the chapter involved little more than some rewriting of Rosen’s work to make it fit within
the editor’s word limit.) But I advise the reader to visit Yablo’s website (www.mit.edu/yablo/
home.html) for the most up-to-date listing of his works, since he is actively engaged in producing new
material, all of it intriguing whether one agrees with it or not.
The other exception is Azzouni (2004). My review has appeared as (Burgess 2004d).
88 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
Cardinal Bellarmine ‘‘correcting’’ scientific theories of planets or of Norman
Malcolm ‘‘correcting’’ scientific theories of dreaming by appeal to the higher
authority of Aristotle or Wittgenstein (as interpreted by themselves).
Generally, revolutionaries profess to be naturalized. But if they are, if
they think their versions of gravitational theory or whatever are superior
scientifically to standard versions, then one might expect them to publish
their work in theoretical physics journals, or at least to attempt to do so. If
‘‘ontological economy’’ of mathematical apparatus really is as important to
scientists as it is to certain philosophers – something I myself very much
doubt, since it is very difficult to find any clear historical instance of such
a preference – such contributions ought to be welcome. Yet the experiment
of submitting a write-up of a nominalist project to a theoretical physics
journal has never been tried, so far as I know, and candid revolutionaries of
a professedly naturalist stamp would probably concede that if undertaken,
the test would very likely be failed: the papers would not make it through
peer review. But if this is admitted, how can a revolutionary profess to be a
naturalist, adhering to scientific standards in judging theories?
One common line is to claim that though nominalist physics is perhaps
not superior to mathematical physics by the standards of physicists, what
really need to be compared are not just the two versions of physics, but
rather two packages of combined physics and epistemology. Somehow
nominalist revision, which may make the job of the physicist more diffi-
cult, is supposed to make the job of the naturalized, scientific epistemol-
ogist easier. In what way? It is at this point that nominalists of the school
I have been alluding to bring forward their appropriation of Benacerraf’s
discussion of knowledge in his famous paper ‘‘Mathematical truth.’’ The
so-called Benacerraf problem is the puzzle, ‘‘How could we come to know
anything asserting or implying or presupposing that there are numbers or
functions or sets, given that it does not make sense to ascribe spatiotemporal
location or causal powers to such mathematical entities?’’ Nominalism
provides a very easy answer to this ‘‘How can we?’’ question – namely, the
answer ‘‘We can’t!’’ – which otherwise would be a difficult one, it is said.
This line of thought involves a serious confusion, which can be brought
out by considering what properties a belief must have in order to rank as
knowledge. These are three: justification, truth, and whatever it takes to
bridge the gap between justified true belief and knowledge that was
discovered by Edmund Gettier. But the epistemological argument for
nominalism is not about Gettierology. Nor is it really about truth. (The
nominalist argues that standard mathematical existence theorems cannot
be known to be true as a way of avoiding directly confronting the question
Being explained away 89
of whether they are true.) So the issue is one of justification. Once this is
appreciated, it can be seen that the whole idea of trading costs to physics
against benefits to epistemology is a muddle. For providing an explanation
of the historical fact that current mathematical and scientific theories have
come to be believed will be an important task for scientific, naturalized
epistemology regardless of whether or not one takes belief in those theories
to be justified. This task is in no way made easier by the assumption that
the belief in question is unjustified.
The obvious anti-nominalist solution to the Benacerraf puzzle is to
suggest that if you cannot think how we could justifiably come to believe
anything implying, say, ‘‘There are functions,’’ then just look at how mathe-
maticians come to believe, say, Gödel’s result, ‘‘There are solutions to the
field equations of general relativity with closed time-like paths.’’ That’s how
one can justifiably come to believe something implying ‘‘There are func-
tions.’’ The revolutionary nominalist who rejects this answer must think the
actual historical process leading to belief in this theorem of Gödel’s is
somehow not a justifiable process of belief-formation. But it is virtually a
tautology that the belief arrived at is justifiable by mathematico-scientific
standards. And hence the revolutionary nominalist’s position, according to
which it is unjustifiable, must involve covert appeal to suprascientific philo-
sophical standards of justification – must be alienated – after all.
To vary the example, let us consider the claim of nominalists who
maintain that what they are appealing to is just ‘‘what science teaches us
about how we humans obtain knowledge,’’ and see how this applies to, say,
the belief that more than a half-dozen books advocating nominalism have
been published in the past three decades or so. By ‘‘books’’ here I clearly do
not mean concrete book tokens, since there are not just ‘‘more than a half-
dozen’’ but hundreds or thousands of such tokens, scattered through
various institutional and personal libraries. So the belief in question is
one about abstract book types, and hence according to the nominalist must
be something ‘‘science teaches us’’ we cannot know. But is this a teaching of
science, or of some Procrustean epistemological theory? If you asked me for
evidence to justify the belief that more than a half-dozen books advocating
nominalism have been published in the past three decades or so, I could
point to various book tokens on the shelves of my office, with titles like
Ontology and the Vicious Circle Principle and Science without Numbers
and Mathematics without Numbers, and names like ‘‘Hartry H. Field’’ and
‘‘Charles S. Chihara’’ and ‘‘Geoffrey Hellman’’ on the title page, along with
dates like 1973 and 1980 and 1989. Can anyone seriously maintain that science
teaches us that this is insufficient evidence?
90 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
3 HERMENEUTICAL HI-JINKS
To show James is not just making this up, I could reproduced much-
quoted passages from Galileo’s Assayer and Kepler’s Astronomia Nova, but
let me forbear.
The goal for those who accepted this picture was to produce a descrip-
tion of reality ‘‘just as it is in itself,’’ or equivalently a description of the
universe as God sees it, and not as we see it. (Take the invocation of the
Deity literally or metaphorically as you choose.) Such a description would
necessarily be very different from the description of our environment
which we use in everyday life. (According to the seventeenth-century
worthies I have been alluding to, a chief difference would be that the colors
and sounds and odors we see and hear and smell would be gone, and only
size and shape and position, along with speed and direction of motion,
would be left.)
But as David Hume already saw, if one makes one’s standard for
‘‘knowledge’’ the possession of a representation of reality that describes it
‘‘just as it is in itself,’’ then the consequence will ‘‘an universal skepticism’’
and the conclusion that ‘‘knowledge’’ is impossible. Hence Immanuel
Kant’s Copernican revolution. For Kant, the aim is still to separate out,
in our ordinary and scientific accounts of the world, what is contributed by
the world and what by us; but instead of attempting to do this by
producing an account with nothing contributed by us, Kant proposed to
proceed the other way around, by producing an account with nothing
contributed by the world, an account of the pure forms of sensibility and
categories of the understanding supplied by us, into which the world pours
empirical content.
In the century and a half between Kant and Carnap, which I will leap
over in a single bound, there was really surprisingly little change in the
nature of the project. With Carnap there is more talk of ‘‘linguistic frame-
works’’ and less of ‘‘pure forms of sensibility’’ or ‘‘categories of the under-
standing,’’ and there is a shift from claims about what we inevitably must
impose to claims about what we conventionally do impose on the world. But
even if for Carnap there is no one conceptual scheme we must impose on
the world, yet still we must impose some conceptual scheme or other, and
94 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
there can be no question of getting behind any and every conceptual
scheme to the world ‘‘just as it is in itself.’’ Alongside this agreement of
substance between Kant and Carnap, there is a disagreement over termi-
nology, and in particular over the role of the term ‘‘metaphysics.’’
Originally this term applied to the attempt to get behind our conceptual
schemes to a God’s-eye view of reality, something Kant and Carnap agree is
impossible. Kant proposes to use it instead for his own project of articulat-
ing just what the scheme our intuition and understanding impose on the
world amounts to. Carnap, by contrast, proposes simply to retire the term.
Thus for Kant ‘‘the future of metaphysics is critique,’’ while for Carnap
metaphysics has no future.
Against Carnap, Quine claimed that while the fabric of our theory of the
world is ‘‘white with convention’’ and ‘‘black with fact,’’ there are no purely
black threads and no purely white threads in it. The point about black had,
in effect, already been conceded, or rather insisted upon, by Carnap when
he argued, contra Moritz Schlick, that the evidence in science consists of
corrigible reports of observations about the furniture and implements of
the laboratory, and not incorrigible reports about sense-data. The point
about white, about the existence of a purely conventional element, was the
issue between Carnap and Quine.
Quine’s contention was just this. Suppose, as Carnap maintains, we
generally favor one linguistic framework or conceptual scheme over another
on grounds of convenience: in attempting to describe the world, we find it
better suits our purposes to do so in using this framework or scheme rather
than that. Well, what sort of fact is this fact that one scheme is more
convenient than another for us to use in attempting to deal with the world?
It would seem to be a fact not just about us, but also about the world: we are
such and it is such that we can more successfully deal with it in this way rather
than that. So the scheme is not, after all, something contributed purely by us,
since part of the reason we choose it is that the world lends itself to description
in terms of these conceptual resources rather than others.
Rightly viewed, the difference between Quine and Carnap here is one of
detail: much more unites than divides them. In particular, Quine has no more
use than Carnap for the kind of pre-Kantian project of attempting to describe
reality ‘‘just as it is in itself.’’ And yet there is a terminological difference
between the two over the term ‘‘ontology,’’ traditionally a near-synonym for
‘‘metaphysics.’’ Quine agreed with Carnap that ontology in this traditional,
pre-Kantian sense is meaningless. Quine, however, differed from Carnap in
what he called the ‘‘ethics of terminology,’’ insisting that if a word was
meaningless, he had the right to give it a meaning by stipulative definition,
Being explained away 95
and choosing to exercise this alleged right in the case of the word ‘‘ontology.’’
The new enterprise of ‘‘ontology’’ in the post-Quinean sense is simply a
glorified taxonomy, an attempt to catalogue what sorts of objects there are
in reality, not ‘‘just as it is in itself ’’ but as apprehended by us through our
everyday and technical language, our commonsense and scientific theories.
This untraditional use of ‘‘ontology’’ is of a piece with the historically
dubious use of ‘‘nominalism’’ and the historically absurd use of ‘‘Platonism.’’
(In any traditional sense, it is people James is talking about, people like
Galileo and Kepler, who are the Platonists, while an anti-metaphysical
pragmatist like Quine is no more a Platonist than was James.) Why Quine
chose to apply an old label to a new project is to me something of a mystery.
It is clear that having a synonym, ‘‘ontological’’ or ‘‘ontic,’’ for ‘‘existential’’
must have been useful during the heyday of Jean-Paul Sartre. Readers would
have winced if the section of Word and Object entitled ‘‘ontic decision’’ had
instead been entitled ‘‘existential choice.’’ I fear, however, that Quine may
have chosen to use ‘‘ontology’’ mainly to needle Carnap, who seems to have
more than just disliked the word (perhaps because it was a favorite of
Heidegger, who incidentally also used it in a radically untraditional sense).
The danger posed by Quine’s transferring ‘‘ontology’’ from the old project to
the new – rather than coining contrasting labels – is that some may be led to
confuse the two homonymous enterprises.
And just this is what I suspect may have happened in the case of those
recent nominalists who say in one breath, ‘‘I sincerely believe that it is
literally true that there are such things as numbers,’’ and in the next, ‘‘I am
in no way ontologically committed to numbers.’’ This otherwise non-
sensical double-talk becomes less nonsensical if one takes ‘‘ontology’’ in
the second assertion to be meant in a pre-Kantian rather than a post-
Quinean sense. Indeed, while I myself sincerely believe that it is literally
true that there are such things as numbers, I do not believe that the aim of
traditional, pre-Kantian ontology (namely, the aim of getting behind all
conceptual schemes to reality ‘‘just as it is in itself ’’ and cataloguing what
sorts of objects it contains) is a feasible one. Of course, this being my
attitude, I wish to make ‘‘ontological’’ claims, in a traditional, pre-Kantian
sense, neither for abstract objects nor for concrete ones. It is here that
I differ from what seems to be the attitude of the double-talking nomina-
lists, who go on to say in their third breath, ‘‘But I am ontologically
committed to this table and these chairs, and to the moon and the stars.’’
What I see wrong in this kind of nominalism is not its ‘‘anti-realism’’ about
the abstract, but what appears to be its ‘‘realism’’ (in a traditional, pre-
Kantian sense) about the concrete.
96 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
What I am inclined to conclude from the tendency observable over these last
decades for nominalism to morph from one form to another is that nomi-
nalism can never be defeated by arguments solely about the abstract, since
what feeds it is an underlying naı̈veté about the concrete and our knowledge
thereof. It is for this reason that I welcome recent epistemological arguments
for what I will call – from the Greek word for ‘‘simple’’ – the haplist position.
As the nominalist holds that everything there is is concrete, and hence that
there are no numbers, no books (in the sense of types rather than tokens),
and so on, so the haplist holds that everything there is is simple, not extended
and composite, and hence that there are no chairs and tables, and no moon
and stars – and no people, and in particular no haplist philosophers! Though
the haplist conclusion is absurd, attention to what haplists have to say may at
least help show that the explanation of our knowledge of the concrete is not
so straightforward as nominalists seem to suppose. This is especially so since
the form of the epistemological argument for haplism is so similar to that of
the epistemological argument for nominalism.
The nominalist’s skeptical argument goes something like this: I look at my
hand and see that (counting the thumb as a finger) there is a finger and another
and another and another and another and no more, and conclude that the
number of fingers on my hand is five. But if we look at what fundamental
physics tells us is really going on here, what we find is just this: light coming
from an external source is reflected off my fingers over there to my eye over
here, beginning a process in my body that ends with my forming the belief that
the number of fingers on my hand is five. But assume what you will about
whether, in addition to the concrete fingers, such an abstract entity as the
number five exists or not, no such alleged thing plays any role in this
explanation. If I end up speaking as if there were such a thing, there actually
being such a thing plays no role in explaining why I do: the explanation why
I do must be sought quite elsewhere, in the convenience of positing such
‘‘useful fictions’’ as numbers and sets for purposes of getting on in the world.
The haplist’s skeptical argument goes rather like this: I look over there
and see something brown and chair-shaped, and conclude that there is a
chair over there. But if we look at what fundamental physics, as in Richard
Feynman’s Q.E.D., tells us is really going on here, what we find is just this:
photons coming from an external source are absorbed by the electrons
among the myriad fundamental particles swarming in chair formation over
there, some of which electrons quickly emit other photons directed over
here, initiating a process – and so on. But assume what you will about
Being explained away 97
whether, in addition to the simple fundamental particles, such an
extended, composite entity as the chair exists or not, no such alleged
thing plays any role in this explanation, in which the electrons and quarks
do all the work. If I end up speaking as if there were such a thing as the
chair, there actually being such a thing plays no role in explaining why I do:
the explanation why I do must be sought quite elsewhere, in the infeasi-
bility of my keeping track of the complex motions of the myriad tiny
fundamental particles, and consequent convenience of positing such ‘‘use-
ful fictions’’ as chairs and tables for purposes of getting on in the world.
Pointing to the parallelism between the two forms of skepticism,
I submit that if the haplist’s is nothing more than a clever sophism (as
I imagine most nominalists would agree it is), then the nominalist’s is no
better. Still, I would like to make a stronger case against the claim that
while ultimate metaphysical reality ‘‘as it is in itself ’’ does not contain
numbers or books, by contrast it does contain tables and chairs, or the
moon and the stars. This brings me at long last to the topic my title was
intended to herald: the reasons for doubting that ultimate metaphysical
reality ‘‘as it is in itself ’’ contains objects of any sort. These reasons were
adumbrated in a section of A Subject With No Object that has been little
read, but I think it is time to refresh and elaborate upon the suggestion
made there, in the hopes of moving the never-ending but ever-changing
debate over nominalism in a new direction.
2 PLURAL LOGIC
Note the conventions used in displaying these laws. In both (1) and
(2) initial universal quantifiers have been suppressed. In (2), what we
really have is a scheme or rule according to which, for any formula (t),
writing (u) and (v) for the results of substituting u and of substitut-
ing v for each free occurrence of t therein, (2) is to count as an axiom.
In (2) again, the technical proviso is left tacit that the variables u and v
are free for t in (t), which is to say that no free occurrence of t in (t)
occurs within the scope of a quantifier 8u or 9u or 8v or 9v. In (2) yet
again, it is to be understood that there may be parameters, or free
variables not displayed, so that what is really to count as an axiom is
something like:
(3) 8w1 . . . 8wn8u8v (u ¼ v ! ((u, w1 . . ., wn) ! (v, w1 . . ., wn)))
The derivability of the law of symmetry
(4) u ¼ v ! v ¼ u
108 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
depends on allowing parameters, the formula (t) to which (2) is applied
being t ¼ u.
In terms of identity one may define certain other notions, notably
distinctness and unique existence:
(5) u 6¼ v « u ¼ v
(6) 9!x(u) « 9u(u) & 9u19u2((u1) & (u2) & u1 6¼ u2).
Here the distinctness predicate 6¼ and the unique existence quantifier 9! are
to be treated not as primitive but as defined, which is to say that they are not
part of the official notation, but rather are unofficial abbreviations. The
definitions (5) and (6) do not count as substantive assumptions or axioms,
but merely as abbreviations for tautologies, for biconditionals of the form
A « A.
So much for singular or first-order logic. The principles concerning the
formulation of axioms and the status of definitions that have been set out at
some length above in connection with identity are to be tacitly understood
as still applying as we now move on to plural logic, and when we later move
on to set theory. Turning then to plural logic, to begin with we need to add
three items of notation. First, there are plural variables, xx, yy, zz, and so on.
Second, there are plural quantifiers, written 99 and 88. If 9u and 8u are
read ‘‘there is an object, u’’ and ‘‘for any object, u,’’ then 99xx and 88xx may
be read ‘‘there are some objects, the xs’’ and ‘‘for any objects, the xs.’’ Third,
there is a logical predicate of two places, with singular variables going in the
first place and plural variables in the second, u / xx, which may be read ‘‘u
is one of the xs’’ or ‘‘u is among the xs.’’ Much as the symbol used in set
theory for ‘‘element’’ is a stylized epsilon, the symbol used here for ‘‘among’’
is a stylized alpha.
A question immediately arises about the understanding of the plural
quantifier. In a language with a threefold distinction among singular,
dual, and plural, it would be natural to take ‘‘there are some objects . . .’’ to
mean ‘‘there are three or more objects . . .’’ In a language like English,
where we have only the distinction between singular and plural, it is
natural to take it to mean ‘‘there are two or more objects . . .’’ For instance,
in the Geach–Kaplan example (1.10) – that is, displayed item (10) of x1
above – it is natural to understand ‘‘some critics’’ as meaning two or more
critics. But Lewis (1991) takes ‘‘there are some objects . . .’’ to mean ‘‘there
are one or more objects . . .,’’ while Burgess and Rosen (1997) go further
and take it to mean ‘‘there are zero or more objects . . .’’ The last-named
authors, however, show that taking any one reading as official, the other
readings can be defined in terms of it, so in one important sense it does
E pluribus unum: plural logic and set theory 109
not matter which reading we take. The ‘‘zero or more’’ reading will be
adopted here.
To frame a basic deductive system for plural quantification, one adds to
complete such a system for singular quantification the following:
(7) Axiom of Comprehension
99xx8u(u / xx « (u))
(8) Axiom of Indiscernibility
8u(u / xx « u / yy) ! ((xx) ! (yy)).
Axiom (7) is a plural analogue of existential generalization, allowing us, for
instance, to infer (1.8) from (1.5). It says that for any condition there are
some objects such that an object is among them if and only if the condition
holds of it. Which objects are these? The objects of which the condition
holds, of course! (If we adopted the ‘‘one or more’’ reading, comprehension
would have to be formulated as the conditional with antecedent 9u(u)
and consequent (7).) Axiom (8) is a plural analogue of the indiscernibility
of identicals (4). It says that if exactly the same objects are among these
objects as are among those objects, so that these and those are the very same
objects, then any condition that holds of these holds of those.
One can introduce an additional notion and notation, not as primitive,
but as defined, namely, ‘‘the xs are the same as the ys,’’ the definition being
as follows:
(9) xx ¼¼ yy « 8u(u / xx « u / yy).
Then (8) can be abbreviated in the following form, to make clear the
analogy with (2):
(10) xx ¼¼ yy ! ((xx) ! (yy)).
No claim is made that the addition of the basic axioms (7) and (8) to a
complete system of first-order logic produces a complete system of plural
logic. For the moment, however, we have all the logical axioms and rules
we will be needing.
3 EXTENSIONALITY
(10) It is true that there are some objects such that all and only those objects that
are sets and not elements of themselves are among them.
(11) It is false that there is a set of objects such that all and only those objects that
are sets and not elements of themselves are elements of it.
But still ‘‘there are some objects’’ cannot in general be replaced by ‘‘there is a
class of objects . . .,’’ and one need only replace each occurrence of ‘‘set’’ or
‘‘element’’ in (10) and (11) by ‘‘class’’ or ‘‘member,’’ respectively, to see why not.
Another limitation of class-and-set theory is that, unlike plural-and-
singular set theory, it is in a sense incapable of making explicit the
assumption of heredity underlying extensionality. Technically, it would
be possible to replace the plural-logical (3.1), asserting that every set is the
set of some elements, by a class-theoretic version, asserting that every set is
coextensive with some class. But to state this last while keeping element-
hood primitive, and coextensiveness as defined, would be merely to restate
one specific instance of the general scheme of comprehension for classes.
For a genuine statement of the heredity assumption, one would need to
take the notion of a set’s being coextensive with a class to be primitive, and
the notion of an object’s being an element of a set to be defined in terms of
it, namely, defined as the object’s being a member of the class with which
the set is coextensive. And that choice of primitives is extremely unnatural
from a class-theoretic point of view, and to my knowledge no class theorist
114 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
has ever made that choice. Of course, the importance of this limitation
cannot be clear until it is seen what use is made of the heredity assumption
in the further development of set theory.
4 LIMITATION OF SIZE
The set theory based on plural logic and the non-logical axioms of heredity
(3.1), extensionality (3.2), separation (4.3), and reflection (5.7) will be called
BB for Bernays–Boolos. It turns out that all the usual existence axioms of
ZF, as well as the large cardinals obtainable in the manner of Bernays, can
be obtained from BB by deduction as logical consequences.
Bernays was not especially concerned with the intuitive or heuristic moti-
vation for reflection, and in fact assumed reflection in an ostensibly stronger
version than (5.7), with an additional technical condition on t that it is not
immediately obvious how to motivate by appeal to the idea of limitation of
size. Our first task must be to show that this ostensibly stronger version
actually follows from the version (5.7) that has been taken as axiomatic here.
The first step in the deduction is to replace the version of reflection in
(5.7), which does not even explicitly state that t is a set, by a version that
does state explicitly at least that much. The deduction uses a trick
employed over and over by Bernays. The trick consists in noting that any
statement of course implies its own conjunction with any axiom or
theorem C. And so (5.7) yields the following:
(1) ! 9t(Ct & t ).
Taking as C the trivial truism 9u(u ¼ u) we get the following:
(2) ! 9t(9u(u 2 t & u ¼ u)& t ).
7 EXTENSIONALITY REVISITED
To obtain full ZFC we need to obtain three more axioms. The first of these
is a stronger version of extensionality that reads as follows:
(1) 8w(w 2 u « w 2 v) ! u ¼ v.
This will be forthcoming from (3.6) provided we assume the following:
(2) Axiom of Purity
ßu.
From one point of view (2) is an utter absurdity, saying that there are no
objects but sets. Now the mere absurdity of a proposition is no guarantee
122 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
that some philosopher will not endorse it. So perhaps there is a philosopher
somewhere who denies that anything but sets exists, and who denies that he
himself exists. Or perhaps there is a philosopher somewhere who denies that
anything but sets exists, and maintains that she herself is a set. But this is
not what is usually intended by those who adopt (2). From the usual point
of view, (2) merely expresses the intention to exclude anything but sets
from the range of the quantifiers. Note, however, that since we are already
assuming that whenever a set is included its elements are included as well,
the assumption (2) actually involves a restriction not merely to sets, but to
sets all of whose elements are sets, and all elements of whose elements are
sets, and so on. Only pure sets are included, hence the name for (2).
Now there are two approaches that might be taken to obtain (2) and
thence (1). One would be to take it as an axiom. Another would be to try to
find an interpretation of set theory with the axiom (2) within set theory
without the axiom (2). That is, one could try to find a formula such that
each axiom of set theory with axiom (2) becomes a theorem of set theory
without axiom (2) when quantifiers are relativized to . Then for every
theorem of set theory with axiom (2), one would have a theorem of
set theory without axiom (2) saying that holds for those sets for which
condition holds.
Ideally, the formula (u) should be one that intuitively expresses that u
is a pure set, or in other words, that u, its elements, the elements of its
elements, and so on, are all sets. Now intuitively the set u, its elements, the
elements of its elements, and so on, are together some objects such that u is
among them and any element of a set among them is among them. Thus
intuitively if u is pure, there will be some objects such that any element of a
set among them is among them, u is among them, and every object among
them is a set. Conversely, if there are some objects such that any element of
a set among them is among them, and if u is among them, and every object
among them is a set, then it follows that u, the elements of u, the elements
of elements of u, and so on, are all sets, and u is pure. Thus a natural
candidate for the formula (u) would be the following:
(3) 99xx(8v8w(v / xx & w 2 v ! w / xx) & u / xx & 8v(v / xx ! ßv)).
Reflection can be used to show (3) is equivalent to the following alter-
native not involving plural quantifiers:
(4) 9t(8v8w(v 2 t & w 2 v ! w 2 t) & u 2 t & 8v 2 t ßv).
The first conjunct of (4) says that t is transitive. Other variations in the
choice of are also possible.
E pluribus unum: plural logic and set theory 123
Whatever variant is chosen, what has to be proved is, first, that for each
axiom that is being assumed, one can deduce its relativization from
the axioms that are being assumed, and, second, for the axiom (2) that is not
being assumed, one can also deduce its relativization (2) from the axioms
that are being assumed. It follows that whenever follows from the axioms
that are being assumed plus (2), then follows from the axioms that are
being assumed.
Though the tedious verification of details will not be given here – for
they are quite similar to the details involved in the case of the axiom of
foundation, to be discussed below – this is in fact the case whether by ‘‘the
axioms that are being assumed’’ one means the other axioms of ZFC or
means the axioms of BB. Moreover, it is also true that for any large cardinal
axiom, even if stronger than those provided by BB, that one might decide
to assume in the future, the assumption of such an axiom would render
its relativization deducible as well. Thus one may say that, without
losing any other axiom that one might want, axiom (2) and hence axiom (1)
can be ‘‘obtained,’’ not in the sense of being got by deduction as a logical
consequence, but in the sense of being got by relativization or restriction of
quantifiers.
An arguable advantage of the first approach of assuming purity as an
axiom is that it permits a simpler axiomatization. One can introduce what
amounts to a function symbol ee, which applied to a singular variable u
yields a term eeu of a kind that can be substituted for plural variables, and
whose intended meaning is ‘‘the elements of u.’’ The symbol ß can be
dropped, and the symbol need not be taken as primitive, but rather may
be taken as defined by the following:
(5) u xx « eeu ¼¼ xx.
In general, the use of function symbols builds existence and uniqueness
assumptions into the notation, making it unnecessary to assume them as
axioms. In the present case, with ee there is no need for the axiom of
heredity, and no need for one direction of the axiom of extensionality. All
that needs to be assumed as an axiom of extensionality is the following:
(6) eeu ¼¼ eev ! u ¼ v.
The converse follows from the indiscernibility of identicals.
By contrast, the advantage of the second approach of restricting quanti-
fiers is the philosophical one that it makes explicit what the first approach
leaves implicit, namely, that purity is not a substantive assumption, but a
restriction on the universe of discourse. It is the second approach that will
124 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
be adopted officially here. Thus the ZFC version of the extensionality
axiom will not be added to the axioms of BB, and any theorems of ZFC that
depend on it will not be theorems of BB; but for any such theorem , the
relativization will be a theorem of BB, or in other words, it will be a
theorem of BB that holds of pure sets.
The second of the three axioms of ZFC requiring discussion here is the
axiom of foundation, also known as regularity. As axiom (2) implies that all
objects (in the range of the quantifiers) are pure sets, so foundation or
regularity asserts that all objects (in the range of the quantifiers) are well-
founded sets. Since all elements of sets included in the universe of discourse
are themselves included, it follows that if a set u is included, not only is u
well-founded itself, but so are the elements of u, the elements of elements
of u and so on: u is hereditarily well founded.
Several equivalent formal versions of foundation are known, but it will
not be necessary to give any formulation here, since the question of the
status of this axiom is already well explained – with details of the kind
omitted in the discussion of purity above – in introductory textbooks, such
as Hrbacek and Jech (1999). The options are the same as in the case of
purity. Foundation may either be taken as an axiom, while insisting that it
is not a substantive assumption, but merely an expression of the intention
to limit what is included in the range of the quantifiers; or it may be
obtained from the other axioms by relativization. The latter approach has
the advantage of making explicit what the former leaves implicit, and will
be adopted officially here.
1
Friedman makes his papers available, between the time of their writing and the time of their
publication, on the preprint server: www.mathpreprints.com/math/Preprint/show. Type ‘‘Harvey
Friedman’’ into the window for access to these preprints.
126 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
approach to obtaining the axiom, leaving it to the reader to judge how far
this approach motivates the axiom. But to begin with, the statement of the
axiom should be given. It reads as follows:
(1) 8u(u 2 a ! 9w(w 2 u) & 8u8v(u 2 a & v 2 a ! 8w(w 2 u « w 2 v)
9w(w 2 u & w 2 v)) ! 9v8u(u 2 a ! 9!w(w 2 u & u 2 v)).
If we call the sets in a distinguished, then the first clause of the hypothesis
says that distinguished sets are non-empty, and the second that distin-
guished sets are non-overlapping: a distinguished u and v either have
exactly the same elements (and hence by extensionality are exactly the
same set) or else have no common elements at all. The conclusion asserts
the existence of what is called a choice set, having exactly one element in
common with each distinguished set.
Now even before set-theoretic notions are introduced, there is a version
of the axiom of choice that can be formulated as a purely logical assump-
tion. It is a scheme, reading as follows:
(2) 88xx((xx) ! 9w(w / xx)) & 88xx88yy((xx) & (yy) !
8w(w / xx « w / yy) 9w(w / xx & w / yy)) !
99yy88xx((xx) ! 9!w(w / xx & w / yy)).
If we call objects distinctively related to each other, or distinguished for
short, when condition holds of them, the two conjuncts of the hypothe-
sis of the axiom are non-emptiness and non-overlappingness conditions for
distinguished objects. The conclusion asserts the existence of some objects,
which may be called the chosen objects, such that for any distinguished
objects, there is exactly one chosen object among them.
It is an easy exercise to deduce (1) from (2) in our framework, taking as
(xx) in the condition:
(3) 9u 2 a (u xx).
The hypothesis of (1) easily gives us the hypothesis of (2) for (3) as . What
the conclusion of (2) for (3) as gives us is some chosen objects, the ys,
while what the conclusion of (1) demands is a choice set. What is left to the
reader is to verify that the ys do form a set v as required.
It is not quite so easy an exercise to show, though it is also true, that given
the set theory BB, the set-theoretic version of AC in the form (1) implies
(each instance of) the logical version of AC in form (2). (This derivation of
(2) from (1) is an instance of a more general phenomenon of the derivability
of logical conclusions from set-theoretic assumptions, to be discussed in
the next section.) What one proves is the contrapositive, that if (2) fails (in a
E pluribus unum: plural logic and set theory 127
particular instance), then (1) fails. From the assumed failure of (2) for a
particular , one obtains by reflection a supertransitive set t for which
(2)t holds and hence (2)t fails. One can then take as a the set of all subsets
u of t such that
(4) 99xx(u xx & t(xx)).
The non-emptiness and non-overlap clauses in the antecedent of (2)t will
then imply the corresponding clauses in the antecedent of (1) for the set a
defined by (4). But if there were, as per the consequent of (1), a choice set v
for a, then its elements, call them the ys, would be chosen elements, as per
the consequent of (2)t, contrary to the hypothesis that (2)t fails.
It follows that one can obtain the usual set-theoretic version of AC
without adding any new set-theoretic axioms to BB, by adding a version of
AC to the background plural logic. This is the course that will be adopted
here, but the logical version of AC adopted will not be (2) above, but
something else, whose introduction requires some background.
The most important points about AC in the present context would be the
following. On the one hand, AC is useful for proving many mathematical
results in their most general form. This pragmatic consideration has histor-
ically and practically been the most widely persuasive motivation for the
axiom. It is for this reason that, as stated earlier, mathematicians have
generally acquiesced in its assumption: it is the reason why today only
logicians still keep track of which theorems require AC and which do not.
On the other hand, AC is a non-constructive existence assertion, asserting
that something exists for which a given condition holds, without specifying
any particular such thing. That is why when it was first introduced
mathematicians did not at once embrace it. But AC is not the only or
the most basic non-constructive existence assertion in classical mathematics
or logic, since the following basic law of monadic first-order logic is also
such an assertion:
(5) 9u(9v(v) ! (u)).
That is why it is now widely agreed that if one is going to object to non-
constructive existence assertions, one should not wait for AC, but should
begin objecting already at the level of classical logic, if not of classical
sentential logic, thus placing one’s objections entirely outside the scope of
the present paper. And inversely, those who are determined, in the words of
Hilbert, not to be driven out of ‘‘Cantor’s paradise,’’ must begin their
defensive operations no later than the level of monadic first-order logic, or
indeed sentential logic – ‘‘Boole’s paradise,’’ as it might be called.
128 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
Hilbert, and with him Bernays, starting from this last observation, pro-
posed a way of building AC even into first-order, singular logic, where it
cannot otherwise be expressed, even as a scheme after the pattern of (2). They
allow the formation of a term eu[(u)] which can be substituted for free
variables. It may be thought of as a description, ‘‘the chosen u such that (u),’’
provided that this is understood in such a way that, when there is in fact no u
such that (u), what the phrase denotes is some arbitrarily chosen object.
Accordingly the following logical axiom for the e-symbol is assumed:
(6) 9u(u) ! (eu[(u)]).
(Actually, a biconditional version of (6) was for Hilbert the very definition
of the existential quantifier, though few have followed him in this, and we
will not.) The connection with (5) is apparent.
The following is also sometimes assumed:
(7) 8u((u) « C(u)) ! eu[(u)] ¼ eu[C(u)].
This says that what the chosen object is depends not on the condition but
on what things it holds of, so that if C holds of exactly the same things, the
same object will be chosen.
If the e-symbol is added to plural logic, then in terms of it we can define
the chosen object among some given objects:
(8) axx ¼ eu[u / xx].
(If we had the ee notation of the preceding section, aeeu would amount to
‘‘the chosen element of u’’ if u is non-empty.) But actually, in this case it is
more natural to take a as the primitive notion, and let e be defined by:
(9) v ¼ eu[(u)] « 99xx(8u(u / xx « (u)) & v ¼ axx).
To derive (6) it is enough to assume the following:
(10) Axiom of Choice
9u(u / xx) ! axx / xx.
It is this version that will be taken officially as an axiom of plural logic here,
alongside comprehension (2.7) and indiscernibility (2.8).
Now (6) follows from (10) and the definition (9). Inversely, (10) follows
from (6) and the definition (8). As for (7), the acceptance of indiscernibility
(2.8) as a scheme means the acceptance of all its instances, whatever
notations are added to the language. We have now added one new nota-
tion, the a-symbol, as we have the following new instance of (2.8) for it:
(11) xx ¼¼ yy ! axx ¼ ayy.
E pluribus unum: plural logic and set theory 129
From (11) and the definition (9) (together with comprehension), (7)
follows without the need to assume anything like it as an additional axiom.
The main point is that with an a-symbol and the sole additional axiom
(10) for it, the plural-logical axiom of choice (2) can be deduced. The ys
required by (2) are given as follows:
(12) u / yy « 99xx((xx) & u ¼ axx).
The verification that (2) does follow from (10) given the definition (12) is
left to the reader.
1 NEO-NEO-LOGICISM
After a quick review of the original Fregean logicist program, I would like
to describe two recent revivals of logicist ideas – Richard Heck’s predica-
tivist logicism, and the late Richard Jeffrey’s logicistico-formalism – and
briefly suggest how the two might be combined.
Frege in his Begriffsschrift (1879/1967) presented a deductive system of
second-order logic – with the first-order entities called ‘‘objects’’ and the
second-order ‘‘concepts’’ – including an absolutely unrestricted axiom of
Comprehension, as follows:
(1) 9X 8x(Xx « f(x))
together with its analogues for two-, three-, and many-place relational
concepts or relations. The axiom of Extensionality, in the following form:
(2) X Y ! (f(X) « f(Y ))
is then provable using the following definition of coextensiveness, ‘‘the
analogue of identity’’ for concepts:
(3) X Y « 8z(Xz « Yz).
Since (2) implies the uniqueness of the concept whose existence is asserted
by (1), we may speak of the concept under which fall all and only those
objects x for which f(x) holds, or for short, the concept of being an x such
that f(x), for which I will write Æx: f(x)i.
Frege added, informally in the Grundlagen (1884/1950) and formally in the
Grundgesetze (1893/1903) for the purposes of the derivation of arithmetic
from logic, the infamous Basic Law V, the assumption that to each concept
X is associated an object X, its extension, in such a way that the extensions of
two concepts are identical if and only if the concepts are coextensive:
(4) X ¼ Y « X Y.
135
136 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
We may then introduce set-theoretic notation as follows:
(5) Set(y) « 9Y(y ¼ Y)
(6) x 2 y « 9Y(y ¼ Y & Yx)
(7) {x: f(x)} ¼ Æx: f(x)i.
where I have not bothered to write out the definition of bijection in purely
logical terms. He then defines number thus:
Using this definition he derives what has come to be called (on account of a
passing allusion on Frege’s part to Hume) ‘‘Hume’s Principle’’ or HP:
(10) #X ¼ #Y « X Y.
To block the paradox, therefore, one might either restrict (1), or restrict
or replace (4).
The first option was not seriously explored until recently. To be sure,
Russell professed a ‘‘vicious circle principle’’ banning definitions of con-
cepts by conditions involving quantification over concepts, or impredica-
tive definitions as they came to be called. But he also introduced an ‘‘axiom
of reducibility’’ whose effect was to circumvent such predicativity restric-
tions, so that as Ramsey (1925) observed he might as well not have imposed
them in the first place.
The second option is what saves Russell from the contradiction. His ‘‘no
classes theory’’ rejected (4) altogether, and with it Frege’s approach to
logicism, on which numbers are objects or first-order entities. (For Russell
they are third-order entities, and he has to make essential use, as Frege did
Logicism: a new look 137
not, of higher-order logic; also, since unlike Frege he cannot prove that there
are infinitely many objects, he has to assume so as the ‘‘axiom of infinity.’’)
Contemporary neo-Fregeanism, whose continuous history begins (though
there were significant precursors) somewhat over two decades ago with
Crispin Wright’s Frege’s Conception of Numbers with Objects (1983), retains
(1) and rejects (4), but in place of the latter assumes (10) as axiomatic, thus
making numbers into objects after all.
The key technical result about this approach was given precise formu-
lation and rigorous proof by the late George Boolos (1987), who showed
that second-order logic with HP, or Frege arithmetic, and second-order
Peano arithmetic, or second-order logic with the Peano postulates, are
interpretable in each other and hence equiconsistent. The direction of the
interpretability of second-order Peano arithmetic in Frege arithmetic he
called Frege’s theorem. There are serious questions how much more of
mathematics beyond second-order arithmetic one can get on a natural
extension of such an approach. (Kit Fine (2002) has a natural-seeming
extension that gives third-order arithmetic.) There is also a question
whether (10) is close enough to being a ‘‘logical’’ principle (as Frege
thought (4) was) to justify neo-Fregeans in calling their position ‘‘neo-
logicism.’’
The latter kind of question seems less of a issue with Richard Heck’s
neo-neo-logicism, which takes the opposite approach of retaining (4) but
restricting (1), assuming only predicative comprehension. Heck (1996)
explored what one would have been left with if one had modified
Frege’s system only by imposition of a ‘‘vicious circle’’ restriction, without
any ‘‘reducibility axiom’’ to cancel it, and without the further ‘‘no classes’’
restriction. He was able to show (building on early work of Terence
Parsons (1987)) that a system of this kind was consistent. He was also
able to show that it is sufficiently strong to interpret Raphael Robinson’s
system Q of minimal arithmetic. Now while that system appears very
weak, an idea of Robert Solovay, further pursued by Edward Nelson and
then a number of others, has shown that ostensibly much stronger
theories can be interpreted in Q. See Hájek and Pudlak (1998) for details.
All these stronger theories can then be interpreted indirectly (via Q) in
Heck’s system.
Further refinements of these results are possible in several directions.
First, interpretability of Q can be proved for weaker predicative systems
than Heck’s. In the very simplest such system, which I call PV (with P for
‘‘predicative’’ and V pronounced ‘‘five’’), one has comprehension in its
simplest predicative form:
138 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
(12) 9X8x(Xx « f(x)) provided there are no bound concept variables in f
and in addition Law V in its original form (4). With the definitions of set-
theoretic notions as before we get a little bit of set theory. We of course get
the axiom of extensionality for sets
(13) Set(x) & Set(y) & 8z(z 2 x « z 2 y) ! x ¼ y
from the axiom of extensionality for concepts when sets are introduced as
extensions of concepts. We also easily get empty sets, singletons, pairs and
so on, thus:
(14) ˘ ¼ {x: x 6¼ x}
(15) {u} ¼ {x: x ¼ u}
(16) {u, v } ¼ {x: x ¼ u x ¼ v}.
Here the defining formulas have no concept variables at all. When we recall
that we also may allow free concept variables as parameters, we see that we
also get complements, intersections, and unions:
(17) -X ¼ {x: Xx}
(18) X \ Y ¼ {x: Xx & Yx}
(19) X [ Y ¼ {x: Xx Yx}.
This guarantees the existence of x [ {y} for any set x and any object y. That
(13)–(19) and their consequences such as (20) are in effect all we get can be
proved (for the cognoscenti: by using elimination of quantifiers for monadic
first-order logic with identity).
This does not look much like set theory, but in the famous little book
Undecidable Theories by Tarski, Mostowski, and Robinson (1953), which
first introduced Q, a joint result of Tarski and Wanda Smielew is men-
tioned without proof, to the effect that Q is interpretable in the set theory
whose axioms are extensionality, empty set, and adjunction. In order to get
an interpretation of Q we may take 0 ¼ ˘ and for successor use either the
Zermelo definition x 0 ¼ {x} or the von Neumann definition x 0 ¼ x [ {x}.
Interestingly enough, about ten years ago Franco Montagna and Antonella
Mancini (1994) showed that Solovay–Nelson methods for interpreting
other theories in Q can be adapted to prove the Szmielew–Tarski theorem
about the interpretability of Q in another theory.
Logicism: a new look 139
Second, in the case of stronger systems of arithmetic interpretable in Q
and hence by the Smielew–Tarski theorem indirectly interpretable in PV,
it is sometimes easier to prove interpretability in PV directly. For the most
important specific example, a D0-formula in the language of arithmetic is
one containing only bounded quantifiers 8x < y and 9x < y. A difficult
argument of Alex Wilkie (as reported in Hájek and Pudlak, 1998) shows
that the system called ID0, with the principle of mathematical induction (if
f(x) holds for zero and for the successor of any number for which it holds,
then it holds for all numbers) for D0-formulas, can be interpreted in Q. But
A. P. Hazen showed that we can get interpretability of ID0 in PV without
Wilkie’s difficult argument. See Burgess and Hazen (1998) for details.
Third, one can actually go beyond ID0, which allows only for the
operations of addition and multiplication, to a system which allows also
exponentiation, if one works in a slightly stronger predicative Fregean
theory, which I will call P2 V. In this theory there are objects x, degree-
zero concepts X 0, and degree-one concepts X 1. A formula is of degree zero if
it contains no degree-one variables, and no bound degree-zero variables,
and is of degree one if it contains no bound degree-one variables. We then
have two forms of comprehension, for the two degrees:
(21) 9X 08x(X 0x « f(x)) for f of degree zero
(22) 9X 18x(X 1x « f(x)) for f of degree one.
P2 V, with axioms (20), (21), and (4), can interpret the theory known as
ID0(exp), which in a convenient equivalent of its usual formulation may be
taken to have the following axioms:
(23) 0 6¼ x 0
(24) x 6¼ y ! x0 6¼ y 0
(25) x < 0
(26) x < y 0 « x < y x ¼ y
(27) x þ 0 ¼ x
(28) x þ y 0 ¼ (x þ y)0
(29) x 0 ¼ 0
(30) x y 0 ¼ (x y) þ x
(31) x 0 ¼ 00
(32) x y 0 ¼ (x y) x
(33) (f(0) & 8x(f(x)) ! f(x 0 )) ! 8xf(x)
provided f is a D0-formula.
A formula like the conclusion of (33), consisting of universal quantifiers
preceding a D0-formula is called a 1-formula. Many important theo-
rems of number theory (including the Fermat–Wiles theorem) have this
140 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
form. It is known that quite a bit of mathematics can be developed in
such a system as the above (and others known to be interpretable in or
conservative over it). Harvey Friedman has conjectured that every
1-theorem published in the Annals of Mathematics can be proved in
such a system.
The refinements of Heck’s work that I have been discussing so far for
the most part go back to a joint paper by Hazen and myself. That paper
left open how much further one can go. It turns out that, unfortunately,
one is not going to get in this way the whole of first-order arithmetic,
or even all of so-called primitive recursive arithmetic, PRA, which is
generally accepted, following William Tait, as a formalization of finitist
mathematics. This is so even if one goes beyond P2V to P3V and so on,
defined in the obvious way, or even RPV ¼ P1V, the union of all the
Pn V, which amounts to so-called ramified predicative second-order logic
plus Law V. This is on account of considerations related to Gödel’s
second incompleteness theorem, together with the fact that there is a
finitist consistency proof for RPV. (The original consistency proofs of
Parsons and Heck were model-theoretic rather than proof-theoretic in
character, and infinitistic rather than finitistic.) This is the main new
result in this area to be found in my little book Fixing Frege (2005b) where
technical details and bibliographical references for all the material
described so far can be found. (Important improvements have since
been obtained in forthcoming work by Mihai Ganea and by Albert
Visser.) To sum up so far, predicative logicism provides a foundation
for a respectable modicum of arithmetic, but nothing anywhere near the
whole of classical mathematics.
2 LITE LOGICISM
Lite ‘‘beer’’ is a fluid with approximately the taste of a mixture of 50 per cent
real beer and 50 per cent soda water. Lite ‘‘logicism’’ is something brewed
up by my late colleague Richard Jeffrey in his last years (1996, 2002), with
the approximate composition 50 per cent logicism plus 50 per cent formal-
ism. Though this recipe does not, perhaps, make it sound very appetizing,
I myself on tasting it have found it considerably more palatable than I had
expected, and I would like to say enough about it to tempt some of you to
take a sip. The leading idea can be brought out by contrasting the following
Hilbert proportion:
(1) computational : mathematics :: empirical : physics
Logicism: a new look 141
which is the leading idea behind formalism, with the following Jeffrey
proportion:
(2) logical : mathematics :: empirical : physics.
So let me begin with Hilbert in interpreting whom I follow (Weyl, 1944).
With both Hilbert and Jeffrey we have a view of mathematics self-
consciously modeled on a certain philosophy of physics (more popular
perhaps in Hilbert’s day than in Jeffrey’s). On this view the theoretical
portions of physics are only there to imply empirical laws: universal
generalizations whose instances are empirically decidable. Now it is an
immediate consequence of the definition of empirical decidability that
theoretical physics and empirical laws cannot imply any empirically decid-
able sentences that could not be discovered directly by observation. But
they can yield such sentences more quickly, as predictions of experiences
future rather than records of experiences past. A better description of the
philosophy of physics in question is that it takes physics to be nothing but a
giant engine for generating empirical predictions. While the ‘‘nothing but’’
is controversial, it is comparatively uncontroversial that the data to which
physics is responsible are empirical, and that empirical fruitfulness must be
demanded. It is demanded of higher and higher theories that they should
continue to yield more and more empirical predictions.
On Hilbert’s view the theoretical (or as he called them ‘‘ideal’’) portions
of mathematics are only there to imply universal laws whose instances are
computationally decidable sentences (which he considered the only ‘‘real’’
sentences). In modern terminology these would be 1-sentences. Now
again it is an immediate consequence of the definition of computational
decidability that theoretical mathematics and 1-sentences cannot imply
any computationally decidable sentences that could not be discovered
directly by calculation. But again they can yield such sentences as ‘‘pre-
dictions’’ (for instance, the commutative law of multiplication predicts that
the results of multiplying two hundred-digit numbers in one order and in
the opposite order will be the same far more quickly than we can verify as
much by tedious calculations). Hilbert thought that higher and higher
mathematical theory would be computationally fruitful, yielding new com-
putational predictions, in the sense that it would yield 1-sentences more
quickly, but not in the sense that it would outright yield more 1-sentences.
On the contrary, his program was to try to convince the finitist of the
reliability of classical mathematics, through proving by finitist means that
for any 1-sentences having a classical proof, it is possible in principle,
though perhaps not feasible in practice, to produce a finitist proof.
142 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
Gödel’s incompleteness theorems showed Hilbert was wrong: classical
mathematics cannot be finistically proved to be reliable or even consistent;
we must be content with inductive evidence on these points. This is the
negative side of the coin whose positive side is that higher and higher
theories do not just yield quicker proofs of 1-sentences that could be
proved, albeit perhaps very much more slowly, in lower theories, but yield
outright new 1-sentences, so that we have computational fruitfulness in a
stronger sense than Hilbert expected. All this is because a higher theory can
prove the consistency of a lower theory, as the lower theory itself cannot,
and because consistency can be expressed as a 1-sentence.
Though I have so far spoken only of 1-sentences, there are impor-
tant distinctions among them. Hilbert accepted 1-sentences involving
arbitrary primitive recursive functions, including every function in the
sequence addition, iterated addition or multiplication, iterated multipli-
cation or exponentiation, iterated exponentiation, and so on. From certain
philosophical points of view, however, one might wish to stop the series
with exponentiation, or even with multiplication. (Recall, in particular,
that the simplest form of predicative logicism gave only addition and
multiplication, while the ramified form gave exponentiation but not
much more.) In that case, the question of computational fruitfulness, of
whether higher and higher theory does more and more computational
work, would have to be reopened. Do we actually get new 1-sentences
involving only addition and multiplication and exponentiation? Do we get
new 1-sentences involving only addition and multiplication? (We do not
get any involving only addition; for the cognoscenti, this is a consequence of
Pressburger’s theorem.) These questions are non-trivial, but answers are
known. An affirmative answer to the former question is implied by the
work of Julia Robinson (building on the work of Martin Davis and Hilary
Putnam), and an affirmative answer to the latter question is implied by the
work of Yuri Matiyasevich that builds thereupon, for an exposition of
which see Matiyasevich (1993).
No logicist of any stripe can be satisfied with an approach that, like
Hilbert’s as described so far, takes computation to be an end in itself,
without regard to applications. Even Hilbert recognized that some con-
nection must be made between the use in pure mathematics of numerals as
nouns, denoting numerical objects on which we can perform arithmetical
operations, and the doubtless historically far older use in applications of
numerals as adjectives, in numerically definite quantifications. The com-
putational fact that 2 þ 2 ¼ 4 is obviously somehow connected with the
logical fact that if two sheep jumped the fence in the morning and two
Logicism: a new look 143
sheep jumped the fence in the evening, and no sheep jumped both morn-
ing and evening, then four sheep altogether jumped the fence morning or
evening. But Hilbert gave no formal account of the connection.
Why do I call the fact about the sheep a logical fact? If we think of first-
order logic (with identity) as enriched by (definable) numerical quantifiers
of the type
(3.1) 91xAx « 9xAx
(3.2) 92xAx « 8y9x(x 6¼ y & Ax)
(3.3) 93xAx « 8z8y9x(x 6¼ z & x 6¼ y & Ax)
then the fact about the sheep becomes an instance of the general first-order
logical law
(5) 92!xAx & 92!xBx & 9x(Ax & Bx) ! 94!x(Ax Bx).
Any variety of logicist or set-theoretic approach will supply what Hilbert
does not, a systematic way of connecting arithmetical facts with logical laws,
through the characterization of arithmetical relations and operations that
Fregean and Russellian logicism share with (or rather, borrow from) the
Cantorian theory of cardinal numbers. To recall those characterizations, if
a and b and c are respectively the number of As and Bs and Cs, then we have
the following characterizations of arithmetic notions by existential second-
order formulas, wherein R is two-place and S is three-place:
(6.1) a b «
9R(R gives a bijection between the As and some of the Bs)
(6.2) a þ b ¼ c «
9R(R gives a bijection between the As and some of the Cs and
R gives bijection between the Bs and the rest of the Cs)
(6.3) a b ¼ c «
9S(S gives a bijection between the pairs
consisting of an A and a B and the Cs)
Tarski’s tort
1 DEFINABILITY IN DISREPUTE
While what Alfred Tarski labeled his ‘‘semantic conception of truth’’ has
been much discussed, one topic that has not received all the attention it
deserves is his choice of that label. It is this comparatively neglected aspect
of Tarski’s conception that I wish to address here. But first a word about
the situation prior to Tarski.
I begin with a result I learned as a fifteen-year-old student in a summer
mathematics program for high-school students run by the late Arnold
Ross: the theorem that every natural number is interesting. The proof is
by contradiction. Suppose that not every natural number is interesting.
Then the set of uninteresting natural numbers is non-empty. So by the
well-ordering property of the natural numbers, it must have a smallest
element n. But if n is the smallest uninteresting natural number, then n is
interesting for that very reason. Thus we have a contradiction, establishing
that our original hypothesis was false, and that every natural number is
interesting after all. But, of course, some numbers do appear completely
uninteresting to most of us. I suppose a so-called dialethist might claim
that here we have yet another example of a true contradiction, but the more
usual reaction to this bit of adolescent mathematical humor is that ‘‘inter-
esting’’ is too vague or ambiguous, too subjective or relative, a concept to be
admissible in mathematical reasoning. And when Alfred Tarski was begin-
ning his mathematical career, most mathematicians held essentially the
same opinion about the concept of truth. In order to understand what
Tarski was up to with his truth definition, one needs to keep ever in mind
this historical fact.
The first suspect notion that engaged Tarski’s attention was not that of
truth, but rather that of definability. That notion belongs to the same family
as the notion of truth, since an object is definable if there is a condition true
of or satisfied by it and it alone. And eighty years or so ago this notion of
149
150 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
definability was in as much disrepute as the notion of truth itself. Thus
Tarski begins his first relevant paper (Tarski 1931), on the notion of defin-
ability for sets of real numbers, by remarking ‘‘Mathematicians, in general,
do not like to operate with the notion of definability; their attitude towards
this notion is one of distrust and reserve.’’ And he goes on to concede
‘‘The reasons for this aversion are quite clear and understandable.’’ Indeed,
the grounds for mathematicians’ suspicions about definability are not far
to seek. The emergence of Russell’s and other set-theoretic paradoxes
had put mathematicians in mind of some of the paradoxes propounded
by ancient philosopher–logicians – Poincaré, as I recall, somewhere
explicitly mentions Zeno the Eleatic and the school of Megara in this
connection – beginning with the paradox of the liar. And soon people
began inventing modern paradoxes of a similar stripe. The closest in spirit
to Russell’s paradox of the set of sets not elements of themselves was
Grelling’s heterological paradox, about adjectives or adjectival phrases not
true of themselves. Paradoxes of this type had an important influence,
in that they helped convince Russell and others that what was responsible
for the set-theoretic paradoxes was not the assumption that actual infin-
ities exist – the heterological paradox has nothing to do with infinity – but
a kind of self-reference or vicious circularity that came to be called
impredicativity.
There were also paradoxes about definability: Berry’s, Richard’s, and
above all König’s. This last was especially important because while no one
had ever taken Berry’s or Richard’s arguments to be anything but ingenious
sophisms, König and presumably at least two others (the referee and the
editor who accepted his note (König 1905/1967) for publication), took his
argument to be a legitimate proof, or more precisely, a legitimate disproof
of the hypothesis that the continuum can be well ordered. The argument, it
will be recalled, is that supposing there exists a well-ordering W of the
continuum, we may consider the set of real numbers that are definable in
terms of W (including those that, like real number zero, for instance, are
definable even without mentioning W ). Since by one theorem of Cantor
there are only countably many finite strings of letters of the alphabet to
serve as definitions, this set must be countable. Since by another theorem of
Cantor there are uncountably many real numbers, the complement of this
set must be non-empty. But then, since W is by hypothesis a well-ordering,
it must have a W-least element: the W-least real number not definable in
terms of W. But this last description provides a definition of the number in
question (in terms of W ), thus yielding a contradiction, and refuting the
supposed theorem of Zermelo.
Tarski’s tort 151
It was, however, not just on account of this paradox of König’s that the
repudiation of definability as an unmathematical notion was especially
firm on the part of the defenders of set theory. For there were other, more
direct arguments than König’s against Zermelo’s axiom of choice, based on
the assumption that the existence of a set or relation or function depends
on its being definable. In replying to these arguments, the defenders of set
theory emphasized the lack of mathematical precision in the notion of
definability. Thus Hadamard, in the exchange with other French analysts
on the axiom of choice (Baire et al. 1905), makes this point and goes so
far as to say the notion of definability belongs to psychology rather than
mathematics.
And yet Tarski saw that the notion of definability had important
mathematical applications, as becomes especially clear in the various
follow-ups to Tarski (1931/1983b) from which emerged the so-called
Tarski–Kuratowski algorithm, which allows one to compute the topolo-
gical complexity of point-sets in the line or plane or space (open, closed, Fr,
Gd, Borel, analytic, co-analytic, projective) by consideration of the logical
complexity (number of alternation of quantifiers when reduced to prenex
form) of the condition that defines the set. The ideas in this short paper,
though of the sort that once absorbed come to seem obvious, were of
the greatest importance, especially after Addison clarified the connec-
tion between the hierarchies of interest to topologists and the hierarchies
introduced, also in the first half of the 1930s, by the recursion theorist
Kleene. These ideas opened the door to the application of ever more
sophisticated logical techniques to the descriptive theory of point-
sets, eventually leading to the explanation by Gödel, Cohen, and their
successors of why so many problems in descriptive set theory had resisted
solution – they are undecidable on the basis of the conventional axioms
of set theory – and in the work of Woodin and his predecessors, showing
how a satisfactory solution was obtainable on the basis of large cardinal
axioms.
It may be noted that Tarski in these early papers was concerned with
something more general than the definability of an element of a domain
(which was what was at issue with the Berry, Richard, and König para-
doxes), namely, the definability of a subset of the domain, which is a matter
of there being a condition satisfied by all and only the elements of that
subset (definability of an element reducing to a special case, the definability
of its unit set). If one-, two-, three-, and many-dimensional sets are in
question, it is necessary to consider satisfaction for conditions with one-,
two-, three-, or many variables. And as Tarski notes, the notion of truth is
152 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
simply the degenerate or dimension-zero case of the notion of satisfaction.
Thus there is a direct line between the earlier papers, which defined
satisfaction for a single, specific interpreted language, and the great
Wahrheitsbegriff paper, which defined it for all interpreted languages of a
given kind. What concerned Tarski in that later paper is the same thing
that had concerned him in his earlier papers, namely, the rehabilitation of a
notion in disrepute among contemporary mathematicians.
Tarski in his great paper on truth (Tarski 1935/1983c) was not interested in
determining the meaning of the word ‘‘true.’’ He thought he already had a
partial understanding sufficient to determine what the extension of ‘‘true’’
was supposed to be. This understanding is expressed in Convention T, or
rather, in his laying down Convention T as a criterion of ‘‘material
adequacy.’’ And he repeatedly tells us that he has no interest in going
further and determining the intension of ‘‘true.’’ The other requirement he
states for a truth definition, that of ‘‘formal correctness,’’ has nothing to do
with fidelity to the intuitive sense of the term, but merely means mathe-
matical rigor, which is of course essential if the suspicions prevalent among
mathematicians about the notions with which he is concerned are to be
allayed. Material adequacy and formal correctness are his only official
requirements, though naturally he is also interested in the usefulness of
notions he is defining, beyond the applications he has already made of
them in his earlier papers on definability. To repeat, there is no require-
ment of fidelity to the intuitive, pre-theoretic sense of ‘‘true,’’ beyond
conformity to Convention T.
Of course, mathematicians in propounding definitions of mathematical
terms for words already in extra-mathematical use are generally even less
interested than Tarski was in their ordinary meanings. For they care no
more about extensional than about intensional agreement between the
technical sense being introduced and the ordinary sense, and they do not
lay down any criteria of ‘‘material adequacy’’ based on their (total or
partial) understanding of the word in its extra-mathematical sense. Thus
mathematicians feel no compunction whatsoever in speaking about
Hilbert ‘‘space,’’ though it certainly is not the kind of ‘‘space’’ that, say,
astronauts travel around in. But there is also a less superficial sense in which
mathematicians are unconcerned with meanings. For they are not really
concerned even with the meaning of the term in its technical sense, at
least not if ‘‘meaning’’ is understood in the same fine-grained way it is
Tarski’s tort 153
understood by lexicographers propounding definitions or philosophers
propounding analyses. This deeper kind of indifference to meaning, or at
least interest only in a very coarse-grained kind of ‘‘meaning,’’ is best
illustrated by an example.
An analysis text may define the constant e using the well-known repre-
sentation as the limit of a sequence:
(1) e ¼ limn!1 (1 þ n1)n.
Thereafter, all theorems about e in the text will refer back to this definition,
or to previous lemmas based on this definition. This includes, for instance,
the well-known representations as the sum of a series:
(2) e ¼ 1/0! þ 1/1! þ 1/2! þ 1/3! þ 1/4! þ . . .
Surely it is in this practice of fixing a definition and referring all later results
back to it that we should look for the origin of Frege’s notion that in a
properly constructed scientific language, each name should be associated
with a single, fixed definition.
The language of the mathematical community, however, does not con-
form to this requirement. For while one textbook writer may take (1) as the
definition and (2) as a theorem, another writer may do the reverse. Even a
mathematician taught originally from a textbook using one of these
approaches may him- or herself, when he or she comes in due course to
write a textbook, adopt the other. Moreover, even if a sizable majority
favors one approach, which is as may be, they will admit the legitimacy of
the other. There is no question of insisting on one definition as the true,
original one. It would be wrong to say that mathematicians do not care
about distinctions between definitions that are mathematically equivalent,
or even to say that they do not care about distinctions between those that
are provably equivalent, or even to say that they do not care about dis-
tinctions between those that have actually been proved to be equivalent, if
the proof is long and difficult and involves advanced ideas. But they are
indifferent to distinctions between definitions for which there are compa-
ratively well-known, short, simple, elementary proofs of equivalence. (1)
and (2) are certainly not synonymous in any reasonable sense of ‘‘synony-
mous,’’ but they are equally acceptable as ‘‘definitions’’ of e. It is in this
situation that we find the origin of the notion expressed in Quine (1936)
and elsewhere that definitional status is local and transitory – a notion at
the root of his ultimate rejection of the analytic/synthetic distinction.
This same kind of indifference to meaning may be found also in Tarski’s
paper, in addition to the kind of indifference to meaning I mentioned
154 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
earlier. For as Wilfrid Hodges reminds us,1 while Tarski’s general defini-
tion of truth is applicable to arbitrary interpreted languages of a certain
kind, for certain special interpreted languages another kind of definition of
truth, very different in appearance from the general definition, is available:
a definition of truth by elimination of quantifiers. The alternative defini-
tion is equally mathematically rigorous or ‘‘formally correct,’’ and equally
‘‘materially adequate,’’ so that it agrees in extension with the general
definition applied to this specific case, though it is by no means synony-
mous with the general definition in any reasonable sense of ‘‘synonymous.’’
Where such an alternative definition is available, Tarski is perfectly
happy with it. Thus Tarski is unconcerned with the meaning of ‘‘true’’ in
a double sense: first, he is unconcerned with pinning down precisely the
meaning of ‘‘true’’ in ordinary language, or in insuring that ‘‘true’’ as a
technical term will agree more than extensionally with ‘‘true’’ as an ordinary
term; second, he is unconcerned with differences between alternative
technical definitions, if these have been proved extensionally equivalent.
And if Tarski is doubly unconcerned with pinning down the meaning of
‘‘true,’’ he is even less concerned with analyzing the meaning of any other
word or symbol. A clause such as either of the following:
(3) (A and B) is true iff A is true and B is true
(4) True(A B) «True(A) True(B)
emphatically cannot be construed as telling us the meaning of the
word ‘‘and’’ or the symbol ‘‘.’’ For in Tarski’s original set-up, the ‘‘object
language’’ for which truth is being defined is contained in the metalanguage
in which the proof is being given. That is why we see ay-en-dees on both
sides of (3) and carets on both sides of (4). In order to understand the
definition, one must understand the metalanguage, and that includes
understanding the object language which is part of it, and therewith each
of the words or symbols of the object language.
1
In his ‘‘Tarski’s truth definitions,’’ in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy, http://plato.stanford.edu/
entries/tarski-truth/ (available only on-line).
Tarski’s tort 155
known as the theory of models. Hodges, however, has noted how very slow
Tarski was to advance beyond the 1933 definition of truth for sentences of
an interpreted language to the definition of the notion that is central to the
theory of models, namely, the notion of truth in a structure for sentences of
an uninterpreted language.
Formally the step is a very short one. An interpreted language is naturally
thought of as an ordered pair consisting of an uninterpreted language and
an interpretation. And an interpretation is simply a set, the domain, and an
assignment of a relation or operation of the right number of places on it to
each non-logical primitive. But that is essentially what a mathematical
structure is: a set, the domain, and certain distinguished relations and/or
operations on it, distinguished from each other by certain symbols asso-
ciated with them. For instance, a ring is, first of all, a set with two binary
operations, one written additively and one written multiplicatively. And
formally, the step from a two-place relation between a sentence and an
ordered pair consisting of an uninterpreted language plus an interpretation
or structure to a three-place relation among a sentence, an uninterpreted
language, and a structure or interpretation is a very short one. But though
Tarski was in effect operating with the latter notion within a few years, he
did not give an explicit definition until over two decades later. Indeed, it is
oversimplifying to say that he gave the definition, since it appears in a joint
paper with a student (Tarski and Vaught 1956).
This notion of a sentence of a given uninterpreted language being true
in a structure, or conversely, of a structure being a model of a sentence of
an uninterpreted language, has proved immensely useful both in appli-
cations to core mathematics (mainly abstract algebra) and in applications
to the metamathematics of set theory. The notion is also needed to
give a fully rigorous statement of the Löwenheim–Skolem and Gödel
completeness theorems, which were proved before they were stated, so
to speak.
Closely related to this last application was another application envi-
sioned by Tarski, that of giving a definition of logical truth. Here, however,
his work (Tarski 1936/1983d) is of more ambiguous status. Tarski himself
pointed to one limitation of his definition of logical truth or truth by virtue
of logical form alone as truth in all models: the definition presupposes a
division of symbols and notions into logical and non-logical, of which
Tarski was not to give an account until a late lecture, published only
posthumously (though since much discussed). Kreisel (1967) pointed
to another limitation: logical truth in an intuitive sense is truth in all
interpretations in an intuitive sense, and is not restricted to truth in
156 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
interpretations in the technical sense considered by Tarski, where the
quantifiers must range over a set and not a proper class. For first-order
logic, as Kreisel notes, the completeness theorem shows that it is enough to
consider interpretations where the domain is a set. But for second-order
logic (if one grants that it is logic) the assumption that holding in all
interpretations and holding in all set-interpretations – the intuitive notion
and the Tarski notion – coincide is not provable on the basis of the usual
ZFC axioms for set theory, but is in effect a large cardinal assumption. But
despite the limitations of Tarski’s approach on this one issue, there is no
denying that Tarski’s definition of truth was immensely successful.
Yet Tarski’s achievement was marred by a misdeed on his part that
opened the door to considerable mischief. His violation did not rise to the
level of felony or even misdemeanor – indeed, as my title suggests, it was a
civil rather than a criminal wrong. It was a case of trademark infringement:
his appropriating to his own use the linguists’ term ‘‘semantics.’’ Of course,
it was not really an actionable offense at all, since academic disciplines,
unlike business corporations, are not legal ‘‘persons’’ with standing to sue
anyone, though in a way that is a shame. (It would be a very good thing if,
for instance, the International Seismological Union could collect hefty
punitive damages from any writer who uses ‘‘epicenter’’ as a fancy synonym
for ‘‘center of activity.’’) And if Tarski’s act were actionable, there would be,
as in virtually all cases of this particular offense, something to be said for the
defense. There was a minority usage of ‘‘semantics’’ for something other
than a theory of the meanings of words. Indeed, there were several minority
usages, and in ‘‘The semantic conception of truth’’ (Tarski 1944), he is
quick to disassociate himself from one of them, the ‘‘General Semantics’’ of
another Polish thinker, Count Alfred Korzybski.
But there can hardly be any question that what ‘‘semantics’’ conveyed
and conveys to the mind of the general reader is a theory of meaning,
which Tarski’s theory most emphatically was not. By calling his theory
‘‘semantics,’’ Tarski opened the door to endless misunderstandings on this
point. There has been significant damage to logic arising from such
misunderstandings, from confusion of model theory or ‘‘semantics’’ impro-
perly so-called with meaning theory or ‘‘semantics’’ properly so-called.
Needless to say, if one is careful, one can avoid the confusion even
while keeping the double use of ‘‘semantics’’ by distinguishing formal from
linguistic. But in general usage ‘‘formal semantics’’ is a case of oxymoron
and ‘‘linguistic semantics’’ a case of pleonasm, and it would have been better
not to create a situation where there is a call for distinguishing adjectives
in the first place.
Tarski’s tort 157
Tarski’s usage did create such a situation, or at least the decision by most of
his successors to follow him in his usage of ‘‘semantics’’ has done so. For his
usage, though not in fact followed by workers in first-order model theory,
has generally been followed by philosophers, and even more so by com-
puter scientists working in the field of modal, temporal, and related logics.
Hence, for instance, the title ‘‘Semantical considerations on modal logic’’
for the paper Kripke (1963) in which the inventor of Kripke models finally
belatedly published his model theory for modal logic. Not everyone who
follows Tarski’s usage is confused, of course, but everyone who does so
encourages confusion, and there has been confusion enough, and this of
two kinds: spurious attributions of ontological commitment to commonplace
locutions and unwarranted complacency about the intelligibility of dubious
notions. Let me take up the first of these phenomena first, illustrating by the
case of tense logic.
In tense logic we have future-tense and past-tense operators F and P
whose intended meaning is something like ‘‘it (sometime) will be the
case that . . .’’ and ‘‘it (once) was the case that . . .’’ These behave syntacti-
cally like negation: they are one-place connectives. But it is not hard to see
that we cannot treat them model-theoretically like negation. These parallel
clauses:
(5) M |¼ A iff it is not the case that M |¼ A
(6) M |¼ FA iff it will be the case that M |¼ A
It is a significant historical fact that the model theory for modal logics was
worked out in the late fifties and early sixties, while the distinctions among
logical demonstrability, logical validity, analyticity, aprioricity, and neces-
sity in the sense of ‘‘would have been no matter what’’ or ‘‘couldn’t have
been otherwise’’ were largely overlooked until the later sixties and early
seventies – not that everyone pays sufficient attention to such distinctions
even today. That is to say, we were in possession of a model theory for
modal logic well before most modal logicians had an unambiguous and
unconfused understanding of what the modalities mean, or even any firm
guarantee that the modalities do mean something. This fact alone should
warn us that it is one thing to have a theory of models, and another to have
a theory of meaning. The following argument is utterly invalid:
These sentences have models.
These sentences have a semantics.
These sentences have a meaning.
Philosophically speaking, the model theory for modal logic has much
less direct value than does the parallel model theory for temporal logic. This
is because different theories about time do naturally present themselves as
theories about the relative-futurity relation on stages of the world, whereas
different conceptions of modality do not naturally present themselves as
theories about the relative-possibility relation on states of the world. It is
very useful to know that a certain class of modal models corresponds to a
certain axiomatic system, if there is reason to be interested in that axiom
system. But philosophically speaking, model theory is of little direct use in
establishing that a given axiom system is appropriate for a given conception
of modality. Indeed, though we have had the model theory for getting on
towards a half-century, the correct axiom system has been convincingly
determined only for a couple of conceptions of necessity: truth by virtue of
logical form, and provability in a given formal system.
I have addressed these topics elsewhere, but let me add just a word here
about provability logic. Here we have a clear understanding or intended
interpretation of what the box and diamond are to mean, and hence a clear
understanding or intended interpretation of what it is for a sentence
involving boxes and diamonds to be a law of logic, true in all instances –
essentially, for all substitutions of sentences of first-order arithmetic for the
sentence letters p, q, r, and so on. We have a proof that a certain axiomatic
system, GL, is sound for this intended interpretation. We have also, thanks
Tarski’s tort 161
to Segerberg, a proof that GL is both sound and complete for a certain class
of modal models. But for a long time this is all that we had, and we did not
have what we want from a theory of models, namely, an assurance that
truth in all models corresponds to truth in all instances, according to our
intended interpretation. This is something like the Kreisel gap noted earlier
in connection with first-order logic, but very much more serious.
But the serious lack was eventually supplied by the genius of Solovay. As
it happened, he made use of Segerberg’s earlier result. That is to say, rather
than ignore the modal models altogether and directly establish that if a
sentence is consistent with GL then it is true in some arithmetical instance,
thus establishing the completeness of GL for the intended interpretation,
he showed how from a model of the appropriate class of a sentence to
produce sentences of first-order arithmetic that, substituted for the sen-
tence letters, would result in an instance that is true according to the
intended interpretation, thus showing that truth in all models does corre-
spond to truth in all instances, and thus indirectly establishing the com-
pleteness of GL for the intended interpretation, given Segerberg’s result
about its completeness for models of the appropriate class. The model
theory is useful, but it is useful only as an auxiliary. Segerberg’s contribu-
tion did not go to waste, but Solovay’s contribution was crucial. For a full
exposition of these matters, and references to the further literature, see
Boolos (1993).
There are other examples of the same phenomenon, where the
model theory plays only an auxiliary role. One pertains to intuitionistic
logic, with Tarski and Kripke in the role of Segerberg and Kreisel in the
role of Solovay. For an exposition see Burgess (1981a). What reflection on
these examples should make clear is that merely possessing a model-
theoretic characterization of a given axiomatic system of modal logic
does not suffice to tell us that the system captures (that is, is sound and
complete for) any interesting interpretation or concept of necessity.
Provision of a purely formal ‘‘semantics’’ for an axiomatic system that
had been without one – for instance, the provision by Fine and by Meyer
of a purely formal ‘‘semantics’’ for the system R of relevance/relevant logic –
does little, and by itself does nothing towards establishing the coher-
ence and intelligibility of any underlying motivating ideas or intended
intuitive interpretation. This last is one case where there certainly was
premature celebration, provoking a paper, ‘‘When is a semantics not a
semantics?’’ by B. J. Copeland (1979), that is still well worth reading to
dispel confusions. So Tarski’s using the word ‘‘semantics’’ in connection
with his truth definition has opened the door to confusion in the area of
162 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
modal and more generally intensional or philosophical logic, which people
like Copeland and myself have then had to come along after and try to
straighten out.
Now one who opens a door that should have been left closed cannot be
held responsible for every mischievous thing that then walks through it,
and Tarski was himself the first victim of mischief resulting from his
original offense. I think he was naughty, and should have been made to
stand in a corner by linguists; but he actually suffered something consid-
erably worse: he was stood on his head by Donald Davidson and his
disciples. For Tarski’s usage has not only tended to encourage the modal
muddles I have been bemoaning, but also seems to me to have been in part
responsible for the insufficiently critical reception of the truth-conditional
theory of meaning; and this theory is diametrically opposed to Tarski’s
own views on the meaning of truth and to his views on the paradoxes with
which we began. Now while I hope it will be universally agreed that the
modal muddles Tarski’s usage may have encouraged are bad things, this
certainly will not be agreed about the acceptance of a truth-conditional
theory of meaning or the rejection of Tarski’s view of the paradoxes.
The most I can hope will be agreed is that if Tarski’s usage contributed
to the formation of a predisposition to accept the one and reject the other
that was independent of the real merits of the case, then that development
was a bad thing.
In any case, besides Tarski’s usage of ‘‘semantics’’ there is another feature
of Tarski’s definition of truth, or rather, of the Tarski–Vaught definition of
the model, that may have been operative. To begin with, it may be noted
that once we make the transition to the Tarski–Vaught notion of truth in a
model, we soon find ourselves departing from Tarski’s original notion that
truth for a given language is to be defined in a metalanguage containing
that language.
For the languages for which truth in a model are being defined are
formal languages, while the papers on model theory containing the defi-
nitions are, like other mathematical papers, invariably written in (a mathe-
maticians’ dialect of) a natural language, nowadays usually English. Thus
instead of
(7) M |¼ (A B) « (M |¼ A M |¼ B)
(8) M |¼ (A and B) iff (M |¼ A and M |¼ B)
Tarski’s tort 163
we find
(9) M |¼ (A B) iff (M |¼ A and M |¼ B).
And whereas (7) and (8) do not on the face of it look as if they could be
telling one anything about the meaning of ‘‘’’ or ‘‘and’’ that one did not
already know – after all if one doesn’t know the meaning of ‘‘’’ already one
is not going to understand the right-hand side of (7), and if one does not
know the meaning of ‘‘and’’ already one is not going to understand the
right-hand side of (8) – by contrast (9) does rather look as if it were telling
us something about the meaning of ‘‘,’’ given that we already know the
meaning of ‘‘and.’’
It is tempting to think of the status of (9) as being something like the
status of the following:
(10) ( jai D) is true iff is true and D is true.
And (10) does tell us something – I do not say everything, but I do say
something – about the meaning of the Greek word ‘‘jai.’’ But notice that
(10) tells us something about the meaning of ‘‘jai’’ only because we already
know the meaning of ‘‘and’’ and because we already know the meaning of
‘‘true,’’ at least to the extent of knowing Convention T. So there is a
significant difference between (10) and (9), since the latter involves the
symbol ‘‘|¼’’ rather than the English word ‘‘true.’’
If we consider the clauses in a Tarski–Vaught style definition, thus:
(11a) M |¼ A iff not M |¼ A
(11b) M |¼ (A B) iff (M |¼ A and M |¼ B)
(11c) M |¼ (A B) iff (M |¼ A or M |¼ B)
we cannot take these to be telling us both what the double turnstile means
and what the caret, wedge, tilde, and so on mean. For there are too many
unknowns and not enough equations. The intention is that the double
turnstile is to be read as ‘‘true,’’ the caret as ‘‘and,’’ the wedge as ‘‘or’’; but the
biconditionals would be equally appropriate if instead the double turn-
stile were read as ‘‘false’’ and the caret as ‘‘or’’ and the wedge as ‘‘and.’’ If a
student with no previous knowledge of these matters is told that the
caret, wedge, and so forth are to be read as ‘‘and,’’ ‘‘or,’’ and so forth,
then the student may be able to figure out that the double turnstile might
be read as ‘‘true’’; inversely, if the student is told that the double turnstile
is to be read as ‘‘true,’’ then the student may be able to figure out that the
caret might be read as ‘‘and,’’ the wedge as ‘‘or,’’ and so forth. But the
student has to be given some clue or other.
164 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
Now, once the model theorist is past the student stage, and knows that
the double turnstile is customarily to be read as ‘‘true,’’ the model theorist
does learn something about how an addition to the usual list of logical
symbols might be read, if the colleague proposing the addition indicates
how the usual definition of double turnstile is to be extended to the
extended language. For instance, a clause
(12) M |¼ (A # B) iff not (M |¼ A and M |¼ B)
would suggest the reading ‘‘not both’’ for the down arrow. And to give a
perhaps more realistic example, in papers on generalized quantifiers the
same symbol Q gets used over and over, with different clauses in the
definition of double turnstile in different papers, suggesting different read-
ings in different papers, among them ‘‘there exist infinitely many,’’ ‘‘there
exist uncountably many,’’ ‘‘most,’’ and others. The analogue of (12) in a
given paper in such cases tells one something about what the symbol Q is
being used to mean in that given paper. But our ability to guess the readings
is entirely dependent on our familiarity with the meanings of ‘‘infinitely
many’’ and ‘‘uncountably many’’ and ‘‘most,’’ and on our familiarity with
what ‘‘true’’ means, at least to the extent of being familiar with Convention
T, and with the custom of reading the double turnstile as ‘‘true.’’
And in any case, we are not really being told that ‘‘QxA(x)’’ in a given paper
means ‘‘there exist infinitely many x such that A(x),’’ but only that it means
something that is true if and only if there exist infinitely many x such that
A(x), a condition fulfilled not only by ‘‘there exist infinitely many x such that
A(x)’’ but also by ‘‘it is not the case that for all but finitely many x it is not the
case that A(x),’’ and by infinitely many other alternatives. After all, merely to
be told that some sentence of a foreign language we do not understand is true
if and only if, say, snow is white, does not tell us what the sentence means.
Taken together with our knowledge that snow is white, it does tell us that the
sentence means something true. But that is all. Merely being given a list of
items of the following kind, one for each sentence of the foreign language:
(13) ‘‘[FOREIGN SENTENCE]’’ is true iff [ENGLISH SENTENCE]
will not tell us what the sentences mean. If I tell you
(14a) ‘‘To viomi eimai arpqo’’ is true iff snow is white
(14b) ‘‘To jaqbotmo eimai latqo’’ is true iff coal is black
I allow you, given the common knowledge that snow is white and coal is
black, to infer that the two Greek sentences quoted are true; but I do not
divulge the meaning of any Greek sentence.
Tarski’s tort 165
Donald Davidson conjectured, however, in Davidson (1967) and
sequels, that if we require some finite apparatus to generate recursively,
with clauses like (10), a whole list of items of type (12) for every Greek
sentence, and if we impose some suitable further restrictions, then in fact
what appear on the right-hand side of each item on the list will have to be
English sentences with the same meaning as the Greek sentence on the left-
hand side. Or rather – since he was writing during the era of Quinean
suspicion about meaning – the Greek and English sentences will have to be
close enough in meaning, according to our intuitive, pre-theoretic under-
standing of ‘‘meaning,’’ that appearing on opposite sides of a list generated
in the manner indicated can serve as a workable substitute for the intuitive,
pre-theoretic, but to some suspect, understanding of sameness of ‘‘mean-
ing.’’ In short, while in order to learn the meaning of Greek sentences and
the words of which they are composed it is not enough to be told things like
(14a,b), Davidson conjectured that, in order to do so it may be enough to
be told, or to come to know, such things in the right way.
Davidson’s conjecture that theories of truth can in this sense serve as
theories of meaning eventually gave rise to what I will call Davidsonianism,
without intending to imply that Davidson himself fully subscribed to it,
namely, the truth-conditional theory of meaning. Formally, indeed, the
step from Davidson’s theory about how to tell the meanings of foreign
sentences to speakers who already know the meaning of English sentences
to the Davidsonian theory that knowledge of the truth conditions of
English sentences is what knowledge of the meaning of English sentences
consists in, can be a very short one. For the simplest version of
Davidsonianism would simply be the analogue of what Davidson says
about Greek and English applied to English and a hypothetical innate
language of thought. Using the language of Descartes to represent the
language of thought, coming to know the meaning of the English sentences
‘‘Snow is white,’’ ‘‘Grass is green,’’ and so on, amounts to coming in the
right way to know the following:
(15a) ‘‘Snow is white’’ est vraie ssi la neige est blanche
(15b) ‘‘Grass is green’’ est vraie ssi l’herbe est verte.
Davidsonianism as such, it should be emphasized, is not committed to the
language of thought hypothesis; I only say that Davidsonianism is imme-
diate from the conjecture of Davidson if one accepts that hypothesis.
For some of us Davidsonianism seems, not least on account of its
apparent assumption that truth is an innate idea, possession of which is a
prerequisite for all language-learning, to be preposterous. For others, the
166 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
Davidsonian assumption is so much taken for granted that it is hardly
recognized as a substantive assumption at all. My concern here will be
not with the enormous question of the merits or demerits of the truth-
conditional theory of meaning, but only with the extent to which Tarski
deserves a share of the blame or credit for its becoming so widely held a
belief among philosophers as it currently is.
The first thing that must be said on this head is, of course, that Tarski’s
responsibility is limited. Davidson himself is not fully responsible for his
disciples’ extrapolations from his conjectures, and Tarski is certainly not
fully responsible for widespread sympathetic reception of those conjec-
tures. It must be acknowledged, for one thing, that their sympathetic
reception was surely in part due to the prestige of the name of Davidson
as a result of quite other achievements. But then again, was it not in part
due to the prestige of the name of Tarski, which Davidson so frequently
invoked?
Well, even if so, it must be acknowledged, for another thing, that the
invocation of Tarski’s name was not entirely appropriate, since as
Davidson, if not every one of his disciples, was aware, those conjectures
amount to an inversion of Tarski. For they make what for Tarski were
clauses in a definition of truth in terms of already understood notions like
negation and conjunction and disjunction, into definitions of a kind of
those operators, in terms of a notion of truth taken as primitive. We
constantly find in the writings of Davidson and disciples mentions of a
‘‘Tarskian’’ theory of truth, where ‘‘counter-Tarskian’’ or ‘‘anti-Tarskian’’
would have been more accurate, if less likely to confer borrowed prestige on
bold (which is to say doubtful) new conjectures. And Tarski, of course, is
not responsible for this usage. But would the idea of invoking Tarski’s
name at all in connection with a theory of meaning have occurred to
anyone, if Tarski had not himself attached to his theory a label ordinarily
used for the theory of meaning, the label ‘‘semantics’’?
7 THE ‘‘ S E M A N T I C ’’ PARADOXES
1 THE QUESTION
Which if any of the many systems of modal logic in the literature is it whose
theorems are all and only the right general laws of necessity? That depends
on what kind of necessity is in question, so I should begin by making
distinctions.
A first distinction that must be noted is between metaphysical necessity or
inevitability – ‘‘what could not have been otherwise’’ – and logical necessity
or tautology – ‘‘what it is self-contradictory to say is otherwise.’’ The stock
example to distinguish the two is this: ‘‘Water is a compound and not an
element.’’ Water could not have been anything other than what it is, a
compound of hydrogen and oxygen; but there is no self-contradiction in
saying, as was often said, that water is one of four elements along with earth
and air and fire.
The logic of inevitability might be called mood logic, by analogy with
tense logic. For the one aims to do for the distinction between the
indicative ‘‘it is the case that . . .’’ and the subjunctive ‘‘it could have been
the case that . . .,’’ something like what the other does for the distinction
between the present ‘‘it is the case that . . .’’ and the future ‘‘it will be the case
that . . .’’ or the past ‘‘it was the case that . . .’’ The logic of tautology might
be called endometalogic, since it attempts to treat within the object language
notions that classical logic treats only in the metalanguage. However, it
hardly deserves a name, since it immediately splits up into two subjects.
For a second distinction must be between two senses of tautology. On
the one hand, there is model-theoretic logical necessity or validity, the non-
existence of a falsifying interpretation, ‘‘being true by logical form alone.’’
On the other hand, there is proof-theoretic logical necessity or demonstrabil-
ity, the existence of a verifying derivation, ‘‘being recognizable as true by
logical considerations alone.’’ Likewise, there is a distinction between two
notions of contradiction, model-theoretic unsatisfiability and proof-theoretic
169
170 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
inconsistency, and between two notions of implication, model-theoretic
consequence and proof-theoretic deducibility. There would be at least a
conceptual distinction even if logic were understood narrowly as first-order
logic, where the model-theoretic and proof-theoretic notions coincide in
extension by the Gödel Completeness Theorem. There may be a difference
in extension between them when logic is understood more broadly: for
instance, if it is taken to include higher-order logic and the mathematics
that goes with it.
Logicians often call model-theoretic and proof-theoretic necessity
semantic and syntactic logical necessity. However, there is a conflict between
this usage and the older usage of linguists on which, roughly speaking,
‘‘semantic’’ means ‘‘pertaining to meaning’’ and ‘‘syntactic’’ means ‘‘per-
taining to grammar.’’ There is a conflict between the two usages of
‘‘semantics,’’ especially, because there is or may be a gap between mathe-
matical modeling and intended meaning. In any case, shorter labels than
‘‘the logic of semantic logical necessity’’ and ‘‘the logic of syntactic logical
necessity’’ would be useful. One might use proplasmatic logic and apodictic
logic, from the Greek for model and proof. But it may be more suggestive
to use validity logic and demonstrability logic, by analogy with provability
logic. The analogy between provability logic and demonstrability logic is
especially close, the one being concerned with what a theory can prove, the
other with what we can demonstrate, the ‘‘can’’ in each pertaining to ability
in principle, regardless of practical limitations.
The question which is the right system of tense logic is not one for the
logician: the logician can indicate how this or that or the other system
corresponds to this or that or the other theory of the nature of time, but
which is the right theory of the nature of time is a question for the physicist.
Similarly, the question which is the right system of mood logic would seem
to be one not for the logician, but for the metaphysician. By contrast, the
question which is the right system of validity or demonstrability logic
cannot be passed off by logic to some other discipline.
The question which is the right validity logic has been answered at the
sentential level, which is the only level that will be considered here: it is the
system known as S5. This result is essentially established already in Carnap
(1946).
The question which is the right demonstrability logic, again at the
sentential level, goes back to the earliest days of modern modal logic. For
though the founder of the subject, C. I. Lewis, did not clearly distinguish
among metaphysical, model-theoretic logical, and proof-theoretic logical
modalities, still he did always write of necessitation as implication, and did
Which modal logic is the right one? 171
often write of implication as deducibility, so that it is reasonable to
conclude that by necessity he primarily meant tautology, by which in
turn he primarily meant demonstrability. No one today, however, takes
seriously his suggestion that the right logic for this notion might be the
feeble S1 or the bizarre S3. To the extent that there is any consensus or
plurality view among logicians today, I take the view to be that the right
demonstrability logic is S4. (Even in ‘‘relevance’’ or ‘‘relevant’’ logic, where
S4 cannot be literally accepted, since the classical sentential logic it is based
on is rejected, still it seems to be a consensus or plurality view that the right
logic should be ‘‘S4-like.’’) The locus classicus for such a view is a paper from
the proceedings of a famous 1962 Helsinki conference on modal logic
(Halldén 1963).
While the argument for the soundness of S4 as a demonstrability logic
given there seems as compelling as an ‘‘informally rigorous’’ argument can
be, there is no real argument for completeness, which remains an open
question. It therefore remains conceivable that the right logic is something
stronger than S4: that it is something intermediate between S4 and S5, such
as S4.2 or S4.3; or that it is something stronger than S4 but incomparable
with S5, such as the logic called Grz after Grzegorczyk (1967) and the logic
that ought to be called McK after McKinsey (1945). (In the literature it has
heretofore been misleadingly called S4.1, though it is not intermediate
between S4 and S5.)
The issues are sufficiently illustrated by the cases of the distinctive axioms
of S4.2 and of McK, which are equivalent respectively to (&&p
&&p), the principle that ‘‘nothing is both demonstrably not demon-
strable true and demonstrably not demonstrably false,’’ and to &&p
&&p, the principle that ‘‘everything is either demonstrably not demon-
strably true or demonstrably not demonstrably false.’’ Halldén rightly says of
the latter – what he could also have said of the former – that it is not an
intuitively plausible principle when the box & is meant as demonstrability.
But to say this is to do something less than to give an ‘‘informally rigorous’’
argument for the claim that either principle outright fails as a general law, let
alone for the claim that any principle not a theorem of S4 does so.
The question which is the right provability logic has been answered, and
though results are often stated for a single-theory, classical first-order
arithmetic, many hold for all true theories satisfying certain minimum
requirements of strength. Actually, one must distinguish the question of
which logic gives all and only those principles about provability all whose
instances are provable by the theory in question from the question which
gives all and only those principles that are valid (or demonstrable by us).
172 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
The answer to the former question is given by a system GL, and to the latter
question by a system GLS. Both differ from the Lewis systems S4 and S5 by
lacking the law &(&p!p). The failure of this law is, roughly speaking, the
content of the Gödel Incompleteness Theorems. The standard reference is
of course Boolos (1993).
Below, in x2 I will recall the case for the soundness of S5 as a validity
logic and of S4 as a demonstrability logic. In x3 I will recall the Carnapian
case for the completeness of S5. In x4 I will indicate the minimal require-
ments of strength that are assumed in provability logic, and that I will be
assuming in demonstrability logic also, and attempt to clarify the relation-
ship between the two logics. In x5 I will present a case against McK as a
demonstrability logic; and it will generalize to a case against any system not
contained in S5, such as Grz. Finally, in x6 I will present a case against S4.2;
and this will of course also constitute a case against any stronger system,
such as S4.3. But the case of weaker systems intermediate between S4 and
S5 will be left open, and with it the general question.
2 SOUNDNESS
Suppose that the antecedent of (5) is true, which is to say that the following
is false:
(6) It is true by logical form alone that p.
Since (6) is false, there must be some y of the same logical form as p that is
false. Now consider anything else of the same logical form as (6). It will
look like the following, wherein q has the same logical form as p:
(7) It is true by logical form alone that q.
174 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
But then y also has the same logical form as q, and since y is false, (7) is
false. In other words, anything of the same logical form as (6) is false, and
hence the following is true:
(8) It is true by logical form alone that it is not true by logical form alone that p.
Thus the consequent of (5) is true, as required.
What is needed for logical necessity of a sentence p in a world w0 is more than its
truth in each one of some arbitrarily selected set of alternatives to w0. What is
needed is its truth in each logically possible world. However, in Kripke semantics it
is not required that all such worlds are among the alternatives to a given one.
It is then suggested that one should adopt not the standard model theory,
or the simplification thereof described above, but rather a deviant model
176 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
theory, which after simplification amounts to just this, that the only model
admitted is the one consisting of all rows of the truth table.
There is a fallacy or confusion here. What is wanted is that the technical
notion of coming out true in all models should correspond to the intuitive
notion of coming out true under all interpretations, or all substitutions of
specific p1, . . . , pk for the variables p1, . . . , pk. Since, for instance, among all
the many substitutions available there are ones in which the p1 substituted for
p1 is the same as the p2 substituted for p2, so that it is impossible for p1 and p2
to have different truth values, there must correspondingly be among the
models one available where the only rows of the truth table present are those
for which the value given to p1 is the same as the value given to p2.
The confusion in the objection becomes apparent when one notes that
in the deviant model theory suggested, &(p1 p2) counts as valid,
whereas of course &(p1 p1) does not, so that the standard rule of
substitution fails. But the rule of substitution must hold so long as one
adheres to the standard conception of the role of the variables p1, . . . , pk,
according to which arbitrarily selected p1, . . . , pk may be substituted for
them. Indeed, the deviant model theory corresponds to a deviant concep-
tion on which independent p1, . . . , pk must be substituted for distinct p1, . . . ,
pk. The confusion is worse confounded when it is suggested that the
difference between the standard and deviant model theories somehow
corresponds to a difference between non-logical and logical notions of
necessity. For what is at issue is, to repeat, differences in conceptions of the
role of variables, not in conceptions of the nature of necessity.
Yet, confused as it is, the objection does serve to call attention to an
important question. Each substitution of specific p1, . . . , pk for p1, . . . , pk
determines a non-empty set of rows of the truth table, consisting of all and
only those rows x such that it is not impossible by the logical forms of the pi
alone for them to have the truth values x assigns to the corresponding pi.
The question is, is it the case that for any arbitrarily selected non-empty
subset W of the set of rows of the truth table, there are specific statements
p1, . . . , pk that determine, in the manner just described, exactly that subset?
In other words, if a formula is not a theorem of S5, and therefore fails in
some standard model, is there some specific instance in which it fails? An
affirmative answer to this question is precisely what is needed to establish
the material completeness of S5 as validity logic.
It is a reasonable assumption, and one presumably made by the critics
alluded to, that there exist indefinitely many a, b, g, . . . that are independ-
ent in the sense that any conjunction of some of them with the negations of
the rest of them is possible, in the relevant sense of possibility. For instance,
Which modal logic is the right one? 177
if a, b, g, . . . are of simple subject–predicate form with distinct subjects
and predicates in each, they will be thus independent. Given this assump-
tion, an affirmative answer to the foregoing question is forthcoming. As
this result has in effect already been expounded several times in the
literature, in Carnap (1946), Makinson (1966), and S. K. Thomason
(1973), there should be no need for me to do more than give an illustrative
example here. Indeed, a simple one, involving just three sentence letters
p, q, r, should suffice.
Consider the set W containing just the three rows in which two of p, q, r
are true and the other false. Call the one where r alone is false x, the one
where q alone is false y, and the one where p alone is false z. What is to be
established is that given independent a, b, . . . , there are truth-functional
compounds p, y, q thereof that might be substituted for p, q, r, for which
the three rows indicated represent all and only the combinations of truth
values that are not false by logical form alone.
To find the required compounds, one first finds three auxiliary compounds
, u, , that are pairwise exclusive and jointly exhaustive, meaning that the
conjunction of any two must be false by logical form alone, while the
disjunction of all three must be true by logical form alone. Setting ¼ a and
u ¼ a b and ¼ a b will do. One next lets the auxiliaries , u,
correspond to the rows x, y, z, and takes as the substitute for a given one of
p, q, r the disjunction of the auxiliaries corresponding to the rows in which it
is true. Thus the substitute p for p should be u or a (a b), which
simplifies to a b. It can be worked out that the substitutes y and q for q and r
simplify to a b and a, respectively. And it can then be worked out that
exactly two of the three, a b and a b and a, must be true, and that
given the independence of a and b it may be any two of the three, as required.
Before leaving the topic of validity logic it may be mentioned that the
fact that S5 is indeed the right logic can be confirmed in a different way.
After soundness is established in order to show that no stronger system than
S5 is acceptable, one would appeal to the result of Scroggs (1951), according
to which the only extensions of S5 are finitely-many-valued logics. One
would then argue that no finitely-many-valued logic can be correct for
semantic logical necessity (given the same reasonable assumption as above,
that there are indefinitely distinct independent statements).
Clearly (30 ) above by itself does not, with (20 ) above, yield (10 ) above.
Rather, one would need the following stronger assumption:
5 AGAINST McK
6 AGAINST S4.2
It is rather discouraging that forty years have passed since Frederic Fitch
first propounded his paradox of knowability without philosophers having
achieved agreement on a solution.2 As a general rule, when modal phe-
nomena prove puzzling, it is a good idea to look at the corresponding
temporal phenomena, and accordingly I propose to examine here not the
knowability principle that whatever is true can be known, but rather the
discovery principle that whatever is true will be known.
As Fitch’s modal paradox attacks the knowability principle, so an
analogous temporal paradox threatens the discovery principle. The for-
mulation of the paradox is as follows. Start with the minimal tense logic
with G and H for ‘‘it is always going to be . . .’’ and ‘‘it always has been . . .’’
as primitive, and F and P for ‘‘it sometime will be . . .’’ and ‘‘it once was . . .’’
defined as G and H.3 Add a one-place epistemic operator K for ‘‘it
is known that,’’ and add as axioms minimal assumptions for this new
operator, expressing that anything known is true, and that if a conjunction
is known, so are both conjuncts:
(1) Kp ! p
(2) K(p & q) ! Kp & Kq.
1
First published in Slaerno (2007).
2
(Fitch 1963). For a summary of recent debates, see B. Brogaard and J. Salerno, ‘‘Fitch’s Paradox
of Knowability,’’ in Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy: http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/fitch-
paradox/ (available only on-line).
3
See (Burgess 1984a). The various theorems of tense logic cited below can all be found in this source.
185
186 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
The paradox is that one can then derive the following:
(4) p ! Kp.
The derivation of (4) using (3) is, apart from replacing & and à by G and F,
the same as Fitch’s derivation, which is too well known to bear repeating
here.
The operator K is intended to indicate human knowledge, not divine
omniscience. The grounds for belief in the discovery principle have indeed
traditionally involved a belief in divine omniscience, but it is not this belief
alone that supports the principle, but rather this belief plus a further belief
that on some future day God will bring it about that whatever is hidden is
made manifest (quidquid latet apparebit). Obviously that day has not yet
come, and the conclusion (4), that everything true is already humanly
known, is an absurdity, and so we have a reductio of the principle (3).
The ‘‘dialethists’’ and other proponents of radical revisions of classical
logic can be counted on to tout their proposed revisions as solutions to
this paradox, as they have touted them as the solutions to so many others.
But a priori it is overwhelmingly more likely that the problem lies not in
the underlying classical logic, but in the least familiar element, the axiom
(3), the only axiom in which temporal and epistemic operators interact.
And indeed, that is where the problem lies. One has to be careful in going
back and forth between symbolism and English prose, and Fitch, or rather
his hypothetical temporal analogue, was not careful enough.
In tense logic p, q, r, . . . are supposed to stand for tensed sentences,
whose truth value may change with time (or if one wants to speak of
‘‘propositions,’’ then they must be propositions in a traditional rather than
a contemporary sense, propositions that are themselves tensed, and whose
truth value may change with time). FA is supposed to be true at a given
time if A is true at some later time. What (3) actually expresses thus
amounts to this:
(5) If p is true now, then at some later time it will be known that p is true then.
The proposed formalization as (3) has in effect turned the principle that
any truth will become known into the principle that any sentence that
expresses a truth will come to be known to express a truth. But this last
formulation invites the immediate objection that the sentence in question
may cease to express a truth before the knowledge of the truth it once
expressed is acquired.
And so (5) surely does not express what Shakespeare meant in saying
‘‘Truth will out.’’ He meant to imply that if Smith murders Jones secretly,
Can truth out? 187
so that no one knows, then it will become known that Smith murdered
Jones secretly, so that no one knew. He did not mean to imply that if what
the form of words ‘‘Unknown to all, Smith has murdered Jones’’ now
expresses is true, then there will come a time when what that same form of
words then expresses will be known to be true. Thus the temporal analogue
of Fitch’s argument does not discredit the discovery principle, because the
target of that argument is not a correct expression of that principle.
2 INEFFABLE TRUTHS
3 EPHEMERAL TRUTHS
4 A REFORMULATION
We have seen that (1.3) – displayed item (3) of x1 – is not the right
formalization of the discovery principle. What is? It cannot be claimed
4
I mean the riddle:
Q. What is it that God never sees, that the king seldom sees, but that you and I see every day?
A. An equal.
This seems less a problem for theologians than for partisans of ‘‘substitutional quantification.’’
190 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
that a complete solution to the paradox has been obtained until this
question is answered.
One answer suggests itself at once. Now that we have restricted the
principle to truths that will remain expressible in our language in the
future, it is tempting to formulate the principle as the principle that any
sentence that will continue to express a truth in the future will come to be
known to express a truth. This goes over into symbols as follows:
(1) Gp ! FKp.
And (1) is, unlike (1.3), immune to Fitch-style paradox, even if one
considerably strengthens the background tense logic. For definiteness, let
us consider the tense logic, call it Llinear, that is appropriate for linearly
ordered time without a last time. Then the immunity of (1) from Fitch-
style paradox is the content of the following proposition.
Proposition. Let T be Llinear plus (1.1), (1.2), and (1). Then (1.4) is not a
theorem of T.
Proof. Consider an auxiliary theory T , obtained from L by adding a
constant p and the following axiom:
(2) Fp.
Then p is not a theorem of T . For if we take any of model of Llinear, and let
p be true at and only at the times later than the present, then (2) will be true
at all times, but p will not, being false at all past times and at the present
time.
Next assign each formula A of the language of T a translation A into the
language of T , by taking Kp to abbreviate p & p. Thus (1.1), (1.2), (1), and
(1.4), respectively, are translated as follows:
(3) p&p!p
(4) (p & q) & p ! (p & p) & (q & p)
(5) Gp ! F(p & p)
(6) p ! p & p.
Note that the translation (6) of (1.4) is not a theorem of T . For if it were,
substituting p for p and applying truth-functional logic, p would be a
theorem, as we have seen it is not.
To show that (1.4) is not a theorem of T, it will suffice to show that the
translation of any theorem of T is a theorem of T . And to show this, it will
suffice to show that the translations (3)–(5) of the three axioms of T are
theorems of T . For the first two axioms this is trivial, since (3) and (4) are
truth-functional tautologies. For the third axiom, the following is a theo-
rem of Llinear:
Can truth out? 191
(7) Gp & Fq ! F(p & q).
And (5) follows by truth-functional logic from (2) and (7), to complete the
proof.
(1) Pp ! FKPp
(2) p ! FKPp
(3) Fp ! FKPp
(4) Gp ! FKGp.
(For the cognoscenti, the assumption here is that the rule of temporal
generalization, on which (10) depends, continues to apply after the
formal language has been enriched by the addition of the epistemic
operator K.)
(1), (2), and (4) are immediate from (5), (6), and (9), respectively. As for
(3), it can be derived as follows:
(11) FPp ! FFKPp from (1) by (10)
(12) FPp ! FKPp from (11) and (8).
6 EXAMPLES
7 ‘‘ N O W ’’
Nonetheless, it may seem that the most obvious correction of (1.5) would
be the following:
(1) If p is true now, then at some later time it will be known that p was true now.
And (1) seems to tell us more than (4.1) (by way of (6.3)) tells us.
It is known that (1) cannot be expressed using just the temporal oper-
ators G and H and F and P. But tense logicians have considered other
operators. Most to the point in the present context, they have considered a
‘‘now’’ operator J, so interpreted that even within the scope of a past or
future operator Jp still expresses the present, not the past or future, truth of
p. And with this operator (1) can be symbolized, as follows:
(2) p ! FKJp.
One may be tempted to think that (2) would do better as a formalization
of the discovery principle than does (4.1). But this is a misleading way of
putting the issue. For if the operator J is admitted, subject to its usual laws,
then (4.1) implies (2). For one of the usual laws is precisely
(3) p ! GJp
and (2) is immediate from (3) and (4.1). So the temptation here is simply
the temptation to add J to the language.5
I think the temptation should be resisted for a double reason. My first
reason is that introducing the J-operator is unnecessary in order to answer a
when-question. For I have just finished arguing that (4.1) does, after
all, provide answers to such questions. Against this it may be said that
(2) appears to have the advantage of doing so without depending on
chronometry. But my second reason for avoiding the J-operator is that
this apparent advantage comes at the cost of involving us with the problem-
atic notion of a de re attitude towards a time.
This truth is perhaps most easily brought to light by switching tempo-
rarily from regimentations using tense operators to regimentations using
5
I owe this observation to Williamson.
194 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
explicit quantification over times. So let t, u, v, . . . range over times. And
let t < u mean that time t is earlier than time u, or equivalently, time u is
later than time t. Let each tensed p be replaced by a one-place p (t) for
‘‘p [is] the case at time t.’’ Every formula A built up from the letters
p, q, r, . . . will similarly be replaced by an open formula A (t). PA and
FA, respectively, will be replaced by
(4a) 9u(u < t & A (u)) (4b) 9u(t < u & A (u)).
In a formula A(t) the parameter t may be thought of as standing for that
time which is now present. Leaving open how to symbolize the epistemic
operator, (5.2) and (2) above go halfway into symbols as follows:
(5) p(t) ! 9u(t < u & it is known at time u that 9v(v < u & p(v)))
(6) p(t) ! 9u(t < u & it is known at time u that p(t)).
8 DE RE ATTITUDES
There are (at least) three major difficulties in making sense of the notion of
a de re knowledge about an object a. Or to put the matter another way,
there is only one obvious strategy for making sense of the notion of a de re
attitude, namely, reduction to a de dicto attitude, and there are (at least)
three major obstacles to this strategy. The strategy is to understand a
subject as knowing of an object a that F(x) holds of it if and only if the
subject knows that F(a) where a is a term denoting a. The three obstacles
or problems relate to the choice of term a.
A first general problem with de re knowledge is that of anonymity. There
may simply be no term a denoting a. This problem has been encountered
Can truth out? 195
in the case of times in x2, and given the restriction on the discovery
principle imposed there, it may be set aside here.
A second general problem with de re knowledge, and one relevant to the
question whether J should be admitted, is the problem of aliases. The
problem is that there may be two terms a and b denoting an object a, and it
may be that the subject knows that F(a) but does not know that F(b), or the
reverse. The star whose common name is ‘‘Aldebaran’’ has also the official
name ‘‘Alpha Tauri.’’ It seems that a subject may have been told by differ-
ent authoritative sources, and hence may know that
(1) Aldebaran is orangish.
(2) Alpha Tauri is the thirteenth brightest star.
and yet, being in ignorance that the two names are names for one and the
same heavenly body, may not know that
(3) Alpha Tauri is orangish.
(4) Aldebaran is the thirteenth brightest star.
And this makes it hard to answer the question whether the subject knows of
the star itself, independently of how it is named, that it is orangish, or the
thirteenth brightest. The existence of aliases is a problem insofar as privi-
leging one of them over the other seems arbitrary.
The same problem can arise for times. Robinson may know that one
rainy day Smith committed murder, and may know that Jones was mur-
dered, and not know that the murder Smith committed was that of Jones.
In this case Robinson will know that
(5) At the time when Smith committed murder, it was rainy.
but not that
(6) At the time when Jones was murdered, it was rainy.
And this makes it hard to answer the question whether Robinson knows of
the time itself, independently of how it is described, that it was rainy then.
Where there exists some standard term for each object of a given kind,
one can always stipulate that a subject is to be credited with de re
knowledge about the object a that F(x) holds of it, if and only if the
subject has de dicto knowledge that F(a) where a is the standard term for
a. Admittedly, such a stipulation may be more a matter of giving a sense
to a kind of locution (ascriptions of de re knowledge) that previously had
none, than of finding out what sense this kind of locution had all along.
Pretty clearly it would be a case of giving rather than finding if
196 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
one took as canonical terms for heavenly bodies the official names
adopted by international scientific bodies, preferring ‘‘Alpha Tauri’’
over ‘‘Aldebaran.’’
For times, the obvious candidates for standard terms are those provided
by chronometry. If one is content with (4.1), there is no need to enter into
the problem of de re knowledge about times at all, and so no need to fix on
any standard terms for times. If one adopts (7.2), reliance on chronometry
is the only obvious way to impose a solution on the problem of aliases. But
in that case the one advantage (7.2) appeared to have over (4.1), that of not
depending on chronometry, must be recognized to have been illusory. This
consideration argues, I claim, in favor of the J-free formalization (4.1) and
against the J-laden formalization (7.2).
A third general problem with de re belief is the problem of demonstratives
(and with them indexicals). When the star Alpha Tauri, alias Aldebaran, is
visible in the night sky, one can point to it and say ‘‘that star,’’ and so achieve
reference to it. Now it seems someone looking at the star may well know
(5) That star is orangish.
and yet not knowing the name of the star may well not know either (1)
or (2).
This is, so far, just a special case of the problem of aliases. But demon-
stratives are especially troublesome because, on the one hand, when avail-
able, they seem to provide so direct a way of referring that it is hard to insist
that nonetheless it is some other way of referring that provides the canonical
terms for reduction of de re to de dicto; but on the other hand, demonstra-
tives themselves are not viable candidates for canonical terms, simply
because they are usually not available: if we took demonstratives as canon-
ical terms, most objects would suffer from anonymity most of the time.
Demonstratives act, so to speak, as spoilers, making any other candidates
for the office of canonical term look unworthy, while themselves not being
eligible for that office.
But this problem has been encountered in the case of times in x3, and
given the restriction on the discovery principle imposed there, it may be set
aside here, as the problem of anonymity was set aside. The problem of
aliases, I claim, is enough to make the admission of J undesirable.
9 AN IMPERFECT ANALOGY
I have done with the topic of the discovery principle. But what of the
knowability principle, and the original, modal version of Fitch’s paradox?
Can truth out? 197
Table 10.1
Temporal Modal
I began this essay by recalling that there is a close parallel between temporal
and modal. I should now note that while there are many analogies, in
connection with Fitch’s paradox there is also one glaring disanalogy, that
makes the original, modal problem more refractory than its temporal
analogue. Perhaps the best way of proceeding would be to begin by simply
listing pairs of analogous notions in parallel columns as in Table 10.1.
But returning to what is formally representable, I have recalled in the left
margin in the table the numbers of temporal formulas we have met earlier,
and assigned in the right margin numbers to the analogous modal for-
mulas. Fitch’s (1) is as quickly dismissible as its analogue (1.3).6 The
difficulty comes when one seeks a replacement.
The absence of any obvious analogue for possibilities of standard chro-
nometric specifications for times makes (2) and (3) much less satisfactory
than (4.1) and (5.2) – and (4) correspondingly much more tempting than
(7.2). But the same absence makes the problem of de re knowledge of
possible situations connected with (4) at once more critical and more
difficult to solve or evade than was the problem of de re knowledge of
temporal moments connected with (7.2).
I will not enlarge further here, partly because it would be a good exercise
for readers to work out the analogy for themselves, but mainly because
6
For a full exposition of the essentially grammatical fallacy in the paradox, see Rückert (2004). Rückert
draws on Wehmeier (forthcoming).
198 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
I would be largely repeating points that have been made by Dorothy
Edgington in her proposed solution to the paradox, and by Timothy
Williamson in his criticisms thereof.7 A further disanalogy emerges in
discussion of Edgington and Williamson that is not formally representable,
and is therefore not indicated in Table 10.1. It is just this, that generally
speaking the fact that something is only actually true and not necessarily
true tends to matter less to us than the fact that something is only at the
present moment true and not permanently true. Or to put the matter
another way, what will be true when the world is older matters more to us
than what could have been true if the world had been otherwise, since we
hope to live on into ‘‘future worlds’’ but do not expect to transmigrate into
‘‘possible worlds.’’
So far as the present investigation is concerned, it seems that the analogy
between mood and tense takes us only so far, and in the end provides us not
with a solution, but only with a better understanding of just what makes
the problem difficult.
7
See Edgington (1985) and Williamson (1987). For further relevant publications see Brogaard and
Salerno (note 2).
8
See Prior (1967b, chapter VII).
Can truth out? 199
the special letters, may be substituted for those special letters. These
include the special letters themselves, any formula beginning with a
modal operator & or }, and any formula obtainable from formulas of
these two kinds using the truth functions and past-tense operators H
and P.
A single axiom links the temporal and modal operators:
(1) a ! &a.
One can obtain by substitution
(2) Pa ! &Pa.
One cannot derive
(3) Fa ! &Fa.
Taking for a in (1)–(3) ‘‘A sea fight is occurring,’’ in Prior’s system one
can conclude that if a sea fight is occurring or has occurred, then the
occurrence of a sea fight is (historically) necessary; but even if a sea-
fight is only going to occur, then its occurrence is (historically) con-
tingent, though once it does occur, it will become (historically)
necessary.
A version of the knowability principle can be expressed in this context by
the formula
(4) &Ga ! }FKa.
And from (4) one can derive, using various tense-logical and modal
theorems, the following rough analogues of the corollaries in the proposi-
tion of x3:
(5) (Pa Ú a Ú Fa) ! }FKPa
(6) Ga ! }FK}Ga.
The details will not be given here, because the system is ultimately
unsatisfactory.
Let me explain how. From (4), by way of its corollaries, one can
conclude the following, wherein I contract ‘‘possibly will’’ to ‘‘may’’:
(7) If Smith is murdering Jones, then it may become known that Smith has
murdered Jones.
(8) If the memory of Smith’s victim will always be honored, then it may become
known that the memory of Smith’s victim may always be honored.
(9) If the universe is always going to be expanding, then it may become known
that the universe may be always going to be expanding.
200 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
What one cannot conclude is:
(10) If the memory of Smith’s victim will always be honored, then it may become
known that the memory of Smith’s victim will always be honored.
(11) If the universe is always going to be expanding, then it may become known
that the universe is always going to be expanding.
So (4) seems too weak.
The strengthening of (4) to
(12) Ga ! }FKGa
would provide assurance of (10) and (11), but unfortunately (12) is too
strong. For it would also provide assurance of the absurd
(13) If Smith murdered Jones but will forever escape detection, then it may
become known that Smith murdered Jones but will forever escape detection.
This is Fitch’s paradox, adapted to the present context.
11 VERIFICATIONISM
9
For a recent expression of this view see Belnap and Green (1994).
Can truth out? 201
Banning statements about the actual future is a radical step. Presumably
the friends and relations of Jones know that his memory possibly will always
be honored, and possibly will not always be honored. They know }Ga and
&Ga, where a is
(1) The memory of Smith’s victim is honored.
The Peircean, however, rejects as meaningless
(2) The memory of Smith’s victim will always be honored.
unless ‘‘will’’ is either strengthened to ‘‘necessarily will’’ or weakened to
‘‘possibly will.’’ The Peircean it seems, cannot allow the friends and
relations to hope that (2) is true, or to fear that it is not.10 Likewise,
cosmologists presumably already know that it is possible the universe will
expand forever, and possible that it will not. The Peircean cannot allow
them to wonder if it in actual fact will.
So Peirceanism is a radical doctrine. But then, so is the knowability
principle. The question is, do the two forms of radicalism cohere? If an
adherent of the knowability principle were to embrace Peirceanism,
would the resulting position have any coherent motivation? Or would
embracing Peirceanism be mere ad hoc epicycling, avoiding counter-
examples by declaring them meaningless? This is too large, and too
non-logical, an issue to go into here, but at least a word may be said
about the historical sources of epistemological views like the discovery
and knowability principles on the one hand, and of Peirceanism on the
other.
Belief in the discovery principle, I said at the outset, has traditionally
rested on theological grounds. Belief in the knowability principle has,
by contrast, been mainly an expression of a commitment to a certain
philosophical theory of meaning, verificationism. The radical epistemolo-
gical view that there are no unknowable truths has usually been a conse-
quence of the even more radical semantical view that understanding a
sentence consists in grasping under what conditions it would be known to
be true.
Belief in Peirceanism has had several sources. Prior cites late-medieval
logicians who have held a similar view on theological grounds, but
the more recent proponents of the view seem to base their adherence
on grounds that ultimately are verificationist. Thus combining the
10
This observation is repeated from Burgess (1979d).
202 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
knowability principle with Peirceanism could be viewed as combining
two manifestations of an underlying verificationism. Of course, there
are many varieties of verificationism, and it remains to be seen whether a
single variety can cogently motivate both these manifestations simultane-
ously. A key issue will be the verificationist’s attitude towards the reality
of the past.
11
1 QUINE’S CRITIQUE
203
204 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
x3 below will list some lessons from Quine’s critique, after x2 has
examined the early responses to it. Since I will be arguing that most of
these simply missed the point, I should say at the outset that this is easier to
see by hindsight than it was from expositions of the critique available at the
time, and that the early responses were useful insofar as they provoked new
expositions. That there are flaws in Quine’s own presentations is conceded
even by such sympathetic commentators as Dagfinn Føllesdal and Leonard
Linsky, and at least as regards his earliest presentations by Quine himself.2
To remove flaws is the aim of the present x1, and the aim suggested by my
title, which readers familiar with the history of mathematics will recognize
as echoing Saccheri’s Euclides ab omni naevo vindicatus or Euclid Freed from
Every Blemish. Such readers will also recall that though Saccheri’s aim was
to defend Euclid, ironically his work is today remembered as a contribu-
tion to non-Euclidean geometry. While I hope to avoid a similar irony, I do
not hesitate to depart from Quine on occasion, and begin with two
limitations that I think need more explicit emphasis than they get from
Quine.
2
The most important of Quine’s presentations is ‘‘Reference and modality,’’ in From a Logical Point of
View (Quine 1953/1961/1980). Citations of this twice-revised work here will be by internal section and
paragraph divisions, the same from edition to edition. This work supersedes the earlier Quine
(1947a). For commentary see the editor’s introduction to Linsky (1971a) and Linsky (1971b). See
also Føllesdal (1969) and Føllesdal (1986).
3
A theme in his reviews (Quine 1946, 1947b).
4
See the last paragraph of the third section of ‘‘Reference and modality,’’ ending: ‘‘for if we do not
propose to quantify across the necessity operator, the use of that operator ceases to have any clear
advantage over merely quoting a sentence and saying that it is analytic.’’
Quinus ab omni naevo vindicatus 205
modalities, to modalities applying to open formulas as in 9x&Fx, rather
than modalities applying to closed formulas as in &9xFx. Second, the
critique is limited to non-trivial de re modality. The first point has been
generally understood. Not so the second, which calls for some explanation.
I begin with an analogy. One can contrive systems of sentential modal
logic that admit modalities notationally, but that make every modal for-
mula more or less trivially equivalent to a non-modal formula. It suffices to
add as a further axiom the following, whose converse is already a theorem
in the common systems:
(1) P ! &P.
This corresponds to a definition according to which P holds necessarily just
in case P holds – a definition that could silence any critic who claimed the
notion of necessity to be unclear, but would do so only at the cost of
making the introduction of the modal notation pointless.
Analogously, one can contrive systems of predicate modal logic that
admit de re modalities notationally, but that make every de re formula more
or less trivially equivalent to a de dicto formula. The precise form a trivial-
ization axiom would take depends on whether one is considering monadic
or polyadic predicate logic, and on whether one is admitting or excluding
an existence predicate or an identity predicate or both. In the simplest case
it suffices to add as a further axiom the following, whose converse is already
a theorem in the common systems:
(2) 8x(&Fx ! &8yFy).
This corresponds to the trivializing definition according to which F holds
necessarily of a thing just in case it is necessary that F holds of everything –
a definition that could silence any critic who claimed the notion of de re
modality to be more obscure than that of de dicto modality, but would do
so only at the cost of making the introduction of de re notation pointless.
When Quine complains of the difficulty in defining de re modality, he is
tacitly assuming the trivializing definition above has been rejected; so his
critique is tacitly limited to systems that, like all the common ones, do not
have the trivialization axiom as a theorem. To accept such a system as the
correct system, the one whose theorems give all and only the general laws
necessarily holding in all instances, is to reject the trivialization axiom as
not being such a general law, and hence is to reject the trivializing
definition, which would make it one. Note that Quine’s objection is thus
to the unprovability of something, namely trivialization, not the provability
of anything.
206 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
5
Contrast the opening section of ‘‘Reference and modality,’’ on knowledge and belief contexts, with
the antepenultimate paragraph of the paper, beginning: ‘‘What has been said in these pages relates
only to strict modality . . .’’
6
For a contemporary account deploring such tendencies, Kneale and Kneale (1962, pp. 628ff).
Such tendencies are exemplified by the usage of all the participants in the exchange discussed in x2
below.
Quinus ab omni naevo vindicatus 207
(3) It is analytically true that all bachelors are unmarried.
(4) It is logically true that all unmarried men are unmarried.
(30 ) ‘‘All bachelors are unmarried’’ is analytically true.
(40 ) ‘‘All unmarried men are unmarried’’ is logically true.
One objection was to the common feature of (3) and (30 ), involvement with
broadly analytic rather than narrowly logical truth; another, to the com-
mon feature of (3) and (4), treatment of modality as a connective in the
object language applying to sentences, rather than a predicate in the
metalanguage applying to quotations. What is important to understand
is that in his critique of modal logic Quine presses only his objection to the
second feature – a feature presupposed by quantified modal logic, since
quantification into quotation contexts is obvious nonsense – waiving his
objection to the first for the sake of argument. Others of the period shared
neither Quine’s worries about the broad, semantic notion, nor his concern
to distinguish it from the narrow, syntactic notion, and often wrote
‘‘logical’’ when they meant ‘‘analytic.’’
Analytic truth and a priori truth. Quine’s first and foremost target,
Rudolf Carnap, and others of the period, took the distinction between
analytic and synthetic to be central to epistemology because they took it to
coincide with the distinction between a priori and a posteriori. They
recognized not a trichotomy of ‘‘analytic’’ and ‘‘synthetic a priori’’ and ‘‘a
posteriori,’’ but a dichotomy of ‘‘analytic’’ and ‘‘a posteriori.’’
A priori truth and linguistic truth. Quine often complained that others
were sloppy about distinguishing use and mention. If one is sloppy,
quibbles and confusions can result if, as was commonly done, one
uses ‘‘linguistic’’ interchangeably with ‘‘analytic’’ or ‘‘a priori’’ and ‘‘empiri-
cal’’ interchangeably with ‘‘synthetic’’ or ‘‘a posteriori’’ respectively. For
consider:
(5) Planetoids are asteroids.
(6) Ceres is the largest asteroid.
(50 ) In modern English, ‘‘planetoids’’ and ‘‘asteroids’’ refer to the same things.
(60 ) In modern English, ‘‘Ceres’’ and ‘‘the largest asteroid’’ refer to the same thing.
7
For a less rough formulation, see T. Parsons (1969).
210 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
adding a new selection principle as an ingredient to the concept of modal-
ity. But with any such addition of a new intuitive ingredient there is a
danger that one will be making one’s conception no longer one of merely
verbal necessity; or worse, that one will be making it arbitrary and
incoherent.
This abstract dilemma is concretely illustrated by Quine’s mathematical
cyclist example, an elaboration of an old example of Mill’s, and his morning
star example, an adaptation of an old example of Frege’s. The only obvious
approach to reducing the application of modal notions to a thing to an
application of modal notions to words, would be to represent or replace a
thing by a word or verbal expression appropriately related to it. In fact,
there are two strategies here, the most obvious one being to take the
expression to be a term referring to the thing, and an only slightly less
obvious one being to take the expression to be a predicate satisfied by the
thing. Hence the need for two examples.
Together (9a–d) contradict the known actual existence of persons who are
at once mathematicians and cyclists.
Quinus ab omni naevo vindicatus 211
More formally, allowing non-selective application of the strategy amounts
to adopting the following as an axiom, which can be seen to collapse modal
distinctions all by itself:
(10) 8x(Px ! (&Fx $ &8y(Py ! Fy))).
This is the first horn of the dilemma.
On the other hand, the obvious fall-back would be to allow (10) to apply
only selectively, only to certain selected ‘‘canonical’’ predicates. In order
for (10), restricted to canonical predicates, to give an adequate definition of
de re modality, it would suffice for two things to hold. It would suffice to
have first that for each thing there is (or can be introduced) some canonical
predicate it satisfies; and second that for any two canonical predicates A, B
we have:
(11) 9x(Ax Ù Bx) ! &8y(Ay $ By).
This condition would preclude taking both ‘‘x is a mathematician’’ and ‘‘x is
a cyclist,’’ or both Plato’s ‘‘x is a featherless biped’’ and Aristotle’s ‘‘x is a
rational animal,’’ as canonical. But how is one to select what predicates are
admitted as canonical? It seems that making a selection, choosing for
instance between Plato and Aristotle, would require reviving something
like the ancient and medieval notion of ‘‘real definitions’’ as opposed to
‘‘nominal definitions’’; and this is something it seems impossible to square
with regarding the necessity with which we are concerned as simply verbal
necessity.
8
It may be worth digressing to mention that Quine’s one and only contribution to the formal side of
modal logic occurred in connection with this law, though the history does not always emerge clearly
from textbook presentations. The earliest derivations of the law took an old-fashioned approach on
which identity is a defined second-order notion, and on such an approach the derivation was
anything but straightforward. Quine was one of the first to note that on a modern approach with
identity a primitive first-order notion, the derivation becomes trivial, and goes through for all systems
at least as strong as the minimal normal system K. This is alluded to in passing in the penultimate
paragraph of the third section of ‘‘Reference and modality.’’ For the original presentation see (Barcan
1947). For a modern textbook presentation see Hughes and Creswell (1968, p. 190).
Quinus ab omni naevo vindicatus 213
So (17) leaves open what terms should be allowed to be substituted for
variables.9
What (16) says is that for the fall-back strategy being contemplated to
work, we must be able to go beyond (17) to the extent of allowing canonical
terms to be substituted for the variables. This condition would preclude
taking both ‘‘the morning star’’ and ‘‘the evening star’’ as canonical. But
owing to the symmetry involved, it would be entirely arbitrary to select
‘‘the morning star’’ as canonical and reject ‘‘the evening star’’ as apocryphal
(or the reverse), and it would seem almost equally arbitrary to reject both
and select some other term such as ‘‘the second planet.’’ This is the second
horn of the dilemma.
And with this observation Quine rests his case, in effect claiming that
since the obvious strategies for doing what needs to be done have been tried
and found to fail, the burden of proof is now on the other side to show, if
they can, just how, in some unobvious way, what needs to be done can be.
And with this observation, I too rest my case for the moment.
1.7 Coda
Quine’s critique was directed toward the strict kind of modality and
toward quantification over ordinary sorts of objects: persons, places,
things. Much of his discussion generalizes to other kinds of modal or
intensional operators and other sorts of objects, to show that for them,
too, the most obvious strategy for making sense of quantifying over such
objects into such modal or intensional contexts faces an obstacle. But
whether this obstacle can be surmounted, by the most obvious fall-back
strategy of identifying an appropriate class of canonical terms or in some
other way, needs to be considered case by case. The most important case of
a non-strict modality for which a reasonable choice of canonical terms
seems to be available (for almost any sort of objects) will be mentioned at
the very end of this study. Here I want to mention a case of a special sort of
object for which a reasonable choice of canonical terms seems to be
available (for almost any kind of intensional operator).
For several writers, beginning with Diana Ackerman, have pointed out
that numerals suggest themselves as non-arbitrary candidates for canonical
9
In the original paper where (17) was derived there were no singular terms but variables, and nothing
was said about application to natural language. For an idea of the range of options formally available,
see the taxonomy in Garson (1984).
214 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
terms if one is going to be quantifying only over natural numbers. And the
numerals are in effect taken as canonical terms in two flourishing enter-
prises, intensional mathematics and provability logic, where the modality in
question is a version or variant of strict modality.10
Still, natural numbers are a very special sort of object. Workers in the
cited fields have noted the difficulty of finding canonical terms as soon as
one goes beyond them even just to other sorts of mathematical objects,
such as sets or functions. To avoid difficulties over there simply being too
many objects to find terms for them all, let us restrict attention to recur-
sively enumerable sets of natural numbers and recursive partial functions
on natural numbers, where there is actually a standard way of indexing the
objects in question by natural numbers or the numerals therefor. Even here
there does not seem to be any non-arbitrary way of selecting canonical
terms, since there will be many indices for any one set or function, and two
indices for the same object will not in general be provably indices for the
same object.11
Whatever successes have been or may be obtained for non-strict modal-
ities and ordinary objects, or for strict modalities and non-ordinary objects,
they only make it the more conspicuous how far we are from having any
reasonable candidates for canonical terms in the case to which Quine’s
critique is directed.
2 QUINE’S CRITICS
10
See Ackermann (1978). Lectures of Kripke have brought this formerly under-appreciated paper
to the attention of a wider audience. See also Shapiro (1985) and especially Boolos (1993, pp. xxxiv
and 226).
11
Workers in the cited fields have in effect suggested that something like indices can serve as canonical
terms for more fine-grained intensional analogues of recursive sets and functions. But these too
would be very special objects. The best discussion of these matters known to me is in some work not
fully published of Leon Horsten.
12
Whose published proceedings make up a memorable issue of Acta Philosophica Fennica, and include
not only Kripke (1963) but Hintikka (1963).
Quinus ab omni naevo vindicatus 215
celebrated 1970 Princeton lectures.13 But the impression that somehow an
appropriate theory of models or of reference can refute Quine’s critique can
be traced back a full half-century. For less sophisticated model theories for
quantified modal logic go back to some of the first publications on the
subject, by Rudolf Carnap, in the 1940s;14 and the application of less
sophisticated theories of reference to modal logic goes back to one of the
first reviews of Quine’s critical writings, by Arthur Smullyan, again in the
1940s.15
For purposes of examining the main lines of response to Quine’s
critique prior to the new developments in model theory and the theory
of reference in the 1960s and 1970s, and Quine’s rebuttals to these
responses, it is almost sufficient to consider just three documents,
together constituting the proceedings of a notorious 1962 Boston collo-
quium. The main talk, by Quine’s most vehement and vociferous oppo-
nent, Ruth (Barcan) Marcus, was a compendium of almost all the
responses to Quine that had been advanced over the preceding fifteen
years, plus one new one. The commentary, by Quine himself, marked an
exception to his apparent general policy of not replying directly to critics,
and gives his rebuttal to almost all early objections to his critique. An
edited transcript of a tape recording of a discussion after the two talks
among the two invited speakers and some members of their audience,
notably Kripke, was published along with the two papers, and clarifies
some points.16
2.2 Potpourri
A half-dozen early lines of response to the critique may be distinguished.
Most appear with differing degrees of explicitness and emphasis in the
13
Kripke (1972/1980). 14 Carnap (1946, 1947).
15
Smullyan (1947), with elaboration in Smullyan (1948). Smullyan’s priority for his particular response
to Quine has been recognized by all competent and responsible commentators. See Linsky (1971b,
note 15) and Føllesdal (1969, p. 183).
16
Thus the items are: (i) the compendium (Marcus 1963a); (ii) the comments (Quine 1963) later
retitled ‘‘Reply to Professor Marcus’’; and (iii) the edited discussion (Marcus, Quine, Kripke et al.
1963).They appear together in the official proceedings volume (Wartofsky 1963). The same publisher
had printed them in 1962 in Synthese in a version that is textually virtually identical down to the
placement of page breaks, (i) and (ii) in a belated issue of the volume for 1961, and (iii) in an issue of
the volume for 1962. (There have been several later, separate reprintings of the different items, but
these incorporate revisions, often substantial.) Two of the present editors of Synthese, J. Fetzer and
P. Humphreys, have proposed publishing the unedited, verbatim transcript of the discussion, with a
view to shedding light on some disputed issues of interpretation; but according to their account,
one of the participants, Professor Marcus, has objected to circulation of copies of the transcript or
the tape.
216 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
compendium, and most are rebutted in the commentary thereupon. They
all involve essentially the same error, confusing Quine’s philosophical
complaint with some formal claim. Since – despite the best efforts of
Quine himself in his rebuttal and of subsequent commentators – such
confusions are still common, it may be in order to review each response and
rebuttal briefly.
(A) The development of possible-worlds semantics shows that there is no
problem of interpreting quantified modal logic. This response is represented
in the compendium by the suggestion that disputes about quantified
modal logic should be conducted with reference to a ‘‘semantic construc-
tion,’’ in which connection the now superseded approach of Carnap is
expounded (with the now standard, then unpublished, approach of Kripke
being alluded to as an alternative in the discussion). Perhaps Quine
thought the fallacy in this response obvious, since he makes no explicit
response to it in his commentary; but it has proved very influential, albeit
perhaps more as an inchoate feeling than as an articulate thought. The
fallacy is one of equivocation, confusing ‘‘semantics’’ in the sense of a
mathematical theory of models, such as Carnap and Kripke provided,
with ‘‘semantics’’ in the sense of a philosophical account of meaning,
which is what Quine was demanding, and thus neglecting the dictum that
‘‘there is no mathematical substitute for philosophy.’’17 A mathematical
theory of models could refute a technical claim to the effect that the common
systems are formally inconsistent, but without some further gloss it cannot
say anything against a philosophical claim that the common systems are
intuitively unintelligible. In the case of Carnapian model theory this point
perhaps ought to have been obvious from the specifics of the model, which
validates some highly dubious theses.18 In the case of Kripkean model theory
the point perhaps ought to be obvious from the generality of the theory,
from its ability to accommodate the widest and wildest variety of systems,
which surely cannot all make good philosophical sense.
17
These are the closing words of Kripke (1976). The fallacy recurs again and again in other contexts in
the literature. See Copeland (1979).
18
Notably the Barcan or Carnap–Barcan formulas, which give formal expression to F. P. Ramsey’s odd
idea that whatever possibly exists actually exists, and whatever actually exists necessarily exists. (The
‘‘Barcan’’ label is the more customary, the ‘‘Carnap–Barcan’’ label the more historically accurate
according to Cocchiarella (1984), which also explains the connection with Ramsey.) If these formulas
are rejected, one must distinguish a thing’s having a property necessarily (for every possible world it
exists there and has the property there) from its having the property essentially (for every possible
world, if it exists there, then it has the property there). I have slurred over this distinction so far, and
will for the most part continue to do so.
Quinus ab omni naevo vindicatus 217
(B) Quantified modal logic makes reasonable sense if 8 and 9 are read as
something other than
P ordinary quantifiers, such as Lesniewski-style substitution
operators and . This is the one substantial novelty in the compendium.
One rebuttal, of secondary importance to Quine, is that if one allows
oneself to call substitution operators ‘‘quantifiers,’’ one can make equally
good or poor sense of ‘‘quantification’’ not only into modal but into
absolutely any contexts whatsoever, including those of quotation. But
quantification into quotation contexts is obvious nonsense – on any
reasonable understanding of ‘‘quantification.’’19 Still, the rebuttal of pri-
mary importance to Quine is a different and more general one, applying
also to the next response.
(C) Quantified modal logic makes reasonable sense if & and } are read as
something other than strict modalities, such as Prior-style temporal operators
G and F. This response is represented in the compendium by the sugges-
tion, made in passing in the introduction, that modal logic is worth
pursuing because of the value of studies of various non-alethic ‘‘modal-
ities.’’ The specific example of temporal ‘‘modalities’’ was suggested by
Quine in his last remarks in the discussion, his purpose being to bring out
his primary point of rebuttal to the previous response, that Lesniewski’s
devices are just as irrelevant as Prior’s devices, given the nature of his
complaint. If his complaint had been that there is a formal inconsistency
in the common systems, then it would have been cogent to respond by
considering those systems as wholly uninterpreted notations, and looking
for some reading of their symbolism under which they would come out
saying something true or plausible. But the nature of the critique is quite
different, the complaint being that the combination 9x& is philosoph-
ically unintelligible when the components 9 and & are interpreted in the
usual way.20
(D) Quantified modal logic is not committed to essentialism because no
formula expressing such a commitment (no instance of the negation of (2))
is deducible in the common systems, even with the addition of any desired set
of consistent de dicto axioms. This response does not explicitly occur as
19
As shown by examples in the opening section of ‘‘Reference and modality.’’ This point seems to be
conceded even by some who otherwise take an uncritically positive view of the compendium, as in
the review Forbes (1995). The last sections of Kripke (1976) in effect point out that the claim that the
ordinary language ‘‘there is’’ in its typical uses is a ‘‘substitutional quantifier’’ devoid of ‘‘ontological
commitment’’ is absurd, since ‘‘ontological commitment’’ is by definition whatever it is that the
ordinary language ‘‘there is’’ in its typical uses conveys.
20
‘‘What I’ve been talking about is quantification, in a quantificational sense of quantification, into
modal contexts, in a modal sense of modality’’ (Wartofsky 1963, p. 116).
218 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
such in the compendium, and would have been premature, since the
results of Parsons which it quotes did not come until a few years later. But
it is advanced in a slightly later work of the same author, and has been
influential in the literature.21 It could be construed as merely a general-
ization of the next response on the list, and Quine’s rebuttal to the next
response would apply to this one, too. Basically, the response is the result
of terminological confusion, since its first clause is only relevant if
‘‘commitment to essentialism’’ is understood in Quine’s sense, but its
second clause is only true if ‘‘commitment to essentialism’’ is understood
in a different sense partly foreshadowed in the compendium and expli-
citly introduced as such by Parsons. It has already been noted in the
exposition of the critique both that Quine’s complaint is not about the
provability of anything, and that Parsons’ results substantiate some of
Quine’s suspicions.
(E) The mathematical cyclist example does not show there is any
problem, because no de re conclusions of the kind that figure in the
example (conclusions (9a–d)) provably follow in the common systems
from such de dicto premises as figure in the example (premises (8a–d)).
While the example gives a legitimate counter-instance to the law that
figures in it (law (10)), that law is not a theorem in the common systems.
This response occurs in a section of the compendium where Quine’s
criticisms are said to ‘‘stem from confusion about what is or is not
provable in such systems,’’ and where it is even suggested that Quine
believes & (P!Q)!(P!&Q) to be a theorem of the common sys-
tems!22 This response, which accuses Quine of committing a howler of
a modal fallacy, is itself a howler, getting the point of Quine’s example
exactly backwards. The complaint that we cannot deduce examples of
non-trivial de re modality from plausible examples of non-trivial
de dicto modality by taking something like (10) as an axiom, because
we would get a contradiction, is misunderstood as a formal claim that
something like (10) is an axiom, and we do get a contradiction. Quine’s
rebuttal in his commentary borders on indignation: ‘‘I’ve never said or,
21
Marcus (1967). And about the same time we find even the usually acute Linsky (1971a, p. 9) writing:
‘‘Terence Parsons bases his search for the essentialist commitments of modal logic on Kripke’s
semantics, and he comes up (happily) empty-handed . . . He finds modal logic uncontaminated.’’
The continuation of this passage better agrees with Parsons’ own account of his work and its bearing
on Quine’s critique.
22
See Wartofsky (1963, pp. 90–2). It is just conceivable that this is deliberate exaggeration for effect, a
rhetorical flourish rather than a serious exegetical hypothesis. Marcus (1967) cites some other authors
who have written in a similar vein about the example.
Quinus ab omni naevo vindicatus 219
I’m sure, written that essentialism could be proved in any system of
modal logic whatsoever.’’23
(F) The morning star example does not show there is any problem, because
while the law that figures in the example (law (17)) is a theorem of the common
systems, the example does not give a legitimate counter-instance, as can be seen
by applying an appropriate theory of reference. This response is repeated, with
elaboration but without expected acknowledgments – it is described as
‘‘familiar,’’ but no specific citation is given – in the compendium. The
citation ought to have been to Smullyan.24 This response again mistakenly
takes Quine to be claiming to have a counterexample to a formal theorem
of the common systems. (And if Quine had claimed that (12) and (14)
constitute a counterexample to (17), it would have sufficed to point out that
one is not required, just because one recognizes an expression to be a real
singular term, to recognize it as legitimately substitutable for variables
in all contexts. This point has been noted already in the exposition of the
critique, but the response under discussion seems to miss it.) Nonetheless,
response (F) is worthy of more extended attention.
23
And ‘‘I did not say that it could ever be deduced in the S-systems or any systems I’ve ever seen’’
(Wartofsky 1963, p. 113). Despite these forceful remarks, the understanding of Quine’s views has not
much improved in the later Marcus (1967).
24
An earlier paper by the author of the compendium (Marcus 1960) gives a more concise statement of
the response in its last paragraph, where a footnote acknowledges the author’s teacher Frederic Fitch.
The latter, in Fitch (1949) and Fitch (1950), acknowledges Smullyan. (See footnote 4 in the former,
footnote 12 in the latter, and the text to which they are attached.)
25
The major one being Weiss (1967), and the minor one the collection of survey articles (Klibansky
1968). The former contains Prior (1967a) while the latter contains Marcus (1968). The conference
talks (Marcus 1963b, Prior 1963) are to be found in the previously cited Helsinki proceedings.
Another advocate of closely related ideas has been J. Myhill.
220 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
response (F) calls for more attention than the others is that it represents an
early attempt to apply a theory of reference distinguishing names from
descriptions to the interpretation of modal logic, and understanding why
this attempt was unsatisfactory should lead to increased appreciation of
more successful later attempts.
The ideas on reference that are involved derive from Russell. The
writings of Ramsey, alluded to in passing in the compendium, and of
Carnap, with whom the author of the compendium at one time studied,
may have served to transmit Russell’s influence, though of course Russell
himself was still writing on reference in the 1950s, and still living in the
1960s, and should not be considered a remote historical figure like Locke or
Mill. But whether his influence on them was direct or indirect, Smullyan’s
disciples are unmistakably Russell’s epigones, even though they seldom
directly quote him or cite chapter and verse from his writings.26
The Smullyanite response, it will be seen, splits into two parts, one
pertaining to descriptions, the other to names. The theory of descriptions
presupposed by the Smullyanites is simply the very well-known theory of
Russell. The theory of names presupposed is the less well-known theory
Russell always took as a foil to his theory of descriptions. This is perhaps
best introduced by contrasting it with the theory of Frege, according to
which the reference of a name to its bearer is descriptively mediated, is
accomplished by the name having the same meaning as some description,
and the description being uniquely true of the bearer. The theory of Russell
is the diametrically opposed one that the reference of a name to its bearer is
absolutely immediate, in a sense implying that the meaning of a name is
simply its bearer, from which it follows that two names having the same
bearer have the same meaning. It is taken to follow (‘‘compositionality’’
being tacitly assumed) that two sentences involving two different names
with the same bearer, but otherwise the same, have the same meaning, and
hence the same truth value (with one sole exception, usually left tacit, the
exception for meta-linguistic contexts, for those sentences, usually involv-
ing quotation, where the names are being mentioned as words rather than
being used to refer).
This theory is Russell’s account of how names in an ideal sense
would function. While Russell illustrated his theory by examples involv-
ing names in the ordinary sense, he actually more or less agreed with
26
Let me not fail to cite chapter and verse myself. For the most relevant pages of the most recently
reprinted work, see Russell (1985), pp. 113–15.
Quinus ab omni naevo vindicatus 221
Frege about these (so that the Fregean theory is often known as the
Frege–Russell theory). Moreover, he held that ordinary, complex things
are not even capable of being given names in his ideal sense; that names in
the ideal sense could be given only to special, simple things (such as sense
data). There is an ambiguity running through the writings of all the
Smullyanites as to whether they do or do not wish to claim that names in
the ordinary sense function as names in the ideal sense. But they do
unambiguously wish to claim, contrary to Russell, that whether or not
they are already in existence, names in an ideal sense can at least be
introduced for ordinary things. For this reason, while the Smullyanites
may be called ‘‘Russellians,’’ it is perhaps better to add the distinguishing
prefix ‘‘neo-.’’
So much for the background assumptions of response (F). Its further
articulation has several components:
(F0) Quine’s example is ambiguous, since the key terms ‘‘the morning star’’ and ‘‘the
evening star’’ might be either mere definite descriptions or genuine proper names.
(F1a) If the key phrases are taken to be descriptions, then they are only apparently and
not really singular terms, and (12) is only apparently and not really a singular
identity, so one gets only an apparent and not a real counterexample to (17).
(F1b) Moreover, though the foregoing already suffices, it may be added that (13) and
(14) are ambiguous, and it is not unambiguously the case that they are of opposite
truth value, the former true and the latter false, as the example claims.
(F2) If the key phrases are taken to be names, then (14) means the very same thing as,
and is every bit as true as, (13), contrary to what the example claims.
To dispose of the issue (F0) of ambiguity, the example may be restated
twice:
(12a) Hesperus is Phosphorus.
(13a) Necessarily, Phosphorus is Phosphorus.
(14a) Necessarily, Hesperus is Phosphorus.
(12b) The brightest star of the evening is the brightest star of the morning.
(13b) Necessarily, the brightest star of the morning is the brightest star of the morning.
(14b) Necessarily, the brightest star of the evening is the brightest star of the morning.
27
Reply to Sellars, in Davidson and Hintikka (1969, p. 338). This formulation is the earliest adequate
one known to me, the rebuttal even in the 1961 version of ‘‘Reference and modality’’ being
inadequate.
28
As was pointed out in Kripke’s last few remarks in the discussion at the colloquium. Quine
seems to accept the observation in his last remark. Marcus had apparently ceased to follow by this
point.
224 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
as if it were supposed to be self-evident.29 Elaboration is provided by
later disciples in the compendium and elsewhere. The elaboration in
Prior’s talk at the 1962 Helsinki conference is of especial interest because
it anticipates in a partial way a significant later contribution to the theory of
reference.
Since this has not hitherto been widely noted, I digress to quote the
relevant passage:
It is not necessary, I think, for philosophers to argue very desperately about what is
in fact ‘‘ordinary’’ and what is not; but let us say that a name in Russell’s strict sense is
a simple identifier of an object . . .
[T]here is no reason why the same expression, whether it be a single word like
‘‘This’’ or ‘‘Tully,’’ or a phrase like ‘‘The man who lives next door’’ or ‘‘The man at
whom I am pointing,’’ should not be used sometimes as a name in Russell’s strict
sense and sometimes not. If ‘‘The man who lives next door’’ is being so used, and
successfully identifies a subject of discourse, then ‘‘The man who lives next door is
a heavy smoker’’ would be true if and only if the subject thus identified is a heavy
smoker, even if this subject is in a fact a women and doesn’t live next door but only
works there. And if ‘‘Tully,’’ ‘‘Cicero,’’ ‘‘The Morning Star’’ and ‘‘The Evening
Star’’ are all being so used, then ‘‘Tully is Cicero’’ and ‘‘The Morning Star is the
Evening Star’’ both express necessary truths, to the effect that a certain object is
identical with itself.30
The distinctive part of the passage, not in the founder or other members of
the Smullyanite school, is the middle, where it is suggested that even an
expression that is not a name in the ordinary sense may sometimes function
as a name. This is a different point from the trivial observation that names
often have descriptive etymologies, and those familiar with the later liter-
ature will recognize how what is said about ‘‘the man who lives next door’’
partially anticipates what was later to be said about ‘‘referential’’ as opposed
to ‘‘attributive’’ uses of descriptions.
29
Fitch (1949) explicitly claims that Quine’s contention is ‘‘clearly’’ false if the key expressions are taken
to be names.
30
Prior (1963, pp. 194–5). Prior was from Balliol, and I have heard it asserted – though I cannot
confirm it from my own knowledge – that there was a tradition of setting examples of this kind in
undergraduate examinations at Oxford in the 1960s.
Quinus ab omni naevo vindicatus 225
most emphatically rejected by later work in the theory of reference: the
epistemological implication that discoveries like (14a) are not ‘‘empirical’’ (at
least not in a non-quibbling sense), and are not properly astronomical
discoveries:
[T]o discover that we have alternative proper names for the same object we turn to
a lexicon, or, in the case of a formal language, to the meaning postulates.. . . [O]ne
doesn’t investigate the planets, but the accompanying lexicon.31
The same thought had been expressed in slightly different words – ‘‘dic-
tionary’’ for ‘‘lexicon,’’ for instance – in the discussion at the colloquium.32
The picture underlying such remarks had been sketched in the compen-
dium itself:
For suppose we took an inventory of all the entities countenanced as things by
some particular culture through its own language . . . And suppose we randomized
as many whole numbers as we needed for a one-to-one correspondence, and
thereby tagged each thing. This identifying tag is a proper name of the thing.33
To talk of an ‘‘inventory,’’ and especially to presuppose that we know how
many numbers would be ‘‘needed for a one-to-one correspondence,’’ is to
assume that we are dealing with a known number of unproblematically
identifiable items. If it is a matter of applying tags to such items, then of
course we should be able to keep a record of when we have assigned
multiple tags to a single one of them, though our record would perhaps
more colloquially be called a ‘‘catalogue’’ than an ‘‘accompanying lexicon’’
or set of ‘‘meaning postulates.’’
The rebuttal to the Smullyanites on names consists in observing that
what is said in the last few quotations is false. Take first Prior. If one defines
‘‘names in the strict sense’’ as expressions with the magical property of
presenting their bearers so absolutely immediately as to leave no room for
empirical questions of identity, then there never have been in any histor-
ically actual language and never can be in any humanly possible language
any such things as ‘‘names in the strict sense.’’ As Russell himself noted,
even ‘‘this is the same as this,’’ where one points to the same object twice, is
31
Marcus (1963b, p. 132). Note the characteristically Carnapian expression ‘‘meaning postulates.’’
32
For the published version, too familiar to bear quoting again, see Wartofsky (1963, p. 115). This is one
of the parts of the discussion where comparison with the verbatim transcript could be most
illuminating. It is a shame that the scholarly public should be denied access to so significant a
historical document.
33
Wartofsky (1963, pp. 83–4). This passage has sometimes been misleadingly cited in the later literature
as if it were unambiguously about ordinary names in ordinary language.
226 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
not a linguistic and non-empirical truth, if the object in question is
complex, and one points to a different component each time.
Take now the compendium and its sequel. Assigning names to heavenly
bodies may be like tagging, but it is not like tagging individuals from among
a known number of unproblematically identifiable items, since we always
have unresolved questions before us about the identity of asteroids or
comets, as Frege long ago noted. And to resolve such questions one must
investigate not some ‘‘accompanying lexicon’’ or ‘‘meaning postulates,’’ but
the planet(oid)s themselves.
In brief, the following have the same status as (6) and (60 ) respectively,
and not as (5) and (50 ):
(12a) Hesperus is Phosphorus.
(12a0 ) In modern English, ‘‘Hesperus’’ and ‘‘Phosphorus’’ refer to the same thing.
Quine’s own formulation of this rebuttal is almost too well known to
bear quotation. But while what Quine means is what I have just said, what
Quine says may be open to quibbles, since taken with pedantic literalness it
would seem to be about (12a0 ) rather than (12a):
We may tag the planet Venus, some fine evening, with the proper name
‘‘Hesperus.’’ We may tag the same planet again, some day before sunrise, with
the proper name ‘‘Phosphorus.’’ When at last we discover that we have tagged the
same planet twice, our discovery is empirical. And not because the proper names
were descriptions.34
3 QUINE’S LESSONS
34
Wartofsky (1963, p. 101). Quine surely means that (12a0 ) is not just a linguistic empirical discovery but
a properly astronomical empirical discovery. By contrast, Marcus in Wartofsky (1963, p. 115),
distinguishes ‘‘such linguistic’’ inquiry as leads to discoveries like (12a0 ) from ‘‘properly empirical’’
methods such as lead to discoveries about orbits.
Quinus ab omni naevo vindicatus 227
impossible to make sense of. A yet further lesson is that quantification into
contexts of subjunctive modality is virtually indispensable.
This last lesson is not as explicitly or emphatically taught as the other two,
and moreover Quine’s remarks are flawed by a tendency to conflate sub-
junctive or ‘‘metaphysical’’ modality with scientific or ‘‘physical’’ modality – as
if we could not speak in the subjunctive of counterfactual hypotheses to the
effect that the laws of science or physics were violated. But due allowance
being made for this flaw, I believe that the work of Quine, supplemented by
that of his student Føllesdal, gives a broad hint pointing in the right direction.
Føllesdal’s treatment of the topic begins by quoting and stressing the
importance of some of Quine’s remarks about the question of the mean-
ingfulness of quantification into contexts of subjunctive modality:
It concerns . . . the practical use of language. It concerns, for example, the use of
the contrary-to-fact conditional within a quantification . . . Upon the contrary-to-
fact conditional depends in turn, for instance, this definition of solubility in water:
To say that an object is soluble in water is to say that it would dissolve if it were in
water. In discussions in physics, naturally, we need quantifications containing the
clause ‘‘x is soluble in water.’’35
Such passages stop just short of saying, what I think is true, that while
quantification into contexts of strict modality may be nonsense, quantifi-
cation into contexts of subjunctive modality is so widespread in scientific
theory and commonsense thought that we could not abandon it as non-
sensical even if we wanted to.
Putting the lessons cited together, it follows that there is a difference between
strict and subjunctive modality as to what expressions should be accepted as
meaningful formulas and so a fortiori as to what formulas should be accepted as
correct laws. The strictly or ‘‘logically’’ possible, what it is not self-contradictory
to say actually is, and the subjunctively or ‘‘metaphysically’’ possible, what could
potentially have been, differ in the formalism appropriate to each.
35
The quotation from Quine is from ‘‘Reference and modality,’’ antepenultimate paragraph. The work
of Føllesdal where it is quoted is Føllesdal (1965). Føllesdal’s final footnote suggests that ‘‘causal
essentialism’’ is better off than ‘‘logical essentialism,’’ and that Quine’s own proposal to treat
dispositions as inhering structural traits of objects is a form of ‘‘causal essentialism.’’
228 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
Before proceeding to a summary of recent work in modal logic which is directed
toward clear solutions to [such] problems . . . it is important to realize that the
perplexities about interpretation can only be understood in terms of certain
presuppositions held by Quine and others which I will call ‘‘the received view’’ (rv).
A bit later one finds the assertion that: ‘‘The Russellian theory of descrip-
tions and the distinction between proper names and descriptions is rejected
by rv.’’ This is immediately followed by the assertion that the morning star
example (3.1) is ‘‘resolved on Russellian analysis as was shown by Smullyan . . .
and others,’’36 and somewhat later by the insistence that ‘‘The usefulness
of the theory of descriptions and the distinction between descriptions and
purely referential names was argued long before it proved applicable to
modal logic,’’ so that one cannot simply reject them, as Quine is alleged
to do.
Now some of this account is quite correct, since the theory of descrip-
tions and of the distinction between them and names as one finds it in the
compendium, for instance, did not originate there, or even with Smullyan,
who first applied it to the interpretation and defense of modal logic, but
was indeed argued by Russell long before. But some of this account is quite
incorrect. It is not true that Quine’s rebuttal to Smullyan on descriptions
requires rejection of Russell’s theory of descriptions.37 And it is not
unambiguously true that Quine’s rebuttal to Smullyan on names requires
rejection of ‘‘the distinction between descriptions and proper names.’’ It is
true that it requires rejection of the neo-Russellian conception of that
distinction, but it is not true that Quine insists on rejecting any distinction
between descriptions and proper names. This should be clear from the last
half-sentence of the rebuttal quoted earlier: ‘‘And not because the proper
names were descriptions.’’
Before Quine, difficulties with the theory that the reference of a name to
its bearer is absolutely immediate had been recognized by Føllesdal and
Alonzo Church.38 And before Quine, difficulties with the theory that the
36
Klibansky (1968, pp. 91ff). This echoes Fitch (1950, p. 553) where it is said that: ‘‘Smullyan has shown
that there is no real difficulty if the phrase [sic] ‘the Morning Star’ and ‘the Evening Star’ are
regarded either as proper names or as descriptive phrases in Russell’s sense.’’ The syntactic ambiguity
in this last formulation as to whether ‘‘in Russell’s sense’’ is supposed to modify ‘‘proper names’’ as
well as ‘‘descriptive phrases’’ matches the ambiguity in the formulation quoted earlier as to whether
‘‘Russellian’’ is supposed to modify ‘‘the distinction between proper names and descriptions’’ as well
as ‘‘theory of descriptions.’’ The ambiguity is appropriate, since the theory of names in question is
neo-Russellian.
37
Though this may not yet have been made clear at the time the encyclopedia article was written, since
the formulation of the rebuttal I have quoted dates from two years later.
38
See Føllesdal (1961), x17, pp. 96ff) and Church (1950). Both address Smullyan and Fitch.
Quinus ab omni naevo vindicatus 229
reference of a name to its bearer is descriptively mediated had also been
recognized.39 But before Quine, those who recognized the difficulties with
the absolute immediacy theory generally either did not take them to be
decisive or took them to be arguments for the descriptive mediation theory,
and vice versa. But if the first lesson of Quine’s critique for the theory of
reference is that the neo-Russellian theory of names is untenable, the last
half-sentence of his rebuttal suggests a second lesson, that this first lesson is
not in and of itself an argument for the Fregean theory. Putting these
lessons together, it is not to be assumed that there are just two options; there
is space for a third alternative.
39
For work on difficulties with the Fregean theory in the 1950s and early 1960s, see the
discussion in Kripke (1972/1980), and Searle (1967). The doctrines in ‘‘Naming and necessity’’
were first presented in seminars in 1963–4, and whereas that work apologizes for being spotty
in its coverage of the literature of the succeeding years, it is pretty thorough in its discussion
of the relevant literature (work of P. Geach, P. Strawson, P. Ziff, and others) from the
immediately preceding years. (Searle discusses work of yet another contributor, Elizabeth
Anscombe.)
40
In Field (1989, chapter 3). Field also cites several expressions of the same or related views from the
earlier literature, and such citations could in a sense be carried all the way back to the ‘‘principle of
predication’’ (von Wright 1951).
230 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
Max Creswell.41 (What is at issue in the latter connection is that a
two-place predicate Rxy may correspond to a phrase with two verbs,
such as ‘‘x is richer than y is,’’ each of which separately can be left in
the indicative or put in a non-indicative mood, as in ‘‘x would have
been richer than y is’’ contrasting with ‘‘x would have been richer than
y would have been,’’ so as to allow cross-comparison between how what
is is, and how what could have been would or might have been.)
Second, there may well be a formal difference already at the sentential
level. For logical modality, at least in some of its versions or variants, iterated
modalities make good sense. I allude here again to work on intensional
mathematics and provability logic, where being unprovable is to be distin-
guished from being provably unprovable. For metaphysical modality, it is
much less clear that iteration makes sense. In Prior’s well-known work on
systems combining subjunctive mood operators with past and future tense
operators, for instance, iterated modal operators collapse, unless separated
by temporal operators: there is no distinction recognized between what is as
of today possibly possible and what is as of today possible, though there is a
distinction between what as of yesterday it was possible would be possible as
of today and what after all is possible as of today. In later work also on the
interaction of mood and tense the purely modal part of the logic adopted
amounts to S5, which collapses iterated modalities.42
Third, there is the difference that while logical possibility does not admit
of degrees – a theory cannot be just a little bit inconsistent – metaphysical
possibility seems to, with some possibilities being more remote than others.
At any rate, this is the thought that underlies theories of counterfactuals
since the pioneering work of R. Stalnaker.43 In particular, miraculous
possibilities, involving violations of the laws of physics, are in general
more remote than non-miraculous possibilities, a fact that may make the
error of earlier writers in associating counterfactuals with physical necessity
in some respects a less serious one.
Thus there is a fair amount of work that has been – or can be construed
as – exploration of the formal differences between the two kinds of modality.
41
In Creswell (1990). Cresswell also cites several expressions of the same or related views from the
earlier literature, and such citations could in a sense be carried all the way back (Lewis 1970). This is
the earliest relevant publication known to me, but its author has suggested that there was very early
unpublished work on the topic by A. P. Hazen and by D. Kaplan. The parallel phenomenon for
tense in place of mood was noted even earlier by P. Geach.
42
See Prior (1967b, chapter VII), and among later work R. H. Thomason (1984). The purely modal
part is also S5 for virtually all the workers there cited, as well as later ones like A. Zanardo.
43
Stalnaker (1968). This feature becomes even more prominent in later work on the same topic by
D. K. Lewis and others.
Quinus ab omni naevo vindicatus 231
As apparent formal differences accumulate, the situation comes to look like
this: there is one philosophically coherent enterprise of logical modal logic,
attempting to treat in the object language what classical logic treats in the
metalanguage; there is another philosophically coherent enterprise of meta-
physical modal logic, attempting to do for grammatical mood something like
what temporal logic does for grammatical tense; there is a mathematically
coherent field of non-classical logics dealing with technical questions about
both these plus intuitionistic, temporal, and other logics; but there is no
coherent field broad enough to include both kinds of ‘‘modal logic,’’ but still
narrower than non-classical logic as a whole. In this sense, there is no coherent
enterprise of ‘‘modal logic’’ – a conclusion that may be called Quinesque.
44
Unfortunately this comes in the form of a review of a book by a third party, and is subject to the
limitations of such a form. The third party is Leonard Linsky; the book is Linsky (1977); the review is
Marcus (1978). The three quotations to follow come from pp. 498, 501, and 502–3.
232 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
It is one of the achievements of Kripke’s account, with its effective use of the
theory of descriptions, the theory of proper names, the distinction between
metaphysical and epistemological modalities (for example, necessary vs. a priori),
that it provides us with a more coherent and satisfactory analysis of statements
which appear to assert contingent identities.
Third, the contribution most praised is the provision of a novel account of
the mechanism by which a name achieves reference to its bearer:
Kripke provided us with a ‘‘picture’’ which is far more coherent than what had
been available. It preserves the crucial differences between names and descriptions
implicit in the theory of descriptions. By distinguishing between fixing the mean-
ing and fixing the reference, between rigid and nonrigid designators, many
nagging puzzles find a solution. The causal or chain of communications theory
of names (imperfect and rudimentary as it is) provides a plausible genetic account
of how ordinary proper names can acquire unmediated referential use.
All this amounts to something approaching an adequate acknowledg-
ment of substantial additions by the new theory to the old, but what needs
to be understood is that the new theory in fact proposes substantial amend-
ments also. The new theory is not ‘‘direct’’ in anywhere near as extreme a
sense as the old. On the new theory, which is a ‘‘third alternative,’’ the
reference of a name to its bearer is neither descriptively mediated nor
absolutely immediate, but rather is historically mediated, accomplished
through a chain of usage leading back from present speakers to the original
bestower of the name. Also the new theory does not endorse the ‘‘necessity
of identity’’ in anything like so broad a sense as does the old theory, or on
anything like the same grounds. On the new theory, ‘‘Hesperus is
Phosphorus’’ is only subjunctively or metaphysically necessary – not strictly
or logically necessary like ‘‘Phosphorus is Phosphorus.’’ And moreover the
metaphysical necessity of identity is the conclusion of a separate argument
involving considerations peculiar to subjunctive contexts, about cross-
comparison between actual and counterfactual situations – not an
immediate corollary or special case of some general principle of the intersub-
stitutability of coreferential names in all (except meta-linguistic) contexts.45
The gap between the old, neo-Russellian theory and the new, anti-
Russellian theory is large enough to have left space for the development
45
In this connection mention may be made of one serious historical inaccuracy – of a kind extremely
common when authors quote themselves from memory decades after the fact – to be found in the
book review, where it is said that the compendium maintained ‘‘that unlike different but corefer-
ential descriptions, two proper names of the same object were intersubstitutable in modal contexts’’
(p. 502). In actual fact, in the compendium it is repeatedly asserted that two proper names of the same
object are intersubstitutable in all contexts.
Quinus ab omni naevo vindicatus 233
of several even newer fourth and fifth alternatives, semi- or demi-semi- or
hemi-demi-semi-Russellian intermediate views, of which the best known
is perhaps Nathan Salmon’s.46 These differ from the Kripkean, anti-
Russellian theory in that they want to say that in some sense ‘‘Hesperus is
Phosphorus’’ and ‘‘Phosphorus is Phosphorus’’ have the same ‘‘semantic
content.’’47 They differ from the Smullyanite, neo-Russellian theory in that
there is full awareness that in some sense assertive utterance of ‘‘Hesperus is
Phosphorus’’ can make a difference to the ‘‘epistemic state’’ of the hearer in
a way that assertive utterance of ‘‘Phosphorus is Phosphorus’’ cannot. How
it could be that utterances expressing the same semantic content have such
different potential effects on epistemic states is in a sense the main problem
addressed by such theories. My concern here is not to offer any evaluation,
or even any exposition, of the solutions proposed, but only to point
out that they all operate in the space between Fregeanism and neo-
Russellianism – and therefore in a space of whose existence Quine was
one of the first to hint.
46
Salmon (1986). While the early Marcus followed Smullyan, the later Marcus has developed in
response to Kripke an idiosyncratic theory that may be described as intermediate in degree of
Russellianism between Salmon’s and Smullyan’s. See Marcus (1990).
47
For Kripke’s rejection of this view, see the closing paragraphs of the preface to Kripke (1980).
234 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
But when Kripke lectured on the distinction between logical and meta-
physical modality, modal logicians did not rush home to check which
conclusions hold for the one, which conclusions hold for the other, and
which result from a fallacious conflation of the two. It is a striking fact that
the basic article – an article written by two very eminent authorities – on
modal logic in that standard reference work, the multi-volume encyclo-
pedia mistitled a ‘‘handbook’’ of philosophical logic, makes no mention at
all of any such distinction and its conceivable relevance to choosing among
the plethora of competing modal systems surveyed.48
No wonder then that workers from other areas interested in applying
modal logic seem often not fully informed about formal differences
between the two kinds of modality. To cite only the example I know
best, consider philosophy of mathematics, and debates over nominalist
attempts to provide a modal reinterpretation of applied mathematics,
where quantification into modal contexts is unavoidable. Those on the
nominalist side have quite often supposed that they could get away with
quantifying into contexts of logical modality, while those on the anti-
nominalist side have quite often supposed that anyone wishing to make
use of modality must stick to the traditional formal systems, which do not
allow for cross-comparison. Both suppositions are in error.49
Take the theory of reference now. Here a great many people seem to
have difficulty discerning the important differences among distinct anti-
Fregean theories. To mention again the example I know best, many
nominalists seem to think that the work of Kripke, David Kaplan, Hilary
Putnam, and others has established something implying that it is impos-
sible to make reference to mathematical or other abstract, causally inert
objects.50
Such misunderstandings are encouraged by the common sloppy use by
specialists of ambiguous labels like ‘‘causal theory of reference’’; and even
those who carefully avoid ‘‘causal theory’’ in favor of ‘‘direct theory’’ are
often sloppy in their usage of the latter, encouraging other confusions. Of
late, not only has the confused opinion become quite common that
Quine’s critique has somehow been answered by the new theory of
48
Bull and Segerberg (1984). Other articles in the same work, some of which I have already cited, do
recognize the importance of the distinction.
49
It would be out of place to enter into technicalities here. See Burgess and Rosen (1997).
50
In actual fact, on Kripke’s theory, for instance, a name can be given to any object that can be
described, not excluding mathematical objects. But again see Burgess and Rosen (1997). (The theory
of P. Geach probably deserves and the theory of M. Devitt certainly deserves the label ‘‘causal,’’ and
does have nominalistic implications.)
Quinus ab omni naevo vindicatus 235
names (the one coming from ‘‘Naming and necessity’’); but so has the even
more confused opinion that Quine’s critique was already answered by an
old theory of names (the one coming from Russell through Smullyan to the
compendium); and so too has the most confused opinion of all, that there
is no important difference between the old and new theories. Confusion of
this kind is found both among those who think of themselves as sympa-
thizers with ‘‘the’’ theory in question,51 and among those who think of
themselves as opponents of ‘‘it.’’52 The latter cite weaknesses of the old
theory as if pointing them out could refute the new theory – a striking
example of how confusion over history of philosophy can lead to confusion
in philosophy proper.
There is hardly a better way to sort out such confusions than by
considering the relations of the old and the new theory to Quine’s critique,
from which therefore some people still have something to learn. Neither
the old theory nor the new provides a refutation of that critique, but the
reasons why are radically different in the two cases. The old theory
attempted to refute that critique, but in doing so it arrived at consequences,
notably the one made explicit in the ‘‘lexicon’’ passage quoted earlier, that
reduced the theory to absurdity. Quine’s rebuttal, pointing out the unten-
ability of these consequences, refuted the old theory. Quine’s critique does
not refute the new theory, but then neither does the new theory refute
Quine’s critique, nor does it even attempt to do so. The new theory would
refute any incautious claim to the effect that ‘‘quantification into any
intensional context is meaningless,’’ since it shows that proper names
have all the properties required of canonical terms for contexts of subjunc-
tive modality. But Quine’s critique was addressed to strict modality, and as
for that, the main creator of the new theory of names has said as I do:53
‘‘Quine is right.’’
51
For comparatively moderate instance see the review Lavine (1995).
52
For an extreme instance see Hintikka and Sandu (1995). This work acknowledges no important
differences among: (i) the neo-Russellian theory of Smullyan as expounded by the early Marcus
(which incidentally is erroneously attributed to Marcus as something original, ignoring the real
authors Smullyan and Russell); (ii) theories adopted in reaction to Kripke by the later Marcus; and
(iii) the theory of Kripke.
53
In context, what is said to be right is specifically the rebuttal to Smullyanism on names quoted
earlier. See Kripke (1972, p. 305).
12
Translating names
Mill taught that the signification of a word has in general two components,
denotation and connotation, but that in the special case of a proper name
there is no connotation, and the signification of the word is just its
denotation. According as ‘‘meaning’’ is aligned with ‘‘connotation’’ or
with ‘‘signification,’’ this doctrine comes out as ‘‘A proper name has no
meaning’’ or as ‘‘The meaning of a proper name is just its denotation.’’
Today ‘‘Millianism’’ is most often used as a label for the latter version:
(1) The meaning of a name is its denotation.
An immediate objection to (2) is that different names for the same item
may be distinguished in level (formal, familiar). Such features are very
important for usage. (Imagine what a diplomatic contretemps would result
if President Chirac were to write President Bush a letter beginning ‘‘Yo,
Dubya!’’) And with words that (unlike proper names) appear in diction-
aries, such features are commonly noted in their definitions, presumably as
part of the meaning of the word. It is therefore, the objector claims,
reasonable to take them to be part of the meaning of a name as well.
To this objection a Millian may reply by insisting that level is a feature of
usage but not of meaning. This reply illustrates in miniature the fact that in
this area there are no conclusive proofs or refutations, but in the end only
judgments as to the overall plausibility of proposals as to where to draw the
line between semantics and pragmatics. Alternatively, a Millian might
concede that (1) and (2) do indeed need to be qualified, while insisting
that the objection does not touch what is really important in Millianism, of
which the unqualified (1) and (2) are inadequate formulations. This
236
Translating names 237
alternative illustrates the fact that it is difficult to find formulations agree-
able to all parties of the main theses in dispute. Here I will for brevity let the
simple (1) and (2) stand as formulations of Millianism. (Features of level
have been mentioned only to illustrate the two facts about the nature of the
debate just indicated, and otherwise will play no role in the discussion
below.)
I will likewise stick with fairly simple formulations of two other theses,
one common to most Millians and anti-Millians alike, the other a premise
of one popular form of anti-Millianism. The common thesis is composi-
tionality, thus:
(3) Short, simple sentences differing only by substituting one word for another
with the same meaning have the same meaning.
Then (2) and (3) together at once give the following:
(4) Short, simple sentences differing only by substituting one name for another
with the same denotation have the same meaning.
The anti-Millianism thesis is so-called transparency, thus:
(5) When short, simple sentences have the same meaning, a subject’s asserting or
assenting to one and denying or dissenting from the other is an indication of a
deficiency in the subject’s linguistic knowledge.
All examples below will involve short, simple sentences (usually three-word
sentences of name–copula–adjective form). In particular, none will involve
such complications as embedding in ‘‘So-and-so believes that . . .’’ contexts.
The anti-Millian argument I wish to consider produces certain exam-
ples, and appeals to pre-theoretic intuitions to support the following claim
about them:
(6) There are cases of two short, simple sentences that differ only by substitution
of one name for another having the same denotation, where a subject may
assert or assent to one sentence and deny or dissent from the other sentence,
not for lack of linguistic knowledge, but rather for lack of some other kind of
knowledge.
The other knowledge in the best-known examples is biographical or
astronomical or geographical or historical (counting etymological knowl-
edge, which is not needed for fluency in the present form of a language, as
historical rather than linguistic).
While the examples most often cited pertain to persons (Marcus Tullius
Cicero) and planets (Venus), there are also examples about cities. Thus
Jones may while doing some tourism have cruised by moonlight past the
238 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
famous skyline of the former Ottoman capital, and may while negotiating a
business deal have paid a rapid visit to an undistinguished commercial
district on the outskirts of the same city. If the place was consistently called
‘‘Byzantium’’ by the tour guides and ‘‘Istanbul’’ by the business people,
Jones may end up asserting ‘‘Byzantium is sublime’’ and ‘‘Istanbul is tacky’’
while denying ‘‘Byzantium is tacky’’ and ‘‘Istanbul is sublime.’’ The anti-
Millian’s intuition is that this shows Jones to be a geographical ignoramus,
but does not show Jones to be a linguistic incompetent like the prize-
fighting fan Pete, who applauds whenever someone calls Muhammed Ali
‘‘a great boxer’’ but would take offense if anyone called him ‘‘a great
pugilist.’’
This particular case involves binomialism of the first (Hesperus/
Phosphorus) kind, where an item has two different names tracing back
to two different acts of naming (by Megarian colonists in the seventh
century BC E , and by the Atatürk government in the 1930s). But similar
examples can arise with binomialism of the second (Cicero/Tully) kind,
where two names trace back to the same original act of naming along
divergent paths of transmission. A tourist trip to ‘‘Peking’’ may be confined
mainly to the Forbidden City, while a business meeting in ‘‘Beijing’’ may
be held in a quarter built in the 1950s in high Stalinist style.
Now (4) and (5) and (6) cannot all be true, and an accumulation of
examples makes (6) hard to deny. The anti-Millian, assuming (5), con-
cludes that the Millian thesis (4) is false. A militant Millian may simply
insist that since (4) is true, (5) must be false. But many Millians would,
I think, prefer to find some independent argument against (5), not relying
on (4), and one place where they have looked for the materials to construct
such an argument has been in Saul Kripke’s notorious ‘‘A puzzle about
belief’’ (Kripke 1979). That paper contains two examples that, however the
author intended them, anti-anti-Millians might appropriate and exploit
for purposes of arguing against (5), and it is the anti-anti-Millian appro-
priation and exploitation of the first of these, the Pierre example, that I
wish to consider here.
The example involves the translation of proper names, and so I should
acknowledge at the outset the fact that in common parlance one seldom
speaks of ‘‘translating’’ proper names at all. In the broad sense used here,
whatever expression is used in a translation of a sentence at the place
corresponding to the place where a name is used in the sentence being
Translating names 239
translated may be called a ‘‘translation’’ of that name. But it must be
acknowledged that most proper names simply do not have non-trivial
translations: typically a name is not replaced by something else when
translating a sentence in which it occurs, but simply taken over for use in
the language into which the sentence is being translated, as a so-called
exonym.
It would be an absurd affectation for a native English speaker, describing
to other native English speakers a recent trip to Italy, to speak of having
been to ‘‘Roma’’ and ‘‘Napoli’’ and ‘‘Firenze.’’ For the famous tourist
destinations of Rome and Naples and Florence are among the minority
of Italian cities whose names do have non-trivial English translations, or
‘‘Anglicizations’’ as they are more ordinarily called. But if I wish to mention
some less famous Italian place, such as Princeton’s sister city Pettoranello,
there is no alternative to using the Italian name.
More precisely, one uses in speech as close an approximation to the
Italian name as one can manage, given the phonetic differences between
Italian and English. In writing, one can just use in English the original
name if translating from a language written in the Roman alphabet,
perhaps modulo some diacritical marks and ligatures. (Thus in the days
of old-fashioned manual typewriters, ‘‘Gödel’’ was often written ‘‘Goedel,’’
and even today ‘‘Gauß’’ is still written ‘‘Gauss.’’) With languages written in
another alphabet one uses what is ordinarily called a ‘‘transliteration,’’ and
with languages not written alphabetically a ‘‘transcription.’’
The Pierre example involves ‘‘London’’ as the name of the great city in
England, which unlike ‘‘Liverpool’’ or ‘‘London’’ as the name of the town in
Ontario does have a non-trivial French translation, ‘‘Londres.’’ The most
direct way to turn the Pierre example into an argument against (5) begins
with the following comparatively uncontroversial assumptions:
(7a) ‘‘Londres’’ is the correct French translation of the English ‘‘London.’’
(7b) ‘‘est joli[e]’’ is the correct French translation of the English ‘‘is pretty.’’
(7) ‘‘Londres est joli[e]’’ is the correct French translation of the English ‘‘London
is pretty.’’1
The next step would be a comparatively uncontroversial inference from (7)
to the following:
1
Should it be ‘‘Londres est joli’’ or ‘‘Londres est jolie’’? Having consulted with quite a number of
informants, French and Québecois, I can report that native Francophones themselves are undecided
as to the genders of most city names, ‘‘Londres’’ included.
240 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
(8) The meaning of ‘‘Londres est joli[e]’’ (in French) and the meaning of ‘‘London
is pretty’’ (in English) are the same.
Kripke then describes the case of one Pierre, of whom he claims the
following:
(9) Pierre assents to ‘‘Londres est joli[e]’’ and dissents from ‘‘London is pretty.’’
(10a) There is no deficiency in Pierre’s knowledge of French.
(10b) There is no deficiency in Pierre’s knowledge of English.
(10) There is no relevant deficiency in Pierre’s linguistic knowledge.
Taken together, (8) and (9) and (10) give a counterexample to (5), which
may be claimed to neutralize the anti-Millian force of the Byzantium/
Istanbul and Peking/Beijing examples, and of the better-known Cicero/
Tully and Hesperus/Phosphorus examples.
3 ANTI-ANTI-ANTI-MILLIANISM
I do not wish to question here the truth of (7), or the cogency of the
inference thence to (8). Moreover, in the example as Kripke describes it, (9)
seems indisputable, too. I think, however, that doubts may be raised about
(10), and in order to raise them I wish to question not the truth of but the
grounds for (7a). So let me begin by mentioning a way to argue for the
correctness of translating ‘‘London’’ as ‘‘Londres’’ that would be wholly
inappropriate in the present context.
The argument I have in mind takes as its initial premise the one
undisputed fact in this area:
(11) ‘‘Londres’’ (in French) and ‘‘London’’ (in English) denote the same place.
It then proceeds to this intermediate step:
(12) ‘‘Londres’’ (in French) and ‘‘London’’ (in English) have the same meaning.
And it then proceeds to the final conclusion (7a). Such an argument would
be inappropriate in the present dialectal context, because we are supposed
to be looking for an anti-anti-Millian argument independent of distinc-
tively Millian assumptions, while it is precisely the distinctively Millian
thesis (2) that would be needed to get from (11) to (12).
Questions of dialectic aside, it seems clear that while sameness of
denotation is a necessary condition, it is simply not a sufficient condition
for correctness of translation of place names. If some Francophone coun-
terpart of Jones exclaims, ‘‘Que Byzance est belle!’’ and ‘‘Que Stamboul est
laid!’’ he surely has to be translated as saying ‘‘How beautiful Byzantium is!’’
Translating names 241
and ‘‘How ugly Istanbul is!’’ and not ‘‘How beautiful Istanbul is!’’ and
‘‘How ugly Byzantium is!’’ Nor is this just because the person whom we are
translating is confused about the identity of the city. ‘‘Staline restait à
Moscou’’ and ‘‘Djougachvili se cachait’’ surely have to be translated ‘‘Stalin
remained in Moscow’’ and ‘‘Djugashvili was hiding,’’ not ‘‘Djugashvili
remained in Moscow’’ and ‘‘Stalin was hiding,’’ even if the translation is
from the writings of Trotsky and is being prepared for a groupuscule of
Trotskyites all thoroughly aware that Stalin/Staline and Djugashvili/
Djougachvili are one and the same person.
These examples may make it look as if an etymological connection and/
or a resultant phonetic or orthographic relationship were the key. But
such links are neither necessary nor sufficient for correct translation. Some
of the most ancient and famous countries – Egypt, India, Greece – have
long been known to most of the outside world by names having nothing
to do with their native names. Any one of these cases shows etymological
and phonetic and orthographic links are not necessary, as would the case
of ‘‘Deutschland’’ aka ‘‘Germany’’ aka ‘‘Allemagne.’’ The Greek case shows
that they are not sufficient, either. For there actually exists in English a
name for the country in question, the name ‘‘Hellas,’’ that is etymologically
connected and phonetically and orthographically related to the native
name; but nonetheless it is the unconnected, unrelated ‘‘Greece’’ that is
the correct translation of the native name in all common, prosaic contexts.
(Use of ‘‘Hellas’’ and ‘‘Hellenic’’ is appropriate only in the kind of contexts
where ‘‘Hibernia’’ and ‘‘Hibernian’’ might be used instead of ‘‘Ireland’’ and
‘‘Irish.’’)
But if not merely denotation, or that plus etymology, what does make a
given translation of a given name correct or incorrect? A clue is given,
I think, by the case of the translation into western European languages –
more usually called the ‘‘Romanization’’ – of Chinese proper names.
Historically, approximate phonetic transcriptions were used. But since
the differences between the principal Chinese ‘‘dialects’’ are so great, and
the different European languages are so many, that practice led to chaos,
and hence to a demand for a fixed system. Unfortunately not one but two
systems were fixed (both based on Mandarin pronunciation on the Chinese
side, but who knows what on the European side), one by European scholars
and another by the Chinese government. As a result, most important
Chinese geographical places and historical personages can be translated
in either of two ways into English or French. And often, as with ‘‘Hsüan-
tsang’’ aka ‘‘Xuánzàng’’ (the historical personage on whom the character
Tripitaka in A Journey to the West is based), it is difficult for the average
242 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
Anglophone or Francophone reader to trace any link between the Wade–Giles
and Pinyin versions. But at least the situation is better than it was when this
same personage was also being called by the names ‘‘Hiouentang’’ and ‘‘Yuan
Chwang’’ and half a dozen others.
While the case of the Romanization of Chinese, where conventions were
consciously and deliberately and explicitly adopted (and where there are
two rival sets of conventions), is unusual, I take it to illustrate a more
general principle. The general principle is that what counts as the (or a)
correct translation of a name from one language to another is determined by the
conventions and customs of the community of bilinguals and specifically of
translators. Needless to say, those conventions and customs are constrained
by the requirement that the name and its translation must have the same
denotation, and may be influenced, though not determined, by etymo-
logical or phonetic or orthographic considerations. In the case of second-,
third-, and fourth-hand borrowings, as when, say, an Arabic or Hebrew
place-name migrates via Greek and Latin and French to English, suffering
distortions at each step, the correct formulation of the general principle
would have to be more complicated. (The case where there is no link of any
kind, even through a chain of intermediaries, need not be considered, since
in this case all names will initially be like ‘‘Pettoranello’’ in lacking non-
trivial translations.) But leaving aside details, if anything like this principle
is granted, there would seem to follow another important principle, to the
effect that bilingual competence involves something more than just competence
in each of the two languages separately, something that can only be acquired by
contact with members of the bilingual community, direct or through their
writings.
Now to return to Pierre, the general principle just formulated raises
doubts whether (10a) and (10b) are enough to imply (10). Kripke describes
Pierre as lacking even the minimal kind of contact with the bilingual
community he could acquire by looking into a French–English dictionary.
Supposing Pierre keeps a diary in his native French of his experiences in the
English city where he finds himself, he will write for the name of that city
‘‘London’’ if he has seen the local name written, or if he has only heard it
spoken, something on the order of ‘‘Lonnedonne.’’ Either way, a single
glance at his diary would suffice to show any bilingual that Pierre lacks the
knowledge, which a French–English dictionary could provide him with,
that ‘‘London’’ is one of the small minority of English place-names that has
a non-trivial French translation, and that this translation is ‘‘Londres.’’
I wish to suggest that what this shows is that Pierre is lacking bilingual
competence, and that this is a lack of a kind of linguistic knowledge,
Translating names 243
making (10) false. Thus at bottom, I suggest, Pierre’s state is not after all so
very different from that of Ali’s linguistically challenged fan Pete.
5 ENVOI
About the Pierre puzzle there remains one further point to be acknowl-
edged. Suppose Pierre were informed that the French translation of
‘‘London’’ is ‘‘Londres.’’ This might well clear up his confusion, but then
again it might not. For Pierre might conclude that there are two homo-
nymous names ‘‘Londres’’ in French, one denoting a pretty place he saw in
pictures back in France and one the ugly place where he lives now that he
has come to England, just as there are two homonymous names
‘‘Bretagne,’’ one denoting a peninsula that is part of France, and one
denoting a large island across the Channel from France. There is this
difference, that in the case of ‘‘Bretagne’’ there are two different names in
Translating names 245
English, ‘‘Brittany’’ and ‘‘Britain,’’ while in the case of ‘‘Londres’’ there is (so
far as Pierre knows) in English just ‘‘London.’’ Pierre may be somewhat
puzzled why the English have not had the wit to add something to one or
both of the names, as the French distinguish their peninsula ‘‘Bretagne’’
from the island ‘‘Grande Bretagne’’ or the German town ‘‘Aix-la-Chapelle’’
from the French town ‘‘Aix-en-Provence.’’ But perhaps after his ugly
experiences living in London he expects no better of the English.
It is clear that if Pierre were to fall into the kind of confusion I have just
been describing, then the Pierre example would reduce to a variant of
Kripke’s other example, the Paderewski example. But this example raises a
quite different set of issues from the issues about translation with which
I have been concerned here, and must be left for another occasion.
13
Relevance: a fallacy?
1 INTRODUCTION
246
Relevance: a fallacy? 247
Table 13.1
2 EXAMPLES
Background to Example 1
The game of Mystery Cards is played thus: the red and black cards from an
ordinary deck are separated. One red and one black ‘‘mystery card’’ are set
aside face down, without having been seen by any player. The remaining
twenty-five red and twenty-five black cards are combined, shuffled, and
dealt out to the players, whose object is to guess the mystery cards. The
players take turns questioning each other. The player whose turn it is
addresses the player of his choice asking a question of the form, ‘‘Is it the
such-and-such red card and the thus-and-so black card?’’ If the player
questioned has either or both of the cards named in his hand, he must
answer ‘‘No’’; otherwise he must answer ‘‘Maybe.’’ Both question and
answer are audible to all players. If a player feels ready to guess the mystery
cards, then on his next turn, instead of asking a question he may make a
statement, saying ‘‘It’s the such-and-such red card and the thus-and-so
black card!’’ He then looks at the mystery cards. If his guess is correct, he
turns them face up and is declared the winner. If wrong, he puts them back
face down, exposes his own hand, and is disqualified from further play.
Admittedly this game is a dull one, but it exhibits in simplified form the
principle at work in several more interesting games (e.g. the one marketed
under the trade-name CLUE, the importance of which was pointed out to
me by D. K. Lewis).
Example 1. Argument
During the course of a game of Mystery Cards, Wyberg hears von Eckes ask
Zeemann, ‘‘Is it the deuce of hearts and the queen of clubs?’’ He hears
Zeemann reply ‘‘No.’’ Later in the game he manages to figure out that it is
the deuce of hearts. He argues: it isn’t both the deuce of hearts and the
queen of clubs; but it is the deuce of hearts; so it isn’t the queen of clubs. He
goes on to use this information to win the game.
Example 1. Analysis
Let p ¼ ‘‘The mystery red card is the deuce of hearts,’’ q ¼ ‘‘The mystery
black card is the queen of clubs.’’ Zeemann’s hint is no more and no less
than that (p & q). Her statement is made on purely truth-functional
grounds: she sees the queen in her hand. Her statement is not made on
250 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
the basis of any ‘‘relevance’’ between p and q: the two mystery cards were
chosen entirely independently of each other. Zeemann is justified in
denying a truth-functional conjunction, but would not be justified in
denying cotenability. Since the premise (p q) is not available to
Wyberg, his argument is an instance of (II) that can be neither read as
nor replaced by an instance of (IIB).
Had Wyberg been a relevantist, unwilling to make a deductive step not
licensed by the Anderson–Belnap systems E and R, he would have been
unable to eliminate the queen of clubs from his calculations, and would
have lost the game. A relevantist would fare badly in this game and others,
and in game-like situations in social life, diplomacy, and other areas – unless,
of course, he betrayed in practice the relevantistic principles he espouses
in theory.
Background to Example 2
Dr. Zeemann has just been awarded her degree for a dissertation in number
theory. Her main result is a proof that every natural number n has either a
certain property A(n) or a certain property B(n). As written up in her thesis,
the proof is by induction on n, as follows:
Case n ¼ 0. We show that A(0). [Here follows a proof.]
Case n ¼ 1. We show that B(1). [Here follows a proof.]
Case n 2. We assume as induction hypothesis that either A(n 1) and A(n 2), or
A(n 1) and B(n 2), or B(n 1) and A(n 2), or else B(n 1) and B(n 2).
[Here follows a proof treating each of the four cases separately.]
She remarks that the famous d’Aubel–Hughes Conjecture would imply
that B(0), whereas the equally famous conjecture of MacVee would
imply that A(1), but reports that she has no light to shed on these old
conjectures.
Commentary
Before proceeding, let us note that, following the universal practice of
mathematicians, Zeemann has taken her proof that A(0) to dispose of the
case n ¼ 0 of the general theorem that for all n, either A(n) or B(n). In other
words, she argues from the premise A(0) to the conclusion that A(0) or
B(0). This is worth mentioning because relevantistically inclined writers
have been known to claim that no one ever seriously argues from p to p or q.
Indeed, in everyday conversation we are, in R. C. Jeffrey’s words, ‘‘at a loss
Relevance: a fallacy? 251
to know what the motive could be’’ for someone to pass from p to the
longer and less informative statement that p or q. ‘‘Knowing the premise,
why not assert it, rather than the conclusion?’’ However, in mathematics we
often have good reason to say less than we know: We will assert less than we
could about the cases n ¼ 0 and n ¼ 1 in order to incorporate these cases in
a generalization holding for all values of n. Now the inference from A(0) to
A(0) or B (0) is only valid if ‘‘or’’ is taken as Ú rather than þ. Hence
Zeemann’s theorem must be formalized as (8n)(A(n) Ú B(n)) and not
(8n)(A(n) þ B(n)). This means that any argument of form (I) in which
the major premise is supplied by Zeemann’s theorem will be an instance of
(I) that can be neither read as nor replaced by an instance of (IB). Let us
proceed to examples.
3 CONCLUSION
No doubt the reader can construct further examples. One might consider,
for instance, the case of a person who remembers that once upon a time he
was told either that p or that q, but cannot now remember which.
Investigating a bit, he quickly establishes that p, and so concludes that
q. Such examples, I submit, show that as far as negation, conjunction, and
disjunction are concerned, ‘‘classical’’ logic (and with it the whole logical
tradition from Chrysippus onwards) is far closer to commonsense and
accepted mathematical practice than is the ‘‘relevant’’ logic of Anderson
and Belnap.
One ploy the relevantist might use in trying to escape from our counter-
examples may already have occurred to the reader. What if we take the
‘‘relevance’’ required for the truth of p þ q and the falsehood of p q not as
something objective and absolute, but as something subjective and relative?
We might then say this of the Mystery Cards, for example: in objective fact
there is no connection between its being the deuce of hearts and its being
the queen of clubs, the red and black cards having been chosen separately.
In Zeemann’s mind there is no such connection, her statement that it is not
both being based solely on her knowledge that it is not the latter. But
Zeemann’s information establishes such a connection for Wyberg, so that
he is in a position to assert what she is not, namely p þ q. Hence his
argument can be represented as a case of (IIB).
I doubt such a subjectivization and relativization of ‘‘relevance’’ offers a
viable way out to followers of Anderson and Belnap. If (IB) and (IIB) are to
cover all instances of (I) and (II) in mathematics and everyday argumenta-
tion, ‘‘relevance’’ will have to be not just subjectivized but trivialized. Any
grounds for assertion p Ú q short of the simple knowledge that p, or that q,
will have to be taken as sufficient grounds for asserting p þ q: the statement
by a reliable person that she either knows p or knows q though she is not
saying which; the knowledge that p holds for m ¼ 0 and q holds for m ¼ 1,
coupled with ignorance as to whether m ¼ 0 or 1; the simple recollection
that one once knew p or knew q though one has now forgotten which. (And
paradoxically, the acquisition of more information could threaten one’s
right to assert p þ q: if one’s informant decides to provide more specific
information, if the value of m is settled, if one’s memory improves,
one may suddenly lose the right to assert p þ q.) Relevantism would reduce
to the position that (IA) is valid when and only when one’s grounds
for asserting p Ú q are something other than the simple knowledge that q.
Such a position, however, looks suspiciously like a confusion of the criteria
254 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
for the validity of a form of argument with the criteria for its utility, a
confusion of logic with epistemology.
Indeed, some writers have been willing to dismiss the whole relevantistic
movement as a simple case of confusion between the logical notion of
implication and the methodological notion of inference. The following
(unpublished) remarks of G. Harman on this point will bear quoting:
By reasoning or inference I mean a process by which one changes one’s views,
adding some things and subtracting others. There is another use of the term
‘‘inference’’ to refer to what I will call ‘‘argument’’, consisting in premises, inter-
mediate steps, and a conclusion. It is sometimes said that each step of an argument
should follow from the premises or prior steps in accordance with a ‘‘rule of
inference’’. I prefer to say ‘‘rule of implication’’, since the relevant rules do not say
how one may modify one’s views in various contexts. Nor is there a very direct
connection between rules of logical implication and principles of inference. We
cannot say, for example, that one may infer anything one sees to be logically
implied by one’s prior beliefs. Clearly one should not clutter up one’s mind with
many of the obvious consequences of things one believes.
Furthermore, it may happen that one discovers that one’s beliefs are logically
inconsistent and therefore logically imply everything. Obviously, one ought not to
respond to such a discovery by believing as much as one can. Some philosophers
and logicians [the reference is to Anderson and Belnap] have imagined that the
remedy here is a new logic in which logical contradictions do not logically imply
everything. But this is to miss the point that logic is not directly a theory of
reasoning at all.
And indeed if ‘‘relevance’’ is taken to be something subjective and relative
(according to the proposal discussed above), I do not see how the relevant-
ists could escape Harman’s charge that they confuse implication and
(useful) inference.
I do not, however, believe that the authors of Anderson and Belnap
(1975) understand by ‘‘relevance’’ something subjective. What little they tell
us about the nature of ‘‘relevance’’ (e.g. pp. 32–3, where they quote with
approval from several sources) strongly suggests that it is a matter of
meaning. Certainly their commonest charge against classical logic (first
raised on p. xxii and repeated ad nauseam) is that it ignores ‘‘intension’’ and
meaning. Meaning, however, is something that, generally speaking, will be
the same for Wyberg as it is for Zeemann. That relevance is meant to be a
semantical, and hence impersonal, notion and not a matter of individual
psychology, is further suggested by the relevantists’ criticism of T. J. Smiley
(p. 217), who is faulted for ‘‘epistemologizing’’ and ‘‘psychologizing’’ the
logical notion of entailment. Thus if the authors of Anderson and Belnap
(1975) intend by ‘‘relevance’’ something less than objective, they are highly
Relevance: a fallacy? 255
remiss in failing to alert readers to the fact; while if ‘‘relevance’’ is supposed
to be impersonal, then the claim that the relevantistic position is (even in a
weak sense) compatible with commonsense and accepted mathematical
practice succumbs to the counterexamples presented above.
In closing, let me reiterate that I have been concerned here solely with
the original Anderson–Belnap account of ‘‘relevant’’ logic, and with their
claim that their systems E, R, etc., are in better agreement with common
sense than is classical logic. I have not been concerned with other rationales
for developing these systems, nor with the possibility of imposing inter-
pretations on them that were not originally intended by their authors. (It
has been suggested, for instance, that some of the formalism created by
relevantists might be useful in developing a logic of ambiguity, or of truth-
in-fiction.) Workers in category theory, one of the least constructive
branches of modern mathematics, have found certain technical uses for
intuitionistic logic; but no one imagines that this vindicates Brouwer’s
philosophy of mathematics. Similarly, the discovery of serendipitous
applications of some of the formalism created by Anderson and Belnap
would not justify the claim that their logical systems are accurate formal-
izations of current mathematical practice. Still less could it justify the
abusive tone of their remarks about classical logicians.
14
1 TEXTS
1
For more on the contrast between the two approaches to philosophy of mathematics, see the editorial
introduction to Benacerraf and Putnam (1964).
256
Dummett’s case for intuitionism 257
Dummett has remarked of his case for intuitionism that ‘‘it is virtually
independent of any considerations relating specifically to the mathematical
character of the statements under discussion. The argument involve[s] only
certain considerations within the theory of meaning of a high level of
generality, and could, therefore, just as well have been applied to any
statements whatsoever, in whatever area of language’’ (1973a, p. 226).
Hence it is best to begin an examination of his case by considering some
of his views on meaning.
Especially important for Dummett are what I will call neutrally theories
of language of the first type. On a theory of this type, the meaning of a
sentence is identified with the conditions for correctness of the sentence (or
pedantically: of an assertion made by uttering the sentence) as a represen-
tation of reality. A speaker’s ability to use the sentence is explained by
reference to his grasp of these correctness conditions. Correctness may be
conceived of in more than one way, and hence more than one subtype
within the first type of theory of language is possible.
Especially important for Dummett is the distinction between those
conceptions on which correctness is, and those on which it is not, some-
thing always at least in principle potentially recognizable by human beings.
The best-known theory operating with a conception of correctness as
always recognizable is the intuitionistic proof-conditional theory of meaning
for the mathematical part of language. (The provability of a mathematical
conjecture is recognizable by discovering a proof.) The generalization of
this theory to the whole of language would be a verification-conditional or
verificationist theory.
The best-known correctness conception on which correctness is some-
times recognizable, sometimes unrecognizable, is the usual conception of
truth. (On the usual conception, the truth of a mathematical conjecture need
not imply the existence of a proof of the conjecture or any other means of
recognizing the conjecture as true.) To avoid ambiguities, I will call truth-as-
usually-conceived verity. Many distinguished philosophers have advocated
verity-conditional or verist theories of meaning. Dummett calls the special-
ization of such a theory to the mathematical part of language a Platonist
theory (though I imagine that he would be hard pressed to locate a passage in
the Republic or the Timaeus where such a theory is taught).
How can graspable correctness conditions be assigned to each of the
indefinitely many sentences of a language? The only answer that immedi-
ately suggests itself is: inductively. The theories of language of the first type
258 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
considered by Dummett take the sentences of the language to fall into a
hierarchy of degrees of complexity, with the correctness conditions for
those of higher degree being determined inductively from the correctness
conditions for those of lower degree. For example, such theories include an
induction clause indicating how the correctness conditions of a disjunction
are determined from those of its disjuncts. On an intuitionist or verifica-
tionist theory this clause takes the form:
(1) A proof (or verification) of a disjunction consists in the specification of one of
its disjuncts together with a proof (or verification) of that disjunct.
On a Platonist or verist theory this clause takes the form:
(2) A disjunction is true if and only if at least one of its disjuncts is true.
On any theory of language of the first type there is an external standard
against which rules of implication are to be judged. A rule is acceptable if
and only if it preserves correctness, leading in all instances where the
premises are correct to a conclusion that is correct. It is by appeal to such
induction clauses as (1) and (2) above that one can seek to demonstrate that
certain rules are correctness-preserving or sound.
Given the Platonist theory of meaning, the usual soundness proof for
classical logic established that all the rules of that logic are acceptable.
Given the intuitionist theory of meaning, the usual soundness proof for
intuitionistic logic establishes acceptability for all intuitionistic rules, but
not for all classical rules: the acceptability of rules depending on the laws of
double negation or excluded middle is doubtful when such rules are
applied to sentences for which an effective decision procedure is lacking,
such as those involving unbounded quantification over an infinite domain.
Dummett’s strategy is to argue for the repudiation of classical logic in favor
of intuitionistic logic by arguing for the repudiation of Platonist (or more
generally: verist) theories of meaning in favor of intuitionist (or more
generally: verificationist) theories.
On a verist theory, sentences whose correctness need not be recognizable
may be said to represent transcendent features of reality, while sentences
whose correctness must be recognizable may be said to represent immanent
features of reality. Dummett, like Brouwer, denies that any sentence of any
possible language can represent transcendent features of reality. But where
Brouwer sees this denial as expressing a limitation on reality, Dummett sees
it as expressing a limitation on language.
Dummett’s case against verism rests on principles summed up in the
slogan that meaning is use. He offers various formulations of these
Dummett’s case for intuitionism 259
principles, some in terms of meaning, others in terms of understanding,
some telling us what these consist in, others through what they are exhaus-
tively manifested. The following are typical (1973a, pp. 216, 217):
The meaning of . . . a statement cannot be, or contain as an ingredient, anything
which is not manifest in the use made of it, lying solely in the mind of the
individual who apprehends that meaning: if two individuals agree completely
about the use to be made of the statement, then they agree about its meaning. The
reason is that the meaning of a statement consists solely in its rôle as an instrument
of communication between individuals . . . An individual cannot communicate
what he cannot be observed to communicate . . .
[T]here must be an observable difference between the behavior or capacities
of someone who is said to have . . . knowledge [of the meaning of an expression]
and someone who is said to lack it. Hence it follows . . . that a grasp of the meaning
of a . . . statement must, in general, consist of a capacity to use that statement in
a certain way, or to respond in a certain way to its use by others.
Shared by all such formulations is an association of meaning with public
and observable use of language as a vehicle of communication, and a
dissociation of meaning from private and hidden use of language as a
vehicle of thought.2 Likewise, any association of meaning or understanding
with something in the conscious or unconscious mind, or in the structure
or functioning of the brain, is rejected. Though he himself avoids the label,
Dummett may be called a behaviorist in his approach to meaning, provided
this label is understood in a broad enough sense to cover not only the
stimulus-response behaviorism of Skinner, but also the logical behaviorism
of Ryle.
A thoroughgoing behaviorist will require that any apparatus posited by a
semantic theory must be identified or directly correlated with some isolable
features of publicly observable verbal behavior. As Dummett formulates it,
the behaviorist demand is that there must be a ‘‘one-one correspondence
between the details’’ of the apparatus posited by a semantic theory and
‘‘observable features of the phenomenon’’ (1977, p. 377). Dummett
describes rejection of this behaviorist demand as one form that the rejection
of the principle that meaning is use might take.
The great majority of contemporary linguists reject this behaviorist
demand as likely to lead only to sterility and stagnation in semantics.
The great majority of contemporary linguists posit in their semantic
theories an apparatus neither identified nor directly correlated with any
2
For more on the contrast between the two sorts of use of language, see the opening paragraphs of
Harman (1982).
260 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
set of isolable features of publicly observable verbal behavior. The original
version of Chomsky’s semantic theory, for example, posited an apparatus
of deep structures. Chomsky and the great majority of contemporary
linguists claim that the apparatus posited in their semantic theories is
psychologically real, represented in ways as yet undiscovered in the mind
or brain.3 But they do not claim the apparatus to be directly represented in
behavior.
Thus the principle that meaning is use, on which Dummett bases his
case for a revision of current mathematics, itself already amounts to a
demand for a revision of current linguistics. For this reason Dummett’s
arguments for the principle are of interest apart from their role in his
case for intuitionism. These arguments have often been criticized by
Davidsonians. Here they will be criticized from a viewpoint closer to that
of the Chomskians.
Two arguments for the principle that meaning is use are to be found in the
texts under examination. They are versions of what have come to be called
the acquisition and manifestation arguments. The first (1973a, p. 217) begins:
[O]ur proficiency in making the correct use of the statements and expression of the
language is all that others have from which to judge whether or not we have
acquired a grasp of their meanings. Hence it can only be in the capacity to make a
correct use of the statements of the language that a grasp of their meaning, and of
those of the symbols and expressions which they contain, can consist.
The rather familiar line of this opening4 alerts us that the argument is going
to turn on how an observer Y, say a teacher, can judge that a speaker X, say a
learner, attaches the standard meaning to an expression E. Perhaps before
proceeding further it would be well to review schematically the accounts of
such judgments offered by behaviorists, on the one hand, and by those
anti-behaviorists who associate meaning or understanding with a state of
the mind or brain, on the other.
On the behaviorist account, for X to attach the standard meaning to E is
for X to be able to use E standardly. On this account, Y’s judgment that X
3
A minority of linguists adopt the position advocated in Soames (1985), regarding such claims of
psychological reality as at best premature, but nonetheless insisting on the legitimacy of introducing
an apparatus of deep structures or the like in semantic theory, despite behaviorist objections.
4
Charles Chihara has pointed out in conversation the parallelism between the argument of Dummett
just quoted and the notorious argument of Norman Malcolm against the conception of dreams as
mental or neural activity taking place at specific times during sleep. Malcolm’s argument may be
paraphrased: our telling stories when we wake up is all that others have from which to judge whether
we have dreamt. Hence it can only be in the disposition to tell stories when we wake up that having
dreamt can consist.
Dummett’s case for intuitionism 261
attaches the standard meaning to E is a simple inductive inference from the
premise that X has been able to use E standardly in all observed instances to
the conclusion that X will be able to use E standardly in all instances. The
anti-behaviorist account is much more complex.
The first step towards an anti-behaviorist position is acceptance of the
general psychological principle that different people similar in their out-
ward behavior are normally similar also in the inward mental or neural
states that causally underlie behavior. The second step is acceptance, as a
special linguistic instance, of the hypothesis that there exists a mental or
neural state S(E) normally causally underlying the ability to use E stand-
ardly. Thus far a behaviorist may or may not go along. Where the
behaviorist must refuse to follow is at the anti-behaviorist’s third step,
the identification of attaching the standard meaning to E with being in the
state S(E) rather than directly with being able to use E standardly.
To appreciate the rather subtle distinction here, imagine an abnormal
case where a native English speaker X is able to communicate with a native
Chinese speaker W only because X has implanted inside his skull a mini-
supercomputer programmed to translate back and forth between English
and Chinese sentences. There may be no ‘‘difference in the behavior or
capacities’’ of X and W that is observable to those of us lacking telepathic
powers and X-ray vision. X and W may ‘‘agree completely about the use to
be made’’ of various Chinese words and phrases. Yet on account of the
absence of ‘‘an ingredient . . . lying solely in the mind’’ or brain, the anti-
behaviorist will deny that X attaches the standard meanings, or any mean-
ings at all, to those words and phrases.
The status of such science-fiction examples is in itself a matter of slight
importance, but there are more important further differences between
behaviorists and anti-behaviorists. One who identifies attaching the stand-
ard meaning to E with being the hypothetical state S(E) will presumably be
willing to entertain hypotheses about the composition and components of
S(E) and to permit a theory of the standard meaning of E to posit an
apparatus correlated with these hypothetical components of S(E). But while
S(E) itself is normally correlated with the ability to use E standardly, there
is no reason to suppose its components to be directly correlated with
any ‘‘isolable, though interconnected, practical abilities’’ (Dummett 1977,
p. 377). Hence the anti-behaviorist rejection of the requirement that the
apparatus posited in a theory of the standard meaning of E must be directly
correlated with isolable features of publicly observable verbal behavior,
which we have already seen to be the issue dividing Dummettians and
Chomskians.
262 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
On the anti-behaviorist account, for X to attach the standard meaning to
E is for X to be in a mental or neural state S(E) posited to underlie, in
normal cases, the ability to use E standardly. On this account, Y’s judgment
that X attaches the standard meaning to E rests on: (a) the evidence for the
presupposition that there exists a mental or neural state underlying, in a
normal case, the ability to use E standardly; (b) the evidence that X’s case is
a normal one; and (c) the evidence that X has been able to use E standardly
in all observed instances. The evidence (c) is the only evidence cited in the
behaviorist account. The evidence (b) may consist in no more than the
absence of evidence that X’s case is an abnormal one. The evidence (a) may
consist in no more than the evidence for the general psychological principle
that different people who are similar in their outward behavior are nor-
mally similar also in their inward mental and neural states.
A behaviorist, of course, may question the strength of the evidence for
this general psychological principle. Quineans, for example, have claimed
that different people identical in their outward behavior may be ‘‘like
different bushes trimmed to resemble identical elephants.’’ Dummett’s
objections to anti-behaviorism, however, do not take this form, being a
priori and philosophical rather than a posteriori and psychological.
Returning now to the argument whose opening was quoted above, it
continues (1973a, pp. 217–18):
To suppose that there is an ingredient of meaning which transcends the use that is
made of that which carries the meaning is to suppose that someone might have
learned . . . [to] behave in every way like someone who understands the language,
and yet might not actually understand, or understand it only incorrectly. But to
suppose this is to make meaning ineffable, that is, in principle incommunicable. If
this is possible, then no one individual ever has a guarantee that he is understood
by any other individual; for all he knows, or can ever know, everyone else may
attach to his words . . . a meaning quite different from that which he attaches to
them. A notion of meaning so private to the individual is one that has become
completely irrelevant to mathematics as it is actually practised, namely as a body of
theory on which many individuals are corporately engaged, an enquiry within
which each can communicate his results to others.
5
Paul Benacerraf suggested to me in general terms that Dummett’s arguments might have force for one
part of language but not another.
Dummett’s case for intuitionism 265
(a) Ascriptions of knowledge of meaning must be supported by appeal to observ-
able evidence.
(b) Knowledge of the meaning of an expression consists in no more than the
ability to use it in a certain way.
(c) Ascriptions of implicit knowledge must be supported by appeal to observable
evidence.
(d) Implicit knowledge consists in no more than the ability to behave in a certain way.
The anti-behaviorist rejects (b) but accepts (a). (The anti-behaviorist acc-
ount of the observable evidence supporting an ascription of knowledge of
meaning has been reviewed schematically above.) Since the conclusion
Dummett desires is (b) and not (a), the premise he requires is (d) and not
(c), even if his own formulations are less than unequivocal (1973a, p. 217;
1977, p. 376):
6
A not unrelated reason for rejecting truth-conditional theories of meaning is advanced in Harman
(1982):
Davidson, Lewis, and others have argued that an account of the truth conditions of sentences of a
language can serve as an account of the meanings of those sentences. But this seems wrong. Of course,
if you know the meaning in your language of the sentence S, and you know what the word ‘‘true’’
means, you will also know something of the form ‘‘S is true if and only if . . .’’; for example, ‘‘‘Snow is
white’ is true if and only if snow is white’’ or ‘‘‘I am sick’ is true if and only if the speaker is sick at the
time of utterance’’. But this is a trivial point about the meaning of ‘‘true’’, not a deep point about
meaning.
For more on the philosophical significance (or lack of it) of the concept of truth, see Soames (1984).
7
Saul Kripke has suggested that Dummett’s statement may be accurate as an account of local
conditions at Oxford. But surely it would bespeak a certain parochialism to confuse ‘‘fashionable
among Oxford philosophers’’ with ‘‘received among philosophers generally.’’
Dummett’s case for intuitionism 267
to mention Dummett himself, be considered ‘‘received wisdom among
philosophers’’?
For many philosophers what is most puzzling about Dummett’s case for
intuitionism will not be the question arising in his case against Platonism:
(a) Why are we supposed to reject verist semantics?
but rather the question arising in his case against formalism:
(b) How is the rejection of verist semantics supposed to lead to the rejection of
classical mathematics?
This latter question will now be taken up.
8
It is something of an oversimplification to describe Quine as a dualist, inasmuch as he often indicates
that he regards the distinction between the observational periphery and the theoretical interior as a
matter of degree rather than kind. But for Dummett the similarities between Quine’s position and
that of the prototypical dualist Hilbert are more important than such differences.
Dummett’s case for intuitionism 269
in deductions acquired? On a verist or verificationist theory the answer is:
by grasping the correctness conditions (1) or (2) above. This answer is not
available on a dualist theory, and no explicit answer is offered in Hilbert
(1925) or Quine (1951b). There is, however, an answer that immediately
suggests itself, namely, that the ability is acquired by directly grasping such
rules of implication as the following:
(3) A disjunction is implied by each of its disjuncts.
A disjunction implies whatever is implied by each of its disjuncts. In
other words, the ‘‘meaning of the logical constants’’ – if what determines
their use may be called their ‘‘meaning’’ – consists ‘‘directly in the validity
or invalidity of possible forms of inference’’ (Dummett 1977, p. 363). It
seems to be this answer that Dummett associates with dualism. It is worth
mentioning that quite apart from any general dualist views, the specific
view that an account of the ‘‘meaning’’ of the logical particles is best given
in terms of such implication conditions as (3) rather than such truth
conditions as (2) has had many distinguished advocates, including (accord-
ing to Prior 1960) several of Dummett’s Oxford colleagues.
Dualist theories may be called semi-verificationist. They are not verifi-
cationist in the strict sense, since some sentences are not assigned correct-
ness conditions. They are verificationist in a loose sense, since all sentences
that are assigned correctness conditions are assigned decidable, recogniz-
able, verifiable correctness conditions.
May dualist theories of language be called theories of meaning?
Dummett sometimes takes ‘‘(theory of) meaning’’ in a broad sense, and
insists on an affirmative answer (1973c, p. 378):
A model of language may also be called a model of meaning, and the importance
of the conception of language sketched at the end of ‘‘Two Dogmas’’ was that it
gave in succinct form the outline of a new model of meaning. It is well known that
some disciples of Quine have heralded his work as allowing us to dispense with the
notion of meaning. But even the most radical of such disciples can hardly propose
that we may dispense with the notion of knowing, or having mastery of, a
language; and there is nothing more that we can require of a theory of meaning
than that it give an account of what someone knows when he knows a language . . .
[W]hatever warrant there may be for asserting that Quine has destroyed the
concept of meaning does not appear from the ‘‘Two Dogmas’’ model of language
taken by itself. That has merely the shape of one theory or model of meaning
among other possible ones.
However, Dummett sometimes takes ‘‘(theory of) meaning’’ in a narrow
sense, and insists on a negative answer (1973b, p. 309):
270 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
The theory of meaning, which lies at the foundation of the whole of philosophy,
attempts to explain the way in which we contrive to represent reality by means of
language. It does so by giving a model for the content of a sentence, its represen-
tative power. Holism is not, in this sense, a theory of meaning: it is the denial that a
theory of meaning is possible.
When in the narrow, negative mood (as throughout 1977) Dummett is
prepared to join Brouwer and Heyting in declaring that many of the
sentences of classical mathematics are ‘‘incoherent’’ and ‘‘unintelligible.’’
This sounds odd. For Dummett can hardly deny that the sentences of
classical mathematics possess a definite usage within pure mathematics and
a definite utility through applied mathematics. How can he, as a professed
adherent of the slogan that meaning is use, then deny that those sentences
have a meaning? Taken literally, the slogan implies that a sentence having a
use thereby has a meaning. The answer, the explanation of the oddity, is, of
course, that Dummett, as we have already seen, adheres to the slogan that
meaning is use only in a non-literal, almost idiosyncratic, sense.
The narrow, negative terminology need not be misleading provided the
following point is never forgotten: When Dummett says that many sentences
of classical mathematics lack meaning-in-the-narrow-sense, he is only saying
(in highly emotive terms) that the theory of meaning-as-conditions-for-
correctness-as-a-representation-of-reality is inapplicable to those sentences.
This factual claim about how language is cannot by itself imply any norma-
tive claim about how mathematics ought to be. Some extra, tacit premise of a
normative or prescriptive character is needed. As I interpret it, Dummett’s
criticism of dualism is prescriptive, and rests on an extra, tacit premise of
anti-instrumentalism or representationalism, according to which every sen-
tence of a language ideally ought to play a representational rather than a
merely instrumental role. Thus when Dummett writes: ‘‘A sentence is a
representation of some facet of reality’’ (1973b, p. 309), according to my
interpretation he has not quite accurately reflected his own view: ‘‘ought to
be’’ ought to be where ‘‘is’’ is in the quoted formulation.
The requirement of representationality is, of course, accepted by Platonists,
who hold, in opposition to intuitionists and formalists, that this require-
ment is already met by our current language. Representationalism unites
Platonists and intuitionists in opposition to formalists, much as behaviorism
unites Quineans and Dummettians in opposition to Davidsonians and
Chomskians. (There are, however, important differences between the
Harvard behaviorism of Skinner or Quine and the Oxford behaviorism of
Ryle or Dummett. Moreover, it is not obvious that a verificationist or dualist
must be a behaviorist.)
Dummett’s case for intuitionism 271
Consider the situation of a philosopher initially sympathetic, for behav-
ioristic or other reasons, to a naive descriptive verificationism like that of
the early positivists, who comes to appreciate that such a theory is inade-
quate as an account of the actual, current patterns of use in our language.
One response would be to revise the theory to fit the facts of language,
perhaps falling back to a semi-verificationist, dualist position. Another
response would be to require a revision of language, to fit the norms of the
theory. Quine and Dummett exemplify these two responses. Dummett’s
against Quine stands or falls with the success or failure of his attempts to
motivate the requirement of representationality.
In both the texts under examination Dummett discusses, by way of
offering such motivation, the following worry about languages of the sort
depicted by dualist theories: in such a language, there is a threat of
deducing incorrect primary sentences by means of secondary sentences.
In one text, the worry seems to be that incorrect primary sentences
might be deduced from (theories composed of) secondary sentences
(1973a, p. 220):
With what right do we feel assurance that the observational statements deduced
with the help of complex theories, mathematical, scientific and otherwise, embed-
ded in the interior of the total linguistic structure, are true, when these observation
statements are interpreted in terms of their stimulus meanings? To this the holist
attempts no answer, save a generalised appeal to induction: these theories have
‘‘worked’’ in the past, in the sense of having for the most part yielded true
observation statements, and so we have confidence that they will continue to
work in the future.
This worry, or rather, the demand for a guarantee against it, is easily
dismissed. Of course there is a threat that a scientific theory about, say,
black holes or quarks may have incorrect observational consequences. We
have seen such threats realized many times in the history of science, and we
have known since the time of Hume that there can be no guarantee against
them. And of course there is a threat that a mathematical theory about, say,
l-adic cohomology or o-complete ultrafilters may have incorrect and even
inconsistent computational consequences. We have seen such threats real-
ized a few times in the history of mathematics (in connection with
infinitesimal calculus and naive set theory), and we have known since the
work of Gödel that there can be no guarantee against them. If and when
such threats are again realized, we will, as we always have in the past on such
occasions, revise our theories. But why even then, let alone now, revise our
logic? It is a delusion to imagine that a preemptive change of logic could
provide a guarantee against such threats, unless, indeed, the new logic were
272 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
so restrictive as to make the formulation of any non-trivial theories
impossible.
In the other text, the worry seems to be that incorrect primary sentences
might be deduced from correct primary sentences by way of secondary
sentences. On a sequential formulation of logic, this is the worry that a
sequent
( ) A1, . . . , An ) B
with the Ai primary and correct and B primary and incorrect, might be
deducible by pure classical logic, if secondary sentences are allowed to
appear in the deduction. If only primary sentences are allowed to appear in the
deduction, there is nothing to worry about, since primary sentences are
decidable, and not even intuitionists doubt the trustworthiness of classical
logic as applied to decidable sentences. As Dummett says, it would be a
‘‘severe defect’’ in the classical rules of implication if by means of them ‘‘we
can construct a deductive chain leading from correct premises to an
incorrect conclusion’’ (1977, p. 364). He reminds us that even on a dualist
theory there is an external standard against which the acceptability of rules
of implication is to be judge. A rule is acceptable only if it is sound, only if it
preserves correctness in all instances where the notion of correctness is appli-
cable, that is, in all instances where the premises and conclusion are all
primary sentences. (Thus even if the ‘‘meaning’’ of the logical particles is
given by implication conditions, not just any old particles and conditions
will do. This point has been illustrated by Prior (1960). Dummett does not
claim that classical logic is, in this sense, demonstrably unsound (as is Prior’s
‘‘tonk’’ logic). What worries Dummett is that classical logic seems to be not
demonstrably sound. He desires a guarantee of soundness, or what would, as
we have seen above, be sufficient for this, a guarantee of conservativeness, a
guarantee that the addition of the secondary sentences to the language does
not permit the deduction of any sequences ( ) involving only primary
sentences that were not deducible already (1977, pp. 363–4).
Dummett seems to hold that such a guarantee could only be provided by
a semantic soundness or conservativeness proof, and that such a proof or
‘‘justification’’ will be available only if we revise the language and extend the
assignment-of-correctness-conditions or ‘‘interpretation’’ to ‘‘all statements
or formulas with which we are concerned’’ (1977, p. 220). Dummett seems
to overlook the possibility of a purely syntactic proof of soundness or
conservativeness. As Richard Grandy has pointed out in a perceptive review
(Grandy 1982), just such a guarantee as Dummett seems to desire is
provided by the famous Cut-elimination Theorem of Gentzen, according
Dummett’s case for intuitionism 273
to which any sequent ( ) that has a deduction at all has a deduction in
which no symbols occur that do not occur in ( ) already. Moreover, though
Gentzen’s theorem is about classical logic, Gentzen’s proof is given in
intuitionistic metamathematics. Thus the threat that worries Dummett
seems elusive, to say the least.
In any case, the guarantee he desires would be intangible, on his own
admission. For it is precisely the theme of Dummett (1973b) that no
‘‘justification of deduction’’ or soundness of proof can be ‘‘suasive,’’ that
is, can persuade anyone sincerely in doubt as to the soundness of the logic.
For any such proof, being a proof, would itself use logic.
In opposition to Kreisel, Dummett is concerned to argue for intuition-
ism not as one legitimate form of mathematics among others, but as the sole
legitimate form (1977, p. 360). Dummett is concerned to argue for a
revision amounting not to a reform, but to a revolution, in mathematics.
Any revolution involves costs that the benefit of an intangible guarantee
against an elusive threat of unsoundness seems insufficient to outweigh. It
seems that its desirability as a means toward the end of guaranteeing
soundness is not a consideration sufficient to motivate the requirement
of representationality.
Dummett might, of course, rest his case against formalism on the
desirability of representationality as an end in itself. That he indeed
values representationality highly for its own sake is suggested by his apply-
ing the uncalled-for emotive term ‘‘unintelligible’’ to sentences that he
knows perfectly well how to use, but that happen to lack meaning-in-the-
narrow-sense-of-conditions-for-correctness-as-a-representation-of-reality.
Dummett’s value judgment might, however, be questioned by many
mathematicians.
It hardly needs saying that the requirement of representationality will be
rejected by the many pure mathematicians who value mathematics as an
art. From their point of view, there is no sole legitimate form of mathe-
matics. A mathematician may work now in intuitionistic, now in classical
mathematics, just as a painter may work now in a representational, now in
an abstract style. Personal taste will dictate how much time is devoted to
each, though it may be said that the overwhelming majority of mathema-
ticians find more beauty in the classical than in the intuitionistic style.
What does perhaps need saying is that the requirement of representa-
tionality may also be questioned by the many applied mathematicians who
value mathematics for its contribution, through science, to the theoretical
prediction and practical control of experience. From their point of view, it
is essential that language should contain some sentences to serve as records
274 Mathematics, Models, and Modality
or predictions of experience, as representations of empirical reality. But
beyond this it seems wisest to accept the advice of Carnap (1950) and be
‘‘tolerant in permitting linguistic forms.’’ It is questionable whether the
scope, accuracy, and efficiency of applications to the empirical world
would be enhanced by imposing the restriction that all sentences must
play a representational rather than a merely instrumental role in language.
Many physicists, mathematicians, logicians, and philosophers have sug-
gested precisely the contrary: that intuitionistic restrictions on mathe-
matics would be detrimental to applications. Such views as the following
are often voiced (Manin 1977, pp. 172–3):
[C]onstructivism is in no sense ‘‘another mathematics’’. It is, rather, a sophisti-
cated subsystem of classical mathematics, which rejects the extremes in classical
mathematics, and carefully nourishes its effective computational apparatus.
Unfortunately, it seems that it is these ‘‘extremes’’ – bold extrapolations, abstrac-
tions which are infinite and do not lend themselves to a constructive interpretation –
which make classical mathematics effective. One should try to imagine how much
help mathematics could have provided twentieth century quantum physics if for
the past hundred years it had developed using only abstractions from ‘‘constructive
objects.’’
I do not pretend to be an expert in such matters, but there are several
studies in the literature that seem to me to indicate that such complaints are
not entirely without foundation. As one example, there is an important
series of papers by Pour-El and Richards (1979–87) establishing that much
of the machinery of functional analysis deployed in quantum physics
cannot be developed in its usual form with recursive analysis. And experi-
ence shows that what can or cannot be done recursively is a usually reliable
(though by no means infallible) guide to what can or cannot be done
intuitionistically.
As another example, there is a paper of Douglas Bridges (1981), examin-
ing quantum physics from an intuitionistic viewpoint. Bridges is, to be
sure, a follower of Bishop’s intuitionism-without-choice-sequences rather
than of Brouwer’s intuitionism-with-choice-sequences, but Bishop’s school
has thus far been able to go further than Brouwer’s school in reconstructing
applicable portions of functional analysis. Bridges is obliged to concede
that ‘‘a constructive examination of the mathematical foundations of
quantum physics does reveal substantial problems.’’ It is also worth men-
tioning that even if the indications cited are misleading and it turns out to
be possible in principle to get by with intuitionistic functional analysis in
applications to quantum physics, getting by in this way is very likely to be
infeasible in practice.
Dummett’s case for intuitionism 275
Table 14.1
Philosophies of mathematics
PLATONISM FORMALISM
(Hilbert)
Associated theories of meaning
VERISM HOLISM
(Quine)
Character of objection to theory of meaning
RADICAL DESCRIPTIVE PRESCRIPTIVE
We do not and could not speak a language We ought not to speak a language of the sort
of the sort described by the theory described by the theory
Principle on which the objection is based
BEHAVIORISM REPRESENTATIONALISM
There can be nothing more to knowing the Every sentence ought to serve as a
meaning of a sentence than being able representation of extra-linguistic reality,
to use it not a mere intra-linguistic instrument
for deducing other sentences
Argument for principle
If there were anything more to such Representationality is desirable
knowledge, the extra ingredient could (a) as a means towards guaranteeing
be neither acquired nor manifested. soundness
(b) as an end in itself
Comment
The acquisition and manifestation (a) Soundness can be guaranteed without
arguments involve fallacies and circularities representationality
(b) Representationality may conflict with
the desirable end of applicability
4 SUMMARY
277
278 Annotated bibliography
284
References 285
Birkhoff, Garrett (1937) ‘‘Rings of sets,’’ Duke Mathematical Journal vol. 3,
pp. 443–54.
Bochenski, I., Church, A., and Goodman, N. (1956) The Problem of Universals:
A Symposium (Notre Dame, IN: Notre Dame University Press).
Boolos, George (1984) ‘‘To be is to be the value of a variable (or to be some values
of some variables),’’ Journal of Philosophy vol. 81, pp. 430–39, reprinted in
(Boolos 1997), pp. 54–72.
(1985) ‘‘Nominalist Platonism,’’ Philosophical Review vol. 94, pp. 327–44,
reprinted in Boolos (1997a), pp. 73–87.
(1987) ‘‘The consistency of Frege’s Foundations of Arithmetic,’’ in Thomson
(1987), pp. 3–20; reprinted in Demopoulous (1995), pp. 211–33, and in Boolos
(1997a), pp. 182–201.
(1993) The Logic of Provability (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).
(1997a) Logic, Logic, and Logic (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press).
(1997b) ‘‘Must we believe in set theory?’’ in Boolos (1997a), pp. 120–32.
Borges, Jorge Luis (1962) ‘‘Tlön, Uqbar, Orbis Tertius,’’ translated from the
Spanish by Alastair Reid, in A. Kerrison (ed.) Ficciones (New York: Grove
Press).
Bridges, Douglas (1981) ‘‘Towards a constructive foundation for quantum
mechanics,’’ in Richman (1981), pp. 260–73.
Brouwer, L. E. J. (1975) Collected Works, vol. I: Philosophy and Foundations of
Mathematics (Amsterdam: North Holland).
(1976) Collected Works, vol. II: Geometry, Analysis, Topology and Mechanics
(Amsterdam: North Holland).
Bull, R. A. and Segerberg, Krister (1984) ‘‘Basic modal logic,’’ in Gabbay and
Guenthner (1984), pp. 1–88.
Burgess, John P. (1969) ‘‘Probability logic,’’ Journal of Symbolic Logic vol. 34,
pp. 264–74.
(1977a) ‘‘Forcing’’ in Barwise (1977), pp. 403–52.
(1977b) ‘‘Descriptive set theory and infinitary languages,’’ in Proceedings of the
1977 Belgrade Symposium on Set Theory and Foundations of Mathematics,
Mathematical Institute, Belgrade, pp. 9–30.
(1978a) ‘‘Consistency proofs in model theory: a contribution to Jensenlehre,’’
Annals of Mathematical Logic vol. 14, pp. 1–12.
(1978b) ‘‘Equivalence relations generated by families of Borel sets,’’ American
Mathematical Society Proceedings vol. 69, pp. 323–6.
(1979a) ‘‘A reflection phenomenon in descriptive set theory,’’ Fundamenta
Mathematicae vol. 104, pp. 127–39. P1
(1979b) ‘‘Effective enumeration of classes in a 1 equivalence relation,’’
Indiana University Mathematical Journal vol. 28, pp. 353–64.
(1979c) ‘‘A selection theorem for group actions,’’ Pacific Journal of Mathematics
vol. 80, pp. 333–6.
(1979d) ‘‘The unreal future,’’ Theoria vol. 44, pp. 157–79.
(1980a) ‘‘A measurable selection theorem,’’ Fundamenta Mathematicae vol. 100,
pp. 91–100.
286 References
(1980b) ‘‘Sélections mesurables pour relations d’équivalence à classes Gd,’’
Bulletin des Sciences Mathématiques vol. 104, pp. 435–40.
(1980c) ‘‘Decidability and branching time,’’ in K. Segerberg (ed.) Trends in
Modal Logic, Studia Logica vol. 39, pp. 203–18.
(1981a) ‘‘The completeness of intuitionistic propositional calculus for its
intended interpretation,’’ Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic vol. 22,
pp. 17–28.
(1981b) ‘‘Quick completeness proofs for some logics of conditionals,’’ Notre
Dame Journal of Formal Logic vol. 22, pp. 76–84.
(1981c) ‘‘Relevance: a fallacy?,’’ Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic vol. 22,
pp. 97–104.
(1981d) ‘‘Careful choices: a last word on Borel selectors,’’ Notre Dame Journal of
Formal Logic vol. 22, pp. 219–26.
(1982a) ‘‘What are R-sets?’’ in Metakides (1982), pp. 307–24.
(1982b) ‘‘Axioms for tense logic, I. Since and until,’’ Notre Dame Journal of
Formal Logic vol. 23, pp. 367–74.
(1983a) ‘‘Classical hierarchies from a modern standpoint, I. C-sets,’’ Fundamenta
Mathematicae vol. 115, pp. 81–96.
(1983b) ‘‘Classical hierarchies from a modern standpoint, II. R-sets,’’ Fundamenta
Mathematicae vol. 115, pp. 97–105.
(1983c) ‘‘Common sense and ‘relevance,’’’ Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic
vol. 24, pp. 41–53.
(1983d) ‘‘Why I am not a nominalist,’’ Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic
vol. 24, pp. 93–105.
(1984a) ‘‘Basic tense logic,’’ in Gabbay and Guenthner (1984), pp. 89–134.
(1984b) ‘‘Read on relevance: a rejoinder,’’ Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic
vol. 25, pp. 217–23.
(1984c) ‘‘Dummett’s case for intuitionism,’’ History and Philosophy of Logic
vol. 5, pp. 177–94.
(1985) ‘‘From preference to utility: a problem of descriptive set theory,’’ Notre
Dame Journal of Formal Logic vol. 26, pp. 106–14.
(1986) ‘‘The truth is never simple,’’ Journal of Symbolic Logic vol. 51, pp. 663–81.
(1988) ‘‘Addendum to ‘The truth is never simple,’’’ Journal of Symbolic Logic
vol. 53, pp. 390–2.
(1989) ‘‘Epistemology and nominalism,’’ in Irvine (1989), pp. 1–15.
(1990) ‘‘Sets and point-sets,’’ in Fine and Lepin (1990), pp. 456–63.
(1992) ‘‘Proofs about proofs: a defense of classical logic, I,’’ in Detlefsen (1992),
pp. 79–82.
(1993) ‘‘How foundational work in mathematics can be relevant to philosophy
of science,’’ in Hull et al. (1993), pp. 433–41.
(1995) ‘‘Frege and arbitrary functions.’’ in Demopoulos (1995), pp. 89–107.
(1996) ‘‘Marcus, Kripke, and names,’’ Philosophical Studies vol. 84, pp. 1–47,
reprinted in Humphreys and Fetzer (1998), pp. 89–124.
(1998a) ‘‘How not to write history of philosophy,’’ in Humphreys and Fetzer
(1998), pp. 125–36.
References 287
(1998b) ‘‘Occam’s razor and scientific method,’’ in Schirn (1998), pp. 195–214.
(1998c) ‘‘Quinus ab omni naevo vindicatus,’’ in A. A. Kazmi (ed.) Meaning and
Reference: Canadian Journal of Philosophy Supplement vol. 23, pp. 25–65.
(1999) ‘‘Which modal logic is the right one?’’ Notre Dame Journal of Formal
Logic vol. 40, pp. 81–93.
(2001) Review of Balaguer (1998), Philosophical Review, vol. 101, pp. 79–82.
(2002a) ‘‘Nominalist paraphrase and ontological commitment,’’ in Anderson
and Zelëny (2002), pp. 429–44.
(2002b) ‘‘Is there a problem about deflationary theories of truth?’’ in Horsten
and Halbach (2002), pp. 37–56.
(2003a) ‘‘Numbers and ideas,’’ Richmond Journal of Philosophy vol. 1, pp. 12–17.
(2003b) ‘‘A remark on Henkin sentences and their contraries,’’ Notre Dame
Journal of Formal Logic vol. 44, pp. 185–8.
(2004a) ‘‘Quine, analyticity, and philosophy of mathematics,’’ Philosophical
Quarterly vol. 54, pp. 38–55.
(2004b) ‘‘Mathematics and Bleak House,’’ Philosophia Mathematica vol. 12,
pp. 18–36.
(2004c) ‘‘E pluribus unum: plural logic and set theory,’’ Philosophia Mathematica
vol. 12, pp. 193–221.
(2004d) review of Azzouni (2004) Bulletin of Symbolic Logic vol. 10, pp. 573–7.
(2005a) ‘‘No requirement of relevance,’’ in Shapiro (2005), pp. 727–50.
(2005b) Fixing Frege (Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press).
(2005c) ‘‘Translating names,’’ Analysis vol. 65, pp. 196–204.
(2005d) ‘‘Being explained away,’’ Harvard Review of Philosophy vol. 13,
pp. 41–56.
(2005e) ‘‘On anti-anti-realism,’’ Facta Philosophica vol. 7, pp. 121–44.
(forthcoming) ‘‘Protocol sentences for lite logicism,’’ in Lindström
(forthcoming).
Burgess, John P. and Gurevich, Yuri (1985) ‘‘The decision problem for linear
temporal logic,’’ Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic vol. 26, pp. 115–28.
Burgess, John P. and Hazen, A. P. (1998) ‘‘Arithmetic and predicative logic,’’ Notre
Dame Journal of Formal Logic vol. 39, pp. 1–17.
Burgess, John P. and Rosen, Gideon (1997) A Subject With No Object: Strategies for
Nominalistic Interpretation of Mathematics (Oxford: Oxford University
Press).
Cantor, Georg (1885) review of Frege (1884), Deutsche Literaturzeitung, vol. 6,
pp. 728–9.
Carnap, Rudolf (1946) ‘‘Modalities and quantification,’’ Journal of Symbolic Logic
vol. 11, pp. 33–64.
(1947) Meaning and Necessity: A Study in Semantics and Modal Logic (Chicago:
University of Chicago Press).
(1950) ‘‘Empiricism, semantics, and ontology,’’ Revue Internationale de
Philosophie vol. 4, pp. 20–40.
Chihara, Charles (1973) Ontology and the Vicious Circle Principle (Ithaca, NY:
Cornell University Press).
288 References
(1989) ‘‘Tharp’s ‘Myth and Mathematics,’’’ Synthese vol. 81, pp. 153–65.
(1990) Constructibility and Mathematical Existence (Oxford: Oxford University
Press).
Chomsky, Noam (1959) review of Skinner (1957) Language vol. 35, pp. 26–58.
Church, Alonzo (1950) review of Fitch (1949) Journal of Symbolic Logic vol. 15,
p. 63.
Cocchiarella, Nino (1984) ‘‘Philosophical perspectives on quantification in tense
and modal logic,’’ in Gabbay and Guenthner (1984), pp. 309–53.
Cohen, R. S. and Wartofsky, M. W. (1965) (eds.) Boston Studies in the Philosophy of
Science, vol. II (New York: Humanities Press).
Copeland, B. J. (1979) ‘‘When is a semantics not a semantics: some reasons for
disliking the Routley–Meyer semantics for relevance logic,’’ Journal of
Philosophical Logic vol. 8, pp. 399–413.
Creswell, Max (1990) Entities and Indices (Dordrecht: Kluwer).
Davidson, Donald (1967) ‘‘Truth and meaning,’’ Synthese vol. 17, pp. 304–23.
Davidson, Donald and Harman, Gilbert (1972) (eds.) Semantics of Natural
Language (Dordrecht: Reidel).
Davidson, Donald and Hintikka, Jaakko (1969) (eds.) Words and Objections: Essays
on the Work of W. V. Quine (Dordrecht: Reidel).
Demopoulos, William (1995) (ed.) Frege’s Philosophy of Mathematics (Cambridge,
MA: Harvard University Press).
Detlefsen, Michael (1992) (ed.) Proof, Logic and Formalization (London:
Routledge).
Diogenes Laertius (1925) Lives and Opinions of Eminent Philosophers, translated
from the Greek by R. D. Hicks, Loeb Classical Library (Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press).
Dummett, Michael (1959) ‘‘Truth,’’ in Dummett (1978), pp. 1–24.
(1973a) ‘‘The philosophical basis of intuitionistic logic,’’ in Dummett (1978),
pp. 215–47.
(1973b) ‘‘The justification of deduction,’’ in Dummett (1978), pp. 290–318.
(1973c) ‘‘The significance of Quine’s indeterminacy thesis,’’ in Dummett (1978),
pp. 375–419.
(1977) Elements of Intuitionism (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
(1978) Truth and Other Enigmas (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press).
Edgington, Dorothy (1985) ‘‘The paradox of knowability,’’ Mind vol. 94,
pp. 557–68.
Evans, Gareth and McDowell, John (1976) (eds.) Truth and Meaning: Essays in
Semantics (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
Farber, M. (1950) (ed.) Philosophic Thought in France and the United States
(Buffalo, NY: University of Buffalo Press).
Feferman, Solomon (1977) ‘‘Theories of finite type related to mathematical
practice,’’ in Barwise (1977), pp. 913–72.
Field, Hartry H. (1980) Science Without Numbers: A Defense of Nominalism
(Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press).
(1989) Realism, Mathematics and Modality (Oxford: Basil Blackwell).
References 289
Fine, A. and Lepin, J. (1990) PSA 88 [Proceedings of the 1988 Convention of the
Philosophy of Science Association], vol. II (East Lansing, MI: Philosophy of
Science Association).
Fine, Kit (2002) The Limits of Abstraction (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
Fitch, Frederic (1949) ‘‘The problem of the morning star and the evening star,’’
Philosophy of Science vol. 16, pp. 137–41.
(1950) ‘‘Attribute and class,’’ in Farber (1950), pp. 640–7.
(1963) ‘‘A logical analysis of some value concepts,’’ Journal of Symbolic Logic
vol. 28, pp. 135–42.
Føllesdal, Dagfinn (1961) ‘‘Referential opacity and modal logic,’’ Harvard
University doctoral dissertation, reprinted as Føllesdal (1966).
(1965) ‘‘Quantification into causal contexts,’’ in Cohen and Wartofsky (1965),
pp. 263–74; reprinted in Linsky (1971a), pp. 52–62.
(1966) Referential Opacity and Modal Logic, Filosofiske Problemer, vol. XXXII
(Oslo: Oslo Universitetsforlaget).
(1969) ‘‘Quine on modality,’’ in Davidson and Hintikka (1969), pp. 175–85.
(1986) ‘‘Essentialism and reference,’’ in Hahn and Schlipp (1986), pp. 97–113.
Forbes, Graeme (1995) review of Marcus (1993), Notre Dame Journal of Formal
Logic vol. 36, pp. 336–9.
Frege, Gottlob (1879) Begriffsschrift: eine der arithmetischen nachgebildete
Formelsprache des reinen Denkens (Halle: Louis Nebert).
(1884) Die Grundlagen der Arithmetik: Eine logisch-mathematische Untersuchung
über den Begriff der Zahl (Breslau: Wilhelm Koebner).
(1893/1903) Grundgesetze der Arithmetik, begriffsschriftlich abgeleitet, 2 vols.
(Jena: Pohle).
(1950) The Foundations of Arithmetic, translation of Frege (1884) from the
German by J. L. Austin (London: Blackwell).
(1967) Begriffsschrift, translation from the German of Frege (1879) by S. Bauer-
Mengelberg, in van Heijenoort (1967), pp. 1–82.
French, Peter A. and Wettstein, Howard K. (2001) (eds.) Midwest Studies in
Philosophy XXV: Figurative Language (London: Blackwell).
Gabbay, D. and Guenthner, F. (1984) (eds.) Handbook of Philosophical Logic,
vol. II: Extensions of Classical Logic (Dordrecht: Reidel).
Gabbay, D., Rahman, S., Symons, J., and van Bendegen, J. P. (2004) (eds.) Logic,
Epistemology, and the Unity of Science (Dordrecht: Kluwer).
Garson, James (1984) ‘‘Quantification in modal logic,’’ in Gabbay and Guenthner
(1984), pp. 249–308.
Goodman, Nelson (1956) ‘‘A world of individuals,’’ in Bochenski et al. (1956),
pp. 197–210; reprinted in Benacerraf and Putnam (1964).
Goodman, Nelson and Quine, W. V. O. (1947) ‘‘Steps toward a constructive
nominalism,’’ Journal of Symbolic Logic vol. 12, pp. 97–122.
Goranko, Valentin (1994) ‘‘Refutation systems in modal logic,’’ Studia Logica
vol. 53, pp. 299–324.
Grandy, Richard (1982) review of Dummett (1973a), Prawitz (1977), etc. Journal of
Symbolic Logic vol. 47, pp. 689–94.
290 References
Grice, H. P. and Strawson, P. F. (1956) ‘‘In defense of a dogma,’’ Philosophical
Review vol. 65, pp. 141–58.
Grzegorczyk, Andrzej (1967) ‘‘Some relational systems and the associated topo-
logical spaces,’’ Fundamenta Mathematicae vol. 60, pp. 223–31.
Haack, Susan (1974) Deviant Logic (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).
Hahn, L. E. and Schlipp, P. A. (1986) The Philosophy of W. V. Quine (LaSalle, IL:
Open Court).
Hájek, Petr and Pudlak, Pavel (1998) Metamathematics of First-Order Arithmetic
(Berlin: Springer).
Haldén, Søren (1963) ‘‘A pragmatic approach to modal theory,’’ Acta Philosophica
Fennica vol. 16, pp. 53–64.
Hale, Bob and Wright, Crispin (2001) The Reason’s Proper Study: Essays towards a
Neo-Fregean Philosophy of Mathematics (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
Hallett, Michael (1984) Cantorian Set Theory and Limitation of Size (Oxford:
Clarendon Press).
Harman, Gilbert (1982) ‘‘Conceptual role semantics,’’ Notre Dame Journal of
Formal Logic vol. 23, pp. 242–56.
Heck, Richard G., Jr. (1996) ‘‘On the consistency of predicative fragments of
Frege’s Grundgesetze der Arithmetik,’’ History and Philosophy of Logic vol. 17,
pp. 209–20.
Heijenoort, Jean van (1967) (ed.) From Frege to Gödel: A Sourcebook in
Mathematical Logic, 1879–1931 (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press).
Hempel, Carl G. (1950) ‘‘Problems and changes in the empiricist criterion of
meaning,’’ Revue Internationale de Philosophie vol. 4, pp. 41–63.
Hersh, Reuben (1997) What is Mathematics, Really? (Oxford: Oxford University
Press).
Hilbert, David (1925/1967) ‘‘On the infinite,’’ translated from the German by
Stefan Bauer-Mengelberg, in van Heijenoort (1967), pp. 367–92.
Hintikka, Jaakko (1963) ‘‘Modes of modality,’’ Acta Philosophica Fennica vol. 16,
pp. 65–82.
(1982) ‘‘Is alethic modal logic possible?’’ Acta Philosophica Fennica vol. 35,
pp. 89–105.
Hintikka, Jaakko and Sandu, Gabriel (1995) ‘‘The fallacies of the new theory of
reference,’’ Synthese vol. 104, pp. 245–83.
Hofweber, Thomas and Everett, Anthony (2000) (eds.) Empty Names, Fiction and
the Puzzles of Non-Existence (Chicago: CSLI).
Horsten, Leon and Halbach, Volker (2002) (eds.) Principles of Truth (Frankfurt:
Hänsel-Hohenhausen).
Hrbacek, K. and Jech, T. (1999) Introduction to Set Theory, 3rd edn (New York:
Marcel Dekker).
Hughes, G. E. and Creswell, M. J. (1968) An Introduction to Modal Logic (London:
Methuen).
Hull, D., Forbes, M., and Okruhlik, K. (1993) (eds.) PSA 92 [Proceedings of the
1992 Convention of the Philosophy of Science Association], vol. II (East
Lansing, MI: Philosophy of Science Association).
References 291
Humphreys, P. and Fetzer, J. (1998) (eds.) The New Theory of Reference, Synthese
Library vol. CCLXX (Dordrecht: Kluwer).
Irvine, Andrew (1989) (ed.) Physicalism in Mathematics (Dordrecht: Kluwer).
James, William (2000) ‘‘Pragmatism,’’ in Pragmatism and Other Writings, ed.
G. Gunn (New York: Penguin), pp. 1–132.
Jeffrey, Richard C. (1996) ‘‘Logicism 2000,’’ in Stich and Morton (2002),
pp. 1–132.
(2002) ‘‘Logicism lite,’’ Philosophy of Science vol. 69, pp. 447–51.
Kahle, Reinhard (forthcoming) (ed.) Intensionality: An Interdisciplinary Discussion
(Boston: A. K. Peters, Lecture Notes in Logic).
Katz, Jerrold (1985) (ed.) The Philosophy of Linguistics (Oxford: Oxford University
Press).
Kitcher, Philip (1978) ‘‘The plight of the platonist,’’ Noûs, vol. 12, pp. 119–36.
Klibansky, Raymond (1968) Contemporary Philosophy, 4 vols. (Florence: Editrice
Nuova Italia).
Kneale, William and Kneale, Mary (1962) The Development of Logic (Oxford:
Clarendon Press).
König, Julius (1905) ‘‘Über die Grundlagen der Mengenlehre und das
Kontinuumproblem,’’ Mathematische Annalen vol. 61, pp. 156–60.
(1967) ‘‘On the foundations of set theory and the continuum problem,’’ trans-
lation of König (1905) from the German by Stefan Bauer-Mengelberg, in van
Heijenoort (1967), pp. 145–9.
Kranz, D., Luce, R., Suppes, P., and Tversky, A. (1971) Foundations of
Measurement (New York: Academic Press).
Kreisel, Georg (1967) ‘‘Informal rigour and completeness proofs,’’ in Lakatos
(1967), pp. 138–57.
Kripke, Saul (1963) ‘‘Semantical considerations on modal logic,’’ Acta Philosophica
Fennica vol. 16, pp. 83–94.
(1972) ‘‘Naming and necessity: Lectures give to the Princeton University
Philosophy Colloquium, January, 1970,’’ in Davidson and Harman (1972),
pp. 253–355 and 763–9; reprinted with a new preface as Kripke (1980).
(1976) ‘‘Is there a problem about substitutional quantification?’’ in Evans and
McDowell (1976), pp. 325–420.
(1979) ‘‘A puzzle about belief,’’ in Margalit (1977), pp. 239–83.
(1980) Naming and Necessity (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press).
(1982) Wittgenstein on Rules and Private Language (Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press).
Lavine, Shaughan (1995) review of Marcus (1993), British Journal of the Philosophy
of Science vol. 46, pp. 267–74.
Lakatos, Imre (1967) (ed.) Proceedings of the International Colloquium in the
Philosophy of Science, London, 1965, vol. I (Amsterdam: North Holland).
Lee, O. H. (1936) Philosophical Essays for A. N. Whitehead (New York: Longmans).
Lewis, David K. (1969) Convention (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press).
(1970) ‘‘Anselm and actuality,’’ Noûs vol. 4, pp. 175–88.
(1991) Parts of Classes (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
292 References
Linsky, Leonard (1971a) (ed.) Reference and Modality (Oxford: Oxford University
Press).
(1971b) ‘‘Essentialism, reference, and modality,’’ in (Linsky (1971a), pp. 88–100.
(1977) Names and Descriptions (Chicago: University of Chicago Press).
Linström, Sten (forthcoming) (ed.) Logicism, Intuitionism, Formalism. What Has
Become of Them? (Berlin: Springer).
Maddy, Penelope (1980) ‘‘Perception and mathematical intuition,’’ Philosophical
Review vol. 89, pp. 163–96.
(1984) ‘‘Mathematical epistemology: what is the question?’’ The Monist vol. 67,
pp. 46–55.
(1990) ‘‘Mathematics and Oliver Twist,’’ Pacific Philosophical Quarterly vol. 71,
pp. 189–205.
Makinson, David (1966) ‘‘How meaningful are modal operators?’’ Australasian
Journal of Philosophy vol. 44, pp. 331–7.
Manin, Yuri (1977) A Course in Mathematical Logic, translated from the Russian
by N. Koblitz (Berlin: Springer).
Marcus, Ruth Barcan (1960) ‘‘Extensionality,’’ Mind vol. 69, pp. 55–62.
(1963a) ‘‘Modalities and intensional languages,’’ in Wartofsky (1963),
pp. 77–96.
(1963b) ‘‘Attribute and class in extended modal systems,’’ Acta Philosophical
Fennica vol. 16, pp. 123–36.
(1967) ‘‘Essentialism in modal logic,’’ Noûs vol. 1, pp. 90–6.
(1968) ‘‘Modal logic,’’ in Klibansky (1968), pp. 87–101.
(1978) Review of Linsky (1977), Philosophical Review vol. 87, pp. 497–504.
(1990) ‘‘Some revisionary proposals about belief and believing,’’ Philosophy and
Phenomenological Research vol. 50 (Supplement), pp. 133–53.
(1993) Modalities: Philosophical Essays (Oxford: Oxford University Press).
Marcus, R. B., Quine, W. V., Kripke, S. A. et al. (1963) Discussion of Marcus
(1963a) in Wartofsky (1963), pp. 105–16.
Margalit, Avishai (1977) Meaning and Use (Dordrecht: Reidel).
Martinich, A. P. (1979) The Philosophy of Language (Oxford: Oxford University
Press).
Matiyasevich, Yuri (1993) Hilbert’s Tenth Problem (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press).
McKinsey, J. C. C. (1941) ‘‘A solution to the decision problem for the Lewis
systems S2 and S4, with an application to topology,’’ Journal of Symbolic
Logic vol. 6, pp. 117–34.
(1945) ‘‘On the syntactical construction of modal logic,’’ Journal of Symbolic
Logic vol. 10, pp. 83–96.
Metakides, George (1982) (ed.) Proceedings of the First Patras Logic Symposion
(Amsterdam: North Holland).
Montagna, Franco and Mancini, Antonella (1994) ‘‘A minimal predicative set
theory,’’ Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic vol. 35, pp. 186–203.
Müller, Gert-Heinz (1976) Sets and Classes (Amsterdam: North-Holland).
Nabokov, Vladimir (1980) Lectures on Literature, ed. F. Bowers (New York:
Harcourt Brace Jovanovich).
References 293
Newman, J. R. (1956) (ed.) The World of Mathematics, 4 vols. (New York: Simon
and Schuster).
Parsons, Charles (1980) ‘‘Mathematical intuition,’’ Proceedings of the Aristotelian
Society, vol. 80, pp. 145–68.
Parsons, Terence (1969) ‘‘Essentialism and quantified modal logic,’’ Philosophical
Review vol. 78, pp. 35–52; reprinted in Linsky (1971a), pp. 73–87.
(1987) ‘‘On the consistency of the first-order portion of Frege’s logical system,’’
Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic vol. 28, pp. 61–8; reprinted in
Demopoulos (1995), pp. 422–31.
Pollard, Stephen (1996) ‘‘Sets, wholes, and limited pluralities,’’ Philosophia
Mathematica, vol. 4, pp. 42–58.
Pour-El, M. and Richards, I. (1979) ‘‘A computable ordinary differential equation
which possesses a computable solution,’’ Annals of Mathematical Logic vol. 17,
pp. 61–90.
(1981) ‘‘A wave equation with computable initial data such that its unique
solution is not computable,’’ Advances in Mathematics vol. 39, pp. 215–39.
(1983) ‘‘Noncomputability in analysis and physics: a complete determination of
the class of noncomputable linear operators,’’ Advances in Mathematics
vol. 48, pp. 44–74.
(1987) ‘‘The eigenvalues of an effectively determined self-adjoint operator are
computable, but the sequence of eigenvalues is not,’’ Advances in Mathematics
vol. 63, pp. 1–41.
Prawitz, Dag (1977) ‘‘Meaning and proofs: on the conflict between classical and
intuitionistic logic,’’ Theoria vol. 43, pp. 2–40.
Prior, Arthur N. (1960) ‘‘The runabout inference-ticket,’’ Analysis vol. 21, pp. 38–9.
(1963) ‘‘Is the concept of referential opacity really necessary?’’ Acta Philosophical
Fennica vol. 16, pp. 189–99.
(1967a) ‘‘Logic, modal,’’ in Weiss (1967), vol. V, pp. 5–12.
(1967b) Past, Present, and Future (Oxford: Clarendon Press).
Putnam, Hilary (1971) Philosophy of Logic (New York: Harper).
(1975) ‘‘Truth and necessity in mathematics,’’ in Mathematics, Matter, and
Method (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press), pp. 1–11.
Quine, W. V. O. (1936) ‘‘Truth by convention,’’ in Lee (1936), pp. 90–124.
(1946) Review of Barcan (1946), Journal of Symbolic Logic vol. 11, pp. 96–7.
(1947a) ‘‘The problem of interpreting modal logic,’’ Journal of Symbolic Logic
vol. 12, pp. 43–8.
(1947b) Review of Barcan (1947), Journal of Symbolic Logic vol. 12, pp. 95–6.
(1951a) ‘‘Carnap’s views on ontology,’’ Philosophical Studies vol. 2, pp. 65–72.
(1951b) ‘‘Two dogmas of empiricism,’’ Philosophical Review vol. 60, pp. 20–43.
(1953) From a Logical Point of View (Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Press).
(1960) Word and Object (New York: John Wiley and Sons).
(1961) From a Logical Point of View, 2nd edn (Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press).
(1963) Comments on Marcus (1963a) in Wartofsky (1963), pp. 97–104.
294 References
(1969) ‘‘Reply to Sellars,’’ in Davidson and Hintikka (1969), p. 338.
(1970) Philosophy of Logic (Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice-Hall).
(1980) From a Logical Point of View, 3rd edn (Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University Press).
(1981) ‘‘Response to David Armstrong,’’ in Theories and Things (Cambridge:
Harvard University Press), pp. 182–4.
Ramsey, Frank Plumpton (1925) ‘‘The foundations of mathematics,’’ Proceedings of
the London Mathematical Society vol. 25, pp. 338–84.
Rayo, Augustin and Uzquiano, Gabriel (1999) ‘‘Towards a theory of second-order
consequence,’’ Notre Dame Journal of Formal Logic vol. 40, pp. 315–25.
Rescher, Nicholas (1968) (ed.) Studies in Logical Theory (Oxford: Basil Blackwell).
Richman, F. (1981) (ed.) Constructive Mathematics [Springer Lecture Notes in
Mathematics 873] (Berlin: Springer).
(1975) Logic Colloquium ’73 (Amsterdam: North Holland).
Rosen, Gideon and Burgess, John P. (2005) ‘‘Nominalism reconsidered,’’ in
Shapiro (2005), pp. 460–82.
Rükert, Helge (2004) ‘‘A solution to Fitch’s paradox of knowability,’’ in Gabbay
et al. (2004), pp. 351–80.
Russell, Bertrand (1902/1967) letter to Frege, translated from the German by
Beverly Woodward, in van Heijenoort (1967), pp. 124–5.
(1985) The Philosophy of Logical Atomism, ed. David Pears (LaSalle, IL: Open
Court).
Salerno, J. (2008) New Essays on the Knowability Paradox (Oxford: Oxford
University Press).
Salmon, Nathan (1986) Frege’s Puzzle (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press).
Schindler, Ralf-Dieter (1994) ‘‘A dilemma in the philosophy of set theory’’, Notre
Dame Journal of Formal Logic vol. 35, pp. 458–63.
Schirn, Matthias (1998) (ed.) Philosophy of Mathematics Today (Oxford: Oxford
University Press).
Scroggs, Schiller Joe (1951) ‘‘Extensions of the Lewis system S5,’’ Journal of
Symbolic Logic vol. 16, pp. 112–20.
Searle, John R. (1967) ‘‘Proper names and descriptions,’’ in Weiss (1967) vol. VI,
pp. 487–91.
(1979) ‘‘Metaphor,’’ in Martinich (1979), pp. 92–123.
Shahan, R. W. and Swoyer, C. (1979) (eds.) Essays on the Philosophy of W. V. Quine
(Norman: University of Oklahoma Press).
Shapiro, Stewart (1985) (ed.) Intensional Mathematics (Amsterdam: North
Holland).
(1987) ‘‘Principles of reflection and second-order logic,’’ Journal of Philosophical
Logic vol. 16, pp. 309–33.
(1997) Philosophy of Mathematics: Structure, Ontology, Modality (Oxford:
Oxford University Press).
(2005) (ed.) The Oxford Handbook of Philosophy of Mathematics and Logic
(Oxford: Oxford University Press).
Skinner, B. F. (1957) Verbal Behavior (New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts).
References 295
Skura, Tomasz (1995) ‘‘A Lukasiewicz-style refutation system for the modal logic
S4,’’ Journal of Philosophical Logic vol. 24, pp. 573–82.
Slupecki, Jerzy and Bryll, Grzegorz (1973) ‘‘Proof of the L-decidability of Lewis
system S5,’’ Studia Logica vol. 24, pp. 99–105.
Smullyan, Arthur (1947) review of Quine (1947a), Journal of Symbolic Logic vol. 12,
pp. 139–41.
(1948) ‘‘Modality and description,’’ Journal of Symbolic Logic vol. 13, pp. 31–7.
Soames, Scott (1984) ‘‘What is a theory of truth?’’ Journal of Philosophy vol. 84,
pp. 411–29.
(1985) ‘‘Semantics and psychology,’’ in Katz (1985), pp. 204–26.
Stalnaker, Robert (1968) ‘‘A theory of conditionals,’’ in Rescher (1968), pp. 98–112.
Stanley, Jason (2001) ‘‘Hermeneutic fictionalism,’’ in French and Wettstein
(2001), pp. 36–71.
Stich, S. and Morton, A. (2002) (eds.) Benacerraf and his Critics (London:
Blackwell).
Stigt, W. P. van (1979) ‘‘The rejected parts of Brouwer’s dissertation on the
foundations of mathematics,’’ Historia Mathematica vol. 6, pp. 385–404.
Tarski, Alfred (1931) ‘‘Sur les ensembles définissables de nombres réels,’’
Fundamenta Mathematicae vol. 17, pp. 210–39.
(1935) ‘‘Der Wahrheitsbegriff in den formalisierten Sprachen,’’ Studia
Philosophica vol. 1, pp. 261–405.
(1936) ‘‘Über den Begriff der logischen Folgerung,’’ in Actes du Congrès
International de Philosophie Scientifique, vol. VII (Paris: Hermann), pp. 1–11.
(1944) ‘‘The semantic conception of truth,’’ Philosophy and Phenomenological
Research vol. 4, pp. 341–75.
(1983a) Logic, Semantics, Metamathematics, 2nd edn, ed. J. Corcoran
(Indianapolis: Hackett).
(1983b) ‘‘On definable sets of real numbers,’’ translation of Tarski (1931) from
the French by J. H. Woodger, in Tarski (1983a), pp. 110–42.
(1983c) ‘‘The concept of truth in formalized languages,’’ translation of Tarski
(1935) from the German by J. H. Woodger, in Tarski (1983a), pp. 152–278.
(1983d) ‘‘On the concept of logical consequence,’’ translation of Tarski (1936)
from the German by J. H. Woodger, in Tarski (1983a), pp. 409–20.
Tarski, Alfred and Vaught, Robert (1956) ‘‘Arithmetical extensions of relational
systems,’’ Compositio Mathematica vol. 13, pp. 81–102.
Tarski, A., Mostowski, A., and Robinson, R. M. (1953) Undecidable Theories
(Amsterdam: North Holland).
Thomas, Robert (2000) ‘‘Mathematics and fiction I: identification,’’ Logique et
Analyse vol. 43, pp. 301–40.
(2002) ‘‘Mathematics and fiction II: analogy,’’ Logique et Analyse vol. 45,
pp. 185–228.
Thomason, R. H. (1984) ‘‘Combination of tense and modality,’’ in Gabbay and
Guenthner (1984), pp. 135–65.
Thomason, S. K. (1973) ‘‘A new representation of S5,’’ Notre Dame Journal of
Formal Logic vol. 14, pp. 281–7.
296 References
Thomson, J. J. (1987) On Being and Saying: Essays for Richard Cartwright
(Cambridge, MA: MIT Press).
Tomberlin, James E. (1994) (ed.) Logic and Language [Philosophical Perspectives,
vol. VIII] (Atascadero, CA: Ridgeview Publishing).
Uzquiano, Gabriel (2003) ‘‘Plural quantification and classes,’’ Philosophia
Mathematica, vol. 11, pp. 67–81.
Wartofsky, Max (1963) (ed.) Proceedings of the Boston Colloquium for the Philosophy
of Science 1961/1962 (Dordrecht: Reidel).
Wehmeier, Kai (forthcoming) ‘‘Modality, mood, and descriptions,’’ to appear in
Kahle (forthcoming).
Weiss, Paul (1967) (ed.) Encyclopedia of Philosophy, 6 vols. (New York: Macmillan).
Weyl, Hermann (1944) ‘‘David Hilbert and his Mathematical Work,’’ Bulletin of
the American Mathematical Society vol. 50, pp. 612–54.
White, Leslie A. (1947) ‘‘The locus of mathematical reality: an anthropological
footnote,’’ Philosophy of Science vol. 14, pp. 289–303, reprinted in Newman
(1956), vol. IV.
Whorf, Benjamin Lee (1956) ‘‘Science and linguistics,’’ in Language, Thought, and
Reality: Selected Writings, ed. J. B. Carroll (Cambridge, MA: MIT Press),
pp. 207–19.
Williamson, Timothy (1987) ‘‘On the paradox of knowability,’’ Mind vol. 96,
pp. 256–61.
Woods, John (2002) Paradox and Paraconsistency: Conflict Resolution in the
Abstract Sciences (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).
Wright, Crispin (1980) Wittgenstein on the Foundations of Mathematics
(Cambridge: Cambridge University Press).
(1983) Frege’s Conception of Numbers as Objects (Aberdeen: Scots Philosophical
Monographs).
Wright, G. H. von (1951) An Essay in Modal Logic (Amsterdam: North Holland).
Yablo, Steven (2000) ‘‘A paradox of existence,’’ in Hofweber and Everett (2000),
pp. 275–311.
Index
Absolute, the, see monism Boolos–Bernays set theory (BB), 119, 123, 124,
abstractness versus concreteness, 24, 31 126–7, 134
Ackermann, Diana (Felicia Nimue), 213 Borges, Jorge Luis, 7, 98
acquisition argument, 260 Bouchard, Pierre, xiii
Addison, John W., 151 Bridges, Douglas, 274
adjunction, axiom of, 138 Brouwer, L. E. J., 3, 11, 18, 55–6, 59, 81, 82, 258,
aliases, problem of, 195 274–5
alpha symbol (a), 128 Bryll, Grzegorz, 181
Alston, William, 4, 85, 87 Burgess, Alexi, 12, 167
analyticity, 6, 77–9, 80, 82, 84, 153, 206 Buss, Sam, 145
Anderson, A. R., 16, 17, 246–8, 250, 252–5 Byzantium and Istanbul, 238, 240
anonymity, problem of, 194
Anscombe, Elizabeth, 229 Cantor, Georg, 49, 104–5, 114, 115, 116, 117, 127,
anti-realism, see Dummett, Michael 129, 130, 143
Archytas of Tarentum, 52 Carnap, Rudolf, 77, 93–5, 220, 274
Aristotle, 88, 209, 211 modal logic and, 170, 172, 177, 181, 215, 216
attitudes, de dicto and de re, 193–6 ontology and, 5–6, 59–64, 68–9, 85, 87
Azzouni, Jodi, 91–2 Quine and, 69, 71–2, 74–6, 78
Castan~eda, Carlos, 64, 91
Bacon, John, 100 Cauchy, Augustin, 233
Balaguer, Mark, 63 Chihara, Charles, 1, 3, 7, 12, 32, 33–4, 35, 36, 38–9,
Barcan, Ruth C., see Marcus, Ruth Barcan 46, 52, 53, 89, 167, 260
Barcan formula, 216 Chinese, 241–2, 261
Barker, John, 12, 167 choice, axiom of (AC), 116, 151
Barwise, Jon, 278 Chomsky, Noam, 19, 71, 79, 260, 270, 271
behaviorism, 19, 79–80, 259–65, 270, 272 chronometry, 187, 192–3, 196–202
Bellarmine, Robert Cardinal, 59, 88, 256 Church, Alonzo, 228
Belnap, Nuel D., Jr., 16, 17, 246–8, 250, 252–5, 280 Church’s theorem, 12
Benacerraf, Paul, 85, 86, 88, 264 Church’s thesis, 178
Benthem, Johann van, 100 Chrysippus, 246, 253
Berkeley, George, 98 Cicero and Tully, 238, 240
Bernays, Paul, xii, 8, 9, 117, 119, 120, 124, 125, 128, classes, 9, 112–13
129, 134 Cocchiarella, Nino, 216
Berry, G. G., 149–51 Cohen, Paul, 151, 277
Bigfoot, 25–7 compositionality, 237
Birkhoff, Garrett, 180 comprehension, axiom of, 109, 135
Bishop, Errett, 274 concept (Begriff ), 114, 135
Bleak House, 50, 60, 68, 69, 73, 79, 83 conceptualism, 3, 24–30
Boole, George, 127 conditional logic, 283
Boolos, George, xii, 8–9, 53, 59, 68, 106, 112, 129, conservativeness, 45, 270, 272, 280
130, 132, 134, 137, 172, 174 constructibility, 124
297
298 Index
continuum hypothesis (CH), 277 Fitch, Frederic, 14, 185–6, 187, 196, 197, 219, 223,
Convention T, 152–3, 163, 164, 167 224, 228
Copeland, B. J., 161 Føllesdal, Dagfinn, 227, 228
Craig’s lemma, 178 formalism, 11, 135, 140, 268, 270, 273
Creswell, Max, 230 Forbes, Graeme, 217
Curley, E. M., 17 foundation, axiom of, 123, 124, 125
cut-elimination, 19, 272 foundations of mathematics, 7, 66–8
Frankel, Abraham, 116
Davidson, Donald and Davidsonianism, 162, Frege, Gottlob, 18, 81
165–6, 260, 266, 270, 271 anti-psychologism and, 3, 25, 48
Davis, Martin, 142 logicism and, 10, 78, 135–6, 137, 143, 145
definability, 149–51 names and, 153, 210, 220–1, 226, 229,
definitions, status of in mathematics, 152–3 231, 244
demonstrability, 13, 169–71, 172, 173, 177, 178–84 Frege’s theorem, 66–8, 114, 137
demonstratives and indexicals, 196 French, 239–41, 242, 244
Descartes, René, 2, 165, 166 Friedman, Harvey, xii, 17, 125, 140, 278
Devitt, Michael, 234
dialethism, 186 Galilei, Galileo, 1, 55, 59, 68, 69, 93, 95
disjunction, Ganea, Mihai, 140
intensional versus extensional, 247 Geach, Peter, 107, 229, 230, 234
meaning of, 258, 269 Gell-Mann, Murray, 55
Dickens, Charles, see Bleak House generalized-quantifier logic, 164, 277, 281
discovery, principle of, 185–96, 201 general relativity, 35, 58, 73
Dixon, Thomas, 69 Gentzen, Gerhard, 271, 272
Diogenes, 28 God, 2, 6, 47–8, 63–4, 69–70, 71–2, 92–3, 94,
dualism, 267–9, 270, 272 186, 189
Dummett, Michael, 3, 12, 18–20, 63, 82, 85, 87, Gödel, Kurt, 85, 89, 124–5, 151, 277
256, 260, 264, 266, 268 completeness theorem, 144, 155, 182
incompleteness theorems, 58, 63, 140, 142,
Edgington, Dorothy, 198 172, 270, 271
Égré, Paul, xiii Goodman, Nelson, 31–2, 33, 37, 85, 90
Einstein, Albert, 55 Goranko, Valentin, 183
epistemology, 5, 39–41, 71, 88–9 Grandy, Richard, 270, 272
naturalized versus alienated, see naturalism Greece and Hellas, 241
epsilon symbol (e), 128 Grelling, Kurt, 150
equivalence, 278–9 Grice, H. P., 78, 79, 248
essentialism, 209, 217 Grzegorczyk, Andrzej, 171
Euclid, 104 Gupta, Anil, 280
extension (Umfang), 114–15, 135, 136 Gurevich, Yuri, 282
extensionality, axiom of, 110–11, 121, 123, 124,
135, 137 Haack, Susan, 263
Hadamard, Jacques, 151
fables, 50 Haldèn, Søren, 171, 173
Fara, Michael, xii Hale, Bob, 61
Feferman, Solomon, xii, 42, 43, 179 haplism, 96, 97
Fermat–(Wiles) theorem, 139 Harman, Gilbert, xiii, 254, 266
Fetzer, James, 215 Hazen, A. P., 139, 140, 230
Feynman, Richard, 96 Heck, Richard, 10, 11, 135, 140
fictionalism, 4, 5–6, 47, 48–51, 52–7, 58, 59, 72–4, Heidegger, Martin, 95
76, 83, 91 Heijenoort, Jean van, 104
Field, Hartry, 1, 3, 7, 32, 33–4, 35, 36, 38–9, 40, 46, Hellman, Geoffrey, 4, 7, 46, 89
47, 61, 72, 89, 229 heredity, 110, 111, 113, 123
figuralism, 91 hermeneuticists, 3–7, 16, 34, 51–7, 58,
Fine, Kit, 17, 137, 161 90–2
finitism, 140, 179 Hersh, Ruben, xi
Index 299
Herzberger, Hans, 280 language of thought, 165
Hesperus and Phosphorus, 15, 221, 226, 232, Laplace, Pierre-Simon Marquis de, 233
238, 240 Lavine, Shaughn, xi
Heyting, Arend, 3, 81, 283 Lesniewski, Stanislaw, 217
Hilbert, David, 11, 55–6, 82, 127, 140–3, 144, Levy, Azriel, 117
268–9 Lewis, C. I., 13, 170, 172, 230
Hintikka, Jaakko, 174–5, 203, 235, 281 Lewis, David, xiii, 59, 63, 230, 249,
Hodges, Wilfrid, 154, 155 266, 283
holism, 11, 268, 270 limitation of size, 114, 116, 117, 129
Horsten, Leon, 214 Lindemann, Ferdinand von, 52
Hume, David, 19, 58, 72, 93, 98, 135, 136 Linsky, Leonard, 218, 231
Hume’s principle (HP), 67–8, 76, 78, 83, 136, 137, literalness, 53, 54, 56–7
270, 271 Locke, John, 220
Humphreys, Paul, 215 logic, descriptive vs prescriptive, 16, 18
logicism, 10–11, 135–40, 142, 143, 145
idealism, 3, 24–30, 98 London, see Puzzling Pierre
ideology, 86, 101, 102 Löwenheim–Skolem theorem, 155
implication versus inference, 254 Lucas, J. R., 179
impredicativity, see predicativity and lumpers and splitters, 112
impredicativity
incompleteness theorems, see Gödel, Kurt Maddy, Penelope, xi, xii, 40, 47, 57
independence-friendly (IF) logic, 281 Makinson, David, 177
indiscernibility of identicals, 107, 109, 123 Malcolm, Norman, 88, 260
indispensability, 33–4, 101 Mancini, Antonella, 138
infinitary logic, 278, 281 manifestation argument, 260
infinity, axiom of, 116, 121 Manin, Yuri, 38, 274
instrumentalism, 4, 11, 41, 47 Maoism, 275
introduction and elimination, 19–20 Marcus, Ruth Barcan, 15, 215, 218, 219, 223, 224–5,
intuitionism and intuitionistic logic, 1, 11, 18–20, 226, 233, 235
81–2, 83, 174, 270, 274, 281, 283 Matiyasevich, Yuri, 11, 142, 145
Dummett and, 1, 3, 257, 258, 267 Mauldin, Daniel, 279
maximality, principle of, 116, 117
James, William, 92–3, 95, 102 McKinsey, J. C. C., 171, 180
Jarndyce and Jarndyce, see Bleak House meaning, 12, 19, 78, 79, 80, 163–4, 257
Jeffrey, Richard, xiii, 11, 135, 140–1, 144, 250 descriptive versus prescriptive theories of,
Jensen, Ronald, 277 267, 270
truth-conditional or ‘‘verist’’ theory of, 12, 162,
Kamp, Hans, 282 257, 258, 266, 267, 269
Kant, Immanuel, 93–4 see also compositionality, disjunction,
Kaplan, David, 107, 230, 234 dualism, names, representationalism,
Kepler, Johannes, 2, 69, 93, 95 semantics, translation, transparency,
Khayyam, Omar, 52 verificationism
Kleene, S. C., 151 Menchù, Rigoberta, 64
knowability, 14, 185, 196–202 Mendel, Gregor, 80
König, Julius, 150–1 Meyer, Robert, 161
Korzybski, Alfred, 156 Mill, John Stuart, 15, 210, 220, 236, 244
Kreisel, Georg, 132, 155, 161, 174, 273, 283 Millianism, 236–44
Kripke, Saul, 14, 16, 17, 35, 167, 214, 215, 223, 233, modality and modal logic, 13, 16, 157, 160, 169–84,
235, 266, 280 185, 203–4, 231
models for modal logic, 13, 129, 161, 175, 216, de dicto and de re, 14, 204–5, 209
218, 283 quantification and, 14–15, 204–27
names and, 15, 174–5, 229, 231–2, 233, 234, 238, models, 12–13, 16, 157–61, 174–6
240, 242, 244 monism, 7, 100–1
Kripke–Platek set theory (KP), 278 Montagna, Franco, 138
Kronecker, Leopold, 52 Moore, G. E., 53
300 Index
Morning Star and Evening Star, 212, 221, 228 predicativity and impredicativity, 10, 11, 41, 42,
see also Hesperus and Phosphorus 136, 137, 145, 179
Mortensen, Chris, 17 Pressburger’s theorem, 142
Myhill, John, 219 primary versus secondary sentences, 268, 270,
mystery cards, game of, 249–50, 253 271, 272
Prior, Arthur, 14, 78, 158, 189, 217, 220–1, 224, 225,
Nabokov, Vladimir, 50 230, 270, 272, 282
Nading, Inga, 69 probability, logic of, 282
names, proper, 14, 15, 221, 224, 231–3, 236–45 provability, logic of, 160–1, 170, 171, 174, 177
naturalism, 2, 7, 48, 74, 87 purity, axiom of, 121–3, 124, 125
necessity, 13 Putnam, Hilary, 33, 34, 36, 61, 101–2, 142, 234
as analyticity, 206 Puzzling Pierre, 15, 238–40, 244–5
logical, 13–14, 169, 229–30, 234
metaphysical, 14, 169, 226–7, 229–30, 234 quantification,
Nelson, Edward, 137, 138 generalized, see generalized-quantifier logic
neo-Fregeanism, 135, 137 modality and, see modality, quantification and
neo-logicism, see logicism plural, see plurals and plural logic
neo-intuitionism, see intuitionism substitutional, 217
Neumann, John von, 86, 116, 138 quantum mechanics, 35, 58, 274
Nietzsche, Friedrich, 63 Quine, W. V., 19, 47–8, 52, 54, 68–9, 70, 74–5, 78,
nihilism, 100–1 80, 82, 85, 92, 99–100, 157–9, 262, 266,
nominalism, 1, 3–7, 20, 23–30, 31–45, 46–7, 51, 52, 268–9, 270–1
71, 72–4, 85–92, 95–7, 103 analyticity and, 76, 77–9, 82–3, 153
hermeneutic, see hermeneuticists Carnap and, 6, 69, 71–2, 75, 78, 94–5
instrumentalist, see instrumentalism modality and, 14–15, 203–29
revolutionary, see revolutionaries nominalism and, 32, 33, 34, 60, 61–2, 71–3, 85,
nonmonotonic logic, 283 90, 101–2, 276
Nootka, 98
numbers, 23–4, 27–8, 51, 52, 70–1, 86, 149 Ramsey, F. P., 136, 216, 220
Rayo, Augustin, 9
Ockhamism, 198–200, 282 Read, Stephen, 17
ontology, 6, 86, 91–2, 94–5, 98, 101, 102 realism, 1–2, 23–30, 47–8, 64, 95
metaphysical, 1, 46, 47, 72
Paderewski, 245 naturalist, see naturalism
pairing, axiom of, 116, 121 reducibility, axiom of, 136, 137
paradise, Cantor’s, 71, 127, 134 reflection, principle of, 117–19, 120, 122, 133, 134
paradoxes, 10, 12, 14, 130, 150–1, 166, 185, 196, 200 regimentation, 157
Parsons, Charles, 6, 62, 76 relativization, 118, 122, 124, 125
Parsons, Terence, 137, 140, 209, 218 relevance, logic of, 16–18, 20, 246–55
Peano postulates, 136, 137 replacement, axiom of, 112, 116, 121
Peirceanism, 200–1, 282 representationalism, 270, 273–4
Penrose, Roger, 179 revolutionaries, 3, 7, 16, 18, 34, 51, 57–8, 59, 87–9
Pi-one (1) sentences, 139, 141–2, 145 Richard, Jules, 150, 151
Plato, 28, 57, 211, 274–5 Richards, Ian, 274
Platonism, 69, 90, 95, 257, 267, 270 Riemann, Bernhard, 79
plurals and plural logic, 9, 106–9, 129–30 Robinson, Julia, 11, 142, 145
Poincaré, Henri, 150 Robinson, Raphael, 137
Pollard, Stephen, 9 Rorty, Richard, 101, 102
positivism, 271, 272 Rosen, Gideon, 3, 5, 46, 47, 51, 59, 60, 87, 90, 91
post-modernism, 102 Ross, Arnold, 149
Pour-El, Marian, 274 Rückert, Helge, xii
power, axiom of, 121 Russell, Bertrand, 10, 46, 64, 81, 136, 143, 150, 224,
pragmatism, 47, 102 225, 228, 235
Prawitz, Dag, 19, 263 Russellianism, 14, 220–1, 223, 228, 231, 232–3
predicate-functor logic, 99–100 Ryle, Gilbert, 19, 270, 272
Index 301
S4 (modal system), 13 tense logic, 157–9, 170, 185–202, 281–2
S5 (modal system), 13 Tharp, Leslie, 49
Salmon, Nathan, 233 Thomason, S. K., 177
Sandu, Gabriel, 235 Tlön, 98
Sartre, Jean-Paul, 95 transitivity, 120
Schindler, Ralf-Dieter, 112 translation, 238–44
Schlick, Moritz, 94–5 transparency, 237
Scroggs, S. J., 177 truth, 12, 149, 151–2, 154, 280
Searle, John, 19, 229
second-order logic, 131, 135, 156 union, axiom of, 121
Segerberg, Krister, 161, 281, 282 Urquhart, Alasdair, 17
selection, measurable, 279 Uzquiano, Gabriel, 9, 112
semantics, 12–13, 129–30, 159, 165, 166, 168,
216, 259 validity, 13, 169–70, 172–4, 176–7
separation, axiom of, 8, 114–15, 134 Van Fraassen, Bas, 47, 280
set theory, 104–29, 277–81 Vaught, Robert, 155, 278
see also Zermelo–Frankel set theory verificationism, 201, 257, 267, 269, 270, 272
Shapiro, Stuart, 5, 9, 57 verism, see meaning, truth-conditional
Shelah, Saharon, 279 theory of
Silver, Jack, 278 vicious circle principle, 136, 137
skepticism, 19, 96, 97, 263 Visser, Albert, 140
Skinner, B. F., 19, 80, 270, 271
Skura, Tomasz, 183 Wang, Hao, 42
Slupecki, Jerzy, 181 Wehmeier, Kai, xii
Smielew, Wanda, 138–9 Weinstein, Scott, 45
Smiley, T. J., 254 Whorf, Benjamin Lee, 97, 98
Smullyan, Arthur, and Smullyanism, 215, 219–20, Wiles, Andrew, 49, 53
221, 223, 228, 233, 235 Wilkie, Alex, 139
Soames, Scott, xiii, 260 Williamson, Timothy, xii, 193, 198
Solovay, Robert, 137, 138, 161, 174, 277 Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 88, 266
Stalin and Djugashvili, 241 Woodin, Hugh, 151
Stalnaker, Robert, 230, 283 Wright, Crispin, 60–1, 137, 263
Stanley, Jason, 52 Wright, G. H. von, 229
Strawson, P. F., 79, 229, 248
supertransitivity, 120 Yablo, Steve, 5, 49, 52, 53, 60, 87, 90, 91