Signos Do Paradoxo
Signos Do Paradoxo
ERIC GANS
Eric Gans
August 6,1996
Contents
Introduction:
Why Generative Anthropology?
in the following chapter under the rubric of "mimetic paradox" was originally
formulated as “mimetic crisis.” Paradox is the counterpart in the sphere of
representation of crisis in the sphere of reality. Both are projections of the
originary event of the human upon the different axes of text and world—the
projections that define and distinguish the humanities and the social sciences.
The deconstructionists who, like their New Critical ancestors, purport to find
everything in the text, are incapable of theorizing the emergence of the textual
within the world—the very emergence by whose paradoxical structure they define
textuality. Nor can the mathematical sophistication of chaos theory and the like
by means of which social scientists seek to quantify the notion of crisis take the
place of an anthropology that understands language and other forms of
representation as specifically human means of deferring specifically human
crises. To understand human origin as the punctual event that invents and
discovers both crisis and paradox, crisis as the realization of paradox, paradox as
the solution to crisis, requires a theory of its own.
The degree to which the disciplines of the humanities and the social sciences
alike are reified as "methodologies" depends on their distance from the central
core of the human. We may affirm with full confidence that "in the last analysis"
they are all branches of the non-methodology that takes this central core as its
subject mater. But we no longer have the luxury, either as individuals or as a
community, of entertaining last analyses. On the contrary, generative
anthropology is intended as an antidote to the eschatologies, religious and secular,
that have hitherto monopolized the human center. So we must forever defer our
statement of the ultimate purpose of originary thinking. The effect of the most
fundamental form of thinking on our overall system of thought must remain
undecidable. But this very undecidability—this unpredictable addition of new
degrees of freedom to the system—fulfills the theory's purpose according to its
own conception of human culture: the deferral of violence through representation.
*
Like humanity and its language, generative anthropology has its own genesis.
René Girard's originary scene, ambivalently monogenetic and polygenetic,
universal and particular, situates the human community on the periphery of a
circle surrounding a sacred center1. What this scene lacks is the linguistic sign by
means of which the peripheral humans could avoid violence by deferring their
mimetic-appetitive appropriation of this center. Whence my formulation in The
Origin of Language of the "originary hypothesis" that the sign originates as an
“aborted gesture of appropriation.”2
Introduction 5
But it is not enough to claim that language must be a part of any scene of human
origin; why need there be a scene of origin at all? The value of our answer to this
fundamental question of anthropology is proportional to its parsimony. Since
formulating the originary hypothesis, I have continued to work toward its
minimization, most recently by subordinating the naturalistic model of the
originary scene to the fundamental triangular model of mimesis (see Chapter 2).
It should suffice to argue that because language intrinsically requires self-
consciousness, it cannot emerge unconsciously. But this a priori, even if accepted,
does not suffice to permit us to construct a scene of origin. Another argument is
that although all higher animals have communication systems, "languages" of a
kind, none have anything resembling religious observances, with their uniquely
human scenic event-structure that can most parsimoniously be derived from a
single ancestral event. But the historical evidence can never be sufficient to justify
the reconstruction of an originary "big bang" that is by definition
incommensurable with this evidence. Backward extrapolation cannot offer a
compelling reason for abandoning the standard (non)explanations of human
origin.
The skepticism that greets the originary hypothesis is a healthy one.
An anthropology is more than an intellectual construction; it is a worldview. For
a radically new anthropology to be accepted as true, it must offer a demonstrable
ethical advantage to those who accept it. I claimed in Originary Thinking that
return to the origin establishes the conditions for universal human dialogue. But
this formulation still fails to indicate why we need a scene of origin as a basis for
dialogue instead of the more commonplace and less controversial proposition that
we are all members of the same species.
At first glance, the minimal condition of the dialogue in which generative
anthropology consists is that we agree on the fact of an originary event, the
articulation of which can then become the first object of this dialogue. The
reconstruction of the originary event provides a minimal configuration within
which all essential human categories may be situated.
But let us take one step farther. What I have called the heuristic fonction of the
originary hypothesis may also be put in terms of dialogue: whether or not we agree
that it took place, or even that it is meaningful to ask the question, the originary
event provides us with a minimal subject of conversation. Whatever our
skepticism about the event's historical reality, if we want to speak together as
human beings, the principle of parsimony entails that this event is the minimal
object on which we can exercise our respective imaginations. And if, as a result
of our dialogue, we come to agree on anything that will help us to attain an
Introduction 6
increased understanding of human culture, the originary event is the most limited,
least confining object of such agreement.
Why a scene rather than a "theory"? But the minimal anthropological "theory"—
in Greek, an overview, a scenic perspective—is one derived from a single scene.
Because the birth of the human coincides with the birth of the scenic, it cannot be
conceived as a series of non-scenic changes of state. To speak of the human as
"always already" constituted is not to deny its essential scenicity; on the contrary.
The rejection of the metaphysical notion of pure self-presence is not a rejection
of scenicity itself; it is an appeal for the restoration of the anthropological
concreteness or "ostensivity" that metaphysics had sacrificed in its effort to
liberate itself from the irrationality of religious commemoration.
But let us suppose that the originary hypothesis is false; that nothing like an event
of origin ever occurred; that language, and along with it, religion, desire, and all
the other unique traits of human self-consciousness emerged imperceptibly within
hominid communication systems. Sacrificial ritual and its derivative structures
then commemorate no specific event; they are all ideological operations serving
to impose closure on open-ended forms of interaction. Since they are preceded by
no real event, we should say rather that they invent closure, presence, and so on.
But if such an invention exists, then it must itself be traceable to an origin. When
the thought-form of Western metaphysics appeared to be the problematic
invention, Heidegger traced its origin back to Plato. But if the presence of
metaphysics is only an intellectual version of the logocentrism already manifested
in religious ritual, then we are entitled to know at what point this earlier violence
was done to the eventless origin of language. If the event represented in ritual
commemorates no real event, at least we cannot deny that it commemorates a
representational event.
For to take the deconstructive position to its extreme turns it into its opposite. If
indeed language from the very first is a trace supplementary to a lost presence, so
that the event it pretends to commemorate does not precede it but is in effect
coeval with it, as the Son is coeval with the Father in Trinitary theology—I think
this is a fair summary of Derrida's position in De la grammatologie—then all the
theory of writing, of the supplement, of deferral, is in effect a theory of the
originary event. It suffices to understand the always-already not as an abstract
model formulated in the framework of metaphysics, but as a concrete one realized
in an ostensive context among beings who only learn to think about their death
because thinking is a life-and-death operation.
Closed forms of thought are built around apocalyptic events that provide "final
solutions" to all the problems within their universe. If we would rid ourselves of
Introduction 7
this sort of thinking, we must exchange the apocalyptic model of the event for an
originary model. Events are openings, not closures. The only acceptable
intellectual utopia is one whose story has a beginning but no end.
The theorists of the "always-already" refuse in the name of an abstract openness
the very idea of anthropology. When they have deconstructed the categories of
human thought down to their founding paradox, they think they have found our
thinking's fatal weakness, when in fact they have arrived at the source of its
strength. Thought acquires new degrees of freedom not by expelling paradox, but
by reproducing its pattern of supplementation. Man will ever remain the
paradoxical animal, not least because today the very name of "man" has become
unsayable.
*
The present book is divided into two parts. The first contains originary analyses
of such phenomena as being, thinking, irony, and the erotic; the second deals with
violence (the sparagmos), evil, rhetoric, and the victimary element of postmodern
culture. Each of the two develops a different innovation with respect to my
previous expositions of generative anthropology.
The chronologically prior innovation, more personal but less fundamental, is that
of the second part. As a result of my emphasis on the sign rather than on Girard's
"emissary violence" as the point of departure for the human, I had deferred the
full integration of the latter element into the originary scene of generative
anthropology. The present work gives violence its due within the originary scene
by reinterpreting as the sparagmos, the tearing apart of the central object by the
members of the nascent human community, what I had previously described as its
"peaceful division" in the protosacrificial feast that brings the originary event to a
close. For, in accordante with the minimality of the hypothesis, the division of the
object need not be wholly peaceful so long as the violence it entails remains
contained within the limits of the communal order established by the originary
sign. In this way, the Girardian version of the originary hypothesis is not so much
refuted as included within that of generative anthropology.
The relationship of the questions of violence and evil to the culture of the
postmodern era is mediated by the Holocaust as the defining historical event of
this new era. This idea informs the ensuing discussions of the "Jewish question,"
victimary rhetoric, and the "minoritary" cultural system that is emerging in the
United States and, no doubt, in the world as a whole.
The second, more fundamental, new element may also be understood, although
in a very different way, as a "return to Girard": it is the renewed emphasis on the
Introduction 8
Paradoxical Thinking
2
For Charles S. Peirce, the sign is defined as "determined by something else", that
is, it stands in a horizontal relation to its referent.1 The inadequacy of this relation
is then supplemented by a hypothetical third term or "interpretant," along the lines
of the "third man" of Greek philosophy who furnishes the ground of resemblance
between a real man and the idea of a man. The sign-relation is explained through
a movement of infinite regress, thereby deferring the horizontal encounter
between sign and referent at the cost of the definitional rigor of the system. In
distinguishing families of signs by their type of motivation, Peirce can make no
place for the arbitraire du signifiant that distinguishes human language; the
arbitraire is not a zero degree of motivation but a formal absolute—one that, like
all absolutes, is not immune to deconstruction.
In contrast to Peirce, Saussure sees in the sign nothing but verticality. In giving
to the bar that separates signifier from signified the—in his perspective
primordial—anthropological function of paternal interdiction, Lacan implies the
necessity of a generative-anthropological explanation for the emergence of the
formal-vertical from the horizontal. The bar is a mystery; if the sign and what it
refers to are identical areas on either side of a sheet of paper, one wonders not
only what function can be served by turning the paper over, but how we ever got
from the real world to the paper in the first place. By bracketing the referent of
the sign and substituting its signified or concept, Saussure only defers the
understanding of the horizontal relationship between sign and referent as two
worldly things.
My solution to this aporia was published well over a decade ago in The Origin
of Language. The terms in which it was expressed, as well as those in which it has
been repeated and refined in my more recent books, have sometimes been
misunderstood as formulating a new "myth of origin." No doubt I grasped the
essence of the problem better than the strategy for articulating it. I offered a
minimal hypothesis for the origin of language, of the human—of "man," as we
said at the time. But depicting a scene of origin of language, as opposed to merely
affirming language's essential scenicity, could not fail to give the appearance of
an excess rather than a minimum of content. Which is all the more the case when
the rival hypothesis is that no hypothesis is conceivable.
The "triangular" version of the originary hypothesis that I present here differs
little in substance from that of The Origin of Language, but that difference makes
it henceforth impossible to tax the hypothesis with naturalistic naïveté. Our
fundamental anthropological intuition is far more sensitive to the mode of
narrative presentation of the hypothesis than to its real content. The description of
a collective scene of origin goes against the grain of a postmodern intellectual
Paradoxical Thinking 12
of representation, the central figure takes over the negative role of the mimetic
obstacle. The goal of the imitated worldly activity has become its otherworldly
model.
Mimesis
Imitation leaves its ontology unthematized; it knows only that since you are like
me, I can do as you do. Mimesis thematizes its ontology. This great misunderstood
concept of the metaphysical tradition was confined by Aristotle's Poetics to the
esthetic domain for over two millennia until Girard gave it its due by revealing
that human desire, and the human as such, obeys the paradoxical structure of
mimesis.
Imitation of behavior among similar creatures is generally unproblematic. More
precisely, I can imitate your actions unproblematically so long as they do not
involve the appropriation of a scarce object that we both desire to possess. But the
search for such objects is precisely the kind of behavior that makes imitation
advantageous. The evolution of higher animals has been driven by the difficulty
of obtaining appetitive satisfaction, particularly food. If I serve as your model in
the hunt, all will go well until your imitation reaches the point of reproducing my
appropriative gesture toward the same object. At this point imitation provokes
rivalry; the mimetic model becomes an obstacle.
The becoming-obstacle of the model is not in itself uniquely human. At the most
elementary level of imitation, when a swarm of animals gather around a source of
nourishment, each one becomes sooner or later an obstacle for the others. But the
energy and attention of members of the group are directed to the prey, not to each
other. If they do enter into conflict, or even begin to devour each other, this
remains incidental to the appropriative operation that ultimately benefits the
swarm and the species to which it belongs. The mimetic obstacle is there, but it
remains epiphenomenal with respect to the benefit conferred by imitation.
In animal imitation, the becoming-obstacle of the model remains an unpleasant
side effect that must be countered by the very process of mimetic evolution that
serves to increase it. Whereas the less fit among the multiple members of lower
species can easily be sacrificed, higher animals, of greater individual value to their
species, are worth preserving within a hierarchical order that prevents mimetic
conflict, or limits it to one-on-one battles for supremacy. The "alpha" animal is
the product of a higher level of mimetic tension than can exist within the leaderless
swarm. His maintenance of order implies a degree of rivalry with his fellows. But
this order is not threatened by the reinforcement of collective mimesis. Animal
Paradoxical Thinking 14
common interest risks provoking the hostility of the group. The second, less
obvious, element is the preexistence of the animal hierarchy spoken of above.
Freud's scenario of the murder of the father in Totem and Taboo may be rewritten
in ethological terms: the alpha animal attempts to exercise his normal privilege in
appropriating the object of common desire, but because of the increased level of
mimesis and consequent dedifferentiation, the others no longer defer to him but
imitate his appropriative gesture "out of turn," with the consequence that he must
abort his own action, the others then following suit.3
There is no reason to doubt the plausibility of this scenario; but its naturalism is
incompatible with minimalist rigor. This is more obvious in the case of animal
hierarchy, but it applies to the plurality of others as well—and this despite the
necessarily public nature of the event of origin. For the "public" can be modeled
as easily by two people as by two hundred.
The problem is not that an alpha animal may not have existed, but that its
empirical existence, even were we certain of it, cannot be substituted for an
explanation of the breakdown of its dominant role. To account for the end of
hierarchy by its inherent instability is merely to beg the question. Thus the alpha's
existence does not serve as a true explanatory element, but as a relay or
intermediary stage that avoids the crucial question of fixing the degree of freedom
inherent in the specific operation of human mimesis.
Animal hierarchy arises in order to avert the conflict implicit in mimesis. But
this intermediate stage between lower life-forms and the human only interests us
insofar as it determines the minimal conditions of emergence of the latter. That
reliance on animal hierarchy is inherently misleading is already apparent from the
examination of Freud's model, despite its lack of ethological references. Freud
envisioned the prehuman horde as a hierarchically organized group, the liberation
or dehierarchization of which corresponded to the appearance of man. But we
cannot understand the mimetically dedifferentiated state in which the originary
scene takes place simply as a product of the unexplained dissolution of a previous
hierarchy. It must be explained from within as the subject's state of undecidability
between the mimetic other-mediator's two roles of model and rival. This statement
of the problem makes clear that it is unnecessary to postulate a protohuman animal
hierarchy; mimesis itself defines a hierarchy, however unstable, between subject-
self and other-model, and this hierarchy is the basis upon which all others are
founded.
Similarly, the triangular formulation of the hypothesis eliminates the need for
the independent postulation of the plurality of others. The determining factor in
the conversion of the appropriative gesture into a sign is not fear of the violence
Paradoxical Thinking 16
of the other(s), but the incompatibility of the two roles of subject and other in the
mimetic process. This correction should not be taken as a sanitization of our
bloody past."Fear" and "violence" are not the clear-cut categories they appear to
be. If fear of the violence of my mimetic model(s) is supposed to explain my
failure to carry my appropriative gesture to completion, it hardly explains why I
continue to perform the gesture under a new intention, or why I remain within the
mimetic configuration rather than seeking to escape from it. The subject's
attachment to the scene, whatever its dangers, demonstrates that mimesis rather
than fear is the explanatory element; but in that case, the most economical
explanation is the one that presupposes nothing beyond the triangular mimetic
configuration.
*
Reduced to the mimetic triangle purged of all naturalistic elements, the originary
hypothesis may be formulated as follows: the sign originates as the solution to the
"paradoxical state" or "pragmatic paradox" engendered when the mimetic relation
to the other-mediator requires the impossible task of maintaining the latter as
model while imitating his appropriative action toward a unique object. Put in
geometric terms, the parallel lines of imitation must converge toward a single
point. The mimetic model is both model and (potential) obstacle; it is at the
moment when this contradiction prevents action that the human linguistic sign
appears.
The cessation of action in the situation of mimetic crisis is more radical than in
that of hierarchical submission, where the non-alpha animal acts out its
submission by its very stasis—and where it would normally expect to take its turn
after its superiors. We need a more general word than "action" or even "behavior"
to describe what is prevented in a truly paradoxical situation—habitus, perhaps—
a term that designates simply a coherent mode of being. The psychological
correlate of the paradoxical state of mimesis is anxiety, as was the case with
Pavlov's dogs. The situation is obviously similar, but here the feedback loop is
minimized; it is not determined by the interference of two con-ditioning factors
that drive the subject to two incompatible actions at the same time, but by an
internat contradiction in the (mimetic) mode of behavior itself. When mimetic
attraction has reached a sufficient in-tensity, behavior as such becomes
impossible.
What is done in this circumstance is no longer to "behave," but to produce a sign.
The triangular model of the hypothesis permits a more rigorous analysis of how
the function and character of this designating sign differ from those of the original
appropriative gesture. In the naturalistic model, the clearest function of the sign is
Mimetic Paradox 17
The sign begins as the same physical action as the aborted gesture of
appropriation, but the intended deferral of horizontal interaction with its object
allows it vertically to "intend" this object in the phenomenological sense, to take
it as its theme. What unblocks the mimetic process has its source within mimesis
itself. As the appropriative intention of the original gesture makes its imitation
impossible within the framework of animal relations, it increasingly focuses
attention on the object to be appropriated. When I imitate the other in his
appropriation of an object, my attention focuses on him if I have my own
counterpart to his object, but on the object if it is the same for us both. The
intensification of mimesis, by putting into question the equivalence between my
object and the one that partakes of the aura of the mediator, makes it increasingly
less satisfactory for me to choose an object different from his. The normal child
chooses a mate in imitation of his father's choice; Oedipus, the mimetic archetype,
can take no wife other than his father's.
The movement toward the object—and concomitantly away from the model—is
inherent in mimesis as such. The appropriative gesture is so to speak already
"predisposed" to re-present the object even as it performs its practical function.4
What remains for the originary scene to accomplish—but it is the accomplishment
that makes all the difference—is the thematization of the intention to represent
and defer appropriation. Once attention to the object and its interdiction by the
other have increased to the point of rendering appropriative action impossible, the
mimetic shift to the object formalizes—in effect, brings to (human)
consciousness—this already-existing tendency.
This analysis moves in the opposite direction from Girard's original exposition
of mimetic desire in Mensonge romantique, which consists in bringing to light the
mediating third element behind the "romantic lie" that conceives of desire as a
dual object-relation. Here it is the object of desire rather than the mediator that is
exposed as central to what had appeared to be a one-on-one relationship of
behavioral imitation. This counterintuitive result requires explanation.
Appetitive behavior normally directs itself to objects, and it is not stretching the
analogy too far to say that it "intends" these objects. A cat hunting a mouse knows
what object it is looking for as much as a human hunter stalking a deer. But the
cat's behavior, unlike the hunter's, is an unlearned routine that includes its object
categorically within it—not hunting behavior that happens to alight upon a mouse,
but mouse-hunting behavior. When imitative learning does take place with respect
to such behavior, the object, as part of the behavior itself, does not fall under the
spell of the imitation; if one cat learns from another a new mouse-hunting
technique, no particular mouse receives thereby a supplementary value. The
Mimetic Paradox 19
supplement that comes from re-presentation of the object can only arise when it
is not already present as an element of the learned activity.
Desire is always mediated desire. The movement of appetite toward desire is that
of an intensified mimesis that discovers not only behavior but the goal of behavior
in the other. What causes the late emergence of the object into the mimetic
equation is not indifference to it but, on the contrary, the practical object-
orientation of animal behavior. Because the object as source of food, shelter,
sexual release, and so forth is less freely chosen (more "scarce") than the
behaviors of the subject by which it may be appropriated, the techniques of
appropriation are subject to mimetic learning before there is any need to "learn"
the object of appropriation. It is only at an advanced stage of mimesis that not
merely the action itself but its goal falls under the influence of the mediating other.
Why should the intensification of mimesis lead the subject away from the other's
behavior toward the object to which it is directed? This movement reflects an
internalization of the model's motivation, the self's closer assimilation to the
other's own reality. The more closely I imitate my model's goal-directed action,
the more I share the goal of this action, which is not located in the action itself but
precisely in its external object. (This analysis applies as well to self-directed
actions; a higher level of mimesis will lead me, for example, to imitate the other
animal's "narcissism" and groom it rather than myself.) Whence the apparent
paradox that as imitation becomes more intense, it prefigures the triangular
structure of human representation, focusing less on the model's behavior and more
on the object to which it is directed.
model and object in a single behavior. I imitate the other in my énonciation and
the object in my énoncé. Instead of my action being a simple means of self-
expansion into the world through the incorporation and obliteration of external
objects, it becomes a means to preserve these objects by reproducing them within
myself. I can now continue to imitate the gesture of my model despite the presence
of an obstacle to appropriative action. Because the model does not disturb my
signing behavior, it is the object that is perceived as the obstacle to its own
appropriation; this is what we call its sacrality.
This model of the first emission of the sign is that of its "early" or "thoughtful"
emission. In the sense that I emit the sign as the result of my own abortion of the
gesture of appropriation rather than in imitation of my model, the decision to emit
the sign is the originary example of thinking, as discussed in Chapter 7. This may
be contrasted with the emission of the sign under the mimetic influence of the
model by the "late" participant still seeking to appropriate the object. This exercise
of influence is discussed in Chapter 12 under the rubric of "originary rhetoric."
Once again, the specific difference between these two moments of the emission
of the sign is clarified by the use of a minimal rather than a naturalistic context.
The originary sign is the first instance of the free, conscious, intentional
thematization of an object. Our analysis cannot be content with showing that the
sign is freely performed, but must show how freedom is born with the sign. Like
the birth of verticality from horizontality, the birth of freedom from necessity is
another statement of the paradox of originary signification. Its explanation can
never be complete; as the birth of a new level of complexity, it is irreducible to
any earlier configuration. But rather than lament the futility of intellectual
bootstrapping, we should take such paradoxes—and all paradox reduces to this
one, the paradox of the human-as-such—as guarantees of the inexhaustibility of
originary thinking.
In a brief discussion of the question of freedom in the Introduction to Originary
Thinking, I used Kant's formulation of the esthetic judgment ("without a concept")
as my model for the freedom of the signifying intention: the subject was
influenced by the "beauty" of his gesture, that is, by its ability to re-present the
all-desirable central object. This is a suggestive formulation; but it complicates
the matter by introducing the category of the esthetic, in which the subject's
attention oscillates between sign and referent. The esthetic is dependent on the
sign; it perpetuates our paradoxical experience of the sign's thematization of its
referent as already significant. To grasp the originary freedom of the sign prior to
the reinforcement provided by the esthetic, we must attempt instead to define
Mimetic Paradox 21
"freedom within the limits of mimesis": to understand how a mimetic act can free
itself from "instinctive" or nonreflective dependency on its model.
The transformation of the aborted gesture into a sign is a movement from the
imitation of a human model to the "imitation" of an appetitive object. In the
mimesis of the object, the subject is not copying another's gesture, but
representing the object itself.
Let us consider for a moment the subject-object relation. I appropriate an object
in order to fulfill an appetitive need. Whether or not I am imitating a human
mediator is not critical so long as I indeed have this need. Up to this point, mimesis
is merely a beneficial way of learning the technique of such necessary
appropriative gestures.
We might then be tempted to call even the appropriative gesture "free" when it
arises in a nonmimetic context. I may have learned it from another, but my
performance of it is dictated by my own needs, and in higher animals these needs
themselves need not obey a strict physiochemical calculus of stimulus-response.
For example, animals engage in various kinds of play. Here we come up against
the traditional question of "free will," which is, along with the existence of God,
one of Kant's antinomies of pure reason.
Generative anthropology offers a new understanding of the concept of freedom
as well as of that of God. Ours is a strictly anthropological explanation; it makes
no cosmological claims. The question of freedom versus determinism, like that of
the existence of God, is really a purely anthropological question. One can no
longer take seriously the nineteenth-century "science of religion" that wanted to
derive the concept of God from our awe of the cosmos. The reality is just the
opposite: having sufficiently deferred human violence by means of the concept of
God, we become interested in the relatively dangerous cosmos on the model of
extremely dangerous humanity. Religion tends to apply to the cosmos a model of
divine power that is indeed of value in anthropological situations but has little
functionality in cosmological situations. In times of crisis, cosmic or otherwise,
we appeal to God because in our fundamental, originary model of crisis, the sign
as name-of-God provides the solution.5
The problem of freedom versus determinism is equally anthropological rather
than cosmic, "cultural" rather than "natural." To say that the future movement of
a particle is "determined" is to conceive a mind potentially aware of this
determination. The simple anthropological test of determinism is the following: if
after calculating the future state of a system, I can inform the system of my
calculations without leading it to deviate from them, that system may be called
determined. If, on the contrary, I must hide my calculations to avoid such
Paradoxical Thinking 22
deviation, then the system is free; for someone within the system could eventually
perform the same calculations as I have.
The obvious objection to this definition is that it is biased in favor of language
users; how could I convey the results of my calculations without language? But
the burden of proof should lie not with the definition but with its critics. It is for
them to show why, if human language is just one among many means of
communication that makes no real difference to the matter of free will, it has such
an effect on the system that contains it, why the animals whose languages they
study so intensively are incapable of such feats. Nor should the question be
deflected by bringing in artificial intelligence. Jusqu'à nouvel ordre, computers
have been constructed by human beings for their own benefit.
The freedom of signing as an act of representation distinguishes it from imitation
as a new, human variety of mimesis. To imitate is not to represent. I imitate you
because we are analogous beings; I need make no conscious effort to follow your
gestures, to thematize them as objects of representation.6 The mimetic crisis leads
to stasis precisely because prehuman imitation is nonreflexive; the subject has no
knowledge of itself as a self imitating another. In contrast, my representation of
the object is a conscious thematization. I am not like the object; I cannot follow it
by analogy. When I imitate you, I imitate your action, make movements analogous
to yours; but when I represent an object, I designate it, not a particular action of
it. My intention of the object is an intention to recall it into being, to double it
using only my own resources. I cannot perform the sign, as opposed to the gesture
of appropriation, without thematizing the purpose of the sign to represent its
object.
The key to the freedom of the sign lies in the detemporalizing/retemporalizing
movement discussed in chapter 6 of Originary Thinking ("Narrativity and
Textuality"). Imitation has no inherent form. The practical gesture is
"horizontally" contiguous with its object; its lack of end-in-itself is visible in its
outward formlessness. Because appropriation ends with the object, not with the
act itself, if I imitate you successfully, I have no awareness of the limits of my
gesture, which are imposed upon it from without. The nonformal quality of the
practical gesture is reflected in the continuity between its temporality and that of
the life-world to which it is subordinate; the hunter's movements must obey the
rhythms of the animal he hunts rather than his own. In contrast, the sign is
detemporalized, cut off from its natural aim and therefore from the time in which
such aims are realized.
In the discussion in Originary Thinking, the sign's detemporalization of the
original appropriative gesture was considered tantamount to its constitution as
Mimetic Paradox 23
form, even esthetic form (for example, "In the originary scene itself, in the
presence of the sacred, the esthetic contemplation of the sign is the complement
of the sign's desiring prolongation toward the center" [103]). But in the present
discussion, we stand at the origin of form, which we must explain without
recourse to the notion of the esthetic. This explanation will return us to the
question of freedom.
Abortion of the gesture is not in itself detemporalization; it is such only when
the aborted gesture becomes an action in its own right—an action of a new kind,
devoid of direct worldly aim. We may say that it defers this aim, that its very
existence as form is a worldly realization of deferral, by which I refer to the
fundamental equivalence, pointed at by Derrida's seminal term différance,
between differentiation as marked by the sign and deferral of the mimetic conflict
that the loss of difference risks bringing about. The sign re-presents the object as
what may truly be called an object of desire, now that its potential appetitive
attractiveness is cut off from practical action. Desire is not first experienced and
then "repressed," as in the psychoanalytic model; its thematization of its object is
itself a product of the repression of the possibility of discharge in appetitive
satisfaction.
The detemporalized gesture possesses a new, formal temporality.The beginning
and end of a form are within the form itself. At the origin of formality is the new
aim of the aborted gesture, which is transformed from a practical into a
representational act. Within the practical realm, the goal is no longer to
appropriate the object in imitation of the human mediator but to imitate the object
to the latter's satisfaction, that is, well enough to make him understand the new
sense—which can already be called the "meaning"—of the gesture. This is an aim
external to the gesture itself, but one that depends on its formal closure as a
representation. This closure is not perceived within the practical world but on the
other's imaginary scene of representation. In practical terms, this imaginary aim
mediates the deferral of conflict, averting the potential wrath of the other-mediator
toward his disciple-rival.
It is justifiable to follow past practice in calling this originary form of
representation "designation" and the utterance that performs it an "ostensive,"
with its connotation of pointing. (But it is useless in this context to speculate on
the oral versus manual character of the "aborted gesture"; we may just as well
assume it to have both.) In principle, any appropriative gesture will "point" toward
its object in the sense of serving as a natural sign that draws attention to it, but
this within the continuum of worldly action that leads ultimately to its
appropriation. Now that the latter course has been foreclosed, the sign does
Paradoxical Thinking 24
action-object from his blocked action, in imitation of the object that has become
the obstacle to this action.
This distinction between action and object is the real anthropological point of
Derrida's distinction between speech and writing. Unlike speech, writing is clearly
the production of an object; the act of writing is of no independent interest. Even
when we see someone writing, we only want to know the result, not observe his
performance. In speech, on the contrary, performance and production of the
language-object are one and the same. Once the énonciation is over, there is no
more énoncé. Whence what Derrida refers to as the speaker's illusion of self-
presence. To the extent that what is essential is the language-object and not the
process of its creation, our analyses are in agreement. The self-presence of speech
is blind to its own constitution; if language were indeed mere self-presence, it
could not fonction within the intersubjective triangle of mimesis. As we have
observed, mimetic performance requires no self-consciousness whatever; I can
follow your movements without being conscious of any self, yours or mine. The
self can only emerge in the context of the forming of the sign-object. But this
"object" is, in Derrida's scheme, the equivalent not of speech but of writing.
This is the justification for the claim that writing qua trace is prior to speech. Yet
the dismissal of self-presence as illusion throws out the baby with the bathwater.
The originary sign qua writing can only emerge from within the worldly
temporality in which it is performed; its existence presupposes the reality and
suspension of this temporality before its metaphysical abolition or "forgetting."
The sign is writing only because it is first speech; it has form because it first
became form by emerging from the nonformal in the aborted gesture. Only once
the event of this emergence has taken place does the completed sign transcend the
worldly temporality in which it was enacted to become "vertical" form, "written"
form, if we like.
This critique has its psychological corollary: the illusion of self-presence is the
self. The self is never self-present in the metaphysical sense of Aristotle's
unmoved mover, but it subsists as that which experiences itself as self-present
(whatever the philosopher may think of it). It is Derrida's metaphysical view of
paradox that leads him to reject the self as an illusory category because it is
founded on an "illusory" experience. Deconstruction constitutes the very
anthropological reality that it thinks it has abolished. The speaker-as-writer uses
the specifically human language that the deconstructor has in his own way
defined, all the while thinking he has subverted this very specificity.
The real truth of originary self-presence is the presence of the participants to
each other as mutual communicators of the sign. The mediator cannot retain his
Mimetic Paradox 27
hierarchical distance from the subject in the presence of the sign. In the naturalistic
or "circular" version of the originary hypothesis, this goes without saying. But this
is explained by assuming that the intensity of mimesis is such as to break down
or "dedifferentiate" the old animal hierarchy. The triangular version avoids this
supplementary postulate. Because it posits only the minimal hierarchy of mediator
and disciple from the outset, it provides a model of the establishment of their
reciprocal, dehierarchized presence under the sole weight of the sign.
The scene of mutual communication of the sign, whether between two beings or
ten thousand, is determined by the active stasis of sign production. What is
centrally present to me is not myself nor even the other participants but the central,
sacred object of desire. The signing self defers its self-presence through
identification with the object as its giver of form; this deferral of self-identity
breaks the paralysis caused by mimetic paradox. "Presence" comes into being
filled with absence, difference, and differentiation; but it is presence nonetheless,
the only kind possible, whatever more perfect models the imagination can
conceive by extrapolating from the positive moment of this paradoxical process.
Mimetic Paradox
Paradox is a structure of language; it cannot be conceived without the sign. But
neither can the sign be conceived without paradox. The horizontal and the vertical
cannot be cleansed of one another. The doubling of reality by the sign-world
cannot follow either the Saussurean or the Peircean model. The sign that is in the
world represents the world it is in; the sign that stands above the world remains
within the world of the sign.
There is more than an analogy between this situation and that of the mimetic
subject who finds the doubling of his model's gesture blocked by the collision of
converging trajectories. There are neither two places in the same universe nor two
separate universes for the one to find room to mimic the other. The constitution
of the sign is the creation-and-deferral—the différance—of paradox. Paradox
itself is paradoxical; that is what makes it paradox. It cannot be reduced to "lowest
terms," only deferred. But neither is it ever present before our eyes; it is always
in a state of deferral.
Paradoxical Thinking 30
The subject sets the process in motion by imitating the object, doubling within
his own action the inaccessible goal of his mimetic gesture. This action liberates
the gesture from its stasis by separating the components of the mimetic blockage.
On the one hand, the signing gesture, unlike the gesture of appropriation, can be
imitated without further difficulty, since it has its end in itself and not in the
material world. On the other, the object is designated, represented as an obstacle
to the very appropriative action its designation incites. Instead of two bands
converging on the object, we have two coterminous gestures cut off before they
can interfere with one another, but which thematically reject the practical aim that
incited them in the first place.
What this transformation generates is a radical redefinition of the ”practical”, a
program for the stabilization of the human community through signification the
validity of which has been demonstrated by our continued use of it for at least
30,000 years. This program creates paradox by deferring it. The referent is no
longer a simple object of appropriation but an object of signification; there is no
way to maintain a barrier between its "natural" and its "cultural" being. Formally
to designate the object through language is inevitably to designate it as an object-
of-designation; the object I mean is always already an object-meant. This is not
an artifact of mimesis that can be overcome with the benefit of a lucid theory of
desire; it is already the case for the first sign, the originary aborted gesture, at the
first moment of human thought.
*
The exploitation of our experience of this paradox, the recuperation of the
difference between the object and the object-as-designated-by-the-sign, is the role
of the esthetic, which I have described as the state of contemplation that oscillates
between these two "versions" of the object.10 The use of language in situation
forecloses the esthetic, which flourishes only when time is allowed for this
oscillation—time that serves the further deferral of action. Esthetic institutions
specifically valorize this time, which ritual inserts into its own practical context
of sacrifice.
Other loci of revelation of the originary paradox of the sign—irony,
signification, being, the Platonic Idea, thought, the erotic and the unconscious—
will be discussed in the chapters that follow. It remains an open question whether
a more schematic exposition of the ensemble of these categories is possible.
3
Why is there such a thing as paradox? To ask the question in this manner is to
collude with metaphysics in making it impossible to answer. The parasitic Other
of truth is in fact the generative principle of truth, the truth of logic as well as that
of the originary ostensive sign. There is a prelogical and even a prehuman form
of paradox, although the latter can only be so called from the perspective of the
sign that resolves the crisis it engenders. Pavlov's experimentally induced
"paradoxical" state, although confined to the stimulus-response mechanism—and
something of an experimental artifact—is not without analogy to the nascent
paradox of mimesis. But the stasis of the mimetic subject as described in the
previous chapter, unlike that of Pavlov's dogs, is structured vertically as well as
horizontally. The subject is not torn between two independent mimetic programs,
but between imitation of the other and rivalry with the other grounded on this very
imitation. Mimetic paradox lies on the frontier between the prehuman and the
human. The sign resolves prehuman paradox, but only to create true, human
paradox.
Paradox is an elusive category in which metaphysical skeptics find support for
their assertion of the inadequacy of human thought. Not even Russell's theory of
types can insure against it.1 But the real import of paradox is anthropological. The
scandal of paradox is that the transtemporal proposition-based language of
metaphysics should be subject to it. Paradox is the emergent structure of human
language, and its reemergence reminds us of our language's intrinsic historicity.
Paradoxical Thinking 32
One may well assume that if language-using beings were discovered in some
other galaxy, we would find their logic identical to our own. But this would be
because their system of representation would have evolved in a similar way to our
own. What metaphysical thought cannot conceptualize is that human language,
from which logic is abstracted, is not an eternal reality like mathematics but a
historical one. No doubt there must be enough freedom in any practical sign-
system to permit the formulation of statements like "This statement is false" or
"The barber shaves every man who doesn't shave himself," but this is because
human needs determine what systems are practical and what statements interest
us in them. Our fascination with paradox has historical roots far deeper than the
sort of difficulties that concerned Russell. The place of paradox in human
representation is older than the possibility of logical thought; it is older than
language itself.
The structure of the originary crisis deferred by the emergence of humanity is
the "pragmatic paradox" or "double bind" of mimesis, which gives rise in the
human context to the triangle of mimetic desire.2 In this configuration, the subject-
disciple takes the mediator as his model in an attempt to duplicate a behavior that
has led to a favorable result. There is no need to supply an ad hoc explanation for
the role of the human mediator, let alone to indulge in Freudian mythology.
Animals that are capable of modifying their behavior do so by imitation, and
inevitably some members of a group—older, stronger, sexually dominant—are
more valuable objects of imitation than others. But A's peaceful imitation of B's
food-gathering routine ends when A challenges B for the last piece of food. The
disciple becomes a rival; peaceful imitation, "the highest form of flattery," turns
into conflict. The mediator who at first welcomed the disciple now rejects him.
However vertical/metaphoric the latter's conduct with respect to the former, there
can be no guarantee that it will not impinge horizontally/metonymically upon his
being; true verticality is the product of the doubling of the real world by the world
of human language.
The prehuman protoparadox of mimetic stasis discussed in the previous chapter
arises when mimesis becomes so intense that, on the one hand, the only possible
action is the imitation of the model, but on the other, this imitation, once it extends
to the specific object of the model's appropriative praxis, comes into potential
conflict with the latter's aim. This stasis is broken by the sign, which defers all
appropriative action. But with signing comes true paradox: the sign cannot
represent the object-as-such, only the object-represented-by-the-sign. "Culture"
cannot thematize "nature" except as nature-thematized-by-culture; the thing
The Necessity of Paradox 33
anticipation of artworks specially designed for this purpose, only because its
inaccessibility prefigures existential absence. The sacred object's repulsion of the
movement of desire provides the framework for esthetic experience by forcing us
to turn back to the sign; this is the movement of return that will later be generated
by the imaginary referent of the artwork.
In the structure of paradoxical experience in general, it is the subject's turning
back rather than the object's repulsion that is primary. Hence we should not speak
of a "paradox of the sacred" distinct from that of the esthetic. Sacredness is
experienced as really inherent in its incarnation; the return from the latter to the
sign is experienced as the effect, not of the paradoxical sign-referent relation of
signification—in which the referent is always already inhabited by the signing
relation—but of the obstacle of sacred presence. No doubt this presence is itself a
"paradoxical" inherence of the transcendent in the immanent, but when we try to
describe sacred revelation as paradox, we must fall back on the structure of
signification—on the sacred as a form of representation—thereby in effect
eliminating the specificity of the experience of the sacred. Girard's neglect of
language as a primary constituent of the human is no doubt traceable to his
decision to grant primacy to the sacred over the linguistic—in the vocabulary of
The Origin of Language, to institutional over formal representation.
But the esthetic turning back is also a turning forward; the esthetic returns to the
sign, but it also anticipates the defiguration of the referent in the sparagmos (see
Chapter 10). The resentment generated by the return from the object is an
anticipatory movement, however long deferred, of appropriation. The resentful
imagination would linger indefinitely on the margin of the scene of its exclusion;
but exclusion from the center is also the deprivation of what are ultimately
appetitive needs. Hence, within the operation of esthetic deferral, oscillatory
movements in the direction of the center have the marginally greater effect; an
inevitable gradient leads to the sparagmatic consumption of the central object.
Paradox is the form taken within the world of representation by the conflict that
representation was created to avoid. Pragmatic paradox realizes within human
behavior what irony reveals to its detached observer: the impossibility of
maintaining a strict separation between words and things, language and
metalanguage. Just as the mediator cannot designate an arbitrary object to his
disciple without its becoming significant as the object-designated-by-the-
mediator, so the sign cannot designate a referent that is not the referent-
designated-by-the-sign. In the difference between these two homologous
structures lies the specificity of human representation as a means for deferring the
originary crisis of mimesis.
The Necessity of Paradox 35
Logical Paradox
The protoparadoxical stasis in which the subject oscillates between mimetic
attraction and repulsion, between model and obstacle, is the originary state of
crisis that language emerged in order to defer. Likewise, new linguistic forms
emerge as means of resolving paradoxes that arise in the usage of earlier forms. 4
In contrast, logical paradox is the explicit failure to formalize this oscillation in
the detemporalized language of metaphysics. The oscillation that time permits in
the world of experience is incompatible with the consistency required of a logical
system.5 Conversely, no attempt to eliminate paradox from language can retain
the freedom of reference that is an indispensable characteristic of natural
language.
Logical paradox is late in relation to pragmatic paradox, but not simply
derivative of it. Logic, metaphysics' most objective achievement, is not a "cultural
form" like the religious and esthetic forms that find their model in the ostensivity
of the originary scene. Logic can be construed as a pure system invulnerable to
anthropological reflection, on the model of mathematics with which it has so
much in common.6 But the historical function of logic is to serve as a model of
signification relations; because logical propositions presuppose a world that they
are true of, logical systems cannot exclude paradox.
It is in the very nature of logic to be obsessed by and wish to expel paradox; the
protection of form against its dissolution in the chaos of content is the essence of
all cultural operations. But the analogy between logical paradox and Girard's
emissary victim, however illuminating it may be in a broader anthropological
context, is not helpful in the domain of logic itself. The originary hypothesis can
tell us why we are interested in paradox; it cannot supply its own technique of
logical analysis.
Logical systems can be used to construct paradoxical statements because the
Achilles' heel of metaphysics is its inability to prevent the mutual contamination
of form and content, language and reality. The confusion of levels or "logical
types" is unavoidable once language becomes able to take itself as object. Logical
paradox articulates the inevitable interference between language and
metalanguage into a contradictory self-reference, as epitomized by the archetype
of logical paradox, the common denominator of all the others: the Liar paradox—
"This sentence is false."
Negative self-reference is not merely an occasional possibility of language in its
"linguistic universality," its capacity to take anything whatever as its theme. In the
hypothesis of linguistic evolution formulated in The Origin of Language, it is
Paradoxical Thinking 36
the locus of paradox. Although this paradox occurs at a lower level of our
decoding of the sentence from the Liar, this is a sign rather of derivative than of
primitive status. The predicate involved in the barber "who shaves everyone who
doesn't shave himself," or more rigorously,"all those and only those who do not
shave themselves" includes within itself lower-level propositions ("clauses"). The
paradoxes of set theory, which, because of the need to define set membership, are
always constructed from complex predicates of this kind, are not primary
paradoxes of language; their existence is dependent on the prior possibility of
semantic paradoxes.7
Once falsification is permitted, one cannot avoid paradox: one sentence's denial
of the truth of another sentence cannot insure against the vulnerability of its own.
It is no accident that this denial is the basic form of the verbal duel or agon.
"You're a liar!" "You're another!" The symmetry of such dialogues, which tend to
lose their content and degenerate into exchanges of empty accusations, should not
make us forget the essentially "vertical" nature of each assertion with respect to
the preceding one. The series avoids paradox only so long as each speaker
maintains an identity separate from his rival's; paradox arises when A says "You're
a liar!" but B, countering the form rather than the content of his rival's statement,
replies "No you aren't!" Such turn-abouts are a frequent source of comedy
routines. Russell's theory of types would make impossible the agon of verbal
conflict by establishing a strict form-content hierarchy. We could not call each
other liars in typed sentences; I might, but then the you who accuses me in return
does not bear the same index as the you I accused, who has no right to talk about
my language at all. In Russell as in Plato, metaphysics defers conflict through the
establishment of a hierarchy of signs.
In the normal dialogic use of "this sentence is false," "this sentence" would refer
to another sentence than the one being asserted—it might, for example, be
accompanied by a deictic reference to a sentence on the blackboard. No doubt the
ambiguity can be reduced by more explicit specification, as in "the sentence you
are currently reading/hearing is false." But natural language is not equipped for
the unambiguous designation of the sentence one is in the process of speaking or
reading. The ambiguity can never be wholly eliminated without the use of
artificial terminology, and any such specifications would weaken still further the
connection with any conceivable contextual imperative/interrogative. It is
precisely the imposition of decontextualization that produces the self-reference
indispensable to paradox. Just as Oedipus's pragmatic paradoxes stem from the
lack of reference of the notions "rival" or "bride" outside his immediate family,
which is so to speak their original context of enunciation (tout Freud est là), so
logical paradox arises when the declarative sentence is enclosed within such a
Paradoxical Thinking 38
1. The Petersburg paradox is a result of probability theory that for the modern
mathematician is not paradoxical at all. Yet its paradoxical effect exemplifies in
a pragmatic context the same structure as the fundamental human paradoxes of
desire and signification.
It is usually formulated as follows. A player flips a coin until it comes up tails
and is paid according to the number of heads thrown: $1 for no heads, $2 for one,
$4 for two—in the general case, $2n for n heads. This looks at first sight to be a
playable game, comparable to one in which, for instance, the payoff would be $n
for n heads, where the player's expectation would be 1/2+2/4+3/8+ . . . = 2. Yet
simple arithmetic shows that the expectation of 1 + 2/2 + 4/4 . . . is infinite. Thus in
order to make the Petersburg game fair, the player must put up an infinite sum of
money to play even once, a result that is clearly "paradoxical."9
Because of the properties of infinite series, this result could be presented in much
more striking fashion: the payoff could begin only alter the trillionth consecutive
head, at only one trillionth of a cent, and yet the player's expectation would remain
infinite so long as it doubles with each successive head.
Paradoxical Thinking 40
voluntary and contingent on the level of form. Our intuition of paradox is our
reaction to the undecidable self-reflectivity of human representation that is both
the mark of its origin and its guarantee of survival.
4
There are two fundamental conceptions of truth: the ostensive and the
declarative, the truth of faith and the truth of reason. Today's reader is likely to
deny this symmetry; the believer even more than the secular intellectual will reject
the idea that these two "truths" might be discussed in the same context. Yet both
derive, and in that order, from the originary use of language.
Human language does not begin with the declarative sentence, but with the
ostensive. To go beyond the declarative of propositional thought to the ostensive
reference that ultimately founds it is the gesture of originary thinking. This
operation of liberation from the metaphysical "prison-house of language" is not a
romantic return to the nature that stands behind our fallen culture. The ostensive
lies within the realm of human language. Originary thinking liberates thought
from metaphysics by returning it to its minimal presuppositions. Because the
originary moment of thought precedes the declarative, we are not prisoners of the
formal propositions of metaphysics; we may deconstruct them through the
procedure of originary analysis. In revealing the incompleteness of metaphysics,
deconstruction turns us toward anthropological concreteness.
In a language lacking the declarative conception of propositional truth, to
conceive the ostensive that lies behind the declarative is already to "believe" it, to
accept on faith its presence-as-truth. There would be no declarative truth without
ostensive truth; no truth of reason without the truth of faith. This has always been
known by religion, but not in a way that has permitted it to be understood by
Two Varieties of Truth 45
Thus the sign does not represent a certain kind of object, but recognizes an object
that can only be represented. Significance is not a quality independently possessed
by the center that the sign acknowledges, but one attributed by the sign to its
referent in the mode of already belonging to that referent. This is not a
paradoxically circular definition of significance, but a description of the
paradoxically circular procession that constitutes significance. The truth of the
originary sign is neither the correspondence between a preestablished meaning
and an object that fulfills it, nor that between a preestablished significance and a
sign that recognizes it. The usefulness of the notion of "truth" is to thematize the
stability of the relation established by the sign, so that its utterer can stand back
from it and "see that it is good." The truth of the originary sign is the rightness of
the sign-signifying-the-significant or designating-the-designatable, the
designatum as a designandum.
The originary relation between the sign and its object is not transparent to
intuition. It is one that requires thought, that is indeed a defining condition for real
thinking, as opposed to models of ratiocination that can be performed by
computers. Since it is religion rather than metaphysics that has been concerned
with the commemoration of humanity's historical origin, it is not surprising that
the best analogy in traditional cultural practice to the operational identity of the
originary sign is the name-of-God. The originary sign names, in all the ambiguity
of the term—at the same time giving a name to and repeating the name of. The
idea of God is the originary source of this ambiguity; the sign names what is
already worthy to bear the name, what therefore already possesses it, for were it
not already God's name it could not be used to name him. The name-of-God is on
the one hand infinitely "proper," confined to the unique object that occupies the
center, but on the other, it is infinitely generic, designating a central locus that
may ultimately be occupied by anything whatever.2 But as this is understood and
other signs for other referents become available, the generative relationship
between the unique central being and the anything-whatever of significance—
God as the source of language—becomes itself a theme for cultural preservation
in ritual and subsequently in mythical narrative.
Ostensive truth is the result of standing back from signification to view the
"goodness" of its results. This goodness is that of the human community united
by the sign; but it is mediated through the signifying relation to the central object.
The identity of the Word with God and of both with Truth is thematized in the
partial synthesis of metaphysical and religious thought carried out within early
Christianity.
Two Varieties of Truth 47
as though it were a mere dictionary entry because in his eyes it permanently retains
its ostensive force.
The emancipation of meaning from the originary presence of the central locus
passes through the temporal detachment of the imperative before reaching
fulfillment in the transcendental model of the declarative. The open-ended truth
of the imperative corresponds to an overestimation of the power of language over
the world. This truth cannot be counteracted by the world outside language;
instead a new, metalinguistic operation emerges, that of falsification. Instead of
the oscillation, infinite in principle, between the understanding of the meaning of
the imperative and the (inexpressible) renunciation of the attempt to fulfill it, the
subject replies with an "objective" predication of nonfulfillment. With the
declarative comes the notion of propositional truth familiar to philosophy.
Because the declarative provides a model of reality, a predicated "other scene" on
which the desired referent can be found, it can be verified against this reality. That
is, its truth has become independent of its meaning.
linked to the declarative language of reason, let alone shown to constitute its
source.
The late metaphysical working-through begun most visibly by Nietzsche is the
deconstruction of the Platonic separation of ideas and things that is at the
foundation of the metaphysical concept of correspondence-truth. Generative
anthropology traces the emergence of truth through paradox; Continental
metaphysics is uninterested in paradox because it is uninterested in logic, which
can give it no assistance in its task of assimilating the revelatory. Or to put it less
sympathetically, in its effort to assimilate its mimetic intuitions to the laws of
metaphysics, Continental thought has made paradox so much a part of its
connotative pathos that it is unable to stand back from it in order to grasp its
structure.
The effects that dazzled the generation of 1968—largely faded today in the
harsher light of cultural politics—are expressions of the quasi-aporetic situation
of the metaphysical thinker trying to think himself out of metaphysics. That such
a thought process requires a guarantee outside the realm of metaphysics itself is
an idea too dangerous to be entertained, for pushed one step farther it would
destroy the resentful attachment of the deconstructive enterprise to its ancestral
thought-form. The obsession of deconstructive thinking with attacking the father
masks a filial relationship with metaphysics that resembles Hamlet's relationship
with Gertrude more than Oedipus's with Laius.
By recurring to paradox, we abandon the stormy Continent for the dry terrain of
Anglo-Saxon analytic philosophy. The usefulness of this displacement is
strategic; the failure of declarative language to exclude paradoxical statements is
a chink in the armor of metaphysics, one through which, after a little prying, there
appears a glimmer of anthropological light.
Predication
The defining operation of the declarative is predication, the most elementary
form of which is the negative reply to the imperative. Predication, the attribution
of a predicate to a subject or "topic," affirms the validity of a model of reality in
which the subject-topic is declared to inhabit the universe of the predicate. But
the worldly referent does not participate directly in this model, in which the
simplicity of the ostensive truth relation is deferred to a linguistic "other scene."
The declarative is in principle subject to verification through the examination of
the real-world association of subject and predicate. But this verification is not, as
for the ostensive and imperative, implicit in the intentional structure of the form
Paradoxical Thinking 52
Depending on circumstances, I might look out the window to see for myself. But
this empirical act is essentially late with respect to my synthetic understanding of
the meaning of the sentence. The linguistic expression is self-sufficient; its
understanding includes within itself the synthesis that the elementary forms found
and/or created between the word and the world. The confirmation that was
inherent in the linguistic experience of the ostensive and a reality of praxis for the
imperative becomes a secondary truth-verifying operation on the already-
constituted declarative.
We have noted that the gap between the understanding and the verification of
the declarative has the temporality of deferral. The originary utterance of the
ostensive sign deferred conflict over the central object by substituting a sign that
all could possess for a thing that had become inaccessible. The declarative doubles
this linguistic process by proposing a second sign—the predicate—that locates
the object within a linguistic model. This model is in principle verifiable; all
language eventually leads back to the world. But verification is no longer
contained within the intentional structure of the linguistic form itself. On the
contrary, the deferral of verification is central to its intention; to test the linguistic
model against reality is to reopen the potential for conflict inherent in the
unfulfillment of the original imperative. Verification provokes interpersonal
tension because it demonstrates worldly desire's dissatisfaction with the merely
linguistic response that the declarative provides.
We may distinguish between two kinds of verification of the predicate, only the
second of which really merits the name. In the originary case, the hearer of the
declarative performs the verification as a prolongation of his former imperative,
that is, in order to fulfill his intention of acquiring the object. As a result of the
information conveyed by the declarative, the original speaker is better equipped
to find the object he seeks. This form of verification does not question the veracity
of the predicate, but merely seeks to transcend the predicative situation toward the
topic about which the predicate supplies new information. The second kind is
carried out independently of praxis because the speaker's predication is suspected
of being false. The first case contains the second nonthematically; my need to act
on the information tests its truth as a matter of course. Conversely, the expulsion
of the practical concern of originary verification by the second form coincides
with the establishment of metaphysical philosophy, the love of wisdom for its own
sake.
The thematic notion of truth emerges when the two types of verification are
recognized as distinct, so that disbelief in the predication is distinguished from
mere dissatisfaction with predication as a response to the imperative. At this point,
Paradoxical Thinking 54
the declarative has become an acceptable answer to the imperative, which has
become a de facto interrogative. Only if the predicate is false does it now bear a
potential for conflict; if true, its speaker would presumably have nothing to fear
from his interlocutor's disappointment.
Verification in the first case, that performed out of impatience to possess the
referent, dismisses the specific pertinence of the declarative at the same time as it
makes use of the information it imparts. It avoids conflict by substituting the first
interlocutor for the second in the performance of his own imperative. The
association of the (ostensive) sign with its referent in the immediate mode of
presence has been stretched to the limit, but it has not been broken. The second
case, however, introduces the possibility of untruth where in the first we could
still speak of "inappropriateness." The untrue predicate does not designate an
absent presence, a locus in which the referent may be found; it hides a definitive
absence. What is significant is not untruth itself but the predicate's suspicious
potential for untruth, its fundamental fictionality.7 Not only is language capable
of misleading, but even when true, it constructs a fictional world separate from
reality. But this gives no comfort to the superficial postmodern tendency to use
the fictionality of the declarative as an excuse to ignore its correspondence with
the real. On the contrary, it is precisely its fictionality that makes the declarative
the locus of a new form of truth.
Truth is the result of the secondary deferral accomplished by predication, of the
gap between understanding the predicate and verifying it. The predicate
depresentifies; to make present the depresentified takes real time. In the
meantime, the status of the predicate remains unclear. We justifiably call it
fictional—and the in principle indefinite deferral of correspondence-truth implied
by this term is precisely what permits the existence of esthetic fictions—so long
as we remember that fiction is from the beginning the deferral of truth; one has
no conceptual existence without the other.8
Since declarative truth is in essence deferred, not present in the utterance itself,
it cannot foreclose the possibility of the radical form of fictionality we call
paradox. The deferral of empirical verification risks being usurped by a form that
transforms the fictional hesitation between truth and falsity into an oscillation in
which understanding itself, made to depend on this verification, is indefinitely
deferred. Yet to consider paradox a danger to language is perversely to ignore that
the source of all logical paradox is the formal verticality of representation that
defers the originary protoparadox of mimesis, the antinomy of imitation and
rivalry.
Two Varieties of Truth 55
On Irony
The standard treatises on rhetoric tell us that the figure of irony consists in saying
the opposite of what one means. For example, Pierre Fontanier's Figures du
discours (1827): "L'ironie consiste à dire . . . le contraire de ce qu'on pense, ou de
ce qu'on veut faire penser" [Irony consists in saying . . . the contrary of what one
thinks, or of what one would have one's interlocutor think];1 or as my (American
Heritage) dictionary puts it, "The intended meaning of the words used is the direct
opposite of their usual sense." One might wonder what could be the possible use
of such a figure, why anyone should bother to express an idea by affirming its
direct opposite. Yet the expression "the irony of fate" suggests a direct connection
between the catastrophic occurrence of "the direct opposite" of one's expectations
and the opposition between the words of the ironic tenor and vehicle. And we
designate by the expression "romantic irony" an attitude toward life that consists
not so much in anticipating the opposite of one's expectations as in a knowing
superiority to the ironies of fate that await us in the real world.
Irony attends us everywhere, always gifted with prestige, although its association
with meaning makes the term sound just a bit quaint in comparison with such
postmodern terms as différance or scriptible. No mere figure of speech, irony is
central to all thought, for the use of language as such is essentially ironic. The
Greek eiron is the (apparent) fool, the dissembler, but the root of the word is the
same as that (eiro, from IE * wer→word) of speech itself.
*
The idea that one can mean the contrary of what one (ostensibly) says, that a sign
can be made to bear the opposite of its normal sense, is clearly dependent on the
prior existence of a sign-system. But it would be metaphysical naïveté to affirm
that irony is inherent in sign-systems-in-general, as though irony existed
independently of human forms of representation. Irony is a characteristic of the
On Irony 57
How does this anthropological concept of irony square with the standard
rhetorical definition? To say the opposite of what one means is not so simple a
phenomenon as the words make it appear. Not all statements have "opposites";
nor is the ground of opposition simply logical. Were irony a mere matter of
reversing truth value, it would be impossible to detect and would in fact make
language wholly indeterminate; the assertion of any proposition p would also be
the ironic assertion of not-p. Clearly this is not the way irony works.
If I look out the window and see that it is raining, it would not be ironic to say
"It's not raining"—unless this statement repeats a previously made claim that my
observation would falsify. ("No, it's not raining! Those raindrops are just figments
of my imagination!") The normal ironic remark would be something like "What a
lovely day!" This remark requires no preestablished context because fair or
"good" weather is normatively felt to be desirable. My irony expresses
disappointment; I would like to be able to say "What a lovely day!"3 sincerely,
but under the circumstances I can only say it ironically. My words reflect my
desire, but at the same time, through a change in tone, they are "quoted" rather
than asserted, so that I am merely pronouncing the (ostensive) phrase in the
absence of its referent. My language points to the rain but declares it to be
sunshine.
We recall from the preceding chapter or from The Origin of Language that this
is precisely the intentional structure of the derivation of the imperative from the
ostensive: the ostensive, which normally designates a referent actually present to
the speaker, is uttered in the absence of such a referent in order to make it appear.
This intention depends on a magical conception of ostensive language: since the
word is pronounced only in the presence of the object, pronouncing the word
alone is expected to produce the object. In the ironic situation, we know better.
Saying "What a lovely day!" is not going to put an end to the rain. It expresses my
disappointment; but the focus of this disappointment is less that the weather is
contrary to my wishes than that my language is unable to alter it. The hierarchy
of form over content, words over things, by means of which the imperative is
derived from the ostensive, has no effect on the things themselves. This is a
reproach directed against the originary project of language, which in the case of
the weather may easily enough be attributed to the will of God. The ironic sign
expresses originary resentment, the human reaction to the withdrawal of the center
that language both commemorates and supplements. Irony makes explicit the
resentment that is at the heart of all language, the disappointment of the originary
aborted gesture that reveals itself in the sparagmos once the danger that blocked
the gesture's original aim is past.
On Irony 59
We do not ironize when faced with the real power of the sacred center to defer
human conflict. But whatever the flourishes of the cosmological imagination, this
power is not transferable to the natural world; God lets it rain on the just as on the
unjust, which is really to say that he can do nothing for or against either. By our
irony we reject ad maiorem Dei gloriam this attribution of impotence to God,
implicitly reproaching him with deliberately choosing not to grant our wish for
sunny skies. In demonstrating the impotence of language to grant our wishes, we
at the same time imply that the Being who gave us language does not lack the
power to do so, with the result that we are justifiably dissatisfied when this Being
does not use this power for our benefit.
The pleasure of irony is truly an esthetic pleasure, functioning through the same
oscillatory movement as esthetic experience between ascetic form and seductive
content. The fact that I can express my wish and imagine its fuffillment depends
on the unreality of this fulfillment. My subsequent ironic statement is an ex post
facto "artwork" that is given form by the preexistent denial of my desire—a desire
that need not even have been previously formulated. By exclaiming "What a
lovely day!" I transform the simple frustration of my implicit desire for clear skies,
scarcely more than an appetite, into an esthetic experience that "drowns" my
resentment of the central power from which I am excluded. Who has not
experienced the disappointment of having one's ironic outburst voided by the
sudden realization of one's purported wish? If the rain immediately ceased, could
the sunlight be bright enough to compensate me for the vanished pleasure of
irony? The ironist is a masochist; his proof of being is furnished by suffering.
Rather than an expression of divine favor, the reappearance of the sun would be
for him a demonstration that God does not exist.
On the one hand, irony demonstrates our independence from the constraints of
the sign-referent hierarchy: form cannot dictate to content, language has no
ontological privilege with respect to reality. On the other, by its very expression,
irony resentfully affirms the authority of the form it has denied. The ironic
deconstruction of the hierarchy between words and things pays homage to this
hierarchy by implying that it presides over its own deconstruction. By pretending
that my words are not powerless to realize my desires, I confront the scene of
representation with my own powerlessness as a reproach, as though the power
were available but arbitrarily withheld. This withholding is what provides the
peaceful resolution of the originary event; but now it no longer appears to be
necessary, since all I desire is a nice day. (Think how strange—and unironic—it
would be if the object of my desire were openly conflictive or resentful. Only in
a world of black comedy can someone say ironically, "Nice torturing, Bob!" to an
Paradoxical Thinking 60
Romantic Irony
The world's failure to meet the ironist’s expectations becomes proof of his
victimary centrality. The historical origin of this phenomenon is in Rousseau's
Rêveries, which begin with the immortal words, "Me voici donc seul sur la terre,
n'ayant plus de frère, de prochain, d'ami, de société que moi-même. Le plus
sociable et le plus aimant des humains en a été proscrit par un accord unanime"
[Here I am, then, alone on earth, deprived of brother, neighbor, friend, any social
contact other than myself. The most sociable and loving of men has been banished
from society by a unanimous agreement]. The romantic subject's worldly role of
hapless victim hides a divine self-consciousness for which the worldly separation
between form and content, sign and thing is an illusion. This is not yet an ironic
position. Because the romantic recognizes that qua human subject he contains
within himself the totality of the scene, the center as well as the periphery, he is
content to smile down from above on the follies of human praxis, without
considering that these follies include his own since he too is forced to live in the
world.
Romantic irony is a "late," second-generation phenomenon that in France
corresponds to the disillusionment of the failed romantic revolution of 1848. Even
when the first-generation romantic—speaking not just for himself but for the
whole of humanity—utters ironically, "What a lovely day!" he is not yet a
romantic ironist. Chateaubriand or Hugo say such things, not Baudelaire or
Kierkegaard. The early romantics fail to see the contradiction between the formal
superiority over the world conferred on them by the sign and their use of the sign
in futile contestation of the forms of worldly superiority. The romantic ironist
knows that his extraworldly stance makes him complicit in the worldly iniquities
he denounces. He more than anyone is aware of the fragility of ontological
hierarchies, which all begin from the hierarchy of signs and things. Thus the
On Irony 61
Olympian posture of the romantic ironist is itself ironized—which does not mean
that it is abolished. The writer of the lines
Tu le connais, lecteur, ce monstre délicat
Hypocrite lecteur, mon semblable, mon frère!4
has in no way renounced the privilege of the writer's position. What he derides is
the reader's complicity with this position, and his own complicity with that
complicity. Baudelaire mocks us all for pretending that language can transcend
reality, and that he as the writer can use language to transcend even that
transcendence.
As opposed to the naive romantic, the victim of the mensonge romantique, the
romantic ironist is aware of the nonoriginality of worldly desire. Nor is it fair to
condemn his transcendental stance as mere illusion when it displays the
understanding that he is condemned within the world to imitate the very conduct
he has unmasked. The romantic ironist grasps from above the unity of the scene
that he cannot experience in the world. His is an authentic mode of
anthropological thought.
Romantic irony is not immediately dependent on language because the subject
no longer identifies himself as a mere peripheral language speaker; his
participation in the scene of representation is central and originary. Romantic
irony plays on the contrast between material triviality and spiritual importance;
the individual is powerless, ignored, yet a possessor of the whole through the
intermediary of the sign. This is Pascal's roseau pensant in a secular world; irony
is as close as the late romantic will come to a belief in divine providence.
things is merely a deferral, a différance, that form offers only a distraction, not a
barrier, against the chaos of indifferentiation.
In the terminology of The End of Culture, popular art takes the attitude of
consumption rather than production. This point may be sharpened by reference to
the sparagmos as satisfying not only alimentary appetite but originary resentment.
The individual both participates in the collective disfigurement of the central
object and acquires his own portion of it. In the former respect, the sparagmos is
a success; the central figure is indeed destroyed. Insofar as I feel myself a mere
member of the collectivity, my resentment against the center has been fully
satisfied. But as an individual defined in a one-on-one relationship with the center,
my satisfaction is concentrated in my individual portion, which bears to the central
figure as a whole the same paradoxical dependence/independence relationship as
the sign to its referent: the part expresses the power of the center only because of
the totality that was destroyed in order for the part to come into existence. As a
representation, the part is ironically superior to the whole, but only because the
reality of the whole is prior to that of the part. Popular art expresses the collective
satisfaction of the sparagmos as though there were nothing to mourn for in the
destruction of the originary totality, as though there were no more to the individual
than his existence among the "people," whereas the irony of high art reflects the
individual's paradoxical relationship with the totality that must be destroyed in
order for him to possess it.
The irony of fate does not require language in order to manifest itself, but it is
only understandable through a representational lens; the pursuit of the train is an
allegory of desire-in-general. To obtain one's desire is fatal—this is the deepest
irony of tragedy, that of Oedipus.
We may define tragic irony more precisely. The tragic situation is the reductio
ad absurdum of mimesis, the failure of representation. Oedipus is so mimetic that
he no longer understands that mimesis is representational. He can only imitate by
literally usurping the other's place. Hence at every turn, when Oedipus seeks
otherness, he arrives at sameness. He leaves home—but he returns home. He
abandons his mother—but he finds his mother. The irony of the Oedipus recurs
again and again to the failure of initiation, the impossibility of finding an object
outside the family circle, of transforming the specificity of family reality into a
representation of behavior in general. Language cannot provide its usual
assistance in avoiding conflict because for Oedipus the universe of representation
is ironically indistinguishable from the life-world. The sign cannot realize its
ontological privilege of detachment from the referent.
Hence when Oedipus condemns the murderer, it is himself whom he condemns.
This is sometimes presented as a failure of "intelligence"; as with the man who
catches the doomed train, Oedipus's fabled reasoning powers only help realize the
oracle's prediction. Thought is always ironic, that is, it deconstructs vertical
difference into horizontal sameness; but this very fact makes thought useless to
one whose desire is confined within the scene about which he thinks. All I learn
from thinking my categorical desire for women cannot help me understand my
specific desire for my mother.
Irony performs the same function in tragedy as in the simple scene of "What a
lovely day!" but tragedy shows us that the impotence of representational
difference can have more dangerous consequences than the frustration of desire.
In revealing the ultimate common source of form and content, sign and referent,
sacred and profane, ontic and ontological, tragedy represents, and thus again
defers, the failure of deferral, the inevitability of conflict. The extraordinary
stability of language and representational systems that permits us to appreciate
three-thousand-year-old texts and thirty-thousand-year-old paintings is due to the
resiliency of the paradoxical structure of signification, of which irony is the
experiential component.
Irony is more fundamental than the esthetic effect, which should be considered
a particular form of irony. It is the fundamental cultural mode or "trope" because
all culture is grounded in nature, the hylé, where the sign and the referent are cut
from the same cloth. Reconstruction inhabits structure from the beginning; irony
Paradoxical Thinking 64
continually knits up what it has undone, as is the case for the whole family of
paradoxical structures that make up the human. Irony both points out and repairs
the inadequacy of the deferral of violence through representation that is the
essence of human culture. Ultimately all formal difference breaks down, but we
can only learn this from within a new formal difference that has not yet broken
down. The ironies of tragedy can only be contemplated in a state of ironic—but
untragic—repose.
Irony removes the security of the sign and returns us to originary chaos, but this
chaos is accessible only through a system of representation that remains intact.
Our sympathy with the victims of tragic irony does not prevent us from knowing
that it isn't really a lovely day, or from knowing the true identity of Laius's
murderer. This is the vulnerable point of tragedy and of the esthetic/ironic in
general as a model for anthropological understanding. Tragedy's insight into the
inevitable dangers of human indifferentiation leads it ultimately to reaffirm—
however ironically—the arbitrary victimizations it inherits from its mythical
sources. Its demystifications are always finite and ultimately self-liquidating.
The esthetic depends on finitude, spatio-temporal decisiveness, however
arbitrary. To remain undecided within the symmetry of the agon is to renounce
art’s formal promise to defer our resentment. We identify with the hero on the
level of content while we await his demise on the level of form; it is this ironic,
paradoxical structure that has made human culture capable of lasting as long as it
has. All the post-sacrificial wisdom of the Gospels cannot prevent the Passion
narrative from taking on the very tragic structure it denounces. The secret of the
historical success of Christianity lies in this paradox, not in the eternal truth of the
moral Kingdom that shares the fragility of all utopias.
Irony is built into the formal representation-relation that is the basis of human
culture. In this sense, it is truly a transhistorical phenomenon, one that annuls its
own historicity in the very act of producing it. Not that irony does not have its
own history as a cultural mode. From classical tragedy to romantic melodrama,
the cultural subject anticipates through representation the demise of the scenic
center, but his efforts to escape its fate only encounter the same ironic structure
on a higher plane. Postmodern culture takes ironic anticipation to a still higher
level, where the very reality of the sign-referent relation is denied in advance. But
this denial, in its formal abstraction, changes nothing essential; regardless of
wisdom or cynicism, in order for the esthetic to function, we must experience
irony through our own lived illusion and disillusion.
On Irony 65
*
Does generative anthropology, in laying out explicitly the paradox of cultural
form, escape deconstruction through irony, or does it fall subject to the facile but
suggestive schema of Paul de Man's Blindness and Insight, where each insightful
demystification has its own blind spot? The best answer is that like all cultural
operations, generative anthropology works not by dichotomy but by deferral.
Unless we believe in the chimera of the "end of history," we are forced to
anticipate a future understanding of irony and paradox (which may not necessarily
use the terms "irony" and "paradox") from the standpoint of which our own
analysis is structurée without being structurante. In contrast with de Man's
schema, which is, like everything else in his work, a radically nihilistic denial of
history, our model respects the human labor, material and intellectual, that the
resiliency of our cultural structures permits us to carry out. The continual deferral
of our ever-present propensity for self-destruction is the highest or, in any case,
the most necessary of human achievements. May God, or the ironic contemplation
of his absence, save us from the utopian search for final solutions.
6
For over a century, thought has attempted to free itself from metaphysics.1 A
certain philosophical postmodernity has declared this a vain endeavor, having
decided that metaphysics is the indispensable form of any coherent reflection. Yet
since humanity existed before metaphysics, we should be able to survive its
demise. It suffices that we oppose to it a form of thought sufficiently powerful to
be able to think both its beginning and its end.
Primitive, egalitarian societies function by means of ritual distribution systems
guaranteed by the symmetrical differentiations of mythical speech. With the
appearance of social hierarchy, the mastery of ritual distribution becomes fixed in
one place and refuses to circulate; the new task of cultural language is to justify
this disequilibrium. But in the society of the "Greek miracle" that arises in the
margins of the archaic empires, the accelerated circulation of goods and ideas
loosens hierarchical rigidity and gives language a competitive value. The Sophists
learn to manipulate speech for the purpose of persuasion. Yet, whether out of
indifference or self-interest, they do not seek the a priori conditions of this
manipulation; language is for them simply a tool in the hands of man who claims
to be "the measure of all things."
The Concept as Ethical Content
Following Socrates, Plato understands that "free" speech, far from being
gratuitous, is the sign of a new, implicit ethical order. In order to understand this
order, it is necessary to reflect not on what language refers to but on what it
signifies to the community. We may roughly express this distinction by
contrasting the ensemble of worldly referents of a word (its "denotation" in
Plato and Conceptual Thought 67
analytic philosophy) with its "signified" or meaning (its "connotation"). But for
Plato, the latter is not an abstract meaning but a substantial content that the users
of the word possess in common. The intuition that the usage of certain words
reveals an ethical content that is more than an abstract signification is the very
foundation of philosophical reflection. This intuition is already implicitly that of
the Socrates of the early dialogues, and was no doubt that of the historical figure
who irritated his contemporaries by forcing them to define courage, beauty,
friendship, and the like. It is by deepening his understanding of the content of
words that Plato will transform Socrates' open interrogations into conceptual
thought, which is only another name for metaphysics.
In order to grasp the ethical point of departure for this way of thinking, let us
listen to the debate between Socrates and Callicles in the Gorgias:
1. [Callicles:] For by nature the ugliest thing is also the worst: to suffer injustice;
whereas it is only because of the law that it is worse to commit it….
Unfortunately, it is the weak and the masses who have created the laws….They
say that it is unjust to wish to have more than the others.... For, as they are
inferior, it suffices for them to have equality! (482abc)
What is by nature beautiful and just, is that . . . he who wants to live his life
rightly must… give to each desire that may come upon him its fullness of
satisfactions…. Should they who are able to enjoy without restraint all that is
good pose as a master over themselves what is decreed . . . by the multitude?....
Sensuality, license, unreserved freedom . . . that is virtue and happiness! (491e,
492c)
2. [Socrates:] But [the pleasures] that are good, are they also those that are
useful….? Now, pleasures as well as pains, it is those that are useful that one
must choose and practice? [Thus] it is for the sake of good things…. that we
should do everything…. Do you not agree…. that the good is, without exception,
the end of all our acts and that it is for the purpose of the good that all the rest
must be done, but not the good for the purpose of the rest… ? Is it not therefore
for the purpose of good things that one should carry out all acts, including those
that are pleasant, but not the good for the purpose of the pleasant? (499de, 500a)
For Callicles, to satisfy one's desires, assuming one can get away with it, is a
clearer path to happiness than obedience to the law, which this proto-Nietzschean
sees as the instrument of domination by the weak over the strong. All other things
being equal, the "unjust" person who disobeys the law to promote his own
satisfaction has the advantage over his obedient opposite number. But the unjust
does evil, and evil is harmful, whence Socrates demonstrates that no one can
knowingly be unjust. No one can intend the harmful, therefore knowingly do evil,
Paradoxical Thinking 68
even if the harmful is "pleasant." Any conflict on this point is not real but illusory,
an error of ignorance.
Of the two arguments, it is rather Socrates' that strikes us as contrived. The
question Socrates avoids is how he knows that "the good" is always the same for
all. In the practical (ontic) world, the concepts of good and evil are "indexed";
what is good for me is not necessarily good for you. Indeed, if my good and your
good involve the possession of an identical object—a person we both love, an
honor we both covet—the two goods cannot be identical. This is the very structure
of mimetic rivalry. We will not be able to avert conflict merely by pronouncing
some magic word ("good,""just," or "beautiful") as we might the name of a god
in a rite.
There is nothing sacred in the words themselves. Plato's new sacred is the
concept. At the time of the Gorgias, the Eidos/Idea/Form has not yet been
conceived. But what Plato has already discovered is that the concept of the Good,
to which the Just and the Beautiful are related (and which ancient philosophy
never really distinguishes from it), contains something more than the meaning of
the word. The eirenic sharing of the concept that founds the identity of your good
with mine is not a product of the meaning of the word "good," but of its ethical
content, a notion explainable only within the framework of an originary
anthropology.
Plato's doctrine of the good-as-concept, the decisive moment of the forgetting of
the sacred-ontological denounced by Heidegger, is not yet fully developed at the
time of this not altogether persuasive refutation of the anti-idea of Callicles. When
the latter's argument is taken up again by Thrasymachus in Book I of the Republic,
the insufficiency of the old answer of the Gorgias motivates the displacement of
the subject, in the sense of the Subject of the Good, from the individual human
soul to the political collectivity. The capstone of Socrates' argument is that "no
ruling authority works for his own benefit, but . . . for the benefit of him who is
under his authority" (346e). This is the beginning of a necessary but incomplete
return to the communal origin of the Idea, where alone the notion of a commonly
possessed, conflict-deferring content makes sense.
What separates us from Plato is supposedly his "realism." But the reality of the
Ideas is nothing but what we have been calling their "content." Let us forget for a
moment the heaven where the Ideas with a capital "I" are supposed to dwell. Their
reality has a more concrete meaning, which the lesson of the Gorgias can help us
to uncover. A "real" idea is an idea that intervenes in reality between desiring
beings. It is an apotropaic object that serves to defer potential conflict. The reality
of the Idea is the substantiality that makes it capable of replacing the thing that
Plato and Conceptual Thought 69
provokes the conflict. It is because Callicles and Socrates possess in common the
Idea of justice that they cannot rationally come to blows. Those who do are only
the ignorant who do not possess the Idea, or rather, who are unaware that they do
so.
The concept is a representation; ultimately, nothing more than a word. But the
word is not a simple duplicate of the thing. The thing is unique, or, to speak more
prudently, reproducible with difficulty. The word is multiple, or, let us say,
reproducible with ease. Where we would have to divide the thing, we can share
the totality of the word. Where, between you and me, the good-as-thing would
pose a problem, the good-as-word would not; it is neither your word nor mine,
but everyone's. As though a word could replace reality, the cynic will object. But
it can, on the condition that the good-as-word acquire the reality that will
transform it into a concept, that is, an entity of another order, which is, like the
word, infinitely shareable but which, being substituted for the good-as-thing,
stands in the path of conflictual desire.
the sacred difference attached to the scenic center. This prolongation, this
fetishizing of the word in its difference from the thing, is an alternative, equivalent
characterization of metaphysics.
In our hypothetical originary scene, the role of language is reduced to its strict
minimum: the momentary hesitation between the (chaotic) beginning and the
(minimally ordered) end of an act of collective appropriation. The minimal
linguistic act is the re-presentation of an already-present object by means of an
ostensive sign that will preserve the memory of the object after its disappearance.
The ostensive word is not yet a concept; it is the name of an object-in-situation, a
phenomenon that we can no doubt better understand as the "name of God."2 It is
by means of the ostensive that we teach words to children; they subsequently learn
to use these words as imperatives to make appear objects designated in their
absence, and finally to construct "complete sentences," that is, declaratives. In the
declarative sentence, language achieves its mature capacity to create imaginary
models on the "other scene" of representation. We may then give a preliminary
definition of the concept as the word/noun understood as necessarily an element
of a declarative sentence, cut off from the original act of naming. ("Noun," like
"name," comes from the Latin nomen.) Metaphysics, by denying the existence of
an utterance-form more primitive than the declarative, incarnates the refusal to
think the origin of language as an event.
This metaphysical sacrifice of the elementary linguistic structures institutes
"logocentrism" in the precise sense of domination by the declarative sentence or
proposition, the strong meaning of the word logos. It is this, rather than the
strategic marginalization of writing, that is the founding expulsion of Western
philosophy. The ostensive exists only in situation; spoken or written, it cannot
detach itself from the place in which it is uttered. The arrow on the signpost, the
sign on a door of the toilet constitute an ostensive form of writing that presupposes
on the part of its reader the same (virtual) copresence with the referent as the living
word. The inaugural gesture of metaphysics, which makes possible analytic
thought, suppresses the ostensive that attaches us to the trace of the historical
presence we continue to commemorate under the name of God. The concept, the
Platonic Idea, is something we all possess without having to point to it, that is,
without needing to perform the ostensive sign that defers potential conflict among
those who covet the same object. It is not in its role as a grammatical form that
the ostensive is dangerous. What is protected against by its exclusion (and not
merely from grammar books) is the renewal of its originary function of
designating the sacred center of the communal circle.
Plato and Conceptual Thought 71
The fundamental circular structure of ritual reveals the connection, not obvious
in the abstract, between ostensive language and religion. The oft-repeated notion
that philosophical logocentrism is in complicity with religion misunderstands the
communal operation of the sacred. Traditional metaphysics redefines the sacred
in its own terms as a "first principle," as though the universe itself were deduced
from a master proposition. The logos of the conceptual sacred of metaphysics,
whose gods, beginning with the demiurge in the Timaeus, have never been
worshiped by anyone, is not the logos of the historical religions. The deferred,
discursive presence that presides over metaphysics is not the real presence that
the rite claims to realize. The ostensive is banished by the linguistics of the
philosophers, who replace faith in the divine presence it designates by confidence
in the self-presence of philosophical language.3
The two logoi, that of religion and that of metaphysics, the one that refers to
originary revelation and the other that denies it, can only be reconciled in the
discourse of originary anthropology. There is, however, a fundamental parallelism
between the conceptual "forgetting of Being" inaugurated by metaphysics and the
new, similarly "declarative" conception of the name of the divinity that a few
centuries earlier in Judea had become the point of departure for a religious
revolution. Their common replacement of predeclarative linguistic structures by
the declarative sentence establishes between Hebrew religion and Greek
metaphysics the founding homology of Western culture.
I have proposed elsewhere an exegesis of the ehyeh asher ehyeh by which God
names himself to Moses in Exodus 3.4 By refusing the ostensive-imperative name
by which the divinity can be called, Moses liberates his people from the sacrificial
system that commands divine presence. God is the central being of the scene of
representation that survives the disappearance of the central object of the originary
scene; in the terms of Originary Thinking, he is the subsistence of the central locus
of the scene remembered as a being. In Exodus, the divine being, whose concrete
origin is recalled by the ritual fire of the burning bush, becomes "transcendental,"
detaching itself from any specific historical locus. But this detachment itself is an
event that takes place in a specific historical locus. The liberation provided by
revelation has the strength and the weakness of never being able to deny its
historicity. The two "universal" religions born from Judaism, Christianity and
Islam, remain as attached as their ancestor to a historical place of foundation.
To eliminate the ostensive is to expunge the local historicity of the deferral of
collective violence by means of the sign. The originary opposition between center
and periphery that founds and is founded by language is the source and model of
all the great philosophical dichotomies: word and thing, form and content, Idea
Paradoxical Thinking 72
and copy, ontological and ontic, and so forth. But if all these oppositions are
already latent in the sign as such, it is only from the time of the declarative
sentence that they can be thematically expressed. To understand a declarative
sentence, one situates it on an "other scene" that is not a simple prolongation of
the present scene but a mental scene inhabited by imaginary objects.
The Mosaic revelation distances the corporeal presence of the divinity that was
formerly accessible to invocation by means of the imperative. But in contrast to
metaphysics, religion cannot demand the exclusiveness of the declarative. The
God who names himself "esoterically" as a sentence (ehyeh asher ehyeh) in
Exodus 3 consents, in a second "exoteric" moment in Exodus 6, to condense this
sentence into a single word/name (YHVH).5 This inversion of the historical order
of linguistic evolution is analogous to that of the grammar books, which define
the imperative as a "transformation" of the declarative.
But whereas the inversion of the grammars is a simple forgetting of linguistic
origin, that brought about in Exodus puts linguistic form in a dialectical
relationship with the divine will, for which it proposes a paradigmatic model. To
the request for a (magical) name, the answer is a sentence, which is only then
recondensed into a (religious) name. The God who maintains himself in the "other
world" chooses to manifest himself to a man, to let himself be called by him. Our
knowledge of God's choice determines the nature of our address; we are no longer
commanding God but appealing to him.
pious, like all the other virtues in the Socratic dialogues, is indistinguishable from
the just (dikaion); the consequence is to eliminate from religion the very revealed
element through which it preserves humanity's originary historicity.
For anyone who takes religion seriously, it is the divine will that determines what
is pious and not the reverse. The god who would be satisfied with the Platonic
definition of piety is one no longer capable of being worshiped. The fact that the
metaphysical God has no proper name—not even the sentence-name revealed by
Moses—is an indication of this. The philosophical divinity covers over a profound
contradiction: he is a person-subject possessed of a will, yet this will, like the
content of the Platonic concept, never reveals itself in any specific time or place.
It is by means of this construction that metaphysics conjures away the
paradoxicality of its "declarative" sacred.
Plato's God is a weapon against the narrow humanism of the Sophists, which he
interprets as a radical individualism, indeed, an anarchism incompatible with
maintenance of the social order. For the Plato of the Theaetetus, he who affirms
that "man is the measure of all things" would deny all values that transcend the
individual. In the face of this danger, Plato relocates the foundation of the human
community outside of it, but this "outside" is no longer revealed in the localized
history of religious revelation. In this manner, he creates the no-man's-land that
metaphysics will inhabit for over twenty centuries—that it has not yet abandoned.
The Euthyphro is the only Platonic dialogue in which the argument is directed
not at the opinions or attitudes of the interlocutor but at a specific act, an event of
ethical significance. Euthyphro accuses his father of having brought about the
death of a thête or dependent (of Euthyphro), who suffocated when the father had
had him bound and imprisoned because this dependent had himself been guilty of
the murder of a slave (of the father). Socrates is surprised that the death for which
Euthyphro is requesting punishment was not that of a member of his family: only
this would justify so great a lack of filial respect. Thus Plato gives us to understand
that the father's murder of a murderer through negligence should be left without
punishment. No doubt the piety that demands this punishment is mechanical,
formalistic, blind respect for tradition rather than true justice deserving of divine
approval. Nonetheless, a man has perished. The traditional piety of Euthyphro
recognizes in its own way, by speaking of "pollution" (miasma), a disequilibrium
that Plato prefers not to acknowledge. In the place of the old logic of pollution,
which obliged Orestes to appear before the Areopagus even though he too had
only requited a murder, philosophy substitutes a logic of neutralization. In either
case, we fall short of a moral judgment that views any murder as a crime against
human reciprocity.
Paradoxical Thinking 74
Socrates slips from the idea that the name is made necessary by the impermanence
of things to the idea that the name must "signify a movement and a translation,"
that is, that rather than imposing its stability on the flux of things, the name must
itself be a model of the thing-in-movement that it designates.
But if this is the point, then it is easy enough to find examples of word/things
that are "immobile." The still-ostensive name of Heraclitus thus becomes the
conceptual name of Plato, which expresses or "contains" the quintessence of an
action—movement or the stopping of movement—attributed to the thing by
Socrates' fantastic etymology. His first example of an "immobile" word says it all:
it is the word epistémè (knowledge), which he would derive from histesin epi ("[it]
stops on"), "the sign that knowledge 'stops' our soul 'on' things" (437a). In order
to refute the Heraclitean who claims that knowledge has a stable existence only
in relation to the instability of the things to which it refers, Plato derives the very
name of "knowledge" from the already-theorized action of knowledge-that-
arrests-movement; like the God of Exodus, he arrives at the name only by the
detour of the sentence.
The endpoint of Plato's reasoning is the demonstration that, since nothing in the
words themselves could universally impose a revelation of their referents as being
either in movement or in repose, our sole source of knowledge concerning the
accuracy of words is the things (ta prâgmata) themselves. But it is precisely at the
moment in which Plato abandons words for things that he discovers the
fundamental relationship between the word and the thing it designates. For the
deconstruction of the originary opposition between the stable word and the
unstable thing does not for all that render the things of this world capable of
offering to the word the solid basis that would permit it to function within a
semantic system. Once the semiotics of Cratylus-Heraclitus has been refuted by a
declarative conception of language, Plato finds himself obliged to present a stable
correlative for language that would not only be other than things-in-movement,
but of another nature from them. As he puts it, in order that there be knowledge,
there must exist not only beautiful and good things, but something that would be
"beautiful and good in itself" ( ti . . . autô kalén kai agathôn,439C).
It is thus upon the stability of the signified that Plato constructs his theory of
knowledge. Heraclitus, in remarking that things constantly "translate" themselves,
would not have been able to think that this state of flux makes them incapable of
functioning as correlatives of the linguistic sign. Heraclitean ostensive nomination
depends in fact on a subjacent sacred model. The originary ostensive is not the
name of an impermanent thing, but the name of permanence itself—the name of
God. To rid himself of the sacred Being that lurks within the Heraclitean flux,
Plato and Conceptual Thought 77
Plato must ground the sign not upon its worldly referent but upon the signified,
which is by nature in a state of extraworldly repose.7 The impermanence of each
beauty is unimportant, provided that the Beautiful remain in place.
Plato is the first real theoretician of signification. Without the signified, there
can be no linguistic sign; Plato was the first to understand this capital fact, the
foundation of all semiotics.8 But metaphysics is not content to be a theory of the
sign, nor a fortiori a linguistics; it wants to found an ontology. The signified
"beautiful" will consequently be transported beyond the region of perishable
things to become the Form-Idea "the Beautiful."
Plato realizes that language cannot be explained on the basis of ontological
monism. The word is something other than the thing, and not merely another
variety of thing (an "imitation" like that of the artisan, for example). But lacking
the possibility—ethical as well as intellectual—to return this dualism to its
anthropological source, he fetishizes it and consequently degrades it. To affirm
that the Ideas alone are real is not to distinguish them absolutely from worldly
things, but on the contrary, to assimilate the two. As soon as one imagines a
"heaven" inhabited by the Ideas, one makes them play the same role in the other
world as things play in this one, just as they do in the myth of the Cave. The other
world is in fact the "other scene," the scene of representation, on which only signs
appear.
What then is the relationship between the world of Ideas and the other world of
souls, that imaginary locus consecrated by religion, described at length in the
Phaedo? Let us not be too hasty to naturalize the religious heaven as an instrument
of priestly manipulation of the credulous or as the fantastic wish fulfillment of
some inborn desire for immortality. Its model is clearly, as Plato reveals, the
(signified of the) sign. But Plato fixes this model in a dualistic ontology by
suppressing the originary link between signifier and referent, a connection the
syntactic trace of which is precisely the ostensive.
So long as the sign serves as a means for the revelation of the central object of
desire, the other world of permanent Being will appear to be inhabited by that
object rather than by the sign itself. The originary model of immortality is that of
the sacred center of the scene of representation. To use language is to institute a
relationship that is from the beginning formal and consequently liberated from the
force of time. Those who would put a transcendent Language in the place of the
Christian or Hegelian logos forget that language is not, but that it is constructed,
and that the point of departure for this construction cannot well be the declarative
sentence that crowns it. No doubt some of the responsibility for this lapse is
attributable to Saussure's emphasis on signification at the expense of syntactic
Paradoxical Thinking 78
regret the repressive domination of metaphysics without admitting that its logos
is human language itself.
The originary-without-an-origin language of deconstructive thought is a free
play of the signifier that, by returning us to the material reality of the sign, puts
signification and therefore metaphysics into question. Heidegger could conceive
of a "thinking of Being" that would stand opposed to metaphysics as the ostensive
is to the declarative, that would designate Being itself rather than creating fictive
models of it taken from the realm of the ontic. The disappearance of this pre-
Socratic paradise in the postmodern era has relegated ostensivity to the religious
domain in which it originated, and where no philosopher is likely to seek it out.
As a consequence, Benoist has recourse to psychoanalysis as postmodernity's
official originary anthropology—an anthropology in which the substitution of
ontogenesis for phylogenesis permits the evacuation of the ethical. But chassez le
religieux, il revient au galop: what psychoanalytic authority supplies is nothing
other than a myth of origin. Within the horizon established by the author's
concluding reference to Heraclitus, the reign of the mythical is all the less
contested for being entirely unavowed.10
It is time to return la dépense to the ritual context where Georges Bataille found
it.11 Benoist's summary reference to the potlatch reflects a typical postmodern
failure to understand—as Bataille did in his lucid moments—that this marvelous
flux, this outpouring of energy beyond all reason, is born not in the delicious
polymorphism of individual desire but in the ritual "cruelty" (to use Artaud's term)
of societies far removed from our intellectual utopias. The pre-Socratic chaos
expelled by metaphysics is the decadence of a ritual order subject to a control far
more rigid than latter-day metaphysics imagines. When Plato attempts to
constrain the tyrannical excesses of individual desire, it is to avert crisis in a barely
postritual society, not to put a phallocratic brake on the pristine appetites of
originary humanity. Originary humanity already knows language and order in
their most rigid sense; our dream of anarchy is conceivable only on this basis.
The metaphysical conception of language is defined by the expulsion of the
elementary linguistic forms. But Plato does not expel the ostensive as such
because he does not theorize it as such. Had he been able to theorize it, he would
not have had to expel it. Plato fears the immediacy of language that itself acts on
the world. The Sophists are dangerous because their rhetoric restores to language
its originary power of creating meaning, but in a context where the speaker is no
longer subject to the transcendent communal order incarnated in ritual. The
stability of the Ideas that maintain the social order is founded on a deeper, albeit
Paradoxical Thinking 80
still mystified vision of the originary event and of the scene of representation that
preserves it.
The formal logic of signification justifies the founding gesture of metaphysics.
The concept is indeed immortal because it does not belong to the real world,
whatever its point of entry into human language. But if the nominalized virtues of
the early dialogues and the Ideas themselves of the later ones possessed only the
formal immortality of the sign-in-general, they would fail to meet the ethical
requirements that Platonic thought imposes on them. In attempting to find in
language the basis of a conflict-free community, Plato creates a form of thought
that effaces the historical origin of language as the human community's means to
defer conflict. In order for the concept to be immortal, it must be without origin
and therefore without history. On the contrary, the real immortality of the concept
is in its evocation of the scenic sharing of the sign in the originary event as a
transtemporal guarantee of communal peace.
7
"To be" is to be in the center, at the locus of significance; "to do" is to act on the
periphery. The substantiality and subsistence inherent in the verb "to be" are those
of the originary center. To be present in the center of the scene is to be uniquely
significant precisely because it is to be absent from any project of action. Being
is present-to-consciousness because it cannot be made present-to-hand. It is the
foundation of the specifically human form of knowledge because it introduces the
stasis of representation between the imitator and his mimetic model. To imitate
the central being, I cannot simply mimic its behavior; I must re-present its self-
substantial form.
Because being is the chief preoccupation of metaphysics, it is the key locus of
its deconstruction, which undermines the metaphysical duality of idea and reality
through the revelation of being's ostensive nature. For Heidegger, being can
"reveal" or "hide" itself because it resides in a locus that can be pointed to rather
than in the transcendent Platonic realm of Ideas. The return to Being from the
preoccupation with beings is a return to originary scenicity from the ideal scene
of metaphysics; in a still-mystified form, thought returns from the world of
concepts to its ground in originary language.
Being is not identical to sacrality, nor to significance. The central object is sacred
insofar as its inaccessibility defers mimetic conflict, but this deferral is
Paradoxical Thinking 82
effective only because the quality of the sacred is attributed to the object rather
than to the peripheral humans whose mutually repelling desires render it
inaccessible. In contrast, being inheres in the role of the center-as-mimetic-
obstacle. There is no adjective analogous to "sacred" to describe the object that
"has" being, because being is precisely not a quality but a form of action. Unlike
the sacred, it cannot be conceived as subsisting in a transcendent realm, but is only
realized in the mimetic context. The third term, significance, is the status of the
object qua referent of the sign; the referent's significance "expresses" its prior
being. Significance is for the user of language; being is in and for itself.
The relationship between the ostensive being of the central object and the use of
"to be" as the copula parallels that between elementary and mature language.
Ostensive language contains no predicative description of being; being is what is
being "done" by the objects to which the ostensive refers. In contrast, the
declarative sentence, by subordinating the presupposed significance of its topic to
the new information provided by the predicate, permits us to thematize the notion
of being as such by extrapolation from the copula "to be." The thematic
understanding of the ontological (Being) must be won through the ontic (beings).
It is useful to trace the various words for being back to the more concrete terms
like "bear" (bhŗ → ? bhū → to be) or "stand" (stare → Sp. estar) that have been
pressed into service as copulas. Many such words other than "be" exist in our
vocabulary: "he looks good,""it appears correct" express a restricted sense of
being. But this passage from the concrete to the abstract is only possible because
the notion of being as we have defined it is implicit in language from the original
ostensive designation. To re-present the object is to imply that it is, in the sense
that the term has in the cogito: being as the mark of potential thematization. It is
because being is already implicit in the ostensive that we experience the
substantiality of the topic (the "substantive" or noun) as existing prior to
predication.
What is is what stands before us as the forbidden goal of our (originally
appropriative) mimetic behavior. In this standing-before or standing-against our
desire, the central being appears to be in-itself; in our concentration on the object,
our former (human) mimetic model is forgotten. This is no mere illusion that the
originary hypothesis dispels. The resistance of being to imitation in action (and
not simply its resistance to physical appropriation) makes it imitable only through
representation. Whereas mimesis of others is unproblematic, representation of
central being is the originary act of self-consciousness. The ritual reproducer of
this act, for example, the shaman in a trance state of "possession" by the divine
figure whose costume he wears, is at the other end of the mimetic spectrum from
Originary Being, Originary Thinking 83
the unaware subject of everyday mimesis; where the latter merely prolongs the
prehuman imitative pattern, the ritual performer's concentration on his task takes
him beyond consciousness.
Being is the foundation of the internal-external scene of representation on which
all formal activity—language, desire, thought—takes place. Our interest in the
object is ultimately always the same, but the scenic manifestation of the object-
as-being opens up between it and the subject—whose subjectivity is thereby
established—a space-time of deferral, what Sartre called a néant, within which a
new set of mimetic behaviors toward the object may be elaborated. There is no
simple mimetic fit between the behavior of the subject and the being of the object;
in contrast with the imitation of a human mediator, the formal "imitation" of the
central object has no a priori content. The sign provides a minimal representation
of the referent's formal closure; ritual and secular art will incarnate it and
temporalize it in various guises. The appropriation of central being through
mimesis is the human project par excellence.
We need not linger over the gaps in Heidegger's conception of the ontological-
ontic opposition. Lacking a theory of human origin, he generates an ontology of
the human from Dasein or being-present-(to) without providing a theory of the
scene on which this scenic presence-to might have emerged. Dasein's presence to
time in the form of Death remains a figure of Hegelian phenomenology; for a
person to know his own death, it must be revealed to him in specific circumstances
of the kind that the originary hypothesis proposes. But we can accept the
fundamental ontological intuition of Heidegger's "existentialism": that real
Paradoxical Thinking 84
Originary Thinking
As the species whose propensity to mimesis makes it its own most serious
problem, humans must think because they are too mimetic to act peacefully
otherwise. The aim of thinking is not to reproduce the originary unity that
obtained during the emission of the sign, but rather to reconstruct it in such a way
as to reduce the tension between periphery and center, subject and object.
Thinking deconstructs the figures by means of which the sacred center defers the
establishment of reciprocal relations with the profane periphery. Thinking reduces
"outward" to "inward" form, visible to invisible; it struggles to maintain the
fundamental arbitrariness of the sign in opposition to the cultural institutions,
ritual and esthetic, that would take advantage of the sign's materiality in order to
motivate its relationship with its referent. Where the sign minimally re-presents
the formal closure of the object, thinking prolongs representation into analysis.
Originary signification defers the sparagmos, but thinking is the antisparagmos
that reunites the object's scattered remains, recomposing Being from beings.
On this point, two directions are possible. Metaphysical thought conceives of the
scene of representation on which it manifests itself as an atemporally stable locus,
denying the mimetic tension that is its historical raison d'être. Such thought
remains within the limits of the declarative proposition, in which "to be" is merely
a copula linking a noun with its predicate. Because this model of language cannot
figure the (ostensive) interest in the noun-topic that precedes and provides the
basis for predication, it cannot conceive originary being. The being in a
proposition cannot merely be; it must always do what is predicated of it, the
archetype of which predicative doing is, as we have seen, to be absent. The limits
of metaphysics are not those of the declarative sentence itself; they are those of
the model of language—and the thinking that it generates—that takes this
sentence-form as its originary basis.
In contrast, originary thinking—practiced throughout most of history
exclusively in the religious sphere—privileges the ostensivity of central Being, its
Paradoxical Thinking 86
presence. Generative anthropology is a new way of thinking, but only in the sense
that it thematizes an activity that has gone on since the origin.
The most obvious originary model for thinking would be that the first thought is
expressed in the first sign, and that the content of this thought is the central object,
the object of Girard's "first noninstinctual attention." Once the gesture of
appropriation has been transformed into a sign, the central object becomes an
object of desire situated on an internal scene of representation where we may
contemplate or "think about" it.
But this is not really what we mean by thinking. Thought is not reducible to the
desiring contemplation of the imaginary referent of language. It is an activity of
reflection on the contents of one's mental processes, an effort rather than a
pleasure. Indeed, this effort requires us to renounce our pleasure in the immediate
contemplation of the mental image from which our desire constructs the image-
as-we-would-like-it-to-be; thinking is a deconstructive search for the original and
ultimately for the originary components that underlie the idea/image. To think
about a concept is not to contemplate it in the imagination but to analyze our
immediate idea of it into the more primitive notions that the idea's figurality has
occulted. The Socratic elenchos is an exercise in thinking that requests, as against
easily imagined figures of courage or beauty, an analysis of its prefigural essence.
All thinking is originary analysis.
Thinking as a renunciation of pleasure, as a form of deferral, is the mental
correlate of the physical abortion of the originary appropriative gesture. The
thought that gives rise to language is the thought-not-to-appropriate the object.
The pleasurable image of the object-as-appropriated must be thought through to
the separate components hidden by the image, notably the copresence of the
mediating others and the danger they represent. This first act of thinking that
motivates the production of the originary sign acknowledges the presence of
others within the sphere of the apparently binary relationship of appetite; it is the
originary deconstruction of desire avant la lettre. The result of this first thought
is the turning-back of the appropriative gesture as an imitation/representation of
the object. This movement is not "instinctive" but reflective; thought produces not
a mere turning-away but a modified turning-toward. The gesture is aborted as
appropriation but pursued as representation.
The originary position of thought is complementary to that of rhetoric. In the
"rhetorical" moment of the originary scene, the already constituted community of
emitters of the sign successfully attempts to influence by their example the
isolated individual who has not yet joined the group. The "late" phenomenon of
rhetoric mimetically persuades the "last" emitter of the sign to join what he takes
Originary Being, Originary Thinking 87
*
What we think about, and why we think it, is an open matter; but this very
openness is understandable only in the context of its origin. We began to think, as
we began to speak, not to fulfill the destiny of an élan vital, but to defer the
intraspecific problems that would otherwise have prevented us from existing.
The scene of representation is the locus of desire, religion, and art; it is also the
locus of thought. Where religion operates through submission to the power of a
preestablished center, in thinking we put aside our desire for central being to
construct a hypothetical model of its interaction with its human periphery. But it
is not surprising that the most fundamental and consequently the most dangerous
kind of thought, reflection on human origin, has historically been confined to the
context of established religion, where speculation on fundamental anthropology
is constrained by theological dogma.
In contrast, thought independent of institutional authority has been throughout
Western history virtually synonymous with metaphysics, the forgetting of the
ostensive movement toward the center. Socrates' conceptual analysis, rejecting
the cosmic globalism of his predecessors, constitutes a new stage in the separating
out of thought from the religious elements of the scene. As we saw in the
preceding chapter, in posing the "reality" of the Idea-concept exemplified by the
Good, Socrates-Plato attempts to define the basis of the human community
independently of religious revelation. As the founding model for over two
millennia of metaphysical reflection, the Socratic elenchos creates a propositional
agon with respect to which the transcendental status of the Idea plays the role of
deus ex machina.
Generative anthropology, which is originary thinking founded on hypothesis
rather than revelation, explicitly locates the deconstruction of the object of
thought within the minimal configuration of the originary scene. It thereby comes
qualitatively closer than its predecessors to the unreachable ideal of intellectual
self-generation: to be a way of thinking that includes paradoxically within itself
the content of any conceivable metathinking about it.
But the only valid demonstration of this claim is to be found in the work that
realizes it. One recalls from the opening of the preface—over sixty pages long!—
to Hegel's Phenomenology that a truly "philosophical" work cannot expound its
truth in a preface. Hegel lacked only the distinction between ostensive and
declarative, anthropology and metaphysics, to be able to articulate this paradox.
We may express it thus:Generative anthropology must be its own originary
analysis.
8
power of the Verb can only be conserved unused, outside of spoken language.
What is revealed is that the word-in-general is not indeed the name of God but of
a worldly object, not of Being but of a being among others.
Our task in this chapter is to understand how the unique originary sign provides
the opening to this plurality. If representation were nothing but designation-as-
significant, it would require no more than a single sign of ostension-in-general—
a pointing finger. We have assumed that the sign originates in the mimesis of the
formal closure of the object that has been cut off from direct appropriation. The
object is placed on a scene where it can for the first time be contemplated and its
formal articulations explored; the potential scenic contemplation of other objects
follows as a consequence. This "disinterested" contemplation of the object as
form, in tension with its appetitive interest qua content, prefigures its later
transfiguration via the sparagmos into the Being of the center-in-itself in the
"religious" moment of the scene.
The deepest mystery of metaphysics is its repression or forgetting of the relation
between the Being of the scene, to which religion attributes personhood as God,
and the metaphysical scene-as-such on which objects present themselves to our
"objective" contemplation. It is the mark of the Continental-existential school of
philosophy to have remained aware of this mystery, which Anglo-American
analytic philosophy dismisses as meaningless because its criterion of
meaningfulness takes the institution of the metaphysical scene as its unexamined
precondition.
Personhood is the quality of the being that defers its own appropriation, that
opposes its will to the appetites of the members of the community, whose own
sense of self is given to them as derived from this deferring force. In the face of
the resistance of the center, the human self discovers its own relation to it as
desire. Religious understanding detaches the personhood of the center from the
object that inhabits it and attributes it to a being existing prior to the scene and
ontologically independent of it; the central object becomes the locus in which this
being chooses to reveal itself. It is this detachment of being from scene that
provides the context in which the scene of representation is opened up to beings
in general. Any object that appears on it is capable of arousing mimetic desire and
thereupon of being endowed with significance and represented by a sign.
The originary sign is singular and, in its origin as a gesture of appropriation,
motivated rather than arbitrary. Its change of motivation from practical-
appropriative to theoretical-signifying is the source of the so-called arbitrariness
of the signifier. Insofar as the sign is a material act, it has a worldly reality that is
subject to variation. Our question is how some such variation could come to be
Paradoxical Thinking 92
of its referent, the signified qua mental image becomes the sole subsisting
correlative of the sign.
The sparagmos is the radical making-absent of the object. The object is destroyed
as unified figure, as formal and personal whole, not merely as edible flesh. Thus
what we call the persistence of the figure of the object in the signifying
imagination should be understood as its return, on the model of the "return of the
repressed," or of Jesus's return from the world of the dead. Despite the defiguring
intent of its original sacrificers, the figure retains its existence through the sign.
By the same token, the ritual commemoration of the originary event gives proof
that the sign has defeated the praxis of originary resentment that the sparagmos
was meant to realize. Like Saul on the road to Damascus, the member of the
originary community discovers that annihilation consecrates rather than
obliterates the central figure.
The signified is the trace of a referent made absent by the violence of the
sparagmos. But this violence, in which Girard finds the source of the object's
significance, is a secondary product of originary representation, a reaction to the
resentment aroused by the object's resistance to appropriation. The sparagmos
does not create significance, but when it destroys the already-significant referent,
it leaves the signified in its place. The destruction of the central figure, to be
replaced only by the imaginary figurality of the signified, is the originary
withdrawal of the divinity. God's withdrawal in Exodus from the figure itself
signifies the revelation that the basis of human scenicity is not figural, that it
inheres in the circular—minimally, triangular—structure of mimesis.
The unique central being is destroyed in the sparagmos; the sign remains
because, indefinitely repeatable, it defers the resentment inspired by the unique
center. The passage from the unique sacred referent to the signified via the
sparagmos is the originary passage from "proper" to "common" noun. Now that
the ostensive sign has survived the destruction of its single privileged referent, the
sparagmos's ultimate aim of obliteration has become both impossible and
unnecessary.
The retention of the sign as signified depends on the sacrifice of its exemplary
object, which religion reinterprets as the withdrawal of the sacred Being that
inhabited this object. We accept this sacrifice because we have in fact anticipated
it, indeed, participated in it. To give significance to an object, to show interest in
it, to desire it, is to retain its figure at the same time as we engage in its imaginary
defiguration. The signified, as the residue of the violence of the sparagmos,
remains the locus of the tension between the figure as a specific incarnation of
desire and the negation of this specificity in the generality of the sign. If I say
The Origin of Signification 97
The Erotic
In the originary scene, it is reasonable to assume that the birth of human desire
induces a state of sexual excitement in the participants.1 The central desire-object
would then be the first object of human sexual desire as well. In this context,
sexuality does not lose its specificity; yet the sexual is not, as in psychoanalytic
theory, the primary component of desire, but a supplement to the mechanism of
desire as such. Sexual desire, as opposed to sexual appetite, is desire before it is
sexual.
Within the originary context, mimetic mediation by the others' desires is occulted
by the sacralization of the central figure. The erotic may be defined as that which
preserves the supplementary libidinal charge attributed to desire in the originary
scene beyond the boundary of its original context. The erotic resembles the
esthetic as a category at first attached to the sacred but in principle detachable
from it.
The erotic, in other words, is whatever in the central being actively compels
mimetic desire independently of the mimetic models on the periphery. In the
originary scene, the central object's apparent withdrawal from our desire is the
effect of mediation by the others. But what is crucial for the erotic is that this
withdrawal be attributed to the object itself by the desiring subject—presumably
in the course of the latter's act of representing its formal closure, as discussed in
Chapter 2. The erotic exists as a category as soon as it can be intuited as an effect
aroused in the self, and consequently capable of being aroused in others. Thus if
I wish to imitate this effect of the central object, I will myself withdraw from the
other's desire.
The erotic object is self-mediating because we can feel it deliberately resist our
desire. Only a person, a subject of "free will," is truly capable of such resistance,
although we like to attribute this capacity to animals like cats whose behavior
contains elements of both dependence and independence. The first personhood is
attributed to the sacred center as the originary desire-object and the model for the
actions of human desire-objects in the life-world.
Desire for another human being, although not exclusively sexual, is given its
most powerful orientation by the libido or sexual appetite. But the eroticism of
objects other than sexual is not a deviation of the libido from its sexual aim; it is
simply proof of the noncoincidence of the erotic with the sexual.2
Desire cannot emerge as a human phenomenon in the intimate sphere of
sexuality. On the other hand, it cannot operate without the sexual energy that
attaches us to our fellow humans. Even in the prehuman state, appetite for the
Paradoxical Thinking 100
other is more labile than appetite in imitation of the other. Already in the lower
animals we can distinguish between the physical reality of sexual pleasure and the
specificity of its object; an analogous distinction exists only marginally in the
alimentary sphere in the difference between taste and nutritive value. But although
the higher animals can be "perverse" their one-on-one operations of sexual
competition are not yet erotic. The model of the mimetic center confers on the
other an eroticism only possible in the human universe of the sign. The lability of
sexual desire makes the erotic as mediated by the sign the typical human desire,
one not wholly dependent on a corporeal need, yet funded by a visceral source of
energy that we may call with Freud the libido. In contrast with the prehuman
world, which is dominated by appetites directed to extraspecific objects of
alimentary consumption, the exemplary human desire is erotic attraction to a
fellow human.
The eroticism of culture supplements the zero-sum game of mimetic desire and
resentment. Secular culture seduces us through the erotic, which appears to give
our desire something for nothing. The erotic object as self-withholding subject
lures us to construct an imaginary scene on which that other-subject can be
possessed. We forget the mediation of our desire through the cultural sign in our
erotic attachment to the otherness that is the content of the sign. We dream of an
individual possession of the whole that denies its ancestry in the sparagmatic
fragmentation of the originary event. From the communal scene to the erotic one,
only the mechanism of desire is preserved—but this mechanism is everything. In
high art, the structure of originary experience is reproduced in an esthetic
oscillation that is foregrounded at the expense of erotic fixation. The popular arts
are less embarrassed to provide the material for imaginary wish fulfillment. But
when the esthetic mechanism remains wholly occulted and the erotic reigns
undisturbed, we fall altogether out of the domain of "legitimate" culture into that
of pornography.3
Romantic Love
The phenomenon of romantic love as we know it since the feudal era extends to
the erotic sphere the Christian revelation of the equivalence between divine and
human personhood. In love, the object of desire is revealed as not simply a
troubling otherness that attracts our desire by withdrawing from it, but as another
subject. The so-called overestimation of the sexual object is not an illusion but,
on the contrary, a realization that the structure of desire is essentially interpersonal
rather than objectal. The erotic couple attempts to expel the mediating other from
the scene of representation, to substitute a dual reciprocity, a mutual mediation,
Two Psychoanalytic Categories 101
for the circulation of the mimetic triangle. Triangularity haunts erotic desire as its
origin and inevitable temptation, but it is not the structure of the erotic in itself.
The increasingly self-aware formulations of love in the West since the eleventh
century testify to the growing importance of the erotic couple as a cultural model.
Romantic love includes the sacred source of being within the relationship itself.
Just as the esthetic becomes independent of the public scene of representation by
internalizing the scene's mimetic structure in the subject's oscillation between sign
and referent, the object of erotic desire is the incarnate sign of his/her own being,
generating in the partner a personal sacred that lasts at least the time of a sexual
encounter, and perhaps a lifetime.
The fullest potential of the love relationship is in creating a model of reciprocity
without an alien center. In the reciprocal erotic scene, as opposed to the perfect-
except-for-the-center symmetry of the originary scene, each is a center for the
other. This intimate version of the Gospel utopia, however unrealistic it may be
as a model for social relations, can function in the erotic context because it is
based on desire rather than "brotherly love." The erotic is both figural and
intersubjective; it is attached both to the material reality of the other and to his/her
status as subject.
Because the erotic creates a microcosm of the human universe that requires no
external transcendent figure, it is the privileged content of secular culture, which
must arouse and purge desire without the benefit of the ritual reconstitution of
collective presence. This privileged status only clearly emerges in the neoclassical
era, which is characterized by its thematization of the scenic.4 Love creates a
personal scene of representation homologous to the public one, with the beloved
as its sacred center; this homology is thematized from the beginnings of romantic
love with the troubadours and systematized as a worldview by Dante and the neo-
Platonists. Throughout the neoclassical era, the private erotic scene draws away
the energies that classical forms concentrated on the public scene, until the
romantics finally enshrine it as the authentic scene of origin.
Yet the movement toward the intimate love scene reveals that the essential
characteristic of the erotic figure is its "otherness," its possession of another self
that it withholds from us. This otherness both requires figurality and conflicts with
it. The selfhood of the other is only visible through the figure but, at the same
time, as figure it is fixed in its frame, subordinated to the gaze of the spectator.
The inherent tension between the other-subject's freedom and its fixation in the
image is latent throughout the neoclassical era, which remains attached to the
public scene of representation; it emerges explicitly in the idolatry of postromantic
decadence, and becomes irreconcilable at the onset of modernism, the moment of
Paradoxical Thinking 102
divorce between high art and the erotic. The crucial moment in this history is that
of realism, the first modern challenge to the esthetic legitimacy of the Platonic
Idea.
scientific conclusion that Emma cannot live. As the prototypical realist heroine,
Emma withdraws from our desire by desiring in a new mode, that of the modern
consumer, who can never be satisfied because she consumes with the goal of
going beyond consumption. Realism is the disillusionment of narrative textuality:
the satisfaction of desire can end a narrative, but not satisfy us forever as literary
characters are supposed to be satisfied. Emma shares this disillusionment; she
consumes the objects in her life as we consume her story. She is always in our
sight, yet her description is vague. Emma is withdrawn from us concomitantly
with her own eroticism; the author's emphasis on her awaiting of her lovers' desire
expresses an emergent awareness of the seductive power of this withdrawal on
the reader.
Thus realism is the moment in which the strategic withdrawal characteristic of
the erotic other has begun to be a figural absence, a lack of figuration. The figure
of beauty that was never other than a sign, a support for esthetic oscillation, now
appears to block the circular movement of this oscillation by offering too much to
the audience's desire. The driving force in this evolution is the increasing
integration of desire into the market system—the emergence of "consumer
society" which reveals the dependency of the supposedly anarchic force of desire
on the social order it is supposed to be contesting. In this context of the
commercial circulation of desire, the esthetic oscillation between sign and referent
comes into conflict with the quasi-permanent investments of the erotic.
The erotic retained the spectator's interest in the sign-cum-referent as a whole; it
operated as a supplement to the esthetic, the apparent "free lunch" from which the
romantics believed they could profit without penalty.5 But now the hitherto
unproblematic constancy of the image, whether conceived as a conventional
figure or as an imaginative creation, is discovered to be a cultural artifact. When
I invest my libido in the other as figure, it remains blocked at the level of the
image and cannot return to the sign because, like Emma, it takes the image as an
article of consumption.6 The image is a fetish that hides the sign-nature of the
fictional figure. In consumer society, the centralized image is no longer sacred but
cynically manipulative; it is too productive of resentment to perform the cultural
task of purging it. Late romantic art turns away from and problematizes the figure,
not because it has lost its power—the heavily charged eroticism of the Decadents
is proof of the contrary—but because this power is no longer under the artist's
control. Whence the wild oscillations in this period between asceticism and
pornography (and the pornography of asceticism), as exemplified by the careers
of Wilde, Beardsley, Verlaine, or J.-K. Huysmans.
Paradoxical Thinking 104
erotic figure is precisely the one that continues to produce its effect not in spite of
but as a result of the ironization of the form in which it is presented. It is present
as objective figure and absent as subjective irony; this merely restates the
principle of the erotic in general, which is the tantalizing withdrawal of the
subject-other.
The more ironic, the more erotic; the more open the eroticism, the more the self-
staging of life becomes indistinguishable from art, as a figure like Madonna makes
clear. The deliberately seductive figures of popular culture are translated directly
into the seductions of the life-world. Let us recall that the source of the privilege
accorded the erotic element in culture is that it provides the spectator with the
context-free conditions of desire that obtain in the world of intimacy. As esthetic
form loses its historical innocence, this imaginary intimacy can no longer be
segregated from that of everyday life. In order to be able to resist the seductions
of popular culture, we would have to refashion the entire erotic imagery of our
daily lives. This is not within our capacity. We can renounce active participation
in the culture, but not absorption of its imagery; desire even after analysis retains
its mimetic power.
It is no coincidence that our culture comes to be stigmatized as offering only the
temptations of "sex and violence" at the very moment in which it is experiencing
a qualitative leap in the reciprocity of sexual relations. The postmodern rejection
of the naive culture of the (essentially if not exclusively feminine) image parallels
the demise of the masculine warrior-ideal. The new sexual reciprocity, in personal
as opposed to instrumental relationships, is anything but a sterile nondifference.
A satisfactory love relationship cannot be founded on an abstract symmetry; to
the extent that it refuses hierarchy, it must cultivate and generate difference rather
than identity.
Postmodern popular culture helps us to understand the mechanism of the
generation of difference within the erotic sphere. Erotic content is typically
perverse, coquettishly designed to seduce the desiring subject through an
appearance of self-containment. But the erotic figure is in fact wholly dependent
on the desire of the other that it is designed to arouse. This is the reason for its
irony. The cultural image that operates within the limits of esthetic form avenges
itself in the erotic sphere by assuming its objectality in full awareness of its power
over the spectator's desire. The same eroticization takes place in the sphere of
intimate relations, where the members of the couple ironically exploit erotic
figurality in acts of mutual seduction. In love relationships, as with a lesser
intensity in all human relationships, ironic self-consciousness guarantees against
the instrumental domination of one person by another.
Paradoxical Thinking 106
The Unconscious
The unconscious is a necessary yet invisible category, a paradoxical candidate
indeed for inclusion in the paradoxical scene of origin of human consciousness.
Freud first performed a kind of originary analysis of the unconscious in Totem
and Taboo, by tracing its origin to the repressed memory of the murder of the
father who had kept all the women of the "horde" to himself.9 But this has not
been the path followed by psychoanalysis. However decentered the
psychoanalytic vision of the human subject, however dependent it may be on
language, the idea that the unconscious could have a collective origin has only
been preserved by those who entertain the misguided notion of a "collective
unconscious."
Were the unconscious merely the complement of the conscious, it would have
no conceptual weight. Clearly I am unconscious of everything of which I am not
conscious. But we come doser to a useful understanding of the concept when the
field of potential consciousness is limited by the minimality of the originary scene.
Simply to note that, in this scene, if I am conscious of the central object I am
unconscious of everything else is already to give a preliminary definition of the
unconscious: it remains only to specify the "everything else."
Two Psychoanalytic Categories 107
The desire directed to the center of the originary scene is mediated by the others,
or in the triangular model, the other, on the periphery. This mediation is our
knowledge, an element of our theoretical model; it is the basis of our analysis of
the mimetic origin of language. The turning-away from the direct imitation of the
other that permits the imitation/representation of the object creates an opening for
this representation's own modeling by consciousness; the history of consciousness
is made up of the successive stages through which representation turns back
toward its mimetic origin. Consciousness of mimesis is accessible to the
participants in the scene itself only through the mediation of the center, which is
also to say the alienation of this consciousness to the center. The interminable
process of understanding this alienation is the basis of our historicity; but
concomitant with our increasing lucidity about mimesis is our growing awareness
that its "unconscious" triangular structure cannot be grasped from within.
The collective mediation of the participants in the originary scene is the real
cause of their resentment of the central object. The obstacle to their desire is not
the object itself but the concurrent desires of their fellows. Should we then say
that what we really resent is not the center itself but these other desires? But this
formulation is unsatisfactory; we cannot resent anything but the object of our
resentment, any more than we can desire the desire-object of the others rather than
the object that in fact we desire. It is therefore preferable to say that our resentment
is indeed directed to the center, but that it is determined by our unconscious
mimetic relationship with the desiring others on the periphery.
This formulation locates the unconscious in a different place within the scene
than Freud's or even Girard's model. For Girard as well as for the author of Totem
and Taboo, what must be repressed is the relation to the center itself, conceived
as an originary murder. The murder is differently motivated in the two theories.
For Freud, the father is the object of a universal thematic and prescenic
resentment, the result of his monopoly of the women, who are the "natural" desire-
objects of the group of sons. For Girard, the originary victim is arbitrarily chosen
during the scene itself rather than in advance. This difference has enormous
consequences for the respective theories of desire each derives from the originary
scene—Freud's "derivation" being determined a posteriori by his preexisting
model of the Oedipus complex. Because of the intentional nature of the murder,
Freud cannot speak of the repression of its memory in the originary context.
Instead, he makes the notion of guilt the basis for a new internalization of the
interdiction of the center, which will eventually lead to this repression, as well as
to the various forms taken by the religious commemoration of the dead father,
who provides the model for the transcendent divinity. Throughout his work, it is
Two Psychoanalytic Categories 109
aggression against the father/center rather than the more notorious desire for the
mother that is the exemplary object of repression.
Girard avoids the embarrassment of having to explain the repression of a
thematic intention. In the absence of such an intention, it is indeed possible to
speak of the "repression" of the emissary murder. Myth mystifies this violent
event by recalling only its beneficial consequences; as many mythical and quasi-
mythical texts attest, the disappearance of the central figure is presented as the
effect of its own "divine" will.10 The repressed mediation of desire that was the
key to the mimetic model of Mensonge romantique remains at the root of Girard's
theory of desire; its translation to the cultural realm changes the object and scope
of repression, but not the structure of mediation.
A founding murder is a memorable event the repressed memory trace of which
may easily enough be imagined as a kind of space-occupying content displaced
from the conscious to the unconscious mind. But a rigorously conceived
unconscious should not be a mere double of consciousness; the very ease with
which we imagine the murder scene should warn us that this conception of the
unconscious is as mythical as its purported content.
This problem does not arise if the originary content of the unconscious is the
collective mediation of the subject's desire for the center. Mediation is not an
event; it is not "visible" even when recognized. Because the originary hypothesis
dispenses with the concrete figures of emissary or paternal murder, it can also
dispense with the dubious notion of an already-figural unconscious content.
The idea of an unconscious is incompatible with the propositional universe of
metaphysics. What can be "repressed" from a world of propositions can only be
another proposition, and the missing proposition can always be reconstituted from
its elements. What requires an unconscious is one's own situation within the
universe one represents, just as the paradoxes of representation are the inevitable
byproducts of self-reference. Mimesis leads to paradox because of the
impossibility of definitively separating the world of the model from the world of
the subject; their reunion is deferred by metaphysical language only at the cost of
eventual deconstruction. No doubt paradox is formalizable only in propositional
forms, but we can grasp the anthropological significance of paradox only once we
realize that rather than a perversion of the declarative proposition, paradox is
inherent from the beginning in the verticality of language.
The unconscious, as Lacan says, is "structured like a language." But Lacan has
no idea, beyond those of Saussure, of how a language is structured. It is the
paradoxical origin of language that leaves the unconscious as the unformulatable
residue of the sign. Our claim that mediation by the periphery is the unconscious
Paradoxical Thinking 110
indistinguishable from the metaphysical subject. The residue of the immortal soul
unrecognized by metaphysics provides the first content for the unconscious in the
form of the romantic's "irrational" aspirations to centrality. The loss of divine
mediation is a preparation for the understanding of human mediation.
When Descartes attempted to define the human subject, he left it to God to
guarantee the relationship between this subject and the empirical world. Now that
it is certain of its individual being, the self of the cogito, having put aside desire
(the "passions") and even empirical knowledge, requires a transcendental
mediator to reestablish what bas been destroyed. In contrast, the romantic
bourgeois self is no longer bound by communal mediation; he has become
ostensibly self-mediating. But to absorb the mediator into the self is not to
eliminate him, merely to render his domination unconscious. In its typically
modern,"internal" form, mediation becomes invisible to the subject and at the
same time figurable within the world of narrative; this is the theme of Mensonge
romantique. We need not take the mediating figures in these works at face value,
as though we each walked the streets of the modem city shadowed by our personal
mediator. The individualized, thematized mediator or Dostoevskian double is just
as usefully understood as the external projection in a unique Other of the multiple
mediations installed within the self, of what we may begin to call the character's
unconscious. The force of mediated desire has become visible to the subject in his
moments of acute self-consciousness in the form of an inhabiting other, an
alienated self.
This late romantic sense of alienation, of being possessed by a double, is the
coming to consciousness of mimetic desire as an operational element in an
evolving exchange system within which the deliberate mediation of desire
through advertising and product diversification has become essential. This is the
onset of the mature, desire-based phase of the market era that we call consumer
society.
The historical significance of consumer society has been difficult to evaluate in
the face of the century of diatribes with which it has been greeted by the
intelligentsia from Thorstein Veblen on down, incorrigible believers in the
resentment-free utopia that will satisfy all their resentments. We are perhaps still
insufficiently distanced from the Marxian-socialist illusion to carry out this
evaluation. Nascent consumer society is clearly the efficient cause of modernism
and its associated political extremisms, as well as of the decline of traditional
metaphysics. The establishment of the priority of desire over cognition is not a
temporary aberration engineered by the self-serving bourgeoisie, but the
Paradoxical Thinking 112
Originary Violence
The Sparagmos
Here is Girard's description of the founding "emissary murder":
Plus les rivalités s'exaspèrent, plus les rivaux tendent à oublier les objets qui en principe
la [sic] causent, plus ils sont fascinés les uns par les autres…. Il n'y a plus d'autre terrain
d'application possible pour la mimésis que les antagonistes eux-mêmes. [The more
intense the rivalries become, the more the rivals tend to forget the objects that in
principle are their cause, the more they become fascinated by each other…. There is no
longer any possible field of application for mimesis other than the antagonists
themselves.] (Des choses cachées, pp. 34-35)
Sparagmos and Resentment 116
continued existence as a figure; but in the sparagmos, the figural nature of the
victim, the object of originary resentment, is precisely what is destroyed. Nothing
is left; the only worldly guarantee of the existence of the being that had occupied
the center of the scene is the persistence of the scene itself. As Mallarmé put it in
Un coup de dés…, "Rien n'aura eu lieu que le lieu"; nothing will have taken place
but the place. Girard's act of violence, because it must be the direct source of both
the fragility and stability of the nascent human community, is both too radical, in
that it occurs outside the universe of the sign, and too limited, in that it leaves
unscathed the figurality of the victim.
As with all institutions of mimetic desire, the sparagmos, the praxis that realizes
the intention of originary resentment, is paradoxical: it seeks to abolish the central
figure while incorporating the power that derives from its very figurality. The
violence of the sparagmos is the originary example of evil, of disorder within a
structure of order. It inspires doubt concerning the moral standing of the originary
event, indeed, of humanity itself: has the deferral of violence led only to greater
violence? But conversely, in the ethical world founded on the sacrificial violence
of the sparagmos, this violence becomes the originary focus of moral reflection.
This reflection has taken two directions, privileging respectively the human
periphery and the sacred center of the scene. The first or "Greek" path is that of
"political science": the critique of sacrificial violence by thinkers like Xenophanes
and Heraclitus leads to Plato's and Aristotle's deritualized models of the
organization of the human community. The second, "Hebraic," path is the
iconoclastic critique of the esthetic or idolatrous element of the sacred exemplified
by the Mosaic revelation.4
The revelation in the sparagmos of the internal violence of the originary
communal order opens the political space within which higher—freer but less
equalitarian—forms of organization will arise. Resentment at others' real or
fancied proximity to the center provides the fuel for the motor of history, a motor
that does most of its work in crises, when the accumulated resentment of a social
group is released in sparagmatic rage against its object.5
The minimality of the originary hypothesis requires not merely that the appetite
originally aroused by the central object be satisfied, but that discharge be provided
for the supplementary tension contributed to the scene by the mimetic relationship
among the participants. The projection of this tension onto the central figure is
sufficient to make it an object not merely of appetite but of desire; its
inaccessibility gives it an esthetic value as a form re-presented by the sign.
Similarly, in the sparagmos, the rational appetitive operation of dividing the object
is supplemented by the violent discharge of this tension in what is also a
Sparagmos and Resentment 118
imagery in the sourire grec. This tendency is analogous to the later emergence of
metaphysics in the cognitive realm; in both cases the immediate, ostensive
revelation of otherness is softened and assimilated to the contemplation of an
idealized version of everyday human experience. Neither Greek religion nor
Greek philosophy is capable of grasping the ultimate incompatibility of the
religious and the esthetic that is made explicit in the Mosaic revelation.
The forms of high art realize the understanding that the enunciation of the sign
is primordially a renunciation of its object, and that, as representations, artworks
derive their power from this renunciation, which they reproduce in our
imagination. The idolatrous moment of incarnation provides a pleasure that is
continually sacrificed and renewed in the oscillatory movement of the imagination
from esthetic sign to imaginary referent.
The work of high art defers or sublimates originary resentment by maintaining
the paradoxical duality of mimesis, the identification with both the mediator and
the object, both the periphery and the center of the scene. To identify with the
central object is to condemn the sparagmos from the totalizing perspective of the
sign in the process of representing its object; to participate in the sparagmos is to
take the sign for granted as an already-constituted substitute for the object. The
participant identifies with the central figure only in the negative sense, retained in
popular art, of desiring the destruction of its formal closure, which he experiences
no longer as the basis of his representational "imitation," but merely as a barrier
excluding him from the center. Only if the whole is broken can the breaker possess
his part. The fact that formal closure must be realized as a prerequisite of its
destruction is an element of the self-consciousness of high, but not of popular art.
Yet popular culture has its answer to its rival's claims. The "end" of culture, in
the Darwinian sense that explains why humanity survived in the first place, is to
permit a group that mimesis has made its own potential worst enemy to obtain
appetitive satisfaction. The sparagmos shows that the originary deferral of
potential violence through the sign was not free of cost; the resentment generated
by this deferral provokes this supplementary violent discharge of mimetically
bound energy when the deferral is terminated.
High art well understands that the primary operation of secular culture is not the
provision of appetitive satisfaction but the renunciation expressed by the aborted
gesture. But for the bottom line of human society to be positive, what is deferred
must be accomplished, and this applies not only to appetitive satisfaction, the
ultimately realized pleasure of consumption, but also to the discharge of originary
resentment in the sparagmos. There is no a priori reason for culture to reflect on
itself; culture need only defer consumption sufficiently for it to take place without
Originary Violence 121
conflict, even at the additional cost of the violent discharge of resentment. To the
extent that all cultural activities perform the same basic function, high culture's
ascetic pretensions strike the partisan of popular culture as hypocritical. Whether
or not one accepts one's individual responsibility for the violence of the
sparagmos, it is the necessary evil that esthetic culture continues to reproduce on
the imaginary scene of representation.
High art is the formal expression of cultural totality. The renonciation of the
material referent is rewarded by the beauty of the (nearly) immaterial sign.
Because religion lacks the flexibility of art in abandoning the reality of its referent,
religious sacrifice can defer originary resentment toward the divine center, but not
mature resentment toward a human occupant of the center. The society of the
Greek city-states only evolved a secular esthetic once it had freed itself from the
ritually fixed hierarchies of the archaic empires.
But if Greek religion takes second place to art, in the other birthplace of Western
civilization, Hebrew religion dominates and expels the esthetic. Indifferent to the
secular distinction between art and entertainment, the anesthetic divinity has no
use for images of any kind. The esthetic elements of ritual that do not fall under
this ban, such as song and dance, are activities of the human periphery rather than
representations of the sacred center. When Chassidim dance in honor of God in
imitation of their biblical ancestors, the center is left empty; none of the dancers
represents God himself.
The central question of Western civilization before the postmodern era has been
how to reconcile the high art of the Greeks with the uncompromising Hebraic
expulsion of the esthetic, which continues to be reflected in Christian suspicion
of secular art. Secular culture since the Renaissance sees its relationship to
religion in terms of oppression and liberation, categories that fmd easy analogies
in the political sphere. The originary hypothesis gives us a vantage point from
which to examine this relationship anew.
Esthetic experience depends on the paradoxical oscillation between the
contemplation of the sign with its referent and the contemplation of the referent
without the sign. The sign assures us of the significance of the referent, but the
referent cannot stand alone without losing its significance and returning us to the
sign. This model describes the experience of the esthetic at a moment prior to any
conceivable distinction between high and popular. The oscillation is that of
ostensive signification itself, circulating between sign and referent. The subject
attempting to forget the sign's reminder of triangular mediation in order to possess
the thing-in-itself is continually thrown back upon this mediation when the thing-
Sparagmos and Resentment 122
in-itself vanishes before his eyes. The object can be appropriated imaginarily only
through the sign; this is the origin of the specifically human imagination.
What makes art so powerful an anthropological discovery procedure is our need
to purge ourselves of the violence inherent in the centrality of the image. In the
end, what justifies representation is its management of resentment in the service
of appetitive satisfaction, and this management necessarily passes through the
sparagmos. We may purchase a good conscience by imagining ourselves in the
place of the tragic hero who is the object of our resentment rather than give this
resentment free rein. But in the end, we are participants in his undoing. In the last
analysis, our esthetic pleasure, whether in tragedy or in the crudest popular
fantasy, derives less from taking pleasure in the details of the hero's suffering than
from the experience of formal necessity that justifies our imagination of this
suffering. Even the ultimate Mallarmean deconstruction of the image, "le sein
brûlé d'une antique Amazone" ["the burnt breast of an ancient Amazon"—that is,
the right breast, supposedly prevented from growing so that the Amazon could
draw her bow], leaves just enough to the imagination to provide a focus for
imaginary violence. Hypocrite spectateur…
But if the introduction of the sparagmos into our model of the originary scene
problematizes the purgative operation of the esthetic, it makes clearer the crucial
function of maintaining in memory the imageless sign. This operation is
accomplished by religion. The originary category of the sacred cannot
differentiate between the central object and the being of the locus it occupies;
religion proper begins when the feast is over, the object has disappeared, and the
sign remains in the memory along with the image of its referent. The subsistence
of the ostensive sign as a communal cultural reality after the central locus has
been emptied is guaranteed by the persistence of both this image, which no longer
corresponds to anything the community can point to, and the central locus bereft
of its occupant.
The "being" of the locus is the divinity. Like the content of all revelations, the
dissociation imposed by the Mosaic revelation between the divinity and the image
was already present from the beginning. The central object is remembered through
the image, but the image masks the real source of significance, which is not the
object but the total configuration of the scene, held together by the mimetic
tension between center and periphery. The religious moment internalizes the
founding principle of the community in its union around the originary center.
The tension inherent in the dual conception of the central locus, spatio-
temporally particular but ontologically absolute, is not resolvable within religion
itself. It is reproduced in our era in the tension between physical anthropologists'
Originary Violence 123
sign. The participants who approach and dismember the object act as a community
only in the minimal sense that they are bound together by the memory of the sign;
this minimum of virtual solidarity, consonant with the parsimony of our
hypothesis of origin, is just sufficient to permit them to survive the sparagmos.
This minimally cooperative action is the prototype of all ethical activities. In
contrast with the symmetry of the originary emission of the sign, the archetype of
the moral order, which is characterized by a temporary but absolute deferral of
conflict, the sparagmos is not the prototype of a communal ideal. It is just
cooperative enough so that the community does not dissolve in the contagion of
mimetic violence.
But if the origin of the ethical is only minimally moral, then it is maximally
immoral. The violence of the sparagmos makes it the origin of evil; the first
collective act is the "fall of man." The criterion of parsimony would indeed be
violated by any model that required a durable state of nonviolence as a
consequence of the emission of the sign. The sparagmos is the originary violent
act, for violence is conceivable only within the human order of representation.
Viewed from the standpoint of its future repetition in ritual, it is a cultural act, a
"tradition." But this only goes to show that violence is inherent in cultural
traditions. The dedifferentiation of violence exceeds all differences but the
difference of language. Disorder that exceeds language is no longer human; it is
the horizon against which the human drama plays itself out, and which the
violence of the drama continually challenges.
We must therefore avoid the temptation to reduce the violence of the sparagmos
to the "discharge of aggression." What is being discharged is not some Freudian
Trieb but originary resentment against the center, which itself derives from the
mimetically induced excess of appetite for the central object. Only in hindsight
does this discharge of resentment appear to have taken place safely under the
control of the culture of deferral inaugurated by the sign. The violence that
destroys the central figure eliminates the originary inspiration for the (esthetic)
judgment that produced the sign. Religion founds the community on the subsistent
being of the center. But the primal experience of Being is that of mourning; the
mystical intuition of an ineffable essence recalls the loss of its originary
incarnation. The central figure that originally attracted the group's appetites has
been defigured by those who henceforth depend on it all the more as their cultural
model.
Originary Violence 125
property. The sparagmos creates the private individual by effacing the public
visibility of his action and its results, in contrast to that of the original (aborted)
gesture of appropriation.
This passage à l'acte provides the model for the crucial realization of evil intent,
which would otherwise remain the purely imaginary object of esthetic catharsis.
There is no need to postulate an internal differentiation of the community that
would violate the equalitarian morality of the sign. The sparagmos, in which the
exercise of violence toward the sacred center is accompanied by the denial of
individual responsibility for this violence, is the model for all acts of evil, both
collective and individual.
paradox (like that of the "third man" with which it has much in common) is just a
metaphysical version of the paradox of mimesis discussed in Chapter 2, expressed
in a vocabulary that recalls the Heraclitean argument in the Cratylus.9 For the sign
of language to constitute itself as a trace of a different (or différant) kind from
those of previous life-forms, including their "language," the recuperation of the
"trace" by unconscious mimesis must be revealed to be inadequate. This
revelation, the matter of the originary hypothesis, is entirely lacking in Derrida's
ontology. What is missing from this philosophical exposition is the very notion of
the human. This is the ultimate demonstration of metaphysics' incapacity to
generate an anthropology.
*
The upshot of our analysis is that the realized resentment we call evil is
indispensable to the constitution of the human community. In order that the center
be constituted as a being independent of the material object that occupies it, this
object must be destroyed. But the revolt against God must end in failure. The
participants in the sparagmos, in seeking to destroy the center itself, attain only
its material occupant; their intent is frustrated by the persistence of the sign and
the significant memory that guarantees it. The sparagmos is the felix culpa by
which alone humanity could come into being bearing the "knowledge of good and
evil" imparted in the originary event.
The postmodern era has is a "problem of good" rather than a "problem of evil."
Positive social science finds it harder to understand altruism than selfishness,
order than disorder. Scientists seek to explain human as well as animal
selflessness by the presence of an "altruism gene" that would contribute to
reproductive fitness. In this modern equivalent of phrenology, a material
equivalent is sought for "dispositions" that are simple consequences of human
mimesis. Evil behavior, on the contrary, seems to require no explanation, as
though the success of human societies could be measured by the reproductive
fitness of its individual members taken separately. This cynicism reflects the
widespread resentment of the social order as such in the age of "the end of
culture." In these circumstances, it is useful to recall that the originary form of
moral good is preserved and reproduced in the virtual scene of representation that
is actualized in our everyday use of language. The inalienably reciprocal structure
of linguistic communication lies at the core of our humanity; it is a model of good
that precedes any possible model of evil.
The sparagmos introduces into our model of the originary scene a moment of
apparently unbounded selfishness that anticipates Nietzsche's movement "beyond
good and evil," while at the same time debunking through its mimetic symmetry
Originary Violence 131
his resentful dream of the superior "overman." The individual participant in the
sparagmos is able to act without concern for his fellows' actions because his act,
however violent, cannot lead out of the community defined a priori by the sign;
but this implies that, by the same token, all his fellow participants act in exactly
the same manner.
The guarantee provided to the social order by representation as such,
independently of the ritual repetition of the originary scene, is a resource first
tapped by the bourgeois market system—and by the romantics whose ostensibly
antimarket individualism was in fact an adaptation to this system. In the first stage
of this process of "secularization," the selfish desires of the participants in market
exchange are recuperated for the benefit of the whole, as in Mandeville's
eighteenth-century "Fable of the Becs." But a second crucial moment comes with
the recognition of the mimetic nature of these "individualistic" desires, and the
birth of the institutions of consumer society that generate as well as exploit them.
This is the cultural era of modernism. The romantics continued to respect the
traditional opposition between good and evil, which they saw being sacrificed to
the immorality of the free market. The modernists followed Nietzsche in their
rejection of this opposition. In their case as well as his, the ultimate and
unexpressed article of faith was the universality of the originary scene. But the
Holocaust, the ultimate political expression of modernism, forces us to rethink
this universality in the postmodern era: to what extent can the unity of the scene
innocently be imagined?
In ending the deferral initiated by the sign, in lifting the moral inhibition on the
aim of the originary appropriative gesture, the sparagmos opens the space of the
ethical. In this collective rather than communal action, the symmetrical concern
for one's fellows that characterized the moment of signification has been replaced
by a violent concentration on the object in an undifferentiated context of
resentment and appetite.10 The communal peace, instigated by the sign, that is the
ultimate guarantee of the sparagmos is for the moment no longer a matter of
concern. In the sparagmos, the sign, as the expression of renunciation, is
"forgotten"; with the destruction of its original referent, it passes out of
consciousness into the unconscious of collective mediation wherein its guarantee
resides. The forgetting of the sign defers the moral model with respect to which
the participants in the sparagmos would be condemned for their act. Although the
individual members of the community remain within the moral context
established by the sign, they are not for the moment guided by the renunciation of
desire imposed by this context.
Sparagmos and Resentment 132
The possibility of crime, that is, of deviation from ethical as opposed to moral
behavior, is prefigured in the originary evil or immoral act of violence toward the
center. Just as the criminal typically satisfies his resentment in isolation, the
sparagmos already isolates its participants from each other by suspending the
communal reciprocity created by the sign.
The criminal's isolation is that of the individual usurper of the center. The origin
of social differentiation is the act of such a usurper (the "big-man" referred to in
The End of Culture), and this breach of originary equality, socialist utopias to the
contrary, can never be healed.
This human usurpation of the center—and the "mature" form of resentment that
follows from it—had already been anticipated in the unconsciously controlled
anarchy of the sparagmos.
11
The purest expression of the fundamental religious intuition that the sacred being
of the scene subsists independently of its central figure is found in the revelation
to Moses at the "burning bush" in Exodus 3.1 The foregrounding of the sparagmos
sheds new light on this scene, while giving particular urgency to the "Jewish
question" that the Holocaust was intended to foreclose: Is the anthropological
truth of the Mosaic revelation indeed transcended by the Pauline revelation that
founds Ch ristianity?
Messianic Awaiting
The structure of awaiting is always vulnerable to attempts to close the circle;
awaiting must be satisfiable in principle. But in the Mosaic revelation, not only is
awaiting thematized in what Martin Buber emphasizes as the future sense of ehyeh
(I shall be), its permanence is implicit in God's reply of a declarative sentence to
the request for his name.3 To await the divine in the world is to accept its
ontological separation from the world (which is not to forgo the ironic questioning
or deconstruction of this as of any formal separation). Because the awaited arrival
of the Messiah, even were it eventually to take place, can never be anticipated, the
Jew is defined by his thematization of awaiting rather than by his expectation of
what he awaits. This thematization has come to dominate postmodern thought in
its secular translation as différance, or deferral. To await the Messiah is to inhabit
a worldly scene defined by the deferral of his arrival. This awaiting has the same
Sparagmos and Resentment 136
structure as the impossible desire of the man of resentment to abolish the scene of
representation on which alone his desire is defined.
The Passion demonstrates that the enunciation of the moral model of absolute
reciprocity as an ethic sufficient for the conduct of everyday life, far from
providing an "ontological proof" that the moral Kingdom is realizable on earth, is
destined to reanimate the originary resentment that led to the sparagmos. Unlike
the self-perpetuating thematization of awaiting in the Mosaic revelation, making
explicit the implicit moral configuration of the originary event undermines its
original deferring effect.
At the origin, the sparagmos occurs once the sign has appropriated for its
peripheral enunciators the formal closure of the central figure, so that it is no
longer necessary for this closure to subsist in itself. As it comes to appear
superfluous, the figure's figurality becomes vulnerable to the resentment it
generates and open to the defiguration of the sparagmos.
But what this central figure "says" to the periphery in the originary event is the
substance of what Jesus would articulate as morality: "You are all equal, because
you all imitate me." This message of peace is in effect a call to war; the central
figure affirms its difference from its peripheral imitators in the act of denying it.
There is no escaping from this impasse any more than from any other variant of
the foundational human paradox.
Those who bewail the perversity of the Jews' rejection of Jesus's message tend
to forget the Gospels' insistence on the unanimity of this rejection at the moment
of the crucifixion. The utopian Kingdom of Jesus's preaching could not be
convincing in itself. The light that shone in the darkness and that the darkness
knew not is a metaphor for the sparagmatic extinction of the one who would usurp
the center. The first real Christians were the Gentiles converted by Paul's
centralization of the Christ, not the Jews convinced by Jesus's moral
omnicentrism.
The success of Christianity is founded on the failure of Jesus's moral revelation
because this revelation is part of a whole that includes the worship of the
victimized divine enunciator, the Word made flesh. For Christians, God's promise
of deferred but eternal presence was fulfilled in Jesus because the crucifixion
demonstrates the eternity of this presence in the logos—in language as the
ultimate guarantee of human reciprocity. Those who remained Jews claimed, on
the contrary, that if this guarantee indeed exists, there is no particular reason to
value either Jesus's enunciation or its enunciator. All were already aware of the
moral imperative of reciprocity; but they also knew that it could not become the
The "Jewish Question" 137
inspired by the Roman occupiers. It is Saul’s falling-away, not his Judaism itself,
that is revealed to him on the road to Damascus as already tantamount to belief in
Christianity. Judaism is not meant to be an established church. The eternal exile
who commemorates each year the Exodus from Egypt should permit the
Christians to withdraw in their turn from an Israel defined by the eternal awaiting
of God's presence. Such a one would not have been visited by a revelation of the
centralized victim.
Hebrews. All potential conflict is to be purged by the passion story, in which the
sparagmos is exposed as a lynching for which everyone is responsible. Everyone;
yet the chief actors in the story are the Jews, who refused to accept the
reevaluation of the figural as a guarantee rather than an obstacle to universal
religion. The particularist interpretation of the Passion, which puts the blame on
the Jews rather than on mankind in general, is no doubt a sacrificial misreading
of the Christian message. But it is not only suggested by the Gospels, it is
historically inevitable. Just as Jesus's omnicentric moral message is overshadowed
by the centrality of its enunciator, so mankind's universal guilt for the crucifixion
is eclipsed by that of his local adversaries.
Persecution of the Jews was never altogether successful, nor really intended to
be so. What constitutes them as the first Western minority in the sense of realizing
an articulated cultural interaction with the surrounding majoritary world is the
paradoxical necessity of their survival in their guilt-bearing scapegoat role. The
mimetic behavior required by the imitatio Christi is accompanied by the
resentment of those who refuse to imitate, who follow God's Law rather than a
divine-human mediator. The position of the Jews as a stigmatized minority in
Christian society articulates the tension between the figural and the religious, or,
in other terms, between incarnation and abstraction, that is the source of the West's
peculiar strength.
The anesthetic universality of the Hebrew God was a reaction to the Hebrews'
dependent status in the Egyptian empire, but the relationship it established was
exodic rather than minoritary. The Hebrews could borrow from the "wisdom
literature" of their masters, but their theology—their originary anthropology—
belonged to a different world. In contrast, in the Christian imperium, the
underlying theology was the same. The "chosen people" were no longer the
unique witnesses of the true God; they became the original witnesses of his
promise, now renewed and once again deferred. The "ecumenical" Gentiles
accepted Christ's guarantee of the fulfillment of the promise; only the Jews could
accept the horizon of endless awaiting.
The all-too-familiar figure of the Jewish moneylender is a caricature of the
minority's function within the majority: the agent of exchange value as opposed
to use value, deferred as opposed to immediate satisfaction. The alien minority's
anesthetic ease with exchange and circulation and the majority's world of figural
stability stand in a relation of mutual resentment.
As the self-abolishing goal of Christian resentment, the elimination of the Jews,
by conversion or "final solution," has been throughout history the touchstone of
Christian universality.6 The success of Christianity as a universal religion requires
Sparagmos and Resentment 140
in principle the conversion of all humanity, but the measure of this success is the
conversion of the group from which Christianity recruited its original
membership. Yet the Pauline epistles offer no specific model of Jewish
conversion. Paul's preaching, whether to the Romans or the Hebrews, consistently
demands mimetic adherence to the scene of the crucifixion.7 His establishment of
the centrality of the crucified Christ makes further conversions on the model of
his own inconceivable.
The birth of organized antisemitism in medieval Europe coincides with the
Crusades, whose participants, bearing the sign of Christ, were incited to impose
stigmatizing signs on those not of their number. This differential stigmatization
was precisely what the anesthetic imperative of the Mosaic revelation had been
meant to prevent. To stigmatize the Jews with a figure only demonstrates the
superiority of their afigurality, whereas the centralization of the figure of Christ
as the mediator of the omnicentric community reinforces the center as a locus of
sacrifice.
The Jews' anesthetic faith kept them—or at least a "saving remnant"—from
succumbing to the seduction of Christian figurality at a time when there was as
yet no ethical ground on which to condemn the particularism of this figurality.
Today the prudential advantage of the anesthetic position is clearer. In spite of the
Bible's paternalistic language, the unfigurability of the Hebrew God evacuates
polemics about such things as God's gender. The attribution of gender to God is
ultimately a matter not of theology but of figuration; but figuration unsupported
by image is merely heuristic. We think of God in something like a human form
because the human is our only model of a person, but there is no objective support
for our image. Thus, in a patriarchal society, we imagine the "typical" human
language user and the God who created him in his image as male; when gender
roles become more equal, our imaginary figure of God may be modified
accordingly.
The postmodern era is well aware of the strategic role of the scenic center in the
mimetic exchange of resentments. Even if the figure of Christ cannot legitimately
be called a figure of resentment, it remains a potential focus of concentration for
the resentful, like the grain of sand that brings about crystallization in a solution
at the saturation point. Pure water remains unaffected; but how many can apply
this metaphor to their souls? The historical revelation of the single son of God
cannot but provoke the envy of those not so honored, whatever assurance we are
given of his infinite imitability. Today one might ask, for example, why not the
daughter of God? No figure can be general enough to include the entire human
community; as soon as attention is concentrated on it, someone is bound to see in
The "Jewish Question" 141
it a sign of exclusion. One lesson of the postmodern era is the essential plurality
of the human, its inexhaustibility by any single figure.
By rejecting the Trinity's integration of religion with history and God with man,
Judaism maintains a clear separation between the sacred and the profane, or in
other terms, between words and things. Whereas the Jewish pseudoeschatology
of the Messiah is no more than an ironic commentary on the paradoxical
unliveability of indefinite deferral, the Christian eschatology guarantees to its
believers the closure of worldly history.
The Christian apocalypse defines human self-knowledge as finite, where the less
ambitious Mosaic epistemology of deferral can accommodate the unbounded
knowledge that accumulates throughout history. The awaiting of the Messiah is a
learning process, a time of ethical evolution, whereas Christ's return or "second
coming," although similarly deferred, reveals only what had already been revealed
on his first appearance. The canonical account of this return in the book of
Revelation presents the historical time of awaiting not as a process of the
acquisition of ever greater degrees of freedom, but as the societal derepression of
violence. To the Christian preconception of the "apocalyptic" state of the world at
the second coming, we may oppose the quizzical dicta of rabbis and secular Jews
alike on the coming of the Messiah, which is not unlike that of the "unexpected
examination" discussed in Chapter 3.8
omnicentric par la force des choses, self and other can no longer defer their
mutual recognition. What is missing from this apocalyptic vision is a concept of
how the scene is to function in a postscenic era. Culture, and cultures, go on after
the Bomb; the "Hiroshimists" only repeat the impatience of the first Christians in
thinking that deferral has been abolished and culture returned to a state of nature.
In contrast to this emphasis on physical destruction, the Holocaust is about a
human violence that exceeds and discredits the scene of culture. So long as the
scene of representation wholly contains the violence that is perpetrated upon it,
we remain within the domain of the esthetic. Evil, as we have seen in the
preceding chapter, follows the model of the sparagmos in its destruction of the
worldly correlate of the scene of representation; it is the irreversible defiguration
of the figure. We may then understand absolute evil as an evil so great that it has
no figure whatsoever.
Evil can be recuperated by culture, but only a posteriori. Its intent is to destroy
the scene of culture; the failure of its intent is the failure of resentment, since it
depends on what it seeks to annihilate, but its failure in reality is the result not of
internal logic but of insufficient means. The postmodern era begins at the moment
in which we realize that the means are indeed available.
The originary violence of the sparagmos intends not merely the defiguration of
the central figure but the obliteration of its very being. Its failure to do so is due
to the religious preservation of the being of the scene, not to any lack of intention
on the part of the participants—to conscience, we might say, rather than
consciousness, this being the moment at which they are distinguished. In the
derived mode of sacrificial ritual, the radical nature of this defiguration is
mitigated by the force of religious commemoration.
With the decline of the religious under the pressure of modern resentment,
radical evil is rediscovered in the form of a transsacrificial purgation, a
defiguration that exceeds and denies the scenic in dememorializing its victim(s),
obliterating every trace of them from the internal scene of representation of those
who are to "benefit" from their elimination. Those who actually carried out this
work, as their leaders told them in the horribly perverted but still recognizable
terms of the Judeo-Christian civilization they were attempting to transcend, were
obliged to steel themselves "heroically" to the task of denying the sacralizing
effect of the figures of death they were obliged to witness. The mission of the final
solution was to cleanse the esthetic scene once and for all of those whose
anesthetism made them the living reminders of the sparagmatic origin of the
figure, whose existence was therefore incompatible with tribal compactness.
Sparagmos and Resentment 144
The horror of the camps is their scenelessness; for the first time in history, a
central policy of violence is deliberately excluded from the scenic structure of
culture. The rationalized, industrial slaughter carried out far from the German
heartland was meant to avoid attracting public attention, to permit not only denial
but ignorance. This destruction was not intended to be exemplary, to play out a
sacrificial drama in which the executioner is in complicity with his victim, but
simply to be effective, to remove a certain figure from the scene.
Thus, what makes the Holocaust exemplary of a newly radical category of evil
is not the multiplicity of its victims, but their lack of esthetic exemplarity. The
victim of the sparagmos is a figure; the victims of the Holocaust were chiffres,
abstractions. The antisemitic rage that had fueled the Nazi movement and that had
been vented in moments like the Kristallnacht had to give way to an industrially
rationalized extermination; it was no longer a matter of discharging this rage, but
of purging it once and for all. Like a carnivore killing off the species it feeds on,
the Nazi model was not meant to express antisemitism but to abolish the need for
it. The more Nazi society revealed its mimetic obsessions with "ugly" images,
whether of Jews or of "decadent" art, the more desperately it sought the final
expulsion of these images, after which its obsessions would presumably be
lifted.10 This was history's most radical attempt to expunge the Pauline revelation
of the centrality of the victim in the cause of reserving the center for the positive
figure of Aryan exemplarity. It nevertheless remains within the Pauline-Christian
context by the very fact of this attempted abolition. Paul's problem is that he
cannot forget the figure of the other he has persecuted. But if that is the sole
difficulty, then it should suffice to remove the figure of the persecuted other from
the scene so as to leave nothing but the celebratory image of the self.
The failure of this repetition of the Pauline experience of persecution in Christian
Europe after nearly two millennia revealed the ultimate inadequacy of a
recuperative, which is to say, a political, esthetic. The final solution, the
culmination of this esthetic, is also the first act of the postmodern transcendence
of the esthetic.
For resentment cannot be abolished any more by sating it than by ignoring it. As
a result of the Holocaust, the victimary figure, rejecting esthetic catharsis, returns
with a vengeance. Rather than dwell on the paradoxical nature of the Nazi project
as a scenic hatred that would abolish the scene of its hate—a structure it shares
with so many lesser projects—we would do better to regard its apocalyptic
accomplishment as a revelatory antidote to future utopias of all kinds.
It took some time for the Holocaust to enter the general consciousness as the
largely successful realization of a model of absolute evil. It offers a powerful and
The "Jewish Question" 145
Rhetoric, the frère ennemi of philosophy, has had a bad name in Western thought
since Plato. But without rhetoric, ethical revolutions would never take place.
Force majeure, military conquest explain nothing; what force made the soldiers
march? Historically better causes only replace inferior ones when people are
persuaded of their superiority. Originary thinking must clarify our understanding
of the sources and consequences of these revolutions.
Like originary resentment, of which it is the expression, originary rhetoric is an
"immature" form the full development of which awaits the possibility, realized
with the declarative sentence, of thematizing the latent symmetry between the
peripheral human subject and the sacred center. In the originary scene, the loci of
being and language are incompatible; the sign exists only to represent—to
imitate—the center that its user cannot possess. In the "early" phenomenon of
thought described in Chapter 7, the "first" participant discovers the necessity of
converting the gesture of appropriation into a sign. In contrast, originary rhetoric
is the mimetic appeal of the visibly already-constituted community to the "late,"
isolated individual who for fear of exclusion from this community is induced to
renounce his attempt to appropriate the central object. (Needless to say, what are
distinguished are not different individuals but different moments of the founding
relationship between the human individual and the community.) From the
beginning, rhetoric attacks not the other's utterance but his position, vulnerable
through its excessive claim on the center.
Sparagmos and Resentment 148
The originary event allows for no neutral vantage point from which the
instrumental force of its rhetoric can be perceived. The persuader is as moved by
this force as the interlocutor whose difference from himself he seeks to abolish;
the former's priority in the use of the sign leaves him with no residual superiority
over the latter in the face of the absolute difference accorded by the sign to its
central referent. To persuade one's fellows—and oneself—to defer conflict
precludes the language of individual desire.
At the origin, it is the (free, symmetrical) form of language that liberates
humanity from the animal world, not its content. If we examine this content alone,
we see only the alienation of human freedom to the center in something like a
Hobbesian social contract. (Hence a superficial understanding of the originary
hypothesis has led some to consider the scene of origin as nothing but a staging
of the social contract.) The originary rhetoric that persuades the participants to
avert conflict by renouncing their appropriative movement toward the center is
effective only because its dynamic is symmetrical. Had the signal for renunciation
been given by a single dominant individual, it would by definition have failed.
For this is the pattern of prehuman conflict avoidance, where each subordinate
animal recoils before the "alpha”'s threat rather than conceiving itself—through
the necessary mediation of the center—as a member of a community capable of
enforcing general equality.
The sacralization of the center is the "better cause," not by virtue of any quality
inherent in the central being itself, but because it defers conflict within the group.
The model of originary rhetoric is not that of the lawyer persuading a neutral jury,
but that of the disputant who is able to persuade his adversary—inspire him to
linguistic mimesis—because his language bears the force of the community.
Powerful rhetorics need no third parties; they undermine the presuppositions that
sustain their adversary's dialectical capacity.
The operation of linguistic persuasion for which we use the term "rhetoric" is
associated with the law court because it is there that the linguistic transcendence
of potential conflict was first thematized. But the thematization of persuasion is
already resistance to it; to speak of "persuasion" rather than logical demonstration
implies that one is not oneself persuaded, and even that to persuade others requires
that one not be oneself persuaded. The study of rhetoric is the beginning of its
demystification—of demystification in general. To teach rhetoric is to step back
from the scene of its originary use, to declare oneself sufficiently far from crisis
to be able to resist its persuasive force. Persuasion can only be reduced to a
repeatable technique once the rhetorical power of the community, as manifested
Originary and Victimary Rhetoric 149
in ritual, has become an object of reflection drained of its sacred aura, no longer
revelatory but instrumental.
Although the Greeks taught other agonistic arts, rhetoric is the only one that
depends on the deliberate reproduction of the critical tension of the originary
scene. To teach racing or wrestling, one steps back from the phenomena to
observe them, but one does not "demystify" them; in learning to anticipate the
moves of my adversary, I do not concentrate my effort on resisting their mimetic
force. Reflection on persuasive language, on the contrary, is a conquest of a new
freedom from the clutches of communal belief; I learn to resist the persuasion of
the scene in order better to produce it in others. Rhetoric exemplifies the
secularization of the institutions of human interaction that will become the driving
force of market society; the market gains efficiency and dynamism from the
continual discounting of reflection on its operations. What is bought and sold at
the nerve centers of the market—stock markets, currency exchanges—are the
products of the ever-changing anticipation of others' knowledge and intentions.
The paradox of originary rhetoric is that persuasion, indifferent to truth, is
accomplished by means of an utterance the signified of which is the absolute truth
on which humanity is founded. From the beginning, the relation between the
rhetorical and the representational use of language is one of mutual dependency;
we are persuaded to represent the central object because of its significance, but
the object is significant only because we are persuaded to represent it. At a later
stage, this relation will evolve into the opposition between rhetoric and
metaphysics. The scene of metaphysics requires no persuasion, only logical
demonstration of a truth indifferent to person and place. Plato/Socrates' scorn for
Gorgias and his ilk is founded on the rhetor's indifference to truth as he ups the
ante of the oratorical agon. Since the typical civil case involves roughly
symmetrical arguments, the winner may well be the one whose skill "makes the
worse cause appear the better." But really powerful arguments overwhelm their
adversary without need for judge or jury; these are never understood as merely
"persuasive."
Just as the symmetrical oppositions of Saussurean linguistics cannot exist within
originary language, which represents the uniquely significant, so the rhetorical
duel of the law courts cannot exist within originary rhetoric, which begins with
communal unanimity. Like all symmetries, that of the rhetorical agon derives
from a unique difference. In the courtroom reproduction of the originary pattern
of crisis and persuasion, each of the opposing advocates attempts to reproduce in
his hearers a crisis state of isolation from the community that only his language is
"originary" enough to resolve. Each speaker in the debate persuades us in turn.
Sparagmos and Resentment 150
mature resentment with the birth of hierarchical society and the observable reality
of the occupation of the communal center by another human being. But it is not
necessary to posit so rigid a connection between models of interaction and social
structures. Centralization is relative to the scene on which it occurs; it need not
await realization in the most visible forms of social practice before being
thematized in everyday human interaction. Just as we may take the inauguration
of the imperative-declarative dialogue to be the beginning of mature rhetoric, so
we may take it to be the first act of mature resentment.
In the terms of the linguistic universe obtaining when he speaks, the speaker of
the imperative need have no thematic sense of superiority to his interlocutor, any
more than a baby calling for a toy or its mother considers itself superior to those
it expects to obey it. The linguistic structure of the imperative provides the sole
necessary asymmetry. But the declarative reply, by bringing to light the difference
between the locutor and locutee of the imperative, provides the occasion for the
scandalized thematization of the other's centrality that we call resentment. The
imperative speaker is now shown to have usurped the center in attempting to speak
with its authoritative voice. The declarative is no doubt the constative form that
lends metaphysics its objectivity, but in its subversion of the imperative
intentional structure it is in the first place the formal expression of mature
resentment, which is to say, of rhetoric. Metaphysics and polemical rhetoric, the
frères ennemis of Western thought, are the fils jumeaux of the declarative response
to the imperative.
In the declarative versus imperative model of mature rhetoric, the agon is
decided by position on the scene of representation, not position in the world. The
declarative reply denounces the naïveté of the imperative's assumption that
language has power over reality. In place of the immediate presence defined by
the originary community and invoked by the user of the imperative, the
declarative offers the purely imaginary presence of a linguistic model.
The offer of a sign instead of a thing is an objectively unfriendly gesture toward
the original speaker. We all know the joke about the man who asks his valet to go
see if he left his hat on the bed; the valet returns, saying that yes, he did leave his
hat on the bed. We suspect the declarative speaker, like the valet, of playing dumb
in resentful revolt against his master. But whatever the intention or ability of the
declarative speaker to carry out the command, the metadiscourse of the
declarative, as opposed to the normal nondiscursive response to the imperative,
opens up a new linguistic possibility within which resentment can insert itself.
The declarative reply functions as an objective expression of resentment in
denying the central discursive position of its interlocutor. Yet it is also the
Sparagmos and Resentment 152
insist on God's invisibility as speaker; the language of the center emanates from
it, but is not enunciated by it.
The Genesis creation speech is exemplary of the overreaching nature of the
rhetoric of mastery. The language does not persuade by itself, but as a supplement
to a power relationship, the vulnerability of which it thereby reveals. Feminist
cultural analysis has promoted a model of human interaction that defines male
privilege by the use of language, and more generally by the occupation of the
spectator's peripheral position on the scene of representation. But this model only
reflects the increased circulation of desire and its discourses in nineteenth-century
bourgeois society and the concomitant decline of the rhetoric of mastery observed
in its early stages by Nietzsche. As a general rule, the use of signs is not an
attribute of mastery but its opposite. The master is the sign, he need not emit it.
The iconography of majesty, as practiced, say, by Louis XIV in the early modem
era, consists in concentrating maximal expressive power in a minimal sign, a
vanishingly slight gesture—which nevertheless remains an ever-so-small
indication of weakness. The only authentic rhetoric of mastery is silence.
Victimary Rhetoric
In our analysis, the rhetoric of mastery is derivative of the primary form of
rhetoric, which emerges from the periphery as a denunciation of those who usurp
the center: the outsider, or the collectivity of outsiders, undermines the position
of the insider. By the basic geometry of the center-periphery opposition, rhetoric
is a "majoritary" phenomenon; the peripheral denouncers are more numerous than
their central targets. But the essential features of the circle are derived from those
of the mimetic triangle, where numbers are irrelevant. The success of the
declarative rhetoric that persuades the original mediator/imperative speaker to
renounce his claim to the center is independent of the threat of many against one.
The rhetoric of mastery retains the fundamental geometry of the mimetic
triangle/circle while inverting the direction of communication. But modern
victimary rhetoric performs a geometric inversion of the mimetic configuration
itself.2
This is not a simple switching of positions. "Victim" is a central, not a peripheral
category. Victimary rhetoric attacks the majoritary periphery by positing the
equivalence of the eccentric position of the persecuted minority with the
sacrificial center. Thus victimary rhetoric is not simply the dialectical antithesis
of the rhetoric of mastery. In defining a new peripherality as the result of exile
Originary and Victimary Rhetoric 155
from the center, victimary rhetoric temporalizes the static geometric structure; the
postmodern victim is a victim of history.
The violence of the sparagmos demonstrates that, in the minds of the
participants, it is they rather than the central figure who are the original victims.
The victimary is not the unequivocal category it may appear to be from a cursory
reading of Girard. The distinction between persecutor and victim is an etic, not an
emic one; the use of these categories destabilizes the human center versus
periphery configuration. Once they are thematized and become weapons in the
rhetorical agon, the respective positions are revealed to have been reversible from
the beginning. The sparagmos is the revenge of the "victims" of the object's
withdrawal from the arena of mimetic desire, and the object's revenge for its
defiguration in the sparagmos is the constitution of subsistent divine Being in its
place. This originary series of reversals is the foundation of the institutions that
preserve the cultural order.
The historical emergence of the category of the victimary corresponds to the
cultural articulation of the reversibility that resentment has reflected from the
outset. Originary resentment already makes an inarticulate victimary claim.
Exclusion from the center is always felt as victimage, however ethically justified
this exclusion may be and however dependent the resenter may be on the center
he attacks.
Explicit victimary rhetoric is an innovation of Christianity. How indeed can Saul
answer the complaint, "Why do you persecute me?" But the exemplarity of Christ
as the victimary model maintains the emphasis on the center.3 In contrast, today's
victimary rhetorics emerge from and remain on the periphery of the circle; indeed,
they put the very idea of a circular scenic structure into question.
Rhetoric is the voice of resentment against centrality, whether the speaker seeks
to confound an opponent or to urge his own partisans to action. Traditionally, this
resentment is not expressed directly in noncritical situations. Following the model
of the imperative-declarative dialogue, traditional rhetoric opposes the objectivity
of the subject's position to the subjective illusion of the opponent's. The rhetoric
of explicit invidious comparison belongs to the context of social revolution, where
it functions to encourage the slaves to throw off their chains. In contrast, the
persuasive force of victimary rhetoric is directed essentially to the majority rather
than the minority. Victimary rhetoric insistently thematizes positional difference.
It makes explicit the critique of centrality that has always been the motivation of
rhetoric, a revelation that can only be made with impunity from the inverted
victimary position—the position of internal exile created by Rousseau in his
Rêveries du promeneur solitaire.4
Sparagmos and Resentment 156
Victimary rhetoric reaffirms the reciprocity of the Christian moral utopia, not as
universal love, but in the resentful mode of "the last shall be the first," the "last"
being defined as the collective victims of historic injustice. To occupy the
victimary position absolves one of the narrowness of one's own worldly interests;
the place of the victim is the sole locus of human truth and the sole human truth
is that of victimization. But the victimary critique of universal anthropology is
circularly self-fulfilling. It is an anthropological hypothesis only in the
tautological sense that its denial of universality makes it the only universal
statement conceivable in its own terms.
Victimary rhetoric is able to blackmail traditional liberalism because it hides its
ontology behind an empirical mask. The universalist opponent is ostensibly
denied his discursive position only until such time as the victimary difference has
been abolished. What is not generally recognized is that the basis of this rhetoric
is the denial of the universal as such, that is, of any discursive position not
implicated in victimization on one side or the other. The claim to take such a
neutral position is ipso facto proof that one is on the side of the victimizers.
The victimary position is historically associated with the Left. But the very
distinction between Right and Left, born with the French Revolution, is one that
emphasizes the symmetry of resentments on which modern politics is founded.
As a complement to the age-old grievances of the have-nots is opposed the
defining feature of the modern political configuration: the grievances of their
former masters deposed by the Revolution. What defines the resentment of the
Right in opposition to that of the Left is the "sacrificial" death of Louis XVI in
which de Maistre saw the inaugural moment of a "redemptive" era of history.8
The symmetry of Right and Left is not mechanical, but it is more fundamental
than their differences. The Left's use of victimary rhetoric is "classical," referring
as it does to the long-term effects of broad-based social distinctions, whereas that
of the Right is "romantic," directed at the usurpation of power by an illegitimate
demotic elite. The predominance of the Left in postmodern victimology—a
phenomenon that would have been impossible to anticipate in the 1930s, and one
that may not continue indefinitely—is the result of the demonstration given by the
Holocaust that whatever the evils of minority resentment, the resentment of the
majority holds ultimately the greater danger. But the long-term promise of
postmodern victimary politics is to defuse the old, simplistic resentments by
creating new means for the marketplace to arbitrate between the competing claims
of "disadvantaged" categories.
*
Sparagmos and Resentment 160
The great debate of the postmodern era is whether there can be a debate at all;
whether human society in the era of the universal market can tolerate universal
dialogue. The principle of the free market, broadly conceived, is that the exchange
process is a positive-sum game from which all parties benefit in the long run.
Victimary rhetoric directly contradicts this principle by reducing to the binary
opposition of persecutor and victim the differentiation of positions on which any
exchange is based.
The traditional defense of difference has not been made from the dynamic
standpoint of exchange, but from the static one of the structural-metaphysical
opposition of ideas. Derrida's identification of the operation of differentiating
deferral or différance is a major turning point in postmodern understanding. But
the victimary accusation of nonreciprocity can never be satisfactorily answered
within the universalism of metaphysical discourse, since the accuser simply
relabels the universal as the majoritary. The response in which we may seek the—
always provisional but no less real—ethical solution to the postmodern dilemma
can come only from within a way of thinking grounded in the moment of human
history in which the universal and the particular are (still) the same: the moment
of origin. The ultimate offensive of rhetoric against metaphysics reveals our need
for an originary anthropology that understands better than either the mimetic
origin of human truth.
13
Culture in its most inclusive sense may be defined as any exploitation of the
material, "horizontal" elements of the signifier. Culture is found wherever we do
not adhere rigorously to the arbitraire du signifiant. The sign itself is the minimal
constituent of the human, and the binding force of the human community, but it
is everywhere supplemented by the material specificity of culture.
If we claim to be able to put in question our attachment to this supplement, it is
surely not through naive reliance on the intuition of presence that exemplifies for
Derrida the universalism of classical metaphysics. We are surrounded by culture,
our lives are suffused with it. It is only in the midst of cultural plethora that we
can have the luxury of belonging to no culture in particular. Postmodernity is "the
end" of culture because postmodern culture is such that the pretense of belonging
to it knows itself to be an illusion.
"Double-minority" Culture
The essence of all culture is the deferral of resentment. Popular culture expresses
and offers imaginary satisfaction to "the people," those who define themselves by
their collective rather than individual resentment of the social order. In traditional
societies, this self-definition was a given; in modern ones, it is, regardless of
economic circumstances, essentially voluntary. The social configuration of post-
modern popular culture reproduces the structure of esthetic
Sparagmos and Resentment 162
paradox: the "people" expresses its resentment through the mediation of internal
minorities who define themselves by their resentment of the people themselves.
The exemplary source of the phenomenon of minoritary culture is America's
black minority, which has provided the dominant models of American popular
culture since before the Civil War. The white-black interaction resembles more
the archaic majority-minority relationship between Greeks and "barbarians" than
that between Christian culture and the Jews. "The" Jew is hated because he refuses
to humble himself to the imitatio Christi, whereas the blacks have been
stigmatized as a mass whose very human capacity for the imitatio is put in
question. In keeping with this distinction, the Jewish cultural contribution to the
West has been made by individuals idiosyncratically integrating their "anesthetic"
Jewishness into the esthetic culture of their time, whereas American blacks have
evolved a distinctive communal culture of their own that has served as a mimetic
model for the white majority. The really distinctive Jewish element in modernity
is not the contribution of Marx, Freud, Einstein, Proust, or Derrida, but, as we saw
in the preceding chapter, the suspicion of esthetic centrality put on the world-
historical agenda by the Holocaust. The black element, on the other hand, is
central to modern popular culture, because the stigmatized position of the blacks
makes their community a model for the deindividualized "people" in general.
The worldwide popularity of American mass culture, which gives it a near-
monopoly over what is fast becoming a frontierless market, is no doubt to be
attributed to the peculiar intensity of this black-white relationship, which has
undergone a significant shift in the postmodern era. Until that time, the majority
culture assimilated minority contributions by absorbing toned-down versions of
them into its own less parochial universe. Nor was black culture itself overtly
hostile to the white majority. Today minority resentment is no longer merely the
underlying source of American popular culture; it has become its principal theme.
The more violently this resentment is expressed, for example in rap lyrics, the
greater the sales among the very whites against whom the resentment is directed.
This suggests a model of postmodern culture in which the status of persecuted
minority has become the sole source of cultural legitimacy.
The majority participates in this culture only passively, by consuming the
creations of appropriate minorities, thereby purging itself of its "white guilt."1 But
the particular success of postmodern minoritary culture depends on an additional
articulation. Minority status is not confined to racial or ethnic difference. The
most culturally significant American minority is not African Americans but youth.
The consumerism, expanded affluence, and prolonged schooling of the postwar
years made of youth an open-ended cultural minority capable of standing in for
The End of Culture 163
those minorities that exemplify victimization. In the postmodern era, the youth
culture has become so dominant in the popular sphere that the peculiarity of its
dominance is overlooked. Cultural awareness now belongs to those with the least
historical awareness; the only persons who can create a living culture are those
too young to have roots in its past. The youthful minority subsumes and subverts
all the others. It is by now virtually all-inclusive, since even the middle-aged can
identify with the youth culture of their own time (witness the strength of baby-
boomer nostalgia for the Beatles). Present or retrospective resentment against
adult society is the only membership requirement. In America's unique "double-
minority" configuration, youth as the open minority provides a vehicle for near-
universal mass identification, while its model of resentment is borrowed from the
closed, ascriptive minority exemplified by the blacks.
The postmodern era is a turning point in cultural evolution. The worldwide
triumph of American popular culture based on the double-minority configuration
suggests that culture is produced by and for victims; victimage is the prior
guarantee of its appeal to the general population. The high culture invented by the
Greeks now appears to have been but a temporary deferral of this victimary
structure, one that ultimately remains governed by it.
The typical participant in contemporary popular culture is obliged to assume
attitudes specific to the open minority (youth) within which he may be included,
attitudes which in turn have their source in the closed minority (blacks) from
which he is in the general case excluded. Hence the attitudes expressed by the
youth culture are uncharacteristic of the middle-class youth—white or other—
who are its chief customers. Their assumption is an exercise in role playing. For
their part, its producers must be able to demonstrate their minoritary-victimary
status concretely. These persons, however financially successful, however
reflexively self-ironic, must serve the majority as incarnations of "their" culture.
Because they must renounce, whether naively or ironically, their essential
freedom with respect to this culture, they are supremely inauthentic at the very
moment when cultural authenticity becomes their source of fame and fortune.
Their performances, however ostensibly inner-directed, are as mediated by the
eyes of the majority as ritual dances performed by Indians for tourists.
Role playing has always been a sine qua non of cultural performance, but now
for the first time the performer must in addition to his performance role play the
existential role of an "authentic minority representative," hostile or, at the very
least, indifferent to the majority that provides him with the greater part of his
income. This role may be assumed in the most outrageously ironic fashion, and,
indeed, the success of the violent hyperboles of rap attests to its consciousness of
Sparagmos and Resentment 164
this irony and even to the sharing in it by its consumers. One should not
underestimate the postmodern sophistication of our minoritary popular culture.
But the bottom-line selling point of this culture is that it bears an indubitable,
irreversible guarantee, a mark of "nonwhiteness" —whence the cultural
exemplarity of American blacks.
Postwar/Postmodern
Nazism attempted to resist the centrifugal tendencies of market society through
a return to esthetically centered social compactness—to precisely the archaic
sacrificial universe from which the Mosaic revelation had turned away. In
reaction, postmodern culture is hostile to majoritary solidarity and suspicions of
its imagery. Unlike postmodern high culture, which operates in an ironic,
citational mode, mass culture cannot function without figures on which desire and
resentment can focus. The necessary esthetic closure that postmodernism rejects
becomes permissible in the interest of affirming the cultural closure of the
minority, which can presumably never victimize the majority.
The current, historically unique experience of reverse discrimination
deconstructs anew the absolute difference between persecutor and victim that the
Holocaust seemed to have established once and for all. In the light of the
Holocaust, the scenic opposition between center and periphery, hitherto the
hidden basis of all cultural structures including language, takes on an
unambiguous victimary aspect; our ideal moral certainties are regrounded in the
opposition between (Nazi) persecutor and (Jewish) victim. But the descent of the
absolute into the empirical world is the moment of its undoing. As soon as we
posit an absolute difference between victim and persecutor, the underlying
symmetry of their relation reasserts itself. When the SS torturer becomes the
villain of the war film, he is turned into a sacrificial figure, a scapegoat, the
structural equivalent of the Jew Süss in Nazi cinema. In the already tiresome
clarity of this symmetry, culture has been abandoned to youth; adults are too
world-weary to participate whole-heartedly in the eternal and now transparent
structure of victimary resentment.
The minority experience, which is fast becoming the universal model of
experience in a multicultural society, follows two contrasting models. On the one
hand, the minority forms a relatively autonomous community modeled on the
society as a whole; on the other, it plays the role of the isolated, "late" subject who
is reconciled to the originary community on the basis of originary resentment of
The End of Culture 165
The revelations of minority culture are of two kinds. On the one hand, there is
the resentful myth of an inaccessible majority paradise, which serves to mask the
underlying unity of the human that the high culture, faithful to the lesson of the
originary sign, always held out to its audience. But on the other, minority culture,
more vital because less implicated in the social order than that of the majority,
provides an object-lesson in the everyday deferral of resentment. A long-lost
Dionysian frenzy reappears in the ecstatic forms of postwar popular culture, in its
music and dance, the audience of which more than that of any other popular form
incarnates the "people." These central genres of the youth culture are not
coincidentally those most subject to black and other minority influences. The
rhythms and chord progressions of popular music dissolve individuality in a real
or imaginary group movement that is the historical heir to sacrificial ritual. They
create, in an imaginary context, the resentful unanimity of the sparagmos.
The internal tension of popular music—melody/rhythm and lyrics—parallels
and reinforces that generated by the double-minority structure of its audience.
Even before the advent of the youth culture, African rhythms in their American
distillation had become the driving force in Western popular music. In contrast to
the lyrics, these rhythms can be participated in directly. On the one hand, one is
drawn to a cultural universe from which one will always be excluded—the
pseudosadistic world of rap lyrics, for example, but in an earlier era, the world of
idealized romantic love was sufficiently exotic. But on the other, by giving oneself
over to the rhythms of the music, one renounces one's individual identity for the
sake of maximal participation in what is now experienced as a minority
community.
Unlike high culture, with its unlimited resources of self-construction, popular
culture cannot function on the basis of a commitment to vicarious martyrdom. The
effectiveness of popular culture depends on deindividuation, on the assimilation
of the individual to the community. Popular culture protects us from the rigor of
the centerless, victimless marketplace. That it can only be participated in through
this very marketplace is the paradox that makes bourgeois culture the instrument
for the revelation of the paradoxical foundation of all culture.
Since the romantic era, the cultural sphere has been obsessed by a resentful
denial of the bourgeois exchange system, but today the cultural world can no
longer pretend to be separate from the world of the market. The market's
universality depends on its ability to sell particularity, all the more so when
minority particularity expresses an internally generated resentment against this
very universality. To turn away from the nonuniversal is then to reject cultural
content in general, to experience the end of culture. Is such a rejection an "antilife"
The End of Culture 167
gesture? We should not be too quick to give our answer in a world whose artists
are functionaries of the marketplace.
some not long ago thought it confined. The magazine published it without
comment; it is difficult to imagine that its editorial staff has not been "sensitized"
on this matter for future sleep-related reviews.
It would seem that a minor change in language would obviate the accusation of
exclusion. Instead of "bring someone of the opposite sex," bring your significant
other" would suffice. (We aren't yet ready for "others.") Since the buyer's sex is
indeterminate, there would be little loss in the vividness of the expression. The
difference is nevertheless of historic importance. The image of a couple, a man
and a woman, is replaced by an abstract association of two indeterminate
individuals. This raises the question of the cultural function of such stereotypical
images.
The current preoccupation with nonexclusion concerns many groups of greater
numerical importance than the homosexual community. But it is in this particular
case—which not coincidentally puts in question the fundamental biological
purpose of the sexual associations that "sleep sofas" cater to—that the
problematization of the stereotype, the universal image, extends from the pictorial
into the verbal.
The category of the stereotypical is halfway between the semantic and the
grammatical; it refers to the imaginary content of a minimally described human
situation. The figure of the heterosexual couple as imagined from the CR text does
not require us to consider, for example, its racial or religious composition;
minimal descriptions of humanity do not generally force their users to make such
distinctions. Sexes are another matter. Most languages have a concept of gender
that makes it difficult to avoid identifying a given individual's sexual identity. The
change from "opposite sex" to "significant other" imposes a clear loss of semantic
information. Expressions like "significant other" are justifiably perceived as
euphemisms that reflect the political tensions of our era with regard to the
legitimacy of couplings other than traditional marriage. The elimination of the
expectation that couples be heterosexual, let alone married, forces us to decrease
the semantic content of our language, and thereby to face, in the kind of minimal
situation where stereotypes are in order, a de-esthetization that deprives the figure
of the social universal of imaginary presence. The de-esthetization of language is
crucial because it affects our most fundamental means of communication. The
image is supplementary to the word. If we have to restrain our words, the restraint
cannot be eluded by an image; it has become integral to human communication.
Not long ago, the "typical" American was a white male, most probably a WASP.
Today any group intended as typical will include members of several races and
both genders. The least problematic solution for a single individual is
The End of Culture 169
mere cultural relativism. For the relativist, there is no hierarchy of cultural beliefs,
but the anthropological dialogue in which he participates is exempted from this
refusal of evaluation. What is now proposed makes no exemptions because it
proposes no dialogue; it substitutes the absolutism of ideology for the
universalism of truth.
The origin of metaphysics lies in Socrates' intuition that because human harmony
is founded on the "other scene" of language, this scene must be guaranteed from
the violence of human action. By attributing the concepts of human language to
an ahistorical, transcendental source, Plato laid the groundwork for the first
universal cultural discourse, the first theoretical anthropology. PC, on the
contrary, in an era disabused of this ahistorical transcendence, considers itself
obliged to sacrifice the universality of its discourse to the originary aim of
deferring the resentment it expresses. But how can the peace be kept without a
universal dialogue in which all may participate with the common aim of self-
knowledge?
The problems of grammatical gender can be muddled through, along with those
of the imagery of everyday discourse. Despite the polemical rhetoric that
accompanies these adjustments, they contribute to the long-term pacification of
the cultural sphere. After the divisiveness of the sacred, that of the esthetic too is
now, at least in principle, laid to rest. The imagery consumed by a cosmopolitan
society is henceforth to be produced by its constituent minorities, not by the
society as a whole. The center is not empty but filled with figures of peripherality.
This is an equilibrium state of esthetic culture, henceforth no doubt its permanent
state.
Our language will never cease revealing to its postmodern demystifiers its
dependence on hegemonic figures. In what metalanguage then can we as members
of a single species discuss this revelation? In the very same language—we have
no choice—but understood as the witness to our common origin. As the romantics
and their disciples the existentialists liked to remind us, we are all late with respect
to the origin, speaking a language already constituted before our arrival and whose
implicit figurality excludes us. But the inherent reciprocity of language dissolves
our lateness and integrates us into the community.
When all are included in the dialogue, the problems of hegemonic priority, of
domination and victimhood, will have been reduced to querelles de mots. But by
then the conversation will have moved on to new resentments, new real and
imaginary exclusions. To perpetuate this conversation is the end of culture, the
end of history. It is also the end of originary thinking.
Reference Matter
Notes
Chapter 1
1. The principal sources for the originary scene are La violence et le sacré
(Paris: Grasset, 1973); in English, Violence and the Sacred (Baltimore:
Johns Hopkins University Press, 1977); and Des choses cachées depuis la
fondation du monde (Paris: Grasset, 1978); in English, Things Hidden Since
the Foundation of the World (Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press,
1987).
2. My previous works on generative anthropology, which will be referred to
throughout, are The Origin of Language (Berkeley: University of California
Press, 1981); The End of Culture (Berkeley: University of California Press,
1985); Science and Faith (Savage, Md.: Rowman & Littlefield, 1990); and
Originary Thinking (Stanford, Calif.: Stanford University Press, 1993).
3. Mensonge romantique et vérité romanesque (Paris: Grasset, 1961); in En-
glish, Deceit, Desire, and the Novel (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University
Press, 1965).
Chapter 2
1. The complete definition, given in his letter to Lady Welby of December 23,
1908, is as follows: "I define a Sign as anything which is so determined by
something else, called its Object, and so determines an effect upon a person,
which effect I call its Interpretant, that the latter [person] is thereby
mediately determined by the former [object]. My insertion of ‘upon a
person’ is a sop to Cerberus, because I despair of making my own broader
conception understood." See Charles S. Peirce, Values in a Universe of
Chance (Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday Anchor Books, 1958), p. 404.
2. This suggests an originary analysis of Roman Jakobson's familiar
metonymy-metaphor dichotomy as homologous to the opposition between
the horizontal and vertical components of the original mimetic paradox.
3. Freud's "originary hypothesis" will be discussed in greater detail in Chapter
9.
4. To this mimetic predisposition corresponds the cognitive evolution toward
the formation of prelinguistic "concepts" referred to by Derek Bickerton
and others as the necessary preliminary to human language. See Bickerton's
Roots of Language (Ann Arbor, Mich.: Karoma Publishers, 1981) and his
later synthesis, Language and Species (Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1990), which is even less concerned than the earlier work to
hypothesize an originary scene of language. Imitation is "always already"
protolinguistic, not merely in the abstract sense that après coup we can
recognize an unthematized version of concentration around the center, but
in the very concrete sense that neurons are becoming devoted to
differentiating among categories of objects as a result of this concentration.
This having been said, because Bickerton's conception of early linguistic
evolution, although a considerable advance over purely linguistically
oriented theories, does not recognize the centrality of mimesis, it fails to
take issue with what is after all the fundamental question of the origin of
language: the crossing of what Bickerton calls the "Rubicon" of interactive
speech.
5. See my "The Unique Source of Religion and Morality," Anthropoetics 1,
no. 1 (June 1995; URL:
http://www.humnet.ucla.edu/humnet/anthropoetics/), and Contagion 3
(Spring 1996): 51-65.
6. The game of "Simon Says" is a practical demonstration that in matters of
simple mimesis, language only gets in the way. The ironic point of the game
is the difficulty of listening for the words when it is so natural "simply" to
repeat the gesture.
7. The slippage from anthropological to positive thought is notable in the
following passage: "La trace, archi-phénomène de la ‘mémoire,’ qu'il faut
penser avant l'opposition entre nature et culture, animalité et humanité,
etc…. Archi-écriture, première possibilité de la parole, puis de la 'graphie'
au sens étroit, lieu natal de ‘l’usurpation’ dénoncée depuis Platon jusqu'à
Saussure, cette trace est l'ouverture de la première extériorité en général,
l'énigmatique rapport du vivant à son autre et d'un dedans à un dehors:
l'espacement" [The trace, archi-phenomenon of "memory," that must be
thought before the opposition between nature and culture, animality and
humanity, etc…. Archi-écriture, first possibility of speech, then of the
"graph" in the narrow sense of the term, birthplace of the "usurpation"
denounced from Plato to Saussure, this trace is the opening of the first
exteriority in general, the enigmatic relationship of the living to its other
and of an inside to an outside: spacing]. De la grammatologie (Paris:
Editions de Minuit, 1968), p. 103; translation and emphasis mine. In this
passage as elsewhere, Derrida is not really tempted by positivism; he
simply has no means within his metaphysical vocabulary to describe the
emergence of the human (the "trace") as an event.
8. This nondistinction is characteristic of the formal signs of language, the
"types" of which our utterances are the "tokens." It is their signifying
intention that distinguishes the formal equivalence classes of language from
the empirical classes of animal signals.
9. Girard distinguishes these terms in Mensonge romantique by the
coexistence or noncoexistence of the mediator in the universe of the
subject. Don Quixote does not live in the same universe as Amadis, whom
he is therefore able to emulate openly; in contrast, Dostoevsky's "eternal
husband" does not realize that his desire for his wife is mediated by that of
the lovers he in effect procures for her, who are in turn secretly influenced
by his own desire.
10. See Originary Thinking, chap. 7 ("Originary Esthetics").
Chapter 3
1. The formulation of Russell's theory is itself paradoxical, as Alexandre
Koyré points out in Epiménide le menteur (Paris: Herrmann, 1947). Koyré
refutes Russell's theory of types by showing through the transfinite
technique of "triangulation" that the statement of the theory itself can be of
no possible type.
2. The term "pragmatic paradox" was given currency by Watzlawick and
Beavan's The Pragmatics of Human Communication (New York:
Norton,1967); like "double bind," it has its origin in the thought of Gregory
Bateson. See the latter's Steps to an Ecology of Mind (New York: Ballantine
Books,1972), especially pp. 271-78.
3. Let us recall our definition of esthetic experience from Originary Thinking:
the oscillation between the contemplation of the referent as formally
designated by the sign (the movement from sign to referent) and the
imaginary contemplation of the referent alone as content. To this worldly
content, in turn, significance, the effect of the mediating obstacle between
subject and object, is restored by the return to the sign.
4. The ostensive → imperative → declarative progression is discussed at length
in The Origin of Language; see also Originary Thinking, chap. 4 ("A
Generative Taxonomy of Speech-Acts").
5. This incompatibility holds even for a system that includes a formalized
temporal dimension; the term "oscillation" as used here is not a wave
function defined over time, but an indeterminate movement between two
poles within which no points in time can be isolated. It is impossible to
define the status of the esthetic imagination at a given time t0 as opposed to
t1.
6. Here we reach one of the frontiers between the anthropological and the
"natural" sciences. No doubt mathematics is a product of human thought
that reflects the needs and interests of the creatures who
invented/discovered language in a context of potential mimetic conflict.
But, in contrast to the cultural forms whose structure can be illuminated by
the originary hypothesis, the thematization of the scene and what derives
from it can tell us only one thing about mathematics: its incompleteness.
Gödel's proof, which makes arithmetic into a self-representation malgré
elle, demonstrates that mathematical truth cannot be fully formalized; this
is as close as mathematics can come to being formulated as a system of
signs. But this proof does not involve paradox, which is only inevitable in
sign-systems that refer, like human language, to a world that they are not.
7. There is a clear homology between these paradoxes. Just as the barber
cannot shave himself, the sentence cannot affirm its own falsity. The
difference is that, in the case of the barber, the paradoxicality of shaving
himself is the result of a rule enunciated by the sentence itself—there being
nothing inherently paradoxical in shaving oneself—whereas in the other it
is intrinsic to the declarative sentence—which cannot be true and false at
the same time.
8. An analogous extension procedure may be applied to the Barber paradox:
instead of the man who shaves every man who doesn't shave himself, we
may seek, for example, the wife of the man who cuts every woman's hair
whose husband doesn't cut her hair.
9. For a mathematical discussion, see William Feller, An Introduction to
Probability Theory and Its Applications (New York: John Wiley and Sons,
1950), pp. 199-201. Despite the player's infinite expectation per game, the
author shows that a "fair" price per session, in the sense that the ratio of
expected gain to entrance fees tends to 1, is log2n, where n is the number of
games. Thus a player intending to play 8 games should pay $3 per game,
for a total of $24. This analysis eliminates the paradox from a mathematical
standpoint at the price of complicating the theoretical model by adding the
concept of variance to the simple one of expectation. (It should also be
remarked that it is not typical, or practical, for gambling establishments to
inquire as to how many games will be played before setting their price.)
But even were this solution unknown, the paradox would remain pragmatic,
not mathematical. There are no mathematical paradoxes because
mathematical elements are not representations but pure representata; that
is the most fundamental definition of mathematics.
10. Leaving time aside, if the bank has $1 million, the payoff series chokes off
after about 21 terms (1020 is just over 1 million), and so the game is worth
about $21—which means that a series of 5 heads, paying $32, would
already provide the player with a profit.
11. It is nevertheless the case that, in a simple mathematical model using
expectation only, the paradoxical effect can only be removed by reducing
the coin-flipping time to an infinitesimal. Which is to say that at the level
of mathematical theory that obtained when the "Petersburg paradox" was
proposed, the game poses a pragmatic paradox that holds under any
conceivable worldly conditions.
Chapter 4
1. This term was originally applied to the experience of revelation. See
Science and Faith, chap. 3.
2. This is the case for all proper names; as soon as we know what they
designate, they begin to designate it generically. When I know Achilles, I
can call someone else "an Achilles." The historical is always in the process
of becoming conceptual; or seen from the other side, the conceptual is
eternally in the process of shedding its historicity.
3. This process is discussed in more detail in The Origin of Language with no
specific reference to truth and falsity.
4. One recalls especially the heavy-handed irony of Limited inc. (Baltimore:
Johns Hopkins University Press,1977), Derrida's response to John Searle's
"Re-iterating the Differences: A Reply to Derrida," in Glyph no. 1 (1977).
Searle's article responds to Derrida's critique of Austin's conception of the
"speech-act" in the 1971 article "Signature Evénement Contexte," an
English version of which was published in the same issue of Glyph.
5. This has been increasingly evident since Le bouc émissaire (Paris: Grasset,
1982); in his most recent book, Quand ces choses commenceront (Paris:
Arléa, 1994), Girard insists on the dependency of his theory of desire on
the Christian revelation.
6. This is, of course, a simplification, since ostensive or "deictic" elements are
not absent from declarative language. It is remarkable how large a
proportion of the ground-breaking insights in theoretical linguistics, from
Jakobson's discussion of "shifters" to Benveniste's dichotomy between
discours and histoire—not to speak of the theory of speech-acts that grew
out of Austin's "performatives"—make reference to this still insufficiently
theorized ostensive element.
7. We need not distinguish at this point between untruths and lies. The
possibility of lying is inherent in the thematization of (un)truth, since all
use of language is intentional, and known to be intentional. It is because of
the thematic intentionality of language that only a sophisticated mind can
distinguish between believing your predication to be false and accusing you
of lying.
8. The culturally late phenomenon of fiction proper makes use of this
separation between meaning and truth to construct an imaginary world. But
fiction too has its truth functions, which we learn from the literary text
rather than know in advance; if I say "Hamlet is the son of Claudius," I am
making a statement just as false as if I say "Franklin Roosevelt was the son
of Theodore Roosevelt."
Chapter 5
1. Pierre Fontanier, Figures du discours (Paris: Flammarion, 1968 [1827]),
pp. 145-46.
2. The questioning of the absolute difference that constitutes the linguistic
sign might be called "originary deconstruction." The binary oppositions
such as speech/writing, male/female, etc., on which deconstruction
typically operates are metaphysical derivatives of the originary dichotomy
between the ostensive sign and its object. By taking this into account
theoretically, we effectively merge deconstruction into generative
anthropology.
3. But one could indeed say "[Oh no! Tell me] it's not raining!" in a tone of
incredulity; or even in a deadpan tone: "It's not raining [again]." The
interactive nature of language makes it impossible to define the limits of
the ironic once and for all. My objection to the straightforward "It's not
raining!" as an example of irony is rather that its mechanical negation of
"It's raining" fails to reveal the wish that has been denied by the rain.
4. "You know him, reader, this delicate monster / Hypocritical reader, my
fellow, my brother!" These are the last fines of "Au lecteur," the liminal
poem of Baudelaire's Les fleurs du mal.
Chapter 6
1. The reader will recall that in Chapter 4 and previously in Originary
Thinking, I defined metaphysics as the way of thinking founded on the
principle that the declarative sentence—the "proposition"—is the
fundamental linguistic form.
2. Our intuitive comprehension of this term is the simplest indication of the
persistence of our attachment to the originary scene. We could not conceive
the existence of God, even in order to deny it, without basing our
conception on an experience of the sacred, an experience of which the
name-of-God is the crystallization. (For further elaboration of this idea, see
Science and Faith, and, particularly, Originary Thinking, chap. 2, "The
Anthropological Idea of God.") In contrast, the construction of a concept of
God that needs no name is the task of metaphysics.
3. As the original target of deconstruction, the phenomenological notion of
the "self-presence" of speech refers to the speaker's presumed relation to
his utterance rather than to its specificity; for all the notion of "self-
presence" tells us, he could be engaged in glossolalia. Only the context of
philosophical discourse suggests that the referent of the utterance is situated
on the "other scene" of the declarative. Where is self-presence in, for
example, an imperative utterance that specifically designates what is
experienced-as-absent? Only in the fact that (assuming I am not deaf) I hear
myself speak, that is, my heard speech supplies me with feedback while I
speak, not in anything relating to the specifics of human language. Only in
the case of the metaphysical proposition, entirely contained within the
imaginary scene of representation, can the content of the utterance be
characterized either as absolutely present (to itself) or as absolutely absent
(to the empirical world).
4. See Science and Faith, chap. 3.
5. As I have pointed out elsewhere (see "The Unique Source of Religion and
Morality," Anthropoetics 1, no. 1 [June 1995; URL:
http://www.humnet.ucla. edu/humnet/anthropoetics/] and Contagion 3
[Spring 1996]: 51-65), in the original revelation in Exodus 3.14, God
already distinguishes between the full sentence by which he names
himself to Moses and his instruction to tell the people "I am/will be
(ehyeh) has sent me to you."
6. See Henry Teloh, The Development of Plato's Metaphysics (University
Park: Pennsylvania State University Press, 1981): "The date of composition
of the Cratylus, unfortunately, is in dispute. I do believe, however, that
separate Forms appear at the end of the dialogue (439c-440d), but in a very
rough and rudimentary manner, which indicates that Plato has just started
to think about them" (p. 83). The fact that Teloh's arguments are taken from
the metaphysical tradition only adds strength to my own very different
ones.
On another point, it can hardly be a simple coincidence that the name of
Euthyphro reappears in the Cratylus (and nowhere else in Plato), in an
ironically marked fashion: "That [this onomastic ‘science’] fell upon me,
the one whom I consider responsible for this, Hermogenes, is above all
Euthyphro" (396d). Is this not a sign of the progression of Plato's reflection
on the eidos? It is Euthyphro who is said to have inspired Socrates with his
divine etymologies; we shall see that it is precisely these which lead the
Platonic Socrates from Heraclitean Cratylism to the notion of the Idea-
signified.
7. In contrast, Plato is familiar enough with the plurality of "barbarian"
languages to recognize the instability of the signifier, it is precisely for this
reason that he denies the usefulness of the empirical search for "primitive"
names.
8. In contrast, Parmenides, the thinker of the One, of absolute permanence, is
not a semiotician. The dialogue that bears his name and which is faithful to
what we know of his thought shows that the One, far from being, like the
Platonic Idea-signified, a fixed point between the contrary mobilities of
signifier and referent, is as mobile as the world. of Heraclitus. The word
"One" designates an absolute totality that is unnameable—"One" is not a
name but an attribute—and indeed, like the "set of all sets," properly
inconceivable. As such it stands at the moment just prior to the emergence
of metaphysics at which the sacred-ostensive component of Being has not
yet been replaced by the abstract presence of the Ideas.
9. But Lacan himself has no illusions concerning the freedom of the
imaginary, which he describes on the contrary as enslaved to the desire of
the Other.
10. After the famous fragment 60, "War is the father, the king of all things,"
the last Heraclitean passage Benoist quotes is: "Denizens of the night:
magicians, bacchants, lenai, myths; one is initiated sacrilegiously into the
mysteries practiced among men." He then concludes, "Voici venir encore
ces ombres et ces masques, ces figures de mauvais augure que l'on cache"
[Here they come again, those shadows and those masks, those hidden
figures of evil portent] (p. 181). Benoist would have done well to read
Girard's remark on Heraclitus in La violence et le sacré, "N'est-ce pas la
genèse même du mythe, l'engendrement des dieux et de la différence sous
l'action de la violence … qui se trouve résumé dans le fragment 60?" [Is it
not the very genesis of myth, the creation of the gods and of difference
through the action of violence … that is summed up in fragment 60?] (p.
129).
11. See especially Bataille's La part maudite (Paris: Editions de Minuit, 1967).
Chapter 7
1. See Husserl's Logische Untersuchungen (1913), vol. 1, chap. 3, where he
attacks Mill's conception of logic as a branch of psychology.
2. This is the notion that our theories of cosmogenesis should privilege the
fact that such theories could only be invented in a universe that produces
theory-generating creatures like ourselves. The result of this "profound"
idea is to use the latest cosmogenic equations to conjure up myriads of
nonanthropic universes among which ours is a "miraculous" exception. The
theoretical hubris of this sort of reasoning is all too typical of originary
thinking in a postreligious age. Instead of concentrating their mental energy
on the genesis of the human on this planet, which alone is a fitting subject
for self-inclusive, or, in other words, paradoxical, reasoning of this sort, our
cosmic philosophers expend their ingenuity in finding sophisticated
disguises for naive assurances of our "universal" importance.
3. See Chapter 12 for further discussion of this subject.
Chapter 8
1. See Chapter 10 for a fuller discussion of the place of the sparagmos in the
originary scene.
2. On this point, Derek Bickerton's views, as expressed in Roots of Language
(Ann Arbor, Mich.: Karoma Publishers, 1981), seem fully justified:
cognitive distinctions among categories of beings must preexist their
manifestation in speech. But as Bickerton is very much aware, these
distinctions can be elicited from chimpanzees; the real mystery of the origin
of human speech is what function it came into being to serve ("What
selective advantage did the species gain?" [p. 225]), and on this score,
Bickerton's hypotheses offer no improvement over common sense.
3. This resistance to appropriation is an absolute resistance that manifests
itself as inherent in the sacred object, as opposed to a relative, situational
resistance that the members of the group could either attempt to overcome
or accept as a practical deterrent to action. The resistance of the sacred
object retains our attention without permitting the generation of a praxis by
means of which to overcome it.
4. We should assume the image of the object that enters into this new form of
mental association to share the common tendency of perceptual traces to
differentiate themselves at the generic level, broadly defined.
Psycholinguistic research has established that all people regardless of
language share the same basic level of perceptual selectivity; they see "dog"
before either "Pomeranian" or "mammal."
5. In particular reference to music, see my "The Beginning and End of
Esthetic Form," Perspectives of New Music 29, no. 2 (Summer 1991): 8-
21.
6. The oscillatory tension characteristically provoked by esthetic form is an
intentional version of the same process. But unlike the signified, which
exists wholly in the imagination and has no "objective correlative," the
esthetic object occupies the communal presence that precedes, and
prepares, the sparagmos.
7. The phonetic system too is subject to historical change through the
selection of more attractive or prestigious "supplementary" elements. The
classic discussion is that of William Labov, Sociolinguistic Patterns
(Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1972).
Chapter 9
1. I will not rehearse here my reasons for assuming the originary event to be
an essentially masculine operation. In today's gender-conscious
environment, it might be taken as a deliberate provocation to draw even so
obvious a parallel as that between ithyphallicity and aggression. (I can
mention as suggestive evidence the ithyphallic hunter in a famous mural
from Lascaux. Nowhere has anyone seen a cave drawing of a female hunter,
let alone a sexually excited one.) But this parallel is of marginal importance
to my argument. The erotic as conceived here does not depend on any
specific genital configuration.
2. This is the valid point of Deleuze and Guattari's "anti-oedipal" theory of
desire, developed in their L'anti-Oedipe (Paris: Editions de Minuit, 1972).
3. The disreputability of pornography strictly as an esthetic genre results from
the incompleteness of the oscillatory relationship established between sign
and imagined referent: at a certain point, the spectator of pornography does
not return from the imagined reality to the sign, since his desire seeks real
satisfaction. This distinguishes the pornographic from the erotic, in which
this mediation is the operative force. This is not to deny the prevalence of
erotic themes (seduction, "narcissism," etc.) in pornography. A given
erotic-pornographic image or text may be situated on the scale established
by this polarity.
4. In the "esthetic history" elaborated in Originary Thinking, the neoclassical
period extends from the beginning of scenic self-consciousness in nascent
Christianity down to the radical self-centering of the romantic era. Chapter
9 of that work discusses the neoclassical esthetic.
5. The theoretical source of this mensonge romantique is the classical
Aristotelian doctrine of mimesis, which the romantics (with some
exceptions) believed they could apply unchanged to the expression of their
new, personal content. The first-generation romantics failed to realize that
their free lunch was in reality a sacrificial meal. Alfred de Musset's
famously lurid image in "La nuit de Mai" of the poet as a pelican feeding
its own flesh to its children reflects the naive beginnings of this realization.
6. As Flaubert puts it, "il fallait qu'elle pût retirer des choses une sorte de profit
personnel; et elle rejetait comme inutile tout ce qui ne contribuait pas à la
consommation immédiate de son coeur" [She had to be able to derive from
things a kind of personal profit; and she rejected as useless everything that
failed to contribute to her heart's immediate consumption] (I, 6).
7. The "narcissistic" figure combines the roles of the subject-other and the
object of desire; she seduces the other by the example of her apparent self-
idolatry. Although the specifics of sexual identity are secondary to the
structure of "narcissistic" seduction, for both cultural and biological
reasons, this has typically been the woman's role. For Girard's discussion
of "narcissism" from the perspective of the mimetic theory of desire, see
Des choses cachées, pp. 391-405.
8. The reader is referred to the discussion in the second part of this volume,
particularly Chapter 13.
9. Totem and Taboo, trans. James Strachey (New York: Norton,1952); the
original, Totem und Tabu, was published in 1920 with the almost
caricaturally self-limiting subtitle einige Übereinstimmungen im
Seelenleben der Wilder und der Neurotiker ("some correspondences
between the mental lives of savages and neurotics"). Freud's "originary
scene" is built up to throughout the book; it occurs in chap. 4, sec. 5 (on
page 176 of a 200-page text): "One day the brothers who had been driven
out came together, killed and devoured their father and so made an end of
the patriarchal horde….The violent primal father had doubtless been the
feared and envied model of each one of the company of brothers: and in the
act of devouring him they accomplished their identification with him, and
each one of them acquired a portion of his strength…. They hated their
father… but they loved and admired him too. After they had got rid of him,
had satisfied their hatred and had put into effect their wish to identify
themselves with him, the affection which had all this time been pushed
under was bound to make itself felt. It did so in the form of remorse. A
sense of guilt made its appearance, which in this instance coincided with
the remorse felt by the whole group. The dead father became stronger than
the living one had been" (pp. 176-78).
10. The classical example in the Girardian corpus is the Tikopia myth
discussed in Des choses cachées, pp. 115-22. After providing the Tikopia
with the basics of their culture, the hero Tikarau is said to climb to the top
of a cliff and fly off into the air. To lend credence to this myth is to
experience a quite literal "suspension of disbelief."
Chapter 10
1. See Originary Thinking, chap. 3.
2. The reader is referred to the discussion in the following chapter.
3. Smith's camel scene is found in his Lectures on the Religion of the Semites
(s.l.: Ktav Publishing House, 1969 [1889]): "The camel chosen as victim is
bound upon a rude altar of stones piled together, . The leader of the band….
inflicts the first wound, … and in all haste drinks of the blood that gushes
forth. Forthwith the whole company fall on the victim with their swords,
hacking off pieces of the quivering flesh and devouring them raw with such
wild haste, that in the short interval between the rise of the day star… and
the disappearance of its rays before the rising sun, the entire camel, body
and bones, skin, blood and entrails, is wholly devoured" (p. 338).
4. The reader is referred to Science and Faith, chap. 3, as well as to the
discussion in the following chapter of the present volume.
5. The object of resentment is the heir of the originary central figure. But as
the exchange system evolves, the directness of this connection is lost. The
Western era of revolutions ended when their potential targets ceased to
occupy the ritual center by "divine right." Many changes of government
have occurred in Europe since 1917, but the overthrow of the Tsar is the
last event generally honored with the term "revolution."
6. See Originary Thinking, chap. 7.
7. For Girard, the sparagmos is not only the origin of evil, but of otherness;
the victim is a member of the community arbitrarily chosen for exclusion
from it. Since Girard's world lacks the sign, it must generate the new,
"vertical" difference of signification within the real world as the becoming-
absolute of the relative otherness of the originary victim. But once we locate
the vertical otherness of signification in the sign where it belongs, we have
no need to generate it from within a wholly undifferentiated world. The
otherness of eater and eaten is part of life from the beginning. The truly
minimal source of the otherness of the sign is not prehuman
dedifferentiation but mimetic desire operating on the most fundamental of
differences.
8. This is also the source of its eroticism, as discussed in Chapter 9. We should
recall in this context that the root meaning of "person" is "mask."
9. For the latter, see Chapter 6. The "third man" paradox is an argument by
regression: if A is a man, and B is the Idea of a man, then their resemblance
requires they have something in common that neither of them is; call it C
(for example, "human appearance"). But then A, B, and C all have
something in common that can only be named by D, and so on ad infinitum.
Aristotle refers to this argument by name in Metaphysics XIII, 4 (1079a) as
a reductio ad absurdum of Plato's doctrine of Ideas; it is used (but not
named) by Parmenides in Plato's eponymous dialogue (132a-133a)—the
one dialogue where Socrates listens respectfully and does not attempt to
refute his interlocutor.
10. This sharpens the definition of the moral-ethical dichotomy discussed in
chap. 3 of Originary Thinking, the contrast is not merely between the
(moral) exchange of signs and the (ethical) exchange of things, but between
the moral concern with reciprocal communication and the ethical
abandonment of this concern in the interest of preserving the community as
a practical, worldly entity.
Chapter 11
1. The reader is referred to the detailed analysis of this scene in Science and
Faith, chap. 3.
2. See Science and Faith, chap. 4.
3. See Buber's Moses (Oxford: East and West Library, 1946), and the
discussion in Science and Faith, chap. 3.
4. In his account in Galatians 1.11-17, Paul emphasizes both the special
circumstances of his conversion "For I did not receive [the gospel] from
man, nor was I taught it, but it came through a revelation of Jesus Christ"
(1.12)—and his mission to the Gentiles—"But when [God] … was pleased
to reveal his Son to me, in order that I might preach him among the Gentiles,
I did not confer with flesh and blood, nor did I go up to Jerusalem to those
who were apostles before me" (1.15-17; Revised Standard Version).
5. Moses and Monotheism (New York: Alfred A. Knopf, 1939); originally
published as Der Mann Moses und die Monotheistische Religion
(Amsterdam: A. de Lange, 1939).
6. The rise of Islam is the most visible evidence that the Pauline synthesis is
insufficient to make Christianity a truly universal religion; the historical
outsiders of Mediterranean civilization reject the central God-man for a
human-mediated scriptural reiteration of Hebrew monotheism. But Islam is
not, as is Judaism, a religion of deferral; the unfigured God mediated
through the Prophet's word is more a sacrificer than a deliverer. Islam takes
from the Mosaic revelation rather the promise of future conquest than the
deferral of present satisfaction. Its rejection of the divine image functions
less to thematize renunciation than to concentrate figural attention on the
demonized enemy. This definitive separation of the figure of sparagmos
from the unfigured divinity inverts the movement toward religious
humanization effected by the Christian Trinity.
7. For example, Romans 6.3-4: "Do you not know that all of us who have been
baptized into Christ Jesus were baptized into his death? We were buried
therefore with him by baptism into death, so that as Christ was raised from
the dead by the glory of the Father, we too might walk in newness of life";
Galatians 2.20: "I have been crucified with Christ; it is no longer I who live,
but Christ who lives in me."
8. See Gershon Scholem, The Messianic Idea in Judaism (New York:
Schocken Books, 1971), and Kafka's formulation: "Der Messias wird erst
kommen, wenn er nicht mehr nötig sein wird, er wird erst einen Tag nach
seiner Ankunft kommen, er wird nicht am letzten Tag kommen, sondern
am allerletzten" [The Messiah will first come when he is no longer needed,
he will first come on the day after his arrival, he will not come on the last
day, but on the last of all]. Hochzeitsvorbereitungen auf dem Lande
(Frankfurt a.M., 1966), p. 90, quoted in John Milfull, "The Messiah and the
Direction of History: Walter Benjamin, Isaac Bashevis Singer and Franz
Kafka," in Festschrift for E. W Herd (Dunedin, N.Z.: Department of
German, University of Otago, 1980), p.187.
9. Hiroshima mon amour (1959). The film sets up a provocative contrast
between a modernized, consumerist Hiroshima and a monumentally lifeless
Europe epitomized by the somber and hauntingly named French city of
Never(s).
10. The futility of this operation is most remarkable in the countries where the
final solution was most effective; today in Poland, for example, there
flourishes the phenomenon known as "antisemitism without Jews."
11. One should contrast the nineteenth-century vision of social victimage
centered around the sentimental figure of le pauvre. But this figure was
drawn from Christian iconography; what it provoked was pity, not guilt for
discrimination. Thus it was compatible and even complementary with the
contrasting discriminatory figure of the "exploiting" Jew.
12. See especially the section "Science et Apocalypse" in Des choses cachées
(pp. 276-85), where Girard develops the idea that the Bomb imposes on us
the "apocalyptic" necessity of accepting once and for all the Gospel critique
of the sparagmatic-sacrificial.
In a more recent, more discursive work, Quand ces choses commenceront
(Paris: Arléa, 1994), Girard insists rather on the openness and
undecidability of history in the context of the always present, always
deferred truth of Christian revelation; his refutation of Francis Fukuyama's
idea of "the end of history" leads him, curiously enough, to the Holocaust:
"L'Holocauste est bien un échec terrible… mais, espérons-le, un échec
temporaire qui ne signifie pas que l'Histoire tout entière ne vaille plus la
peine d'être vécue" [The Holocaust is certainly a terrible failure … but, let
us hope, a temporary one that does not signify that History as a whole is
not worth living] (p. 125).
13. See Chapter 13.
Chapter 12
1. See the discussion of the birth of hierarchical society in The End of Culture,
chap. 6.
2. In geometric terms, a triangle has no center; but the common object of the
subject and the other-mediator is clearly the equivalent of the center of the
circle. The triangular model makes it clearer, in fact, that the victim's
"exile" is not a movement from one closer peripheral position to one farther
away, but expulsion from the very center.
3. Similarly, Jesus's premodern emulators, among the most illustrious of
whom are Hamlet and Rousseau (see my "Littérature et ressentiment," in
Poésie 29 [1984]: 115-25), are always quick to centralize their marginality,
to oppose their authentic uniqueness to the false uniqueness of the
conventional ritual center.
4. See my "The Victim as Subject: The Esthetico-Ethical System of
Rousseau's Rêveries," in Studies in Romanticism 21, no. 1 (Spring 1982):
3-32, as well as Chapter 5 of the present volume.
5. Exemplary of this is a characteristic inversion of the gradient of deferral
that attributes to language a supplement of violence over the worldly act it
replaces. See Tobin Siebers, The Ethics of Criticism (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell
University Press,1988), chap. 4 ("Ethics in the Age of Rousseau: From
Lévi-Strauss to Derrida").
6. See Paul R. Gross and Norman Levitt, "The Natural Sciences: Trouble
Ahead? Yes," in Academic Questions 7, no. 2 (Spring 1994): 13-29. The
authors cite a number of relevant writings.
7. Whence the homosexual movement's insistence on finding a hereditary
basis for "sexual orientation," although in a pre-Holocaust context this is
precisely what would have constituted—and did, in Nazi Germany—
grounds for its members' victimization. We may recall that Jewishness, not
strictly speaking an ascriptive trait either, was defined in racial terms by
Nazi law.
8. See in particular de Maistre's Les soirées de Saint-Pétersbourg (Paris: La
Colombe, 1960), Neuvième Entretien, and my "Maistre and Chateaubriand:
Counter-Revolution and Anthropology," in Studies in Romanticism 28, no.
4 (Winter 1989): 559-76.
Chapter 13
1. "White guilt" is a felicitous expression because it expresses not merely guilt
for belonging to the (white) majority, but guilt for whiteness in the more
abstract sense in which the French word blanc also means "blank." The
white is the unmarked, only visible in contrast to the marked "other."
"White guilt" is the guilt of those who lack the victimary trace of these
others, those who have by default profited from the sacrificial past of
civilization that culminated in the Holocaust.
The first historical manifestation of this essentially post-Rousseauian
phenomenon of which I am aware may be found in Chateaubriand's Essai
sur les révolutions. Describing an encounter with an Indian family near the
Niagara Falls, the author singles out a young warrior for detailed
description: "Le jeune homme seul gardait un silence obstiné; il tenait
constamment les yeux attachés sur moi …. Combien je lui savais gré de ne
pas m'aimer! Il me semblait lire dans son coeur l'histoire de tous les maux
dont les Européens ont accablé sa patrie" [The young man alone maintained
an obstinate silence; he kept his eyes constantly fixed on me …. How
grateful was I to him for not liking me! I seemed to read in his heart the
history of all the ills with which the Europeans have burdened his
fatherland] (I, 624; emphasis mine). I discuss this text in my article "Maistre
and Chateaubriand: Counter-Revolution and Anthropology" (see above, n.
8 to Chapter 12).
2. See Kojève's Esquisse d'une phénoménologie du droit (Paris: Gallimard,
1981).
3. See The End of Culture, chap. 10.
4. In popular figures of unusual appeal, marginality is not simply minority
identity but the implicit or explicit transgression of boundaries; whence the
success of the implicit black-white boundary-crosser Elvis Presley and, at
a later stage, the explicit black-white man-boy-girl Michael Jackson.
5. Psalm 118.22-23, quoted in Matthew 21.42.
6. In Quand ces choses commenceront, Girard takes a critical view of con-
temporary victimary thought as the permeation of society by the Christian
revelation, despite the failure or refusal of its practitioners to acknowledge
this filiation. He defines PC as "la religion de la victime détachée de toute
transcendance … qui vient du christianisme mais qui le subvertit plus
insidieusement encore que l'opposition ouverte" [the religion of the victim
detached from all transcendence . . . which comes from Christianity but
which undermines it even more insidiously than open opposition] (p. 65).
Index
In this index "f" alter a number indicates a separate reference on the next page,
and "ff" indicates separate references on the next two pages. A continuous
discussion over two or more pages is indicated by a span of page numbers. Passim
is used for a cluster of references in close but not consecutive sequence.
Akhenaton, 157
Altruism, 149
Anesthetic, 141, 159, 167, 185
Antisemitism, 160-61, 164, 166, 216
Arbitrariness of signifier, 14, 184
Aristotle, 16, 31, 37, 214
Art: high vs. popular, 70-71, 113, 117-20, 138-40
Auschwitz, 162f, 166
Austin, J. L., 179, 207
Bataille, Georges, 90
Baudelaire, Charles, 69-70
Being, 88, 90, 92-96, 97, 102-4, 106f
Benoist, Jean-Marie, 89-90, 210
Bickerton, Derek, 204, 211
Blacks, 165, 185, 187f, 193
Buber, Martin, 155
Callicles, 77f
Chateaubriand, François-René de, 217
Christianity, 74, 132, 152ff, 156-60, 166, 177
Cogito, 93, 121, 125
Consumer society, 117, 126
Corneille, Pierre, 175
Cosmology, 95
Cratylism, 107
Crucifixion, 158f
Cultural relativism, 198
Culture, 184, 186; popular, see Popular culture
Dante, 115
Dasein, 95
Decadence, 117
Declarative mode, 42, 57, 60-63, 79, 81, 85-86, 93, 110, 153, 172-73, 179
Deconstruction, 4, 31, 59, 97-98, 179, 208f
De-esthetization, 192, 195, 197-98
De Maistre, Joseph, 182
De Man, Paul, 74
Derrida, Jacques, 7, 29-31, 58, 105, 148-49, 179, 182, 184, 204-5, 207
Descartes, René, 125
Detemporalization, 27f
Dialogue, 6, 199
Différance, 27, 29, 35, 60, 71, 96, 148f, 155, 166, 182-83, 216-17
Double-minority culture, 195
Duras, Marguerite, 163
Durkheim, Emile, 2
Paradox, 4, 9, 13, 35f, 37-50, 54, 63, 101, 124, 127, 170, 205ff; pragmatic, 20,
38f, 41, 44; logical, 39, 41-45, 48
Parmenides, 209-10, 214
Passion, 73, 155, 158
Paul / Saul, 155ff, 159, 164, 177-78, 214-15
Pavlov, Ivan, 20, 37
Peirce, Charles S., 13-14
Personhood, 103, 147
Plato, 44, 59, 75-91, 101, 136, 149, 179, 199, 209
Political correctness, 191, 194-99 passim, 218
Popular culture, 184-87, 188ff, 193f; vs. high culture, 117-19, 131-32, 136, 138-
40, 189-90
Pornography, 113, 212
Postmodern(ism), 74, 117-20, 141, 162, 165-67, 184-90
Predication, 59-63
Realism, 115-17
Religion, 2-3, 83-85, 88, 101
Resentment, 67-68, 96, 144-45, 146f, 154, 166-77 passim, 189
Rhetoric, 34, 98, 168-83, 194
Right / Left opposition, 182
Ritual, 94, 145, 152
Romanticism, 69
Roots (television series), 193
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, 69, 178
Russell, Bertrand, 37, 44
Unconscious, 120-27
Utopianism, 167