(Modern Studies in Philosophy) C. B. Martin, D. M. Armstrong (Eds.) - Locke and Berkeley - A Collection of Critical Essays-Palgrave Macmillan UK (1968)
(Modern Studies in Philosophy) C. B. Martin, D. M. Armstrong (Eds.) - Locke and Berkeley - A Collection of Critical Essays-Palgrave Macmillan UK (1968)
(Modern Studies in Philosophy) C. B. Martin, D. M. Armstrong (Eds.) - Locke and Berkeley - A Collection of Critical Essays-Palgrave Macmillan UK (1968)
EDITED BY
c. B. MARTIN
AND D. M. ARMSTRONG
PALGRAVE MACMILLAN
ISBN 978-0-333-10073-8 ISBN 978-1-349-15284-1 (eBook)
DOI 10.1007/978-1-349-15284-1
Published by
MACMILLAN AND CO LTD
Little Essex Street London WC2
and also at Bombay Calcutta lind Madras
Macmillan South Africa (Publishers) Ply Ltd Johannesburg
The Macmillan Company of Australia Pty Ltd Melbourne
This does especial hann by nourishing the assump-
tion that the study of p'hilosophers like Locke and
Berkeley is only a margfnally useful activity which
may be adequately conducted with the mind in neu-
tral. In fact, it can be one of the most rewarding and
demanding of philosophical exercises_
JONATHAN BENNETT
CONTENTS
LOCKE
(c. B. MARTIN)
BERKELEY
(D. M. ARMSTRONG)
KNOWLEDGE
KNOWLEDGE OF EXISTENCE
THEOLOGY
D
SUBSTANCE, REALITY, AND
PRIMARY QUALITIES
JONATHAN BENNETT
PART I
7. Some Examples
Here is one passage where Berkeley makes the shift I
have described from "Does something real correspond to
this sensory state?" to "Does something have this prop-
erty?"
It is worth while to reflect a little on the motives
which induced men to suppose the existence of ma-
terial substance. . . . First, therefore, it was thought
that colour, figure, motion, and the rest of the sensi-
ble qualities or accidents, did really exist without the
mind; and for this reason it seemed needful to
suppose some unthinking substratum or substance
wherein they did exist, since they could not be con-
ceived to exist by themselves . . . . (Principles § 73.)
O'Connor sees that there is a doctrine about substance
of a purely logical kind. But he brings it in as an after-
thought; dismisses it as an impossible interpretation of
"the substratum theory," for no reason I can imagine ex-
cept that he has taken Berkeley as his source for Locke;
and shows, by his use of "something" in the first sentence,
that he has not seen how distinct the two doctrines are:
It is certainly not logically necessary, or even true,
that colours, for instance, cannot occur except as
properties of a coloured something. If I stare at a
light for a few seconds and then tum my gaze away, I
shall see an "after-image" in the form of a coloured
patch which certainly does not inhere in any sub-
stance. The supporter of the substratum theory of
substance has either to claim (i) that the after-image
102 Jonathan Bennett
is itself a substance or (ii) that it inheres in my vis-
ual field. (i) is a reductio ad absurdum of tIle sub-
stratum theory, though a sense datum would qualify
as a substance in the logical ~ense of the word: it has
properties without being itself a property of any-
thing..••1
With satisfying explicitness, Morris presents Berke-
ley's semi-phenomenalism as contradicting something said
"largely on the credit of Aristotle's logic":
Berkeley has little difficulty in showing that the con-
ception of material substance was in the philosophy
of Locke no more than an uncriticized survival. Phi-
losophers had always taken it for granted, largely on
the credit of Aristotle's logic, that qualities must
be supported by some underlying permanent self-
subsistent substance. . . . Berkeley [argues against
this] that throughout our whole experience of the
physical world we never apprehend anything but sen-
sible qualities and collections of sensible qualities. All
we know of things or can know of them is what we
perccive by sense; if there were more in things than
this, we could not know it. This at once becomes
clear, he says, if we consider what is meant by the
term "exists".•.. "There was an odour, that is, it
was smelled; there was a sound, that is to say, it was
heard; a colour or figure, and it was perceived by sight
or touch. This is all that I can understand by these
and the like expressions." This doctrine is evidently
based on the argument that whenever we are aware of
a physical object, introspective analysis shows that
there is nothing present in our mind but a number or
collection of simple ideas of qualities; and it is taken
by Berkeley to prove that knowledge simply consists
in the awareness of sensible qualities. 2
Warnock mixes the substance doctrine with the veil-of-
perception doctrine by sliding smoothly from "matter" to
"the essential 'support' of qualities":
1 D. J. O'Connor, John Locke (London, Penguin Books,
1952.), pp. 80-81.
2 C. R. Morris, Locke, Berkeley, Hurne (Oxford, The Claren-
don Press, 1931), pp. 74-75. '
Substance, Reality, and Primary Qualities 103
PART II
in fact they are not, and in the other someone sees and
feels two things as being of the same size when in fact they
are not.
Suppose, then, that someone who is confronted by a
red thing and a white thing convinces us that he sees them
as having exactly the same color. He may believe us when
we tell him that the things do have different colors; and
if they differ in no other way we can, without asking him
to trust us, prove to him that there is some difference be-
tween the two things which we see and he does not. Also,
we may show him-or he may discover for himself-:-that
the two objects differ in respect of the wave lengths of the
light they reflect, and that wave lengths usually correlate
with seen colors. But if he ignores other people's talk
about the two objects, and ignores esoteric facts of optics,
he may never discover that his seeing of the two objects as
having the same color arises from a sensory defect in him.
A failure of secondary-quality discrimination, in one who
is otherwise sensorily normal, can-and sometimes does-
persist unsuspected through any variations in distance or
angle of view, light-conditions, mouth-washing, cold-
curing, and so on.
Contrast this with the case of a size-"blind" man who,
going by what he sees and feels, judges a certain drinking
mug to have the same size as a certain cup, although in
fact the former is both higher and wider than the latter.
In such a case, we can place the cup inside the mug; or fill
the mug with water, and then fill the cup from the mug
and pour the remaining water on the ground; or place both
vessels on a horizontal surface and draw the size-"blind"
man's hand across the top of the cup until it is stopped
by the side of the mug; and so on. What are we to· sup-
pose happens when our size-"blind" man is confronted by
these manipulations of the cup and the mug? There are
just two relevant possibilities. (a ) We may suppose that
the size-"blind" man has a normal apprehension of what
happens when we manipulate the cup and the mug, and
therefore quite soon realizes that his original judgment
about their sizes must have been mistaken. (b) We may
suppose that in each case there is some supplementary
112 Jonathan Bennett
inadequacy in his perception of what is done to the cup
and the mug, or of the outcome of what is done, so that
what he sees and feels still fits in smoothly with his origi-
Dal judgment that the two vessels are of the same size.
To adopt supposition (a) is just to admit that this case
is radically different from that of color blindness. If the
point of the latter were just that there are or could be aber-
rations in our perception of secondary qualities, then we
could say the same of primary qualities; and we could add
that it is absurd to deny that a certain kind of quality
really is a quality of the things in the world, just because
we do or might sometimes fail to discern it. What gives
relevance and bite to color blindness, and to abnormality
of secondary-quality perception generally, is the fact that
any such abnormality can persist, not just for a few mo-
ments or under special conditions, without the victim's
being given any clue to his abnormality by his other, nor-
mal sensory responses. The manipulations of the cup and
the mug could be performed not by us but by the size-
"blind" man himself: they involve ordinary commerce
with familiar middle-sized objects, and are in a very differ-
ent case from the color-blind man's attention to wave
lengths or to other people's classifications of things by
their colors.
If we want an analogy between size-"blindness" and
color blindness, then, we must adopt supposition (b) .
But look at what this involves: the size-"blind" man must
be unable to see or feel that the cup is inside the mug, or
unable to see or feel that the mug has not momentarily
stretched or the cup contracted; he must be unable to see
or feel that the cup has been filled from the mug, or un-
able to see or feel that there is water left in the mug after
the cup has been filled; he must be unable to see or feel
that his hand is touching the cup as it moves across the
top of it, or unable to see or feel his hand being stopped
by the side of the mug. It will not do merely to suppose
that as the manipulations are performed he sees and feels
nothing. To preserve the analogy with color blindness we
must suppose that what he sees and feels gives him no
reason for suspecting that there is something wrong with
Substance, Reality, and Primary Qualities 113
him; and so his visual and tactual states through all the
manipulations of the cup and the mug must present no
challenge to his belief that he is handling an ordinary pair
of drinking vessels which are of the same size. This is bad
enough, but there is worse to follow. If the size-"blind"
man is to be unable to see or feel the water which remains
in the mug after the cup has been filled from it, this will
require yet further sensory aberrations on his part: if the
water is poured over a lighted candle, or used to dissolve
a lump of sugar, or thrown in the size-"blind" man's face,
his perception of any of these events must also be appro-
priately abnormal if his original judgment is to remain
unchallenged. Similarly with any of the other sensory ab-
errations with which we must prop up the initial one:
each requires further props which demand yet others in
their tum, and so on indefinitely.
The desired analogy with color blindness has collapsed
yet again. In the case of color blindness, the sensory ab-
normality was not clued by the victim's other sensory re-
sponses although these were normal; but to keep the
size-"blind" man in ignorance of his own initial sensory ab-
normality we have had to surround it with ever-widening
circles of further abnormalities.
Strictly speaking, it is not quite correct to say that the
single failure of color-discrimination could well remain un-
clued by the victim's other, normal sensory responses. For
if he detects no difference in color between RI which is
red and WI which is white, what are we to suppose that
he makes of the color of a second red thing, R 2, in rela-
tion to the color of WI? If his only sensory aberration is
to concern the comparison of RI with Wl> then we must
suppose that he sees no difference of color between R2
and R 1, and no difference of color between RI and W b
and yet sees a lmge difference of color between R2 and
WI. This is clearly unacceptable, and so we are in trouble
here unless we suppose our man to be unable to see color
differences between red things and white things generally.
This, however, does not restore the analogy between color
blindness and size "blindness." For the infectious spread
of sensory aberrations around the single initial failure of
114 Jonathan Bennett
size-discrimination does not involve merely other failures
to discriminate sizes. The original aberration can re-
main unclued only if it is backed by failures of shape-
discrimination, movement-detection, sensitivity to heat,
and so on. The single red/white failure spreads to red/
white fanures generally, but need spread no further; but
the failure to discriminate sizes spreads endlessly into all
the victim's perceptions of his environment.
As well as losing our analogy, we are also losing our grip
on the initial datum of the size "blindness" case, namely
that we can agree with the size-"blind" man about the
identity of a certain cup and mug, disagreeing with him
only about their relative sizes. For it has turned out that
there are countless visible and tangible aspects of our en-
vironment in regard to which the size-"blind" man does
not agree with us, so that it is now by no means clear that
we can still assume that we share with him a sensory
awareness of a single objective world.
6. Berkeley's Blunder
I submit, then, that I have presented a truth about pri-
mary and secondary qualities and that it is this after which
Locke was groping. Now, the point which I have brought
out has nothing to do with the veil-of-perception doctrine:
it is not a version of that doctrine, or a qualification of or
a rival to it. It operates on a different level altogether.
One can state and explain what is interesting in the dis-
tinction between primary and secondary qualities-whether
or not one goes so far as to say that secondary qualities
are not "of" tllings as primary qualities are-only on the
basis of normal assumptions about our entitlement to trust
the evidence of our senses. What I have calJed Locke's
"veil-of-perception doctrine" is really just his mishandling
of a certain sceptical question, and the latter makes sense
only if it asks whether the objective world is, really, in any
1N)' at all as it appears to be. An affirmative answer must
be given to this question before one can present the con-
trast between primarY and secondary qualities.
Substance, Reality, and PrimClTY Qualities 119
To be fair, I must concede that the thesis about pn-
mary and secondary qualities can be taken as a qualifica-
tion of the veil-of-perception doctrine in the following
extremely minimal way. The veil-of-perception doctrine
says that statements about objects are logically dissociated
from statements about states of mind, and the primary/
secondary thesis can be seen as conceding that this logical
dissociation does not hold for statements attributing sec-
ondary qualities to objects but only for those attributing
primary qualities to them. I think that it is because the
relation between the two doctrines can be viewed like this
that they are so often conflated; and it is therefore impor-
tant to see what is wrong with this way of looking at the
matter.
Considered as a qualification of the veil-of-perception
doctrine, i.e., as a concession that not all statements about
objects are logically dissociated from statements about
states of mind, the primary/secondary thesis is just a bore.
Even the most fervent super-Lockean would agree that
some predicates of objects are connected with mental
predicates; for example, that we commit ourselves to some-
thing about states of mind when we say that castor oil is
nasty, that warm baths are soothing, that hair shirts are
uncorpfortable, or that the New York subway system is
confusing. If Locke's thesis about secondary qualities were
important only as a concession that some predicates of
objects are logically connected with mental predicates, it
would be without any importance at all since it would be
"conceding" what no one has ever denied. What makes it
interesting is not its saying (a) "Some predicates of ob-
jects have some logical connections with mental predi-
cates," but rather its saying (b) "Secondary-qua~ity predi-
cates of objects have these logical connections with mental
predicates." Now (b) does not offer any useful support
to the view that there are logical connections between
all predicates of objects and mental predicates: the Lock-
ean view of the status of secondary qualities is no more a
stage on the way to complete idealism or phenomenalism
than is the Nazi valuation of Aryans a stage on the way to
a belief in the worth and dignity of all men. In each case,
120 lonathan Bennett
the further step may consistently be taken; but in neither
case is the taking of it just a further development of the
line of thought by which the first stage was reached.
Just as the Lockean thesis about secondary· qualities is
not a significant restriction on the veil-of-perception doc-
trine, so the Lockean thesis about primary qualities is not
-or need not be-a somewhat restricted version of the
veil-of-perception doctrine. If to (a) "Some predicates of
objects have some logical connections with mental predi-
cates" we add the rider "but primary-quality predicates
don't," then the result is indeed all of a piece with the
veil-of-perception doctrine, and is thus in opposition to
idealism or phenomenalism. But if to (b) "Secondary-
quality predicates of objects have these logical connections
with mental predicates" we add the rider "but primary
qualities don't," the result says only that primary-quality
predicates are not connected with mental pred.icates in the
way in which secondary-quality predicates are. This pre-
sents no challenge at all to Berkeley or to any phenomenal-
ist who knows what he is about: I have defended it my-
self, through my discussion of size "blindness," without
conceding a thing to the veil-of-perception doctrine.
This difference of level between the two theses is fairly
clear in Locke's own pages. In his battles with the sceptic,
Locke does invoke empirical facts which are not legiti-
mately available to him; but he does this covertly, and
knows that he ought not to do it at all. As against this, his
discussions of the primary/secondary contrast are riddled
with open appeals to experimental evidence. (This is per-
fectly proper: a satisfactory treatment of the primary/
secondary distinction must begin with empirical facts;
though it ought, as Locke's does not, to connect these with
the relevant conceptual points.) Locke notes this explicitly
in II, VIII, 22: "I have, in what just goes before, been en-
gaged in physical inquiries a little farther than perhaps I
intended . . . I hope I shall be pardoned this little excur-
sion into natural philosophy, it being necessary, in our
present inquiry, to distinguish the primary and real quali-
ties of bodies, which are always in them . . . etc." Again,
in IV, DI, 28, he denies that any "correspondence or con-
Substance, Reality, and Primary Qualities 121
I,. I,.
from the Lockian version in its account of the nature of
27 II., VIII., 28 II., VIII.,
Locke's Version of Representative Perception 139
physical reality. But unless what is said to be represented
by sensible appearance is at least spatial it is not properly
described as physical reality. So a theory which maintains,
with Berkeley, that only spiritual substances are repre-
sented by sensible appearance, or, with Hume, that the
nature of what is represented cannot be determined,
should not according to the above formulation be classified
as a version of the doctrine of Representative Percep-
tion.29 Then, again, different views may be taken of the
nature of sensible appearance. It may be held to be either
dependent on, or independent of, the sensing of it, and so
on, provided that it is not identified with physical real-
ity.sO This is important for our purpose, because Locke
does not seem to have made up his mind about the status
of "ideas of sensation," and this article does not try to de-
termine his view, or views, on that question. Lastly, the
extent of the resemblance of sensible appearance to physi-
cal reality may be variously estimated without violation of
the sine quibus non of the doctrine of Representative Per-
ception. For our purpose, it is Locke's acceptance of the
negative tenet that has to be made out; for it is the nega-
tive tenet that distinguishes the doctrine of Representative
Perception from the Mixed View.
A special problem, which is easily seen to confront the
doctrine of Representative Perception thus formulated, is
presented by the tendency of the positive tenet to conflict
with the negative tenet. For the negative tenet requires
that physical reality should be numerically distinct from
sensible appearance, that no physical reality should be any
sensible appearance: but the positive tenet requires that
physical reality should be known though not sensed, and
this claim can be justified only by showing that sensible
29 There is, so far as I know, no reason why the doctrine of
Berkeley should not be called a version of the doctrine of Repre-
sentative Perception, provided that the positive tenet is fomlU-
lated in such a way as to include non-physical realities among the
realities which sensible appearance may be held to represent.
ct.
30 Hamilton (pp. 804-819) for various possible forms of
Representationism in reference to the ontological status of the
representative entities.
140 Reginald Jackson
appearance can be the source of the knowledge of physical
reality. This obligation is twofold. Not only must it be
shown that sensible appearance is evidence for the exist-
ence of a physical reality of such a kind as the version of
the doctrine of Representative Perception describes. It
must also be shown that sensible appearance is the source
of acquaintance with the qualities which are asserted on
that evidence to belong to physical reality. The latter req-
uisite offers a difficulty apart from the question of the
cogency of the evidence, a difficulty which lies in the
reconciliation of the numerical distinctness of physical
reality and sensible appearance with the necessity of de-
scribing physical reality in terms of sensible appearance.
On the one hand, there is a temptation to express the
fact of numerical distinctness by saying that, just because
no physical reality is any sensible appearance, no attribute
of physical reality can be also an attribute of sensible ap-
pearance. On the other hand, the possibility of describ-
ing physical reality in terms of sensible appearance would
be commonly defended by saying, that physical reality and
sensible appearance have certain attributes in common,
and that to describe physical reality it is necessary only to
enumerate those attributes of sensible appearance which
are also attributes of physical reality. The conflict is evi-
dently due to different uses of the term 'attribute', and
the different uses affect equally such terms as 'quality',
'property', and 'character'. When it is said that no attri-
bute of physical reality can be also an attribute of sensible
appearance, 'attribute' is treated as a particular. When it
is said that physical reality and sensible appearance have
attributes in common, 'attribute' is treated as a universal.
Accordingly the formula which an exponent of the doc-
trine of Representative Perception selects for expressing
the relation of sensible appearance to physical reality will
be conditioned by his attitude towards the problem of the
particularity or universality of attributes.
The settlement of this controversy about the propriety
of the application to characteristics, whether attributes
or relations, of the distinction between universal and par-
Locke's Version of Representative Perception 141
I. PREAMBLE
VI. CONCLUSIONS
The most recent, the most scholarly, and the most de-
fensible of the 'non-traditional' interpretations is in Leo
Strauss's Natural Right and History.1 For purposes of
analysis, his account can be reduced to three assertions:
first, Locke is not a natural law theorist; second, he is a
Hobbesian; and third, his egoism is also demonstrated by
his account of property rights.
Strauss argues that Locke cannot be a natural law theo-
rist, for he gives no account of how men know the law of
nature. He could have said either reason or revelation, but
there are no philosophical theories in the Second Treatise 2
and his other works provide no definite answers either.
Moreover, the first alternative is unacceptable because ra-
tional knowledge also requires proof of God's existence and
human immortality, proofs which Locke says are not de-
monstrable, hence 'natural reason is unable to know the
law of nature as a law'.3 At best, he accepted a 'partial'
law of nature, moral rules which correspond to Scriptural
injunctions, but his rules, when analysed, are not identical
with those of Jesus. Hence, Locke does not adequately ac-
count for man's knowledge of natural law and this shows
that he 'cannot have recognized any law of nature in the
proper sense of the term'.4
In the last analysis this argument asserts that you can
teU what one knows only if he tells you how he obtained
his knowledge; an interesting, if dubious, assumption
which Strauss makes no effort to justify even though his
whole argument rests on its validity. But, no matter; grant
the assumption and, moreover, grant that Locke did not
provide an adequate explanation, still it does not follow
that he was not aware of the problem. In the Second Trea-
t University of Chicago Press, 1953. A condensed version ap·
peared in The Philosophical Review, Oct. 1952.
2 Ibid., p. 220.
S Ibid., pp. 203-4. But see Essay, Book IV, chapter 10.
4 Ibid., p. ::/.20.
Locke's Political Theory and Its Interpreters 181
II
III
IV
life and liberty. At the same time only those with "estate"
can' be full members, for two reasons: only they have a
full interest in the preservation of property, and only they
are fully capable of that rational life-that voluntary obli-
gation to the law of reason-which is the necessary basis for
full participation in civil society. The laboring class, being
without estate, are subject to, but not full members of,
civil society. If it be objected that this is not one answer
but two inconsistent answers, the reply must be that both
answers follow from Locke's assumptions, and that neither
one alone, but only the two together, accurately represent
his thinking.
This ambiguity about membership in civil society by
virtue of the supposed original contract allows Locke to
consider all men as members for purposes of being ruled
and only the men of estate as members for purposes of
ruling. The right to rule (more accurately, the right to
control any government) is given only to the men of es-
tate; it is they who are given the decisive voice about taxa-
tion, without which no government can subsist (§ 140).
On the other hand, the obligation to be bound by law and
subject to the lawful government is fixed on all men
whether or not they have property in the sense of estate,
indeed, whether or not they have made an express com-
pact. When Locke broadens his doctrine of express con-
sent into a doctrine of tacit consent, he leaves no doubt
about who are obligated. Tacit consent is assumed to have
been _given by "every man, that hath any possessions, or
enjoyment, of any part of the dominions of any govern-
ment . • . whether this his possession be of land, to him
and his heirs forever, or a lodging only for a week; or
whether it be barely travelling freely on the highway; and
in effect, it reaches as far as the very being of anyone
within the territories of that government" (§ 119). Locke
is careful to say (§ 122) that this does not make a man a
full member of civil society, but only subjects him right-
fully to its government: the men of no estate are not
admitted to full membership by the back door of tacit con-
224 c. B. Macpherson
sent.35 Of course, Locke had to retreat to tacit consent be-
cause it was impossible to show express consent in the case
of present citizens of an established state. However, his
doctrine of tacit consent has the added convenience that
it clearly imposes obligation, reaching to their "very being,"
on those with no estate whatever.
It appears from the foregoing analysis that the result of
Locke's work was to provide a moral basis for a class state
from postulates of equal individual natural rights. Given
the seventeenth-century individualist natural-rights as-
sumptions, a class state could only be legitimized by a
doctrine of consent which would bring one class within,
but not make it fully a part of, the state. Locke's theory
achieved this end. Its accomplishment required the im-
plicit assumptions which he held. These assumptions in-
volved him in the ambiguities and contradictions that per-
vade his argument. It is difficult to see how he could have
persisted in such contradictions had he not been taking
the class state as one desideratum and equal natural rights
as another.
Locke did not twist deliberately a theory of equal natu-
ral rights into a justification for a class state. On the con-
trary, his honestly held natural-rights assumptions made
it possible, indeed almost guaranteed, that his theory
would justify a class state without any sleight of hand. The
decisive factor was that the equal natural rights Locke en-
visaged, including as they did the right to unlimited ac-
cumulation of property, led logically to differential class
rights and so to justification of a class state. Locke's con-
fusions are the result of honest deduction from a posfulate
of equal natural rights which contained its own contradic-
tion. The evidence suggests that he did not realize the
contradiction in the postulate of equal natural right to un-
limited property, but that he simply read into the realm
of right (or the state of nature) a social relation which he
85 We may notice incidentally that in his discussion of tacit
consent, as well as in that of the supposed express entry into civil
society by the contract, Locke lumps together life, liberty and es·
tate under one tenn, and here the tenn is not even "property" but
"possession" (§ 119, quoted above).
The Social Bearing of Locke's Political Theory 225
II
III
II
'REALITY' IN BERKELEY
I
THE 'FALSE IMAGINARY GLARE' PASSAGE
sion that sensible things are not real if Hylas were right in
taking 'the reality of sensible things' to consist in 'an
absolute existence out of the minds of spirits'. He goes on:
'But I neither said nor thought the reality of sensible
things was to be defined after that manner. To me it is
evident, for the reasons you allow of, that sensible things
cannot exist otherwise than in a mind or spirit. Whence I
conclude . . . etc.' The argument is not that sensible
things cannot exist out of all minds, but do sometimes
exist out of human minds and must therefore sometimes
exist in a non-human mind. It is that sensible things can-
not exist out of all minds, but are undoubtedly real, and
therefore 'real' must be defined in some other way than
'capable of existing out of all minds'. The point about the
ownership of ideas comes in here solely in order to high-
light Hylas's wrong analysis of 'real'.
I do not contend that the passage is flawless. On my
interpretation, Philonous's 'Whence I conclude .. .' is
too abrupt: there should at this point be a reference to the
analysis of 'real' which Philonous does accept. But if we
are to take the passage as giving the continuity argument,
then-apart from the difficulties already mentioned-we
must suppose that in Berkeley's first and almost his only
presentation of that argument he fails to make the point
that something may exist out of all human minds without
existing out of all minds whatsoever. He makes this point
clearly enough in his other, unargumentative discussions
of continuity; but now that continuity is supposed to be-
come really important to him we are invited to believe
that he neglects to say the one thing which most needs
saying.
If someone still insists that in this passage Berkeley is
nevertheless also thinking of the continuity argument and
conflating it with the passivity argument, I cannot prove
him wrong. In an earlier section I listed all but four of
Berkeley's uses of 'depend' and its cognates in speaking of
the relationship between ideas and minds. Of the four
exceptions, one was the passage in § 56 in which Berkeley
criticises an argument which turns upon the ambiguity of
'depend' without himself mentioning this ambiguity; one
398 Jonathan Bennett
was the passage in Principles § 146 where Berkeley himself
exploits the ambiguity in order to move from 'every idea
depends upon (= is owned by) a mind' to 'every idea de-
pends upon (= is caused by) a mind'; and one was the
passage in the third dialogue, p. 193, where Berkeley ex-
ploits the ambiguity in reverse, in his one clear presenta-
tion of the continuity argument, moving from 'some ideas
do not depend upon (= are not caused by) my mind' to
'some ideas do not depend upon (= are not owned by) my
mind'. The fourth use of 'depend' which was omitted
from my list of straightforward cases is the one in the
second-dialogue passage now under discussion, and it may
be that this too should be treated as a mixed use of 'de-
pend', in which it does two things at once. But at least
let it be recognised that in this case the mixture is quite
different from the other three: each of the latter is clearly
and explicitly concerned both with the ownership and
with the causation of ideas, and the ambiguity of 'depend'
is there invoked, in order to explain how Berkeley is (or, in
the first case, how his opponents are) trying to bring the
two things together. In the 'false imaginary glare' passage,
however, the only explicit reference to ownership admits
of a perfectly good explanation as relevant to the criticism
of Hylas's definition of 'real': there is no need to say that
'depend' is used ambiguously here, except the need cre-
ated by an antecedent prejudice in favour of taking this
passage to express the continuity argument.
II
III
IV
T cannot exist apart from t11e sensation of it, for the rea-
son that T cannot be abstracted from ilie sensation of it.
But his statementH iliat "ilie object and the sensation are
ilie same thing and cannot ilierefore be abstracted from
each other" seems to mean only iliat T cannot be ab-
stracted from Qb Q2, and Qs, since it is by definition just
ilie combination of iliem. But since T is just its combined
qualities (which are ideas), then T cannot even be dis-
tinguished from iliem (by step i), let alone abstracted
from iliem (by step ii), so it is difficult to see how Berke-
ley's doctrine that iliere are ideas which are distinguish-
able but not abstractable (that is, which may be "con-
sidered" but not "separated") is relevant to tlIe present
case. Moreover, it may be a fact that "when we do our
utmost to conceive the existence of txtemal bodies, we
are all ilie while only contemplating our own ideas",45 but
if we cannot do more ilian this, the important question
arises: how did we come to think we could?
We seem to be opening a more fundamental vein of
Berkeley's argument when we examine his statement that,
"as it is impossible for me to see or feel anytlIing without
an actual sensation of that thing, so is it impossible for
me to conceive in my thoughts any sensible iliing or object
distinct from the sensation or perception of it".46 This
assumes a shape different from tlIat of the argument just
considered, and at first seems -::learly to tum on ilie doc-
trine of abstract ideas. We believe (0) that we can con-
ceive a given object T as existing apart from ilie perc~p
tion of it by someone; we make tlIis mistake because we
tlIink on superficial examination (b) tlIat we can have an
idea of T existing witlIout having any idea that T is being
perceived. But ilie fact is (c) iliat we have never perceived
T without perceiving it, and this fact (c), by Principle A.
makes proposition (b) false. Our belief (a) is tlIerefore
ungrounded, and it follows from a denial of (0) that T
cannot exist apart from our perception of it.
Now it is clear that tlIe crucial point of this argument
is ilie demonstration that ilie idea T existing cannot be
44 Prin., sec. 5. 45 Ibid., sec. 23.
48 Prin., sec. 5; see also Three Dialogues, I, pp. 261-26:z.
422 Monroe C. Beardsley
abstracted from the idea T being perceived. 47 When we
look about for Berkeley's demonstration, we discover that
he very often says quite explicitly (1) that the reason is,
that "the existence of an idea consists in being per-
ceived";48 that, in short, the ideas are the same. 49 To
be precise, we must heed his warning: "But it must be
well noted that existence is vulgarly restrain'd to actuall
perception, & that 1 use the word existence in a larger
sense than ordinary".50 We can then express this view by
the proposition that "T existing" is precisely identical in
meaning to "T being thought of" :n the widest sense
(Tex is T tb ): "This 1 am sure", remarks Berkeley, "I have
no idea of Existence, or allllext to the word Existence".51
That is, there is no unique idea of existence apart from
perception: "'Tis on the discovering of the nature & mean-
ing & import of Existence that 1 chiefly insist".52 Accord-
ing to this argument, then, "esse est percipi" is analytic;
1 have no abstract idea of Te" for the same reason tllat 1
have no abstract idea of colour: it is not an idea at al1.
Now this is a perfectly good argument, if it is Berkeley's
argument. What is noteworthy about it is that it owes
nothing to the doctrine of abstract ideas. Tex is so far
from being an abstract idea apart from Ttb that it is the
same idea; not only can it not be abstracted (by step ii)
from T tb , but, being identical with T tb, it could not (by
step i) even be "singled out" from T tb-indeed, it could
not even be "distinguish'd therefrom", as Berkeley ad-
mits. 53 If Berkeley's argument here is valid, then there
could indeed be no "nicer strain of abstraction than to
distinguish the existence of sensible objects from their
being perceived, so as to conceive them existing unper-
47 Since the idea T1 being perceived includes reference to a
self, which is a notion, the idea is perhaps more accurately called
a notion. This would make no significant difference as far as the
argument is concerned, I believe, since Berkeley holds also that
we have no "abstract notion" of the powers and acts of the self
apart from the self or apart from the self's ideas (Prin., sec. 143).
48 Ibid., sec. 2. 49 See ibid., sec. 3; CPB 404.
50 CPB 472; see also 471. 51 CPB 681; see also 680, 557.
52 CPB 493. 53 CPB 655.
Berkeley on "Abstrdct IdedS" 423
ceived".54 Indeed one "might as easily divide a thing
from itself', for that is precisely what one would be doing.
But if the conclusion is that "to exist is to be perceived"
is analytic, and for that reason true, it also follows that no
one would even distinguish existence from perception,
and therefore that no one could have been misled by the
belief in abstract ideas to think that it is possible to con-
ceive Tex in abstraction from T th •
As a matter of fact, Berkeley does not confine himself
to the argument that "esse est percipi" is analytic; he also
(2) holds to the position that it is synthetic. And this is
quite incompatible with the other position, for in this
case Tex is an idea, distinct from T th, but inseparable
from it. 55 This argument does depend upon the doctrine
of abstract ideas, as a statement of its steps discloses: (a)
When T is perceived it is accompanied by the idea (Tth)
that T is being thought of by someone; (b) no T has ever
been perceived without being accompanied by such an
idea; by (c) Principle A it follows that (d) T cannot later
be conceived without T til; therefore (e) T ex (since it
includes T) cannot be conceived without T th , and hence
(f) T cannot exist apart from being thought of.
We seem, then, to have discovered the point at which
Berkeley applies his doctrine of abstract ideas to the refu-
tation of realism. Step (f) of the above succinct version
of his argument depends upon considering T ex as an idea
distinguishable, but not abstractable, from T th • And yet
it seems clear that Berkeley himself has provided his own
answer to this argument. For we may ask whether steps
(d) and (e) are in fact correct; "surely there is nothing
easier than for me to imagine trees, for instance, in a park.
or books existing in a closet, and nobody by to perceive
them". To this Berkeley assents, 56 but he considers it ir-
relevant. It is no objection to his argument, he declares,
to say that I can frame the idea of things existing "at the
same time omitting to frame the idea of anyone that may
perceive them". This is only, he says, a case where "the
mind, taking no notice of itself, is deluded to think it can
54 Prin., sec. 5. 115 See ibid., sec. 6. 56 Prin., sec. :1 3.
424 Monroe C. BetITclsley
and does conceive bodies existing unthought of, or without
the mind, though at the same time they are apprehended
by, or exist in, itself'. But (and this is the crucial ques-
tion with respect to steps (d) and (e» is not this possi-
bility (which Berkeley here admits) that Tex may occur
in the absence of Tth (i.e., that we may frame Tex and
omit to frame T th ) precisely what the doctrine of ab-
stract ideas (as we have defined it in Section I above)
denies? In the case of colour and shape, Berkeley strives to
prove just this: that we cannot think of a colour without
thinking of some shape. If we apply this to the present
case, his argument must be that we cannot think of any
particular thing without thinking that it is being thought
of by someone. And yet in order to explain how philoso-
phers have been tricked into realism by their belief in
abstract ideas, Berkeley must (as in the passage above)
contradict his general principle by saying that we can think
of a particular thing without thinking that it is being
thought of.
There is one more instance of Berkeley's use of the doc-
trine of abstraction which requires notice here. At one
time he regarded the inseparability of the primary from
the secondary qualities as "the great argument"117 against
materialism. According to this view the erroneous belief
that extension and motion can be abstract ideas apart
from colours has been chiefly responsible for the error of
realiSID;1I8 and when it is realised that we cannot conceive
extension apart from colour, it will be understood that
extension cannot exist apart from colour; and since the
latter is admittedly subjective, so also must the former
be.lI11 In view of aU the preceding discussion this does not
call for much comment. For if the proposition (11) that I
have no abstract idea of extension apart from colour is
offered as ground for the proposition (b) that extension
cannot exist apart from colour, this inference can only be
effected by Principle B, as discussed in Section III. But
Principle B cannot be applied without either begging the
117 CPB %97. 68 CPB 380.
1111 Prin., sec. 10; see also Three Dialogues, I, p. 253.
Berkeley on "Abstract Ideas" 425
question, or being converted into Principle Ai and Prin-
ciple A will not permit the inference of proposition (b),
but only of the proposition (c) that I have never in fact
experienced extension apart from colour. This is not to
say that Berkeley's discussion of the relation between pri-
mary and secondary qualities amounts to no more than
this; it is only to say that, as far as the doctrine of abstract
ideas is concerned, the following conclusions seem to be
warranted: (1) the doctrine appears to furnish less actual
support to Berkeley's system than Berkeley supposes, and
(2) it suffers from certain inner difficulties which cannot
be removed without changing it in such a way that it
furnishes no support at all.
G. J. WARNOCK'S BERKELEY
J. F. THOMSON
II
III
IV
v
The great historical importance of Berkeley lies, I be-
lieve, in his protest against essentialist explanations in
science. Newton himself did not interpret his theory in an
essentialist sense; he himself did not believe that he had
discovered the fact that physical bodies, by their nature,
are not only extended but endowed with a force of attrac-
tion (radiating from them, and proportional to the
amount of matter in them). But soon after him the essen-
tialist interpretation of his theory became the ruling one,
and remained so till the days of Mach.
In .our own day essentialism has been dethroned; a
Berkeleian or Machian positivism or instrumentalism has,
after all these years, become fashionable.
Yet there is clearly a third possibility-a 'third view' (as
I call it).
Essentialism is, I believe, untenable. It implies the idea
of an ultimate explanation, for an essentialist explanation
is neither in need of, nor capable of, further explanation.
(If it is in the nature of a body to attract others, then
there is no need to ask for an explanation of this fact, and
no possibility of finding such an explanation.) Yet we
know, at least since Einstein, that explanation may be
pushed, unexpectedly, further and further.
But although we must reiect essentialism, this does not
mean that we have to accept positivism; for we may ac-
cept the 'third view'.
I shall not here discuss the positivist dogma of meaning,
since I have done so elsewhere. I shall make only six ob-
448 Karl Popper
servations. (i) One can work with something like a world
'behind' the world of appearance without committing one-
self to essentjalism (especially if one assumes that we can
never know whether there may not be a further world be-
hind that world). To put it less vaguely, one can work
with the idea of hierarchical levels of explanatory hypothe-
ses. There are comparatively low level ones (somewhat
like what Berkeley had in mind when he spoke of 'Laws
of Nature'); higher ones such as Kepler's laws, still higher
ones such as Newton's theory, and, next, Relativity. (ii)
These theories are not mathematical hypotheses, that is,
nothing but instruments for the prediction of appearances.
Their function goes very much further; for (iii) there is
no pure appearance or pure observation: what Berkeley
had in mind when he spoke of these things was always the
result of interpretation, and (iv) it had therefore a theo-
retical or hypothetical admixture. (v) New theories, more-
over, may lead to re-interpretation of old appearances, and
in this way change the world of appearances. (vi) The
multiplicity of explanatory theories which Berkeley noted
(see Section ii (16), above) is used, wherever possible, to
construct, for any two competing theories, conditions in
which they yield different observable results, so that we
can make a crucial test to decide between them, winning
in this way new experience.
A main point of this third view is that science aims at
true theories, even though we can never be sure that any
particular theory is true; and that science may progress
(and know that it does so) by inventing theories which
compared with earlier ones may be described as better ap-
proximations to what is true.
So we can now admit, without becoming essentialist,
that in science we always try to expktin the known by the
unknown, the observed (and observable) by the unob-
served (and, perhaps, unobservable). At the same time
we can now admit, without becoming instrumentalist,
what Berkeley said of the nature of hypotheses in the fol-
lowing passage (S, 228), which shows both the weakness
of his analysis-its failure to realize the conjectural charac-
ter of all science, including what he calls the 'laws of na-
Berkeley as Precursor of Mach and Einstein 449
ture' -and also its strength, its admirable understanding
of the logical structure of hypothetical explanation.
'It is one thing', Berkeley writes, 'to arrive at general
laws of nature from a contemplation of the phenomena;
and another to frame an hypothesis, and from thence de-
duce the phenomena. Those who suppose epicycles, and
by them explain the motions and appearances of the plan-
ets, may not therefore be thought to have discovered prin-
ciples true in fact and nature. And, albeit we may from
the premises infer a conclusion, it will not follow that we
can argue reciprocally, and from the conclusion infer the
premises. For instance, supposing an elastic fluid, whose
constituent minute particles are equidistant from each
other, and of equal densities and diameters, and recede
one from another with a centrifugal force which is in-
versely as the distance of the centres; and admitting that
from such supposition it must follow that the density and
elastic force of such fluid are in the inverse proportion of
the space it occupies when compressed by any force; yet we
cannot reciprocally infer that a fluid endowed with this
property must therefore consist of such supposed equal
particles.'
BIBLIOGRAPHY
LOCKE
Locke's Writings
An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, ed. A. C.
Fraser, 2 vols., Dover Publications, Inc., New York,
1959·
An Essay Concerning Human Understanding, ed. John W.
Yolton, 2 vols., J. M. Dent and Sons Ltd., London,
1961. (This is the best edition of the Essay in print.)
An Early Draft of Locke's Essay, Together with Excerpts
from his Journals, eds. R. I. Aaron and J. Gibb, Ox-
ford, 1936.
Books on Locke
Aaron, R. I., John Locke, 2nd ed., Oxford, 1955.
Bibliography 451
Gibson, James, Locke's Theory of Knowledge and Its His-
torical Relations, Cambridge, 1931.
Hofstadter, A., Locke and Scepticism, New York, 1935.
Leibniz, G. W. von, New Essays Concerning Human Un-
derstanding, translated and edited by A. G. Langley,
La Salle, 1949.
Mandelbaum, Maurice, Philosophy, Science, and Sense
Perception (Ch. 1), Baltimore, 1964.
Morris, C. R., Locke, Berkeley, Hume, Oxford, 1931.
O'Connor, D. J., John Locke, Pelican Books, 1952.
Yolton, J. W., John Locke and the Way of Ideas, Oxford,
1956•
Articles
Allison, Henry E., "Locke on Personal Identity," Journal
of the History of Ideas, '2.7 (1966), 41-58.
Ammerman, Robert, "Our Knowledge of Substance Ac-
cording to Locke," Theoria, 31 (1965), 1-8.
Broad, C. D., "John Locke," The Hibbert Journal, 31
(1933), 24cr-67. (Reprinted in Ethics and the History
of Philosophy, London, 1952.)
- - , "Locke's Doctrine of Substantial Identity and Di-
versity," Theoria, 17 (1951), 13-26.
Davis, John W., "The Molyneux Problem," Journal of the
History of Ideas, 21 (1960), 392-408.
Odegard, Douglas, "Locke as an Empiricist," Philosophy,
40 (19 6 5), 185-9 6.
Yolton, J. W., "Locke and the Seventeenth-Century Logic
of Ideas," Journal of the History of Ideas, 16 (1955).
43 1 -52.
Locke's Writings
Two Treatises of Civil Government, ed. Peter Laslett,
Mentor Books, 1965.
The Second Treatise of Civil Government and A Letter
452 Bibliography
Concerning Toleration, ed. J. W. Gough, Basil Black-
well, 1948.
John Locke, Essays on the Law of Nature, edited with
commentary by W. von Leyden, Oxford, 1954.
Two Tracts on Government, ed. Philip Abrams, Cam-
bridge, 1966 (first English publication of Locke's earli-
est writings on politics).
Locke on Politics, Religion, and Education, ed. Maurice
Cranston, Collier Books, 1965 (contains The Second
Treatise, A Letter Concerning Toleration, A Note on
Happiness, The Sound Mind in the Sound Body, The
Reasonableness of Christianity, The Conduct of the
Understanding) .
Books on Locke
Gough, J. W., John Locke's Political Philosophy, Eight
Studies, Oxford, 1950.
Lamprecht, S. P., The Moral and Political Philosophy of
John Locke (Archives of Philosophy No. 11), New
York, 1918.
Larkin, P., Property in the 18th Century, with Special
Reference to England and Locke, Cork, 1930.
Macpherson, C. B., The Political Theory of Possessive In-
dividualism, Oxford Paperbacks, 1964, Ch. v, "Locke:
The Political Theory of Appropriation."
Strauss, Leo, Natural Right and History, Chicago, 1953,
(pp. 202.51 on Locke).
Articles
Day, J. P., "Locke on Property," The Philosophical Quar-
terly, 16 (1966), 207-20.
Laslett, Peter, "The English Revolution and Locke's Two
Treatises of Government," Cambridge Historical Jour-
nal, 12 (1956),40-55.
von Leyden, W., "John Locke and Natural Law," Phi-
losophy, 31 (1956), 23-35.
Simon, W. M., "John Locke, Philosophy and Political
Theory," American Political Science Review, 45 (1951),
386-<)9.
Bibliography 453
Yolton, J. W., "Locke on the Law of Nature," Philosophi-
cal Review, 67 (1958),477-98.
BERKELEY
Books on Berkeley
Abbott, T. K., Sight and Touch, London, 1864.
Armstrong, D. M., Berkeley's Theory of Vision, Mel-
bourne, 1961.
Hedenius, I., Sensationalism and Theology in Berkeley'S
Philosophy, Uppsala, 1936.
Hicks, G. Dawes, Berkeley, London, 1932.
Johnston, G. A., The Development of Berkeley's Philoso-
phy, London, 1923.
- - , Berkeley's Commonplace Book, London, 1930.
Luce, A. A., Berkeley and Malebranche, Oxford, 1934.
- - , Berkeley's Philosophical Commentaries, London,
1944·
- - , Berkeley's Immaterialism, London, 1945.
- - , The Dialectic of Immaterialism, London, 1963.
Morris, C. R., Locke, Berkeley, Hume, Oxford, 1931.
Sillem, E. A., George Berkeley and the Proofs for the
Existence of God, London and New York, 1957.
Warnock, G. J., Berkeley, Pelican Books, 1953.
Collections of articles
"George Berkeley; Lectures on the Bi-Centenary of his
Death," University of California publications in Phi-
losophy, vol. 29.
Steinkraus, Warren E., New Studies in Berkeley'S Phi-
losophy, New York, 1966.
Bibliography 455
Articles
Bracken, H. M., "Berkeley's Realisms," Philosophical
Quarterly,8 (1958),41-53.
Broad, C. D., "Berkeley's Argument about Material Sub-
stance," Proceedings of the British Academy, z8 (194Z),
119-38.
Cummins, P., "Perceptual Relativity and Ideas in the
Mind," Philosophical and Phenomenological Research,
24 (1963), 20z-14.
Davis, John W., "Berkeley's Doctrine of the Notion," Re-
view of Metaphysics, 1Z (1959), 378-89.
- - , "The Molyneux Problem," Journal of the History of
Ideas, 21 (1960), 392-408.
Grey, Denis, "Berkeley on Other Selves: a Study in
Fugue," Philosophical Quarterly, 4 (1954), 28-44.
- - , "The Solipsism of Bishop Berkeley," Philosophical
Quarterly,2 (195z), 338-49.
Prior, A. N., "Berkeley in Logical Form," Theoria, 21
(1955), 117-Z2 .
Suchting, W. A., "Berkeley's Criticism of Newton on
Space and Motion," Isis, 58 (1967), Summer issue.
Turbayne, Colin M., "Berkeley's Two Concepts of Mind,"
Philosophical and Phenomenological Research, 20
(1959-60), 85-<)2. (There is a reply by qrave, S. A.,
"A Note on Berkeley's Conception of the Mind;' Phi-
losophy and Phenomenological Research, 22 [1961-
6z], 574-76. Turbayne rejoins in "Berkeley's Two Con-
cepts of Mind," Part II, Philosophy and Phenomenolog-
ical Research, 22 [1961-62] 577-80.)
INDEX