Bernardo Kastrup - A Rational, Empirical Case For Postmortem Survival Based Solely On Mainstream Science

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 63

A rational, empirical case for postmortem

survival based solely on mainstream science


Bernardo Kastrup, PhD, PhD1
Essentia Foundation

(18.834 words, read time ~1h 35 min.)

Introduction

What is the best available evidence for the survival of human consciousness after
permanent bodily death? For self-evident reasons, this is undoubtedly a central
question for all of us. Yet, the question itself already betrays a ubiquitous but
nonetheless unexamined assumption: that the postmortem survival of human
consciousness isn’t—at least in principle—the expected outcome and, therefore, one
needs the best possible evidence to convince oneself of it.

Indeed, the continuation of consciousness after bodily death is regarded, in our


culture, as an extraordinary hypothesis that contradicts prima facie expectations. As
such, it requires equally extraordinary evidence—or so the story goes—to be taken
seriously; evidence of a so-called ‘paranormal’ nature. This is a subtle but crucial
point: our culture assumes that the normal, ordinary, mainstream evidence routinely
collected in laboratories worldwide is either neutral on the question of postmortem
survival or outright contradicts it.

But is this really the case? Are we correct in assuming that our ordinary observations
of nature’s normal behavior suggest that consciousness perishes upon bodily death?
In this essay, I shall argue that such an assumption—pervasive and vulgarly intuitive
as it admittedly is—is in fact not correct; that the mainstream evidence, when
assessed carefully and rigorously, indicates precisely the opposite.

1
I have undertaken the writing of this essay as part of my work as Executive Director of Essentia
Foundation. Therefore, should this essay win a prize, the proceeds should be donated directly to
Stichting Essentia Foundation, Stadionweg 1, 1077 RV Amsterdam, The Netherlands, RSIN No.
861178555. Essentia Foundation is an official Dutch Public Benefit Organization—i.e. a charitable non-
profit. Donations received by the foundation are taxed in an advantageous manner, so Essentia will
be able to leverage any eventual prize money more effectively than I, as an individual, could.

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 1


In this context, I shall report on recent results from mainstream fields as diverse as
neuroscience of consciousness and foundations of physics, which provide us with a
picture of reality in which phenomenal consciousness2—that is, our raw
subjectivity—is not a by-product of physicality, but in fact precedes physicality.
Logically, therefore, the eventual loss of integrity of the physical body doesn’t entail
or imply that consciousness suffers the same fate; for consciousness is now
understood to be prior to the physical body, not a product of it. Indeed, this picture
of reality—grounded on decades of repeated and now exhaustively confirmed
experimental results—entails that it is the body that is in consciousness, not
consciousness in the body. After all, you have never become acquainted with this
thing you call your body outside your own consciousness, have you? And if you think
you have, you are conflating theoretical implications with actual acquaintance, a
logical fallacy common enough in our day and age.

As a matter of fact, not only does the empirical evidence indicate the primacy of
consciousness over physicality, but simple reasoning—when done rigorously—
already shows that our mainstream, vulgar physicalist intuitions are incoherent:
when looked at carefully, physicalism—the notion that physical entities are all there
ultimately is—fails on all key post-enlightenment epistemic values: it is internally
inconsistent (meaning that it contradicts itself), conceptually unparsimonious
(meaning that it is not the simplest model to account for the facts), empirically
inadequate (meaning that it cannot accommodate the evidence) and explanatorily
weak (meaning that it doesn’t make sense of observations).

Given all this, I contend that it is, strictly speaking, unnecessary to look to the
paranormal for high-confidence validation of postmortem survival. Not that there is
anything wrong with doing so, or that paranormal research is unreliable (often
enough the contrary is the case); but given present-day cultural sensitivities and
prejudices, I believe that an argument for postmortem survival based solely on
rigorous reasoning and sufficiently replicated laboratory evidence—both of which

2
Throughout this essay, what I mean by the word ‘consciousness’ is what is technically called
‘phenomenal consciousness’ in analytic philosophy: the ability to experience, without necessarily
entailing higher-level mental functions such as introspective meta-cognition. Moreover, as is tradition
in Western philosophy, I use the word ‘mind’ interchangeably with ‘consciousness,’ and thus also in
the sense of phenomenal consciousness.

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 2


are not contested by the mainstream—is more likely to resonate. Moreover, once this
argument is presented, evidence of phenomena currently regarded as ‘paranormal’
may be considered with less prejudice, since the argument lays a coherent theoretical
foundation to accommodate said evidence.

Therefore, this essay shall deliberately overlook evidence of the paranormal and base
its case completely on ‘ordinary’ laboratory results and reasoning informed by
traditional Aristotelian logic. As the reader shall hopefully realize, this self-
constrained approach is already more than sufficient to lead us—with a high degree
of confidence—to vast new horizons regarding the possibility of postmortem
survival.

The fallacy of our everyday intuitions

When we look around ourselves, we see a world of forms distributed across space
and time. Automatically, and without critical reasoning, we assume that these
forms—and the spatiotemporal extension that allows them to exist—are the forms of
the world3 as it is in itself. In other words, we think that the objects we perceive have
standalone reality outside our perceptions; we think that they are indeed the objects
that constitute the world in itself, not just inner representations of ours. To put it as
simply as possible, we regard perception as a transparent window into the world,
which reveals to us—perhaps with some but, at any rate, inconsequential distortion—
the world as it truly is, outside perception.

I shall call this assumption ‘perceptual realism’: the notion that the forms displayed
on the screen of perception are the forms of the world as it is in itself, outside and
independently of perception. Mainstream physicalism is largely founded on
perceptual realism, as the physicalist model presupposes isomorphism—i.e., direct
correspondence of form—between what we empirically perceive and the standalone
structure of the world. Without this presupposition, there would be little sense in
stating e.g., that the world is material, for the properties that characterize

3
Throughout this essay, when I say ‘the world’ I mean by it more than just planet Earth, but also the
totality of our shared environment at a cosmological level.

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 3


materiality—such as size, shape, mass, etc.—are directly derived from, and grounded
on, what is discerned through perception.4

But does this vulgarly intuitive assumption survive careful scrutiny? Do we have
reasons to believe that nature would have equipped us with a transparent window
into the world, revealing to us the world as it is in and of itself? What does modern
science tell us in this regard?

Research done at the Institute of Neurology of the Wellcome Trust Center for
Neuroimaging, in London, has shown mathematically that perception would be
incompatible with life if it were akin to a transparent window [1, 2]. Here is a
somewhat loose verbal paraphrase of the researchers’ rigorous mathematical
account: for perceptual realism to hold, our internal perceptual states would have to
mirror the external states of the world. Indeed, such mirroring is the definition of
perceptual realism. However, since there is no a priori upper bound to the dispersion
of the world’s states—i.e., our mere perceiving the world cannot constrain what the
world is or does—mirroring them internally would mean that there cannot be an
upper bound to the dispersion of our inner states either. Consequently, simply by
looking at the world our inner states could become so disperse that our nervous
system would dissolve into hot soup. This metaphorical imagery may sound
exaggerated, but it captures the technical facts quite accurately: if perception
mirrored the world, there would be no structural upper limit to our internal entropy
and, therefore, no guarantee of our maintaining our structural integrity. Statistically
speaking, perceiving would be very deadly business indeed. Like Perseus facing the
Gorgon, we would be far better off keeping our eyes tightly shut.

Now, since living beings have been safely perceiving the world for about three and a
half billion years, perception is not a transparent window, but an encoded

4
It is true that, under mainstream physicalism, the real world, as it is in itself, has no intrinsic qualities:
in it there supposedly are no colors, flavors, melodies, smells or textures. Under physicalism, these
qualities are side-effects of brain activity and therefore reside entirely within our skull, not in the
world outside. But the contours of the external world—still under mainstream physicalism—are
assumed to be the same, in principle, as the contours displayed on the screen of perception. These
contours can be fully characterized through abstract mathematical relationships—think of angles and
distances—and thus be defined independently of qualities. The alleged absence of intrinsic qualities
in the real world of physicalism simply means that the contours aren’t ‘filled in’ with e.g., colors. This
is how physicalism can be founded on perceptual realism without contradicting itself on this specific
point.

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 4


representation of what is salient about the world instead; a kind of internal dashboard
of instruments telling us what we need to know, but which doesn’t itself look
anything like the world. Indeed, it is precisely this latter fact that places an upper
bound on our internal entropy and allows us to survive perceiving. Perception is a
layer of indirection between us and the world as it is in itself: it tells us what we need
to know to overcome the Gorgon, but without showing us the Gorgon as she actually
is.

It is easy to gain felt intuition about all this. Imagine a pilot flying and airplane during
a severe storm: it would be very difficult to fly safely under such circumstances if all
the pilot had were a transparent windshield to see the storm; there would be just too
much going on outside, too much confusion, too much dispersion to allow for safe
flying. Instead, the pilot ignores the windshield and flies by instruments: the dials on
his dashboard present, at a glance, an encoded representation of what is relevant
about the storm outside. Yet, there is an upper bound to the state dispersion of the
dials on the dashboard: the needles can move left or right, the numbers can vary
within their assigned scales, but all these variations fall within predetermined limits.
The dashboard is designed to prevent information dispersion overload, while
presenting to the pilot what is salient about the world outside.

The possible configurations of a storm are virtually infinite: the number, shape, size
and movements of the constituent clouds, the specific spatiotemporal patterns of
rain drops and lightning distribution, etc. But the dashboard of dials encodes what is
relevant about all those possible variations in a neat, compact form, which limits the
dispersion of the data the pilot has to contend with: it presents the pilot with
indications of relevant air pressure variations, wind speed and direction, etc.,
regardless of which particular pattern of cloud, rain and lightning behavior is
unfolding outside. The airplane’s flying manual doesn’t have to tell the pilot what to
do for each of the countless possible configurations of the world, but solely for each
of the possible configurations of measurements displayed on the dashboard. The
entropy of the world outside, as it is in itself, is unbound. But the entropy of the data
the pilot has to work with is bound by design.

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 5


We are pilots and our dashboard is the screen of perception. Life is our flight through
the storm. We have no transparent windshield to contemplate the world as it is in itself;
for if we had one, we would have to face a more deadly kind of Gorgon: one that,
instead of turning us into stone, melts us into a highly entropic soup. All we have are
our sensors—our eyes, nose, tongue, ears and skin—whose measurement output is
displayed on the dials of the screen of perception. Yet, just as an airplane’s
instrument panel looks nothing like the storm outside, so what appears on the screen
of perception looks nothing like the world as it really is. Allow me to repeat this: by
design, what we see is not—and cannot be—what we get. The world, as it is in and of
itself, is not made of tables, chairs, mountains, moons, stars and what-not. For exactly
the same reason that the storm is not made of dials, the world is not made of matter.
Matter is the dials, not the thing in itself.

Indeed, our very conception of a world of objects distributed across space and time
is but the paradigm of the dashboard: the paradigm of needles moving within dials,
as they make measurements of what is going on outside. Space and time are the
scales of the dials, not the objective scaffolding of the external world. The vulgar
intuition underlying physicalism is thus fallacious: the world isn’t made of material
objects occupying space and time; the latter are just the representational
conventions of our internal dashboard of instruments.

What gives us very high confidence in this conclusion is not only the mathematical
rigor with which it has been derived; it’s not even its self-evident validity once it’s
correctly understood; what really gives us confidence in it is that the exact same
conclusion has been derived from an entirely different and independent line of
argument. Indeed, when independent and seemingly unrelated streams of thought
converge to the same destination, we are justified to feel particularly confident about
the corresponding conclusions.

And so it is that Prof. Donald Hoffman and his team at the University of California,
reasoning from the perspective of evolutionary theory (as opposed to
thermodynamics), have proven mathematically that evolution by natural selection
drives perceptual realism swiftly to extinction [3, 4, 5, 6]. And just like before, while
the mathematics may seem arcane, the conclusion is self-evident once correctly

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 6


understood: perceptual realism would overwhelm us with survival-irrelevant data
and be detrimental to our ability to react timely to environmental challenges.

To demonstrate this, Prof. Hoffman uses a computer desktop metaphor, which is


largely equivalent to the instrument dashboard metaphor I used above: on your
computer desktop, the file corresponding to, say, this essay is represented by a
colored rectangle. But is a colored rectangle what the file really is? Well, of course not.
A computer file is a vast pattern of open and closed microscopic switches in a silicon
chip; it looks absolutely nothing like a colored rectangle. But would it be efficient—
even merely useful—for you to see the file as it really is when using your computer?
Surely not, for having to discern which file you need by decoding a pattern of
millions of open and closed microscopic silicon switches would be literally mind-
boggling; it would guarantee that you cannot use a computer. Therefore, the desktop
metaphor used by a computer’s operating system aims at telling you solely what is
relevant about the files, in a way that encodes the relevant information according to
a structured, entropy-limiting paradigm—namely, the desktop paradigm.

Hoffman’s team has proven that evolution will always seek to do the same: instead
of showing us the world as it truly is—i.e., the millions of microscopic switches in our
analogy—it presents us with a ‘desktop metaphor’ of the world, a ‘virtual reality
headset’ or ‘user-interface’ that sits in between us and the world. What we call the
physical universe is merely this user-interface, this virtual reality headset. The world,
as it is in and of itself, is neither material nor framed by an objective spacetime
scaffolding.

Although these recent results are immensely important, in that they have provided
us with a level of conceptual clarity and mathematical certainty that wasn’t available
before, the conclusions themselves are nothing new. Already in the late 18th and early
19th centuries, Immanuel Kant and Arthur Schopenhauer maintained that what we
ordinarily refer to as ‘matter’ is merely an internal cognitive representation of ours,
not the substance of reality [7, 8]. Both also maintained that space and time are
categories of perception, not an objective empty box where nature places itself in.
Moreover, according to Schopenhauer [8], even Plato himself, two and a half
thousand years ago, already had this insight. Clearly, thus, perceptual realism—a key

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 7


foundation of physicalism—has been known by careful thinkers to be a naïve and
fallacious notion since the inception of Western thought.

The implications of this insight to the question of postmortem survival are as self-
evident as they are inevitable: if spacetime and matter are off the table as
fundamental aspects of reality—for now they are understood to be merely cognitive
representations in human consciousness—the notion that the loss of spatial integrity
of the material body at the time of death implies the end of consciousness loses
whatever couching in logic it might otherwise have. The most we can say is that
death is an event in consciousness: in the consciousness of the dying and of those
observing the dying process and its aftermath. Any extrapolation beyond this is
logically unfounded, regardless of how tempting it might be from a culture-bound
perspective.

More generally speaking, the assumption that bodily death indicates the end of
consciousness is culturally nurtured by mainstream physicalism, a metaphysics that
ties consciousness to the function of living brains. Therefore, an important next step
in my argument for postmortem survival is to show the logical and empirical
untenability of mainstream physicalism, so we can get that out of the way and
explore more promising theoretical landscapes later on.

The internal contradictions of mainstream physicalism

Although largely founded on a form of perceptual realism, mainstream physicalism


entails more: according to it, not only is the world made of a substance—matter or
physicality—outside and independent of consciousness, but particular arrangements
of that substance—such as living brains—also somehow generate consciousness (or
at least an ‘illusion of consciousness,’ as if such an idea were coherent at all). Is
perceptual realism then the only error underlying mainstream physicalism? Not
quite.

Physicalists start from where we all start: from our qualitative experience of the world
around us, with its colors, tones, flavors, smells and textures. They then realize—quite
correctly—that it is useful to describe these qualities in quantitative terms. This way,

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 8


if one tells me that a piece of luggage weighs 50 pounds, instead of 5, I will know
what qualitative experience to expect if I try to lift the piece of luggage. The
convenience of quantitative descriptions is quite general: we describe distances in
yards, colors in Hertz, sounds in decibels, etc., all to very useful practical effect.
Moreover, in describing nature in quantitative terms we can successfully predict
nature’s future behavior by plugging the respective quantities into mathematical
models. This, in fact, is the very basis of engineering and technology.

So far so good.

But then something very strange happens: physicalists start taking the descriptions
for the thing described, the map for the territory. They seemingly forget that the
numbers come after the qualities, merely as a handy way to describe relative
qualitative differences, and—bizarrely—postulate that the numbers are the things in
themselves! They conceptually define what we colloquially call ‘matter’ as an entity
that can be exhaustively described in quantitative terms alone, even though what we
ordinarily refer to as ‘matter’ is eminently qualitative (think of the feeling of carrying
weight, the quality of seeing a color, the loudness of a sound, etc.). In other words,
physicalists maintain that one can say everything there is to say about matter if one
provides a sufficiently long list of numbers; no qualities are needed.

Perhaps even more strangely, having divorced matter from all qualities by definition,
physicalists then proceed to try to explain all qualities in terms of… well, matter. They
maintain that experiential qualities—which philosophers technically call ‘qualia’—are
somehow generated by the particular structure and function of biological nervous
systems, even though these nervous systems—by the physicalists’ own account—are
entirely incommensurable with qualities. The result is what today is called the ‘hard
problem of consciousness’ [9, 10]: there is nothing about physical parameters—i.e.,
quantities—in terms of which one could deduce the qualities of experience. Is this
really a problem to be solved, or merely a glaring internal contradiction of
sophomoric reasoning? Is the fact that one fails to pull the territory out of the map a
problem to be solved by future, improved versions of the map and the process of
pulling, or does it merely show that the very attempt is stupid, and one needs to
revise one’s way of thinking about maps and territories?

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 9


Physicalism attempts to explain consciousness in terms of an abstraction of
consciousness, in consciousness: all we are ever acquainted with are the qualities of
experience, such as the colors we see, the sounds we hear, the textures we feel, the
hurt of heartbreak, the bitterness of disappointment, the warmth of love, the fire of
passion. As such, matter—as conceptually defined under mainstream physicalism—is
but a theoretical abstraction of and in mind, not an empirical fact. We never become
directly acquainted with purely quantitative matter, for we are always cooped up in
qualitative consciousness. Yet, physicalism postulates that consciousness is
reducible to this theoretical abstraction of consciousness, a circularity that,
unsurprisingly, leads to internal contradictions such as the ‘hard problem of
consciousness.’

Notice that I am not denying that which we colloquially refer to as ‘matter,’ i.e., the
contents of perception. These things we perceive and then call ‘material’ objects
undeniably exist as contents of perception. Only a fool would deny that. What I am
questioning is physicalism’s conceptual, theoretical definition of matter as a
substance outside and independent of consciousness.

Even if such a definition didn’t lead to internal contradictions, it would still be a


highly questionable theoretical move insofar as we can make sense of the world
without it. For matter is an extra ontological category beyond the one given—namely,
consciousness. The latter is the sole undeniable fact of existence, the one ontological
category we are directly acquainted with before we start theorizing. Therefore, if we
can successfully model nature using consciousness alone—not your consciousness
alone, or my consciousness alone, or even the consciousnesses of all living beings put
together, but consciousness as a ‘substance,’ a type of existent, which the Greeks
called ‘Oussia’ (Ουσία)—then matter becomes an inflationary postulate that must be
discarded on the basis of Occam’s Razor.

This may be subtle, but it is nonetheless important as a matter of principle.


Admittedly, there is nothing etched in stone in nature proclaiming that the correct
explanations are always the simplest ones. But if we neglect Occam’s Razor, we will
open the door to all kinds of nonsense. For instance, nobody can prove that the laws
of physics aren’t enforced by the Flying Spaghetti Monster manipulating physical

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 10


events, from a higher dimension, with its noodly appendages. But we don’t consider
the Flying Spaghetti Monster a plausible theory of reality because it is conceptually
inflationary; it postulates more than what we need to make sense of things. By
exactly the same token, if there is a successful theory of reality that requires
consciousness alone as ‘Oussia’—and, as I shall soon discuss, there is a hole family of
such theories—then physicalism isn’t a plausible alternative. Physicalists cannot
appeal to parsimony to refute the Flying Spaghetti Monsters promoted at the fringes
of our culture, and then turn around and disregard parsimony to safeguard their own
views. This may ultimately be a moot point—as the internal contradictions of
mainstream physicalism are already sufficient to render it untenable, irrespective of
parsimony considerations—but the principle underlying it is important enough to be
mentioned here.

Strictly speaking, the internal contradictions of mainstream physicalism are more


than enough for any reasonable person to abandon mainstream physicalism
altogether. But it would also be naïve of me to ignore the cultural momentum
physicalism has accumulated, with the sense of plausibility that it artificially
manufactures. I shall thus make a concession to the reader’s presumed expectation
that I provide more than just a logical argument. I shall present and discuss solid
empirical evidence that contradicts physicalism. For, as it turns out, there is plenty
of such evidence in mainstream science. Nonetheless, my discussing it below should
not be construed as an admission, on my part, that anything more than clear logical
reasoning is necessary to falsify physicalism definitively.

Physical realism has been empirically falsified

Another key assumption of mainstream physicalism is physical realism:


fundamental physical entities, be them invisible fields or abstract elementary
subatomic particles, must have standalone existence. In other words, physical
entities must exist in and of themselves and not be dependent on anything
nonphysical to exist. This is so because physicalism postulates that physical entities
are the bottom level of reality, the so-called ontological primitives, the things at the

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 11


very end of the chain of reduction. If it turns out that these physical entities depend
on something else nonphysical to exist, then physicalism is false.

So, do physical entities have standalone existence, insofar as modern science can
determine? The answer is ‘no’: from a series of experiments that started in the late
1970s and have been refined and replicated for over 40 years, we now know that
physical entities do not have standalone existence, but are instead an image, an
appearance, a representation of a deeper layer of reality, which is itself nonphysical
by definition.5 The only alternative to this conclusion is to postulate—in a far more
extreme and implausible version of the Flying Spaghetti Monster—that countless
bazillions of real physical universes pop into existence every unimaginably tiny
fraction of a femtosecond, for which we have precisely zero empirical evidence.

Let us look more closely at this remarkable series of experiments and discuss why
they refute physical realism. The experimental procedure is the following: two
subatomic particles are generated together, so that they are ‘entangled.’
Entanglement is physics jargon for saying that the particles become interrelated in
such a way that their behavior cannot be described independently of one another.
The particles are then shot in different directions at (near) the speed of light and,
after a certain distance is covered, measurements are done on both particles,
separately but concurrently. What then transpires is that the choice of what to
measure about one particle determines the result of measuring the other. How can
this be? How can the choice of what to observe determine what a particle is?
Shouldn’t observation merely reveal what a particle already was, in and of itself,
regardless of what is observed about it?

This result is extremely counterintuitive from a physicalist perspective. If the two


particles were real in the sense of having standalone existence, then their
measurable properties would be whatever they are regardless of what one chooses
to measure about them. Take a table, for instance: it seems to have a certain mass,
height and length regardless of what is being measured about it. If it weighs 40
pounds, then it will still weight 40 pounds when it’s not sitting on a weighing scale—

5
By definition in the sense that what we define as physicality is the appearance, the image of
something else. That something else is then, by the very definition of physicality, not physical.

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 12


or so we like to think. Measurements supposedly reveal something that was already
the case about the table immediately before the measurement was done, not
determine it. If mainstream physicalism were true, the same should apply to the
subatomic particles in our experiment: measurement should simply reveal the
properties the particles already had, in and of themselves, immediately prior to
measurement.

Experimentally, however, what we see is that the properties of one particle depend
on what we choose to observe about the other. It is as though the particles’ properties
didn’t have standalone existence but were, instead, created by the very act of
measurement. As a matter of fact, since there is nothing about a physical particle but
its measurable physical properties, it is as though the particles themselves didn’t exist
unless and until they are measured. This, of course, is incompatible with the
physicalist notion that elementary subatomic particles (or their respective quantum
fields) are things in themselves, not just appearances, representations or images of a
deeper layer of reality.

The first well-known experiments in this 40-year-long series were those performed
by Alain Aspect and his team in the early 1980s [11, 12, 13]. Since their results
contradicted physicalist expectations, physicists at the time came up with a long list
of possible experimental loopholes that, if true, would throw doubt on the
experiments’ conclusions and perhaps save physical realism. Over the years, these
hypothetical loopholes became increasingly implausible to the point of sounding
fantastic. For instance, some physicists speculated that the particles could somehow
be secretly exchanging information with one another, so as to synchronize their
behavior. This would, in principle, account for the observed correlations between the
measurements of the two particles while preserving physical realism. It has also
been speculated that the measurement devices themselves could somehow be
tipping each other off, so as to create the measurement correlations in a kind of
conspiratorial manner. Perhaps the most bizarre of the proposed loopholes has been
that there is some undetectable but real physical entity ‘smeared across’ all
spacetime, which is capable of instantaneously synchronizing the measurements
without relativistic limitations (needless to say, there is precisely zero direct

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 13


evidence for this postulated entity, technically called a ‘global hidden variable’).6
Never mind that these hypothetical loopholes, if true, would themselves create even
more problems for both physics and physicalism; at least they would avoid the
immediate conclusion that physical entities do not have standalone existence and,
thereby, safeguard a physicalist way of thinking.

A whole series of experiments then began in earnest to attempt to close the loopholes
and decide, once and for all, if the original conclusions were really correct [14, 15, 16,
17, 18]. The most remarkable in the series were experiments done in 2015 and 2018 [19,
20], which were celebrated by the popular science press as having closed all the
loopholes [21]. Needless to say, the results were the same as the original experiments:
physical properties do not exist unless and until they are measured. In the words of
renowned physicist Anton Zeilinger, “there is no sense in assuming that what we do
not measure about a system has [an independent] reality” [22]. Physicality has no
standalone existence.

Strictly speaking, it can be argued that what some of the experiments refute is not
physical realism per se, but the combination of physical realism with locality. The
latter is the notion that physical influences cannot propagate faster than the speed
of light. Therefore—the argument goes—perhaps physical realism is still true, and it
is just locality that we have to abandon: the universe may be a relativity-transcending
integrated hole at its deepest level.

The problem is that some of the experiments were constructed precisely to test
physical realism in isolation, irrespective of locality [e.g., 23, 24, 25, 26]. And they, too,
refuted physical realism empirically. As a result, the science press went as far as to
proclaim that “Quantum physics says goodbye to reality” [27], “the unreality of the
quantum world” [21] and even that “reality is what you make of it” [22]. Alas,
mainstream science journalism today doesn’t seem capable of conceiving of
anything that is both objectively real and nonphysical. Even if the physical is not

6
I am not providing references to these loophole claims at this point because the claims are
expounded at length in the technical literature of the experiments designed to close the loopholes, as
referenced below.

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 14


ultimately real, something else clearly is, for the chain of reduction must end with
something that exists in and of itself.

The surviving interpretation of the experimental results that could, in principle, still
preserve physical realism is called ‘Bohmian Mechanics’ [28, 29]. Alas for physicalists,
this interpretation is plagued by a number of other problems. For instance, unlike
regular Quantum Mechanics with its Quantum Field Theory extensions, Bohmian
Mechanics has no relativistic version and, thus, cannot be true. Physicists Raymond
Streater and Luboš Motl are on record reviewing this and other compelling technical
arguments against Bohmian Mechanics [30, 31]. Finally, recent experiments have
refuted the interpretation empirically, driving the final nail into its coffin [32].

As two renowned physicists, along with myself, have discussed on Scientific


American [33, 34, 35, 36]—perhaps the world’s most respected popular science
magazine—the options left on the table are quite clear. Either one has to adopt what
is arguably the most inflationary and implausible theoretical hypothesis conceivable
to physics—namely, that countless new physical universes pop into existence every
fraction of a moment, for which we have precisely zero empirical evidence, and
wherein everything that can physically happen actually does7—or we have to accept
that physical reality is but an image, an appearance, a representation of a deeper, by
definition nonphysical layer of reality. In other words, the physical world is but the
dashboard of perception, not the real world as it is in itself.

Indeed, it is remarkable to realize how well the completely independent lines of


evidence we’ve reviewed thus far converge: the world we see is not the final layer of
reality. Kant and Schopenhauer were right. Physicality is akin to dials on our internal
dashboard of instruments.8 Therefore, it only comes into existence when a

7
The idea here is that, since every physical possibility allegedly does happen in one of these countless
bazillions of physical universes, we just happen to live in the one wherein the particular measurement
correlations we observe take place.
8
Thoughtful physicists acknowledge without hesitation that physics is a science of perception, not of
the world as it is in itself, for we have no access to the latter. Even when we use instruments such as
telescopes and microscopes, we are still limited to perception, for we must perceive the output of such
instruments. Here is how renowned physicist Andrei Linde, famous for his seminal theory of
cosmological inflation, put it: “our knowledge of the world begins not with matter but with
perceptions … Later we find out that our perceptions obey some laws, which can be most conveniently
formulated if we assume that there is some underlying reality beyond our perceptions … This
assumption is almost as natural (and maybe as false) as our previous assumption that space is only a
mathematical tool for the description of matter.” [37, p. 12]

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 15


measurement is actually performed on the real, nonphysical world surrounding us.
Without observation, there is no physicality, for without a measurement the needles
in the dials don’t move and nothing is registered. That’s why physical properties only
come into existence upon being measured: the needles in the dials only move when
the attached sensors probe the environment; prior to this probing, nothing is shown
on the dashboard, even though the real world out there continues to exist. How could
things be clearer or more sensible?

Again, physical properties only come into existence upon measurement because
physicality is the result of measurement, just as the movement of the needles in the
dials on a dashboard is the result of probing the real world outside. This conclusion
is so natural, so self-evidently rational and empirically inevitable that the dogged
resistance against it from the likes of physicist Sean Carrol—who insists on the
equivalent of the Flying Spaghetti Monster in modern physics9—is baffling. Is it really
so incredible that physicality is just the result of our observing our environment?
That it is merely an encoded appearance, a representation, an image of a deeper, by
definition nonphysical layer of reality to which we have no direct access because we
would otherwise die?

The dashboard hypothesis can even make straightforward sense of the correlations
between measurements of two distant entangled particles, as discussed above.
These correlations are only puzzling if we assume that the particles have standalone
existence, not if they are mere images. To see this, consider the following analogy:
imagine that you are watching a football match at home. Because you are such a
great fan of football, you bought two large TVs to follow the same match,
simultaneously, on two different channels. Imagine also that the two different
broadcasters have their own cameras in the stadium, so each channel shows
different images of the same match. And you watch the two different images side by
side.

Now, obviously, the two images will be entirely correlated with one another, for they
are images of the same match, of the same underlying reality. The images have no
standalone existence, only the football match at the stadium—the thing in itself—has.

9
I am being charitable here.

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 16


Nonetheless, the images will also be different, for they are produced by different
cameras and camera angles. Is this in any sense counterintuitive or difficult to
understand?

However, if you were a time traveler from the 19th century and didn’t understand how
TVs work, you would conceivably be flabbergasted by the correlations between the
two images: how can the real little men running around inside the two TVs behave
in such an instantly synchronized, perfectly correlated manner? How can that
happen even when the TVs are totally isolated from one another, and no signal can
be transmitted from one to the other? Magic!

Of course, the source of this puzzlement is the unexamined and arbitrary


assumption, by our time traveler, that the images aren’t actually images, but the
things in themselves. If you think that there are real little men, with standalone
existence, running around inside the two TV sets, the correlation of their behavior
across the sets, when no signal is transmitted between them, would seem magical
indeed. And this is precisely the mistake we make when it comes to the physical
experiments being discussed here: we think of the particles as things in themselves,
not mere images of a deeper, nonphysical layer of reality. If we understood and
accepted the latter, the experiments wouldn’t seem magical at all. But instead, we
insist on thinking like 19th-century people in face of 21st-century experimental
evidence.

Educated but non-specialist readers could contend that these experimental results
are only applicable to the microscopic scale of elementary subatomic particles, and
that the conclusions cannot be extrapolated to the world of tables and chairs wherein
we live. But most physicists know very well that this is a naïve and invalid point.
Although there are undeniable operational differences between the behavior of the
world of tables and chairs and that of isolated microscopic quantum systems, these
differences are per force merely epiphenomenal. After all, macroscopic objects and
events are just compound results of microscopic dynamics. To quote renowned
physicist Erich Joos, a

method for sweeping the interpretive problems under the carpet is


simply to assume, or rather postulate, that quantum theory is only a

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 17


theory of micro-objects, whereas in the macroscopic realm per decree
(or should I say wishful thinking?) a classical description has to be
valid. Such an approach leads to the endlessly discussed paradoxes of
quantum theory. These paradoxes only arise because this particular
approach is conceptually inconsistent … In addition, micro- and macro-
objects are so strongly dynamically coupled that we do not even know
where the boundary between the two supposed realms could possibly
be found. For these reasons it seems obvious that there is no boundary.
[38, pp. 74-75]

Joos goes on to say, “whichever interpretation [of Quantum Mechanics] one prefers,
the classical world view has been ruled out” [38, p. 76]. There is no actual boundary
between the microscopic and the macroscopic. The distinction between the two is
arbitrary, nominal, motivated by convenience and purely epistemic. Our everyday
world is quantum.

Admittedly, there are experts in foundations of physics that are both (a) reluctant to
acknowledge the refutation of physical realism and (b) unable to muster the faith
required to follow Sean Carrol into the many-worlds interpretation of the
experimental results. What do they then make of the results?

A representative case is perhaps that of renowned physicist Carlo Rovelli. For 25


years Rovelli has been on record denying the standalone existence of all physical
observables [39]. His interpretation—called ‘Relational Quantum Mechanics’—is
entirely consistent with the dashboard metaphor discussed above: according to it, all
physical observables are relational, just like movement. The inevitable implication is
that all physical quantities are mere representations of some underlying, absolute
dynamics, just like the movement of dials on a dashboard is a representation of the
dynamics of the outside world.

Rovelli himself explicitly uses movement as an example of what he means by


relationality: if you are sitting inside a high-speed train, in relation to the train you
are not moving. But in relation to someone standing on a platform you are moving
at high-speed. So movement is not absolute; it doesn’t have existence in and of itself,
but depends instead on the things that move. After all, there is nothing to movement

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 18


but things in movement. In this sense, according to Rovelli all physical quantities are
akin to movement.

So far so good for, again, this is entirely consistent with the dashboard metaphor: the
dials’ indications are also relational, not absolute, for they depend—for their very
existence—on the relationships between sensors and the properties of the world
outside. The dials aren’t the world in itself, but the result of an observation of the
world.

But Rovelli’s view immediately raises a critical philosophical qualm: if physicality is


relative, then what is it relative to? If everything is akin to movement, then what is it
that is moving so to give rise to physicality? What is the absolute world that underlies
the relational world of physics?

After 25 years expressly avoiding this philosophical qualm, Rovelli has decided to
finally bite the bullet and publish his answer [40]. His proposal is unexpected, though
probably not in the way he intended: instead of acknowledging that Relational
Quantum Mechanics implies that there is a nonphysical layer of reality underlying
the physical, he maintains that it’s turtles… err, relations all the way down! According
to him, there are only relations. And since relations are physical, there is then only
physicality.

But if relations are all there is, then physical quantities can only be relations across
meta-relations (for there is nothing else that can be relating); and meta-relations are
relations across meta-meta-relations; and so on. The fallacy of infinite regress is upon
us, and it isn’t even disguised by some theoretical subtlety.

Worse yet, there is no meaning—in a straightforward semantic sense—to saying that


there are only relations. It’s like saying that there is only movement, but nothing that
moves. This is something one can write in words in a way that satisfies all
grammatical and syntactical rules, but which lacks all semantic content. It literally
means nothing. It’s akin to saying that the Cheshire Cat’s grin stays behind after the
cat itself disappears. Lewis Carrol wrote this to great literary effect, which he got
away with because we all understand it to be a metaphor. But Rovelli means it
literally.

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 19


Surely there is more to Rovelli’s argument than this, right? Well, having made his
case for Relational Quantum Mechanics in an explicit, unambiguous and strictly
scientific manner, at a crucial juncture Rovelli suddenly changes tack altogether and
appeals instead to 3rd-century Indian mystic Nāgārjuna. Such an arbitrary pivoting
away from science would be suspicious enough, but it gets worse. According to
Rovelli’s read of Nāgārjuna, the ultimate essence of reality is emptiness, in a literal
sense. In other words, there is nothing going on right now (not just no-thing,10 which
is what Nāgārjuna probably meant, but literally nothing). That there obviously is
something going on—for even if life is entirely illusory, illusions are not nothing—
doesn’t seem to bother Rovelli. Moreover, even if Nāgārjuna did mean what Rovelli
thinks he did, merely referring to Nāgārjuna doesn’t exempt Rovelli from having to
make explicit, rational sense of the empirically absurd statement that nothing exists.
For again, even if the world is an illusion, something is having the illusion.

It’s precisely the absurd claim that reality is essentially nothing that gives Rovelli an
excuse to reconcile ‘movement’ with the absence of anything that ‘moves.’ But at
what cost? Adding two absurdities together doesn’t magically erase them; it just
compounds them. Why would Rovelli even attempt such a move? Only he, of course,
can answer this question, but he is open about the subjective motivation behind his
appeal to Nāgārjuna: he describes how relieved he was upon reading the Indian sage,
because it freed him from the pressure of having to find out what the underlying
essence of reality is.

I find this extraordinarily interesting from a psychocultural point of view. Here we


have a leading champion of the enlightenment values—conceptual clarity, explicit
reasoning, explanatory closure, empirical grounding, etc.—suddenly resorting, at the
critical juncture of his argument, to a vague, ambiguous, handwaving appeal to
another man’s introspective insights more than 17 centuries ago, so as to avoid a
conclusion he dislikes. Rovelli prefers to say that reality is nothing—regardless of
how silly this claim is from a rational, scientific perspective—instead of something
nonphysical. Who would have guessed that, to save physicalism, renowned scientists

10
No-thing in the sense of no objects separate from, or outside, the subject of experience; no substance
in the sense of no objective substance, as opposed to a field of pure subjectivity.

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 20


would resort to mystics? Fantastically, we now find ourselves in a situation wherein
people like me argue for postmortem survival based purely on mainstream science
and reason, while people like Rovelli defend physicalism based on vague appeals to
centuries-old mystical writings. Oh, the irony.

I shall close this section with a prediction. Confronted with the self-evident
untenability of his case, Rovelli and others will eventually propose an entirely
abstract but allegedly absolute ‘something’ to underly the physical world; something
that could only be said to exist by virtue of ostensibly corresponding to some
convenient, overdetermining mathematical equation. They will then insist that this
purely abstract something—lacking any direct empirical evidence—is physical,
despite its intrinsically not having any of the properties we associate with
physicality, such as mass, charge, spin, momentum, etc. There will be an overt,
unashamed attempt to preserve physicalism by mere word redefinition. In other
words, whatever reality turns out to be, they will wrap an overdetermining equation
around it and call it ‘physical,’ so that physicalism is true by definition. If you think
this would be too obvious a charade, watch carefully. It won’t even be malicious, but
driven instead by unexamined—yet irresistible—subjective belief.

Correlations between brain activity and experience contradict physicalism

According to physicalists, it’s the particular structure and dynamics of matter inside
our skulls—i.e., our brain activity—that somehow is or generates consciousness. Their
position is based on reliable correlations between patterns of brain activity and inner
experience. Indeed, that these correlations exist doesn’t even require scientific
equipment to be determined: alcohol in the blood stream and trauma to the head
have obvious correlates in inner experience. Physicalists then construe these
correlations as instances of causation: specific patterns of brain activity are thought
to be or generate inner experience.

There is now growing neuroimaging literature substantiating this point. For


instance, neuroscientists have identified specific patterns of neuronal activation that
correspond to subjects dreaming of clenching their hand [41, 42]. The dream

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 21


experience of clenching one’s hand is then construed to be, or be generated by, those
patterns of activation.

Similarly, neuroscientists can determine, based purely on brain activity scans,


whether a subject is dreaming of something as boring as looking at a statue [43, 44].
Even this boring experience correlates with enough brain activation to be recognized
from functional brain scans alone, without the subject having to report it.

If the physicalist hypothesis is correct, we would expect all experiences to correlate


with specific patterns of neuronal activation, just like the ones discussed above. After
all, an entirely non-active brain is a dead brain, which presumably doesn’t generate
any experience. Moreover, as we have just seen, many experiences correlate so well
with brain activation that they can be identified based solely on scans of the latter.

The problem is that there is a broad, diverse, consistent and repeatable pattern of
brain activity impairments or reductions that correlate precisely with richer, more
intense experience. If experience were, or were generated by, brain activity, then how
could we get more experience out of less brain activity?

For instance, up until 2012 neuroscience and most lay physicalists had always
assumed that psychedelics generate immensely rich and intense experiences—
which subjects report as ranking among the top 5 most significant experiences of
their lives [45, 46]—by lighting up the brain like a Christmas tree. That’s why, when
researchers realized that psilocybin (the active ingredient of magic mushrooms) in
fact only reduces activity throughout the brain, without increasing it anywhere (see
Figure 1) [47], the neuroscience community was surprised [48].

Since that seminal study, the results have been consistently replicated for most other
psychedelic substances [49, 50, 51, 52]. In all cases, the physiological effect of the
psychedelic is to reduce brain activity, particularly in the so-called ‘default mode
network,’ which is correlated with our ego or sense of individual identity (see Figures
2 and 3). The phenomenological effect, on the other hand, is one of the richest and
most intense experiences a human being can possibly have. If one’s brain is
effectively going to sleep during those experiences, where are the experiences then
coming from?

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 22


Figure 1. In blue, brain regions with decreased Cerebral Blood Flow (CBF, a proxy of brain
activity) under the effect of psilocybin. Image source: Proceedings of the National Academy of
Sciences of the USA, Vol. 109, No. 6. Copyright © 2012 by the National Academy of Sciences
(NAS) of the USA. Re-use permission for noncommercial and educational purposes is not
required by the NAS.

Figure 2. In blue, reductions on brain activity in the default mode network (associated with the
executive ego) induced by the psychedelic brew Ayahuasca. Source: PLoS ONE 10(2): e0118143.
Reproduced here under a Creative Commons Attribution License.

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 23


Figure 3. LSD effect on the brain. A and B: in blue, brain regions with decreased activity in the
respective frequency band. C: reduced overall power signal of brain activity under LSD, across
the spectrum. Source: Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the USA, Vol. 113,
No. 17. Copyright © 2016 by the National Academy of Sciences (NAS) of the USA. Re-use
permission for noncommercial and educational purposes is not required by the NAS.

No established worldview, regardless of how silly, ever accepts evidence against it


without putting up a fight [53]. And so it is that the neuroscience community and its

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 24


funders have mobilized to levels never before seen, so as to find something in brain
physiology—some physical parameter of brain dynamics—that increases in the
psychedelic state [54]. The best-known result of that effort, which has attracted the
most consensus among physicalists, is the so-called ‘entropic brain hypothesis’ [55].

According to this hypothesis, a physiological parameter the researchers variously


refer to as ‘entropy,’ ‘complexity’ or ‘diversity’ is shown to increase in a statistically
significant manner in the psychedelic state. The not-always-explicit but ubiquitous
and conspicuous suggestion is that this increase accounts for the phenomenology of
the psychedelic state, thereby safeguarding mainstream physicalism.

But if we dig a little deeper into the technical material, things aren’t as they seem.
For starters, what the researchers portentously call ‘complexity,’ ‘diversity’ or
‘entropy’ is just noise; they are talking about unstructured, incoherent brain activity
that forms no discernible pattern. The suggestion that an increase in brain noise
accounts for the highly structured and coherent phenomenology of the psychedelic
state seems highly implausible. No one who has undergone a true psychedelic
experience would describe it as noise or brain fog. Trip reports contain sharp and
highly coherent narratives and insights [56, 57].

Second, if we look at the size of the effect reported, we realize that it is minuscule.11
See Figure 4. We are talking here of an average increase in noise level of about 0.005
in a scale of 0 to 100! See the graph scales in Figure 4. To suggest that such a
minuscule increase in noise accounts for the literally mindboggling intensity and
richness of the psychedelic experience, under physicalist premises, requires a
complete abandonment of any notion of plausibility. It is embarrassing. Moreover,
in several of the cases studied, noise levels actually decreased in the psychedelic
state, although the subjects still did have the experience. What caused the experience
in those cases? It couldn’t have been an increase in brain noise.

11
The researchers’ claim that the effect is statistically significant doesn’t contradict the fact that it is
minuscule. Although there is much debate today about the arbitrariness of the statistical significance
threshold—and the recognition that it is leading to all kinds of spurious conclusions [58, 59, 60]—I am
prepared to grant, for the sake of the discussion, that the effect in question is statistically significant.
But this only shows that the effect exists, not that it is anything more than minuscule.

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 25


Figure 4. Tiny increases in noise in the brain of subjects undergoing a psychedelic experience.
Top: psilocybin. Middle: ketamine. Bottom: LSD. Source: Scientific Reports, volume 7, article
number: 46421 (2017). Reproduced here under the Creative Commons Attribution 4.0
International License.

Third, an appeal to levels of noise to account for the psychedelic experience


contradicts the entire body of work that correlates experience with increases in
activity level, not noise. Can there be two correct but completely different and
mutually incompatible physiological accounts of consciousness? Is it coherent to
maintain that, in the psychedelic state, experience is generated by noise levels in a
brain that is effectively asleep, while in all ordinary cases experience is generated by
brain activation levels?

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 26


Dreams are analogous to the psychedelic state in that the experience is endogenous.
Yet, during dreams, experience correlates with clear patterns of brain activation, not
inactivation accompanied by minuscule increases in noise levels. As we have seen,
when subjects dream of something as boring as looking at a statue, or clenching a
hand, neuroscientists can discern enough brain activation to correctly guess the
dream content. But when someone travels to ‘other dimensions’ and meets
‘unearthly beings’ under psychedelics [57], no activations are to be found; on the
contrary: the subject’s brain effectively goes to sleep. How can this not be interpreted
as directly contradicting mainstream physicalism? Physicalists cannot have a
different and incompatible account of consciousness for each class of evidence,
otherwise their view becomes unfalsifiable.

It is quite safe to say that the psychedelic experience is not generated by minuscule
increases of—of all things—brain noise. The one robust physiological effect of
psychedelics is an overall reduction of brain activity. If brain imaging studies had
shown that psychedelics light up the brain like a Christmas tree, physicalists would
be shouting, “You see?! We told you so!” But now that the result is the very opposite
of what they expected, a significant part of the neuroscience community is prepared
to throw reason and plausibility out the window and entertain embarrassing,
preposterous suggestions with a straight face. This, unfortunately, is the
psychosocial nature of the game.

Moreover, the pattern associating enrichment or intensification of experience with


brain activity impairment or reduction goes much beyond psychedelics. In a
neuroimaging study, researchers took brain activity readings of both a control group
and a group of self-identified mediums while they wrote text. Compared to their
baseline writing, neuronal activity in areas associated with language processing—
such as the frontal lobes and hippocampus—decreased in the group of mediums
when they wrote while in a self-induced trance. In the control group, on the other
hand, brain activity in the same areas increased. See Figure 5. Yet, when the
researchers scored the resulting texts on a scale of complexity, text written by the
mediums during trance was more complex than their baseline writing [61]. As an
observant journalist remarked, more complex writing

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 27


typically would require more activity in the frontal and temporal lobes—but
that’s precisely the opposite of what was observed. To put this another way,
the low level of activity in the experienced mediums’ frontal lobes should have
resulted in vague, unfocused, obtuse garble. Instead, it resulted in more
complex writing samples than they were able to produce while not entranced.
Why? No one’s sure. [62]

Figure 5. EXP: Higher cognitive function accompanied by reductions of brain activity in


different brain regions during trance state (red lines go down from baseline to trance writing).
LEX: controls display increases of brain activity in the same brain regions (blue lines go up
from baseline to ‘trance’ writing). Source: PLoS ONE 7(11): e49360 (2012). Reproduced here
under a Creative Commons Attribution License.

A prospective study of patients who underwent brain surgery for the removal of
tumors—which often causes collateral lesions to surrounding tissue—has shown
that, post-surgery, patients display significantly higher levels of feelings of self-
transcendence [63]. See Figure 6.

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 28


Figure 6. Increased feelings of self-transcendence (ST) after normal brain function is impaired
by surgery. Source: Neuron, Vol. 65, p. 313. Copyright © 2010 Elsevier Inc. Reproduced here
under a license obtained via the RightsLink Copyright Clearance Center.

In a study of pilots undergoing G-force induced Loss of Consciousness (GLOC) in


training centrifuges, subjects reported experiencing “memorable dreams”
comparable to Near Death Experiences (NDEs) during the period of syncope [64].
Clearly, although outwardly the subjects were unresponsive and seemed
unconscious, from the inside they were having rich endogenous experiences despite
the massive draw of blood from their heads caused by centrifugal acceleration.

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 29


In a Dutch study of cardiac arrest patients, a number of subjects reported intense and
rich NDEs during the period of cardiac arrest, when brain activity is at least severely
compromised due to the lack of blood circulation [65].

In cases of so-called ‘Acquired Savant Syndrome,’ subjects display remarkably


increased cognitive abilities (prodigious memory, ability to perform complex
calculations instantly, artistic talent, etc.) concurrent with brain trauma. Car
accidents, lightning strikes, the progression of dementia and even bullet wounds to
the head have been documented as triggers of acquired savant, despite (severely)
impairing brain function [66, 67, 68, 69].

In a study of over one hundred Vietnam war veterans, damage to the frontal and
parietal lobes was shown to increase the likelihood of “mystical experiences” [70].

I could go on and on. Teenagers worldwide play a dangerous game called ‘the
choking game.’ They have realized that partial strangulation—which reduces blood
flow to the head and compromises brain metabolism—can lead to intense and rich
experiences akin to the psychedelic state, but without the drug [71, pp. 310-315]. The
technique of ‘Holotropic Breathwork’ aims to unlock transcendent experiences
through hyperventilation, which constricts blood flow to the brain [72]. Initiatory
rituals in pre-literate cultures worldwide consistently involve severe physiological
stress—through exhaustion, fasting, poisoning, dehydration, exposure to the
elements, etc.—which undoubtedly impair brain metabolism. The rituals are
reported to unlock profound insights about the nature of reality [73]. The list goes on.

In all these cases, there is a robust correlation between brain activity impairment and
enriched, more intense inner experience. In some of the cases—psychedelics, trance—
this correlation is repeatable on demand under controlled experimental conditions.
In the studies involving neuroimaging and permanent brain damage, we know for
sure that the period in which enriched experience is reported is concomitant with
the period of reduced or impaired brain activity. Mainstream physicalism just cannot
account for this.

Therefore, the question now is whether an alternative ontology can do so, while also
accounting for the undeniable empirical fact that, in ordinary circumstances,
experience does correlate with brain activation. I shall shortly discuss an ontology

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 30


that does precisely that. For now, however, the important point is this: our motivation
for assuming that bodily death implies the end of consciousness is largely the
physicalist postulate that brain activity somehow is or generates experience. For if
the brain doesn’t generate experience, why should consciousness end upon brain
death? As such, if mainstream physicalism is proven to be untenable—which I
submit is the case right now—we must review the logic behind our vulgar
expectations. A change in our state of consciousness upon brain death is a very
reasonable inference to make—for our normal state of consciousness seems to be
tightly correlated with regular brain activity—but not the end of consciousness. If
anything, the evidence suggests precisely an expansion of consciousness upon brain
death.

If not physicalism, then what?

In analytic philosophy—the academic discipline that deals with the question of what
reality is, as opposed to how it behaves—there are three main types of ontology, i.e.,
theories about the nature of reality. Each of them faces a canonic challenge or
problem.

Mainstream physicalism—the notion that reality is essentially outside and


independent of consciousness—faces the ‘hard problem of consciousness’ we’ve
discussed earlier.

Constitutive panpsychism—the notion that consciousness is an irreducible property


of elementary subatomic particles—faces the so-called ‘combination problem’ [74]:
how can the fundamentally separate fields of subjectivity of the particles making up
our brain combine to form the unitary consciousness we experience?

Idealism—the notion that reality is fundamentally mental (not in your or my


consciousness alone, but in a transpersonal field of subjectivity spanning the entire
universe)—faces the so-called ‘decomposition problem’: how can one universal
consciousness ground the multitude of seemingly separate minds in existence? After
all, I can’t read your thoughts and presumably you can’t read mine. Neither can I

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 31


know what is going on in the galaxy of Andromeda right now. If all existence is
unfolding in one universal consciousness, why are these things not possible?

We have seen in previous sections that mainstream physicalism is untenable on both


logical and empirical grounds, so we can discard that one.

Constitutive panpsychism, in turn, is physically incoherent, as I’ve argued elsewhere


[75]. It assumes that elementary subatomic particles are entities with defined spatial
boundaries. This way, because the particles that make up our brain are confined
inside the skull, the combined consciousness that allegedly emerges from them is
localized in space, just as we experience our own consciousness. The problem is that
there are no spatial boundaries at the most fundamental physical level. Elementary
subatomic particles are just patterns of excitation—‘ripples’—of spatially unbound
quantum fields that theoretically span the whole universe. There is nothing to the
particles but their respective quantum field, in the same way that there is nothing to
a ripple but the water where it ripples. The only thing that is supposedly truly real, in
and of itself, is the field. Therefore, if constitutive panpsychists want to circumvent
the hard problem of consciousness by attributing consciousness to the fundamental
building blocks of nature, they have to attribute it to the fields, not the particles. And
then they cannot account for the fact that our consciousnesses seem to be localized
in space and separate from one another.

Moreover, the combination problem faced by constitutive panpsychism is also


arguably as insoluble as the hard problem of consciousness [76, 77, 78]. Some argue
even that the alleged combination of fundamentally separate fields of subjectivity is
an altogether incoherent idea [79]. For all these reasons and some more, which are too
technical and detailed to discuss in this essay, constitutive panpsychism is not a
tenable alternative to mainstream physicalism.

This leaves us with idealism and its decomposition problem. If we start our theory
by postulating that there is only one, universal consciousness, and that everything
else in nature can be explained in terms of particular configurations and patterns of
excitation of this one consciousness, can we account for multiple, seemingly
separate minds such as yours and mine?

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 32


Many of the technical discussions about the three problems listed above—which
include the decomposition problem of idealism—are centered on whether they can
be solved in principle. In other words, experts devote a lot of time to trying to find out
whether it is at all coherent to even look for a theoretical solution to each of the
problems. The issue with this approach is that our own cognitive capabilities are not
a reliable basis for determining what can or cannot happen in nature. It is much more
conclusive to look to nature to see if nature herself has already ‘solved’ any of the
three problems. This way, even if we can’t understand precisely how the solution
works, we will know that there is a solution.

In this context, we must ask ourselves whether there are empirical instances of (a)
physical arrangements generating consciousness, (b) fundamentally separate minds
combining to form a higher-level but seemingly unitary mind, and (c) one mind
seemingly fragmenting itself into multiple centers of awareness. To answer any of
these questions in the affirmative, we must also avoid the fallacy of question-
begging, perhaps better known as circular reasoning.

For instance, if physicalists were to claim that each human brain is already an
empirical instance of matter generating mind, they would be begging the question:
since correlation does not necessarily imply causation, human consciousness can
only be said to be generated by human brains if physicalists presuppose
physicalism—the very point in contention—in their interpretation of the empirical
data. The same goes for constitutive panpsychism: human consciousness is only an
instance of combination if panpsychists presuppose panpsychism in their
interpretation of the empirical data.

Once question-begging is excluded, there are no empirical instances of solutions to


the hard problem of consciousness or the combination problem. There just is nothing
in nature that one could argue—without circular reasoning—is unquestionably an
instance of matter generating mind or minds combining to form higher-level minds.

What about idealism, then? Are there unquestionable empirical instances of mental
decomposition that do not beg the question? These instances must be ontology-
independent: it must be undeniable that what started as one mind seemingly
fragments itself into multiple, distinct centers of awareness regardless of one’s

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 33


preferred ontology. In other words, the instances must be such that even reasonable
physicalists and panpsychists would acknowledge that decomposition is happening.
Is there any such instance?

Indeed there is, and it is now very well documented. It is called ‘dissociation’ in
psychiatry. In an extreme form of dissociation—a condition called ‘Dissociative
Identity Disorder,’ or DID—what was originally one integrated consciousness
seemingly fragments itself into multiple, cognitively separate centers of awareness
[80, pp. 167-174 & 348-352]. Each fragment is technically called an ‘alter,’ for ‘alternate
personality.’ Alters may or may not be aware of each other’s existence, but they
always have private memories and idiosyncratic character traits. There is even
evidence for different alters having different physical conditions, such as diabetes
and hypertension. There is also evidence for alters being co-conscious, i.e.,
simultaneously conscious within the one host mind [80, pp. 317-322; 81, pp. 67-68].

Dissociation has literally blinding power. In a 2015 study in Germany, a woman with
a variety of alters—some of whom, peculiarly, claimed to be blind—was instrumented
with an EEG cap, so readings of her brain activity could be taken. When the host
personality or a sighted alter had executive control of her body, the researchers could
see normal brain activity in the woman’s visual cortex. But when a blind alter
assumed executive control, brain activity in the visual cortex would disappear, even
though the woman’s eyes were open [82]. This result not only conclusively proves the
existence of dissociation—no subject can fake blindness by voluntarily turning off
their visual cortex—but, importantly, shows that dissociation can be literally blinding.
Indeed, if a psychological condition can make you blind even when your eyes are
open to the world immediately surrounding you, it is no stretch to imagine that it
could also make other people’s thoughts—and whatever is going on in the galaxy of
Andromeda—inaccessible to you.

The hypothesis here is thus that we—along with every living being—are alters of one
universal consciousness. To substantiate this hypothesis, however, we need to
address three important questions regarding its consistency with empirical
observations.

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 34


First, living beings can be seen; they leave a footprint in their environment that can
be detected. If you were next to me right now, I would be able to detect your presence
through a variety of sensory modalities. Therefore, if living beings indeed correspond
to dissociative alters, then there must be something dissociation looks like when
observed from an outside perspective. And since human DID is the empirical
reference I am using to make my case, the question is whether the dissociative
processes in the brain of a DID patient have a recognizable image when measured
with a functional brain scanner.

Figure 7. The extrinsic appearance of dissociation when observed through fMRI. Source: PLOS
ONE 9(6): e98795 (2014). Reproduced here under a Creative Commons Attribution License.

The answer is, they do. In research completed in the Netherlands in 2014, Yolanda
Schlumpf and her team studied a group of patients diagnosed with DID. The controls
were a group of actors asked to pretend to themselves—a well-established acting
technique—to be in a dissociated state, while lying in a brain scanner. Brain activity
readings of both groups were then taken and compared. The researchers wanted to
know if, by looking at the brain scans alone, they could identify the DID group by
differentiating their scans from those of the control group. And sure enough, they
could [83]. There is indeed something dissociation looks like when observed from the
outside. It can be recognized by external measurement. See Figure 7.

Then the next question arises: people are simultaneously conscious and can interact
with one another while partaking in a common environment. We share the same

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 35


world, wherein we can see and shake hands with one another. Can the same be said
of the alters of a DID subject? Do they partake, while being co-conscious, in a
common mental environment wherein they interact with one another?

To answer this question properly, we have to make sure the analogy between
universal dissociation and human DID is applied and interpreted correctly. From the
point of view of a hypothetical universal consciousness, there is no external world,
since—ex hypothesi—the universal consciousness is all that exists. Therefore, to
compare universal dissociation to human DID, we have to ask not whether a person
with DID can see her alters ‘out there’ in the physical world, but whether the person’s
alters can interact within the mind of the person. In other words, we have to look at
the person’s endogenous, immersive experiences, such as dreams and schizophrenic
hallucinations. But since the clinical overlap between DID and schizophrenia is too
small to study, we must restrict ourselves to the dreams of DID patients. Can the
patients’ alters see and interact with one another when the person is dreaming?

Research done at Harvard Medical School has shown that this is precisely what
happens [84]. Here is an extract from a dream report of a DID patient. The woman in
question had a variety of alters, each going by a different name, such as Annie, Ann
and Jo:

The host personality, Sarah, remembered only that her dream from the
previous night involved hearing a girl screaming for help. Alter Annie, age
four, remembered a nightmare of being tied down naked and unable to cry
out as a man began to cut her vagina. Ann, age nine, dreamed of watching this
scene and screaming desperately for help (apparently the voice in the host's
dream). Teenage Jo dreamed of coming upon this scene and clubbing the little
girl's attacker over the head; in her dream he fell to the ground dead and she
left. In the dreams of Ann and Annie, the teenager with the club appeared,
struck the man to the ground but he arose and renewed his attack again. Four
year old Sally dreamed of playing with her dolls happily and nothing else. Both
Annie and Ann reported a little girl playing obliviously in the corner of the
room in their dreams. Although there was no definite abuser-identified alter
manifesting at this time, the presence at times of a hallucinated voice similar

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 36


to Sarah's uncle suggested there might be yet another alter experiencing the
dream from the attacker's vantage. [84, p. 171]

Clearly, several of the woman’s alters partook in the same dream—a common mental
environment created by the host’s dreaming mind—wherein they perceived and
interacted with one another, even clubbing one another over the head, while being
simultaneously conscious. This is entirely analogous to what, according to the
idealist hypothesis, is happening right now, in the waking world.

But there is a third and final question we must address, if the dissociation hypothesis
is to hold up to its own empirical implications. Before we state the question, though,
some preparation is required. Bear with me.

As discussed above, if living beings are dissociative alters of universal consciousness,


then their living bodies—biology, metabolism—is what the dissociative process looks
like from an outside perspective. This is a simple but critical point: the reason there
are, ordinarily, tight correlations between our conscious inner life and our patterns
of brain activity is that the brain, as part of the body, is part of what our conscious
inner life looks like when observed from an outside perspective. In other words,
instead of being the cause of our inner experiences, brain activity is an appearance, a
representation, an image of our inner experiences on the dashboard of perception;
brain activity is how our inner experiences present themselves to external
observation from second- and third-person perspectives.12 And that’s why there are,
ordinarily, correlations between experience and patterns of brain activity: the image

12
An important observation needs to be made at this point. By saying that our body is what our inner
experiences look like from the outside, I also include in these ‘inner experiences’ those that cannot be
accessed through explicit introspection, but which are nonetheless experienced in the bare
phenomenal sense. Indeed, to be able to introspectively report an experience, to others and even to
ourselves, we must both have the experience, in the phenomenal sense, and know that we have the
experience. This ‘knowing’ of an experience is an internal re-representation of the original qualities,
which requires focused attention and is not always cognitively possible. It entails more than just
phenomenal consciousness, but also what Jonathan Schooler has called ‘meta-consciousness,’ or
conscious meta-cognition [85]. This way, among the experiences whose extrinsic appearance is our
body are those that we cannot re-represent, or access meta-cognitively through introspection, and
therefore know nothing about. They are experiences that, although qualitatively felt, cannot be
reported even to ourselves. The body may also represent experiences that are altogether dissociated
from the executive ego and, therefore, remain ‘unconscious’ from the perspective of the ego. In
conclusion, the body represents more than just the experiences we—i.e., our egos—explicitly know we
have.

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 37


or appearance of a phenomenon correlates per force with the phenomenon it is an
image of.

Allow me to belabor this for emphasis: brain activity is part of the representation of
our inner experiences on the dashboard of dials we call perception. Do you see how it
all comes together? The thing-in-itself is our conscious inner life; that’s what has
standalone existence. Our physical body, on the other hand, is how this thing-in-itself
appears on the dashboard of dials if probed from outside its dissociative boundary.
As such, our physical body—the dashboard representation that arises from external
observation, or measurement, of our conscious inner life—has no standalone
existence; it is merely a representation of conscious processes. Consciousness is
primary, the body secondary.

Very well. Now, if our conscious inner life has an extrinsic appearance in the form of
a living body, then the inner life of universal consciousness must also have an
extrinsic appearance. Moreover, since the appearances in both cases are appearances
of mental processes, shouldn’t they bear at least some similarities? If our personal
mental processes look like biology, shouldn’t the transpersonal mental processes
underlying nature at large—short of its dissociative alters—also look something like
biology? By the logic of idealism, surely, there should be some similarities. But then,
are there? To answer this question correctly, we need a couple more considerations
to guide our logic.

Notice that most of our body is related to our need to perceive, interact with and
survive in an external environment: our arms and hands are meant to manipulate
the world around us; our digestive, respiratory and circulatory systems are meant to
extract energy from the environment; our perceptual systems are meant to collect
information about the environment; and so on. Only our brain correlates with purely
endogenous experiences, such as thoughts, emotions and insights.

Universal consciousness, however, has no environment; it’s all there is. All of its
hypothesized experiences are per force of an endogenous nature. So if we want to
know what nature at large should look like, under the logic of idealism, we need to
compare it to the brain alone, not to the rest of our body. Under idealism, the
inanimate universe—i.e., nature minus its alters—should look something like a

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 38


neuronal network. If you haven’t followed the logic here, consider re-reading the last
three paragraphs again, before you continue.

Neurons in a mouse’s brain Simulated image of the universe

Figure 8. The similarity between the cosmic web and biological neuronal networks. Source:
Mark Miller, Brandels University; Virgo Consortium for Cosmological Supercomputer
Simulations; www.visualcomplexity.com; The New York Times, 18 August 2006.

At first sight, the answer to this third question would appear to contradict idealism:
planets, moons and asteroids drifting about in space don’t look much like neuronal
networks. But the problem here is merely one of scale. If you could zoom all the way
into one of the bazillions of synaptic connections that form our brain, you would see
various types of neurotransmitter molecules drifting about in the synaptic cleft. That
wouldn’t look so different from astronomical bodies floating in space. The right
approach, thus, is to compare the inanimate universe as a whole, at its largest scales,
with whole neuronal networks. And, as it turns out, performing just such a
comparison, under strictly scientific conditions, has been a fashionable thing to do
in academia over the past decade or two. See Figure 8.

Research done at the University of California at San Diego, in 2012 [86], has shown
that “The structure of the universe and the laws that govern its growth may be more
similar than previously thought to the structure and growth of the human brain” [87].

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 39


There are no known reasons, under mainstream physicalism, for why this similarity
should exist at all. None of the known laws of physics accounts for it. The best
physicalists can say is that it is some kind of, well, cosmic coincidence (literally and
figuratively).

Figure 9. Maps of density contrast for slices of the cerebellum (top row), brain cortex (middle
row) and of the dark matter distribution of the cosmic web (lower row). Source: Front. Phys.
8:525731 (2020). Reproduced here under the Creative Commons CC-BY version 4.0 license.

More recent research, based on the broad arsenal of tools of information theory, has
shown that the similarities go even deeper than thought back in 2012: the
idiosyncrasies of the network topology of both the universe at large and biological
nervous systems are surprisingly similar [88, 89]. See Figure 9. In the words of the
researchers,

It is truly a remarkable fact that the cosmic web is more similar to the human
brain than it is to the interior of a galaxy … the human neuronal network and

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 40


the cosmic web of galaxies, when considered with the tools of information
theory, are strikingly similar. [89]

So much for form; how about function? Is there anything about how the inanimate
universe works that resembles the operation of neuronal networks? Surprisingly
enough, in a very recent paper, a team of renowned physicists have shown that the
operation of the laws of physics, computationally wise, could be regarded as a
neuronal network undergoing a learning process. In other words, the universe could
be said to be spontaneously learning—just as minds spontaneously learn—how to
behave [90].

So there you have it: surprising as it may seem to many, we do have rather significant
empirical reasons to answer the third question in the affirmative as well. Obvious
differences in scale and medium aside, there is an important sense in which
biological brains and the universe at large are similar, in terms of their respective
network structures and first-principles of operation. And there is nothing under
mainstream physicalism—or physics, for that matter—that could account for these
correspondences. In conclusion, the empirical implications of idealism—with
dissociation as the mechanism of mental decomposition—do hold up under
empirical scrutiny.

It is not by mere chance that the idealist hypothesis is empirically consistent along
all three independent lines of enquiry we have just discussed. It is not by mere chance
that (a) the inanimate universe, at its largest scales, follows the structure of neuronal
networks, and (b) the laws of physics can be modelled as learning neuronal
networks, and (c) dissociative processes have extrinsic appearances, and (d) alters
can experience the same dream from different points of view, while co-consciously
interacting with one another. Each of these empirical facts is, in and of itself, startling
enough. But when taken together, the notion that they are unrelated and
serendipitous seems to stretch credulity; the correspondences are too specific and
detailed. I thus submit to you that all four facts are true because the idealist
hypothesis is true; that’s the only overarching theoretical framework that makes
satisfying sense of all four facts together. As I repeat often in this essay, if you pay

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 41


attention, you will see that multiple, independent lines of evidence come together in
a manner that cannot be dismissed.

We originally set out to find out if there is a more coherent, empirically substantiated
alternative to mainstream physicalism that could account for (a) the empirical fact
that physical realism is false, (b) the empirical fact that, ordinarily, brain activity
correlates with inner experience and (c) the empirical fact that, extraordinarily, some
impairments or reductions of normal brain activity correlate with enriched, more
intense inner experience. We have found that idealism—with dissociation as the
mechanism of mental decomposition—is a much more plausible ontology that avoids
internal contradictions. We have also found that it can straightforwardly account for
empirical facts (a) and (b) above. What remains to be seen is whether it can also
account for empirical fact (c). I shall now attempt to show precisely that.

The weakening and end of dissociation

We have seen that the living body—with the brain as the locus of endogenous
mentation—is the extrinsic appearance of dissociative processes in a spatially
unbound field of subjectivity; a whirlpool in the stream of universal consciousness,
so to speak. Ordinary brain activity is part of what an alter of universal consciousness
looks like, when observed from across its dissociative boundary.

We can divide the mental processes of the alter into two categories: the dissociative
process itself and the mental contents trapped within the dissociation. The
dissociative process itself is what prevents me from knowing your thoughts and
what is going on in the galaxy of Andromeda. The contents of my dissociation, on the
other hand, are my personal memories, thoughts, insights, etc.—i.e., my private
conscious inner life. Both categories should have extrinsic appearances—i.e., both
categories should, at least in principle, appear to external observation as patterns of
brain activity. Any other expectation would be arbitrary.

Therefore, suppression or disruption of brain activity should, in principle, have two


types of effect, depending on what type of activity is actually suppressed: it may
quell mental contents of the alter or weaken the dissociative process itself. In the

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 42


first case, we will experience the effect as cognitive deficit, brain fog or amnesia. In
the second case, it stands to reason that we should experience an expansion of
awareness, for weakened dissociative boundaries become more porous, more
permeable, and mental processes unfolding outside the boundary should become
cognizable. Indeed, since dissociation is—by its very nature—a process of cognitive
restriction, the weakening of dissociation should have the opposite effect: cognitive
expansion or enrichment, the recovery of previously inaccessible memories, feelings
and insights, a broadening of experience and identity in general.

We do not yet know with precision—though the technical literature provides some
tantalizing clues in this regard—what kinds of brain activity correspond to the
dissociative process itself or to the contents of the dissociation. But it stands to
reason that some suppressions of brain activity should impair the dissociation itself,
while others—perhaps most of them—should impair the contents of the dissociation.
The first should lead to an expansion of consciousness while the latter to some form
of cognitive deficit. Is this what we observe empirically?

As discussed earlier, this is precisely what we observe empirically. While most


impairments of brain function lead to cognitive deficit, psychedelics, certain forms
of trance, brain hypoxia caused by partial strangulation, cardiac arrest, GLOC,
hyperventilation or physiological stress, brain damage associated with acquired
savant, feelings of self-transcendence or mystical experience, etc., cause an
enrichment of experience and a broadened sense of identity.

The reduction or impairment of normal brain activity associated with psychedelics,


trance, hypoxia, trauma, etc. is what a disruption of the dissociative process itself
looks like, when represented on the screen of perception (the dashboard of dials).
The end result is a more porous dissociative boundary and a transpersonal
reintegration of previously dissociated mental contents. This is why psychedelics
lead to some of the richest and most intense experiences of one’s life, at once alien
and familiar; why cardiac arrest can lead to life-changing NDEs; why teenagers
worldwide choose to run the fatal risks of partial strangulation in order to have a
‘high’; why pilots undergoing GLOC report “memorable dreams” when they were
thought to be unconscious; etc. These things aren’t unrelated or merely coincidental.

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 43


Instead, they constitute even more independent lines of empirical evidence coming
nicely together to substantiate idealism. Empirical facts hitherto considered
mysterious, counterintuitive, anomalous or even outright impossible under
mainstream physicalism become entirely natural and intuitive under idealism.

Now, if the living body is the image of dissociation, then death—the end of the living
body—is the end of dissociation. And here we finally address the question of
postmortem survival head on: death is not the end of consciousness, but merely the
end of a particular state or configuration of consciousness—namely, a dissociative
configuration. The end of this configuration is what the end of metabolism is an
appearance of on the dashboard of dials. Just as life is, quite literally, a state of mind,
death is a transition to another state of mind; one that does not correlate with the
localized appearance we call a living body, merely because it is no longer a
dissociative state.13

To understand this properly we need to inquire into our sense of identity. While
many of us conceptually identify with particular contents of consciousness—i.e., a
particular narrative of individual selfhood, such as a place and date of birth,
profession, political views, tastes, etc.—what analytic philosophy calls ‘core
subjectivity’ [91] is what we, when push comes to shove, really feel ourselves to be.
Core subjectivity is “ipseity, or I-ness, by which is meant an implicit sense of self
which serves as the dative ... of experience, namely, as that to whom things are given,
or disclosed, from a perspective” [91, p. 426]. You can visualize core subjectivity as
what would be left of your conscious inner life if you suddenly became completely
amnesic in a perfectly dark, quiet room, before the first new thought arose in your
mind. It is what would remain the same if tomorrow you were to magically acquire
someone else’s memories and character traits, without discontinuity in your
consciousness. It is that pure sense of I-ness, empty subjectivity, unencumbered by
particular narratives or thoughts. And it is the same in you, me and every living

13
Remember: under the logic of idealism, the body is what a dissociative process looks like. Without
dissociation, there is no body (a dead body is just an echo of something nature was previously doing
but no longer is). Without dissociation there is just the inanimate universe, which we could say is the
‘body’ of the non-dissociative, transpersonal processes underlying non-biological nature.

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 44


being, precisely because it is not differentiated. There is an important sense in which
core subjectivity is universal consciousness.

Core subjectivity is independent of dissociation and any other particular


configuration of consciousness, for it is what underlies them all. It is what is always
there, unperturbed, as the context within which particular experiences arise. I am
not saying this from a spiritual perspective—which is not my field anyway—but from
a purely analytic one. This follows from the same logic that accounts for the multiple
independent lines of empirical evidence discussed in detail in this essay.

Therefore, both the beginning and end of dissociation do not affect core subjectivity,
for both are just particular configurations of consciousness. If idealism is true, death,
by its very nature, leaves core subjectivity untouched and uninterrupted. From a
first-person perspective, death is thus witnessed. And this is the first sense—arguably
the only relevant one—in which, under idealism, postmortem survival is certain.

Yet, many of us conceptually identify not with our core subjectivity, but with
particular contents of consciousness. We think of ourselves as the person who was
born then and there, who does this or that for a living, who is married to this or that
other person, who has this or that political view, taste, disposition, etc. Is this
idiosyncratic narrative of self lost upon death—i.e., upon the end of dissociation?

Well, any narrative of personal selfhood is largely based on memory, in the sense that
it is a personal history. One could say that tastes and personality traits are parts of
our personal identity but do not depend on memory. Yet, is this really true? Although
most people don’t like Brussels sprouts, I happen to absolutely love them. If a person
who hates them were to magically acquire my memories—including the memory of
my boundless pleasure munching on Brussels sprouts with gusto—would they still
dislike them?14 Moreover, many of my character traits have changed with time and
maturity. My personality test results from 25 years ago were quite different from
today’s. Yet, I feel like I am still the same person. My character traits seem to be more
a part of my history—my memories—than an intrinsic part of my self. I can very easily

14
If you think they would, perhaps you are assuming that the memories transferred from me to the
other person aren’t complete, in the sense that they comprise the memory of the flavor of Brussels
sprouts but not the memory of my felt enjoyment.

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 45


imagine myself having totally different character traits while still being myself. For
people who score high in empathy, this is so self-evident as to be trivial. There is a
sense in which character traits are as incidental as a bad hair day.

Under idealism, insofar as our individuality is our memories, it isn’t lost upon death
either: the end of dissociation just makes our memories available—through re-
association—to a broader, transpersonal, experiential web of cognition; it doesn’t
eliminate them. As a matter of fact, all mental contents of the alter are released into
this broader cognitive context upon the dissolution of the dissociative boundary,
which had hitherto corralled them together; they ‘get out of jail,’ so to speak.

An analogy may help at this point. Ordinary dreams are subtle forms of dissociation:
during a dream, we identify only with our dream avatar, not with the rest of the
dream. We become dissociated from the parts of our mind that are generating the
rest of the dream, for we don’t think we are doing the streets, cars, buildings, trees or
even the other people in the dream. We think we are our dream avatar—a mere part
of what our mind is actually doing—which is immersed in the imagery of the dream.

When we wake up, however, the dissociation ends. We realize we were doing the
whole dream and our dream avatar, as a differentiated and semi-autonomous agent
within our mind, dies; quite literally. Our dream avatar is toast, gone at the very
moment we wake up. Yet we don’t mourn the death of our dream avatar, do we? Why
not? Because the only two things we instinctively care about remain: our core-
subjectivity is intact—it is the same whether we are dreaming or awake—and we can
still remember the dream, at least in principle, from the first-person perspective of
our avatar. In other words, even our avatar’s narrative of personal selfhood is
preserved, although we no longer identify with it. We remember that our dream
avatar was us, not us our dream avatar, so nothing is lost about either of them.

We have no reason to believe that the end of dissociation impairs memory; if


anything, the opposite is more plausible through cognitive re-associations. DID
patients who reintegrate their alters have, at least in principle, the memories of all
reintegrated alters. They remember what it was like to ‘be’ each dissociative alter,
just as we remember what it was like to ‘be’ a dream avatar. Former DID patients
don’t mourn the death of their alters either, for everything that was relevant about

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 46


them—core subjectivity and memories—remains. This is the second sense in which,
under idealism, postmortem survival is certain.

It is important to realize that these considerations are purely analytic, not spiritual
or intuitive. They are derived from reasoning and evidence, not direct experience.
Therefore, we can take their underlying reasoning apart so as to dig into its
implications more explicitly than would otherwise be possible.

For instance, although idealism implies postmortem survival, it doesn’t imply that
our dead self is going to some ‘otherworld.’ In fact, under idealism we stay right here,
in this world, as it is in itself. This is very important to realize. Idealism postulates no
other world. The only difference death makes is this: instead of observing this world
through the intermediation of the dashboard of dials we call physicality—the
dashboard being part of the survival kit of the alter—we reintegrate into this world
as it is in itself. We ‘become’—in scare quotes because we, of course, never cease to be
what we really are—the very world we merely inhabited during life. In other words,
our point of view—along with our memories—just moves to the other side of the
dashboard from the one we occupied during life. Upon death, we can experience this
world directly, without the intermediation of dials. That’s all there is to it.

Allow me to belabor this point, since it differs rather significantly from vulgar
religious expectations. Upon death, people go nowhere. We all stay in this world, but
on the other side of the instrument panel we call physicality. It’s the difference
between (a) sitting inside the cockpit and looking at the dashboard and (b) flying
outside the metal skin of the airplane and feeling the air, clouds, rain and lightning
directly. In both cases the world is the same, just experienced differently.

Upon death we no longer appear as discrete, discernible entities because we are no


longer dissociated (discrete organisms are the appearance of dissociation, so they
cannot remain when the respective dissociation ends, for the same reason that
flames cannot remain once combustion ends). But everything that ever mattered
about us—our core subjectivity, our memories, the entire history and quality of our
lives as experienced from our first-person perspective—is still in this world, as the
world is in and of itself.

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 47


You might then ask: shouldn’t the living then still be able to discern the presence of
the dead, since the latter are still in this world together with the living? Not
necessarily, because of a cognitive dynamic akin to physical dilution. While a single
drop of dye is clearly discernible when trapped in a dropper, it isn’t so in the ocean,
even though the entire substance of the drop is still there and nothing has
disappeared. Similarly, the mental processes that constitute the inner life of a person,
when circumscribed by a dissociative boundary, are clearly discernible on the
dashboard of perception. But upon the end of dissociation, when the dissociative
boundary unravels, they become dispersed in the broader cognitive space of
transpersonal associations that constitutes the world-in-itself. Everything about the
dead is still in the world, this world, but no longer discernible as a discrete entity, just
as a drop of dye is not discernible in the ocean. This is analogous to what in quantum
physics is called ‘decoherence.’

Moreover, what the dead bring with them upon death—the memories and insights of
a lifetime—changes the whole world at some level, quite literally, even though this
change—given the relative scale of the universe in relation to a person—is far from
being even remotely discernible on the screen of perception. This, under idealism, is
what death means.

Now, I am not a counselor, and my argument aims not at comfort but at truth. That
said, it would be naïve of me to think that comfort and reassurance aren’t important
motivations for interest in postmortem survival. This is only human and, as someone
who has also lost loved ones, I empathize with it. So I will share now, for what it is
worth, my personal way of living according to the ideas I am arguing for in this essay.

Just as a fully diluted drop of dye is spread everywhere in the ocean, to me our
ancestors are ‘behind’ every rock, every cloud, every molecule of air I inhale; just “on
the other side of them from me,” as Owen Barfield put it [92, p. 42]. I touch them when
I step barefoot on the ground or run my fingers along the side of a mountain. I see
them when I look up to the sky on a clear night. I am immersed in them when I dive
into the sea. They touch my skin at all times, for they are the world that envelops me;
literally. And their whole lives, as they have experienced them, are also the world I
inhabit. I may not live their stories, but I live in their stories. Their past is the

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 48


scaffolding of my present. The questions they’ve left unanswered are the air from
which I draw my life’s energy. And I, too, one day, will be an integral part of the world
in which future generations will live; literally. The questions I leave unanswered will
be the air they breathe, the ones I did answer the ground on which they take their
steps. And so nature goes, on and on, dynamically, ever changing, but never losing a
single bit of itself.

What about psi?

Reports of telepathic, mediumistic communication with the dead, as well as of


reincarnation—insofar as they carry credibility—seem to suggest that the dead
continue to exist not only as core subjectivity and memories, but also as
differentiated, individual agents. Can idealism accommodate this evidence while
denying that individual agency—i.e., dissociation—persists upon bodily death?

First of all, let me acknowledge that, stimulating to the popular imagination as they
are, many anecdotal reports of psi phenomena can be dismissed for a variety of
trivial reasons. I also acknowledge, however, that the same cannot be said of much
of the scientific study of psi. As a matter of fact, good psi research—I think of Dean
Radin’s work at IONS and the work done at the Department of Perceptual Studies at
the University of Virginia, for instance—tends to be far superior, in terms of
methodological rigor, experimental design and execution, as well as the rather
conservative character of the accompanying statistical analyses, to most
mainstream scientific research [93]. This happens because, since psi seems to
contradict mainstream physicalism, these studies are designed and executed so as to
withstand particularly severe scrutiny.

Yet, precisely because they contradict the mainstream paradigm, psi phenomena are
still dismissed even when the research that indicates their existence is more rigorous
and reliable than most mainstream research. Why? The reason is well-known to
history: never is a reigning paradigm abandoned because of ‘mere’ empirical
evidence that contradicts it; it is only ever replaced with another paradigm—another
hypothesis about what nature is—that happens to accommodate the evidence better
[53]. As such, for as long as there is no widely recognized alternative to mainstream

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 49


physicalism—and by alternative I don’t mean a religious worldview, but an analytic,
scientific one—‘mere’ evidence won’t defeat it.

And here is where idealism, particularly the analytic idealism I have been arguing for
in this essay, can play a decisive role in our views regarding postmortem survival.
Not only is it backed by several independent lines of mainstream evidence, but it also
makes sense of otherwise anomalous psi evidence; it provides natural space in a
rational, coherent theoretical framework to accommodate the observations in
question.

So the relationship between idealism and the evidence for psi phenomena is
synergistic: while idealism provides a framework to accommodate the evidence and
prevent it from being dismissed on merely theoretical grounds, evidence for psi also
provides substantiation for idealism insofar as the latter predicts its existence. The
question thus is: can idealism accommodate psi? Does it predict the existence of psi
phenomena while denying that personal agency—i.e., dissociation—persists after
death?

Let us first consider telepathy. Under idealism, reality consists of excitations of a


spatially unbound field of subjectivity—i.e., one universal mind. Therefore, what
needs to be explicitly accounted for is why we can’t read other people’s thoughts all
the time; after all, we are all—ex hypothesi—part of the same mind. Idealism accounts
for this by inferring that dissociative processes spontaneously arise in the universal
mind. But no process in nature is perfect or ideal. Combustion never burns
everything there is to burn. Rain fall never precipitates all air humidity. And so it is
not only conceivable, but expectable, that dissociation won’t prevent all cognitive
traffic from crossing dissociative boundaries. That telepathy should occur now and
then, especially under conditions related to impaired metabolism (i.e., weakened
dissociation), is indeed a prediction of idealism. As such, reliable empirical evidence
for telepathy can be legitimately construed as evidence for idealism. And without
idealism to couch it in a theoretical framework, the evidence is neutered.

Let us now consider evidence of reincarnation [94], which seems to most directly
contradict the idealist notion that death is the end of individual agency. Here is a
brief thought experiment: imagine that you are a particularly apt telepath and can

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 50


access all my memories, episodic and otherwise. As a matter of fact, you can do a full
download of my memories for your own private use. This would mean that you can
recall all my knowledge and experiences from my first-person perspective, as if you
had been me. If a researcher would then ask you questions about knowledge that
only I could possibly have had, you would be able to answer all questions not only
accurately, but also from my point of view. Assuming that I am already dead at that
point, the researcher would be liable to interpret your answers as a case of
reincarnation; never mind the fact that no individual agent transferred itself from
me to you, only my memories did.

As we’ve seen above, when a person dies the contents of their dissociation are
released into the broader, transpersonal web of cognitive activity that constitutes the
world as it is in itself. It is conceivable that newly emerging alters, with dissociative
boundaries not yet sealed, could incorporate those contents in the process of their
development. From a first-person perspective, this would literally mean having some
of a dead person’s memories. Yet, there would be no differentiated agent
reincarnating in the new alter; only a form of memory osmosis. I submit that,
empirically, so-called reincarnation cases are indistinguishable from what I am
proposing here.

I understand that many cases of seeming reincarnation are associated with sudden,
even violent death on the part of the supposedly reincarnated agent. This means that
the dead person’s last memories have particularly high emotional charge. We know
from clinical psychology that emotionally charged mental contents are more
‘reactive,’ in the sense that they are prone to forming complexes through cognitive
associations and attaching themselves to other mental contents. In plain language,
psychological trauma translates into paranoia, compulsive brooding, fantasizing and
memory revisionism, evokes all kinds of other emotions and generally permeates all
facets of an individual’s mental life. Under idealism, it is thus entirely reasonable
that, when the emotionally charged memories of a violent death are freshly released
into the transpersonal cognitive context that constitutes our surrounding
environment, they should also be more ‘reactive’ and attach themselves to new alters
in development—i.e., fetuses, babies and toddlers. Even cases of inherited scars can,
in principle, be made sense of in this manner: as we’ve seen earlier, under idealism

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 51


the entire body is the extrinsic appearance of an alter’s mental contents. Thus, it
stands to reason that memories trapped within a forming alter’s dissociative
boundary should also be capable of presenting themselves somatically. As a matter
of fact, I submit that the idealist notion of the body as an appearance of mental
contents is the only hypothesis that explains birthmarks in the context of alleged
reincarnation; for how could a non-physical agent that merely inhabits a body not
only carry over, but also imprint bodily characteristics?

For all intents and purposes, I believe ‘reincarnation’ does happen. But the underlying
mechanism is not quite what the word suggests. For ‘reincarnation’ presupposes a
certain hypothesis about the cause of the phenomenon; namely, that some form of
non-physical, individual agency moves from one body to another, like a Hermit crab
from one shell to another. There is, however, a simpler way to account for the
evidence in a theoretically coherent manner: felt and embodied memories are indeed
transferred, not agency.

A third well-known psi phenomenon is that of mediumship. It entails what is


ordinarily described as communication between a living medium and a dead person.
I confess to having severe prejudice against claims of mediumship, but I shall try to
remain objective. The argument for the reality of mediumship is that the medium
sometimes knows things that only the dead could have known. Therefore—or so the
argument goes—the dead must still exist as individual agents in the afterlife, and
from there communicate the corresponding information to the living medium.

Just as in the case of reincarnation, I submit that there is a simpler explanation for
veridical mediumistic reports: the medium—someone with a naturally porous
dissociative boundary, or who has learned how to deliberately influence the
boundary through trance [61]—picks up, from the immediate cognitive surroundings
that constitute our world as it is in itself, felt memories released into it by the dead.

This is even more plausible if one takes into account that telepathy—a psi
phenomenon so common as to be banal—involves the penetration of two dissociative
boundaries, for there are always at least two people involved. But to pick up on what
is available in our transpersonal cognitive surroundings, a skilled medium only
needs to weaken his or her own dissociative boundary. As a matter of fact, this

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 52


suggests a reason for why mediums don’t seem as capable of reading the minds of
the living as they are the dead’s.

Because—unlike mainstream physicalism—idealism can accommodate and make


sense of telepathy, ‘reincarnation’ and mediumship, insofar as such psi phenomena
are rigorously verified the corresponding empirical evidence further substantiates
idealism. In return, idealism provides a coherent theoretical framework to explain
the evidence, thereby facilitating its acceptance.

Conclusions

That the death of the body implies, prima facie, the end of consciousness
surreptitiously presupposes the theoretical assumptions of mainstream physicalism.
Those assumptions do not have an empirical basis if one judiciously eliminates
question-begging from one’s interpretation of the facts. Therefore, postmortem
survival, objectively speaking, isn’t an extraordinary hypothesis that requires
extraordinary evidence; it is instead a perfectly plausible and rational conjecture.

Indeed, decades of progressively refined and repeatedly replicated experimental


results in foundations of physics have refuted physical realism: physical entities
have no standalone existence and, as such, are merely a superficial appearance of a
deeper, fundamental but nonphysical layer of reality. This alone refutes mainstream
physicalism and its implications regarding postmortem survival.

Moreover, short of fanciful—if fashionable—flights of conceptual abstraction, once


matter is proven to be derivative only mind can be fundamental in nature. Indeed,
mind is the only type of existent—Oussia—we are directly acquainted with;
everything else is theory. Therefore, it is eminently reasonable—arguably even
logically inevitable—to suppose that the deeper layer of reality underlying
physicality is mental in essence. An objective world constituted of transpersonal
mental processes circumvents the so-called ‘hard problem of consciousness’
altogether, allowing us to make progress in our understanding of the nature of
reality.

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 53


In addition, further independent lines of mainstream evidence prove that the
physical world we perceive is but an internal, encoded cognitive representation; a
dashboard of indicators that provides us with useful information about the world,
but which isn’t the world. Because these internal representations are encoded, living
organisms can place an upper bound on the dispersion of their inner states and
thereby maintain their structural integrity. Moreover, if these internal
representations weren’t encoded, we now know that evolution by natural selection
would have driven us swiftly to extinction. All this, although entirely independent
from the reasoning underlying the refutation of physical realism, leads nonetheless
to the same conclusion: what we call the physical world is not what the world is in
and of itself; instead, it is merely a superficial, encoded representation thereof. The
world in itself is not physical; it can only be mental.

As if all this weren’t enough, multiple independent lines of evidence in neuroscience


of consciousness show repeatable correlations between certain impairments or
reductions of normal brain activity and enrichment or intensification of experience.
This cannot be accounted for under mainstream physicalism; it can only be
accounted for by the idealist hypothesis that our conscious inner lives—our very
minds—are dissociative processes in a spatially unbound field of subjectivity. Certain
disruptions or reductions of brain activity are simply what an abating of the
dissociation looks like when represented on our internal dashboard of dials.
Suggestive evidence regarding dissociative dream states, as well as the structural
and functional similarities between the physical universe and neuronal networks,
provide even more empirical corroboration to the idealist account of the facts.
Idealism not only makes sense of otherwise inexplicable evidence, if also dovetails
perfectly with the experimental refutation of physical realism: the universal field of
subjectivity wherein dissociation takes place is the fundamental level of reality
underlying physicality, and of which physicality is the mere appearance upon
measurement.

Vast amounts of empirical data considered anomalous and confounding under


mainstream physicalism, but nonetheless accepted by mainstream science, can be
elegantly—and exclusively—accounted for under an idealist ontology whereby
dissociation is the mechanism of mental decomposition. A direct implication of this

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 54


view—and therefore of the data itself—is that the death of the body represents merely
the end of a dissociative process, not the end of consciousness. Everything that
matters about who we are—our core subjectivity and our personal memories—is left
untouched by bodily death. Instead of disappearing, our conscious inner lives are
reintegrated into a broader, transpersonal cognitive context, thereby effectively
expanding.

It is thus no exaggeration to claim that the postmortem survival of human


consciousness is all but confirmed by mainstream experimental science, provided
that one is rational and objective enough to acknowledge the logical implications of
the evidence. Coming to terms with this fact is one of the greatest challenges our
culture will face in the decades to come.

References

[1] Friston, K. (2013). Life as we know it. Journal of the Royal Society Interface, 10
(86): 20130475.
[2] Friston, K., Sengupta, B. and Auletta, G. (2014). Cognitive dynamics: From
attractors to active inference. Proceedings of the IEEE, 102 (4): 427-445.
[3] Hoffman, D. D. (2009). The interface theory of perception: Natural selection
drives true perception to swift extinction. In: Dickinson, S. et al. (eds.). Object
Categorization: Computer and Human Vision Perspectives. Cambridge, UK:
Cambridge University Press.
[4] Hoffman, D. D. and Singh, M. (2012). Computational evolutionary perception.
Perception, 41 (9): 1073-1091.
[5] Hoffman, D. D., Singh, M. and Prakash, C. (2015). The interface theory of
perception. Psychonomic Bulletin & Review 22: 1480–1506.
https://doi.org/10.3758/s13423-015-0890-8
[6] Prakash, C., Stephens, K. D., Hoffman, D. D. et al. (2020). Fitness beats truth in
the evolution of perception. Acta Biotheoretica. https://doi.org/10.1007/s10441-
020-09400-0
[7] Kant, I. (1781 ® 2008). The Critique of Pure Reason. New York, NY: Penguin.

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 55


[8] Schopenhauer, A. (1819 ® 1969). The World as Will and Representation. New
York, NY: Dover.
[9] Chalmers, D. (2003). Consciousness and its place in nature. In: Stich, S. &
Warfield, T. (eds.). The Blackwell Guide to Philosophy of Mind. Malden, MA:
Blackwell.
[10] Chalmers, D. (2006). Strong and weak emergence. In: Davies, P. and Clayton, P.
(eds.). The Re-Emergence of Emergence. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
[11] Aspect, A., Grangier, P. and Roger, G. (1981). Experimental tests of realistic local
theories via Bell’s theorem. Physical Review Letters, 47 (7): 460-463.
[12] Aspect, A., Dalibard, J. and Roger, G. (1982). Experimental test of Bell’s
inequalities using time-varying analyzers. Physical Review Letters, 49 (25): 1804-
1807.
[13] Aspect, A., Grangier, P. and Roger, G. (1982). Experimental realization of
Einstein-Podolsky-Rosen-Bohm gedankenexperiment: A new violation of Bell’s
inequalities. Physical Review Letters, 49 (2): 91-94.
[14] Weihs, G. et al. (1998). Violation of Bell’s inequality under strict Einstein locality
conditions. Physical Review Letters, 81 (23): 5039-5043.
[15] Tittel, W. et al. (1998). Violation of Bell inequalities by photons more than 10 km
apart. Physical Review Letters, 81 (17): 3563-3566.
[16] Lapkiewicz, R. et al. (2011). Experimental non-classicality of an indivisible
quantum system. Nature, 474: 490-493.
[17] Ma, X-S et al. (2013). Quantum erasure with causally disconnected choice.
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences of the Unites States of America,
110 (4): 1221-1226.
[18] Manning, A. G. et al. (2015). Wheeler’s delayed-choice gedanken experiment
with a single atom. Nature Physics, 11: 539-542.
[19] Hensen, B. et al. (2015). Loophole-free Bell inequality violation using electron
spins separated by 1.3 kilometres. Nature, 526: 682-686.
[20] BIG Bell Test Collaboration, The (2018). Challenging local realism with human
choices. Nature, 557: 212-216. https://doi.org/10.1038/s41586-018-0085-3.
[21] Ananthaswamy, A. (2018). Closed Loophole Confirms the Unreality of the
Quantum World. Quanta Magazine, July 25.

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 56


https://www.quantamagazine.org/closed-loophole-confirms-the-unreality-of-
the-quantum-world-20180725/
[22] Ananthaswamy, A. (2011). Quantum magic trick shows reality is what you
make it. New Scientist, June 22.
https://www.newscientist.com/article/dn20600-quantum-magic-trick-shows-
reality-is-what-you-make-it/.
[23] Gröblacher, S. et al. (2007). An experimental test of non-local realism. Nature,
446: 871-875.
[24] Romero, J. et al. (2010). Violation of Leggett inequalities in orbital angular
momentum subspaces. New Journal of Physics, 12: 123007.
http://iopscience.iop.org/article/10.1088/1367-2630/12/12/123007.
[25] Proietti, M. (2019). Quantum physics: our study suggests objective reality
doesn’t exist. The Conversation, 14 November.
https://theconversation.com/quantum-physics-our-study-suggests-objective-
reality-doesnt-exist-126805.
[26] Proietti, M. et al. (2019). Experimental rejection of observer-independence in
the quantum world. arXiv:1902.05080 [quant-ph].
https://arxiv.org/abs/1902.05080v1.
[27] Cartwright, J. (2007). Quantum physics says goodbye to reality. IOP Physics
World, April 20.
http://physicsworld.com/cws/article/news/2007/apr/20/quantum-physics-
says-goodbye-to-reality.
[28] Bohm, D. (1952). A suggested interpretation of the quantum theory in terms of
“hidden” variables. I. Physical Review, 85: 166-179.
[29] Bohm, D. (1952). A suggested interpretation of the quantum theory in terms of
“hidden” variables. II. Physical Review, 85: 180-193.
[30] Streater, R. F. (2007). Lost Causes in and beyond Physics. Berlin, Germany:
Springer-Verlag.
[31] Motl, L. (2009). Bohmists & segregation of primitive and contextual
observables. The Reference Frame, January 23.
https://motls.blogspot.com/2009/01/bohmists-segregation-of-primitive-
and.html.

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 57


[32] Wolchover, N. (2018). Famous experiment dooms alternative to quantum
weirdness. Quanta Magazine, October11.
https://www.quantamagazine.org/famous-experiment-dooms-pilot-wave-
alternative-to-quantum-weirdness-20181011/.
[33] Kastrup, B. (2018). Thinking outside the quantum box. Scientific American,
February 16. https://blogs.scientificamerican.com/observations/thinking-
outside-the-quantum-box/.
[34] Kastrup, B. (2018). Should quantum anomalies make us rethink reality?
Scientific American, April 19.
https://blogs.scientificamerican.com/observations/should-quantum-
anomalies-make-us-rethink-reality/.
[35] Kastrup, B., Stapp, H. P. and Kafatos, M. C. (2018). Coming to grips with the
implications of quantum mechanics. Scientific American, May 29.
https://blogs.scientificamerican.com/observations/coming-to-grips-with-the-
implications-of-quantum-mechanics/.
[36] Kastrup, B. (2019). The universe as cosmic dashboard. Scientific American, May
24. https://blogs.scientificamerican.com/observations/the-universe-as-cosmic-
dashboard/.
[37] Linde, A. (1998). Universe, Life, Consciousness. A paper delivered at the Physics
and Cosmology Group of the “Science and Spiritual Quest” program of the
Center for Theology and the Natural Sciences (CTNS), Berkeley, California.
http://web.stanford.edu/~alinde/SpirQuest.doc.
[38] Joos, E. (2006). The emergence of classicality from quantum theory. In P.
Clayton & P. Davies (Eds), The re-emergence of emergence: The emergentist
hypothesis from science to religion. Oxford, England, UK: Oxford University
Press.
[39] Rovelli, C. (1996). Relational quantum mechanics. International Journal of
Theoretical Physics, 35 (8): 1637-1678.
[40] Rovelli, C. (2021). Helgoland. New York, NY: Penguin.
[41] Dresler, M. et al. (2011). Dreamed movement elicits activation in the
sensorimotor cortex. Current Biology, 21 (21): 1833-1837.

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 58


[42] Hamzelou, J. (2011). Dreams read by brain scanner for the first time. New
Scientist, 27 October. https://www.newscientist.com/article/dn20934-dreams-
read-by-brain-scanner-for-the-first-time/.
[43] Horikawa, T. et al. (2013). Neural decoding of visual imagery during sleep.
Science, 340 (6132): 639-642.
[44] Costandi, M. (2013). Brain scans decode dream content: Researchers have
decoded the content of people’s dreams using brain scanning technology. The
Guardian, April 5.
https://www.theguardian.com/science/neurophilosophy/2013/apr/05/brain-
scans-decode-dream-content.
[45] Griffiths, R. R. et al. (2006). Psilocybin can occasion mystical-type experiences
having substantial and sustained personal meaning and spiritual significance.
Psychopharmacology, 187 (3): 268-283.
[46] Griffiths, R. R. et al. (2008). Mystical-type experiences occasioned by psilocybin
mediate the attribution of personal meaning and spiritual significance 14
months later. Journal of Psychopharmacology, 22 (6): 621-632.
https://doi.org/10.1177/0269881108094300.
[47] Carhart-Harris, RL et al. (2012). Neural correlates of the psychedelic state as
determined by fMRI studies with psilocybin. Proceedings of the National
Academy of Sciences of the United States of America, 109 (6): 2138-2143.
[48] Koch, C. (2012). This is your brain on drugs. Scientific American Mind, May 1st.
https://www.scientificamerican.com/article/this-is-your-brain-on-drugs/.
[49] Carhart-Harris, RL et al. (2016). Neural correlates of the LSD experience
revealed by multimodal neuroimaging. Proceedings of the National Academy of
Sciences of the United States of America (PNAS Early Edition), doi:
10.1073/pnas.1518377113.
[50] Palhano-Fontes, F. et al. (2015). The psychedelic state induced by ayahuasca
modulates the activity and connectivity of the default mode network. PLoS
ONE, 10 (2): e0118143.
[51] Lewis, CR et al. (2017). Two dose investigation of the 5-HT-agonist psilocybin
on relative and global cerebral blood flow. NeuroImage, July, doi:
10.1016/j.neuroimage.2017.07.020.

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 59


[52] Muthukumaraswamy, SD et al. (2013). Broadband Cortical Desynchronization
Underlies the Human Psychedelic State. The Journal of Neuroscience, 33 (38)
15171-15183. https://doi.org/10.1523/JNEUROSCI.2063-13.2013.
[53] Kuhn, T. S. (2012). The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago, IL: The
University of Chicago Press.
[54] Kastrup, B. and Kelly, E. F. (2018). Misreporting and confirmation bias in
psychedelic research. Scientific American, September 3rd.
https://blogs.scientificamerican.com/observations/misreporting-and-
confirmation-bias-in-psychedelic-research/.
[55] Carhart-Harris, R. L. (2018). The entropic brain – revisited. Neuropharmacology,
142: 167-178. https://doi.org/10.1016/j.neuropharm.2018.03.010.
[56] Strassman, R. (2001). DMT: The Spirit Molecule. Rochester, VT: Park Street Press.
[57] Strassman, R. et al. (2008). Inner Paths to Outer Space. Rochester, VT: Park Street
Press.
[58] Branch, M. N. (2019). The “Reproducibility Crisis:” Might the Methods Used
Frequently in Behavior-Analysis Research Help? Perspectives on Behavior
Science, 42(1): 77–89.
[59] Colquhoun, D. (2016). The problem with p-values. AEON, October 11.
https://aeon.co/essays/it-s-time-for-science-to-abandon-the-term-statistically-
significant.
[60] Woolston, C. (2015). Psychology journal bans P values. Nature, 519 (9).
https://doi.org/10.1038/519009f.
[61] Peres, J. et al. (2012). Neuroimaging during trance state: A contribution to the
study of dissociation. PLoS ONE, 7 (11): e49360.
[62] DiSalvo, D. (2012). When you inject spirit mediums’ brains with radioactive
chemicals, strange things happen. Forbes, November 18.
http://www.forbes.com/sites/daviddisalvo/2012/11/18/when-you-inject-spirit-
mediums-brains-with-radioactive-chemicals-some-really-strange-things-
happen/.
[63] Urgesi, C. et al. (2010). The spiritual brain: Selective cortical lesions modulate
human self-transcendence. Neuron, 65: 309-319.

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 60


[64] Whinnery, J. and Whinnery, A. (1990). Acceleration-induced loss of
consciousness: A review of 500 episodes. Archives of Neurology, 47 (7): 764-776.
[65] Lommel, P. van et al. (2001). Near-death experience in survivors of cardiac
arrest: a prospective study in the Netherlands. The Lancet, 358 (9298): 2039-
2045.
[66] Treffert, D. (2006). Extraordinary People: Understanding Savant Syndrome.
Omaha, NE: iUniverse, Inc.
[67] Treffert, D. (2009). The savant syndrome: An extraordinary condition. A
synopsis: Past, present, future. Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B,
364 (1522): 1351-1357.
[68] Lythgoe, M. et al. (2005). Obsessive, prolific artistic output following
subarachnoid hemorrhage. Neurology, 64 (2): 397-398.
[69] Piore, A. (2013). The genius within. Popular Science, March: 46-53.
[70] Cristofori, I. et al. (2016). Neural correlates of mystical experience.
Neuropsychologia, 80: 212-220.
[71] Neal, R. M. (2008). The Path to Addiction: “And Other Troubles We Are Born to
Know.” Bloomington, IN: AuthorHouse.
[72] Rhinewine, J. P. and Williams, OJ (2007). Holotropic breathwork: The potential
role of a prolonged, voluntary hyperventilation procedure as an adjunct to
psychotherapy. The Journal of Alternative and Complementary Medicine, 13 (7):
771-776.
[73] Eliade, M. (1965). Rites and Symbols of Initiation: The Mysteries of Birth and
Rebirth (Volume 10). New York, NY: Harper & Row.
[74] Chalmers, D. (2016). The combination problem for panpsychism. In: Brüntrup,
G. & Jaskolla, L. (eds.). Panpsychism. Oxford, UK: Oxford University Press.
[75] Kastrup, B. (2020). Will We Ever Understand Consciousness? The Institute of
Art and Ideas News, January 8. https://iai.tv/articles/will-we-ever-understand-
consciousness-auid-1288.
[76] Carruthers, P. and Schechter, E. (2006). Can panpsychism bridge the
explanatory gap? Journal of Consciousness Studies, 13 (10-11): 32-39.
[77] Goff, P. (2006). Experiences don’t sum. Journal of Consciousness Studies, 13 (10-
11): 53-61.

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 61


[78] Goff, P. (2009). Why Panpsychism doesn’t help us explain consciousness.
Dialectica, 63 (3): 289-311.
[79] Coleman, S. (2014). The real combination problem: Panpsychism, micro-
subjects, and emergence. Erkenntnis, 79 (1): 19-44.
[80] Kelly, E. F. et al. (2009). Irreducible Mind: Toward a Psychology for the 21st
Century. Lanham, MD: Rowman & Littlefield.
[81] Braude, S. (1995). First Person Plural: Multiple Personality and the Philosophy of
Mind. New York, NY: Routledge.
[82] Strasburger, H. and Waldvogel, B. (2015). Sight and blindness in the same
person: Gating in the visual system. PsyCh Journal, 4 (4): 178-185.
[83] Schlumpf, Y. et al. (2014). Dissociative part-dependent resting-state activity in
Dissociative Identity Disorder: A controlled fMRI perfusion study. PloS ONE, 9,
doi:10.1371/journal.pone.0098795.
[84] Barrett, D. (1994). Dreams in dissociative disorders. Dreaming, 4 (3): 165-175.
[85] Schooler, J. (2002). Re-representing consciousness: dissociations between
experience and meta-consciousness. Trends in Cognitive Science, 6 (8): 339-344.
[86] Krioukov, D. et al. (2012). Network cosmology. Scientific Reports, 2,
doi:10.1038/srep00793.
[87] Zverina, J. (2012). Human Brain, Internet, and Cosmology: Similar Laws at
Work? UC San Diego News Center, November 19.
https://ucsdnews.ucsd.edu/pressrelease/human_brain_internet_and_cosmolog
y_similar_laws_at_work.
[88] Vazza, F. and Feletti, A. (2020). The Quantitative Comparison Between the
Neuronal Network and the Cosmic Web. Frontiers in Physics, 8: 525713.
https://www.frontiersin.org/articles/10.3389/fphy.2020.525731/full.
[89] Vazza, F. and Feletti, A. (2017). The strange similarity of neuron and galaxy
networks: Your life’s memories could, in principle, be stored in the universe’s
structure. Nautilus, July 20. http://nautil.us/issue/50/emergence/the-strange-
similarity-of-neuron-and-galaxy-networks.
[90] Alexander, S. et al. (2021). The Autodidactic Universe. arXiv:2104.03902 [hep-th].
https://arxiv.org/abs/2104.03902.

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 62


[91] Shani, I. (2015). Cosmopsychism: A holistic approach to the metaphysics of
experience. Philosophical Papers, 44 (3): 389-437.
[92] Barfield, O. (2011). Saving the Appearances: A Study in Idolatry. Oxford, UK:
Barfield Press.
[93] Cardeña, E. (2018). The experimental evidence for parapsychological
phenomena: A review. American Psychologist, 73 (5): 663-677.
[94] Tucker, J. (2021). Before: Children’s Memories of Previous Lives. New York, NY:
St. Martin's Essentials.

Copyright © 2021 by Essentia Foundation 63

You might also like