72TaxLRev235 Taxation and Democracy
72TaxLRev235 Taxation and Democracy
72TaxLRev235 Taxation and Democracy
Citations:
-- Your use of this HeinOnline PDF indicates your acceptance of HeinOnline's Terms and
Conditions of the license agreement available at
https://heinonline.org/HOL/License
-- The search text of this PDF is generated from uncorrected OCR text.
-- To obtain permission to use this article beyond the scope of your license, please use:
Copyright Information
Taxation and Democracy
WOLFGANG SCHON*
INTRODUCTION
* Director, Max Planck Institute for Tax Law and Public Finance, Honorary Professor,
Munich University, Global Professor of Tax Law, NYU School of Law. This Article is an
enlarged version of the author's Max Weber Lecture given at the European University
Institute on October 11, 2017; it has further been presented at the conference on tax
competition celebrating the Seventy-Fifth Anniversary of the Tax Institute at the
University of Cologne in October 2017, at the Tax Policy Colloquium at NYU School of
Law in April 2018, and at the Maarten J. Ellis Leiden Graduation Lecture on International
Tax Law in August 2018. I am grateful to those who granted me advice, comment,
encouragement, and inspiration including hosts and participants of the above-mentioned
academic events: Lily Batchelder, Richard Bellamy, Stephen Daly, Charles Delmotte,
Peter Diamond, Stefan Grundmann, Johanna Hey, Mitchell Kane, Ariel Jurow Kleiman,
Kai Konrad, Yvette Lind, Liam Murphy, Christine Osterloh-Konrad, Alex Raskolnikov,
Kees van Raad, Carina Schwarz, Ayelet Shachar, Daniel Shaviro, Johanna Stark, and Mats
Tjernberg. The usual disclaimer applies.
I The term congruence has been adopted from the work of Wallace Oates, who applied
the term in the context of fiscal federalism specifically. See Wallace E. Oates, Fiscal Feder-
alism 37 (1972); see also Charles B. Blankart, Offentliche Finanzen in der Demokratie
[Public Finance Office] 86-89 (9th ed. 2017). A similar idea in the fiscal federalism litera-
ture is captured by Mancur Olson's use of the term equivalence. Mancur Olson Jr., The
Principle of "Fiscal Equivalence": The Division of Responsibilities Among Different
Levels of Government, 59 Am. Econ. Rev. 479, 483 (1969); see also Mancur Olson Jr.,
Toward a More General Theory of Governmental Structure, 76 Am. Econ. Rev. 120, 123-
24 (1986).
235
236 TAX LAW REVIEW [Vol. 72:
Parts I and II of this Article describe the historical commitments to
the notion of congruence as well as the erosion of congruence, as a
practical matter, based on the evolution of economic and political con-
ditions over time. The Article then turns to analyze three basic issues
regarding the actual realities of congruence, as manifest in current do-
mestic and global conditions. The analysis begins with a discussion of
isolated domestic issues, then proceeds to analyze the complications
that arise under globalization.
First, in the wholly domestic context the question is whether demo-
cratic procedures as established around the world are sufficient to
protect individual taxpayers or whether one requires material consti-
tutional constraints on the content of tax law. From a comparative
perspective, constitutional law and practice differ widely in this re-
spect. Most European countries, but also Latin American countries,
have endorsed substantive principles of taxation under their respec-
tive constitutional laws. 2 These include general instruments like the
protection of property against excessive taxation and the equal treat-
ment of taxpayers but also specific provisions prescribing adherence
to the ability-to-pay principle or the establishment of a progressive tax
system. These material principles work as counter-majoritarian obsta-
cles to tax legislation, making the validity of a tax law dependent on
its content. At the opposite end of the spectrum, in the United King-
dom or in the United States, democratic decision-making in the area
of taxation is hardly constrained by any material constitutional limita-
tions. Part III of this Article explores the historical trajectories that
have led to these different approaches and tries to evaluate their re-
spective merits. This requires a deep exploration of fundamental ele-
ments of the political system, including the justification of taxation as
such, the relationship between the citizens and the state, and the rela-
tionship between the concepts of private property and community-
wide solidarity. The basic conclusion here is that a normative case for
material constitutional constraints can be defended given the substan-
tial erosion of congruence observed in the domestic sphere over time.
Second, the migration and movement of individuals under condi-
tions of globalization places increased strain on congruence. Individu-
als move in the current economy for many reasons that have nothing
to do with taxation. But the consequences for taxation and democracy
are profound. Part IV of this Article analyzes the "mismatches" be-
tween territorial and political allegiance that become visible once we
recognize the coexistence of multiple tax jurisdictions composed of
multiple citizenries. Most constitutions around the world provide that
2 See notes 15, 44, 45, 44, 92, 93, and 110.
2019] TAXATION AND DEMOCRACY 237
voting rights are attached to citizenship. 3 But most countries do not
tax their own nationals when they live abroad. There are two broad
ways to counter the erosion of congruence here. One could attempt to
achieve greater alignment of taxation with voting rights. This ap-
proach, in turn, has two manifestations. There is the question of
whether countries should assert greater taxing claims over (voting)
nonresident citizens. And, there is the question of whether countries
should grant greater voting rights to (taxpaying) resident noncitizens.
Alternatively, in the absence of achieving greater congruence, there is
the question of whether nonvoting taxpayers should be protected
against excessive or inequitable taxation by material principles of con-
stitutional law. Again, the conclusion reached here is that material
constitutional constraints can be justified in these circumstances.
Third, the tax-motivated movement of individuals and capital raises
distinctive challenges for congruence. Jurisdictions frequently engage
in purposeful fiscal policies of tax competition to lure foreign individ-
uals and capital. Foreign individuals and capital (frequently owned by
multinational companies) may respond accordingly but will typically
lack voting rights in their host countries. Part V analyzes this seeming
breakdown in congruence. The distinct element here is that the rele-
vant taxpayers are, by definition, mobile and tax sensitive. Thus, they
can call on self-help measures in the face of excessive taxation. For
4
these taxpayers, the exit option can substitute for voice. The widely
used parlance of citizens and companies "voting with their feet"
points directly to the impact of cross-border movements on the demo-
cratic process. 5 Here, we see the breakdown in congruence inverted.
The original concern dating back to the Enlightenment philosophers
was that the unrepresented would be over-taxed. With globalization
and taxpayer mobility, the concern evolves such that the unrepre-
sented (because typically more mobile on average) will be under-
taxed.
Again, this brings up the issue of material constitutional constraints.
If mobile taxpayers are under-taxed, then it is the body of immobile
taxpayers who will have to make up the difference. Although these
taxpayers may have ample democratic representation, such voice may
be inadequate to protect their interests. This invites the question of
whether material constitutional constraints should limit the scope of
discretion granted to legislators to give in to the pressure of mobile
capital and mobile individuals. Such legislation may result in tax bene-
3 Voting rights are the "crucial mark of citizenship." Richard Bellamy, Citizenship: A
Very Short Introduction 22 (2008).
4 See Albert 0. Hirschman, Exit, Voice, and Loyalty 21 (1970).
5 Charles A. Tiebout, A Pure Theory of Local Expenditures, 64 J. Pol. Econ. 416 (1956).
238 TAX LAW REVIEW [Vol. 72:
fits for powerful groups. These benefits may be out of sync with the
principle of equality of taxation. From an international perspective,
tax privileges that were meant to have been abandoned long ago
under domestic tax law seem to be on the rise again. Given the pres-
sures of globalization, though, it is unlikely that domestic constitu-
tional constraints could be an effective counterweight to this
phenomenon.
21 To quote from Acemoglu & Robinson's exposition: "To facilitate the initial exposition
of our ideas, it is useful to conceive of society as consisting of two groups-the elites and
the citizens-in which the latter are more numerous. Our framework emphasizes that so-
cial choices are inherently conflictual. For example, if elites are the relatively rich individu-
als-for short, the rich-they will be opposed to redistributive taxation; whereas the
citizens, who will be relatively poor-for short, the poor-will be in favor of taxation that
would redistribute resources to them. More generally, politics or social choices that benefit
the elites will be different from those that benefit the citizens. This conflict of social choices
and policies is a central theme of our approach." Id. at 15.
22 For a similar account, see Sharun Mukand & Dani Rodrik, The Political Economy of
Liberal Democracy 3 (Nat'l Bureau of Econ. Research, Working Paper No. 21540, 2015)
(extending the Acemoglu-Robinson model to majority-minority conflicts under ethnic, re-
ligious, and similar cleavages not related to wealth).
23 Under the assumption that the political elite has an incentive to observe the limita-
tions set by the constitution, this leads to specific requirements of "self-enforcement" of
constitutional norms. See James D. Fearon, Self-Enforcing Democracy, 126 Q.J. Econ.
1661, 1665 (2011); Barry R. Weingast, The Political Foundations of Democracy and the
Rule of Law, 91 Am. Pol. Sci. Rev. 245, 251 (1997).
24 Edgar Kiser & Steven M. Karceski, Political Economy of Taxation, 20 Ann. Rev. Pol.
Sci. 75, 79 (2017).
25 Major studies in the field of comparative fiscal history pleading for a cautious case-by-
case approach include Sven Steinmo & Caroline Tolbert, Do Institutions Really Matter?
Taxation in Industrialized Democracies, 31 Comp. Pol. Stud. 165 (1998) and Kenneth
Scheve & David Stasavage, Taxing the Rich 12 (2016).
2019]1 TAXATION AND DEMOCRACY 243
nority interests. This basic question will be analyzed in detail in Part
IV below.
This prevailing role of the principle of equality, still today the "vir-
tue of sovereigns," 36 has consequences for taxation:
31 For an overview of taxation and the Enlightenment, see Jane Frecknall-Hughes, The
Concept of Taxation and the Age of Enlightenment, in 2 Studies in the History of Tax Law
253 (John Tiley ed., 2007).
32 For a thorough analysis of the notion of the "state" in the context of taxation, see
Klaus Vogel, The Justification for Taxation: A Forgotten Question, 33 Am. J. Juris. 19
(1988).
33 2 Thomas Hobbes, Leviathan, ch. XVIII, at 264 (Noel Malcolm ed., Oxford Univ.
Press 2012) (1651).
34 Marc Leroy, Taxation, the State and Society: The Fiscal Sociology of Interventionist
Democracy 127 (2011) (offering the writings of Jacques-B6nigne Bossuet in France as an
example).
35 2 Hobbes, note 33, ch. XXX.
36 Ronald Dworkin, Sovereign Virtue: The Theory and Practice of Equality 6 (2000).
2019] TAXATION AND DEMOCRACY 247
37 2 Hobbes, note 33, ch. XXX. Hobbes further claims that "[t]he subject of every state
ought to contribute towards the support of the government as early as possible in propor-
tion to their respective abilities that is in proportion to the revenue which they respectively
enjoy under the protection of the State. In the observation or neglect of this maxim con-
sists what is called the equality or inequality of taxation." Id.
38 Dudley Jackson, Thomas Hobbes' Theory of Taxation, 21 Pol. Stud. 175 (1973).
39 S6bastien Le Prestre de Vauban, La dime royale, maximes fondamentales de ce sys-
tbme (1707) ("From this necessity, it follows: First, a natural obligation of all subjects to
contribute in proportion to their income or to their industry without anyone being able to
evade this obligation using reasonable means.") (translation by author).
40 2 Adam Smith, An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations, bk.
V, ch. II, pt. II, at 349-52 (Edwin Cannon ed., Univ. of Chi. Press 1976) (1776).
248 TAX LAW REVIEW [Vol. 72:
jointly demanded the tax burden to be foreseeable, easy to comply
with, and cheap in regard to administrative costs. Again, taxpayer pro-
tection is of importance, but we find no mention of democratic proce-
dures in this part of his work.4 1 Rather, these tax principles seem to
work well under any form of government, oscillating between
prescripts of natural law, economic justifications, and prudential max-
ims for a monarch who intends to rule both effectively and efficiently.
In a similar vein, German thinkers of the eighteenth century com-
bined the notion of a natural duty of the state's subjects to pay taxes
with the duty of the state to allocate the tax burden according to the
subjects' fiscal capacities. 42
Beyond theoretical thinking, the principle of equality gained enor-
mous political momentum throughout the eighteenth century. It be-
came a highly controversial issue during the bitter fight of the rising
bourgeoisie against fiscal privileges for the nobility and for the
church. 43 This omnipresent source of social conflict made world his-
tory in the run-up to the French Revolution. The French constitutions
of the revolutionary age used unambiguous language in prohibiting
any form of tax privilege for individuals and social classes. 44 This abo-
lition of personal tax exemptions was later copied by constitutional
texts throughout Europe, including Germany's Article 134 of the Con-
stitution of the Weimar Republic. 45 An explicit ban on tax privilege can
still be found in Europe-for example, in the constitutions of Belgium
and Luxembourg. 46
But the fight for equality in taxation went beyond the abolition of
unjustified privilege for certain individuals and social classes. In his
Principles of Political Economy, published in 1848, John Stuart Mill
highlighted the fundamental nature of the principle of equality in the
41 But see his remarks on the status of the American colonies. Id. bk. IV, ch. IV, pt. VII.
42 Johann Heinrich Jung-Stilling, Die Grundlehre der Staatswirtschaft, ein Ele-
mentarbuch fUr Regentensbhne und alle, die sich dem Dienst des Staats und der Gelehr-
samkeit widmen wollen §§ 818--820 (Marburg 1792).
43 Delalande, note 19, at 24-28; see also Rafe Blaufarb, The Politics of Fiscal Privilege in
Provence, 1530s-1830s (2012); Michael Kwass, Privilege and the Politics of Taxation in
Eighteenth-Century France (2000); Gary B. McCollim, Louis XIV's Assault on Privilege:
Nicolas Desmaretz and the Tax on Wealth (2012).
44 Cf. 1793 Const. art. 20 (Fr.); Delalande, note 19, at 29-33.
45 1919 Const. art. 134 (Weimar Republic) (providing that taxes had to be levied "with-
out making distinctions" in order to prohibit any tax privilege for specific social classes or
individuals).
46 La Constitution [Constitution] 1994 Const. art. 172 (Belg.); Constitution du Grand-
Duch6 de Luxembourg [Constitution] art. 101; see also Bundesverfassung
[BV][Constitution] Apr. 18, 1999, art. 127, para. 2 (Switz.).
2019] TAXATION AND DEMOCRACY 249
47
tax area as "it ought to be so in all affairs of government." The tax
system as a whole was meant to be shaped by this notion.
Two major sub-principles of tax equality stand out to this day:
Equality according to the benefits received from the state, and equal-
ity according to the individual capacity to contribute to the common
good. 48 The most prominent manifestation of the latter dimension of
the principle of equality in fiscal matters is the "ability-to-pay" princi-
ple, which rose to worldwide recognition throughout the nineteenth
and the twentieth centuries, widely replacing the "contractarian" view
of a tax as a consideration for a benefit received. 49
In this content-oriented world governed by general principles of
taxation, democratic decision-making is not a self-evident factor. To
the contrary, the more economists and lawyers elaborated on "scien-
tific principles" for taxation at the end of the nineteenth century, the
more skeptical some of them became regarding the value of parlia-
mentary influence. Adolph Wagner, Germany's most prominent polit-
ical economist of the time, viewed the ascent of "Parlamentarismus"
as an inroad for class warfare into the rational process of tax alloca-
tion.50 For these writers, public finance seemed to be the realm of a
scientifically informed "benevolent dictator.""5 But for their counter-
parts, protection by consent became paramount.
47 John Stuart Mill, Principles of Political Economy, bk. V, ch. II, § 2, at 169 (Johnathan
Riley ed., Oxford Univ. Press 1994) (7th ed. 1871).
48 Richard A. Musgrave, The Theory of Public Finance: A Study in Public Economy 61-
115 (1959).
49 For its history in nineteenth-century England, see Martin Daunton, Trusting Levia-
than: The Politics of Taxation in Britain 1799-1914, at 136-61 (2001); for its history in the
United States, see Ajay K. Mehrotra, Making of the Modern American Fiscal State: Law,
Politics, and the Rise of Progressive Taxation, 1877-1929, at 96-118 (2013); for its history in
Germany, see Dieter Birk, Das Leistungsfdhigkeitsprinzip als Mapstab der Steuernormen
(1983). A comparative analysis has been provided by Scheve & Stasavage, note 25, at 26-
33. This Article cannot discuss the material aspects, in particular the fundamental vague-
ness and uncertainty of the concept of "ability-to-pay." See Johan A. Kay & Mervyn A.
King, The British Tax System 89-102 (5th ed. 1990); Wolfgang Gassner & Michael Lang,
Das Leistungsfshigkeitsprinzip im Einkommensteuer- und Kdrperschaftsteuerrecht, in
Verhandlungen des 14. Osterreichischen Juristentages Vol.111/1 (2000); Louis Kaplow, The
Theory of Taxation and Public Economics 404-05 (2008).
50 Adolph Wagner & Hermann Deite, Finanzwissenschaft, vol. III/1, Steuergeschichte
§ 100 (1910).
51 See the critical comment by Knut Wicksell, Finanztheoretiche Untersuchungen nebst
Darstellung und Kritik des Steuerwesens Schwedens 102 (Jena, Verlag von Gustav Fischer
1896).
250 TAX LAW REVIEW [Vol. 72:
2. Protection by Consent-Taxes as Voluntary Payments
52 For the early history of this concept, see Leroy, note 34, at 115-16 (including his analy-
sis of the unresolved tension between the state's fiscal sovereignty and individual consent
in the writings of Jean Bodin).
53 John Locke, The Second Treatise of Government, ch. XI, § 140, at 74 (C. B. Macpher-
son ed., Hackett Publishing Co. 1980) (1690). The influence of Locke's theory on continen-
tal Europe, in particular the fiscal ideals of the French Revolution, is widely accepted. See
Delalande, note 19, at 26; Jean-Antoine, note 8, § 48.
54 Locke, note 53, ch. XIII, § 158.
55 Customs and excises on goods were not regarded as "taxes" in this sense, which
meant that the fiscal burden on the common man was largely outside the picture.
56 Edward Andrew, Possessive Individualism and Locke's Doctrine on Taxation, 21
Good Soc'y 151 (2012); Edward Andrew, Locke on Consent, Taxation and Representation,
2019] TAXATION AND DEMOCRACY 251
preferences, and the will of the majority of this class represented
pretty accurately the interest of all its members. The potential for con-
flict as to the allocation of the tax burden and the way revenue was
spent was substantially smaller among such a well-connected class of
57
landowners than in modern anonymous and diverse democracies.
The late eighteenth century and the whole nineteenth century, how-
ever, witnessed a constant fight about the enlargement of the
franchise, first from the landowning nobility to the urban bourgeoisie,
and then, at a later stage, from the capitalist businessmen to their em-
ployees.5 8 A constant theme in this period was the concept that voting
rights should be granted in proportion to the amount of tax paid by a
citizen to the state. This carried major implications for the level of
redistribution and also for the size of the public sector and the quan-
59
tity and quality of public goods being provided by the state.
At the U.S. Constitutional Convention in 1787, the issue of multiple
voting rights according to wealth was seriously discussed. In the end,
James Madison convinced the framers of the U.S. Constitution that a
Senate representing the aristocracy of his time-the "landed proprie-
tors"60-would sufficiently serve as a limiting factor to the taxing
power of the House of Representatives. 6 1 In Democracy in America,
Alexis de Tocqueville strongly supported limiting voting rights to the
middle classes who would look for parsimony and efficiency in public
spending. 62 Even John Stuart Mill, a staunch supporter of broad
equality in fiscal matters, not only pleaded in 1861 for a restriction of
voting rights to those who actually pay the tax, he also wanted to take
away any electoral rights from those who lived on public (church) wel-
fare. 6 3 In practice, the function of graduated voting power was ful-
62 Theoria 15 (2015). For a more progressive reading of Locke's writings see Sagit Leviner,
The Normative Underpinnings of Taxation, 13 Nev. L.J. 95 (2012).
57 In Locke's time leading economists believed that not only direct taxes on land but all
other taxes would ultimately fall on the landowners. David Hume, Essays, Moral, Political,
and Literary, pt. II, Essay VIII ("Of Taxes") at 342-43 n.1 (Eugene F. Miller ed., Liberty
Fund rev. ed. 1987) (1777).
5s Daunton, note 49, at 51, 148.
59 The "contractual" nature of tax payments in this period was reinforced by widespread
"earmarking" of contributions to a specific purpose. Kiser & Karceski, note 24, at 82.
60 Notes of the Secret Debates of the Federal Convention of 1787, taken by the Late
Hon Robert Yates, Chief Justice of the State of New York, and One of the Delegates from
That State to the Said Convention, Yale Law School Lillian Goldman Law Library, http://
avalon.Iaw.yale.edu/l8th-century/yates.asp.
61 Noam Chomsky, Requiem for the American Dream: The 10 Principles of Concentra-
tion of Wealth and Power, 1st Principle (2017); Eric A. Posner & E. Glen Weyl, Radical
Markets 86-90 (2018).
62 1 Alexis de Tocqueville, Democracy in America, pt. II, ch. 5, at 199-200 (Harvey C.
Mansfield & Delba Winthrop eds. & trans., Univ. of Chi. Press 2000) (1835).
63 John Stuart Mill, Considerations on Representative Government, ch. VIII, at 169
(Cambridge Univ. Press 2010) (1861).
252 TAX LAW REVIEW [Vol. 72:
filled in the United Kingdom by the constitutional status of the House
of Lords. This body only lost its right to veto "money bills" passed by
the House of Commons in 1911 following a political crisis after the
Lords had voted down in 1910 the government's budget in full. 64
Although France and Germany largely adhere to a content-based
approach to taxpayer protection, these countries as well experimented
with various approaches to proportionality during this time. The
French Constitution of 1791 made voting rights dependent on a fiscal
contribution, a limitation to voting that was abolished only in the
1850s. 6 5 In Germany, from 1849 until 1918, the impact of votes on the
elections to the Prussian House of Representatives was built on the
"Dreiklassenwahlrecht," which provided for three separate ballots,
each of them dedicated to the election of one-third of the members of
the House. 66 As each ballot was allocated to one out of three classes
of taxpayers-each of them providing one-third of the overall tax rev-
enue-it granted disproportionate voting power to the rich. At the
same time, elections to the Imperial Diet, which had been established
after German unification in 1871 and held virtually no taxing powers,
followed the "one man, one vote" rule. A male Prussian would have
different voting power depending on which assembly he was voting
for. It is thus not surprising that the Social Democrats turned out to
hold a much larger faction in the Imperial Diet than in the Prussian
House of Representatives. 67
In our time, concepts like the Prussian "Dreiklassenwahlrecht" are
widely ridiculed as an atavistic remnant from bygone days of class
struggle. Today, equality of voting rights irrespective of the size of the
voters' fiscal contributions to the state is accepted as self-evident, the
result of social and moral assumptions about the equal value of human
beings. 68 But one should not overlook that this result stems from "in-
bred value judgment rather than logic." 69 The result is also at odds
64 Parliament Act of 1911, 1 & 2 Geo. 5 c. 13 (Eng.); see also Chris Ballinger, Hedging
and Ditching: The Parliament Act 1911, 30 Parliamentary Hist. 19 (2011).
65 Jean-Antoine, note 8, paras. 600-617 (2010).
66 At the time of its introduction, the "Dreiklassenwahlrecht" was regarded by liberal
politicians to constitute progress when compared to the previous electoral system, which
was built on the notion of different social classes. Erwin von Beckerath, Die Preussische
Klassensteuer und die Geschichte ihrer Reform bis 1851, at 66 (1912), calls it the "victory
of capitalism over feudalism."
67 Thomas Kiihne, Handbuch der Wahlen zum preup3ischen Abgeordnetenhaus 1967-
1918 (1994); Gerhard A. Ritter & Merith Niehuss, Wahlgeschichtliches Arbeitsbuch:
Materialien zur Statistik des Kaiserreiches 1971-1918 (1980).
68 For a theoretical critique, see Steffen Ganghof, Does Public Reason Require Super-
majoritarian Democracy? Liberty, Equality, and History in the Justification of Political
Institutions, 12 Pol. Phil. & Econ. 179 (2012).
69 Musgrave, note 48, at 116. In a similar vein, see F.A. Hayek, The Constitution of
Liberty 160 (Ronald Hamowy ed., Routledge 2011) (1960).
2019] TAXATION AND DEMOCRACY 253
with the basic premise of congruence. From the standpoint of political
economy, these bygone institutional constraints thus made sense inso-
far as they tried to forge a compromise between the necessity to en-
gage in collective action for the common good on the one hand and
the goal to avoid exploitation of the wealthy minority by a rent-seek-
ing majority.7 0
Taking these issues seriously in a manner consistent with the com-
mitments of the consent-based approach, one should consider further
voting mechanisms that might garner modern endorsement. The
founding father of modern political economy and public choice, the
Swedish scholar Knut Wicksell, pleaded in 1896 for a supermajority
requirement in budgetary and fiscal matters.7 1 He proposed that no
fiscally relevant action should be taken unless there was (nearly)
unanimous consent among the representatives of the different social
constituencies. His work laid the conceptual foundations for the pub-
lic choice approach championed since the 1960s by James Buchanan
and his school. Importantly, Wicksell did not put much trust in mate-
rial principles of taxation, in particular the concept of equality, as
tools of taxpayer protection. From his perspective, once broad consen-
sus among the people's representatives had been reached, the delinea-
tion of the tax base and the shaping of the tax rate could have any
form. Moreover, the allocation of the tax burden would also take into
account the asymmetrical distribution of benefits received by the tax-
payers financed from the tax revenue, which for him rendered the
concept of tax equality even more precarious. 72 Wicksell therefore
had a rather critical view of concepts such as tax justice, which seemed
to him vague and subjective. 73 In his world of (near) unanimity, con-
sent fully substitutes for content.
Twentieth- and twenty-first-century history has seen different theo-
retical and practical attempts to establish alternative models of con-
sent-oriented rules for taxpayer protection. 74 Friedrich August von
Hayek proposed a division of competence between a "legislative as-
sembly" responsible for defining the tax base in the long run and a
"governmental assembly" setting the tax rate and the budget on an
Longmans 1845).
81 Friedrich Julius Stahl, Rechts- und Staatslehre auf der Grundlage christlicher Weltan-
schauung, 419 (1849) ("The legal ground for taxes-the reason why a state is entitled to
impose them and the subjects to pay them-is the subjection as such. Just as such monetary
expenditures are necessarily founded in the nature and the aim of the state, so must its
members cover the expenses. The nation provides as a spiritual whole the means for its
calling as a state and each and every one must donate because he is a member of the
nation. Likewise objectionable in this context is the legal ground that the subjects pay the
256 TAX LAW REVIEW [Vol. 72:
How does this relate to the fact that both Mill and Stahl accepted
the existence of parliamentary powers in fiscal matters? How did they
solve the conflict between the widely accepted notion that the state as
such deserves to be financed by its citizens a priori and the interest of
the citizens to get involved in the decision-making? John Stuart Mill,
in his Considerationson Representative Government, allocated to the
executive the power to shape the fiscal affairs of the state in the first
place. Thus, it should be up to the King of England to deliver the first
shot. Parliament, on the other side, should not be allowed to make
amendments to the budget or to pursue its own policies by budgetary
means, but crucially Parliament retains a veto power. In the United
States, the power of the legislature extends even further, as the option
of an explicit "government shutdown" provoked by Congress, in its
refusal to pass legislation funding the government, has been regarded
as part and parcel of the fiscal constitution for centuries. 82
For Stahl, who sought to preserve the Prussian monarch's preroga-
tive, even the notion of a parliamentary veto right endangered the
stability of the state as such. When speaking in the Prussian First
Chamber in 1849 on constitutional reform,83 he fervently dismissed
the proposal that Parliament should have the power to reject the
King's annual budget proposal, including tax legislation, altogether. A
Parliament-driven government shutdown would not only jeopardize
central functions of the state, it would lead to a "Demokratismus,"84
which was bound to destroy the finely tuned separation and balance of
powers within the state. According to Stahl, parliamentary powers in
the field of taxation only enabled the people's representatives to have
a word on incremental increases of the annual tax revenue, in particu-
lar the introduction of new types of taxes, but not to force their will on
other branches of the government. In his view, the budgetary powers
of the Parliament were not meant to question the raison d'tat as such.
The Lockean notion practiced in England and supported by Mill, that
Parliament may decline any financial contributions demanded by the
King, was explicitly rejected by Stahl as an atavistic remnant of medie-
taxes as an equivalent for the protection of their property, as if they would enter into a
contract with the state.") (translation by author); see also Lorenz von Stein, Lehrbuch der
Finanzwissenschaft 302 (3d ed. 1875).
82 Katharine G. Young, American Exceptionalism and Government Shutdowns: A
Comparative Constitutional Reflection on the 2013 Lapse in Appropriations, 94 B.U. L.
Rev. 991, 1000 (2014); see also Werner Heun, Das Budgetrecht im Regierungssytem der
USA (1989) (providing a German perspective on shutdowns).
83 Friedrich Julius Stahl, Das Steuerverweigerungsrecht: Rede des Dr. Stahl, Abge-
ordneten ffr Angermfinde, Ober-und Nieder-Barnim, Prenzlow, Templin, in der
fdnfundfanfzigsten Sitzung der preupischen Ersten Kammer am 16. Oktober 1849 (Berlin,
Decker 1849).
84 Id. at 14.
2019] TAXATION AND DEMOCRACY 257
val customs, under which different estates (landowners, urban bur-
ghers, etc.) negotiated individually with the King of England their
respective contributions for the King's outlays in his political and mili-
tary ventures.8 5
Following this constitutional debate, the "imposed" Prussian Con-
stitution of 1850 remained ambiguous on this matter, supporting both
the budgetary powers of the representative and the power of the King
86
to carry on levying existing taxes on the basis of previous legislation.
But Stahl's theoretical question became highly topical in the 1860s
when the King of Prussia and the Prussian House of Representatives
disagreed on costly military reform. 7 Otto von Bismarck, then the
Prussian prime minister, deplored what he named a "constitutional
gap" and argued for this to be filled by royal prerogative, "as the life
of the State cannot stand still for a single moment," and sealed the
outcome with a crackdown on the aspiring liberal movement in Prus-
sia.8 8 Ten years earlier, Bismarck had already explicitly rejected the
"powerless position held by the English Crown" 9 as a model for
Prussia.
90
This move set the German stage for more than 150 years. It
shaped the fiscal constitution of the Weimar Republic enacted in
1919,91 and even under the postwar fiscal constitution of the Federal
Republic of Germany, Bismarck's plea that the "state engine" has to
be kept going, has not lost its force. Article 111 of the German Basic
Law empowers the Federal Administration to move on without a for-
mally confirmed budget on a provisional basis in order to keep the
executive branch capable of acting. Moreover, existing tax laws re-
main in force pro futuro until they are formally suspended by the leg-
islator. A similar constitutional framework applies in France 92 and in
other countries in Europe. 9 3
85 Id. at 10-14.
86 Verfassungsurkunde [Constitution] Jan. 31, 1850, arts. 99, 100, 109 (Prussia). See also
von Beckerath, note 66, at 53-57.
87 Karl-Heinrich Friauf, Der Staatshaushaltsplan im Spannungsfeld zwischen Parlament
und Regierung 223 (1968); Hans-Christof Kraus, Ursprung und Genese der "Lockenthe-
orie" im preupischen Verfassungskonflikt, 29 Der Staat 209 (1990).
88 Otto von Bismarck, Rede vor dem Abgeordnetenhaus des Preupischen Landtags vom
27.1.1863, in Die Reden des Grafen von Bismarck-Schbnhausen, Erste Sammiung, Reden
der Jahre 1862-1866, at 20 (Berlin, 2d ed. 1870).
89 Otto von Bismarck, 10 Die gesammelten Werke 44 (1924) (translation by author).
90 Adolph Wagner, Lehr- und Handbuch der politischen Okonomie § 117 (Leipzig, C.F.
Winter'sche Verlaghandlung 2d ed. 1890).
91 Gerhard Anschiitz, Die Verfassung des Deutschen Reiches vom 11. August 1919, ein
Kommentar flir Wissenschaft und Praxis (14th ed. 1933).
92 1958 Const. art. 47 (Fr.); Jean-Antoine, note 8.
93 Bundes-Verfassungsgesetz [B-VG] [Constitution] art. 51 (Austria); Constituci6n Es-
pafilola (C.E.) [Constitution], B.O.E. n. 311, Dec. 29, 1978, art. 134, para. 4 (Spain).
258 TAX LAW REVIEW [Vol. 72:
In sum, one way to understand the continued reluctance to adopt
material constitutional protections in consent-based systems is that a
view has been taken that the prospect of government shutdown oper-
ates as a protective measure of last resort. In systems where that pro-
tective measure is lacking, one observes, by contrast, the adoption of
material constitutional constraints. Whether the option of legislative
veto or explicit government shutdown is a sufficient protective mea-
sure is a complicated question. I turn to this question in the next two
sections of the Article. I first analyze the constitutional structures that
have evolved in countries committed alternatively to content-based
systems and consent-based systems. I then describe the pressures
placed on these constitutional structures by the erosion of congruence
as a practical and political matter.
94 John Snape & Jane Frecknall-Hughes, John Locke: Property, Tax and the Private
Sphere, in 8 Studies in the History of Tax Law 1 (Peter Harris & Dominic de Cogan eds.,
2017).
2019] TAXATION AND DEMOCRACY 259
forraign enemies, and from the injuries of one another; and
consequently there is no longer a Common-wealth. 95
what taxes are unjustified should be interpreted instead as questions about how the system
should define those property rights that arise through the various transactions-employ-
ment, bequest, contract, investment, buying and selling-that are subject to taxation."
Liam Murphy & Thomas Nagel, The Myth of Ownership 74 (2002); see also Leviner, note
56, at 96.
9 See Richard A. Epstein, Takings: Private Property and the Power of Eminent Domain
283-305 (1985) (defending a more expansive reading of the Takings Clause); see also Alex-
andre Mangiavillano, Le contribuable et I'ltat: L'imp6t et la garantie constitutionelle de la
propri6t6 (Allemagne-France 2013) (comparing French and German judicial practices);
Pierre-Lonard Rouzaud, L'imp6t confiscatoire: Notion et jurisprudence (2016).
100 U.S. Const. art. 1, § 8.
101 1793 Const. art. 20 (Fr.).
102 Pa. Const. of 1776, § 41.
2019] TAXATION AND DEMOCRACY 261
This rule never gained any traction in the real world. 103 It would
seem that systems in the Lockean strand largely gave up on the notion
of constitutionalizing protections of private property via limitations on
the taxing power. In part, this may be explained by the backstop pro-
tection of government shutdown discussed above. In part, this may be
explained by the resort to pragmatic, rather than constitutional argu-
ments. And after World War II, the optimistic notion of the state as a
central planner and as a social engineer emboldened legislators to ap-
ply ever higher tax rates on personal income and wealth in most West-
ern countries including the Anglo-American world in order to achieve
distributive goals and a steep increase of the public sector. Old-style
libertarians like Hayek'0 were regarded as outsiders while social
planners like Richard Musgrave10 5 held center stage. While it is true
that in the Reagan-Thatcher era the pendulum swung back in the di-
rection of libertarian theories and a critical view on the role of the
state, this movement was again motivated by the realm of practical
politics and less by constitutional concepts.
It is interesting to learn that the protection of property vis-a-vis the
fiscal powers of the state has taken a different route on the European
continent. The state-oriented view, in regard to the lack of protection
of private property vis-a-vis the tax legislator, was initially the purview
of conservative theorists of the state, like Stahl, and this view held
sway for more than a century. Against this background, during and in
the aftermath of World War I, industrialized countries witnessed an
enormous rise in the overall and average tax burden, described by Jo-
seph Schumpeter as early as 1919 in his seminal article on the "crisis
of the taxing state." 10 These developments overcame concerns as to
07
the overreach of the taxing powers toward the individual taxpayer.1
In this unruly postwar world, Schumpeter uttered a fervent plea for
upper limits on taxation. But his argument was not founded on theo-
retical or legal concepts of individual entitlements or constitutional
constraints. Rather, the argument rested on the sheer practical neces-
sity of leaving private business some space to breathe, in the interest
103 Note that comparative scholarship on the constitutional protection of private prop-
erty typically leaves out issues of taxation. See, e.g., Tom Allen, The Right to Property, in
Comparative Constitutional Law 504 (Tom Ginsburg & Rosalind Dixon eds., 2011).
104 Hayek, note 69, at 430-50.
105 Musgrave, note 48, at 17-22.
106 Joseph Schumpeter, Die Krise des Steuerstaats [Crisis of the Taxing State] (1918);
see also Leroy, note 34, at 55-61.
107 The thesis that major increases in the overall tax burden-including high tax rates on
high-income earners-are correlated to war efforts and the need to deliver a sacrifice fairly
"compensating" for the loss of life and health by others is at the center of Scheve and
Stasavage's book. Scheve & Stasavage, note 25.
262 TAX LAW REVIEW [Vol. 72:
of the nation as a whole. 108 Socialist governments in Europe before
and after World War II did not accept any material limitation to the
taxing power, and-taking a closer look-it seems fair to say that the
socialist governments of the twentieth century built their tax policy on
the remnants of a conservative theory, which had immunized the fiscal
state against individual concerns. 109
Notwithstanding this Hobbesian approach to taxation visible in
many countries, the wish to establish some "content"-oriented barrier
against excessive taxation gained ground during the twentieth century.
In many jurisdictions, constitutions contain provisions prohibiting "ex-
propriating" or "confiscatory" taxation. 110 But these are rather vague,
limited to extreme cases, and therefore hardly play a practical role."'
Even in a content-driven state such as Germany, the constitutional
protection of private property did not play any meaningful role in fis-
cal matters for nearly fifty years after the entry into force of the Basic
Law. As late as 1995, the German Constitutional Court tried to cut
the Gordian knot by establishing the "half income principle," which
was meant to prohibit a tax rate on income exceeding roughly 50%.112
But only a decade later, in 2006, the judges of the Constitutional
Court explicitly retreated from their far-reaching earlier statements
and abandoned this highly debated concept.1 13
2. Redistribution
116 Tsilly Dagan, International Tax Policy Between Competition and Cooperation 18
(2018).
117 Jean-Baptiste le Rond d'Alembert, Essai sur les tl6ments de Philosophie, in 5 Me-
langes de Litt6rature, D'histoire, et de Philosophie 94-96 (Amsterdam, Zacharie Chatelain
& Fils 4th ed. 1767). 1 owe this reference to Moritz Epple, D'Alembert Philosophe Engage:
In6galit6s, Frontieres, et la Societe des Gens de Lettres et des Grands (2017) (unpublished
manuscript).
118 Jean-Jacques Rousseau, Discours sur I'Economie Politique, 1 Economie Politique
337 (1755), https://www.rousseauonline.chlText/discours-sur-1-economie-politique.php.
119 See also Jean-Pierre Gross, Progressive Taxation and Social Justice in Eighteenth-
Century France, 140 Past & Present 79 (1993); Audrey Rosa, Solidarit6 et Imp6t:
Recherche sur les fondements de l'imp6t moderne (2015).
120 Delalande, note 19, at 34-49.
121 Von Stein, note 81, at 321-27.
122 Karl Marx & Friedrich Engels, Das kommunistische Manifest 20 (1848). This text is
still regarded as "seminal" for modern tax sociology. See Martin & Prasad, note 9.
123 Wagner, note 115, § 27; see also Adolph Wagner, Zweiter Theil: Theorie der
Besteuerung, Gebaihrenlehre und allgemeine Steuerlehre in Lehr- und Handbuch des
Politischen Okonomie § 82 (2d ed. 1890).
124 Delalande, note 19, at 34-49.
264 TAX LAW REVIEW [Vol. 72:
French constitutions of the revolutionary age. 125 Taking this demand
for equal sacrifice as a starting point, a fair number of constitutions,
such as the constitutions of Brazil, Italy, Spain, and Switzerland, ex-
plicitly provide for progressive taxation as a matter of principle. 1 2 6
Under German constitutional law, this approach is implicitly related
to the concept of the "social welfare state" laid down in the Basic
Law, which obliges the legislator to level factual inequality and to pur-
sue public welfare. 1 2 7 Building on this concept of the "social welfare
state," in a recent dissenting vote on the constitutionality of inheri-
tance taxation, three judges of the German Constitutional Court em-
phasized a constitutional requirement to implement a meaningful
minimum of redistribution under the German tax system.1 28 These fis-
cal instruments feed into the growing demand for constitutional de-
vices that are meant to limit the scope of economic inequality within a
constituency.1 2 9
Interestingly, the evolved Hobbesian view that embraces a concept
of solidarity eventually took root in countries more firmly connected
to the Lockean conception of the role of the state as well. In the
United States, public finance scholars (some of which had returned
from their studies in Europe) at the turn of the nineteenth century
pressed for progressive taxation on the basis of solidarity among the
citizens of a state in their home country. 13 0 In the work of Edwin R.
A. Seligman and Richard T. Ely, one can clearly see how the Hobbes-
ian concept of being a subject of the (absolute) state morphed into the
concept of solidarity owed to other members of that state. The Lock-
ean contractarian view is clearly dismissed while the concept of tax as
a sacrifice takes center stage. 1 3 1 As with the case of property protec-
125 1793 Const. art. 101 (Fr.) ("No citizen is excluded from the honorable obligation to
contribute towards the public expenses.") (translation by author).
126 Italian Constitution art. 31, para. 1; Constitution of the Kingdom
of Spain art. 31,
para. 1; Swiss Constitution art. 127, para. 2; Constitution of Brazil art. 145, para. 3(1).
127 German Basic Law art. 20, para. 1.
128 Bunderverfassungsgericht [BverfG] [German Constitutional Court] Dec. 17,
2014,
Entscheidungen des Bundesverfassungsgerichts [BverfGE] 136 (252-255), 2014 (Baer, J.,
Gaier, J. & Masing, J., dissenting).
129 Cf. Rosalind Dixon & Julie Suk, Liberal Constitutionalism and Economic Inequality,
85 U. Chi. L. Rev. 369 (2018).
130 Mehrotra, note 49, at 97-118; Edwin R. A. Seligman, Progressive Taxation in Theory
and Practice, 9 Pub. Am. Econ. Ass'n 7, 7-222 (1908); Edwin R. A. Seligman, The Income
Tax, 9 Pol. Sci. Q. 610, 610-48 (1894).
131 See Richard T. Ely, Taxation in American States and Cities 13 (New York, Thomas
Y. Crowell & Co. Publishers 1888) ("Man, as a human being, owes services to his fellows,
and one of the first of these is to support government, which makes civilization possible.
Only an anarchist can take any other view. To the ordinary man it appears right that he
should be called upon to give not only his property for the promotion of common interests,
but even his life, if need be."); Edwin R. A. Seligman, Essays in Taxation 72 (New York,
Macmillan & Co. 1895) ("It is now generally agreed that we pay taxes not because the state
2019] TAXATION AND DEMOCRACY 265
tions, however, the debates over redistribution and overall tax bur-
dens have remained firmly grounded in the realm of politics, rather
than being enshrined in material constitutional limits on the taxing
power.
As noted above, the Hobbesian view evolved over time from the
initial stance that saw the sovereign, or any ruling elite, as the apex for
any obligation to pay tax to a view grounded in solidarity, one in
which the citizens acting under the rules of democratic decision-mak-
ing are the source of power. Since the days of the French Revolution,
the "people" as such-in German parlance the "Staatsvolk"-have
taken over as the source of legitimacy for the exercise of the state's
powers. This replacement of the monarch by the people, which we
witness throughout the nineteenth and twentieth centuries, lends to
the interaction between taxation and democracy a specific twist. Fol-
lowing Montesquieu's and Rousseau's dialectical view of the members
of a nation being both the "objects" of the state's powers and the
"subjects" of government,1 3 2 taxpayers see themselves both as being
part of the taxing power and being subject to its execution. 1 3 3 In other
words, congruence. At first glance, this dialectical perspective might
suggest that the Hobbesian and the Lockean views collapse into one
once full democratic government has arrived. Under the new rules, no
tax will be levied that is not built on the consensus of the people. For
Rousseau such congruence meant that there was no need for further
protects us, or because we get any benefits from the state, but simply because the state is a
part of us. The duty of supporting and protecting is born with us. In a civilized society the
state is as necessary to the individual as the air he breathes; unless he reverts to stateless
savagery and anarchy he cannot live beyond his own confines. . . . We pay taxes not be-
cause we get benefits from the state, but because it is as much our duty to support the state
as to support ourselves or our family."); see also Lily L. Batchelder, Fred T. Goldberg Jr.
&
Peter R. Orszag, Efficiency and Tax Incentives: The Case for Refundable Tax Credits, 59
Stan. L. Rev. 23, 66-68 (2006) (discussing the concept of "civic duty" and its impact on
refundable tax credits); Lawrence Zelenak, Learning to Love Form 1040: Two Cheers for
the Return-Based Mass Income Tax (2013) (discussing the current U.S. debate on taxation
as a "civic duty") (reviewed by Ajay K.Mehrotra, Reviving Fiscal Citizenship, 113 Mich. L.
Rev. 943 (2015)).
132 Montesquieu, Spirit of Laws, bk. 2, ch. 2, at 10 (Anne M. Cohler, Basia Carolyn
Miller & Harold Samuel Stone eds. & trans., Cambridge Univ. Press 1989) (1748); Jean-
Jacques Rousseau, Of the Social Contract or Principles of Political Right, bk. 1, § VII, at 16
(Charles M. Sherover trans., Harper & Row 1984) (1762).
133 This dialectical view is still very much present in current French scholarship. See
139 "Rousseau wiederholt hier den Irrtum des Hobbes und kommt wie dieser zu einer
absoluten Staatsgewalt. Freilich bekennt er sich als Freund der gemeinen Bfirgerfreiheit,
w~hrend Hobbes die Herrschaft des einen tiber alle beginstigt. Aber der Absolutismus
seines als Souveran proklamierten Demos ist ftir die Freiheit der Individuen nicht weniger
gef~hrlich als der Absolutismus des Monarchen bei Hobbes. Ob meine Eigenart von dem
Unverstande der Menge unterdrtickt oder von der Willkir eines Despoten gefesselt werde,
ist fOr meine Freiheit gleich verderblich; und wenn auch die Demokratie Rousseaus der
gemeinen Freiheit aller nicht so abgeneigt ist wie die Despotie des absoluten Firsten, so ist
jene doch starker als diese und es wird schwieriger, ihrer rohen Ubermacht zu wider-
stehen." Johann Caspar Bluntschli, Geschichte der Neueren Staatswissenschaft:
Allgemeines Staatsrecht und Politik Seit dem 16. Jahrhundert bis zur Gegenwart 349-50
(1881).
140 Buchanan, note 74, at 7 (emphasis in original).
141 Id. at 187-92. The link between Buchanan's work and the German debate on consti-
tutional constraints has been emphasized by Vogel. Vogel, note 32, at 19 n.4, 31-32; see also
Charles Delmotte, The Political Economics of Tax Exemptions: Tax Uniformity as a Con-
stitutional Principle (2017); Wolfgang Schan, Grundrechtsschutz gegen den demokratis-
chen Steuerstaat, 64 Jahrbuch des 6ffentlichen Rechts 515 (2016).
268 TAX LAW REVIEW [Vol. 72:
tor doesn't tax himself.1 4 2 Within a democratic environment, collective
decision-making works even better, though, if the principle of equality
in tax matters ensures that there is equal cost for everyone for financ-
ing the collective good. 143 This principle guarantees that majority deci-
sions cannot go too far to the detriment of the outvoted minority.1 4 4
At the same time, it makes sure that minorities with disproportionate,
concentrated power are not in the position to extract unjustified tax
benefits.
Absent material constitutional constraints, the question is whether
it is possible to overcome the conflict between the majority and the
minority by democratic means. In other words, is it possible that the
minority accepts the outcome of a majoritarian vote as the true ex-
pression of the general will of the people? Starting from Rousseau's
optimistic assumptions as to the creation of the volonti gindrale he
was forced to assume that the defeated minority simply "got it
wrong,"1 4 5 that it had a false perception of reality and a misunder-
standing of the best solution and should be educated to accept it. In
today's world Habermas's model of democratic decision-making as a
procedurally organized discourse of arguments is meant to lead to suf-
ficiently justified outcomes.1 46 Against this background, a group of
German constitutional lawyers 47 has rejected the jurisprudence of the
German Constitutional Court on hardwired constraints on the work of
142 Mancur Olson, Dictatorship, Democracy, and Development, 87 Am. Pol. Sci. Rev.
567, 570-71 (1993).
143 Howard R. Bowen, The Interpretation of Voting in the Allocation of Economic Re-
sources, 58 Q.J. Econ. 27, 46-47 (1943). In a similar vein, Hayek proposed that progressive
taxes should only be admissible to the extent that the majority of voters finds itself in the
highest tax bracket. See Hayek, note 75, at 441.
144 It is interesting to note that in The Federalist No. 21 (Alexander Hamilton), Alexan-
der Hamilton pleaded for consumption taxes rather than personal taxes to fund the federal
budget as excise taxes are conceptually applied in a broad manner, leave the decision to
consume to the taxpayer, and cannot therefore serve as a means to expropriate specific
taxpayers or groups of taxpayers: "It is a signal advantage of taxes on articles of consump-
tion, that they contain in their own nature a security against excess. . . . If duties are too
high, they lessen the consumption; the collection is eluded; and the product to the treasury
is not so great as when they are confined within proper and moderate bounds. This forms a
complete barrier against any material oppression of the citizens, by taxes of this class, and
is itself a natural limitation of the power of imposing them."
145 Rousseau, note 132, bk. 4, ch. 2; for a skeptical view on the wisdom of majority rule,
see Hayek, note 75, at 449.
146 Jirgen Habermas, Faktizitdt und Geltung: Beitr5ge zur Diskurstheorie des Rechts
und des demokratischen Rechtsstaats 349-98 (1992); see also James Bohman, Public Delib-
eration 9-21 (1996); John S. Dryzek, Discursive Democracy: Politics, Policy, and Political
Science 14-22 (1990). For a critical view of this concept in the context of European deci-
sion-making, see Fritz Scharpf, De-constitutionalisation and Majority Rule: A Democratic
Vision for Europe, 23 Eur. L.J. 315, 327-30 (2017).
147 Oliver Lepsius, Constitutional Review of Tax Laws and the Unconstitutionality of
the German Inheritance Tax Law, 16 Ger. L.J. 1191, 1202-25 (2016).
2019] TAXATION AND DEMOCRACY 269
the tax legislator in order to retain leeway for such parliamentary de-
liberation and compromise. Similarly, Richard Bellamy has put for-
ward a more procedural understanding of democratic discourse,
148
stressing the value of the political process vis-a-vis the courts.
But is taxation really about democratic discourse? It is interesting
to learn that Knut Wicksell clarified as early as 1896 that it makes a
big difference whether factions within a democratic legislature disa-
gree in terms of their personal opinions or in terms of their personal
interests. 149 Differences of opinion (e.g., how best to attain a common
goal such as environmental protection or a reform of the educational
system) can by and large be addressed by discourse and solved by
majority vote. Differences of interest (e.g., regarding the level of
wealth redistribution within a society) are harder to manage and it
would seem rather naive to regard the outcome of a majority vote as a
simple exercise in philosophical deliberations around a common goal,
15 0 This is one of
given that nobody acts under a "veil of ignorance."
the reasons why Wicksell pleaded for (nearly) unanimous consensus.
He wanted to weed out those proposals that do not seem to carry
enough weight to be regarded as clear outflows of the common good.
As this is a utopian approach and as democratic discourse seems inad-
equate to solve fundamental conflicts of interest, one is left with a
powerful normative case for material constraints to majority voting in
fiscal matters. As congruence erodes, so the normative case for such
constraints builds.
152 Alex Raskolnikov, Accepting the Limits of Tax Law and Economics, 98 Cornell L.
Rev. 523, 560-66 (2013).
153 Louis Kaplow, The Theory of Taxation and Public Economics 401-03 (2008).
154 Wicksell, note 51, at 76-87.
155 Kaplow, note 153, at 398-99.
2019] TAXATION AND DEMOCRACY 271
have offered a normative argument that the case for material con-
straints increases as congruence erodes. For countries that are histori-
cally within the Hobbesian content-based tradition, the adoption of
material constitutional constraints meshes well with basic, underlying
philosophical commitments. For countries in the Lockean consent-
based camp, however, this is not so. In this section, I provide a com-
parative analysis of England, Germany, and the United States to fur-
ther elaborate this divide.
158 See, e.g., Finance Act 2017, c. 10, pt. 1, § 1 (Eng.) ("Income tax is charged for the tax
year 2017-18."); see also Constitution du Grand-Duch6 de Luxembourg [Constitution] art.
100.
159 3 Adolph Wagner & Hermann Deite, Spezielle Steuerlehre § 108 (2d ed. 1912).
160 Daunton, note 58, at 65.
2019] TAXATION AND DEMOCRACY 273
161
ginal tax rate on personal income during the twentieth century. Po-
litical scientists have traced this imbalance back to the "highly
unstable tax structure" brought about by the "centralized single-mem-
ber, first-past-the-post electoral system." 162 On this basis, the postwar
years have seen an unprecedented tax burden on the British economy
for many decades before both the Conservative (Margaret Thatcher)
and Labour (Tony Blair) governments reconfirmed the British con-
sensus to reduce rather than to increase the tax burden of the people.
Once a truly left-leaning government comes to power in England,
there will be hardly any constitutional constraints to their willingness
to move to a new fiscal paradigm.
See the statistical findings in Scheve & Stasavage, note 25, at 57.
161
Sven Steinmo & Caroline Tolbert, Do Institutions Really Matter? Taxation in Indus-
162
trialized Democracies, 31 Comp. Pol. Stud. 165, 171 (1998).
163 Bruce Ackerman, Taxation and the Constitution, 99 Colum. L. Rev. 1 (1999); Boris I.
Bittker, Constitutional Limits on the Taxing Power of the Federal Government, 41 Tax
Law. 3 (1987).
164 McCulloch v. Maryland, 17 U.S. 316, 327 (1819).
165 Panhandle Oil Co. v. Mississippi ex rel. Knox, 277 U.S. 218, 223 (1928) ("The power
to tax is not the power to destroy while this Court sits.").
166 As to the deferential position the U.S. Supreme Court has taken as regards economic
legislation, which is only subject to scrutiny under a "rational basis test," see Gerald Gun-
ther, The Supreme Court, 1971 Term, Foreword: In Search of Evolving Doctrine on a
Changing Court: A Model for a Newer Equal Protection, 86 Harv. L. Rev. 1 (1972) (dis-
cussing the foundations of rational-basis jurisprudence); Raphael Holoszyc-Pimentel, Rec-
onciling Rational Basis Review: When Does Rational Basis Bite?, 90 N.Y.U. L. Rev. 2070
(2015); Vicki C. Jackson, Constitutional Law in an Age of Proportionality, 124 Yale L.J.
3094, 3172-83 (2015); Robert F. Nagel, Legislative Purpose, Rationality, and Equal Protec-
tion, 82 Yale L.J. 123 (1972).
167 See Armour v. City of Indianapolis, 132 S.Ct. 2073 (2012) ("And we have repeatedly
pointed out that '[1]egislatures have especially broad latitude in creating classifications and
distinctions in tax statutes."'); Regan v. Taxation With Representation of Washington, 461
U.S. 540, 547 (1983); see also Fitzgerald v. Racing Ass'n of Central Iowa, 539 U.S. 103, 107-
08 (2003); Nordlinger v. Hahn, 505 U.S. 1, 11 (1992); Lehnhausen v. Lake Shore Auto Parts
274 TAX LAW REVIEW [Vol. 72:
formity Clause, which ensures equal treatment among taxpayers from
different states, has never been developed into an overarching princi-
ple of tax equality.1 69
The most prominent hardwired constraint to federal and state tax
legislation stems from the division of fiscal competences between the
states and the federal government, which the Supreme Court has em-
ployed to limit federal and state taxing powers on many occasions.1 70
At the end of the nineteenth century, the Supreme Court declared a
federal progressive income tax unconstitutional as it did not comply
with the constitutional requirement to "apportion" the tax burden
equally among the states,1'7 and the U.S. Constitution had to be
changed by the Sixteenth Amendment in 1913 to provide a legal basis
for today's federal income tax. State legislators, on the other hand,
have to comply with constitutional limitations of their competences as
well, in particular under the "dormant commerce clause," which has
been employed to strike down tax legislation in a multitude of
cases.1 72 One might fairly say that the constitutional allocation of tax-
ing powers between the federal government and the states establishes
some indirect safeguards for the taxpayers as well, but this seems to be
rather a collateral effect and not an outright goal of this constitutional
framework.
When Chief Justice Marshall declared the power to tax to be "the
power to destroy" in 1819, he simultaneously expressed an optimistic
view as to this dimension of representative democracy:
Co., 410 U.S. 356, 359 (1973); Madden v. Kentucky, 309 U.S. 83, 87-88 (1940); Citizens'
Telephone Co. of Grand Rapids v. Fuller, 229 U.S. 322, 329 (1913); William Barker, The
Three Faces of Equality: Constitutional Requirements in Taxation, 57 Case Western Res.
L. Rev. 1 (2006) (providing a comparative account of the principle of equality in the
United States and Germany).
168 Brushaber v. Union Pacific R.R., 240 U.S. 1, 24-25 (1916); Eric Kades, Drawing the
Line Between Takings and Taxation: The Continuous Burdens Principle, and Its Broader
Application, 97 Nw. L. Rev. 189 (2002). For a more forceful use of the takings clause in
fiscal matters, see Epstein, note 99, at 283-305.
169 Bittker, note 163 (citing Knowlton v. Moore, 178 U.S. 41 (1900) (declaring a progres-
sive inheritance tax to comply with the Uniformity Clause).
170 Ackerman, note 163 (analyzing the constitutional limitations on "direct" federal
taxes).
171 Pollock v. Farmers' Loan & Trust Co., 157 U.S. 429 (1895). It should not go unno-
ticed, however, that at the state level, some constitutions provide that only "proportional"
and no "graduated" or "progressive" income taxes can be levied. See Walter Hellerstein,
Kirk J. Stark, John A. Swain & Joan M. Youngman, State and Local Taxation: Cases and
Materials 98 (10th ed. 2014).
172 Michael S. Knoll & Ruth Mason, The Economic Foundation of the Dormant Com-
merce Clause, 102 Va. L. Rev. 309 (2017).
2019] TAXATION AND DEMOCRACY 275
exigencies of Government cannot be limited, they prescribe
no limits to the exercise of this right, resting confidently on
the interest of the legislator and on the influence of the con-
stituent over their representative to guard them against its
abuse. 173
This approach makes the political process, but also specific instru-
ments such as a "government shutdown," much more important than
substantive limitations on the state's power to tax its own citizens.
And it may well be, as recent studies have tried to show, that in the
United States there exists a relatively stable antipathy among the elec-
torate against "taxing the rich." 174 But even in the United States some
scholars have expressed doubts as to the long-term viability of these
political arrangements.1 75 They propose that basic principles in taxa-
tion should be linked to individual rights and liberties under the Con-
stitution. This is the direction constitutional law has tried to take in
Germany and many other European 76 and Latin American countries.
nance the cost of German reunification. It has remained in place for more than twenty-five
2019] TAXATION AND DEMOCRACY 277
It will remain in force only for the upper 10%, a strange and novel
application of the notion of "solidarity." 1 8 2 In other European nations,
there exists some additional constitutional jurisprudence in this area.
In France, a special income tax rate of 75% on income exceeding 1
million C was declared unconstitutional in 2012 by the Conseil Consti-
tutionnel, but a later version was approved in 2013.183 Nevertheless,
while the Conseil Constitutionnel validated the marginal tax rate of
75%, the Conseil hit the brakes as some items of financial income
were subject to an overall tax burden of more than 90%, which it
found to violate the "ability-to-pay principle" enshrined in the French
Constitution. 18 4 In Switzerland, as early as 1973 the Federal Tribunal
found some elements of a cantonal wealth tax unconstitutional as
progressivity was used to an extent that applied marginal tax rates of
up to 250% in certain tax brackets.1 85
The issue of special tax benefits, or privilege, has not gone away
since the days of the French Revolution. As current political practice
shows, tax privilege today takes the form of intended or unintended
"tax incentives," most prominently tax breaks for business income or
business assets. From a constitutional background this leads to the
problem of the legitimacy of pursuing nontax goals in fiscal legislation.
The most prominent case in recent years, where the overall problem
became highly visible, concerned inheritance taxation as reformed in
2008.186 This legislation combined two main deficiencies where mate-
rial principles of taxation and the legitimating power of democracy
clash. On the one hand, the Bundestag decided to establish generous
tax-free thresholds that exempted 90% of the country's citizens. On
the other hand, rich business owners (in particular family businesses),
being a formidable pressure group in German politics, succeeded in
lobbying for large-scale tax exemptions for business owners. In the
end, neither the large majority of low-wealth voters nor the special-
years. Multiple attempts to have it struck down by the Constitutional Court have failed so
far.
182 Christian Democratic Union et al., Ein neuer Aufbruch fur; Europa-Eine neue
Dynamik fur Deutschland-Ein neuer Zusammenhalt fur; unser Land: Koalitionsvertrag
zwischen CDU, CSU und SPD, 19 Legislaturperiode 68 (2018). For a first critical assess-
ment from the point of view of constitutional law, see Hanno Kube, Steuerpolitische Per-
spektiven der neuen Legislaturperiode-Vorstellung, Wdirdigung, Ausblick, 100 Finanz-
Rundschau 408, 409-10 (2018).
183 Conseil constitutionnel [CC] [Constitutional Court] decision No. 2012-662 DC, Dec.
29, 2012 (Fr.).
184 Conseil constitutionnel [CC] [Constitutional Court] decision No. 2013-684 DC, Dec.
29, 2013 (Fr.).
185 Bundesgericht [BGer] [Federal Supreme Court] July 20, 1973, 1973 BGE 99, 638, 656
(Switz.).
186 Bundesverfassungsgericht [BVerfG] [Federal Constitutional Court] 1 BvL 21/12,
Dec. 17, 2014, vol. 138, 136, 252-55 (Ger.) (Baer, J., Geier, J. & Masing, J., dissenting).
278 TAX LAW REVIEW [Vol. 72:
interest group of superrich business owners contributed a meaningful
amount to the revenue from inheritance tax, which fell upon a small
residual constituency of high-income professionals owning investment
assets but not business assets. Applying the principle of equal treat-
ment, the Constitutional Court urged the German legislature in 2014
to limit the extent of tax breaks for business gradually, but the court
did not dare challenge the underlying policies in a fundamental
fashion.18 7
A. Nonresident Citizens
1. (No) Taxation
2. Representation
iss Kallergis, note 16, para. 297 (2018); Rutsel Silvestre J. Martha, The Jurisdiction to
Tax in International Law 66-73 (1989) (highlighting the "undesirable" character of nation-
ality-based taxation); F. A. Mann, The Doctrine of International Jurisdiction Revisited Af-
ter 20 Years, in Further Studies in International Law 3, 8-9, 14 (F.A. Mann ed., 1990).
189 Hugh J. Ault & Brian J. Arnold, Comparative Income Taxation 431-34 (3d ed. 2010).
190 Reg. § 1.1-1(a)(1) (2015) ("Section 1 of the Code imposes an income tax on the in-
come of every individual who is a citizen or resident of the United States"); Reg. § 1.1-1(b)
("all citizens of the United States, wherever resident, . . . are liable to the income taxes
imposed by the Code whether the income is received from sources within or without the
United States"). For "accidental Americans," the compatibility of citizenship taxation with
international customary law has been challenged recently. See Allison Christians, A
Global Perspective on Citizenship-Based Taxation, 38 Mich. J. Int'l L. 193, 226-30 (2017).
191 S.C. Res. 2023 ¶1 10-11 (Dec. 5, 2011) (condemning the use of "extortion, threats of
violence, fraud and other illicit means" to enforce their "diaspora tax").
192 Levente Torma, IBFD Tax Research Platform, Hungary-Individual Taxation 2
(2018) (showing the special case of Hungary where citizens are deemed to be resident and
therefore taxable with their worldwide income).
193 Indirect taxes such as the nearly omnipresent value-added tax and specific consump-
tion taxes never carried any link to the citizenship of suppliers or consumers as a personal
quality-these taxes are traditionally levied on the basis of the territorially delineated con-
sumption of goods and services.
280 TAX LAW REVIEW [Vol. 72:
in U.S. federal elections wherever they live. 194 But countries that do
not exercise their right to tax their expatriate citizens have to address
the question of whether these expatriates should have voting rights or
not.
State practice varies hugely in this respect. In a 2011 report, 195 the
European Commission for Democracy through Law (Venice Commis-
sion) laid out that there is no uniform model in place. Many countries
sustain voting rights without time limits irrespective of residence (e.g.,
France, Portugal or Switzerland). Other countries award the franchise
only to people living inside their home country and grant narrow ex-
ceptions from this rule specifically to foreign-based diplomatic and
military personnel (e.g., Ireland and Israel). Most countries apply a
compromise position. In Germany voting rights typically expire
twenty-five years after taking foreign residence, and the United King-
dom applies a similar statute of limitation of fifteen years, as many
British citizens learned the hard way when they were denied a vote in
the Brexit Referendum in June 2016.196
While the overall political consensus favors generous allowance of
out-of-country voting, 197 the courts have, nonetheless, frequently held
in favor of legal constraints on expatriate voting rights. Neither the
European Court of Human Rightsl 98 nor the European Court of Jus-
tice' 99 have forced EU Member States to extend voting rights to citi-
zens living abroad, and this result has been confirmed by domestic
courts. 2 0 0 It has been largely accepted that there must be some leeway
for national legislators to decide when the link between people and
their home country has become so tenuous and weak that they are not
194 For a recent account and critical assessment of U.S. worldwide taxation on the basis
of citizenship, see Ruth Mason, Citizenship Taxation, 89 S. Cal. L. Rev. 169 (2016).
195 Eur. Commission for Democracy through Law (Venice Commission), Report on
Out-of-Country Voting (June 24, 2011), https://www.venice.coe.int/webforms/documents/
default.aspx?pdffile=CDL-AD(2011)022-e.
196 This measure was upheld by the British courts. Shindler and MacLennan v. Chancel-
lor of the Duchy of Lancaster and Secretary of State for Foreign and Commonwealth Af-
fairs [2016] EWHC 957 (Eng.).
197 Report on Out-of-Country Voting, note 195, at para. 92; Rainer Baub6ck, Political
Membership and Democratic Boundaries, The Oxford Handbook of Citizenship 60, 70
(Ayelet Shachar, Rainer Baubock, Irene Bloemraad & Maarten Vink eds., 2017); Rainer
Baubbck, Stakeholder Citizenship and Transnational Political Participation: A Normative
Evaluation of External Voting, 75 Fordham L. Rev. 2393 (2007).
198 Doyle v. The United Kingdom [2007] 45 EHHR SE3; Shindler v. The United King-
dom [2013] 58 EHHR 9. For a critical assessment of this jurisprudence, see Richard Lap-
pin, The Right to Vote for Non-Resident Citizens in Europe, 65 Int'l & Comp. L.Q. 859
(2016).
199 Case 300/04, Eman and Sevinger v. College van burgemeester en wethouders van
Den Haag, 2006 E.C.R. 1-8055 paras. 54-55.
200 R (Preston) v. The Lord President of the Council [2012] EWCA Civ 1378.
2019] TAXATION AND DEMOCRACY 281
sufficiently affected by and knowledgeable about the political deci-
sions to be made at home.
The most recent cause c6l6bre in this field is Frank v. Canada, a
case recently decided by the Supreme Court of Canada on the 1993
elimination of expatriate voting rights (becoming effective five years
after a citizen's emigration). In 2015, in a judgment of the Court of
Appeal for Ontario, 2 0 1 the majority of judges rejected the view that
this limitation infringes upon Section 3 of the Canadian Charter of
Rights and Freedoms, which grants each Canadian citizen the right to
vote. Their judgment goes directly back to the contractarian views of
the state as promoted by Locke and Rousseau:
3. Constitutional Constraints
As a matter of constitutional policy, does it make sense to enable
those who do not pay the tax to decide on its levying and on its spend-
B. Resident Noncitizens
1. Taxation
205 Claudio L6pez-Guerra, Should Expatriates Vote?, 13 J. Pol. Phil. 216 (2005).
206 Baubock, Stakeholder Citizenship, note 197, at 2413; Lappin, note 198, at 881.
207 Baubbck, Stakeholder Citizenship, note 197, at 2446.
208 See, e.g., OECD, Model Tax Convention on Income and on Capital: Condensed Ver-
sion 2017, art. 4, paras. 1-2; Ault, note 189, at 431-34.
2019] TAXATION AND DEMOCRACY 283
Finanzarchiv 1 (1892).
212 Jeremy Waldron, Special Ties and Natural Duties, 22 Phil. & Pub. Aff. 3, 5-7 (1993).
213 Daniel Shaviro, Taxing Potential Community Members, 70 Tax L. Rev. 75, 89-97
(2016).
214 Otmar Bibler, Prinzipien des Internationales Steuerrecht IStR 161 (Internationales
Steuerdokumentationsburo Amsterdam C, 1964); Wolfgang Schon, Persons and Territo-
ries: On the International Allocation of Taxing Rights, 6 Brit. Tax Rev. 554, 555-57 (2010).
215 Ernst Isay, Internationales Finanzrecht 46 (Verlag W. Kohlhammer, 1934); Schanz,
note 211, at 6.
284 TAX LAW REVIEW [Vol. 72:
we are confronted by the original idea of personal political allegiance
or nationality." 2 1 6 Similarly, around this point in time, Article 134 of
the Constitution of the Weimar Republic provided that "all citizens,
without any difference, are obliged to contribute to the public weal
according to their means." 2 17
But this traditional approach, which linked taxability to nationality,
was soon regarded as overly narrow and misleading. 2 18 There was am-
ple reason why resident foreigners, who benefit from public goods in
their country of residence and who compete with local citizens in the
economy, should also bear the burden of public financial needs. 2 1 9
Against this background, taxation of residents was more and more
modeled on the tax treatment of citizens. 220 Since the 1920s, citizen-
ship taxation retreated to the background internationally and resi-
dence taxation took center stage. A review of the literature shows that
the old paradigm has been destroyed so thoroughly that renowned
scholars both inside 22 1 and outside 222 the United States now seem to
regard citizenship as a "proxy" for residence in tax matters, thus turn-
ing the historical trajectory on its head.
Yet unlike most current writers, those scholars, who in the nine-
teenth century advocated the move away from a "contractual" and
benefit-oriented approach to taxation toward an approach shaped by
"membership" and sacrifice, 223 clearly struggled with the fault line be-
tween taxation of citizens and taxation of resident aliens. Ely, who
strongly dismissed the libertarian "contractual" view of taxation in the
case of citizens, maintained it grudgingly for resident aliens:
employed to finance preparing a war against his home state) shows that even the benefit
principle is not easy to apply in this situation.
225 See Whitney v. The Commissioners of Inland Revenue [1924] 538 AC 88 (HL) 112
(appeal taken from Eng.).
226 Schanz, note 211, at 8-9; Waldron, note 212, at 16.
227 Waldron, note 212, at 19.
228 David Miller, Justice for Earthlings 143 (2013).
229 John Rawls, The Law of Peoples 38-39 (1999).
230 Michael Blake, Distributive Justice, State Coercion, and Autonomy, 30 Phil. & Pub.
Aff. 257, 289 (2002).
286 TAX LAW REVIEW [Vol. 72:
matters. 231 But we can address the question of whether the current
technical concept of "residence" under domestic and international tax
law works as a good proxy for belonging to a stable political or social
community. This is not the case. As Ruth Mason has shown, the no-
tion of taxable fiscal presence in a jurisdiction on the basis of resi-
dence covers a diversity of cases, such as students studying abroad,
corporate employees being assigned to a foreign subsidiary, perma-
nent resettlers and "accidental" foreign citizens (who have acquired
citizenship in their country of birth on the basis of ius soli but have
never lived there and may not even know about their citizenship sta-
tus). 2 3 2 It is clear that the strength of the link between these groups
and the local communities they live in varies hugely. Moreover, the
overly broad scope of the definition of fiscal residence under current
tax practice (a "substantial presence test" varying from country to
country) typically doesn't meet the benchmark for deep social "inte-
gration" into a domestic community. If anything, the traditional En-
glish concept of "domicile" seems to be a more adequate proxy as it
makes the tax status of resident aliens dependent on the missing inten-
tion of taxpayers to return to their home country in the future. 233
Against this background, current residence taxation for resident
foreigners as such seems to be a legitimate fiscal tool only on the basis
of the benefit principle. The mere fiscal residence of a (foreign) per-
son is and remains therefore fundamentally different from citizenship
as it denotes not a "personal" or a "political" but a merely "territo-
rial" or "economic" concept that does not easily justify worldwide tax-
ation. 234 This indicates a meaningful lack of congruence in the way
that resident noncitizens are generally taxed.
It is interesting that some jurisdictions have been more generous
toward resident aliens regarding the taxation of foreign income. The
most prominent example is the United Kingdom, which has awarded
major tax benefits to non-domiciled foreign residents for more than
100 years. These only have to pay tax on their worldwide income as
far as this income is remitted to (and probably consumed on) the terri-
231 For a fully fledged move from birthright citizenship to a citizenship based on resi-
dence, see Jacqueline Stevens, State Without Nations: Citizenship for Mortals 73-103
(2010).
232 Mason, note 194, at 196-240.
233 See Jonathan Schwarz, Booth & Schwarz: Residence, Domicile and UK Taxation
(19th ed. 2016).
234 Schan, note 214, at 557; Klaus Vogel, Ober "Besteuerungsrechte" und uber das Leis-
tungsfahigkeitsprinzip im Internationalen Steuerrecht, in Steuerrecht, Verfassungsrecht,
Finanzpolitik: Festschrift far Franz Klein 361 (Paul Kirchhof et al. eds., 1994); Albert Hen-
sel, Steuerrecht 50 (1924) (speaking of a "personal-territorial" link between the state and
the resident taxpayer).
2019] TAXATION AND DEMOCRACY 287
tory of the United Kingdom. 235 A similar regime is applied in Japan
where short-term residents (up to five years) are only taxable on their
domestic income. 2 3 6 Over time, more and more countries have de-
cided to follow suit and to postpone the full effect of worldwide taxa-
tion in regard to foreign nationals who move their residence to a new
home jurisdiction. 237 Most recently, Italy introduced in 2017 a new tax
regime that virtually waives worldwide taxation for a period of fifteen
years for taxpayers who relocate to Italy and who did not reside in
Italy for at least nine years of the ten years preceding taking residence
in Italy.238 This shows that at least some countries have developed a
more sophisticated approach to the alignment of tax liability on a
worldwide basis and the stability of the connection between resident
noncitizens and the country. Where this is the case, congruence is bol-
stered, at least to some extent, through the contraction of taxing
rights. But these approaches are the exception rather than the norm.
2. (No) Representation
235 It should be noted that when modern income tax was introduced to Prussia in 1892,
representatives of the enjoyable Rhine Valley towns pleaded for a similar tax privilege for
rich foreigners taking their retirement homes in Prussia; this was rejected by Minister of
Finance Miquel on several occasions. See Walter Mathiak, Das preupische Einkommen-
steuergesetz von 1891 im Rahmen der Miquelschen Steuerreform 1891/93, at 133-35, 169
(2010).
Ault & Arnold, note 189, at 434.
236
Giorgio Beretta, Mobility of Individuals After BEPS: The Persistent Conflict Be-
237
tween Jurisdictions, 72 Bull. for Int'l Tax'n 439, 442-43 (2018).
238 Giorgio Beretta, From Worldwide to Territorial Taxation: Is Italy Now an Attractive
Destination for Migrating Individuals?, 71 Bull. for Int'l Tax'n 437, 437-43 (2017).
239 Ludvig Beckman, Citizenship and Voting Rights: Should Resident Aliens Vote?, 10
ally Michael Blake & Patrick Smith, International Distributive Justice, Stanford Encyclo-
pedia of Philosophy (Oct. 24, 2013), https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/international-justice/.
"Internationalists" such as Rawls, note 229, at 117, and his followers, most prominently
Thomas Nagel, The Problem of Global Justice, 33 Phil. & Pub. Aff. 113 (2005), are quite
restrictive on this issue and only plead for international "assistance" and "humanitarian"
help. See also David Miller, National Responsibility and Global Justice (2007); Blake, note
230. Among tax lawyers, this distinction has been drawn forcefully by Michael Graetz,
Follow the Money 98-103 (2016). Outside the domestic community, a group of "cosmo-
politans," led by Thomas Pogge, World Poverty and Human Rights (2002), have estab-
lished the view that national boundaries following the concept of citizenship have become
arbitrary and should be abandoned when matters of equality and social justice arise. See
also Ilan Benshalom, The New Poor at Our Gates: Global Justice Implications for Interna-
tional Trade and Tax Law, 85 N.Y.U. Law Rev. 1 (2010); Gillian Brock & Thomas Pogge,
Global Tax Justice and Global Justice, 1 Moral Phil. & Pol. 1 (2014); Peter Dietsch
&
Thomas Rixen, Tax Competition and Global Background Justice, 22 J. Pol. Phil. 150
(2014); Miriam Ronzoni, Global Tax Governance: The Bullets Internationalists Must
Bite-and Those They Must Not, 1 Moral Phil. & Pol. 37 (2014). This debate is not ad-
dressed in this Article.
257 Nagel, note 256, at 120.
258 Michael Blake, Global Distributive Justice: Why Political Philosophy Needs Political
Science, 15 Ann. Rev. Pol. Sci. 121, 131 (2012).
292 TAX LAW REVIEW [Vol. 72:
I submit that it is this complex fact-that we are both pu-
tative joint authors of the coercively imposed system, and
subject to its norms, i.e., expected to accept their authority
even when the collective decision diverges from our personal
preferences-that creates the special presumption against ar-
bitrary inequalities in our treatment by the system. 259
This argument runs into problems that become clearly visible in the
case of the taxation of resident noncitizens. While they do not partici-
pate in the political process, as they are not entitled to vote, they are
still under the same coercive power and under current practice subject
to exactly the same tax burden as domestic citizens. And as long as
"citizens and residents, in all but the most extreme cases, provide the
financial and sociological support required to sustain the state," 2 6 0 it
would be hard to explain, or even cynical to assume, that resident
aliens can be forced without constraints to make those "unrequited
payments" to the state but cannot demand equal treatment by that
state.
This leads us to agree with the opinion expressed by Michael Blake,
that "coercion, not cooperation, seems to be the sine qua non of dis-
tributive justice, making relevant principles of relative deprivation." 2 61
Coauthorship in legislation is not required for the claim for equal-
ity. 2 6 2 It is rather "the shared subjection to a coercive state apparatus
that makes for a morally relevant property that fellow citizens
share." 263 Under these circumstances, the right to equal treatment ap-
plies "among those who share in the provision of the basic collective
goods required to develop and act on a plan of life." 2 6 4
From a constitutional policy perspective, this is the line to take. In
order to avoid any discrimination and exploitation of resident nonci-
tizens being fully taxable in a jurisdiction but deprived of the right to
vote, constitutional law should prohibit any specific tax burden due to
foreign nationality. 265 Rather, as they are not full political members of
the local society and not obliged to equal sacrifice, 2 6 6 they should be
taxed less intrusively than local citizens. Thus, while the treatment of
267 Reuven Avi-Yonah, Globalization, Tax Competition, and the Fiscal Crisis of the Wel-
fare State, 113 Harv. L. Rev. 1573 (2000); Philipp Genschel, Globalization, Tax Competi-
tion, and the Welfare State, 30 Pol. & Soc. 245 (2002); Hans-Werner Sinn, The Selection
Principle and Market Failure in Systems Competition, 66 J. Pub. Econ. 247 (1997).
268 Dietsch & Rixen, note 256, at 150-56; Ronzoni, note 256, at 37.
269 Keen & Konrad, note 27.
294 TAX LAW REVIEW [Vol. 72:
tion"270 or the assessment of "aggressive" tax planning by multina-
tional companies. 271 In this respect there is a growing consensus
among states led by international and supranational bodies such as the
G20, the OECD, and the European Union to outlaw some extreme
tax-saving options like tailor-made preferential regimes or tax ar-
rangements devoid of economic reality. But this development has not
fundamentally changed the playing field. It remains undisputed that
countries are still free to define their tax bases and the applicable tax
rates. They are in no way hampered in competing for outside invest-
ment and in particular attracting bona fide business activities. This is
the background for the recent new wave of reductions of corporate
tax rates by the current governments of major countries such as the
United Kingdom and the United States. Moreover, we see a growing
tendency by countries to offer attractive tax packages to "Olympic cit-
izens," 272 high-net-worth individuals, and high-skilled labor.2 7 3 Such
tax reductions will generally force those generous governments either
to shrink the public sector or to increase other taxes or to take on
additional public debt. These competitive moves are not only in line
with international standards after the BEPS Action Plan implemented
by the G20 and OECD and EU law requirements, they are also meant
to put pressure on other governments, most notably on the Member
States of the European Union,2 7 4 to adjust their fiscal policies.
What does this mean for the balance between majoritarian democ-
racy and individual rights in the tax area? The outcome is mixed. We
observe both improvements and distortions of the democratic process
on tax legislation. For taxpayers who are mobile, democratic process
may actually be improved by tax competition (and the mobility it pre-
supposes). For taxpayers who are immobile, the story is a darker one
and invites again the question about the desirability of material consti-
tutional constraints.
270 OECD, Harmful Tax Competition: An Emerging Issue (1998). For the
grounding of
mutual obligations between states to follow certain rules of "sound" tax competition in
political philosophy, see Allison Christians, Sovereignty, Taxation, and Social Contract, 18
Minn. J. Int'l L. 99 (2009).
271 OECD, G20 Base Erosion and Profit Shifting Project, 2015 Final Reports.
272 Ayelet Shachar, Picking Winners: Olympic Citizenship and the Global
Race for Tal-
ent, 120 Yale L.J. 2088, 2117 (2011).
273 Allison Christians, Buying In: Residence and Citizenship by Investment, 62 St.
Louis
U. L.J. 51, 52 (2017).
274 Sch6n, note 30.
2019] TAXATION AND DEMOCRACY 295
tax jurisdiction can be modeled following Albert 0. Hirschman's fa-
mous trinity of exit, voice, and loyalty. 275 A minority of taxpayers
whose fiscal preferences can be suppressed by majority rule but who
are not constrained by strong loyalty to their country can use the exit
route in order to escape adverse conditions in their home state, either
by shifting residence to another country or by moving investment
outside the jurisdiction.
Given the fact that constitutional constraints for tax legislation are
either weak or nonexistent in many countries, the exit option can sub-
stitute for material controls. Tax competition can then work as a limi-
tation on the expropriation of the rich minority by the poor majority.
Importantly, mobile taxpayers need not actually move. It is the mere
threat of migration that can constrain domestic tax policy.
This is particularly relevant for the progressivity of the tax rates on
income, inheritance, and net wealth, which is hardly regulated by con-
stitutional law. For example, the special 75% tax on high-income earn-
ers introduced in France in 2012 was condoned by the French Conseil
Constitutionnel in 2013.276 This surtax on the regular income tax was
nonetheless repealed in 2015, as it turned out that the amount of reve-
nue was negligible, while the threat of emigration by high-net-worth
individuals was serious. 2 7 7 In Germany, the question of whether con-
stitutional law prohibits an income tax rate above 50% has been dis-
cussed ad nauseam both by tax scholars and constitutional lawyers
since the invention of the "half-income limitation" by the Constitu-
tional Court in 1995,278 but not a single tax assessment has been struck
down on the basis of this half-income principle. Tax competition, on
the other hand, drove down the corporate income tax rate from 56%
in 1988 to 15% less than twenty years later. The top income tax rate
fell during the same period from 56% to 47%, including a surtax for
high-income earners ("Reichensteuer") and the "solidarity surcharge"
on the income tax introduced in the course of German reunifica-
tion. 279 Countries such as the United States and the United Kingdom,
where no meaningful constitutional constraints to the tax burden seem
to exist, have embarked on an even more substantial lowering of the
corporate tax burden, following Ireland's example where a 12.5% tax
0
rate has proved to be highly attractive over many years.28 It is not
280 As of 2018, the federal corporate tax rate in the United States has been reduced from
35% to 21%. In the United Kingdom, the corporate tax rate is announced to be reduced to
296 TAX LAW REVIEW [Vol. 72:
unreasonable to assume that without tax competition in place, the bal-
ance of powers between majority and minority in the democratic fiscal
state might be tilted substantially more toward the majority.
17% by 2020. See IRC § 11; HM Revenues & Customs, Rates and allowances: Corporation
Tax, https://www.gov.uk/government/publications/rates-and-allowances-corporation-tax/
rates-and-allowances-corporation-tax (last visited March 11, 2019).
281 See generally Ulli Konrad, Gleichheit und Differentiation: Die Duale Einkommen-
doms by the European Court of Justice. See Case C-513/03, Heirs of M.E.A. van Hilten-
van der Heijden v. Inspecteur van de Belastingdienst, 2006 E.C.R. 1-1981 para. 44.
298 Wolfgang Schon, Steuerstaat und Freiziigigkeit, in Steuer- und Sozialstaat im
europtischen Systemwettbewerb 41 (Ulrich Becker & Wolfgang Sch6n eds., 2005).
299 Id. at 175-80.
300 John Rawls, A Theory of Justice 75 (1971).
2019] TAXATION AND DEMOCRACY 301
of this change of paradigm, however, may be diminished if we expand
the analysis to consider compensating tax treatment across countries.
A case in point is limited tax liability. Foreign taxpayers who are
only taxable in a country on the basis of inbound investment and local
business activities might reject demands of solidarity with the local
fiscal community since they are neither members of the territorially
defined social organism nor in a political sense citizens of that state.
They will simply regard source taxation as a price to pay for setting up
shop. But still, foreign taxpayers will be fully taxable in their state of
residence where principles of worldwide taxation and progressivity of
the tax rate will be applied. The fact that the requirements of social
justice do not apply to them in the source state can be accepted under
the requirements of social justice if and to the extent they are fully
taxable in another state. Residence taxation then works like a back-
3 01
stop to secure "onetime taxation" under a fully progressive tax rate.
On the other hand, the state of residence is in the position to grant tax
reliefs that are perceived to be adequate from the point of social jus-
tice. 302 In a similar vein, a state's complaint about a taxpayer's moving
out of the country is less forceful if and to the extent the taxpayer
becomes subject to fiscal obligations in another state, trading one tax
community for another without drastically reducing the overall tax
burden.
This raises the question of whether it should be ensured that a per-
son is taxable at least in one state in full. In recent years, this problem
has been raised by the G20/BEPS process on international business
303 But
taxation whenever "stateless" income seemed to go untaxed.
the issue was recognized as early as 1888 by Ely who found that full
taxation of resident aliens might be good policy in order to ensure that
people could not free themselves from unlimited tax liability for good
by emigrating from their country of citizenship without fully integrat-
ing into the country of residence. Writing like a "cosmopolitan" politi-
cal philosopher avant la lettre he referred to this as a general matter of
humanity: "It may be further urged that a man owes certain duties to
humanity, and if he fails to discharge the offices of citizenship at
home, it is ethically allowable for a foreign government, which can lay
its hands on him, to force him to do his part towards the support of
304
government."
While the spirit of this position is laudable as long as taxpayers have
not committed themselves to a certain fiscal community it is hard to
VII. CONCLUSION
The congruence of voting on tax legislation, payment of taxes, and
the enjoyment of public expenditure is today more myth than reality,
even in countries with the strongest democratic commitments. Al-
though such congruence may well have been a robust possibility when
Locke articulated a theory of taxation grounded in taxpayer consent,
the expansion of the franchise domestically and the mobility of indi-
viduals and capital globally have continually eroded congruence over
the last three centuries. This invites the pressing question of whether
material constitutional constraints are warranted in order to protect
taxpayer interests.
Within the Hobbesian tradition of content-based protection, such
constitutional constraints are a natural fit and are, indeed, observed in
many jurisdictions across the world that have historically endorsed the
Hobbesian notion of the primacy of the state. At least in the domestic
sphere, I have argued here that there are solid grounds on which to
adopt such constraints within the Lockean consent-based tradition as
well, though the key adherents to that tradition have not, to date,
taken that path.
In the international sphere matters are more complicated. Some-
times one encounters the migration of individuals for nontax reasons,
leading to an erosion of congruence. In this case, I have also argued in
2019] TAXATION AND DEMOCRACY 303
favor of material constitutional constraints. The case of resident
noncitizens is central to this claim. At present, such individuals fre-
quently are liable to tax on worldwide income to a polity in which they
cannot vote. One could cure such defect by enhancing congruence,
either by curtailing taxing rights or by expanding the franchise. Given
that each of these approaches is flawed, the adoption of material con-
stitutional constraints to protect the interests of resident noncitizens is
justified and of a piece with long-standing constitutional commitments
to protect minority interests in liberal democracies.
Once one comes to the problem of tax competition and the issue of
tax-motivated movement of capital and labor, however, the domestic
constitutional well would seem to run dry. Tax competitive forces can
clearly lead to disproportionate burdens being borne by relatively im-
mobile taxpayers. The deep problem here, though, is that domestic
constitutional provisions are no more resistant to the relentless forces
of globalization than are day-to-day nonconstitutional legislative prac-
tice. Absent material constraints at the supranational level, the adop-
tion of constitutional constraints here would seem doomed to failure
as a practical matter.
304 TAX LAW REVIEW