Horace's Satires - A Moral Purpose - A Literary Game - Jerome Kemp
Horace's Satires - A Moral Purpose - A Literary Game - Jerome Kemp
Horace's Satires - A Moral Purpose - A Literary Game - Jerome Kemp
4
Author(s): JEROME KEMP
Source: The Classical World, Vol. 104, No. 1 (FALL 2010), pp. 59-76
Published by: The Johns Hopkins University Press on behalf of the Classical Association of
the Atlantic States
Stable URL: https://www.jstor.org/stable/25799971
Accessed: 09-10-2018 15:50 UTC
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
The Johns Hopkins University Press, Classical Association of the Atlantic States are
collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to The Classical World
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Tue, 09 Oct 2018 15:50:21 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
A Moral Purpose, A Literary Game:
Horace, Satires 1.4
ABSTRACT: In Satires 1.4 we are apparently shown Horace's views on the
purpose of satire and its status as a literary genre. His possible irony and
the extent to which he should be taken at face value (a long-standing source
of debate are) are addressed here with particular reference to Aristotelian
and Philodeman influence. This recently analyzed influence is reappraised
and challenged with regard to its extent and implication. But first I look at
the moral purpose?or otherwise?of Horatian satire as expressed in 1.4.
59
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Tue, 09 Oct 2018 15:50:21 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
60 JEROME KEMP
be more accurate to say that the joke, the irony of the satirist's
persona (by turns glib, hypocritical: in 1.2 sexually obsessive and
adulterous [at 1.2.126-34] in 1.3 inconsistent)4 in fact enhances the
philosophical content?to some extent as an ironic living example of
the particular folly under attack. If the philosophical element in the
Satires is largely dismissed because of its lack of seriousness, then
the Satires' irony (and thus piquancy) is also diminished.5
From 1.4.103 to the end Horace describes his satirical method,
underlining the importance of satire's moral function. He shows how
laughing at folly can serve a serious moral purpose, so explaining
the link between satire and ethics. Two examples follow depicting
his father giving advice through the observation of people's folly. The
first involves the vice of prodigality, brought up previously in Satires
1.2.7-11, and, in terms of the resultant Epicurean advice (as presented
by Horace) of living within one's means, in Satires 1.1 and 1.2 more
generally;6 the second brings to mind Horace's own advice in 1.2:
... a turpi meretricis amore
cum deterreret, "Scetani dissimilis sis":
ne sequerer moechas concessa cum Venere uti
possem, "deprensi non bella est fama Treboni". . . .
(111-114)
when he was warning me against a shameful passion
for a prostitute, "Don't copy Scetanus," or against
chasing after adulterous wives when I could indulge
in a permissible liaison, "Trebonius was caught in the
act and you wouldn't want his reputation."7
to ethics. Mayer ("Sleeping with the Enemy: Philosophy and Satire," in K. Freudenburg,
ed., The Cambridge Companion to Roman Satire [Cambridge 2005] 146-59) again
inclines to discount the importance of the philosophical content in Horace's Satires.
Rudd ("Horace as Moralist," in N. Rudd, ed., Horace 2000: A Celebration: Essays for
the Bimillenium [London 1993] 64-88), takes a similar line to Mayer with regard to
philosophical material in Horace, somewhat modifying his position from 1966. As to
the claim that the Epistles are about life, not philosophy, J. Moles ("Poetry, philosophy,
politics and play. Epistles 1," in A. Woodman and D. Feeney, eds., Traditions and
Contexts in the Poetry of Horace, (Cambridge 2002) 141-57), essentially in agreement
with Macleod, rightly says: "The dichotomy is false. The Epistles are recte vivere as
interpreted by different philosophies" (149). See D. Fowler, "Lectures on Horace's
Epistles;' PCPS (2008) 99-102. J. Moles ("Philosophy and Ethics," in S. Harrison, ed.,
The Cambridge Companion to Horace [Cambridge 2007] 165-80), further explains the
significance of the philosophical content in Horace's works.
4 On the ironic inconsistency of the narrator in Sat. 1.3, see Kemp (above, n.2).
5 See Fowler (above, n.3) 101, on Horace's ironic, changeable philosophical
positioning, and underlying philosophical seriousness in Epist. 1.
6 . . . intra/naturae finis viventi (1.49-50). This suggests, in Epicurean terms,
living according to the fulfilment of desires that are natural and necessary, or merely
natural: Ep. Men. 127.
7 As Brown (above, n.l) 137 rightly notes, his father does not disapprove of
his son using a prostitute, but of his shameful passion (1.4.111). This distinction is
further reinforced by the fact that in his warning against the pursuit of married
women, he suggests seeking gratification that would be permissible, and which could
reasonably include (as in 1.2) a meretrix.
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Tue, 09 Oct 2018 15:50:21 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
A MORAL PURPOSE, A LITERARY GAME: HORACE, SATIRES 1.4 61
8 See Epicurus Ep. Men. 128; RS 15, 21. Although the context here points to
Epicureanism, the notion of choice and avoidance also appears in Aristotle (Top.
5.6. 135M5, De motu an. 8. 701b34, Eth. Nic. 3.12 1119a22, Rh. 1.5 1360b5), and
Stoicism (SVF 3.24, 62, 88, 118, 262).
9 The thought here is very similar, in fact, to one expressed in Rep. (1.2),
where Cicero maintains that one can come to the same ethical conclusions, through
practical (non-theoretical) experience, as philosophers do through theoretical argu
ment. Horace is also highlighting the notion of Roman wisdom passed down through
the generations (116-117)?as he does in Sat. 2.2, when relating Ofellus' precepts.
10 E. W. Leach, "Horace's Pater Optimus and Terence's Demea: autobiographical
fiction and comedy in Serm. 1.4," AJP (1971) 616-32.
11 A. Cucchiarielli (La Satira e il Poeta: Orazio tra Epodi e Sermones [Pisa
2001]) recognizes the parallel with Terence, though rightly does not regard this as
necessarily undermining the passage's serious moral purpose (109, n.88). See also
W. S. Anderson, Essays on Roman Satire (Princeton 1982) 53-56, and D. Armstrong
Horace (New Haven 1989) 2-4.
12 R. L. Hunter ("Horace on Friendship and Free Speech," Hermes 113 [1985]
480-90) sees liber amicus as suggestive of the Epicurean and in particular Philode
man practice of frank speech?naQQ^uia?which Philodemus discusses (in On Frank
Speech and On Flattery) in relation to amicitia. For example: "Let us make it clear to
them that the goods of friendship are very durable and that flattery is the antagonist
of friendship; let us also consider well the goods that arise from frank speech, both
directed towards one's intimate associates and directed towards all men, and let us
avoid as vain the company of adulators, and still more let us not mix with them but
seek the fellowship of those who speak candidly." PHerc. 1082 (col.2.1-14), which
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Tue, 09 Oct 2018 15:50:21 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
62 Jerome Kemp
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Tue, 09 Oct 2018 15:50:21 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
A MORAL PURPOSE, A LITERARY GAME: HORACE, SATIRES 1.4 63
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Tue, 09 Oct 2018 15:50:21 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
64 Jerome Kemp
II. Satire and Its Moral Constraints
The moral function of Horatian satire is not only in keeping with
Horace's praise of his father (even if ironically tempered by the nod
to New Comedy) as one who observed social behavior and from this
drew moral lessons, but it is also in keeping with the practice in
Old Comedy, and Lucilius, of lampooning certain individuals whose
behavior warrants such ridicule, as put in the opening lines:
Eupolis atque Cratinus Aristophanesque poetae,
atque alii quorum comoedia prisca virorum est,
si quis erat dignus describi quod malus ac fur,
quod moechus foret aut sicarius aut alioqui
famosus, multa cum libertate notabant.
hinc omnis pendet Lucilius . . . (1.4.1-6)
The poets Eupolis, Cratinus and Aristophanes, and
other exponents of Old Comedy, had this habit: if
anyone deserved to be noted down for being a villain
and a thief, for being an adulterer or an assassin or
otherwise infamous, they would show great freedom
of speech in branding him. On them Lucilius depends
totally. . . .
However, later on at 1.4.34-38 Horace depicts the satirist (and
thus himself) being criticized for going too far for the sake of a laugh:
perhaps this kind of humor is not always warranted. In response to
this Horace puts forward his views regarding the appropriate use of
humor in an ethical light. The depiction of the humorist at 34-38
(that Horace might be accused of being) in fact appears to represent
just what Horace would disapprove of?the implication being that
Horace is certainly nothing like the type thus described:
. . . dummodo risum
excutiat, sibi non, non cuiquam parcet amico;
et quodcumque semel chartis illeverit, omnis
gestiet a furno redeuntis scire lacuque,
et pueros et anus. (1.4.34-38)
As long as he extracts a laugh, he won't spare himself,
he won't spare any friend; and whatever he's once
scrawled on his pages he'll be itching for everyone
to know as they return from the bakehouse and the
water tank, both slave-boys and old women.
As G. L. Hendrickson first noted, this appears to be an ad
of a view found in Aristotle's portrait of the (3o)u6Aoxog, buff
in Nicomachean Ethics 1128a4-7:23
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Tue, 09 Oct 2018 15:50:21 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
a Moral Purpose, a Literary Game: Horace, Satires 1.4 65
ol [xkv ouv to) yeAoiCf) U7i?q|3dAAovT?<; |3a)|aoA6xoi
Sokouctiv eivai Kal cpoQTiKoi, yAixoLievoi navTcog
tou yeAolou, Kal LidAAov axoxctCoLievoL tou yeAcoxa
7ioLfjaaL f] tou Aeyeiv euoxn^ova Kal far] AutceIv tov
aKuj7ix6|Li?vov. (1128a4-7)
Those then who go to excess in ridicule are thoug
to be buffoons and vulgar fellows, who itch to ha
their joke at all costs, and are more concerned to rai
a laugh than to keep within the bounds of decoru
and avoid giving pain to the object of their raillery.
This characterization of |3a)|aoAoxux or scurrilitas?o
who knows no bounds in his quest for laughs?may well
from the Peripatetics to Panaetius,25 in that it appears in
In fact, the depiction of someone laughing behind someon
Off. 1.134 is similar to Horace's depiction at 1.4.81-89 of
"humorist" he advises people to be wary of?rather than
satirist, like himself: absentem qui rodit amicum, qui n
culpante ("The man who disparages a friend behind hi
fails to defend him against someone else's criticisms,"
tu, Romane, caveto ("Of him, true Roman, pray bewar
From these Ciceronian parallels, it is likely that suc
appropriateness and limits in humor draw from a traditio
to Aristotle's criticisms of |3a)|aoAoxux in Nicomachean Et
The role of the satirist thus concerns matters of conduct
to ethics. And this is enhanced by the fact that the sat
ticular Horace?regards moral instruction as part of satire's
If Horace (or any other satirist for that matter) takes it u
to lampoon others' behavior on ethical grounds, then he
care that in doing so he himself is not exceeding the li
mined by reasonable conduct.
There is a tension, however, in Horace's position.
Aristotelian theory this kind of low humor (pcojaoAox
34-38 and 83-89, is aligned with the kind found in Old
opposed to the subtler brand of humor found in the Ne
Nicomachean Ethics 1128a20-24:
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Tue, 09 Oct 2018 15:50:21 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
66 Jerome Kemp
l&oi b' dv xig Kai ck xdrv kwuco&lcov xoov 7iaAaicov Kal
xdrv Kaivcov- xoig uev ydp f]v yeAolov r] alaxQoAoyia,
xoic; be udAAov rj u7i6voia- biacpeqei b' ou uikqov
xauxa tcqoc; ?uaxr)uoauvnv.
And one can see [the difference] in the case of com
edies, the old and the new. For in the case of old
comedies, obscenity was a source of laughter, while
for the new it is, rather, innuendo. These things differ
greatly in regard to suitable behavior.27
And Horace, having begun the satire by implicitly siding himself,
and explicitly Lucilius, with libertas?outspokenness, and the comic
tradition that goes back to Eupolis, Cratinus, and Aristophanes28?
then goes on to put scurrilitas/|3couoAoxux, (which Aristotle sees as
a trait of Old Comedy) in an unfavorable light.
Since support of libertas and Old Comedy on the one hand, and
the disapproval of it, via Aristotle's views on pcouoAoxux represented
at 1.4.34-38 and 81-89, on the other, appears to be an inconsistent
position, Hendrickson argued that Horace was actually distancing
himself from this comic tradition, and thus also from the satire of
Lucilius.29 Hendrickson regarded Horace's alignment of Lucilius with
Old Comedy in the opening lines as suggesting that Lucilius' brand
of humor was closer to that of the scurra or pcouoAoxog, in line with
Nicomachean Ethics 1128a. But while Lucilian humor was certainly
less subtle and more flagrantly critical of individuals, it does not
necessarily follow that Horace wholeheartedly sees Old Comedy and
Lucilian satire under the same umbrella as pcouoAoxia; the paral
lels drawn between Horace's depictions at 1.4.34-38 and 81-89 and
those found in Aristotle and Cicero are certainly convincing, but
need it automatically follow that Horace would adhere to Aristote
lian theory quite that assiduously? In fact, Freudenburg has accepted
the interpretation that Horace adopts an Aristotelian view regarding
the practice of comedy, but has also rightly maintained that Horace
remains loyal to the tradition of Lucilian humor and Old Comedy.30
Freudenburg looks into these two opposing theories regard
ing comedy: the Peripatetic (represented by New Comedy) and?as
Freudenburg puts it?the iambographic, (from Lau|3iCto, to lampoon,
rather than necessarily denoting metrical form) represented by Old
Comedy31?and notes that the latter, through its continuation in
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Tue, 09 Oct 2018 15:50:21 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
A MORAL PURPOSE, A LITERARY GAME: HORACE, SATIRES 1.4 67
Iambic poetry, and the Cynics and the diatribe, would have been a
recognized rival to Aristotelian theory in the Hellenistic period and
up until Horace's time.32 Thus the idea that the allusion to Aristote
lian theory on (3co[aoAoxia shows an absolute adherence to it starts to
become questionable: Horace sees value in both comedic approaches.
Freudenburg maintains that Horace takes on both traditions and thus
makes "a unique contribution to ancient theories of poetic libertas"
even though the combination of these traditions?because they ought
to be irreconcilable?is "impossible and absurd."33 Although he argues
convincingly for the existence of this hybrid, Horatian theory, the
interrelation between its two antithetical, constituent parts?as put
into practice in Horatian satire?is not fully explained.
The key to this interrelation is indicated at the start of the poem:
that those who are liable to outspoken criticism from the Old Comic
poets are wrongdoers; lampooning those who deserve such treatment
is justified (a point Horace discusses with regard to himself and Lu
cilius at 2.1.24-42). But to lampoon the undeserving, and to do so
merely for the sake of a laugh (that is, without any moral purpose)
is clearly wrong, as exemplified in the two recognizably Aristotelian/
Ciceronian depictions of (3co|aoAoxia at 1.4.34-38 and 81-89. Freud
enburg considers the moral justification and function in the tradition
of Old Comedy and lampoon to show that it can be recognized as a
rival to Aristotelian theory;34 but the important point here is that it is
this moral function, in terms of its practical application to Horatian
satire, which affords its compatibility with Aristotelian theory: it is
the moral function of satire, the major theme of 1.4, as personally
experienced by the satirist himself (first through his father, then
through his liberi amici, and indeed himself [131-138]), which enables
Horace to use lampoon correctly, appropriately within Aristotelian
limits. Clearly, the tradition of invective practiced in Old Comedy
and continued through the Cynics would be theoretically more suited
to satire than the gentler, more impersonal approach propounded by
Aristotle. Horace therefore uses Aristotelian theory to set ethical
limits to a form of comedy which, in its very essence, is opposed to
such Aristotelian theory. This conflict is deliberate: on the one hand
satire has to exercise libertas to be effective, but when the use of
such libertas concerns moral advice and reproof, then it must itself
be subjected to moral constraints, and this is indicated by Horace's
application of Aristotelian theory. Thus these two theoretically ir
reconcilable traditions can, in the practical context of Horatian satire,
121-41) that 1.4 is programmatic, in that from then on Horace abandons Lucilian
invective and the tradition of Old Comedy for a gentler Aristotelian approach, could
to some extent still stand, bearing in mind the fact that the Epodes were likely to
have been composed before 1.4. But to reject the tradition of Old Comedy totally,
in favor of the Peripatetic theory and New Comedy, given the Epodes and Sat. 1.2,
seems to be an unlikely (and very obliquely implied) U-turn. Also, at 1.10.16-17,
Horace openly praises Old Comedy.
32 Freudenburg (above, n.21) 72-86.
33 Freudenburg (above, n.21) 107-108.
34 Freudenburg (above, n.21) 72-86.
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Tue, 09 Oct 2018 15:50:21 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
68 JEROME KEMP
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Tue, 09 Oct 2018 15:50:21 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
a Moral Purpose, a literary Game: Horace, Satires l .4 69
here as simply pointing out generic differences within poetry.37 There
have recently been, however, two studies?by Oberhelman and Arm
strong, and by Freudenburg38?which interpret the passage 1.39-62
as strongly indicating that Horace does in fact regard his satire as
true poetry (iustum . . . poema, 63), and both studies refer to liter
ary theory, in Aristotle and Philodemus, to support their arguments.
Perhaps not surprisingly the introduction to the discussion of the
literary/poetic status of satire is illogical. In response to the state
ment "all these fear verses and hate poets" (omnes hi metuunt versus,
odere poetas, 33), Horace claims, illogically, that he is exempt from
such hatred because he is not a poet: all those who hate poets do
not, in fact, hate poets as Horace apparently understands the term;
they hate satirists. And Horace certainly is a satirist.39
This illogical basis to his line of defense should perhaps warn
the reader of the doubtful seriousness and rationale behind Horace's
apparent claims about the literary status of his own satire. Ober
helman and Armstrong make the fair point at the outset that one
should be guarded in taking Horace at face value.40 They then go on
to draw attention to the fact that in the opening lines of the satire
Horace labels Eupolis, Cratinus, and Aristophanes as poets, so as
to strengthen their argument that Horace would thus (in belonging
to this comedy/satire tradition) see himself as a poet; and again, at
the end of the poem, Horace refers to himself as one of the manus
poetarum (141).41
But why should one take the opening lines, or line 140-41, at
their surface level, though not the discussion (some twenty-three lines)
at 39-62? Indeed, simply following the run of the satire, it seems
that Horace refers to Aristophanes et al. as poets at the beginning,
since that is how they would have been generally regarded, but then
questions labeling them (and himself) as such later on, when he can
address the question both in more detail and in a broader context.
Indeed, it could be that Horace deliberately refers to the writers of
Old Comedy as poets at the beginning almost to prompt the discus
sion of considering their status as such at 45-62. And again, at the
end of the satire, when Horace refers to himself as one of the "band
of poets," it may be reasonable to regard this as Horace again us
ing the word poeta in its broadest sense?that is, bearing in mind
the preceding discussion from 39-62 which, for the time being, has
been deferred:
37 So Brown (above, n.l) 131: "The real object of the passage is to distinguish
between grand poetry, like epic, and less elevated poetry, like comedy and satire."
38 Freudenburg (above, n.21) 119-28; Oberhelman and Armstrong (above, n.18)
233-54.
39 Fraenkel (above, n.36) 127 comments, "This whole section is clearly marked
as a digression." C. Schlegel ("Horace and his Fathers: Satires 1.4 and 1.6," AJP 121
[2000] 97) and Freudenburg (above, n.21) 119 comment on the illogicality.
40 Oberhelman and Armstrong (above, n.l8) 235.
41 Oberhelman and Armstrong (above, n.l8) 239.
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Tue, 09 Oct 2018 15:50:21 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
70 JEROME KEMP
42 Oberhelman and Armstrong (above, n.18) 240-44; they also note the subjunc
tives dixeris, putes, des, and excerpam (1.4.39-42), which could suggest that these
statements here ought to be taken as theoretical and not necessarily representing
Horace's real view.
43 Oberhelman and Armstrong (above, n.18) 242.
44 Oberhelman and Armstrong (above, n.18) 240.
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Tue, 09 Oct 2018 15:50:21 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
A Moral Purpose, A Literary Game: Horace, Satires 1.4 71
pattern of the quantities and rhythm and put the
earlier words later, interchanging first and last, you
wouldn't find?as you would if you broke up "when
once dread Discord broke open War's iron-clad posts
and portals"?the limbs of even a dismembered poet.
It is notable, however, that Anderson (to whom Oberhelman and
Armstrong refer) has suggested that the elisions in line 39 are de
liberately awkward?the satirist (me) being as it were drowned out
by the epic poets (illorum)?and in fact serve to imply Horace's
relative inferiority.45 So the virtuosity of Horace's word placement
may rather be a means to enhancing his somewhat self-deprecating
surface argument.
The consequent claim that the Ennius quotation at 60-62 fur
ther backs up the implied undercutting meaning of the elisions (as
Oberhelman and Armstrong interpret them) and that the underlying
implication in these lines is that word order is important for good
poetry is also questionable. They suggest that the Ennius quotation
is not really notably "poetic": "There is not a single 'poetic' word
in the quotation, while the word order is that of standard Ciceronian
prose!"46 According to the surface argument, however, the regularity
or otherwise of the word order is not what makes these lines of En
nius poetry. The quotation is, surely, poetic because it is a striking
metaphorical allusion, Belli ferratos postis portasque refregit allud
ing to the custom that the temple of Janus was opened at times of
war.47 So in fact the allusion would have had a particular resonance
for a Roman readership; indeed Vergil thought it striking enough to
borrow at Aeneid 7.622.48 In its power and simplicity it stands (in the
run of the narrative) as an example of Ennius' ingenium, his mens
divinior, and the potency of the metaphor will more or less remain
whatever the word order. Therefore, the implication of the Ennius
quotation can in fact be seen as support for Horace's surface argument
and adds weight to W. S. Anderson's interpretation of the elisions
at the beginning of the passage, rather than that of Oberhelman
and Armstrong. Certainly, we can accept that Horace's adept word
placement raises questions in the passage 39-62, but in assessing
the implications of this it may be that Oberhelman and Armstrong
have attempted to define the purpose of Horace's irony too exactly.49
Oberhelman and Armstrong then set these observations on Hor
ace's word order in the context of Philodeman literary theory?in
particular Philodemus' views on poetry and matathesis. Metathesis
(the rearrangement of words) as a method of poetic criticism was
a way of assessing style: the way in which (and extent to which)
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Tue, 09 Oct 2018 15:50:21 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
72 JEROME KEMP
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Tue, 09 Oct 2018 15:50:21 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
A MORAL PURPOSE, A LITERARY GAME: HORACE, SATIRES 1.4 73
the position that the function of poetry should be both moral and aesthetic (unlike
Horace at Ars. P.: 99-100; 333-34; 343-44.), it appears that he did not actually oppose
it: in C. Po. 5, col.i [iv] 1-21 (Jensen [1923] and Mangoni [1993]) Philodemus says that
poetry can be morally instructive, or not. Also on Philodemus and the moral content
of poetry, see E. Asmis, "Philodemus on Censorship, Moral Utility and Formalism in
Poetry," D. Obbink, ed., Philodemus and Poetry (Oxford 1995) 155; and see above, n.15.
56 Translated by Freudenburg (above, n.21) 121; Freudenburg also refers to
Aristotle to make a similar point to that of Oberhelman and Armstrong concerning
metathesis: at Poet. 1451a30-35 Aristotle discusses the importance of the unity of all
the parts (xa |ieor|) and how rearrangement or removal of one part affects the whole.
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Tue, 09 Oct 2018 15:50:21 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
74 Jerome Kemp
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Tue, 09 Oct 2018 15:50:21 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
A MORAL PURPOSE, A LITERARY GAME: HORACE, SATIRES 1.4 75
Also, the surface argument in Horace that meter is not the defin
ing characteristic of poetry (39-41) is also to be found in Aristotle
(as Freudenburg notes, to point out that uiunaic; is the defining
characteristic),62 and it seems that the view that comedy was not,
strictly, poetry, because of its closeness to colloquial speech, was
not uncommon. C. O. Brink draws attention to a passage in Cicero
(Orat. 67), where it is noted that Plato and Democritus are regarded
by some as more poetic, because of their style and rhythm, than the
verse of comedy, which is so close to everyday speech.63 Freuden
burg stresses that Cicero then goes on to comment that poets have
greater freedom in fashioning and joining words together (Orat. 68),
and takes this as Cicero's claim that compositio (the fashioning and
arrangement of words) is poetry's defining characteristic.64 But this
does not effectively detract from the previous remarks discrediting
comedy as poetry. It suggests, rather, that Cicero regards compositio
as another important, perhaps more important factor in poetry and
indeed as such some comedy, at least, and Lucilian satire (given
Horace's criticism of Lucilius' style)?being so close to everyday
speech?could still be regarded as not true poetry.
Thus Horace's surface argument can still essentially hold. While
his apparent assertion that he is not himself a true poet (at least not
yet) can be interpreted as rather extreme and thus somewhat disin
genuous, the distinction being made between comedy and satire, and
poetry of the grand style (epic, tragedy, and lyric), is real enough,
and Horace may even be ironically hinting that Aristotle's stress on
the importance of uiurjaig is itself somewhat extreme.
Although the arguments of Freudenburg and of Oberhelman and
Armstrong supporting the presence of Aristotelian and Philodeman
literary theory to determine Horace's position regarding the literary
categorization of satire (particularly his own), are both enlightening
and in some respects convincing, their resultant conclusions?that
Horace is wholly asserting that as a satirist he is indeed a true poet?
are too definitive. The fact that Horace can be taken in several ways
with regard to his possible irony, or at face value, and with regard to
Macro., Sat. 2.7. Also, on the possible influence of scenarios from mime on Ho
race's Satires (the adulterer escaping at 1.2.126-134, the witchcraft scene in 1.8) see
E. Fantham "mime," in OCD, rev. 3rd ed. (2003) 982, and on Laberius, 809.
62 Arist. Poet. 1, 1447M5; 9,1451b27.
63 Cic. Orat. 67: Itaque video visum esse nonnullis Platonis et Democriti lo
cutionem, etsi absit a versu, tamen, quod incitatius feratur et clarissimis verborum
luminibus utatur, potius poema putandum quam comicorum poetarum, apud quos,
nisi quod versiculi sunt, nihil est aliud cotidiani dissimile sermonis ("For that reason
some, I know, have held that the language of Plato and Democritus, which, though
not in verse, has a vigorous movement and uses striking stylistic ornaments, has
more right to be considered poetry than has comedy, which differs from ordinary
conversation only by being in some sort of verse") G. L. Hendrickson, Cicero: Bru
tus; Orator, H. M. Hubbell tr. (Cambridge, Mass. and London, 1939): Brink (above,
n.21) 162-63; also cited by A. Kiessling and R. Heinze, Quintus Horatius Flaccus,
Satiren (Berlin 1886, reprinted 1957) 76-77.
64 Freudenburg (above, n.21) 127.
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Tue, 09 Oct 2018 15:50:21 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms
76 Jerome Kemp
IV. Conclusion
In Satires 1.4 Horace concentrates on the moral purpose of
satire, with particular reference to the use of exempla, which was
pertinent to Peripatetic ethics, as well as other literary forms. The
ironic stance, the humor, in much of Horace's satire, and most im
portantly in relation to 1.4, in the first three "diatribe" satires, does
not detract from the importance of the moral content, the genuine
moral purpose of the Satires. Horace combines comedy and moral
content?indeed employs humor, the ironic persona of the narrator,
to strengthen certain moral positions?as he implies is his inten
tion at Satire 1.24-25; and in so doing he puts moral philosophy
into a practical context. The influence of Aristotle's discussion of
fkouoAoxux indicates Horace's moral position with regard to satire: in
its essential libertas (which serves a moral purpose), satire requires
ethical constraints.
The nature of language and its meaning was important to phi
losophers, and Philodemus' views on metathesis strengthen the belief
that Horace's position on satire's literary status in 1.4 should not
simply be taken at face value. Horace's elusive position is further
reinforced by references to satire's realism, which points to Aristo
tle's theory of uiunaig. But his use of Aristotelian and Philodeman
literary theory must be appraised with caution: it seems that he is
playing with certain prevalent ideas in literary theory, as well as
propounding a fairly logical, understandable surface argument, so as
to ask his readers what they think constitutes real poetry.
This content downloaded from 210.212.129.125 on Tue, 09 Oct 2018 15:50:21 UTC
All use subject to https://about.jstor.org/terms