MODULE 10 Kant and Rights Theorists
MODULE 10 Kant and Rights Theorists
MODULE 10 Kant and Rights Theorists
Module 10
Kant and Rights Theorists
Name: ___________________________________
Course and Year: __________________________
Date and Time Allotment: _______ (3 hours)
Introduction
This module entitled Kant and Rights Theorist will discuss Kantian Theory otherwise known as
Deontological Theory that focuses on duty as the primary factor for determining if an action is good or not. In this
theory, two tests will have to be passed: The universalizability test and the treatment of humans as an end and not as
means.
I. Objectives:
In this module, you will be able to:
1. Understand Kantian theory.
2. Analyze ethical situations using Kantian Theory.
3. Differentiate legal rights from moral rights.
www.aforisticamente.com
He is a German Lutheran theologian and philosopher famous at the most influential in the Age of
Enlightenment and Western philosophy. He has three know bools: Critique of Pure Reason, Critique of
Practical Reason, Critique of the Power of Judgment. He is renowned student, writer and professor in
mathematics, physics, and metaphysics at the University of Konigsberg.
Kant live during the European cultural revolutions of enlightenment or renaissance in the 18 th century. He
followed his predecessors, Voltaire and David Hume in trying to replace religious traditions, superstitions and
monarchy with rationalism through his three Critiques on reason. Rationalism aims at providing answers to
metaphysical and other questions though the powers of reason alone. These influenced German idealism and
analytic philosophy.
Kantianism or Kantian Ethics is a deontological theory that emphasizes morality based on duty, reason, moral
principle, moral obligation, and motive or intention. It rejects consequences as the basis of morality. Kantian ethical
framework is considered as a Moral Universalism or Moral Absolutism and Moral Formalism.
“Humans are motivated by the duty to act morally or rationally instead of emotionally or without
Duty Principle
reason.”
Kant argues that duty or moral obligation is the very nature of the pure human reason. This means that as
rational agents, people can grasp the moral principles and act out of his principles without the aid of experience and
consideration of consequences.
Good Will “Nothing can possibly be conceived in the world, or even out of it, which can be called good
Principle without qualification, except a good will.”
Good Will
Kant holds that fundamentally, there is only one thing that is good in and of itself – the Good Will. It is the
overarching principle of all morality. Good will is the very nature of the person’s free will. Free will as the ability of
pure reason is an absolute command of reason without qualifications. Thus, good will can freely choose its moral
duty dictated by reason alone.
Good will is “good” by virtue of being an end in itself or as a means to only one end, which is “good”. It is then
bad if the will is a means to another end or ends other than itself. The human reason produces a will that is
universally good in itself and absolutely good.
As universalist, the reason has only one end or “good”, which could be found in the will, reason and person. The
“good” is found in all activities or instances and not only in some instances. Thus, there should be no disparity
between intention and act. Intention and action should be one or good and they justify the end.
As absolutist, the reason allows no exceptions or qualifications other than the “good”. Reason is objectively good
in itself regardless if there is no one that approves of it. An act should absolutely and truly proceed, reflect and
represent the intention. There are two tests: “categorical imperative” and “persons as ends in themselves.”
Categorical Imperative “Act only according to that maxim whereby you can, at the same time, will that it
Principle should become a universal law.”
Person as End “Act so that you treat people never as a mere means to an end, but always as end in
Principle themselves.”
End Lawmaker Principle “Act as if you were, through your maxims, a lawmaker of kingdom of ends.”
Kant thinks that persons as ends are autonomous. Autonomous persons are able to exercise free and good will
by legislating the moral law for everyone. Every rational being is able to regard himself as a maker of universal law
not because of an external moral authority but under the authority of his own reason alone. Being autonomous
demands respect for “ends” or persons have basic moral rights.
Natural Rights Theorists. Greeks like Aristotle had long believed that rights are natural rights that re inherited from
nature and reason, like the rights to life, freedom, property and pursuit of happiness. Many modern thinkers like Hugo
Grotius (1583-1645), Thomas Hobbes (1588-1679), Samuel von Pufendorf (1632-1694), and John Locke (1632-
1704) were natural theorist.
Instrumental Rights Theorists. Consequentialists and Utilitarianists like Jeremy Bentham, John Stuart Mill and Henry
Sidgwick (1907) describe rights as parts of rules instrumental in achieving an optimal distribution of advantages or
greatest utility (happiness) for the greatest number of people. Pure egalitarian theorists also contend that rights lead
to the achievement of a more equal distribution of advantages. Whereas, the prioritarian theorists go beyond by
giving extra weight to the interests of the less privileged.
Contractual Rights Theorists. These thinkers hold that rights are stipulations guaranteed by a certain valid contract
between peoples. They also uphold rights in business contracts. Hobbes, Jean-Jacques Rousseau (1712-1778) and
Locke consider rights in social contracts between the government and its citizens as rights surrender to the authority
in exchange for protection of their remaining rights including their right to social order.
Immanuel Kant (1724-1804), [Kantian and Deontology] holds that human persons have rights that are autonomous,
universal and treat persons as ends. The only innate right is “freedom, insofar as it can coexist with other’s freedom
in accordance with a universal law.” The foundation of Kant’s human dignity and human rights is duty or reason.
Trespassing of moral status only means that one may have to exceed in their rights to the extent that they may
violate others’ rights. Though any response to trespassing must be within one’s rights. For example, if a criminal
attack a person and the person see it as great threat to his life, he has to use any means to preserve his life
even if it may harm or kill the criminal. Any exception to violate rights such as the case of self-defense could
never be the moral standard to violate other’s rights. It should always be the last resort.
In Section 1 under the Bill of Rights, Article III of the 1987 Philippine Constitution, it states: “No person shall be
deprived of life, liberty, or property without due process of law, nor shall any person be denied the equal
protection of the laws.”
2. Legal Rights
A right created under the law. It can be based in the constitution or a statute. It is usually the crystallization of the
tradition, values and what is generally regarded as ethical and moral within a specific political area and
recognized by a duly authorized authority (which in most cases would be the state and its citizens). They might
be loosely termed also as codified moral rights.
Example: A qualified voter has the right to vote provided he/she does not have any of the disqualifications.
Are claims that protect the interests of humans both as individual and as a group. They are “special” rights or
privileges granted by the government or a legal authority through a certain contract of agreement.
Legal rights are also called conventional or political rights, which are created by humans, authorities,
conventions.