Religions 13 00490 v3
Religions 13 00490 v3
Religions 13 00490 v3
Article
Japan, Religion, History, Nation
Timothy Fitzgerald 1,2
Abstract: I connect the invention of Japanese ‘religion’ since the Meiji era (1868–1912) with the
invention of other modern imaginaries, particularly the Japanese Nation State and Japanese History.
The invention of these powerful fictions in Japan was a specific, localised example of a global process.
The real significance of this idea that religion has always existed in all times and places is that
it normalises the idea of the non-religious secular as the arena of universal reason and progress.
The invention of Japanese ‘religion’ had—and still has—a significant function in the wider, global
context of colonial capital and the continual search for new ‘investment’ opportunities. Meiji Japan
illustrates, in fascinating detail, a process of cognitive hegemony, and the way a globalising discourse
on ‘progress’ transformed the plunder of colonial sites into a civilising mission. The idea that there
is a universal type of practice, belief or institution called ‘religion’ as distinct from government,
‘politics’ or ‘science’ was not only new to Japan. It hardly existed in England or more widely in
Protestant Europe and North America until the eighteenth or even 19th century. The idea of a
secular constitutional nation state was only emergent in the late 18th century with the Declaration of
Independence and the US Constitution. Most of Europe—including the colonial powers England
and France—were still Christian confessional church states through most of the 19th century. The
franchise was granted only to Christian men of substantial property, and denied to women, servants,
wage labour, colonised subjects, and slaves. This critical, deconstructive narrative helps us to see
more clearly the ideological function of the generic category of religion in the wider configuration of
modern secular categories such as constitutional nation state, political economy, nature, history, and
science. I also discuss the relation between History as a secular academic science, and the invention
Citation: Fitzgerald, Timothy. 2022.
of ‘the Past’ in universal Time. I argue here that the invention of the Past by professional Historians
Japan, Religion, History, Nation.
has a significant role in transforming modern inventions such as ‘religion’ and the secular categories
Religions 13: 490. https://doi.org/
10.3390/rel13060490 into the inherent and universal order of things, as though they have always been everywhere. I reveal
this on-going process of ideological reproduction by close readings of some recent ‘histories of Japan’
Academic Editor: Mitsutoshi Horii
and the way they uncritically construct ‘the Past’ in the terms of contemporary configurations.
Received: 11 March 2022
Accepted: 18 May 2022 Keywords: Japan; religion; nation; state; history; cognitive hegemony
Published: 27 May 2022
Horii and others have contributed to a growing body of critical literature on the
invention of religion in Japan (Horii 2012, 2016, 2018; Kuroda 1981; Hardacre 1989; Josephson
2012; Isomae 2005, 2007, 2017; Fitzgerald 1993, 1995, 2000a, 2002; Thomas 2019; Maxey 2014).
This issue of the modern invention of religion and religions is not confined to Japan.
As a global discourse, it is part of a much wider critical literature, much of it coming from
within the discipline of religious studies itself (Smith [1962] 1978; Harrison 1990, 2015; Asad
1993; Balagangadhara 1994; Chidester 1996, 2007; McCutcheon 1997, 2018; Dubuisson 2003,
2019; King 1999, 2013, 2017; Fitzgerald 2000a, 2000b, 2007a, 2007b, 2010, 2011; Masuzawa
2005; Cavanaugh 2009; Mandair 2010; Dressler and Mandair 2011; Martin 2010, 2017; Bloch
et al. 2010; Fürhding 2013; Stuckrad 2013; Stack et al. 2015; Horii 2021)2 .
Despite this growing volume of critical literature around the category ‘religion’, it
appears to be largely ignored by historians, anthropologists, orientalists, area specialists,
and more generally, across the humanities and social sciences. This criticism may apply to
Japanese studies, as I hope will be evident in this article.
The assumption that ‘religion’ refers objectively to a global phenomenon, and that
‘religions’ are to be found in all times and places, is a reification that has been thoroughly
normalised and institutionalised. The term has long been uncritically taken as a neutral
transparent category for description and analysis, with an obvious meaning and referent.
There is still widespread resistance to its critique. It is in this sense a hegemonic category. It
appears as innocently neutral, natural, normal and useful, as though unproblematically
corresponding to an intuitively comprehended kind of institution or practice. Meanwhile its
deployment tacitly constructs the secular ground of knowledge and reason.
general. Who has the right to represent who? What are the motives and for whom is the
representation intended? How is it being funded and who benefits from the representation?
For myself, it was primarily a problem of trying to understand the situation I found myself
in. I also had an interest in promoting my career and my identity as a qualified academic
and a teacher (see recent discussions in Fitzgerald 2017a, 2020).
My attempt to redescribe ‘Japanese religion’ as ‘ritual order’ (Fitzgerald 1993) was
influenced by Durkheim. I saw all Japanese institutions—households, schools, univer-
sities, small family businesses, large corporations, government bureaucracies, shrines,
and temples—as having common shared ritual elements that reproduced the collective
representations of Japanese identity. These include the values that configure particular
relationships, the institutional loyalties, the sense of being Japanese, and being a member
of a Japanese nation.
The aforementioned was an imperfect experiment, and yet, it cleared a space for critical
thinking around the category and its relation to the social, the political, the economic, and
the secular, in general. I did not exactly try to redescribe what is already denoted as ‘religion’
in Japan because that would be simply to exchange labels. Instead, I tried to identify the
profoundly shared values operating in all Japanese institutions, and to show that these are
neither ‘religious’ nor ‘secular’, and to force them into these compartmentalised domains
distorts and misrepresents. I do not know if these have been useful or not. It is for others
to judge.
My critique of the use of religion as a descriptive and analytical category in the
Japanese context had added strength because it was part of a larger argument about a
globalising discourse on religion and religions that made the non-religious secular seem as
normal commonsense, rather than what it is, which is a value-laden, ideological construct.
I believed and still believe that the academic study of reified entities called ‘religion’ and
‘religions’ has the effect of making the values and institutions of liberal capitalism appear
as normal common sense. The link between them is buried from view. I developed this
wider argument on several fronts in my first book (Fitzgerald 2000a). I argued that one of
the various agencies for the dissemination of this discourse was the phenomenology of
religion and the world religions model, which is a disguised form of Christian ecumenical
theology. Three chapters were given to Japan. I had also done research in India where there
are also problems with the religion–secular binary. One of my targets throughout was the
claimed universality of problematic binary distinctions between ‘religion’ and ‘secular’,
‘faith’ and ‘knowledge’, ‘supernatural’ and ‘natural’, and ‘spirit’ and ‘matter’.
The widely-made assumption in Anglophone academic studies, that the Japanese
must have religion and religious practices even though they do not have a word for it,
seemed and still seems like an act of cognitive imperialism, all the more powerful for being
unconscious and unintended. It was and is consistent with historical accounts of the impact
of American power on the Japanese elites since the time of Meiji. It made sense of the
search for an equivalent term culminating with shūkyō. It was and is consistent with the
claims made by western imperial powers, that to be modern, rational, progressive, and
civilised, it was necessary for Japan to become a secular centralised nation state with a
written constitution that separated ‘religion’ from government and the ‘state’, and from
‘secular’ domains such as politics, science, law, education, manufacturing, agriculture, and
sports. It was consistent with the history of the Meiji Constitution, the reification of State
Shinto (Jinja, kokutai, or what has come to be called kokka Shinto) as the secular ethics of the
Nation State, and of Buddhism and Sect Shinto as ‘religions’.
My work on the invention of religion in Japan was not intended as a work of histo-
riography. I was not claiming to be a historian of Japan myself. The historical elements
were derived from experts in modern Japanese history. Other elements were derived from
critical readings of anthropologists, sociologists, and religious studies experts. My method-
ology involved close critical readings of a large number of Anglophone representations of
Japanese ‘religions’ by well-established experts. By exposing their internal contradictions, I
Religions 2022, 13, 490 4 of 36
deconstructed their claims to be describing Japanese religions and suggested instead that
they were inventing them, and this caused discomfort and some hostility.
As Josephson put it several years later, my work was “not well received” (Josephson
2012, p. 6). Despite its flaws, I believe my work was innovative and contributed to opening
up a new critical perspective. I contributed to subsequent trends in critique, especially my
emphasis on the ideological operation of the religion–secular binary. It would be wrong
to exaggerate my own influence. Furthermore, it would be wrong to imagine that critical
thinking around the categories we deploy to organise our knowledge—religion, politics, the
state, economics, and many others—has been widely and eagerly embraced by academics.
My readings of the work of some historians later in this essay suggest the opposite. There
is a stubborn resistance to critique, and I think there are reasons for this resistance. One
of the most significant, if unstated functions of secular academics and the universities in
which they work, is to protect and reproduce these categories.
On the other hand, this Special Issue represents something of a breakthrough, and I am
glad to be invited to participate. Professor Horii and I have worked with many others over
the years in pursuing the critical religion agenda, and I am grateful to him for including me.
practice, or experience. Nationalism and patriotism are a case in point. The nation demands
the ultimate sacrifice from devotees. Is worship of the nation a quasi-religion, a pseudo-
religion, a ‘religion-like’ phenomenon, or a proper religion? There are no convincing criteria
to make such distinctions. Furthermore, is not ‘secular religion’ an oxymoron?
The paradox of the matter is, that while on the one hand, just about everything can
be and has been described as a religion or as ‘having a religious dimension’, most of our
institutions such as government, the state, the civil service, business, education, law, and
sports are classified as ‘secular’. Written constitutions such as the US Constitution in its
Bill of Rights (1790/1) stipulate that (1) the private practice of religion is a right of the
Individual, and (2) the State must be protected from religion and from the influence of any
particular religious faith. Most modern secular states have agencies or court procedures for
determining whether or not any particular practice can be properly classified as a religion
or not.
Defining practices as religious rather than secular quarantines them by removing
them as potential sources of opposition to the dominant regime (see Chidester 1996, 2007;
Fitzgerald 2007a, 2007b; Stack et al. 2015; Goldenberg 2012, 2015). The classification of
some group, belief, or practice as a ‘religion’ or ‘religious’ is ultimately a contingent act of
power. This has happened globally, and Japan offers a good example. Firstly, the insistence
by the Americans at the time of Meiji that Japan must have religion, even though there
is no Japanese word for it. And then again, after the Pacific war, when they rewrote the
Japanese Constitution, insisting that, of course, in reality, ‘Shinto’ is a religion and not part
of the Japanese State. The Japanese needed to be instructed by the Americans in what
Shinto is and what it is not. This surely demonstrates that the crucial issue is the control
of the dominant narrative. It is odd that scholars think they have concepts here that are
sufficiently stable for objective description and analysis, not only of contemporary Japan,
but globally, and even ancient times.
The distinction between religion and politics is ubiquitous. I have shown, through
detailed analyses of academic and other discourses, that politics is as indefinable as religion.
On the one hand, there is a politics of everything, including all human relations. And yet
on the other hand, ‘religion’ and ‘politics’ are described as essentially different, such that
if they are allowed to mix, then violence and mayhem may result. I and others, such as
William T. Cavanaugh (2009) in his book The Myth of Religious Violence, have described this
as an aspect of the modern fiction of two entities in continual confrontation with each other,
that is, fanatical faith-based religion attempting to destroy the peace-loving and rational
secular order (Cavanaugh 2009; Fitzgerald 2007a, 2007b, 2011, 2017a).
I and others have argued consistently that we should be studying the deployments of
the category/term/word/idea itself, not only religion, but also others such as ‘politics’, ‘so-
ciety’, ‘nature’, or ‘science’, and not the putative data to which it is supposed to correspond.
(See also Harrison 2015; Cavanaugh 2009; Stack et al. 2015; Horii 2016, 2018, 2021).
Just as all peoples everywhere are attributed with distinctively religious institutions
and practices, so they are attributed—either tacitly or explicitly—with social, political,
economic, cultural, and legal ones. If the people themselves do not make these distinctions,
because they construct their world differently, then they will be redescribed by the historian
or the anthropologist in the Europhone terms. However, is this not a misrepresentation,
and even an act of cognitive imperialism? (See Mandair 2010 on the invention of “Sikhism”
as an act of “epistemic violence”). It implies that the modern anthropologist or historian
knows ‘them’ better than they know themselves. If a historian or anthropologist attributes
a hunter–gatherer band with religious beliefs, a political process, or an economic system,
he or she is imposing alien divisions that simultaneously misrepresent their reality while
universalising ours. Our categories have become so ‘naturalised’ for us that we assume
they must be normal common sense. This has, in the past, lent itself to the narrative of
historical progress and development. If those people do not have words for what we take to
be different kinds of practice or institution, then they are ‘pre-modern’ and backward—or
under-developed—and need to learn English or French so that they can come to recognise
Religions 2022, 13, 490 6 of 36
themselves in their own order of things. This is surely what happened to the Japanese
people at Meiji. We may not consciously intend to associate ourselves with this imperial
discourse, but is it not implicated in our representations?
Even in representations of the supposedly advanced and developed ‘West’, the def-
inition of ‘religion’ and the ‘non-religious secular’ categories are contested and evade
clear definition. This is true, not only in the context of Japanese studies but globally, in
interpretations of the US Constitution, for instance.
Distinctions between religious, political, economic, or technological practices fail to
map onto sociological, anthropological, and historiographical data. If one studies the
actual deployments of these terms, as I and others have done in multiple texts across the
humanities and social sciences, what counts as a religious as distinct from a secular practice
depends on the rhetorical requirements of the moment. In my research, I have found
these categories to be shifting, unstable, indefinable, porous, without clear boundaries,
and frequently including so much possible data that they have no clearly distinct referent
(Fitzgerald 2007a, 2007b, 2011, 2016, 2017a, 2017b, 2019, 2020). It seems therefore that it is the
reproduction of the categorial ensemble, the classification system itself, that is important, rather than
any clearly defined agreement on what each term refers to.
4. Problems with the Meaning of Religion and Related Categories in England and
North America
The difficulty of translating ‘religion’ into Japanese is matched by analogous difficulties
for many, or probably, most languages of the world. The same is true for politics, economics,
culture, nature, society, history, science, and progress.
It may come as a surprise that the term ‘religion’ and many others that are closely
related to religion through binary opposition, such as ‘politics’ and the secular state,
are difficult, if not impossible to translate into 16th and 17th century England. In fact,
something similar is true for all the terms that I have just listed. If these words existed at
all, they operated in radically different semantic contexts. Even in the middle of the 17th
century, which is frequently described as the time of ‘political’ and ‘scientific’ revolution in
England, it is difficult indeed to find a consistent discourse on either ‘politics’ or ‘science’
(see Harrison 2015 for a critical genealogy of the terms ‘religion’ and ‘science’). I have
searched the radical tracts of the famous Putney army debates of the 1640s, and I have
not yet found a consistent discourse on the noun word ‘politics’. The distinctions between
modern generic religion and politics and the state were emergent but not yet imagined.
They were only just starting to emerge in the 1640s, in new discourses of a growing class of
male property owners in their dangerous quarrels with the sacred monarch, in this case
Charles I, the established church hierarchies, and the ancien regime generally.
The distinctions that we now take for granted between religion and the non-religious
secular, between religion and politics, religion and science, and religion and economics,
did not yet exist. My own research suggests that the modern invention of generic religion
and religions emerged initially in England (perhaps it happened earlier in Holland?3 ) after
around 1650—after the Putney Debates in the 1640s, and after the execution of the sacred
monarch in 1649, around the time that Thomas Hobbes published The Leviathan (1652)
and James Harrington published Oceana (1658), and especially in the 1680s in the work of
Nonconformists such as William Penn (1680), the Quaker founder of Pennsylvania, and
John Locke (1689a, 1689b).
The distinctions between natural and supernatural or matter and spirit were config-
ured differently and do not map onto the modern distinction. What many writers refer to
as ‘the scientific revolution’ of the 17th century, referring especially to the work of Galileo,
Descartes, and Newton, began the work of transforming the relations of nature to God.
‘Political economy’ was emergent in the 17th and early 18th century with the French
Physiocrats, and writers such as Montchretien and Cantillon, and became the topic of
Adam Smith’s Wealth of Nations in 1776 (Smith [1776] 1998). There was no discourse on
Religions 2022, 13, 490 7 of 36
‘economics’ in the modern sense until the late 18th and early 19th century in the works of
Ricardo, Bentham, James Mill, and others.
The application of modern categories to what historians refer to as medieval and
early modern England tend to distort and misrepresent. Twentieth century historians
retrospectively organise their representations of earlier English times in terms that had no
clear equivalent and that were, at best, only emergent (Fitzgerald 1999b, 2007a, 2007b). In
this way, they unconsciously smuggle into their representations teleological assumptions
that misrepresent the actual priorities and habits of thought of the time. The people at
those times, not only in England but in Christendom generally, seem to have lived in a
different symbolic order, a different world of representations—(the Bible, the church, the
ancien regime, the Christian Commonwealth, the holistic organic hierarchy of the God-
ordained order, the Great Chain of Being, etc.). Contemporary Anglophone descriptive
and analytical categories such as religion, politics, economics, society, and science do not
map onto medieval and early modern England (for religion, politics, and economics, see
Fitzgerald 2007a, 2007b, 2015a; for religion, secular, and politics, see Cavanaugh 2009; for
religion, nature, and science, see Harrison 1990, 2015; for ‘society’, see Horii 2021). Why
then should these representations be deployed to describe Japan, especially before Meiji?
It is not as if Japan or England were lacking something that they needed. The notion that
somehow their language and conceptual worlds were impoverished because they did not
distinguish between religion and government, or between religious practices and economic
or technological practices, is itself part of the conceit of the discourse on modern secular
enlightenment progress.
In England, the profound transformation in the way that the term ‘religion’ gradually
came to be deployed was closely connected to a new reified discourse on ‘politics’, which
referred to a new kind of government that represented the interests of male property owners
who lacked rights. The new discourse on ‘politics’ was embedded in rhetorical demands
for the separation of Church and State, for Toleration, and for rights of representation in
Parliament for men of substantial property, many of them Nonconformists.
Less obvious but also of great significance was the emergence of a discourse on
‘religions of the world’ that arose from the colonial encounter with other peoples. There
existed a burgeoning literature on this theme in Christian Europe, based on travel diaries
written by all sorts of travellers and colonising agents—explorers, merchants, sailors and
soldiers, missionaries, geographers, plantation owners, and the founders of new colonies.
There was a proliferation of texts, and one of the burning questions was whether or not the
savages, barbarians, pagans, and heathens had anything resembling religion?4 Religion
meant Christian truth, as distinct from superstitions and idolatries. The question, ‘Do
they have religion?’ was equivalent to ‘Do they have rationality, civility, and truth?’ It
could even mean ‘Are they truly human?’ However, we can see the emergence of a term
that was increasingly being deployed to organise knowledge of other peoples, partly as a
way of classifying and controlling them. This was one of the sources of the pluralisation
into ‘religions’.
However, another significant pluralisation referred to the different post-Reformation
‘confessions’ of Christian truth such as Lutheran, Calvinist, and Catholic. Religion, un-
derstood as Christian Truth, encompassed all institutions in England and Europe more
widely. The idea of a non-Christian government or non-Christian law courts was quite
unthinkable until the second half of the 17th century, and was a treasonous and heretical
notion for long after that. The emergence of the pluralised ‘religions’—for example, in the
Treaty of Westphalia (1648)—is almost always a reference to different Christian confessions.
Catholicism, Lutheran and Calvinist were the main ones, but there were a plethora of
different groups. In the Putney Debates, which are so often described as ‘revolutionary’
and ‘political’, the Bible was the main reference point for articulating visions of the world
and how it should be ordered (Hill 1972; Bradstock 2010).
The reification of world religions as a class of phenomena that can be studied objec-
tively, systematically, and scientifically comes later in the late 18th and 19th century, around
Religions 2022, 13, 490 8 of 36
the same time that uppercase History was invented as a scientific professionalised disci-
pline, from around the time that Orientalists were first coining terms such as ‘Hinduism’
and ‘Buddhism’.
Writers such as William Penn (1680, 1701) and John Locke (1689a, 1689b) had to escape
persecution to Holland for suggesting that religion and government could be distinct.
Simply by making this rhetorical claim, the meaning of religion was transformed, ‘politics’
emerged as a noun word, and the new narrative threatened the status quo. Tracing the
emergence of the religion–politics binary, I became conscious of the equally profound
change in other categories, and even their invention, terms that today we take for granted,
and that seem normal and commonplace. ‘Secular’, ‘society’, ‘sacred’, ‘economy’, ‘nation’,
‘state’, ‘progress’, and ‘history’ changed radically in the logic of their deployment and
amounted to inventing a new vocabulary of generic abstractions. These terms constitute
much of the rhetoric of what came to be called ‘the Enlightenment’, and a family of
discourses by writers such as Montesquieu, Turgot, Condorcet, Adam Smith, Jefferson, and
many others on ‘progress’ and improvement—the ‘progress of nations’, and ‘the ‘progress
of the human mind through universal history’.
One of the purposes of my book (Fitzgerald 2007a) was to show how professional
historians reconstruct the past—in this case, the English ‘late medieval’ and ‘early modern’
past—in terms of the categories in which we think today, ideas that we take for granted,
and which we suppose are universal and have transparent meanings, but which in those
past days, had different meanings—if they existed as terms at all. In this way, modern
professional historians invent a history of the English nation that is not merely imaginary,
but which makes the past and the people of the past conform to how we think they ought to
have been, according to our understandings. The process tacitly normalises and universalises
our modern consciousness of the world, as though then was really just like now, and that
the differences were due to their relative under-development.
My argument in Discourse of Civility and Barbarity (2007) is that ‘religion’ and related
categories that today are commonplace were previously embedded—if they existed at all—
into different configurations of meaning and use. People experienced the world through
the conditioning of a different paradigm constructed from different categories. For example,
today, post the English, French, and American Revolutions, we have a strong discourse on
the rights of the Individual and the Citizen, on liberty and equality, on private property, on
democratic representative government, on universal franchise, on secular nation states, and
on economic development. These ideas and the discourses in which they are embedded
arose largely during the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries.
In Europe, in the sixteenth, seventeenth, and eighteenth centuries, the idea of the
‘nation’ was not like the ‘imagined community’ of the centralised, bureaucratic, modern
secular nation state that began to emerge in the late 18th century (Gellner 1983; Anderson
1983; Hobsbawm 1990), and which today constitutes the 193 members of the United Nations.
The older usage was more like the modern usage of ‘ethnic’ or ‘tribe’, referring to a group
that shared a common language, a common territory, and a common sense of identity. The
heart of the nation was located in the court of the anointed monarch. The nation was seen
as an organic hierarchy, typically with a sacred monarch at its heart, and created by God.
One image that represented this organic hierarchy was The Great Chain of Being. Another
was an analogy with the human body, whereby the Monarch was the sacred heart, his
advisors were the head, the nobility and warriors were the shoulders and arms, and the
peasants were the feet.
This is radically different from the “imagined community” of the centralised, secu-
lar, constitutional, bureaucratic, modern nation state with one official language, and the
ideology of the modern world order exemplified by the United Nations.
The list of the imagined communities is very long indeed—the modern nation states
of France, Japan, Saudi Arabia, Great Britain, India, the United States of America, Italy,
Germany, Brazil, all the nations of Latin America, of Africa, of Asia, and all the other
193 fictional entities that are members of the United Nations.
Religions 2022, 13, 490 9 of 36
What people meant by ‘England’ (or France, for example) or ‘nation’ or ‘history’
was radically different compared to today’s uses. To conflate them is to normalise and
universalise what needs to be explained. The religion, history and nation states of Britain,
Germany, France, Japan, or any others are modern inventions.
categories are deployed by historians as though they did not have a history. Thus, while the
Anglophone or, more generally, Europhone term ‘religion’—like ‘secular’, ‘nation’, ‘state’,
or ‘politics’—has a history, it is deployed by historians as though it refers to an ahistorical
constant—an objective, permanent, and universally available factor of all times and places.
6. The Invention of Japanese Religion Was Also the Invention of Japan, the Japanese
Nation State, and Japanese History
On a topic such as Japanese religion and its history, we might productively start
with Helen Hardacre’s observation that, at the time of the Meiji restoration, “The notion
of Buddhism and Shinto as separate religions, the idea of religion itself, and the term
‘Shinto’, were all assuming a place in Japan’s intellectual vocabulary for the first time”
(Hardacre 1988, p. 227; 1989). At a minimum, such a statement implicates the invention
of religion with the invention of universal, uppercase History, and of the modern, secular,
constitutional nation state of Japan.
Tanaka (2006)6 has shown how History, the Nation State, capitalism, and a new
conceptual vocabulary arrived in Japan at the same time. ‘History’, in the modern sense,
began in early Meiji, bringing with it a new sense of uniform, empty, homogenous time.
Two significant aspects of this arrival of ‘modernity’ were the reforms of both calendrical
and clock time in 1872. Clocks were adopted to synchronise timekeeping. The new way
of measuring time imposed a mechanical regularity that suited new capitalist modes of
production, distribution, and consumption of commodities. The Gregorian calendar was
adopted, which involved a significant change from lunar time to solar time. These, in turn,
generated a sense of empty, homogenous, universal time, and with it, a sense of uniform
universal history. The new sense of time and history reordered the past, the collective
memory, and consequently, also reordered the present. It created a rupture in consciousness,
introducing a new way of thinking about and organising ‘Japan’ by overcoming myriad
local and regional differences, and synchronising them into a single imagined nation
state. There was, thus, a change of spatial consciousness as well as temporal. These
changes bewildered and disoriented people, radically disturbing many vital aspects of their
world and their lived lives. All of these sudden combined changes were wrapped in the
discourse of progress from the ignorant and barbaric past to the enlightened new age of
civilised modernity.
Therefore, the invention of ‘religion’ is implicated in the invention of the factual history
of the nation state and a particular sense of time that is associated with modern, modernity,
and modernisation. A significant component of this myth is ‘modern secular liberal (or
socialist) enlightenment progress’. The configuration of categories includes the imagined
community of the modern Japanese ‘nation state’ and its history. ‘History’ in the uppercase
and ‘Nation State’ are as much modern inventions as ‘religion’ and the non-religious
secular. The very idea of ‘modern’ and ‘modernity’ is made possible by these others. It
generates other imagined times such as premodern, early modern, medieval, and ancient. I
suggest that these ideas or mythemes operate together in a way similar to notes in a musical
composition, or signs in a signalling system. Religion, secular, modern, progress, history,
and nation state are imaginaries that are implicated together, they mutually construct each
other. Moreover, they are further tangled up with a large number of other metacategories
such as politics, economy, liberty, society, culture, nature, progress, revolution, and science
to name just a few of the more ubiquitous ones.
These metacategories are abstractions that form part of a system of modern classifi-
cation. They are contingent ways of talking about the world that have been transformed
into common sense. These terms operate together in an ensemble to invent, construct, or
imagine a particular and contingent kind of world. We organise the world and our knowl-
edge of the world as though they are objectively real. I suggest that they are fictions that
organise our knowledge and experience but do not stand for anything outside the belief
system. Though the referent of each term seems intuitively obvious—we all supposedly
know what we mean by ‘religion’ or ‘politics’ or ‘nation’ or ‘nature’ because we know how
Religions 2022, 13, 490 11 of 36
to use the words—they are each and every one contested, and there is little consensus
around their definition. They do not refer to anything outside the rhetorical narratives that
transmit them.
The case of Japan provides one example of how these contested but normalised cate-
gories achieved their global hegemony by way of colonization or the threat of colonization,
which implies cognitive colonization (hence the colonial episteme). All peoples who came
under the globalising power of the Europeans had to reconfigure their own systems of rep-
resentation to fit the dominant imported ones. The elites of the colonised sites internalised
the dominant language and categories.
The aforementioned was not a passive internalization, and was often a first step to
resistance, but resistance in the terms of the dominant. The data collected by explorers,
geographers, colonial administrators, merchants, traders, soldiers and sailors, orientalists
and missionaries, fed back into the Anglophone or Europhone categories and classifications,
and expanded them and changed their shape. Few people who have written about these
issues of translation in the colonial context of unequal power relations are unaware of what
Charles Hallisey called “intercultural mimesis” (Hallisey 1995). No doubt, as Josephson
(2012) has pointed out in his work, The Invention of Religion in Japan, it would be wrong
to deny ‘agency’ to the Japanese in the face of imperial power. However, if ‘the Japanese’
(which Japanese?) had ‘agency’, it was largely the literate male elites with power and status
within their own hierarchies. And it would still be true to say that change was imposed
on Japan by superior military power from out of the barrel of a gun. ‘The Japanese’ did
not decide of their own free will to become a modern, secular, constitutional nation state,
nor did most Americans or French. How many Germans or Italians had any say in the
unification of their new modern nation states in the 1870s? Perhaps few people had much
say in the matter.
The problem of translating terms such as religion, secular, society, history, nation state,
politics, science, or nature has presumably been global, occurring in multiple linguistic
contexts. It has also brought with it the radical reordering of institutions, productive
practices, modes of ownership, and the disorientation of collective memory and time. It
would therefore seem fair to describe this cognitive hegemony as the colonial episteme. This
expression bears some comparison with what Walter Mignolo and Catherine Walsh call
“the colonial matrix of power” (CMP) in their work on decoloniality (Mignolo and Walsh
2018; Horii 2021; see also Gu 2020).
As I have already mentioned, my own research shows that a wide range of Anglophone
terms that we take for granted today, and invest with a transparent normality of meaning,
underwent radical changes in meaning and in the logic of their use since the 17th century.
The problem of much of my own research has been about the origins of these afore-
mentioned categories—not only ‘religion’ but all the categories that have been rhetorically
fused to religion. I am not talking about their etymological origins because I believe that
etymological continuity misleadingly implies that there is a core of essential meaning that
can be traced back to some ancient origin. According to this view, the core meaning remains
stable throughout the succeeding secondary changes in different contexts. However, this
ignores the intractable definitional problems of a word such as ‘religion’ and all the others I
have mentioned.
Much of what has been invented as the Enlightenment constitutes the conception
and birth of a new language of modern progress. Reinhart Koselleck had the idea that
for Germany, the late 18th century is a sattelzeit or watershed marked by large conceptual
shifts. This, I think, is what Koselleck meant by Geschichtliche Grundbegriffe (translated
as ‘basic concepts’; see (Lehmann and Richter 1996). I raise this issue for a very brief
mention because the continual reproduction of the myths and invented traditions that
sustain modern nation states as imagined communities with an ancient past depend greatly
on the work of modern Historians.
Religions 2022, 13, 490 12 of 36
. . . is the data that had allowed generations of historians to fit the Japanese
archipelago in successive European historiographic frameworks fully resilient to
serious comparison? (p. 264)
This rhetorical question acts as a switch point, because from here on, Buc will proceed
with his own project, which turns out to be uncritical and anachronistic. He claims that:
Inverting comparative history’s earlier interest in a catalogue of sameness, one
can put Japan between ca. 1000 and ca. 1600 side by side with Western and
Central Europe in approximately the same centuries, ca. 1000 to ca. 1500, to
notice, in fact, contrasts that have to be explained; contrasts that bring out with
surprising clarity the specificities of each ensemble. In short, the historian has to
work to explain contrasts embedded in similarities. And conversely, sometimes, it
is possible to suggest surprising similarities where master narratives had assumed
difference. (p. 264)
It seems then that, despite Buc’s scepticism about the universalisation of the ‘medieval’
construct, he thinks it is fruitful after all. Placing the emphasis on contrasts presupposes
a framework of shared categories that enable unconnected things to be put side by side.
Medieval is one of them. The problem with a designation such as medieval is that it tacitly
places Japan under the dominance of the master narrative of colonial history. It evokes the
idea of stages of development, from the primitive, to the medieval, the premodern, and
early modern, finally arriving at the height of development, the modern.
This colonising episteme encompasses ‘local’ times and histories within the master
narrative of Universal Time and Universal History, and this master narrative of History,
and its authoritative constructions of a ‘past’, are inseparable from the colonial project
introduced to Japan by Commodore Perry in his iron warship. This came entangled in a
language of backwardness and barbarity, and an imperative to modernise and be civilised
as the Americans and the Europeans.
Buc deploys the term ‘religion’ as a global category encompassing sets of data about
different peoples with different languages and, until the 16th century, very little contact. He
seems entirely unaware of the large corpus of published research on the category religion
that I have referred to earlier. For example, he says:
This presentation will focus on medieval Japan and medieval Europe’s cultures
of war and on how the religions present in each contributed to the form that
warfare took. In West and Central Europe, there was just one religion: a Catholic
Christian faith increasingly centralised and homogenised, after ca. 1100, by the
Roman papacy. In Japan, religion was a hybrid of a Buddhism brought from
Korea and China alloyed with the cult of local gods, the kami. Additionally, there
were notions stemming from Confucianism, and elements coming from Daoism
(which are hard to disentangle from native beliefs). (pp. 264–65)
However, to describe medieval Catholic faith as “just one religion” is to imply that in
the language of that time, there could have been more than one Christian truth, as though
the Universal Church might have been one among several ‘religions’. This constitutes an
anachronism and a misrepresentation. The anachronistic attribution of modern constructs
appears also as ‘religions’ such as Buddhism, Confucianism, and Daoism. There is a
misplaced shift in register between different meanings of the term ‘religion’. The shift in
meaning from Religion as Christian Truth to religion as a kind of practice and institution
that can be distinguished from non-religious secular institutions such as the nation, politics,
economics, and science is a shift in overall paradigm. It is to redescribe the past of both
Europe and Japan in terms of the globalising hegemonic discourse—the ‘grand narrative’
that Buc claims to be avoiding.
Buc claims with confidence:
Of course, no one would deny that there was in the Japanese Middle Ages religion
in war (as opposed to religious war). As is common in most premodern societies,
Japanese medieval warriors mustered temples and shrines’ prayers, curses and
Religions 2022, 13, 490 14 of 36
spells; and they believed that the gods helped them in battle . . . However, unlike
in Catholic Europe or Islamicate polities, the scholarly consensus is that there
was no war for religion. (pp. 265–66)
There are some problems with this claim. There is the invocation of the ‘premodern’
which only has meaning in the context of the master narrative of modern progress that the
author claimed he was avoiding. And there is a problem with the apparent meaningfulness
of the distinction that Buc is making here between “religion in war” and “religious war” or
“war for religion”. This presumes a clear idea of what religion or ‘a religion’ is, as distinct
from any other belief, practice, or institution. It is a spurious distinction when one realises
that there was no such thing as religion in either medieval Europe or medieval Japan. There
is also a tacit assumption that religion refers to temples, shrines, prayers, curses, spells, and
gods—all the cliches about the irrational “premodern” past.
“There is no religion in the Bible” either. As Naomi Goldenberg has argued in her
article with that title:
The author argues that ‘religion’ as a term designating distinct phenomena or
institutions is alien to the Bible, the text that supposedly anchors the concept in
Western politics and imagination. She analyses excerpts from books and lectures
by prominent scholars to show that even when they state outright that ‘religion’ is
non-existent in biblical times and thus is a misleading and inaccurate descriptor,
each one then ignores this insight and proceeds to employ the fiction that ‘religion’
is present in ancient cultures. Such habits of contradiction perpetuate an illusion.
The author then discusses several specific texts from each testament to argue
that the subject of biblical literature is governance. She contends that biblical
depictions of God and His representatives are narratives about sovereignty, au-
thoritative jurisdiction and communal allegiance. (Goldenberg 2018; see also
Stack et al. 2015)
Let us remember that Buc began his essay by criticising the “shallow comparisons”
that “enabled colonial history and constructed the Sociology of Modernity” (p. 262).
Buc uses the term ‘supernatural’, as in “Prince Shōtoku (pp. 574–622) had, with
supernatural help, victoriously fought with the opponents of Buddhism” (p. 267). This
may seem innocent and beyond critique. However, it is part of a pattern. Is he sure that
Shōtoku or any of the people of that time and place distinguished between the ‘natural’ and
the ‘supernatural’? Like his use of the Japanese term kami to mean ‘gods’, it seems normal
and a quibble to critique it, but it is unclear what is being identified. It is well known to
Japanese and foreign scholars in religious studies that the term kami can mean many things,
including sacred aspects of what moderns refer to as ‘nature’. In English, the term ‘gods’ is
radically unstable and has a plethora of uses and references.
Durkheim long ago argued that ‘religion’ cannot be defined in terms of belief in
the supernatural because many, and perhaps, most peoples in the world make no such
distinction (Durkheim, Emile 1912). Arguably, it is a modern distinction, part of the package
of modern secular reason and progress. It comes with the rhetorical separation of ‘religion’
and its beliefs from the claims of materialist, empirical science. The Anglophone terms
‘natural’ and ‘supernatural’ changed radically since the 17th century, and while today there
is a commonly-made rhetorical distinction between supernatural and natural, it is unclear
how it can be made. Neither nature nor supernature are available for empirical inspection.
They are both metaphysical abstractions containing vast amounts of arbitrary data. What
seems interesting to the present writer is the persistence with which scholars with research
skills consistently ignore the critical literature on these issues.
(2) (A) Delmer M. Brown (ed) The Cambridge History of Japan, Vol.1 (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1st published 1993, reprinted 1997, 2003, 2006, 1st published online 2008);
(B) William Tsutsui (ed) A Companion to Japanese History, Oxford: Blackwell, 2007.
Before I begin to make critical comments about The Cambridge History of Japan (Hall et al.
1993), let me start by noting the view of William Tsutsui, the editor of another substantial
Religions 2022, 13, 490 15 of 36
lies in their being unconscious. This is how the myth of secular non-religious reason and
development makes its appearance as simple fact, or as the background to all facts. It
is the technique whereby a rhetorical invention with ideological commitments becomes
transfigured into a largely unconscious working assumption.
There are other indicators of a lack of critical reflexivity. Tsutsui is very critical of the
American historians of the past who “structured their narratives” with “modernization
theory” (p. 2): These scholars figured “the rise of modern Japan” as “an edifying success
story, an almost textbook case of the inevitable triumph of rationality, democracy, and
capitalism, a trajectory interrupted in the Japanese example only by a “temporary” and
“aberrant” prewar turn to authoritarianism and expansionism . . . ” On this perspective,
Japan “should become increasingly similar to the advanced nations of Europe and the
United States as they ‘modernised’ along capitalist lines . . . Thus, the assumed endpoint
of Japan’s historic “upward course” was becoming “just like us”, tracing a step-by-step
process of convergence toward the modern ideal of all-American economic, political, and
social freedom” (p. 2).
Has the structure of modernization theory and history written in the vein of “a
modernising teleology” been overcome? Tsutsui seems to think his volume has overcome it,
and he gives quite optimistic reasons for this. I suggest ‘no’ for several reasons, which are in
line with the theoretical and methodological orientations briefly outlined earlier in this essay.
One is the belief that you can exclude ‘religion’ from an account of Japan’s past without
tacitly invoking the whole Enlightenment discourse on progress in which the invention of
religion is embedded. Another is that the very idea of academic, professionalised history
as an objective empirical factual reconstruction of ‘the past’ is again part of the same
modern configuration that arose out of the matrix of progress and development. Is Tsutsui
advocating a different kind of critical History? I do not think so. Also, if my argument
can be accepted, then the critique of religion and its binary opposition to the non-religious
secular seems, logically, to involve a critique of those other related categories—politics and
economics, for example—that frame modern consciousness and the discourse on progress.
It is worth bearing in mind a couple of points made about history, religion, and politics
by another serious expert on Japanese studies, George Macklin Wilson, in his essay “Time
and History in Japan” (1980), which illuminates the thesis that History in the modern sense—
professionalised universal History and its concomitant empty homogenous time—entered
Japan at the time of Meiji. He quotes a remark made by a Japanese person in 1876: “We
have no history. Our history begins today” (quoted in Wilson 1980, p. 570; also quoted by
Tanaka 2006, p. 1).9
Another remark that Wilson makes that bears on my thesis here concerns the impossi-
bility of distinguishing between religion and politics in ancient Japan. He says:
Nothing intervened between politics and other aspects of official life. Religion in
the strict sense had no independent existence . . . What was political was religious;
the religious was equally political. Matsurigoto (“ceremonial affairs”) is the first
Japanese word for government, and it guarded against a schism between the
civil and the sacral. It means government and also conveys the sense of religion.
(p. 565)
In their Preface to The Cambridge History of Japan, 1993, 2008 (Vol. 1), the general editors
of the Series, John Whitney Hall, Marius B. Jansen, Madoka Kanai, and Denis Twitchett
skillfully summarise many of the problems with the writing of History in general. It is
helpful, therefore, to look at what they say in some detail:
The task (for a History of Japan) was not to be easy. The details of Japanese
history are not matters of common knowledge among Western historians. The
cultural mode of Japan differs greatly from that of the West, and above all there
are the daunting problems of terminology and language. (p. v)
They go on to point out that “foreign scholars have been assisted by the remarkable
achievements of the Japanese scholars during the last century in recasting their history
Religions 2022, 13, 490 17 of 36
which is secular modern professional historiography, the discipline that entered Japan at
Meiji associated with a concept of time as empty and homogenous.
The idea of uppercase professionalised History is ambiguous because the older uses of
the English language word ‘history’ as records of past events was, in some ways, superseded
by the new professionalised discipline that looked for universal meanings and cause–effect
relationships and patterns of meaning. The modern professionalised study of History
was born in a context of doctrines of progress—the progress of nations from oppression
into liberty, progress from religious superstition to scientific enlightenment, progress from
magic to secular reason, progress as the unfolding of the destiny of nations, the progress of
world history, progress as the qualitative development of individuals and nations, progress
as the result of Individual self-realisation through educational improvements, progress
by way of liberalisation and free markets, commodity exchange and the accumulation
of private property. One could add progress from history (myth and legend) to History
(objective fact).
Historical progress from the backward past into the Enlightenment future, and also
evolutionary time, are surely very different from the ideas of time, or the experience of time
typical even of medieval Christian Europe, let alone Heian or pre-Heian Japan. We surely
cannot assume that time as a concept and an experience was the same before and after the
Copernican revolution, or before and after the invention of mechanical clocks, or before
and after the introduction of factory time, or before and after world time zones. Nor can we
assume that the measurement of time, nor the experience of time, was the same before and
after Meiji. It might be that the claims and demands of ‘modern progress and development’
and the introduction of the universal, uniform, monolithic time of History was as radical as
any other change instituted during Meiji (Tanaka 2006). Just as local nations and histories
are subsumed within the uppercase modern Nation States and Histories, so local times are
subsumed by Universal Time along a single axis of progress and development.
Even in 17th century England, the main reference was Biblical times and the revelation
of God’s order. The purpose of good government was to maintain that order instituted by
Christ. Words such as ‘progress’ and ‘revolution’ existed but had different meanings from
the ones they acquired in the 18th century. Compare the progress of the king’s entourage
around the streets of London to the progress of the human mind through universal history.
Compare the revolution of heavenly bodies or the turning of a cartwheel with the French
Revolution. Historians and other professional, middle-class academics live and work in a
time-consciousness that, it seems reasonable to suppose, is very different from the people
he or she claims to be describing. We are all located in conceptions of time that are peculiar
to modernity—clock time, work time, production and consumption time, GMT and world
time zones, skeletal Christian calendars once rich in sacred collective festivals—holy-days,
but now hollowed out and transformed into empty vacation time.
How can we assimilate the experience and concept of time of the modern professional
historian with that of feudal Christian Europe, or pre-Heian or Heian or Edo Japan, or
ancient Egypt, or the vast varieties of time-consciousness, expressed in the cosmologies
and cosmogonies of hunter–gatherers, forest-dwellers, agricultural peasants, literate elites
of ancient complex societies, and so on?
Is it sufficient to say that, because the ancient people who lived in the archipelago
that is today in English called ‘Japan’, had a sense of lineal time—the lineage succession of
king-priests—that therefore they had “historical consciousness”?
Brown also uses the expression “form of historical writing”:
Still another form of historical writing appeared during the last two centuries of
the Heian period: the military tales (gunki monogatari) . . . Linealism was a
prominent characteristic of all historical works written in Japan’s aristocratic age,
and it continued to affect Japanese historical writing in later times. (pp. 519–20;
my italics)
The adjective ‘historical’ is not problematised but is slipped into the historian’s con-
struction of the past almost unconsciously. This strengthens the feeling that we are caught
Religions 2022, 13, 490 21 of 36
in a circularity, where what is presupposed is invoked to establish its origins. Here again,
we find the sense of time constructed partly from the lineal succession of sacred rulers
descended from the Sun God described as Japanese historical works, and forms of Japanese
historical writing, thus deploying an ambiguous and unstable meaning of ‘history’ and
‘historical’ to further embed a confusion of the sense of time of a remote period:
. . . the whole of Nara culture, including history writing, was affected by prin-
ciples enunciated in the Confucian Classics, and from early Nara until today,
Japanese historical works have usually born a Confucian stamp. (p. 521)
According to Brown, the reason why the people of the ancient period developed a
historical consciousness whereas, by implication, the Chinese did not, is that:
Instead of being influenced by a Chinese-style absorption in the rise and fall of
dynasties, Japanese aristocrats were preoccupied with a single line of sovereigns
created by the Sun Goddess. Instead of assuming that the course of human affairs
was shaped by the moral and immoral actions of humans as propounded in
the Confucian Classics, ancient chronicles made vitalistic strength (ikioi) a major
historical determinant. And instead of accepting Buddhist doctrines of inevitable
decline, poets and chroniclers were buoyed by a widespread assumption that the
future would be better than the present. (p. 548)
What this seems to imply is that proper History is comprised of lineality (one king-
priest following another in a lineage); ‘this worldly’ vitality, and optimism, an optimistic
belief in the future. Surely, though, the author is not assimilating an optimism about the
future to the optimism of progress in the sense that, say, Steven Pinker (2018), in his book
Enlightenment Now, has optimism? To claim these as equivalent to historical consciousness
seems a very reduced concept of ‘historical consciousness’.
Brown claims that “Recent mythological studies enable us to see that the Kojiki and
Nihon shoki myths have a definite historical cast. They can be seen to deal with three
successive stages of creation . . . ” (p. 527). Surely this confuses the practice of modern
history and its claims to objective scientific factuality with what modern historians wished
to supersede—myths and legends. The author is working with a concept of ‘history’ that is
too flexible to be believable.
These characteristics of historical consciousness thrived “in constant tension with
polar opposites”:
That is, a belief in Japan’s sacred imperial line was in conflict with imported
Chinese ideas of a cyclical rise and fall of dynasties; Shinto preoccupation with
the life creating power of the kami (native deities) always stood against the
Confucian principle that events in human history are affected by virtuous or
non-virtuous behavior; and historical assumptions of future improvement were
seriously challenged by Buddhist doctrines of inevitable deterioration over time
and by the Confucian belief in the “golden age of antiquity”. (p. 505)
The historian’s deployment of the idea of conflicting polar opposites appears as a tech-
nique for over-essentialising a specifically ‘Japanese’ consciousness. One can understand
and appreciate difference, such as, the difference between the typical ways of thinking of the
elites ruling in different power centres. However, it seems surprising that the author wishes
to make a case for the “uniqueness” of the “Japanese historical expression” in polarised
contrast to “Chinese ideas of a cyclical” time:11
But a study of Japanese historical expression in these pre-800 years indicates
that beliefs, ideas, and assumptions on the Japanese side of the polarity account for
uniqueness in the Japanese historical outlook and help us identify and understand
early stages in the evolution of historical consciousness. (p. 505; my italics)
One can understand a historian claiming to be able to identify some difference of em-
phasis, some distinctiveness and peculiarity. However, to describe the difference between
Chinese and Japanese concepts and experiences of time in terms of “uniqueness” and “po-
Religions 2022, 13, 490 22 of 36
larity” seems to set up an overly essentialised contrast. Was there such a thing as Chinese
against Japanese consciousness? This seems too much like anachronistic attributions of
modern senses of identity. After all, the author is not denying the presence in the ancient
period of imported forms of thought deriving from Buddha and Confucius, for instance,
only that these were confronted and challenged by indigenous ones that were different in
emphasis. It is almost as though the author is attempting to turn alternative concepts of
time into an essentialised difference, a binary polar opposition.
Furthermore, the rather stark contrast between “a belief in Japan’s sacred imperial
line . . . in conflict with imported Chinese ideas of a cyclical rise and fall of dynasties”
seems offset and ameliorated by the Chinese practice of compiling official chronicles “to
glorify and sanctify the imperial line of descent and to add legitimacy and authority to
the position of the current ruler” (p. 514). It may well be that the practices of keeping
chronicles had differences, but to spin the differences of convention into polar opposites
may be over-determined by the author’s desire to assert the early existence of “Japanese
historical consciousness”. And again, the author qualifies this supposed opposition by
making room for challenges, when, for example, he points out that:
Linealism was nevertheless severely challenged in the middle of the eighth
century by rulers who were influenced by Buddhist conceptions of sovereignty.
Evidence of this challenge is most clearly seen in the contemporary chronicle (the
Shoku Nihongi) that covers events at court from 697 to 791. (p. 514)
7.2. Vitalism
The author’s concept of ‘vitalism’ is put with ‘linealism’ and ‘optimism’ to make up
“the core of Japanese historical thought in these early times . . . ” (p. 521; my italics). Vitalism
is an idea that stems “from a constant preoccupation with the origins and enrichment of
physical life” (p. 504) and is identified with kami: “ . . . Japanese assumptions and ideas
concerning the passage of time have been influenced since early times by a deep and
pervasive belief that the kami were worshiped, above all, for their mysterious power to
create, enrich, or prolong any form of physical life” (p. 522). I cannot believe that this is
really sufficient to give us the equivalent of a historical consciousness deeply implicated
in a concept of empty, homogenous universal time, one that was also not available to
Europeans before around the 17th or 18th century.
7.3. Optimism
The third characteristic of early historical consciousness (optimism about the im-
mediate future) emerged as a by-product of interaction between the first two
characteristics: linealism . . . and vitalism. Although linealism is revealed when
examining ancient historical writings against the backdrop of Chinese belief in
dynastic cycles, and vitalism, against the backdrop of Confucian concepts of
moral power, optimism is reflected in resistance to Buddhist doctrines of historical
decline. Like the first two characteristics, the third has roots that run deep into
‘prehistoric’ times. (p. 537; my italics)
Why should we assume that Buddhist doctrines of decline are doctrines of historical
decline? The meaning of history and historical is what is at stake. This expression smuggles
into the text a circularity. And surely what follows is a contradiction: “ . . . people were
not then absorbed in questions about either the distant past or the distant future but in the
forward movement of life through seasons and life cycles” (p. 538).
Again, the aforementioned suggests that, while distinctive tendencies of the thinking
and attitudes of the literate ruling elites of the ancient period might be validly identified by
an expert such as the author Brown, there are, simultaneously, factors that balance them out,
or at least invalidate stark polarisations and binary oppositions. There is circularity and
confusion in the author’s determination to attribute the ambiguous expression “historical
consciousness” to a time and place that was dominated by other conceptions.
Religions 2022, 13, 490 23 of 36
we find the expression ‘kami worship’ (a term redolent of monotheistic theology) and that
the rites are referred to in passing as ‘religious’:
. . . concrete evidence of linkage between kami worship and the rule of hereditary
kings and queens . . . it seems logical to deduce that the queen and those who
followed her were performing rites by which their positions on one particular
line of descent were sanctified by divine beings, possibly already designated as
kami. This linkage between hereditary rulers and religious rites is more sharply
defined by archaeological evidence for the following Yamato period (ca. 250–589).
(pp. 506–7; my italics)
Could the rites not equally have been described as ‘political’? My point here is
that in modern parlance, ‘politics’ is put in binary opposition to ‘religion’, which, in
turn, is misleadingly identified with the ‘sacred’. However, here, “politically” is put into
conjunction with “the sacred . . . imperial line”.
These terminological confusions may seem unavoidable and normal, and it may even
seem unfair and nit-picking to criticise an author for using such common expressions.
However, this is not a personal attack on the author, but an analysis of the displaced
meanings conveyed by the uncritical deployment of tropes. I would suggest that an
accusation of ‘unfairness’ is a defence that assists and promotes the normalisation and
universalisation of modern ideological terminology. It is surely an anachronistic fallacy to
attribute modern discursive representations, which are the product of a particular colonial
episteme and entirely normalised in a world of invented religions and imaginary modern
secular nation states, to sets of human relations and orders of power that simply did not
think in such terms. The accumulation of instances of their deployment compounds the
distortions that are already inherent and unavoidable in representations of the past. It
conveys the teleological idea that the period he describes as ancient or pre-800 AD was
already working its way into ‘our’ advanced modernity but had not quite arrived.
The author implicitly affirms this point when he deploys the expression ‘priestly ruler’
and ‘the sacred chain of priestly descent’ (p. 508). I have already quoted Wilson, who is also
a vastly qualified expert in this field, that the religious was political and the political was
religious, and that the two are encapsulated in the category matsurigoto. The idea of a
‘priestly ruler’ tacitly draws attention to the point that the distinction between religious and
secular rulers is a modern European one. The English, French, and American revolutions
have been described as ‘revolutions’ because they subverted the established power of the
sacred monarchs of the Christian ancien regime. It is almost precisely what the Americans
wanted the Edo and Meiji rulers to incorporate into their written constitution. They were
criticised for failing to achieve this in the Meiji Constitution of 1889 and this is one of the
corrections that the US occupying administration made when it instructed the production
of a new Constitution (1946) that clearly separated priest and governor.
Such an expression ‘priestly ruler’ may be conceptually much closer to the medieval
and early modern Christian European sacred monarchs. I say this not to try to assimilate
ancient Japan to medieval Europe, but rather to relativise and provincialise the modern
cognitive apparatus (Chakrabarty 2000; Masuzawa 2005). The distinction that was rhetor-
ically constructed in the 17th century between ‘religion’ and ‘non-religious government’
embodied a critique of priestly rulers and sacred monarchs. The separation of ‘govern-
ment’ and ‘governor’ from ‘religion’ and ‘priest’ was a fundamental project of bourgeois
modernity, and quickly defined the emergence of the idea of ‘the state’—especially the
Republic—as distinct from the ‘estate’ of the sacred monarch. It also became closely allied
to the discourse on secular scientific progress that emerged most fully around the time that
modern History was being imagined in the early 19th century.
There is, therefore, an inherent danger in attributing such imaginaries as ‘state’, ‘pol-
itics’ or ‘secular rulers’ to medieval and early modern Europe. Yet, here, the author is
attributing them to the ancient period of Japan. The reference to “secular rulers” when
talking about the sutras is problematic for the same reasons: “One of them, the Benevolent
King Sutra (Ninno-kyo), directs this message to secular Rulers . . . ” (p. 514).
Religions 2022, 13, 490 25 of 36
Many readers will feel confused that sacred king-priests who performed ‘religious rites’
were ‘secular rulers’. The problem is that, even in the context of English history, these terms
are unstable in meaning and referent. In late medieval England, sacred Christian monarchs
were sometimes referred to as ‘secular’ in the older deployments of that term. However,
the ‘secular priesthood’ was an even more common expression. Today, the conjunction
of ‘priest’ and ‘secular’ seems contradictory. This is because the term ‘secular’ became
transformed in the dominant discourse of modernity to mean ‘non-religious’. Furthermore
the ‘secular courts’ worked hand in hand with the ecclesiastical courts to bring heretics
to justice. This makes the term ‘secular’ as ambiguous and unclear as ‘religious’ and
‘historical’, and invites confusion when introducing it into a representation of the Japanese
(or European) past.
The idea of the ‘non-religious’ is a co-product of the modern idea of religion. In the
older discourse, ‘the religious’ were the monks, friars, and nuns who belonged to the
‘religious orders’ and renounced the world. However, the dominant modern usage of
‘religious’ is generic and strongly linked to the modern discourse on generic ‘religion’ and
‘religions’. Yet, in yayoi times, according to the author, there were “religious artefacts”,
“religious ritual” and “religious practices” associated with “kami worship” (p. 522).
The expression ‘a state religion’ feels truly anachronistic (p. 540).
The author also resorts—like so many historians—to expressions from contemporary
Sociology such as “social and political control” (p. 522) and “socioreligious relationships”
(p. 524). The conjoining of two terms that are each already unclear in referent is ubiquitous
among academics and merely compounds the problem of meaning.
It is one thing to say that the shrines that housed the kami and the temples that housed
the Buddhas were different, as in, “Both kami shrines and Buddhist temples supported
the position of priestly rulers” (p. 526). However, to say that “Buddhism was clearly
distinguished from Shintoism” (p. 525) is to import modern orientalist essentialisations
of world religions. Perhaps it is unfair to criticise Brown for this, given that the critique
of religion as a category, though initiated by W. C. Smith of Harvard in 1962, had hardly
started in the 1980s, which may have been when Brown was writing. One cannot blame the
historian. How could he avoid it? The professionalised scientific study of religion invented
these entities and is still propagating the discourse on world religions. I am directing
the reader’s attention to these points because there is a pervasive issue of how modern
categories such as History, Nation, and Religion are projected anachronistically back into
the past: “The third stage of pre-Nara linealism (pp. 589–710) was not associated with
mound building but with the construction of Buddhist temples following the introduction
and spread of Buddhism in the sixth century”. (p. 510).
The expression, “the spread of Buddhism”, is so common today that it seems as
natural as spreading butter on toast. We all suppose we know what is meant. However,
the invention of this kind of language is too convenient, and instead of helping us to
understand, it tends to obscure any view of the grassroots meanings, cognitions, institutions,
and processes of power.
It seems that building Buddhist temples and venerating Buddhist artefacts was, in
some ways, a continuation of the function of building mounds, which in itself is an interest-
ing point, but it does not amount to the presence of a ‘world religion’ in the modern sense.
This tendency to reliance on modern neologisms such as Buddhism is, to some degree,
broken down with more manageable expressions such as statues, sutras, memorial services,
and deceased clan heads:
Historical references to hundreds of Buddhist temples built in Japan during
the following century leave little doubt that making Buddhist statues, reading
Buddhist sutras, and holding Buddhist memorial services were largely to console
and honor the souls of deceased clan heads. (p. 511)
In the first instance, these sentences go some way towards deconstructing ‘Buddhism’
by rightly indicating a difference—these acts (building temples and statues, and reciting the
sutras) were less about enlightenment and liberation from the wheel of karma than about
Religions 2022, 13, 490 26 of 36
venerating the ancestors. Unfortunately, any gain is immediately lost by the sentence that
immediately follows: “Thus Buddhism already stood at the core of what has been loosely
called Japanese ancestor worship” (p. 511).
The idea of “Buddhism” standing “at the core” of “Japanese ancestor worship” is to
pile one essentialised entity onto another. It transforms valid distinctions into gross, reified
abstractions.
(3) Karl F. Friday (ed) (2017), The Routledge Handbook of Premodern Japanese History, London
& New York: Routledge12
This is an impressive collection of essays that only recently came into my hands and
I have been unable to read the whole book. I only have the time and space in this short
essay to look critically at the methodological implications of some aspects of the book’s
construction (Friday 2017).
The title of the book is a simple announcement that there is such a thing as “Premodern
Japanese History”. However much contestation there might be about ‘premodern”, “Japan”,
or “history”, it is has the grammatical form of a statement of simple fact.
Part 2 makes it clear that there were ‘political institutions’ in this imagined premodern
Japanese community. These were exemplified by ‘the state’ and its early formation. The
inevitable suggestion of development is found in part of the title of the chapter by Mikael
S. Adolphson (2000), “From classical to medieval . . . ”, and the frequent use of the term
‘medieval’ in the title of several of the chapters locates a dominant sense of universal
historical time.
‘Religion’—which is tacitly a universal essence—was also present in those imagined
communities. There are chapters on “Religion in archaic Japan” by William E. Deal,
“Religion in Nara and Heian Japan” by Mikael Bauer, and “Religion in Medieval Japan” by
Brian Ruppert (2017).
The title of Part 3 is “Society and Culture”, and the title of Part 4 is “Economy and
Technology”. This parading of abstractions implies that it is possible to distinguish between
religion, society, culture, and economy, not only today but in the imagined communities
of premodern Japan. This is the mythological language of modernity transformed into
universal commonplaces. It is how an imaginary past is invented with the rhetorical
inventions of the present.
In his Introduction the Editor Friday engages ambiguously in a reifying construction
of the Past, and, simultaneously, in its deconstruction. His first announcement is “History
changes” (p. 1). This suggests that there is something there to change, “the Past itself,
that must be immutable”. However, the supposedly immutable Past is distinguished
from the mutable representations of historians that change with each generation, and the
imaginative reconstructions that are “assembled to enrich a society’s understanding of
itself”. Is this dichotomy between the immutable past itself and the mutable representations
of that past intended ironically? Moreover, I wonder if there is such a thing as “a society”
with “self-understanding”? It is one cliché after another. I suggest that our impulse to reify
the dominant categories as though they stand for something real and objective persists
amidst the critical and deconstructivist turn.
To “reconstruct premodern Japan” is to invent it. It is to write a particular kind
of fiction—or “fictive writing” (Munslow 2012)—that serves the present order of things.
The secular discipline of History is itself a modern construction, or a construction of the
‘modern’. This circularity is evident where Friday says that the book “reflects prevailing
conventions within the profession that divide Japanese history into three major epochs
(premodern, early modern and modern) or two (premodern and modern) with the break
at or around 1600” (p. 1). This amounts to a ritual reconfirmation of ‘the modern’ and its
universal time as the locus of the real. It is a teleological scheme that makes ideas about
progress and development from the past to the present inevitable. It embeds universal
modern History into the order of things.
Friday recognises this. He refers specifically to the ‘teleological’ implication of the
expression “premodern Japan” (p. 2). However, he seems to dismiss it as mere “hypercrit-
Religions 2022, 13, 490 27 of 36
The myth-making that seems arguably to be the function of History has been growing
as more and more young people, in the search for meaning and for jobs, are recruited:
Since the 1960s scholarship on premodern Japan has broadened, deepened and
expanded exponentially. In both Japan and the West an unprecedented number of
specialists have entered the field. Collectively their work is marked by a shift in
focus from the history of elites to a broader examination of social structures and
their intersection with political, economic, institutional and cultural evolution
. . . analysis guided by theoretical constructs borrowed from the social sciences;
and a fundamental reassessment of nearly all the key tenets of what was once the
received wisdom. (p. 5)
I suggest that the key tenets of received wisdom are heavily present, and fairly buzzing
with metaphysical abstractions such as ‘social structures’, and the imposition on the imagi-
nary ‘other’ of ‘religious’, ‘economic’, ‘social’ and ‘cultural’ institutions, and evolution. The
challenge for those who claim to be writing specifically about religion, and religious institu-
tions and practices, is to explain what specifically distinguishes the religious elements from
the cultural, from the social structures, from the politics, and from the economics? What
criteria are operating in the identification of a practice as specifically religious? The fact
that there is a tradition of scholarship that makes this assumption does not validate it.
The Routledge Handbook of Premodern Japanese History contains Brian Ruppert’s chapter
on “Religion in Medieval Japan”. Ruppert points out that “one scholar”—he is referring to
Jason Ananda Josephson—“has argued that the term ‘religion’ (shūkyō in modern Japanese)
should not be used in reference to Japan prior to the Meiji restoration in 1868” (p. 330). It is
unfortunate that the influence of Josephson’s (2012) otherwise excellent book The Invention
of Religion in Japan should have conveyed the idea that there is only one scholar saying such
a thing about religion, and that the stipulation about Japan should be so insular, and not
include any recognition that the issue of the modern discourse on religion is global.
Ruppert tries to sidestep the problem—“Some kind of terminology must be used
to convey the broad set of beliefs and practices in premodern Japan, and most scholars
continue to use the term since there are few useful alternatives” (p. 330). This entirely
misses the point that the way one classifies ‘beliefs and practices’ has an effect on our
understanding. It is not simply a question about what is ‘useful’. Useful for what? It
might suggest, for example, that the institutionalised practices that the writer identifies
as religious have essentially nothing to do with power, or hierarchy, or government, or
warfare, or technology, or the production of food, or household etiquette, or the ordering
of life in villages. It cuts the joint in ‘unnatural’ ways and distorts the self-understanding
of the people who the historian is claiming to represent. Ruppert’s discussion of what
he refers to as medieval Japanese religion is highly proficient within its own scholarly
parameters, and yet lacking in any kind of familiarity with, or interest in, the wider critical
literature on the invention of ‘religion’ or ‘Buddhism’.
Given that Ruppert is deploying a descriptive and analytical term that is applied
globally to a vast mass of data about human institutions and practices, what common
feature would he identify? I also cannot help wondering how Ruppert or any of his
co-religionists would deal with the argument of the author discussed earlier, Phillippe
Buc, on the comparative role of ‘religion’ in the warfare of medieval Japan and medieval
Christian Europe.
(4) Jason Ananda Josephson (2012) The Invention of Religion in Japan, Chicago: University of
Chicago Press
In contrast, Josephson’s (2012) monograph, The Invention of Religion in Japan, has been
a significant addition to the critical investigation into the category of religion. This is the
book that the previous author, Ruppert, cited but did not seem to think was sufficiently
relevant to his own work to be given much serious consideration. I am interested in the
positive aspects of Josephson’s book, and I am deeply impressed by his language skills, for
he reads in several languages, apparently including Japanese, Chinese, Dutch, German, and
Religions 2022, 13, 490 29 of 36
French, as well as English. He produced new material to add to the existing discussions of
the way in which ‘religion’ entered into the Japanese language as shūkyō:
Drawing on a wide range of historical materials, I trace the sweeping changes—
intellectual, legal, and cultural—brought about by the construction of the category
of religion in nineteenth-century Japan. (p. 5)
The main categories that he subjects to critical analysis are religion, science, and
superstition as they played out in a ‘trinary’ formation as part of the rhetorical powerplay
whereby the Japanese elites were obliged to formulate their own understandings of foreign-
imposed categories:
I see a trinary formation in which the “real” (or in its political form, the “secular”)
is negated by “superstition,” which is in turn negated by “religion”. I will explore
not only the genealogy of religion in Japan, but also the entangled genealogies of
the secular and superstition. (p. 5)
This is a productive aspect of his book. It clarifies the rhetorical manoeuvres that
the Japanese elites deployed to formulate a secular Shinto nation state. The idea that a
trinary rhetorical relation between religion, superstition, and a secular scientific Shinto
operated in the Japanese invention of a modern Constitutional Nation State is interesting
and may have wider relevance. In 17th century England, for example, and, presumably,
Christendom more widely, in the reports on foreign travel and the encounters with savages
and barbarians, there is a tendency to distinguish between True Religion and the false
beliefs and practices that might look superficially like religion but are really superstitions,
the irrational substitutions of true religion. These practices included marriage, child rearing,
government, diet, technology, and much else. There was a Christian, rational, civilised way
to do most things.
In the late 18th century, the US Constitution registered a change in the discursive form
of ‘religion’, in its privatisation of religion and its separation from government. The Bill of
Rights grants a special right to the personal and private practice of ‘religion’, while also
protecting the government and the state from religion. However, the older discourse on
Religion as Christian Truth was still very much available, even at a time when a few writers
were advocating rights for the religions of ‘Hindoos’, ‘Mohammedans’, Jews, and even the
Indian ‘savages’ who either had something like ‘religion’ or had no religion at all. The Bill
of Rights does not define with any precision what is meant by religion or make an explicit
distinction between religion and superstition. However, it is arguably there, implicitly.
It was in the thinking of the Founders such as Jefferson (Fitzgerald 2007a). Today, many
or most nations have court procedures or special agencies such as the British Charities
Commission for deciding whether or not a practice is a genuine religion or not (Owen and
Taira 2015; Taira 2010).
I would like to extend Josephson’s line of thinking here on a third term towards the
chain of binaries that have been rhetorically deployed as correspondences to the religion–
nonreligion binary: not only religion/politics and religion/science, but also faith/knowledge;
fiction/reality; metaphysics/empiricism; spirit/matter; supernatural/natural; other world/this
world; subjective/objective; inner/outer; value/fact. These oppositions are ubiquitous in
the construction of modern consciousness. All of these oppositional distinctions are de-
ployed in a circle of binary substitutions to validate each other. And yet all of them are
contested, non-observable abstractions that organise our knowledge. These are all signs in
the signalling system that constitutes modern secular progress against the backwardness of
religion and superstition. Is there a third term for each of these?
Josephson’s research on Shinto is interesting and worthwhile. He enhances our
understanding of the manufacture of Shinto as a non-religious state ideology, linking it
to the 18th century Kokugaku movement that “rendered Shinto as a ‘science’ . . . what
kokugaku Shinto offered to supply Meiji leaders was not a faith, but a form of knowledge
and a model for statecraft” (p. 19).
Religions 2022, 13, 490 30 of 36
He goes on to point out that, “The concept of a nonreligious Shinto was useful to the
Meiji state because it allowed them to interweave Shinto into the fabric of government,
and to mandate the performance of Shinto rituals without contravening new guarantees of
religious freedom” (pp. 94–95).
Josephson says that this idea of a nonreligious Shinto:
is a problem for scholars because it does not fit many contemporary models of
religion, modernity, or the conflict between religion and science. Particularly
problematic is the fact that the formation and ascent to power of something called
‘Shinto,’ this putatively premodern religion—polytheist and nature worshiping—
coincided not with a premodern politics (Japanese feudalism say) but precisely
with the rise of the modern nation-state. (pp. 94–95)
This is less clear to me. Josephson seems to be anachronistically referring to “premodern
politics (Japanese feudalism say)” just at the same moment he is describing the invention of
‘religion’ and the invention of a modern secular Japanese Nation State. Surely then, the idea
of premodern politics is also as problematic as a premodern nation state or a pre-modern
religion? It could be, as one reviewer helpfully pointed out, that his intended meaning is
a critique of the anachronistic deployment of all three categories. I would prefer to think
that this was his intended meaning. Even in England, there was no consistent discourse
on ‘politics’ as a distinct domain before the second half of the 17th century—even at the
height of the civil wars in the 1640s. There was no ‘premodern politics’ in English. Generic
‘politics’, like generic ‘religion’, is a key term in the rhetorical construction of the ‘modern’.
I do not want to put words into his mouth, but I think Josephson would probably agree that
it would be a mistake to assume a discourse on ‘politics’ in Japan before the invention of the
idea of government separated from ‘religion’. I hope he would agree that these discursive
categories all arose together in a mutual construction of ‘modernity’.
One possible answer to the apparent dilemma of a non-religious State Shinto is that
the Japanese elites had observed US, French, or British symbols of national allegiance, the
rituals that surround supposedly non-religious modern nation states, and the emotions
of patriotism and nationalism associated with them. The patriotic sentiments around
the American nation, its manifest destiny, its exceptionalism, and its public rituals are
difficult to distinguish from what, in other contexts, might be described as ‘religion’ or
‘civil religion’.
It is also worth bearing in mind that, though the Meiji Constitution was modelled to
some degree on the Prussian Constitution of the 1850s, the German nation was not unified
until 1871, so it only just predates the Meiji Constitution. Moreover, it is difficult to separate
the German nation from sentiments of patriotism and self-sacrifice. Much the same can
be said about the patriotic fervour of Great Britain and France. Furthermore, from the
Japanese perspective, the so-called ‘advanced’ nations might have looked rather backward
on the basis of their own criteria. In the case of Britain, the Monarch was—and still is—the
Head of Church and State, which makes the idea of Great Britain as a modern non-religious
secular nation state problematic, to say the least. This is yet another example about who
controls the dominant narrative. In the case of France, Church and State were not formally
separated until 1905. Women were not able to vote in Britain until after World War I nor in
France until 1944. So much for progress.
Modern, supposedly progressive, nation states are all built on mythological foun-
dations, with national history frequently providing the narratives. Recently invented
traditions are displayed in elaborate state rituals that embed the modern state in illusions of
antiquity. Modern states are stage managed to appear continuous with ancient times, great
events, and founders and heroes. Much has been written by scholars on the ‘civil religion
of America’, which surely ought to be a non-sequitur or an oxymoron. Some scholars have
attempted to classify secularism as a religion. Some have claimed that nationalism is a
pseudo-religion. These interventions highlight the extent to which the religion–secular
binary is unstable, and the contingency of the criteria for deciding what goes into one
side of the binary and what goes into the other. The Japanese male literate elites had
Religions 2022, 13, 490 31 of 36
perhaps concluded, very reasonably, that the secular can look very much like what, in other
contexts, would be considered a ‘religion’. The boundary between the religious and the
non-religious is porous and unstable, and if powerful ‘modern’ nations such as America,
France, Germany, or Britain can institute the sacrificial worship of the nation state in all its
transcendental glory, then why should not Japan?
Josephson claims that:
Previous studies of the genealogy of religion in the West have focused on the
term’s emergence among European intellectuals and its subsequent imposition
on other cultures. I will argue that the modern concept of religion owed less
to Enlightenment scholarly discourse than to the power struggles of interna-
tional diplomacy . . . As this chapter will demonstrate, religion is principally a
diplomatic category whose contours emerged through a process of negotiation.
(p. 73)
Josephson’s description of the power struggles over language in the process of negoti-
ations are valuable. However, “international diplomacy”—as he himself points out—came
out of the barrel of a gun, and surely a major reason why the translation of ‘religion’ was
important was its relations to trade and profit. The invention of ‘religion’ was closely
connected to the invention of a modern language of liberal political economy and private
property rights.
Josephson points out that:
A new language was born in this diplomatic crucible of the mid-nineteenth
century. In the years of intense treaty negotiation from 1853 to 1872, Japanese
translators, working under intense pressure, coined new terminology for a range
of novel ideas. There were few precedents for describing many of the concepts
built into the structures of Euro-American modernity. Although standardization
came much later, this conjuncture ultimately gave birth to new Japanese terms to
describe foreign concepts. Japanese translators formulated neologisms to render
“steamship,” “telegraph,” and other new devices, such as ‘republics’ and ‘rights.’
. . . In each case, new terms were devised when necessary to describe the artifacts
and concepts of modernity. (p. 72)
Clearly this is an important point. Steamships and telegraphs were significant, world-
changing technologies of a concrete and tangible kind. “Rights”—as in the universal rights
of man—and “republics” are also world changing, but they are more abstract, and tend
to congregate with closely related terms such as ‘politics’, ‘political economy’, ‘citizen’,
and ‘nation state’. There is only a limited amount that any of us can achieve in a single
monograph, and Josephson has achieved a lot13 I would, however, encourage him (and
other scholars) to employ his skills to problematise the other related secular categories as
well as ‘religion’. Horii has made important moves in this direction.
To take a couple of fairly random examples, he says:
These developments reflect back onto the global discourse of religion, such that
the political goals of Japanese state officials have shaped, in subtle but significant
ways, our own understanding of that concept today . . . (p. 5)
Later he says that:
. . . the book’s chief business, is to document the belated adoption by some
Japanese policymakers of that concept (religion). One of the more striking features
of this story is that religion takes hold in Japan as a nakedly political category,
first considered useful by politicians and put to directly political uses. (p. 71)
However, what is a distinctively ‘political’ goal? And is not the global discourse on
politics equally as problematic as the global discourse on religion? ‘Politics’ and ‘religion’
are rhetorically fused together in a mutual mystification. This is apparent when Josephson
describes ‘religion’ as a “nakedly political category”.
Religions 2022, 13, 490 32 of 36
I suggest that the family of terms around ‘politics’ and ‘political economy’ are as
problematic as ‘religion’. Josephson discusses The Treaty of Amity and Commerce, also
frequently referred to as the Harris Trade Treaty (1858), as though it was more about
‘religion’ than about what presumably required a raft of key terms around ‘economy’,
property laws, ‘the individual’ as in ‘rights of the individual’, ‘liberty’, ‘society’, and so on.
Townsend Harris (1804–1878), who was the first U.S. consul general to Japan and
who conducted the negotiations, was a devout Christian and an international merchant
from New York who made his money in trade with China, and had interests with Siam,
too. Which was more important to him personally, his faith in money or his faith in Jesus?
Josephson suggests, from a reading of his private diaries, that Christian mission was a more
significant motivation than trade mission. However, he seems ambiguous:
Harris articulates his mission not simply in the prosaic context of commerce,
but as part of a decisive historical moment leading to the advent of Christianity
in Japan. Thus, in his own self-representation at the very least, the progress of
international capitalism was placed in the rhetorical frame of a global religious
mission . . . Hence, while trade was the Harris mission’s primary purpose, it
seems clear that its secondary function was to encourage the spread of Christianity.
(pp. 80–81)
It is well known that Christian missions were closely linked to trade missions globally,
in Africa, China, and south-east Asia for example. The Treaty of Amity and Commerce was
fundamentally about trade and commerce. The significant point about the translation of
religion was, presumably, that it cleared the discursive and juridical arena of any practices
and institutions that stood in the way of liberal capitalism, American concepts of private
property rights, and the legal reforms that facilitated global capitalist institutions. The ‘right
to freedom of religion’ gave access to US business interests. America had many trading
links with China and other Asian countries. On the menu were the opening of ports to US
ships; rights for US ships to secure fuel, in particular, coal, which could be mined in Japan;
fixed low import–export duties, and the granting of extra-territorial rights to US citizens.
The freedom of worship and building of churches was part of the agreement, but was it the
dominant part? Or did it facilitate the dominant part?
Josephson says that the Japanese saw Christianity as a ‘heresy’ and Christians as a
threat, and that its introduction would threaten the stability of Japan and sow the seeds of
rebellion and chaos (pp. 84–85). This seems like a very reasonable fear, both in the light of
the Japanese experience with the Portuguese and Spanish in the 16th century, and also in
the contemporary situation in Asia—the Opium wars being only one example. Opening
Japan or China, or any other colonised people to Christians, was simultaneously opening
them up to trade, ‘markets’, changes in land ownership, American and European notions of
private property, and incorporation into the progress of universal History and the cognitive
dominance of Euro-America.
8. Conclusions
My contribution to this Special Issue has been a response to the task given by the editor,
viz “to problematize the concept ‘religion’ in Japanese contexts”. I have felt it necessary to
continue the project that I was pursuing in Fitzgerald (2000a), by placing the problem of
Japanese ‘religion’ in the wider, global context of colonial capitalism. I pursued that agenda
in the books that quite quickly followed (Fitzgerald 2007a, 2007b, 2011, 2015b; also many
journal articles and book chapters). This project has required consideration of the origins
of the contemporary discourses on religion and religions in 17th century England with
a class of property-owning men without rights of representation, anxious to exploit new
colonial opportunities, but frustrated by the arbitrary powers of the sacred monarch, and
the domination of law and government by Lords Temporal and Ecclesiastical. This scenario
helps us to understand the demands for the separation of Church and State, a discourse on
religion and politics, and its emigration to the North American colonies. This discourse was
quite fundamental to ‘the Enlightenment’ in France, Germany, Scotland, and more widely.
Religions 2022, 13, 490 33 of 36
This critical, deconstructive narrative helps us to see more clearly the ideological function of
the generic category of religion in the wider configuration of modern secular categories. In
particular, I have focused on religion in relation to the Enlightenment Project of Universal
History, and the invention of ‘Japan’ as an imagined community in the form of a modern,
secular, constitutional Nation State. I have argued that we cannot properly analyse the term
‘religion’ and its problematic translation without putting the issue in the wider context of
the colonial civilising mission, the insistence on a written constitution that separates religion
and the state, and the introduction into Japan of American understandings of the Individual
and (his) property rights. In my view, the project must be the critical deconstruction not
of religion alone, but of the unconsciously and thus, uncritically reproduced ensemble
of signs. This is the signalling system that transforms the dominant power relations of
modernity into the really real, the inescapable nature of things, the normal.
Notes
1 I am grateful to Professor Mitsutoshi Horii for his invitation to contribute to this Special Issue, and for his help in obtaining some
texts. I am also grateful to my six anonymous reviewers. The first three reviewers read an earlier version of my text. One loved it
and highly praised it. I am grateful to that reviewer for his or her appreciation. The other two hated it, struggled to say anything
positive about it, and seemed personally affronted by it, as though I was attacking them. How to explain such opposite views?
To my way of thinking, the negative readings revealed an unfamiliarity with the critical literature from within their own (or
any other) discipline. And they seemed entirely uninterested in my substantial critique of religion and related categories in the
context of English, and, more widely, Christian European discourse. They were especially irritated by my critical reading of
The Cambridge History of Japan. They claimed that it is outdated, idiosyncratic, and not representative of the state of the field.
My response has been an expanded version of the original argument with critical readings of additional texts by historians of
Japan. My purpose in doing this has been to demonstrate that the problems of historical representation found in The Cambridge
History are not idiosyncratically confined to one (supposedly) out-dated text. They are widely and deeply entrenched in the act of
representing the Japanese past. Every text is different, some are more critically aware than others, but there are common problems
and I have tried to identify these. The Cambridge History is different, but not that much different in regard to the problems that I
identify and analyse. My revised and expanded version was then sent to three more anonymous reviewers. They all gave very
positive readings, and I am grateful to them for their helpful suggestions, which they all stressed were only minor. One of these
reviewers felt that the inclusion of the critique of The Cambridge History made the paper unnecessarily long. I appreciate his or her
point. However, after discussing this with Mitsutoshi Horii, I have decided to retain it nevertheless. I want it to stand on record
for reference. It can be skipped by the busy reader without the central argument being damaged. I have incorporated as many of
the other reviewers’ comments as I can in the short time and space available. If I seem to have ignored any of them, I hope this
will not be taken as a lack of appreciation, but as a problem of meeting the editorial deadline for publication.
2 This is obviously not a comprehensive list. There are many contributors to critical religious studies.
3 Holland has significance as the centre of global capital in the 17th century for understanding both the later emergence of Japan as
a major world power and also for our understanding of the origins of global capitalist institutions such as international banking.
4 See my close critical reading of Samuel Purchas in (Fitzgerald 2007a).
5 Alun Munslow (2012) in The History of History, which is a critique of “modernist common-sense empirical, practical realist and
representationalist historians” (Munslow 2012, p. 2) makes a distinction between ‘fictional’ and ‘fictive’ viz. “ . . . every history is
a narrative discourse that is the construction of the historian . . . This is not to say that the (hi)story is a made-up fiction. The
important point is that acknowledging that history is a fictive (as opposed to a fictional) cultural discourse still takes it out of the
ontological category of empirical practical realism . . . ” (Munslow 2012, p. 2) I am personally not convinced by this precise
distinction between fiction and fictive writing but I do feel quite persuaded by his critique of empirical practical realism.
6 I am grateful to Mitsutoshi Horii for drawing my attention to Stefan Tanaka’s (2006) interesting book.
7 Two of the three anonymous readers of an earlier version of this essay objected to my critique of the Cambridge History on
the grounds that it is an old text and does not fairly represent modern historiography of Japan. I find this objection difficult to
comprehend for the reasons given.
Religions 2022, 13, 490 34 of 36
8 I say this on the basis of my analysis of his editorial introduction. I have not read the whole book.
9 I am indebted to Stefan Tanaka, who quotes this near the beginning of his own book on time and history in Japan, briefly
discussed earlier.
10 In his essay “Time and History in Japan”, Wilson also seems determined to find “historical consciousness” in ancient Japan
(Wilson 1980, p. 557). This surprised me, considering the quote on History entering Japan for the first time at Meiji. Like Brown,
Wilson links this historical consciousness to a linear sense of time. At other times, Wilson seems ambivalent on the matter, by
suggesting that the linear and the cyclical were not incompatible and that they co-existed.
11 Compare this with Wilson (1980, p. 560): “Neither Japanese nor Chinese speculations about history show an exclusive bent
toward linear as opposed to cyclical projections”.
12 I am grateful to Mitsutoshi Horii for finding this volume for me. I was unable to read much of it, partly due to time and partly
due to the very small print. I could not find it online.
13 I have not yet been able to read Josephson’s (2017, 2021) more recent works.
References
Adolphson, Mikael S. 2000. The Gates of Power: Monks, Courtiers, and Warriors in Premodern Japan. Honolulu: University of Hawai’i Press.
Anderson, Benedict. 1983. Imagined Communities: Reflections on the Origin and Spread of Nationalism. London: Verso.
Asad, Talal. 1993. Genealogies of Religion: Discipline and Reasons of Power in Christianity and Islam. Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Balagangadhara, S. N. 1994. ‘The Heathen in His Blindness . . . ’: Asia, the West, and the Dynamic of Religion. Leiden: E.J. Brill.
Bloch, Esther, Marianne Keppens, and Rajaram Hedge, eds. 2010. Rethinking Religion in India. London: Routledge.
Bradstock, Andrew. 2010. Radical Religion in Cromwell’s England: A Concise History from the English Civil War to the End of the Commonwealth.
London: I.B. Taurus & Co.
Brown, Delmer M. 1993. The Early Evolution of Historical Consciousness. The Cambridge History of Japan 1: 504–48.
Buc, Philippe. 2020. Civil war and religion in medieval Japan and medieval Europe: War for the Gods, emotions at death and treason.
The Indian Economic and Social History Review 57: 261–87. [CrossRef]
Bury, John Bagnell. 1920. The Idea of Progress: An Inquiry into is Origin and Growth. London: Macmillan & Co.
Butterfield, Herbert. 1931. The Whig Interpretation of History. London: G. Bell.
Carr, Edward Hallett. 1961. What Is History? Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Cavanaugh, William T. 2009. The Myth of Religious Violence. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Chakrabarty, Dipesh. 2000. Provincializing Europe: Postcolonial Thought and Historical Difference. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Chidester, David. 1996. Savage Systems: Colonialism and Comparative Religion in Southern Africa. Charlottesville: University of Virginia Press.
Chidester, David. 2007. Real and imagined: Imperial inventions of religion in colonial southern Africa. In Religion and the Secular:
Historical and Colonial Formations. Edited by Timothy Fitzgerald. London: Equinox.
Collingwood, R. G. 1946. The Idea of History. New York: OUP.
Collins, Rebecca. 2003. Concealing the poverty of traditional historiography: Myth as mystification in historical discourse. Rethinking
History 7: 341–65. [CrossRef]
Dressler, Markus, and Arvind Mandair, eds. 2011. Secularism and Religion Making. New York: Oxford University Press.
Dubuisson, Daniel. 2003. The Western Construction of Religion: Myths, Knowledge, and Ideology. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Dubuisson, Daniel. 2019. The Invention of Religions. Sheffield: Equinox.
Durkheim, Emile. 1912. The Elementary Forms of the Religious Life. Translated by Joseph Swain. London: George Allen & Unwin Ltd.
Fitzgerald, Timothy. 1990. Hinduism and the World Religion Fallacy. Religion 20: 101–18. [CrossRef]
Fitzgerald, Timothy. 1993. Japanese Religion as Ritual Order. Religion 23: 315–41. [CrossRef]
Fitzgerald, Timothy. 1995. Religious Studies as Cultural Studies: A philosophical and anthropological critique of the concept of religion.
Diskus 3: 35–47.
Fitzgerald, Timothy. 1997. A Critique of the Concept of Religion as a cross-cultural category. Method and Theory in the Study of Religion
(MTSR) 9: 91–110. [CrossRef]
Fitzgerald, Timothy. 1999a. Ambedkar, Buddhism and the concept of Religion. In Dalits in Modern India: Essays in honour of Stephen
Fuchs. Edited by S. M. Michael. New Delhi: Vistaar Publications.
Fitzgerald, Timothy. 1999b. Politics and Ambedkar Buddhism in Maharashtra. In Buddhism and Politics in Twentieth Century Asia. Edited
by I. Harris. London and New York: Pinter/Cassells Academic Press.
Fitzgerald, Timothy. 2000a. The Ideology of Religious Studies. New York: Oxford University Press.
Fitzgerald, Timothy. 2000b. ‘Problems with the Category “Religion” in the Study of Hinduism’. (Canada) Occasional Papers. International
Institute of Indian Studies. Reprinted in J. E. Llewellyn (ed.). 2005. Defining Hinduism: A Reader. London: Equinox.
Fitzgerald, Timothy. 2002. ‘Religion’ and ‘the Secular’ in Japan: Problems in history, social anthropology and religious studies. Elec-
tronic Journal of Contemporary Japanese Studies (EJCJS). Available online: http://www.japanesestudies.org.uk/discussionpapers/
Fitzgerald.html (accessed on 20 May 2022).
Fitzgerald, Timothy. 2007a. Discourse on Civility and Barbarity: A Critical History of Religion and Related Categories. New York: OUP.
Fitzgerald, Timothy. 2007b. Encompassing Religion, Privatised Religion and the Invention of Modern Politics. In Religion and the
Secular: Historical and Colonial Formations. Edited by Fitzgerald. London: Equinox Press, pp. 211–40.
Religions 2022, 13, 490 35 of 36
Fitzgerald, Timothy. 2010. Who Invented Hinduism? Rethinking Religion in India. In Rethinking Religion in India. Edited by Esther
Bloch, Marianne Keppens and Rajaram Hedge. London: Routledge, pp. 114–35.
Fitzgerald, Timothy. 2011. Religion and Politics in International Relations: The Modern Myth. London: Continuum.
Fitzgerald, T. 2015a. Negative Liberty, Liberal Faith Postulates and the World Disorder. In Religion as a Category of Government and
Sovereignty. Edited by Trevor Stack, Naomi Goldenberg and Timothy Fitzgerald. Leiden: Brill, pp. 248–79.
Fitzgerald, Timothy. 2015b. Critical Religion and Critical Research on Religion: Religion and Politics as Modern Fictions. Critical
Research on Religion 3: 303–19. [CrossRef]
Fitzgerald, Timothy. 2016. “Postcolonial Remains”: Critical religion, postcolonial theory, and deconstructing the secular-religious
binary. In The Postcolonial World. Edited by Joytsna Singh and David Kim. London and New York: Routledge, pp. 169–83.
Fitzgerald, Timothy. 2017a. The Ideology of Religious Studies Revisited: The Problem with Politics. In Method and Theory in the Study of
Religion: Working Papers from Hannover. Edited by Steffen Führding. Hanover: Leibniz Hannover University/Brill, pp. 124–52.
Fitzgerald, Timothy. 2017b. Critical Religion: Religion is Not a Stand-Alone Category. In THEORY/RELIGION/CRITIQUE: Classic and
Contemporary Approaches. Edited by Richard King. New York: Columbia University Press, pp. 435–56. ISBN 978-0-231-14543-5.
Fitzgerald, Timothy. 2019. Problems of Representation: Buddha Dhamma, Politics, and Nation States. In Secularism, Religion, and
Democracy In South-East Asia. Published in the Series Religion & Democracy: Re-conceptualizing Religion, Culture & Politics in
Global Context. Edited by Vidhu Verma. Delhi: OUP, pp. 27–53.
Fitzgerald, Timothy. 2020. “The Ideology of Religious Studies: Then and now”, (pp. 269–90); and “Response to Contributors”,
(pp. 439–67). In Twenty Years After—The Ideology of Religious Studies. Implicit Religion Special Issue. Guest Edited by Teemu Taira
and Suzanne Owen. London: Equinox Publishing, vol. 22.
Friday, Karl F. 2017. The Routledge Handbook of Premodern Japanese History. London and New York: Routledge.
Fürhding, Steffen. 2013. Religion, Privacy and the Rise of the Modern State. Method & Theory in the Study of Religion 25: 118–31.
Gellner, Ernest. 1983. Nations and Nationalism. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Goldenberg, Naomi. 2012. An Argument for Thinking of Religions as Vestigial States. Critical Religion Association. Available online:
https://criticalreligion.org/2012/03/12/an-argument-for-thinking-of-religions-as-vestigial-states/ (accessed on 22 May 2022).
Goldenberg, Naomi. 2015. The Category of Religion in the Technology of Governance: An Argument for Understanding Religions as
Vestigial States. In Religion as a Category of Governance and Sovereignty. Edited by Trevor Stack, Naomi Goldenberg and Timothy
Fitzgerald. Leiden/Boston: Brill, pp. 280–92.
Goldenberg, Naomi. 2018. There is no ‘religion’ in the Bible. Implicit Religion 21: 13–29. [CrossRef]
Gu, Ming Dong. 2020. What is ‘decoloniality’? A postcolonial critique. Postcolonial Studies 23: 596–600. [CrossRef]
Hall, John Whitney, Marius B. Jensen, Madoka Kanai, and Denis Twitchett, eds. 1993. The Cambridge History of Japan (Vol. 1). Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Hallisey, Charles. 1995. Roads Taken and Not Taken in the Study of Theravāda Buddhism. In Curators of the Buddha: The Study of
Buddhism under Colonialism. Edited by Donald S. Lopez Jr. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, pp. 31–61.
Hardacre, Helen. 1988. The Shinto Priesthood in early Meiji Japan: Preliminary inquiries. History of Religions 27: 3. [CrossRef]
Hardacre, Helen. 1989. Shinto and the State, 1868–1988. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Harrison, Peter. 1990. ‘Religion’ and the Religions in the English Enlightenment. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Harrison, Peter. 2015. The Territories of Science and Religion. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Hill, Christopher. 1972. The World Turned Upside Down: Radical Ideas During the English Revolution. London: Penguin UK.
Hobsbawm, Eric. 1990. Nations and Nationalism since 1780. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Horii, Mitsutoshi. 2012. Deprofessionalization of Buddhist Priests in Contemporary Japan. In Researching Twenty-First Century Japan:
New Directions and Approaches for the Electronic Age. Edited by Timothy Iles and Peter Matanle. London: Lexington Books,
pp. 215–40.
Horii, Mitsutoshi. 2016. The American Imperialism and the Japanese Encounter with ‘Religion’: 1853–1858. Studi e Materiali di Storia
delle Religioni 82: 838–69.
Horii, Mitsutoshi. 2018. The Category of ‘Religion’ in Contemporary Japan: Shūkyō and Temple Buddhism. New York: Palgrave Macmillan.
Horii, Mitsutoshi. 2021. Decolonizing the Modern Myth: ‘Religion’ and ‘Secular’ Categories in Sociology. London: Palgrave Macmillan.
Iggers, Georg G., ed. 2011. Introduction. In The Theory and Practice of History: Leopold von Ranke. London and New York: Routledge,
pp. xi–xlv.
Isomae, Jun’ichi. 2005. Deconstructing ‘Japanese Religion’: A Historical Survey. Japanese Journal of Religious Studies 32: 235–48.
[CrossRef]
Isomae, Jun’ichi. 2007. The Formative Process of State Shinto in Relation to the Westernization of Japan: The concept of ‘religion’ and
‘Shinto’. In Religion and Secular: Historical and Colonial Formations. Edited by Timothy Fitzgerald. London: Equinox, pp. 93–101.
Isomae, Jun’ichi. 2017. Religion, Religious Studies, and Shinto in Modern Japan. In Religion, Theory, Critique: Classic and Contemporary
Approaches and Methodologies. Edited by Richard King. New York: Columbia University Press, pp. 87–96.
Jenkins, Keith. 1991. Rethinking History. London: Routledge.
Josephson, Jason Ānanda. 2012. The Invention of Religion in Japan. London: The University of Chicago Press.
Josephson, Jason Ānanda. 2017. The Myth of Disenchantment: Magic, Modernity, and the Birth of the Human Sciences. Chicago: University
of Chicago Press.
Josephson, Jason Ānanda. 2021. Metamodernism: The Future of Theory. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Religions 2022, 13, 490 36 of 36
King, Richard. 1999. Orientalism and Religion: Postcolonial theory, India and the Mystic East. London: Routledge.
King, Richard. 2013. The Copernican Turn in the Study of Religion. MTSR 25: 137–59. [CrossRef]
King, Richard, ed. 2017. THEORY/RELIGION/CRITIQUE: Classic and Contemporary Approaches. New York: Columbia University Press.
Kuroda, Toshio. 1981. Shinto in the History of Japanese Religion. Journal of Japanese Studies 7: 1–21.
Lehmann, Hartmut, and Melvin Richter, eds. 1996. The Meaning of Historical Terms and Concepts: New Studies on Begriffsgeschichte.
Occasional Paper No. 15. Washington, DC: German Historical Institute. Available online: https://www.ghi-dc.org/fileadmin/
publications/Occasional_Papers/THE_MEANING_OF_historical_terms.pdf (accessed on 6 April 2018).
Locke, John. 1689a. A Letter Concerning Toleration. Translated by William Popple. London: Available online: http://www.constitution.
org/jl/tolerati.htm (accessed on 20 May 2022).
Locke, John. 1689b. Two Treatises on Government. London: Available online: httpshttps://www.yorku.ca/comninel/courses/3025pdf/
Locke.pdf (accessed on 20 May 2022).
Mandair, Arvind-Pal S. 2010. Religion and the Spectre of the West: Sikhism, India, Postcoloniality, and the Politics of Translation. Columbia:
Columbia University Press.
Martin, Craig. 2010. Masking Hegemony: A Genealogy of Liberalism, Religion, and the Private Sphere. Sheffield: Equinox Publishing.
Martin, Craig. 2017. A Critical Introduction to the Study of Religion, 2nd ed. London: Routledge Publishing.
Masuzawa, Tomoko. 2005. The Invention of World Religions: Or, How European Universalism Was Preserved in the Language of Pluralism.
Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Maxey, Trent Elliott. 2014. The “Greatest problem”: Religion and State Formation in Meiji Japan. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University
Asia Center.
McCutcheon, Russell. 1997. Manufacturing Religion: The Discourse on Sui Generis: Religion and the Politics of Nostalgia. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
McCutcheon, Russell. 2018. Fabricating Religion. Berlin: Walter de Gruyter.
Mignolo, Walter D., and Catherine E. Walsh. 2018. On Decoloniality: Concepts, Analytics, Praxis. Durham: Duke University Press.
Munslow, Alan. 1997a. Deconstructing History. London: Routledge.
Munslow, Alun. 1997b. What is History? In Reviews in History. Reviewed by of E. H. Carr. (Review no. 41a). Available online:
https://reviews.history.ac.uk/review/41a (accessed on 20 May 2022).
Munslow, Alun. 2012. A History of History. London: Routledge (Taylor & Francis Group).
Owen, Suzanne, and Teemu Taira. 2015. The Category of ‘Religion’ in Public Classification: Charity Registration of the Druid Network
in England and Wales. In Religion as a Category of Governance and Sovereignty. Edited by Trevor Stack, Naomi Goldenberg and
Timothy Fitzgerald. Leiden: Brill, pp. 90–114.
Penn, William. 1680. The Great Question to be Considered by the King. Edinburgh: Microfiche, National Library of Scotland.
Penn, William. 1701. Pennsylvania Charter of Privileges. Available online: http://www.constitution.org/bcp/penncharpriv.htm
(accessed on 20 May 2022).
Pinker, Steven. 2018. Enlightenment Now: The Case for Science, Reason, Humanism, and Progress. Viking. London: Penguin Books.
Ruppert, Brian. 2017. Religion in medieval Japan. In The Routledge Handbook of Premodern Japanese History. London and New York:
Routledge, chp. 21. pp. 330–50.
Smith, Adam. 1998. An Inquiry into the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations. Edited by Kathryn Sutherland. New York: OUP. First
published 1776.
Smith, Wilfred Cantwell. 1978. The Meaning and End of Religion. London: SPCK Publishing. First published 1962.
Stack, Trevor, Naomi Goldenberg, and Timothy Fitzgerald. 2015. Religion as a Category of Governance and Sovereignty. Leiden: Brill.
Stuckrad, Kocku von. 2013. Discursive Study of Religion: Approaches, Definitions, Implications. Method and Theory in the Study of
Religion 25: 5–25. [CrossRef]
Taira, Teemu. 2010. Religion as a Discursive Technique: The Politics of Classifying Wicca. Journal of Contemporary Religion 25: 379–94.
[CrossRef]
Tanaka, Stefan. 2006. New Times in Modern Japan. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Thomas, Jolyon Baraka. 2019. Faking Liberties: Religious Freedom in American-Occupied Japan. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Tsutsui, William, ed. 2007. A Companion to Japanese History. Oxford: Blackwell.
Walsh, W. H. 1960. Philosophy of History: An Introduction. New York: Harper Torchbooks.
White, Hayden. 1973. Metahistory: The Historical Imagination in Nineteenth-Century Europe. Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press.
Wilson, George Macklin. 1980. Time and History in Japan. The American Historical Review 85: 557–71. [CrossRef]