Saul Friedländer - History and Psychoanalysis-Holmes and Meier Publishers (1975)
Saul Friedländer - History and Psychoanalysis-Holmes and Meier Publishers (1975)
Saul Friedländer - History and Psychoanalysis-Holmes and Meier Publishers (1975)
HISTORY AND
PSYCHOANALYSIS
By the same author
Pius XII and the Third Reich
Knopf, 1966
Kurt Gerstein
Knopf, 1969
by Saul Friedlander
translated by Susan Suleiman
Publisher's Note vi
Introduction 1
3. Collective Phenomena 81
Conclusion 121
Notes 125
Bibhography 151
Index 167
Publisher's Note
Despite the recent growth of a kind of history that is oriented more toward the
—
study of material conditions than of human motivations that is, despite the
recent appearance on the scene of a "history without people"— the great
majority of historians concur with Marc Bloch's statement that "historical
still
Dostoevsky or Proust, and yet neither of these authors reUed on any kind of
systematization or, a fortiori, on any specific psychological theory. Why
should the historian not emulate them? Because, I would argue, the pro-
cedures of literary or artistic creation are totally different from those followed
by the historian: in the former, the creative imagination dominates, giving rise
to affective states that are not subject to documentary analysis or textual
(factual) constraints; in the latter, the dominant mode is necessarily that of
rigorous, rational, and critical progression.^
—
general hypotheses to be formulated in short, for the development of a
conceptual framework utilizable and applicable not only by psychologists
themselves, but by all those who are engaged in disciplines bearing on the
study of man. It is not a question ofeliminating description and intuition; it is
a question of carrying them through, of completing them.
The theoretical arguments that buttress the possibility of systematization in
Introduction 3
to abstract fi-om the real world the variables necessary for establishing general
laws, but rather to grasp each concrete process in all its complexity, and
consequently in its irreducible originality."'- On this point everyone is
doubtless agreed, but it does not at all follow that, in order to describe the
The position we have been defending is not at all new, and many historians
accept it without qualms: a recourse to economics, demography, or sociology
for the enrichment of historical explanation presents no problems for them.
—
But the minute one turns to psychology especially to psychoanalysis, for as
we shall see the other branches of modem psychology do not lend themselves
—
well to historical investigation one finds that strong reservations are ex-
pressed. To be sure, changes in outlook have occurred here too in recent
years,** but the opposition to systematic psychological history, and especially
to the use of psychoanalysis, can still count on a vast and determined majority.
When William L. Langer, then president of the American Historical
Association, declared in 1957 that the integration of the principles of modem
psychology (i.e., psychoanalysis) into historical investigation was the "next
assignment" that historians must undertake,'^ the only reaction he encoun-
tered was astonishment. And when Sir Lewis Namier had recourse to psycho-
analytic concepts in seeking to understand the behavior of certain English
political figures of the 18th century, or Dodds used these concepts
when E. R.
in elucidating the mentality of vast strata of Greek society during the
and foremost, writers of fiction. Is Elizabeth and Essex a work of history? No,
it is a novel.
Barzun works of psychohistory that contain hardly any other
cites certain
explanations than those one finds in historiography in general, the only differ-
ence being in their use of a few technical terms. The examples he chooses are
not very representative, however, and it is not the presence of a technical
vocabulary that matters. Psychohistory can, as we shall see, open up avenues
that simple common sense would have difficulty in discovering. Barzun him-
self recognizes this, even while using it as one of his principal arguments
against psychohistory. He writes: "Suppose a more intensive and systematic
application to history of Freudian ideas about motive. ... If this were
done ... we should have to say that we had in hand, not a piece of histori-
ography of a new kind, but a piece of psychology— or sociology or anthro-
pology. The method of the discipline would have yielded its proper fruit: the
formulation of a determinism. The novelty of the effort would be in having
established a generality with historical instead of living material.""
The above argument leads straight back into the polemic concerning the
nature of history— indeed, Barzun's concluding pages address themselves
directly to that polemic— and affirms the extreme traditionalist position. But
the fact that a successful application of Freudian notions to history would
is
not give rise to a new determinism and would not produce a work of psy-
chology rather than of history; rather, it would (to repeat once again) lead to a
partial explanation of a partial series of events. It would, in other
words,
equally evident that, beneath the apparent chaos of multiple theories, one can
find overlapping areas —
and Unks of various kinds between psychoanalysis
and phenomenological psychology on the one hand, and between both of these
and experimental psychology on the other.
The problem of psychohistorical explanation and of its verification criteria
remains, however, and it is a major one; indeed, it is one of the central issues to
which the present work will address itself. But many other questions exist as
well, questions that Barzun did not even come close to perceiving. . .
The preceding pages may have given the impression that we ourselves have
no doubts about the possibilities offered by the application of psychoanalysis
to history. In fact, however, the present study much concerned with
is as a
critique of psychohistory as with an examination of the new perspectives it
could open up. The "objective limits" of this discipline become apparent
rather quickly, and we shall have to define them clearly: they are the limits of
psychoanalytic explanation in general, but also of psychohistorical explan-
ation in particular, bothon the level of theory and on the more concrete levels
of biographical interpretation and the analysis of collective behavior.
The lacunae of psychoanalytic theory have often been noted, and we shall
refer to them throughout our study. They are especially apparent outside the
therapeutic context, and it is a great temptation to reject the whole body of
Freudian theories because of their most evident shortcomings. For those who
consider, however, that Freud's contribution remains sufficiently rich and
coherent to be used despite its weak points, the problem will be that of selec-
tion, adaptation, and synthesis. Now a great many psychoanalysts— regard-
less of the "school" they belong to — consider their interpretation of Freud's
thought to be an unimpeachable, monolithic whole, and any attempt to be
selective is met with a ferocious opposition more appropriate to the members
of a religious sect than to the representatives of a still-evolving scientific
discipline.
The task of the historian must in fact be to reexamine psychoanalytic
theory in the light of historical evidence, not to overlook the historical givens
for the sake of preserving intact all the elements of the theory. Perhaps the
historian will even be able to suggest certain theoretical innovations, as the
anthropologists did in their time, thanks to the accumulation of convergent
documentary data. In any case, whenever psychoanalytic theory proves insuf-
ficient, the historian will be obliged to complete his explanation by means of
Introduction 7
been cast in a rather systematic mold. We hope that even if the answers are
only tentative, the questions at least will have been clearly formulated. We
hope above all to present enough material to enable one to formulate a judg-
ment about the possibilities and the limits of this new discipline.
1. The Theoretical Framework
whole to be utilizable."
Now an acceptance of these criteria just about excludes the choice of one of
the theories of personality based on experimental psychology —
both for the
aforementioned reasons and because such theories are fundamentally ahis-
torical. This is particularly true of the method of factorial analysis developed
have shown the contrary to be true in the case of Sheldon (see note 5), and
could have done Ukewise for Murphy and Murray. In fact, psychohistorical
investigation must be constantly on the lookout for new explanations, whether
they occur in the field of psychological theory or in those of genetics or
neuropsychology.* Nevertheless, it would seem in the last analysis that only
the psychoanalytic (or psychoanalytically influenced) theories can furnish
psychohistory with an adequate general framework, for these theories are the
only ones that satisfy the criteria which/or r/ie historian are fundamental.
Psychoanalysis itself and the theories influenced by it also constitute a vast
domain whose limits, furthermore, are difficult to trace exactly. One finds
within the different variants of Freudian thought, the theories of Adler and of
it
"time," "development," and "memory" play a primary role in it. Is not the
fundamental principle of analytic therapy that one understands a patient by
gradually getting to know his past? It is impossible to separate psychoanalytic
theory from the "case history" and psychoanalytic concepts have, for the
most part, a temporal dimension: they seek to describe either the development
of a process or a crucial stage in human existence.'
For a historian, the situation and the interaction of events in time consti-
tute the very content of his discipline; for the psychoanalyst, the situation and
the interaction of events in the course of the evolution of the personality
through its various stages constitute the essential basis of his investigation.
For the one as for the other, the evolution of man is determined by the past. It
has often been noted how much Freud was fascinated by the weight of the past
in the evolution of the personality, by the unalterable impact of a memory
buried in the deepest unconscious: "Our hysterical patients suffer from
adds: "He intended the model of time to become of central importance to his
readers. The emphasis is all on reminiscence. History, the memory
of
existence in time, is the flaw. Neurosis is the failure to escape the past, the
burden of one's history. Neurotics 'cannot escape from the past' . .
.
Freud
12 History and Psychoanalysis
was fascinated and horrified by the power of the past. The whole uniqueness of
man, the cause of his agony, his anxiety, is that man is a historical person, the
mask of his history."'"
The parallel between the aims and procedures of the historian and those of
the psychoanalyst was worth emphasizing; it seems superfluous, on the other
hand, to demonstrate here the vaUdity of our other two criteria: certainly no
reader is unaware that psychoanalysis represents a theory concerned with
extremely complex aspects of human motivation that are likely to interest the
and that it is a structurally coherent theory, whatever
historian, its conceptual
shortcomings may be .
may look for them in this person's life. There may be many — in his marriage and
family life; disappointments with his children or with their attitude towards him;
disappointments in extramarital love relationships; a decrease of sexual prowess
or of attractiveness; illnesses or a general feeling of aging; disappointments in
work, career, or social recognition; or financial worries. All this may be com-
plicated by organic, perhaps involutionary processes. Then there are the factors
suggested by psychoanalytic theories that would have to be considered, such as,
e.g., the loss of an object, abnormal forms of object relationships in terms of
introjection and expulsion, loss of love from the superego, aggression turned
against oneself, or a feeling of discouragement, fatigue, and defeat. . . . Several
of these factors will probably be present in any one case, and many of them can
be found in people of the same age group without depressions. In our search for
the etiological importance of any one of these factors, or any other factor that
may be suggested, we are not able to isolate it, while keeping all others
unchanged, and so to study its consequences alone. We will always have many
more unknowns than we have equations, so to say, so that no conclusion can be
made without the exercise of judgment which may be considered arbitrary.^*
The range and importance of the conclusions one can draw from these various
empirical arguments appear very limited: the experimental criterion, as we
have just seen, is not really applicable to the situations with which psycho-
analysis deals; the therapeutic criterion is not considered significant even by
psychoanalysts; the ability to predict is as spotty in psychoanalysis as in the
other social sciences, due to the interaction of many different factors; finally,
the divergences in cUnical confirmations are no from the divergences
different
in interpretation that one finds in sociology, political science, or even in
economics and demography. The discussions concerning the logical frame-
work of psychoanalysis and the nature of its concepts seem, on the other hand,
to be more significant from the start.
— —
The logical and at first glance decisive argument directed against the
scientific nature of psychoanalytic theory and of its concepts was first formu-
lated by Karl R. Popper and has often been repeated since in a great many
different forms. The inherent weakness of psychoanalysis consists, according
to Popper, in the fact that its concepts allow one to justify any hypothesis
whatsoever, and that no event seems capable of refuting a single one of its
propositions: "Every 'good' scientific theory is one which forbids certain
things to happen; the more a theory forbids, the better it is."^''
Although it is cited everywhere in relation to psychoanalysis, this argument
is false on certain specific points and is logically flawed. As far as the specifics
"contrary"; that means that a third datum might prove both hypotheses false
The Theoretical Framework 15
in a given situation, and that precisely the criterion that Popper cites as the
is
sine qua non of a scientific theory. The attachment of a child to his mother, for
example, attests to the reality of the Oedipus complex; the manifest hatred of a
child toward his mother is sometimes explained as a reaction formation
against a love that the child feels for many reasons to be dangerous, and the
Oedipus complex is again confirmed. But these two contrary hypotheses do
not exclude a third possibility which would be total indifference, the absence
of any emotional relation of a child to his mother; this third situation would
disprove the theory of the Oedipus complex,^* or at least dispute its universal
character.
Kaplan's reply eliminates Popper's formal objection. As for the fact that
psychoanalytic theory sometimes permits the affirmation both of one thing
and its merely a reflection of certain obvious psychological
contrary, that is
Myshkin but loved him too, and that every one of his actions could be inter-
preted as a sign of his love or of his hatred. We are no longer unaware of the
fact that most feelings are ambivalent. The question is whether we must blame
psychoanalysis for its lack of logic, or whether it is human behavior that is
loaded with paradoxes. In other words, which is the logic that must prevail?"
Granted all this, it is still true that psychoanalytic formulations are at times
so metaphorical and vague that it is a practical impossibility to decide whether
an explanation really follows from the theory or whether it is linked to the
theory only because someone made a haphazard association between one
element and another. ^'^ This lack of precision is only partly a result of the
nature of the phenomena being analyzed, and there is no doubt that an evolu-
tion of the theory in the direction of greater conceptual refinement is possible.
and
there can be no difference, in logical terms, between psychoanalysis
any kind of religious belief.
fonns of behavior and to apprehend man "in situation," even while main-
taining an empirical basis accessible to observation. Furthermore, psycho-
analytic theory founded on a series of hypotheses and concepts that permit a
is
progression toward greater precision and rigor: the theory can evolve in the
light of new empirical observations." Finally, Freudian theory is applicable,
"as if were true.
it
the only really significant one, after the refutation of Popper's thesis that
psychoanalysis proved both a thing and its opposite.
These general remarks obviously concern the utilization of psychoanalysis
in history. A recourse to Freudian theories in this domain opens up per-
spectives, forces us to ask questions and gives rise to inquiries that, in them-
selves, considerably enlarge the "territory of the historian." (We shall return
to these themes later.)
thus, even though Jungian theory and existential psychoanalysis appear on the
whole unacceptable, each of them can shed light, for the historian, on
problems that Freudian theory has not, up to the present, been able to treat in a
satisfactory maimer.
Due to its own development in a relatively
uniform and stable social
context, Freudian theory is unable, for example, to explain the effect of
sudden upheavals in the environment on the adult personality, especially in
the case of extreme situations such as imprisonment, emigration, etc." Ego
psychology offers perhaps an adequate conceptual framework, but its applica-
tion remains, for the moment, doubtful. By looking at the problem from
another angle, existential psychoanalysis sheds light on this kind of situation.
A phenomenological observation of individual behavior makes clear the
fundamental need of every human being to safeguard his "self." But this is a
fact thatcarmot be explained in terms of narcissim or of ego ideal, nor even in
terms of Erikson's notion of identity, which relies too heavily on instinctual or
cultural components; it is a phenomenon that existential psychoanalysis
describes without attempting to reduce it to elements devoid of meaning. Now
one characteristic of extreme situations is precisely that the external circum-
stances tend to make the human being lose that feeUng of the integrity of his
"self — sometimes to such a point that the subject loses all sense of his
individual existence. We know that such psychic frustration can accelerate the
process of physical debilitation and lead to illness and death. The exis-
tentialist notions allow us to come close to a phenomenon from which the
analytical reasoning of Freudian theory might risk cutting us off.'"
Psychohistorical Explanation
the Kol Nidre, for example, corresponds to one of the fantasies provoked
by that prayer in the distant past when it was first formulated. Conse-
quently, Reik's interpretation uncovers for us certain aspects of an uncon-
scious objective reality, as would any other interpretation. This relativism
of psychohistorical interpretation risks putting its very foundation into
question. Granted that the tomb of Valentine de Birague provoked certain
fantasies in the historian Michelet; these fantasies throw light on Michelet,
not on the 16th century. But then, how are we to grasp certain uncon-
scious problems of French society in the 16th century? Not by using
countertransference fantasies as our guide, but by attempting to place them
between parentheses.*^ We must pay careful attention to the signs transmitted
by the individual, the society or the culture we are observing, under the
assumption that these signs have a decipherable meaning, subject, in an
absolute sense, to innumerable variations, but whose specific sense can be
objectively understood if they are replaced in their precise historical context.
There are as many different versions of Oedipus as there are individuals;
everyone goes through this decisive phase of his evolution in his own way, and
regardless of the nature of the countertransference, it is this idiosyncratic
and the culturalist theses have been brought closer together as a result both of
20 History and Psychoanalysis
historical explanation (without taking into account, for now, the factual errors
that have been discovered in it, nor the specific problems of psychoanalytic
biography): Freud's essay "Leonardo da Vinci and a Memory of His
Childhood. ""5
Simply summarized, Freud's hypothesis consists of two distinct yet inter-
related propositions: as an illegitimate child raised without a father during the
first years of his life, Leonardo was coddled by a mother on whom all of his
That the general rule is often not certain is demonstrated by Freud's second
hypothesis: no clinical experience has confirmed the relation established by
Freud between the absence of paternal authority and intellectual audacity. On
the other hand, one could argue, the first hypothesis is amply confirmed by
cUnical experience: the relation between homosexuality and fixation on the
mother has often been noted. That is true, but formulated in this way, the
not sufficiently clear. First of all, this type of fixation
is
general rule is
that one can
qualitative and it is only through the analysis of a concrete case
of
decide whether the fixation was powerful enough to prevent any possibility
question.
heterosexual ties; one therefore runs a strong risk of begging the
is generally admitted that it is
at the stage of the
Secondly and above all, it
disruptive
resolution of the Oedipal conflict that such a fixation can have a
22 History and Psychoanalysis
effect. In Leonardo's case, however, the story of his early y ^ars is extremely
vague. We know mother between the ages of three and five
that he left his
years and went to live with his father (remarried in the meantime), who in a
sense readopted him. In all probability, therefore, he entered on the Oedipal
stage far from his mother, in a new family environment. One may well suppose
that the attachment to the lostmother was more intense than the attachment to
a mother who was present would have been, but that is only a conjecture. In
fact, in a case such as this one only the clinical context could furnish the
necessary details; and we are far from that. The indeterminacy of the
particular context is thus added to the imprecision of the general rule, whence
the existence of a double "as if."
Having arrived at this point in the discussion, the historian may decide to
go no further. And yet, the difficulties are surmountable both through a —
growing precision in the formulation of psychoanalytic hypotheses and
through the elaboration of criteria that would endow with greater validity the
application of the general rule to the particular context. The margin of
indeterminacy would persist, but it would perhaps be possible to reduce it to
acceptable proportions.
Four principal criteria seem to be necessary:
First, the criterion oi convergence, which is one of the fundamental criteria
of any scientific explanation. As Kaplan writes: "What counts in the valida-
tion of a theory, so far as fitting the facts is concerned, is the convergence of
."'*''
the data brought to bear upon it, the concatenation of the evidence. . .
United States, he repeated, after a certain time, the identical pattern of self-
destructive behavior: as soon as he encountered opposition on a subject
that
seemed to him important, he became rigid, lost all capacity for negotiation,
endowed his own action with the character of a moral crusade and refused, in
24 History and Psychoanalysis
the name of absolute principles, any compromise with the enemy, which he
soon identified with a specific individual. A strategy of flexibility and com-
promise would have allowed Wilson to get out of the impasse and eventually
achieve his aims, but he insisted on maintaining his aggressive intransigence,
wishing for only one thing: the absolute submission of his enemies. He ended
up by guaranteeing his own defeat and provoking the ruin of his ambitions.
This pattern of repetitive behavior was so clear that even Wilson's "tradi-
tional" biographers noticed it; Arthur S. Link, for example, who is the most
eminent contemporary specialist in this field, writes about Wilson's attitude
while he was president of Princeton:
The years of the Princeton presidency were among the most important in
Wilson's life. The Princeton period was the microcosm of a later macrocosm,
and a political observer,had he studied carefully Wilson's career as president of
Princeton University, might have forecast accurately the shape of things to come
during the period when Wilson was president of the United States. What striking
similarities there are between the Princeton and national periods! During the
first years of both administrations, Wilson drove forward with terrific energy and
A repetitive structure of behavior like the one we have been discussing clearly
indicates an unconscious ambivalence toward the exercise of power: on the
one hand, a practically limitless thirst for power, refusing the slightest con-
cession that might appear as a limitation of power; on the other hand, a self-
destructive attitude that lays bare the presence of strong guilt feelings as far as
the possession of power is concerned — feelings that can only result in ruin (my
own interpretation here is slightly different from the one proposed by the
Georges). An interpretation of this kind is itself supported by certain con-
spicuous facts in the development of Wilson's personality, notably by the
nature of his feelings toward his father: respect, devotion and unlimited love
on the surface, but also, no doubt, a repressed hostility toward a man who,
more than once during the crucial years of childhood, humiliated the future
president.
The facts concerning Wilson's childhood are, in this instance, merely a
supporting hypothesis, and we will have occasion later to see just how
uncertain the biographical reconstruction is. The important thing is the con-
vincing nature of the repetitive form of behavior that is observed, and, from the
point of view of psychoanalytic theory, the practically obligatory character of
the explanation that comes to mind.^"*
It is in relation to the third criterion, that of comparability, that the
The Theoretical Framework 25
bilities of comparison are limited, they are less so in a larger category, and one
can always consider an additional case that will confirm (or weaken) the
hypothesis.
The three criteria we have enumerated so far pertain either to the exhaustive
study of a single case or to the comparative method, both of which are methods
that the historian practices frequently and almost exclusively, and which the
specialist in the "hard" social sciences will not reject either. The fourth
criterion allows us to establish an even closer link with the current metho-
dology of the social sciences: it is the criterion oi quantitative analysis, which
allows one to confirm psychohistorical hypotheses with the help of statistical
analyses whose conceptual framework is more or less independent of psycho-
analytic theory. This type of verification not always possible or significant,
is
First World War. Our understanding of the fall of the Roman Empire is
valid interpre-
different from Gibbon's, but it is not a question of two equally
tations: today we are better informed than Gibbon was.
Now this cumulative
26 History and Psychoanalysis
process, this narrowing of the margin of error, will less easily find a place in
psychohistory, even if psychoanalytic concepts are made more precise and the
theory is further refined; for research concerning unconscious processes,
whether individual or collective, outside a clinical context, can never by —
definition —
be anything but indirect. Typological comparisons and statistical
investigations may indicate various plausible correlations, but the explana-
tion of these correlations will still not be definitely established. Thus, para-
doxically, to a greater extent than the other kinds of historical investigation,
psychohistory will have not only to make systematic use of Erkldren —
explanation as it is envisaged in the social sciences — but will also, and
simultaneously, have to continue relying on Verstehen — intuitive compre-
hension. To repeat what we have said before: by itself, intuitive compre-
hension can lead to absurdities; combined with explanation, it is not only
justifiable, but is essential in a domain such as this one.
The Document
cesses of the individual or group under study. That is a broad definition, but
one that traditional historians would doubtless not reject. It was Henri Marrou
who wrote any source of information that the historian can use in order to
that
know the past represents a document; consequently, a restrictive definition of
the historical document is impossible." A conception so broad, matched by
the method of psychoanalysis itself, which seeks a meaning in the most
massive symptoms as well as in the slightest word or deed, should, at least in
principle, make psychohistory an excessively rich domain, teeming with
possibilities.
But the between excessive richness and confusion is a narrow one,
line
has been surmised that [Luther's] mother suffered under the father's per-
It
sonality, and gradually became embittered; and there is also a suggestion that a
certain sad isolation which characterized young Luther was to be found also in
his mother, who is said to have sung to him a ditty: "For me and you nobody
cares. That is our common fault."
A big gap exists here, which only conjecture could fill. But instead of
conjecturing half-heartedly, I will state, as a clinician's judgment, that nobody
could speak and sing as Luther did if his mother's voice had not sung to him of
some heaven; that nobody could be as torn between his masculine and feminine
sides, nor have such a range of both, who did not at one time feel that he was like
his mother; but also, that nobody could discuss women and marriage in the way
he often did who had not been deeply disappointed by his mother — and had
become loath to succumb the way she did to the father, to fate. And if the soul is
man's most bisexual part, there we will be prepared to find in Luther both some
horror of mystic succumbing and some spiritual search for it, and to recognize in
this alternative some emotional and spiritual derivative of little Martin's "pre-
watching a drunken muzhik torture and finally kill a mare by forcing her to
pull an overloaded cart. The mare is not able to go forward, the muzhik whips
her all the harder: he whips her on the eyes, then exchanges the whip for a
wooden shaft and the shaft for an iron crowbar, with which he finally finishes
like a madman, he seizes a stick, a bough, anything, and breaks it over her back
with three last, terrific blows.— No more. . . .The little girl . . . trembling on the
oven in the comer tries to hide: she hears her mother shrieking."
Here Dostoevsky recounts an event that really took place and which he
again,
read about in the newspapers, for the muzhik's wife hanged herself. But the
details of this scene and those of Raskolnikov's dream are practically identi-
cal: the use of the whip, then of the piece of wood, the terror of the child. One is
meaning appears at first, could become a key piece of evidence for the under-
standing of the writer and of the fundamental themes of his work.
Paradigms of Psychohistory
There is no such thing as one generally accepted paradigm for the application
however; we shall see in the next chapter how difficult and uncertain its
structure of the personality;" one also notes that Neal Smelser, after having
1
take the step of supposing that something occurred in the life of the human
species similar to what occurs in the life of individuals: of supposing, that is,
that here too events occurred of a sexually aggressive nature, which left behind
them permanent consequences but were for the most part fended off and for-
gotten, and which after a long latency came into effect and created phenomena
similar to symptoms in their structure and purpose."'" The same sweeping
transposition occurs in The Future of an Illusion, where religion is identified
as a collective obsessional neurosis,*'' and in Civilization and Its Discontents,
where sublimation seems to function on the level of humanity as a whole
according to the same rules one can discern on the individual level.
Freud arrives at this type of transposition by means of an inductive reason-
ing oriented toward the observation of individual phenomena. He reaches the
conclusion that certain aspects of individual behavior can be explained by the
hereditary effect of an ineradicable collective experience, whence the possi-
bility of going from one level to another, from the collective to the
individual
and vice versa: "The behaviour of neurotic children towards their parents
in
he writes,
the Oedipus and castration complexes abounds in such reactions,"
32 History and Psychoanalysis
"which seem unjustified in the individual case and only become intelligible
expression.
We are thus dealing here with a paradigm of macrohistorical explanation.
It can be used for the analysis of collective mentalities, for the study of a
culture as a total phenomenon, or possibly in studies seeking to discover in a
national character certain underlying characteristics. It can be used, but
prudently, for — as we hardly need point out— psychoanalytic structuralism is
faced with the same theoretical and methodological problems that confront
any structuralist undertaking.
We shall not attempt here a discussion of structuralism in general; it is
Those who reject Freud's "reductionism" and recognize that the applica-
tion of psychoanalytic structuralism is at best limited might turn to two other
paradigms, which in fact are those wemost often in this book:
shall refer to
the paradigm of culture and personality, and the paradigm of "continuous
internalization."
In a very simplified way, one can say that society influences the develop-
ment and the behavior of the individual personality in four principal ways:
through the influence of "primary institutions" on the child; through the constant
adaptation of the ego to its environment; through the internalization through- —
out the existence of the individual, on the level of the superego as well as on
The Theoretical Framework 35
that of the ego— of the
basic social norms; finally, through the reactions that
are provoked on the level of the individual unconscious by the
symbolic
systems adopted by the society.'^
Conversely, in the interaction between the society and the individual, the
latter exerts an influence on his environment through his emotional
invest-
ment or disinvestment in the existing norms and institutions, through the
creation of new symbolic systems (cf. the influence of religious or artistic
expression on social evolution, and vice versa) and through the creation of
new norms (cf. the influence of charismatic personalities in politics or in
religion).
The schemata I shall present in the pages that follow are but the ela-
boration of these basic kinds of interaction. I shall concentrate only on
the socialization of the child through the mediation of the primary institutions
and on the models of internalization, for the other types of interaction are in a
sense obvious. But it is important to emphasize that these diverse kinds of
interactions function simultaneously, in stable or temporary homogeneous
groups as inheterogeneous ones. There exist only differences in degree. I
shall merely outHne here in a very general way a type of analysis whose
specific aspects and variations I shall treat in detail in chapter 3.
What do we mean by "homogeneous" and "heterogeneous" groups? The
homogeneous group is characterized by a relative absence of social differ-
entiation, by a high degree of isolation from the outside world, or else by the
unifying role of an ideology, a collective obsession, a "total institution"" or a
personality. If the homogeneous group has control over unified primary insti-
tutions (mothering and child-raising practices, etc.), it can be considered
stable; if not, then such a group is generally temporary. As for the hetero-
geneous group, it is socially diversified, in permanent contact with other
groups, and primary institutions are not unified.
its
stages of their development will in turn influence the social structure of the
36 History and Psychoanalysis
group through the way in which the each of its members are
roles assigned to
fulfilled; the individual personality will also influence the culture of the group
work necessary for the subsistence of the community is done by women. One
important result of this is that the mother cannot take care of the newborn
child: around two weeks after giving birth, she goes back to work. The child is
left to the "care" of his brothers and sisters, who feed him irregulady, tease
him, maltreat him, and on the whole behave toward him in the most arbitrary
manner. There is no discipline, no systematic upbringing, not even a coherent
mode of punishments and rewards. The child grows up with an attitude of
generalized distrust, doubt, and shame.
basic personality of the Alorese will be characterized by passivity, the
The
absence of curiosity, the absence of initiative and of any capacity for organi-
zation, but also by a profound distrust of others and by sudden, sporadic, and
violent outbreaks of aggressivity. The secondary institutions bear the trace of
this typical personality.
The Theoretical Framework 37
The Alorese male has perfected an extremely complex but totally unpro-
ductive financial system, and his life is spent in exchanges and barters whose
sole objective is to acquire,by means of a totally fictitious wealth, a certain
prestige that will compensate for his ftindamental feeling of frustration and
inferiority. The initial hostility toward the mother is reflected in the relation
between the sexes: it is the women who do the courting in Alorese society, and
the divorce (or infidelity) rate is particularly high. Finally, the Alorese religion
also bears the traces of distrust: nothing is expected from a rather ill-defined,
supreme divinity, and "the spirits of the dead are but impatient creditors who
must be nourished through sacrifices that are brought to them with a great deal
of reluctance: so poor is the balance between frustration and reward, so great
is the distrust. Naturally, there is no question of assuring the favor of the gods
mother"'"^ that we must seek to arrive at a firm and unanimous judgment, one
that will allow us to analyze with precision the interaction between a certain
type of maternal care and a certain type of evolution in the child. The current
lack of precision in this domain does not affect the value of the "culture and
personality" paradigm as an ideal type, nor its possibilities of general or
partial application. One must simply keep in mind that one is dealing in this
instance with a heuristic schema, rather than with a model whose various
elements are all empirically confirmed.
One can go a step and introduce a diachronic dimension into this
ftirther,
occurs; it will be resolved either by the belated adaptation of the family and the
individual to the new social structure, or by a social restructuring that will
level comes from the differences in rhythm that one finds between the
evolution of the social structure, the evolution of the basic elements of the
culture of the group and the evolution of the family structure. It would seem
that basic cultural elements and family structure evolve more slowly than the
other components of the social structure; the result is a series of syncopations
whose influence on the development and on the socialization of the individual
is difficult to determine. But here again, the paradigmatic value of the
proposed model is evident, despite the technical difficulties in its application.
The primary institutions are the model we have been
key element in the
It is Talcott Parsons who stated the most convincing case for an enlargement
of the areas of interaction between the social structure and the structure of the
personality (including, incidentally, the id among the components of the per-
sonality subject to the direct influence of the social structure — a hypothesis
difficult to accept in theory and impossible to demonstrate empirically, given
the nature of the id).'°* Parson's theses were adopted and elaborated on the
basis of ample psychoanalytic material by Fred Weinstein and Gerald M.
Piatt,"" who demonstrated that certain essential aspects of the psycho-
analytic study of collective phenomena were otherwise impossible.
On the static level, this model requires no other explanation than the one
implicit in the very definition of internalization, namely: "all those processes
by which the subject transforms real or imagined regulatory interactions with
his environment, and real or imagined characteristics of his environment, into
inner regulations and characteristics.""" On the other hand, an interpretation
of social change based, on the psychological level, on the notion of inter-
nalization, is not as self-evident as the processes of change that occur in
homogeneous groups. In this regard, one can propose the following points:'"
The Theoretical Framework 39
due to its conformity with the social context, but also with the affective
needs" ^ of the members of the group.
A transformation of the symbolic system without any change in norms
represents a reordering, not a transformation, of the social system. In order to
be adopted, a new symbolic system must conform to the new social situation,
but it must also satisfy the affective needs of the majority of the members of the
group. A transformation of the fundamental norms themselves represents a
transformation of the entire social system. The new norms, emerging from the
old system or from one coexisting with it, will impose themselves according to
the evolution of the social system and according to the ease with which they
are internalized by the members of the group, depending on their fundamental
affective needs.
According to this model, the essential causes of the reordering or the trans-
formation of a social system are social, not psychological, in nature. How-
ever, the integration of a new symbolic system (in the case of reordering) or of
new norms (in the case of transformation) into the society in question depends
not only on social factors, but also on the affective reactions of a majority of
the members of that society— facts that are interpretable only in psycho-
logical terms.
free choice.
psychoanalytic
The imprecisionthat surrounds the concept of a free ego in
"ideological" premises
theory is due in large part to explicit or implicit
unless its field of
according to which no discipline can be considered scientific
the representatives of
study is subject to the laws of a strict determinism. For
totality of the field of
experimental psychology, the necessity of reducing the
according to
human behavior to quantitative sequences is not open to doubt;
40 History and Psychoanalysis
them, it is only by this means that psychology can escape from metaphysics
and become one of the exact sciences."^
The preponderant influence of Fechner's and Briicke's deterministic
theories on Freud's thought has often been mentioned, and it was only after
1923, with the publication of The Ego and the Id, that Freud seems to make
some allowance for an autonomous ego. On the whole, however, the position
of the founder of psychoanalysis may be defined as deterministic in the fullest
sense of the term; and the great majority of psychoanalysts follow in his path.
Ernest Jones, for example, admits the possibility that "the irruptions of spon-
taneous and unrelated phenomena supposedly emanating from 'free will' would
make nonsense of its [psychoanalysis'] scientific pretentions.""'* Consequent-
ly, for many psychoanalysts "the autonomy of the ego is strictly relative,""'
to any objective reality."*' Even Erik H. Erikson's use of these terms lends itself
to confusion, and one has the impression — at least in the theoretical part of his
work — that free will is nothing but a purely subjective experience on the part of
the individual. Thus, in discussing the various aspects of the second stage of
the development of the personality, Erikson states that it is at this time that a
"sense of self-control without loss of self-esteem is the ontogenetic source of a
sense of free-will.""''
The same is not true of the works of Heinz Hartmann and especially of
David Rapaport, the two outstanding theorists of "ego psychology." Heinz
Hartmann describes the autonomy of the ego in the following terms:
these and many others. ... I propose that we adopt the provisional term
"conflict-free ego sphere" for that ensemble of functions which at any given time
exert their effects outside the region of mental conflicts."*
We refer to this independence as the autonomy of the ego from the id. The most
common observation which necessitated this conception was the responsiveness
and relevance of behavior to external reality. But this dependence of behavior on
the external world and on experience is not complete either. Man can interpose
delay and thought not only between instinctual promptings and action, modifying
and even indefinitely postponing drive discharge, he can likewise modify and
postpone his reaction to external stimulation. This independence of behavior from
external stimulation we will refer to as the autonomy of the ego from external
reality. Since the ego is never completely independent from the id nor from
external reality, we always speak about relative autonomy. [And Rapaport
concludes:] While the ultimate guarantees ofthe ego's autonomyfrom the id are
man's constitutionally given apparatuses of reality relatedness, the ultimate
guarantees of the ego's autonomy from the environment are man's constitu-
tionally given drives."'
adolescents elaborate what Erikson calls their "internal life design."'" That is
a key term. In effect, even if Erikson' s writings are ambiguous, so that one can,
ifone wishes, conceive of individual identity as a simple resultant of solutions
elaborated in the previous stages of development, is it not more convincing to
think of the "internal life design" as a free project, a necessary axis of individual
identity, without which identity itself cannot be achieved? Nevertheless, this
internal life most mature and most
design, this choice, will not find its
Of all the fields of historical research, that of biography seems at first glance to
be best suited to the utilization of psychoanalysis. It is here that psycho-
analytic theories are most often applied, and here that psychohistory has
claimed its —
most far-reaching results but it is also here that the aspirations of
psychohistory have most often been questioned.
From the very beginnings of the psychoanalytic movement, the lives
of "great men" have provoked considerable interest. The "Wednesday semi-
nars" conducted by Freud and his closest collaborators were often devoted to
the biographical analysis of famous writers: Lenau, Wedekind, Jean-Paul,
Konrad Ferdinand Meyer, Grillparzer, and Kleist, to mention the best known
ones.' It was at one of these seminars, in 1909, that Freud presented his
The naive self-assurance of the first psychoanalysts, the apparent ease with
which they could, on the basis of a few key pieces of evidence and a few key
Recently, controversies have again come to the fore with the publication of
43
44 History and Psychoanalysis
creation, a political decision or a set of new social norms? What is the im-
portance of biography as the study of a life? The answer is simple: the work is
not comprehensible independently of the personality that created it. The
personality is a single entity: the study of the work and of the personality forms
a single whole. The work, which and the personality, is at
reflects the society
the same time the expression of something that transcends both the one and
the other.
The aim of the biographer will be to discover the link between the
personality and the work, to rediscover the coherence that characterizes any
personality and its creation — and to do this not only on the synchronic level
but also through time, in the genuinely historical dimension. The demon-
stration of the cohesion of the personality is essential to the demonstration of
the coherence of the work.
The conception of the personality as an identifiable, coherent whole is, in
itself, not open to doubt. Personal experience or introspection demonstrates
its and psychoanalytic theory confirms it, as does experimental psy-
validity
chology. Experimental studies on child behavior, for example, bear out the
astonishingly permanent character of an individual personality "style," even
during the phase of development where everything is transformed: "As one
notes behavioral alterations from infancy to . . . later pre-school ages," write
Heider and Escalona, "one knows that not a single behavior has remained the
same, yet one is struck with the inherent continuity of behavioral style and of
the child's pattern of adaptation."* Psychoanalysts discovered, quite early,
this unity of style or of type in the neurotic personality,' but in so doing they
were simply restating a very old theory concerning the "styles" or "types" of
personality in general. A report in the British Journal of Psychology shows
Is Psychoanalytic Biography Possible? 45
We shall come
back, at the end of this chapter, to the problems raised by
typological studies; for the moment, it is the question of the relation between
the typical and the idiosyncratic that must be considered. Here again, one
might ask, should biography not yield to a different kind of study, one that
seeks to discover "styles" or "types" as such? The answer, as one might
suspect, is negative. A style and a type are probably determined by certain
similarities in hereditary traits and in environment. But every individual
represents a variation in relation to the type, and if the latter provides a general
pattern, the idiosyncratic variation denotes a specific one. Even if the
individual life project cannot ignore certain limits imposed on it by the social
framework and by the typical elements (in our present sense of the term), it
Let us take the case of Adolf Hitler. The biographer will have no difficulty
sketching in the relevant social context. A typical pattern will also appear,
even though certain of elements will be contradictory. The "paranoid"
its
style generally attributed to Hitler is in fact selective: if, toward the Jews, his
attitude reveals the presence of psychosis, his paranoid tendencies diminish
considerably in the face of a concrete political or military situation, and are
replaced either by a flexible and realistic evaluation of the situation or by an
obsessional impulse to action, a feeling that time is short and that one lightning
strike has to follow anotherthe decrees of Providence are to be fulfilled. The
if
internal coherence of behavior is there and can be identified, but the usual
typologies risk leading one astray, due to their too facile schematization.
The however, lies elsewhere: the biographer will not be able
real difficulty,
to avoid interpreting one of the dominant elements in Hitler's mental
universe,
namely his anti-Semitism. The biographer will describe it but will also attempt
in psycho-
to explain it, and, according to the usual way of proceeding
biography, he will try to indicate its origin by referring to certain
known
is a
elements in the development of Hitler's personality. The case of Hitler
the results of a
particularly good example, because it allows us to compare
series of interpretations of a single phenomenon.
an indirect one: in the chapter o{ Childhood
and
Erikson's explanation is
Nazi anti-
Society entitled "The Myth of Hitlers Youth," he explains
to the
Semitism in terms of the identity crisis, without, however, referring
Fiihrer's personal motivations." According to Gertrud M. Kurth, on the other
46 History and Psychoanalysis
between Hitler's incestuous tendencies and the figure of the Jew. She writes:
"The connection I am bold enough to believe I have estabhshed is the para-
doxical conclusion that the torrent of apocalyptic horrors that engulfed six
million Jews was unleashed in the futile endeavor to exterminate that inces-
tuous, black-haired little monster that was Adolf Hitler's Mr. Hyde."'^
Georges Devereux, in turn, presents a quasi-rational theory to account for
Hitler's exterminating orders: "Let us recall," he writes, "the way Genghis
Khan and Hitler recruited some of their cadres. Their absolute loyalty, like
that of the Mau-Maus, was guaranteed precisely by the fact that their initiation
involved such hideous crimes that in executing them they 'burned their
bridges' behind them, thus making it impossible for them to re-enter society
except as absolute victors."*^ Admittedly, this "political" exploitation of the
murder of the Jews does not exclude the possibility of profoundly irrational
motives. It is the latter that are emphasized by Gustav Bychowski, according
to whom Hitler's pathological anti-Semitism was related to a deep psycho-
sexual conflict and probably represented the effect of a projection of frustrated
sexual desires on the part of the dictator.'"
We may mention briefly the study by Rudolph Binion in which Binion
concludes that Hitler identified his mother's fate (in his mind she was poisoned
by the Jewish doctor's harmful injections) with his own poisoning by gas in
1918. His aim therefore became to avenge that double poisoning, with which
the Jews were directly associated.'-'
With Walter Langer, whose study was written during the war for the
American Secret Service but was only recently published, we return to a very
general explanation in which Hitler's hatred of the Jews is interpreted broadly
in terms of projection: all of Hitler's undesirable characteristics were pro-
jected onto the Jews —
among these characteristics, Langer mentions in
particular a tendency toward feminine passivity and sexual perversion.
Through the effect of projecdon it was the Jew who came to symbolize sexual
perversion, and if Hitler felt poisoned by his perverse self, it was the Jew who
became the poison. "In his treatment of the Jews we see the 'Identification
with the Aggressor' mechanism at work." writes Langer. Hitler, in other
words, applied to the Jews in reality the treatment he feared he would receive
from his victors in fantasy. This brought him several kinds of gratification.
First, he could appear in the eyes of the world as the pitiless brute he imagined
himself to be; second, was a way of proving to himself that he was as brutal
it
Viennese years. It is plausible to infer that a fear of the father inhibited the
development of a normal sex life, but that the humiliating inhibition was
often men-
rationalized and attributed to the fear of syphilis, which Hitler
tioned. Now since the father was himself identified with the Jews, it was the
Jews who, through syphilis, threatened the health and the life of non-Jews.
48 History and Psychoanalysis
The Jews and syphilis, or infection in general, soon became one and the same
thing.''
The various interpretations we have mentioned most part, on
agree, for the
one essential fact: the psychosexual origin of Hitler's anti-Semitism. For
anyone who has studied the subject, there can be no doubt on that score. But
the statement as such is too general to be meaningful. Once one admits the
psychosexual origin of Hitler's anti-Semitism, one must necessarily look for
specific causes in the childhood or the young manhood of the future dictator.
All of the studies did in fact search in that direction, and that is where the
divergences began. Why? Because of the absence of significant biographical
information, certainly (this despite Hitler's own recollections, as well as those
of his supposed childhood friends — Kubizek, Greiner, Hanisch — and despite
the few more or less exact reconstructions attempted by postwar historians);
but above all because the facts we do possess can be related to each other and
to subsequent events in various ways. What we cannot know is how Hitler
experienced the events we know, and what fantasies they evoked in him. We
have seen, for example, that most interpreters accord a great importance to the
fact that after the death of Hitler's father, during the mother's last ilbess, it
was a Jewish doctor, Dr. Bloch, who in a sense took the father's place; great
importance has also been attributed to Bloch's method of treatment, which
seems to have consisted in injections of morphine. On the surface. Hitler felt
nothing but gratefulness toward Bloch: he wrote to him several times, and
much later, after the annexation of Austria he authorized him to leave for the
United States. But how can we ever know the unconscious fantasies that
became associated with Bloch's role and with his status as a Jew?
Whatever hypothesis one chooses, one can find a way to integrate it into a
total context that will appear coherent, for the possible variations are ex-
tremely numerous. For each hypothesis, one can find sufficient proof in the
huge mass of Hitler's writings, speeches, and conversations, the texts of which
have been preserved. One could conclude that this is precisely the problem of
the verification of psychohistorical explanation and that all of the criteria we
discussed in the preceding chapter prove to be inapplicable to a concrete
biographical case: in this instance several Gestalten are possible, each one no
less plausible than the others; any explanation one chooses will be confirmed
by convergent elements, so that the overdetermination effect will appear. An
objective criterion for selecting the correct interpretation thus becomes diffi-
cult to find.
It is not psychobiography that isand the example chosen is an
at fault here,
extreme one because of the plurality of possible explanations to which it gives
rise. But we should nevertheless beware of this danger: certain cases present
limits that the biographer cannot hope to go beyond. One can define an
unconscious structure, both in its typical and its specific characteristics, but
its genesis is sometimes inaccessible to historical study.
The interpretation of childhood events represents therefore the most un-
certain aspect of biographical investigation, due to the idiosyncratic forms of
individual fantasy as well as to the obvious lack of sufficient documentation.
Is Psychoanalytic Biography Possible? 49
In adolescence, on the other hand, when the identity is formed, when the
various conflicts crystallize and when a crucial choice of cultural models takes
place, the psychic structure appears much more clearly. Often, in the case of
writers or artists, the first works— the Jwv'e/?/7/a that Mauron talks about— are
produced at this time.^° But end of this crucial phase that the
in fact it is at the
complex between the personality and the work (in the broadest sense
relation
of that term) develops, according to a dynamic whose mechanism we shall
discuss in detail but which, in any case, excludes univocal correlations.
Whatever the nature of the work, it obeys an autonomous logic that intro-
duces into the biographical context a complementary element of indeter-
minacy.^^
Paradoxically, the biographer cannot escape from the opposite difficulty
either — that of a case where a manifest determinism exists, but whose impli-
cations caimot be exactly evaluated: the determinism of heredity or physio-
logical determinism in general. The pathological heredity of Van Gogh, for
example, is certainly recognized: Vincent's sister spent thirty-eight years in a
mental institution, and his brother Theo was himself the victim of nervous
disorders that hastened his death.^^ But only in rare cases is the genetic
influence as clear as this, and in most instances the biographer will not know
how to interpret elements that are less clearly marked but that nevertheless
play a preponderant role. One finds a sporadic instability in the Stephen
family, for example, but was it this instability— which never reached the stage
of madness — that accounted for the psychotic outbreaks of the most famous
descendant of the line, Virginia Woolf? Or were the perturbing events of her
childhood sufficient cause to explain her illness?" We
cannot go wrong by
affirming that there was a convergence of the two factors, but that is simply an
elegant way of masking our ignorance.
The degree of repercussion of physiological disorders on behavior is not
between the personality and the work of art (the psychoanalytic biography of
artists); between the personality and political behavior (the biography of
The problem of the relation between the personality of the artist or writer and
his work has been at least as hotly debated as that of the nature of history, and
here too the opposing positions are categorical and often unreconcilable.
Thus, for T. S. Eliot, the attempt to correlate the artist's personality with his
work anathema: "Poetry," he writes, "is not a turning loose of emotion, but
is
already present in his earlier book, Le Dieu cache (The Hidden God),
affirmed categorically that only a social group is capable of elaborating that
coherent "vision of the world" without which the work of art is inconceivable.
Sociology can discover the necessary link between a work and its social
context, but no psychology can possibly "account for the fact that Racine
wrote precisely the corpus of his dramas and tragedies, and explain why he
could in no case have written the plays of Comeille or those of Moliere"."
Without launching a full-scale critique of Goldmann's methods as a whole,
we can raise certain inevitable objections to it.
As concerns the monopoly presumably exercised by the group in the
formulation of a coherent vision of the world, how does one explain the fact
that so many creative personalities are "out of phase" with their society, and
that so many works of art have no discernible relation to the social context in
which they were produced?^" We can, as a matter of fact, borrow an example
from Lucien Goldmann himself: in The Hidden God, Goldmann gives us the
definition of a "tragic vision" found in Pascal and Racine, a vision whose
social bases he analyzes at length as a specific relationship between the
noblesse de robe and the monarchy. Now if there is a single other authentic
exponent of the same "tragic vision," it is certainly Kierkegaard. Yet, the
social context in which Kierkegaard's work and personality existed bears no
relation whatsoever to the one that Goldmann considered as the basis for the
"tragic vision."
Would not be more convincing to postulate the partial influence of the
it
social context, even though it is not always evident, together with the equally
partial influence of personality factors and of autonomous formal elements
inherent to a given artistic domain? The specificity of the individual person-
ality(more or less strong, depending on the artist in question) can give rise to
an "out of phase" relationship between the artist and his group, but since the
work itself will influence the sensibility of the group, it will be integrated into
the collective vision after a gestation period whose length will vary
with the
we shall see a bit further on that it does exist, provided that certain essential
elements be present. But Goldmann, in a work subsequent to The Hidden
52 History and Psychoanalysis
Freud found in each work the theme of parricide motivated by sexual comp-
petition for a woman.
This kind of structuraUst analysis proceeds in two stages: first of all, it seeks
to discover in the work a particular organization of certain "psychic forms"
common to all human beings; this organization can be grasped independently
of any reference to the personality of the artist, to his social situation, etc. In
the next stage, the object is to determine the particular form or the style of this
organization, by considering once again only the elements intrinsic to the
work; this procedure is similar to that of the therapist, who— moving from the
examination of the libidinal content of a case to the patient's particular way of
relating to the world, his immediate object relations —
can understand a "life
style" without having recourse to a detailed anamnesis.^*
Due to the theoretical development of ego psychology and the importance
attached to object relations, analysts of individual works are naturally led to
shift their attention from the thematic content to the mode of expression. On
this particular point, therefore, the structuralist approach has nothing unique
about it. On the other hand, as concerns the bracketing of elements extrinsic to
the work, one runs up against a general difficulty that structuralism is
which the work belongs."*" Such a synthesis leads us quite naturally to the
biography of the artist, as we conceive of it in this book.
According to the paradigm of psychobiography which we discussed in the
last chapter, the problem here is that of the individual bases
of the artist's
3) What is the relation between the personaUty of the artist and the form of
the work?
language of the artist replaces another one, which is the language of neurosis.
On the work of art is therefore a reelaboration
level of individual creation, the
of the artist's infantile fantasies. The forces whose convergence and/or
opposition lead to artistic creation "are the same conflicts which drive other
people into neurosis.""^ The work of art is a substitute for neurosis: the artist
escapes the paralyzing effects of neurosis thanks to his capacity for sublima-
tion and to the weakness of his repressions. For Freud, the work of art is thus
the expression of a psychic conflict which in most people would lead only to
neurosis, but which, in a few rare individuals endowed with a particular
capacity for sublimation, leads to creativity. At the same time, Freudian
theory maintains that a trace of the original conflict, in other words some
element of neurosis, remains in the artist's personality; often, therefore,
traditional psychobiography looks for the meaning of the work by studying this
"nonsublimated" aspect of the artist's behavior.
Most psychoanalysts accept Freud's basic notions on this point, even if
they reformulate them in a more refined way: the creative act corresponds, in
their eyes, to the solution of a conflict-laden intrapsychic situation. Thus, Jean
Delay speaks of the search for a new equilibrium provoked by the lack of
fulfillment that is the neurotic conflict;"^ Melanie Klein evokes the need for
"repairing the damaged object," a need provoked by the feeling of guilt
resultingfrom the destructive rage of the small child's depressive position, as
well as by the need for a sense of wholeness on the part of the subject; this
theme is also developed by Janine Chasseguet-Smirgel;"" Anthony Storr em-
phasizes the adaptive function of the creative act, whose aim is to reestablish
an internal order, to overcome the conflict-laden oppositions and dissocia-
.''*
tions and to establish a solid identity
We may note that for these authors, the creative act is, one form or
in
all artists. To come back to the notions advanced by Melanie Klein and
Janine Chasseguet-Smirgel, it is not necessary to attempt to unify these
various hypotheses, as Janine Chasseguet-Smirgel tried to do: one can easily
imagine that, in some artists, the creative act aims to fill in the gaps of their
maturation at every stage of development in order to arrive at "narcissistic
completion,'"** aim is to arrive at the "reparation of the
v^^hile in others its
object" that Melanie Klein evokes in most of her writings. In each case, the
historian must attempt to determine the specific kind of lack, as well as the
particular mode adopted by the artist in order to make up for it. But ( and this is
where traditional psychoanalytic theory seems to me insufficient) neither the
idiosyncratic restoration of a lack, nor the ability described by Storr— to —
integrate the discordant elements of a personality, to submit to the impulses of
the unconscious and to assimilate them without neurotic collapse,*'' is identi-
fiable with the very essence of creativity or with the creadve act in its entirety.
movement toward the work, and if it remains incapable of explaining the work
in
.'•'
causes. . .
56 His ton' and Psychoanalysis
The dialectical relation between the personality and the work, as envisaged by
Starobinski, does not exclude the "reflection" aspect of the work, but rather
transcends it. Some studies, which we shall cite later, evoke on the whole the
"reflection" stage of the work; as far as I am aware, there exist no studies to
date which show the interaction between the element of necessary dependence
and the element of creative transcendence; but the direction, at least, is clearly
indicated.
In good logical order, the first task of the biographer will be to identify the
repetitive elements in what constitutes the manifest structure of a work and of
a life. This is precisely what Roland Barthes has in mind when he states, in the
first lines of his book on Michelet: "... there is an order to follow. We must
first give this man his coherence." For Barthes, this means looking for a
theses concerning the origin of the psychic constellation which influences their
life and their work. In the case of others, the unconscious material is more or
Let us take the case of Edgar Allan Poe. The obsession with the "dead
mother" dominated the work of the writer, through a series of obvious
symbols, just as it dominated his life: his marriage, his impotence, his
alcoholism, his final escapade. Even though it is often too schematic, Marie
Bonaparte's analysis is —
on the whole correct which does not exclude, of
course, the possibility of a more detailed interpretation, dealing perhaps with
biographical elements that she did not perceive, or with more general uncon-
scious problems revealed in Poe's work.
For the biographer, the death of the mother becomes the fundamental
absence, the narcissistic wound that Poe's life and work attempted to over-
come. The extreme subjectivity of this auteur maudit designates this central
theme in a convincing manner. But the insufficiency of the usual psycho-
biographical method becomes apparent as soon as one compares the case of
Poe with that of another writer, who was just as subjective, just as "explicit"
about the psychological bases of his creative quest, just as deeply hurt by a
maternal absence which, although benign and temporary thus not at all —
—
comparable to death nevertheless provoked an emptiness that the work
sought to fill: I am referring, of course, to Proust. The bedtime kiss, once it was
refused, became a wound perhaps as intolerable as the one suffered by little
Edgar, whose mother abandoned him by dying. From that moment on, writes
George Painter, "[Proust] sought everywhere for the infinite, unconditional
,""
love which he had lost. . .
Is Psychoanalytic Biography Possible? 57
individual nuances, and only they, that count: the historian must be able to
rely both on systematic explanation, which leads from the discovery of a
fiindamental lack to its transmutations, and on his intuition, which alone
allows him to evaluate the importance of each element; at the same time, he
must not attempt to establish an exclusive and univocal causal relation
between the psychic structure he has identified and the nature of the specific
symbolic transformation."
On the level of the search for an unconscious coherence of themes in the
work and their correlation with the biographical context, the historian can
study the life of artists by the same method as the life of writers. Thus, in his
Pitti. Finally, in the Virgin and Child of the Medici Chapel, the "tragic fixity
of the mother's stare is made all the more apparent by the fact that the child,
seated on her lap, twists himself violently backward, as if he wanted not only
to catch hold of the breast but to attract to his little self the attention of that
Day and Twilight in the Medici Chapel are the beardless, finished figures of
Julius and Lorenzo. Finally, it may happen that in a single group, such as
Victory, which includes two men, the young one has the polish of a finished
work, whereas the old one has the tremor of the nonjinito. So many examples,
spanning the whole career of the artist, cannot be simple coincidences; whence
the following law, which seems to govern Michelangelo's unconscious: each
time \iQgoes to work on a figure whose age or attributes make him appear as a
figure of paternal authority, he goes at it with incredible violence, a sacrile-
."'*
gious temerity atoned for by the sudden interruption of the work. . .
punitive behavior that the artist inflicted on himself in his everyday life.
Dominique Fernandez illustrates this hidden dialectic between homosexuality
and fantasies of punishment by means of a comparative analysis of three
drawings: Ganymede carried off by an eagle, Tityus endlessly devoured by the
vulture, and Phaeton falling with his chariot.
endless torture; the fall of Phaeton indicates the final catastrophe. The three
nudes are endowed
all with intense sensuality, like three images of the most
shameless abandonment and self-exhibition. At the same time, however, these
three poses constitute the punishment itself, according to the secret law which
makes Michelangelo condemn himself for the very thing that arouses his
passion. Ganymede with his legs spread apart represents an invitation to love,
Is Psychoanalytic Biography Possible? 59
the excitation of the first step, a provocative enticement, but also, at the same
time, the body pulled apart, imprisoned in the claws of the predatory bird,
mortally paralyzed. Tityus lying on his back represents the imminence of
pleasure, but also, at the same time, the eternity of punishment. Phaeton, in his
backward swoon, represents the climax of voluptuous ecstasy but also, at the
same time, the irrevocable engulfment by the waves."
concentrated."^" That is true, but the essential relation between the individual
unconscious and the form or style of the work requires a method of analysis
that it has not been possible, until now, to elucidate. We have seen that the
structural analysis of works of art attaches particular importance to the dis-
covery of a relation between the form of the work and certain general
structures of the unconscious evoked by the artist, without considering it
nature, have been made to relate certain forms of artistic expression (poetic
rhythm^^ or kinesthesia, for example)" to certain unconscious processes. But
as far as specific relations on the level of psychoanalytic biography are
concerned, there has been nothing. The fascinating study by Anton Ehrenz-
weig— which attempts to show that the primary processes, far from being the
domain of formlessness and chaos, are a structured field from which all
genuine creation derives, thus constituting a substratum that encloses
artistic
the "hidden order" of art— contributes very little to the questions that concern
the biographer. When Ehrenzweig evokes the particular form of certain works
by Beethoven or Mozart, it is in the framework of a general demonstration, just
as when he analyzes works by Picasso, Jackson Pollock, or Bridget Riley. His
to please both his father and his stepmother. Anything one can say on this
subject is purely hypothetical. . .
."" In this particular case, we must agree.
Yet, is this not a particular aspect of the psychoanalytic biography of artists
whose analysis will have to be attempted? Is this not what William Langer
would call "the next assigrunent?"
In his Art and Illusion,^^ the art historian E. H. Gombrich shows that the
artistdoes not copy an "objective" reality, but represents a stylized vision of
the world in the famework of conventional schemata current in the period and
in the culture in which he lives. This seems undeniable. But in that case, could
we not say that it is the social context which in large part determines the
conventional schemata that the whereas the individual varia-
artist relies on,
tions in relation to this "norm" are determined by the artist's personality, and
especially by the play of unconscious processes? We have here a possible
model of the interaction between society and personality as regards the
creation of works of art. An example borrowed not from Gombrich but from
Lucien Goldmann will make this hypothesis more concrete.
According to Goldmann, the economic and social structure resulting from
a laissez-faire economy produced, in literature, a certain type of novel: the
novel with a problematic hero. Since Malraux's novels were written toward
the end of this period,^^ he still used, necessarily as it were, the typical schema.
Goldmann stops there, but one can go a step further: if Malraux internalized
the conventional novelistic schema imposed by the social structure in which
he lived, his interpretation of this schema was very different from the inter-
pretation one finds in Roger Martin du Gard, Jules Romains, or Thomas
Mann. It is in the particular interpretation of the conventional schema, both on
the thematic and on the formal levels, that one can situate the influence of the
personality.*^
One can also come back to a variant of the classical model of culture and
personality, in which society influences the personality, notably in the frame-
work of the family. The family is both the mirror of a typical social reality and a
particular way of experiencing this typical context. In the Critique of Dia-
lectical Reason, Sartre shows this double aspect of the family milieu, as well
as the link — obvious, as far as we are concerned— that the family represents
between the general social structure and the formation of the artistic
personality:
The Flaubert family was of the semi-domestic type; it was a little behind the
industrial families which the father Flaubert cared for or visited. The father
Flaubert, who felt that he was "wronged" by his patron Dupuytren, terrorized
everyone with his own worth and ability, his Voltairian irony, his terrible angers
and fits of melancholy. We will also easily understand that the bond between the
small Gustave and his mother was never determining; she was only a reflection
of the terrible doctor. Thus we have before us an almost tangible cleavage which
will often separate Flaubert from his contemporaries; in a century when the
conjugal family is the type current among the wealthy bourgeoisie, when Du
Camp and Le Poittevin represent children freed from the patria potestas,
1
hand, bom the same year, will be fixed all his life on his mother. And this
difference explained by the difference in their respective environments.
is
Flaubert's bourgeoisie is harsh, new. (His mother, vaguely connected with the
nobility, represents a class of landowners in process of liquidation; the father
comes straight out of a village and wears strange, peasant clothing even at
Rouen— a goatskin in winter.) This bourgeoisie comes from the country; and it
returns there, too, since it uses its gradually won wealth to buy land. Baude-
laire's family, bourgeois, urban for many years already, considers itself in some
small way belonging to the new nobility (la noblesse de robe); it owns stocks and
bonds. Sometimes between two masters, the mother appeared all alone in the
glory of her independence. Later it was all in vain for Aupick to play at being the
"boss"; Mme. Aupick, stupid and rather vain, but charming and favored by her
period, never ceased to exist in her own right.^^
We need not be concerned here with the fact that Sartre establishes only a
"surface" relation between the particular family constellation and the writer's
personality; what matters, once again, is the encounter of the typical with the
idiosyncratic. In effect, the schema inspired by Gombrich's notion and the
one we have just illustrated by an example from Sartre dovetail with each
—
other and they do so, furthermore, in the theoretical context of the modes of
socialization of the individual, which we presented in the preceding chapter.
The example given by Sartre illustrates the socialization process of the child;
Gombrich's notion illustrates the internalization of norms which takes place
throughout one's lifetime. But that is not all.
and his own situation in the worid.'"' This provides us with an essential key to
psychobiographical interpretation. Finally, the work in question also em-
bodies a deeper model: a particular archetypal constellation, that of
the
"forbidden princess."
The work thus bears within itself its own structural coherence, the imprint
as well as.
ofthe society around it and the imprint ofthe author's personality,
62 History and Psychoanalysis
Aron." That is true, but the example he cites is a special case which allows one
to explain only a limited sector of human activity, the sector in which "the
person wholly disappears behind the function."^'' This kind of case offers no
particular interest to the biographer. But the moment one attempts to deal with
more complex and more ramified functions which contain elements of uncer-
tainty and choice, one inevitably observes the relevance of personal motives.
Thus, in the case of political figures, the circumstances surrounding the
.
It seems evident, therefore, that just as one cannot wholly deny the
influence of the role on the personality, one cannot ignore the opposite
influence, that of the personality on the role. This obvious interaction, even
while it eliminates a first objection, leads straight to another problem: how can
the biographer distinguish the specific influence of the role from that of the
personality, in studying a particular decision for example? How is he to find,
beneath the mask imposed by the role, the idiosyncratic elements of the
personality?"
The answer can be briefly stated: by comparing the behavior of the same
individual in several different roles, one can attribute the characteristics that
change to the influence of the various roles, and the permanent characteristics
to the influence of the personality.
The rate of success is no higher in the domain of political psychobiography
than it is in that of psychobiography in general. Simplistic interpretations are
found side by side with traditional biographies, which may themselves use a
few psychoanalytic concepts, thus adding very little to an understanding of the
personality studied.''^ Even more than in the case of writers and artists, there is
obviously a great temptation to analyze according to the criteria of psycho-
history the behavior of political figures who are still active. In such instances.
64 History and Psychoanalysis
Bullitt cites an imposing list of sources they consulted. In fact, he notes that
Freud "was dissatisfied by his studies of Leonardo da Vinci and of the Moses
statue by Michelangelo because he had been obliged to draw large conclusions
from few facts, and he had long wished to make a psychological study of a
contemporary with regard to whom thousands of facts could be ascer-
tained."*" The simplistic character of the result, the quasi-mechanical appli-
cation of the least elaborated analytic concepts, give one the impression that
most of the work is attributable to the American ambassador rather than to the
father of psychoanalysis. Yet, for our purposes this study is not lacking in
interest, for despite all its faults, it confirms on the essential points the
hypotheses at which the Georges arrived independently. (Their book was
published in the early 1950's; the manuscript of the Freud-Bullitt book was
completed in the was not published until 1966.) In certain
1930's, but
instances, the Freud-Bullitt work even furnishes added elements to complete
an explanation by the Georges.
Let us begin by recalling the main characteristics of the unconscious
repetitive structure in Wilson's behavior as outlined in the Georges' work, a
structure that they discern at every decisive stage in Wilson's public life. The
structure in question can be reduced to three distinct propositions.
First proposition: It is necessary to distinguish Wilson's behavior at the
time he was a "power-seeker" from the time he was a "power-holder." In the
first instance, Wilson was able to act with sufficient flexibility; it was in the
second situation that the difficulties appeared. When he was in a position of
power, Wilson manifested an aggressive behavior tending to force others into
the most total submission. Whenever he came up against significant opposi-
tion, he was unable to act with enough flexibility to overcome the obstacle. On
the contrary, he would formulate the conflict in terms of absolute principles
and, in their name, adopt an attitude of total intransigence; the result was
inevitably disaster, whereas any willingness to compromise would have
assured his success.
Second proposition: Wilson's hunger for success was limitless. As soon as
he had realized one ambition he launched himself into a new task, without
Is Psychoanalytic Biography Possible? 65
granting himself so much as a moment of rest to savor the success already
attained.
Third proposition: One of the most disastrous consequences of Wilson's
personal insecurity was his inability to ask for other people's advice con-
cerning problems which for him were charged with emotional significance,
unless he was sure that his advisers were not in a position to oblige him to
change his mind.
For the Georges, the origin of this behavior is to be found in Wilson's
childhood: "It our thesis that underlying Wilson's quest for political power
is
and his maimer of exercising it was the compelling need to counter the
crushing feelings of inadequacy which had been branded into his spirit as a
child. His interest in power, in political leadership, was based, we submit,
. . .
on the need to compensate for damaged self-esteem. The urgent inner need
constantly to struggle against these mischievous self-depreciating legacies
from his early years crippled his capacity to react objectively to matters at
hand."8'
We may briefly summarize the Georges' hypothesis as follows: Wilson's
father was excessively strict, and manifested an ironic attitude toward him
which had disastrous effects. The child, however, reacted to this only in a very
indirect way: he learned to read considerably late, and this inaptitude
represented a symbolic affront to the ambitions and demands of the father. On
the other hand —
and it is here that one can, by inference, propose the thesis of
—
repressed and displaced hostility in his adult life the young Wilson mani-
fested toward his father a deference, a devotion, and a love that immediately
strike one as "reaction formations" because of their excessive and unusual
character. The result was a displacement of hostility such that Woodrow
Wilson never allowed any other person to exercise power over him. He
constantly took revenge on others for the humiliation inflicted on him by his
father, since he could not express his hostility toward the father himself As
the Georges put it: "Throughout his life his relationships with others seemed
shaped by an inner command never again to bend his will to another man's. He
seems to have experienced men who were determined to make their view-
points prevail against his own— men like Dean West at Princeton or, later.
Naturally, he was not able to change his character even had he wanted to
change it, with the result that controversy and disastrous defeat occurred in
varying degrees in all three cases. "'^
The documents have been able to examine confirm, almost without
I
exception, the hypotheses of the Georges, Freud and Bullitt arrived at very
similar conclusions: according to them, it was the unconscious conflict with
the father that explained, in large part, Wilson's rigid attitude (a genetic
explanation that the Georges also propose), and was also the weight of the
it
superego imposed by the father which incited Wilson to incessant effort so that
success never brought him any rest. Despite all this, however, the Georges'
study shows once again how even the most successful psychobiographies
present certain problems that cannot be overlooked.
In the Georges' biography, Wilson's repetitive behavior, determined by his
unconscious conflicts, occupies all of the foreground, whereas the projects of
the president, of the man responsible for formulating a basic conception of
international order, appear only incidentally and are practically submerged by
the force of his unconscious conflicts. In Link's biography, on the other hand,
even if the outline of Wilson's repetitive behavior is sketched in, its uncon-
scious character, its conflictive origin and the influence of the unconscious
tendencies in question on the other aspects of Wilson's behavior are not
indicated: we have, instead, the evolution of a conscious will enriched by an
increasingly varied and complex experience, aiming for the conquest of power
but also for the realization of poHtical principles belonging to the American
progressive tradition. A complete biography of Wilson should in fact be a
synthesis of the two and the Georges'. Such a study would
studies. Link's
allow us to follow the growth of Wilson's project stage by stage, but within the
limits imposed by the unconscious structure of the President's pesonality; it
— —
would show us in the realization of this project the tragic interaction
between a conscious will pursuing its goal and the unconscious impulses that
divert it and eventually lead it to arouse opposition to its own desired ends.
Can such a double gaze be united into a single vision, one that avoids mere
artificial juxtaposition? One may well doubt it.
Furthermore, the Georges did not at all consider the possible influence of
organic illness on Wilson's behavior. Freud and Bullitt, on the other hand,
were aware of the possibility and posed the question repeatedly, but in the
absence of documentation they could not provide an answer.''' In the inter-
vening years, we have acquired further information. Thus, as we noted earlier,
Edwin Weinstein indicates that Wilson probably sufl"ered from a cerebro-
vascular ilhiess as early as 1896, and that in 1906 in any case, a definite
deterioration was noticeable. His aggressivity and intolerance at the time of
the Princeton controversy could therefore be attributed, at least in part, to an
organic cause.'- An examination of Wilson's behavior from the end of the war
on leaves no doubt about this point; the clinical and documentary evidence
provided by Weinstein is massive, and the behavior that the Georges explain
exclusively in psychodynamic terms was very probably due to the effect of a
serious deterioration in the cerebrovascular system.'* Thus, if one does not
Is Psychoanalytic Biography Possible? 69
take the physiological processes into account, one ends up with an over-
simplified uni-causal explanation; if one does take them into account, one
necessarily adds yet another element of indeterminacy to the overall picture of
the relation between Wilson's real personality and his public behavior. As
Lucien Febvre would say, however, "What matter? The historian does not
."
have the right to desert. . ,
incomprehensible to his small son, God is given the attribute of ira miser-
ACORDIAE— a wrath which is really compassion. With this concept, Luther
was at last able to forgive God for being a Father, and grant Him
justification."'"^
In his biography of Gandhi, Erikson raises the individual conflict between
father and son to the level of a nuclear conflict in the charismatic personality in
general.'"^ This hypothesis not enough to replace the larger framework we
is
evoked above, but it can allow us to define some of its aspects more precisely.
Concerning the relation between the charismatic leader and his followers, for
example: the conflict with the father, which is reflected in the leader's relation
with the sons, allows him not only to formulate the bases of a new identity and
a new ideology, but also to establish with his disciples and the masses a
relation of love, one that does
however, exclude hostile authority; such a
not,
relation is in fact the only kind that will satisfy the needs of the masses, who
hunger for emotional bonds but also for submission.
Corresponding to the typical conflict of the charismatic leader, there seems
to be a typical emotional need in those who become his disciples. Let us take
the men around Gandhi: "These young people," writes Erikson, "highly
gifted in a variety of ways, seem to have been united in one personality 'trait,'
namely, an early and anxious concern for the abandoned and persecuted, at
first within their families, and later in a widening circle of intensified concern.
At the same time, they were loyal rebels: loyal in their sorrow, determined in
Gandhi, displaying a wish to serve, which
their rebeUion. All this they offered
was determined as much by personaUty as by tradition. Gandhi's capacity
both to arouse and to squelch ambivalence [in his disciples] must have been
formidable; but he put these men and women to work, giving direction to their
capacity to care, and multiplying miraculously both their practical gifts and
"'°''
their sense of participation.
Despite the nebulousness of the style, Erikson presents a simple hypo-
thesis: the disciples of charismatic leaders are men who find a satisfying
solution for their personal problems and achieve a sense of personal equili-
brium by submitting to a leader who provoked ambivalence, even while he
channels the energies of his followers toward practical tasks that reinforce
each one's sense of participation.
The real gap in Erikson's analyses appears when he tries to explain the role
history book duly notes, but it does not in itself constitute an explanation.
The explanation Erikson offers in Young Luther is hardly more con-
Man
vincing; repeats the classical themes concerning the evolution of Christian
he
thought from its beginnings to the 16th century, without making clear, for all
concept is defined as a collective need for restructuring the image of the world.
This no more than a repetition, with the term "unconscious" tacked on, of
is
personality and not toward another, even though the new synthesis may have
been formulated by a certain number of people belonging to the same socio-
cultural milieu, sometimes acting together in the same religious or political
arena. Why did the masses turn toward Hitler and not toward a whole series of
other German right-wing agitators of the same period, most of whom had
arrived at the same basic reformulation of German identity in general racial
terms?
Here we encounter the artist's particular talent for symbolic reformulation,
which nothing allows us to identify or explain with precision. The conditions
favorable to the domination of a charismatic personality, the mode of domina-
tion of that personality at various levels, the particular circumstances which
allow him to reformulate the values of a group — all this is open to psycho-
historical investigation, as it is to more traditional modes of inquiry. The
fundamental nature of charisma resembles the symbolic language of the artist,
applied to the reality of the political or social world. Further than this, we
caimot go.
Psychohistorical Typology
At the beginning of this chapter, we showed the intimate connection that exists
between the "type" and the individual. Biography, admittedly, is the search
for a particular style, for the idiosyncratic variation in relation to a typical
norm, but it is nevertheless true that typology is important in its own right as an
autonomous field of study, as a verification criterion for psychohistorical
explanation in general,'"'' and as a specific verification criterion in the analysis
of stable homogeneous groups.'"* I shall discuss it here as an autonomous
field of study.
The typologies inspired by psychoanalysis have long ago gone beyond the
limits of clinical classification, in search of significant categories in the domain
of politics or ideology,'"' in that of intelligence or cognition,' '" or else in that of
moral behavior: we may example, the fascinating perspectives for
recall, for
research opened up by the few remarks Stefan Possony devotes, at the end of
his biography of Lenin, to the psychological type of the traitor.'"
Any typology is first of all a matter of definition, and a given social or
political category does not necessarily have a psychological equivalent; con-
versely, certain identifiable psychological types are not easy to incorporate
within the known frameworks of a given sociocultural system. The revolu-
tionary personality or the fascist (authoritarian) personality, for example,
have been studied more than once. But, to take only the example, is there latter
the mere study of a few historical cases belonging to the same category;
second, offering an example of psychohistorical typology that seems to
satisfy our verification criteria.
conditions, subject to change: thus, if the data concerning women are still
partially correct, those concerning Protestants are totally out of date."* As for
McClelland's other hypotheses, we shall examine them by considering the
biographies of three of the greatest English scientists: Newton, Faraday, and
Rutherford.
It turns out, first of all, that the thesis according to which scientists become
irreligious is one considers only the period during which the
invalid, even if
Or again: "The great gift Rutherford possessed for friendship was exercised all
isonly in the case of Newton that one could speak of a veritable obsession.'-'
Faraday had numerous duties as a councillor of the realm in various domains,
and part of his time was devoted to visiting the sick as well as to his activities
as an elder in the sect to which he belonged, the Sandemanians.'- As for
Rutherford, the range of his various social activities was a natural conse-
quence of his warm and "extroverted" personality.
As concerns the avoidance of complex emotions and especially of all inter-
personal aggressivity, McClelland's thesis is no more valid than on the other
points. Admittedly, one could explain Newton's intense aggressivity
toward
Leibniz orHook as an "ideological" corollary to his strict Protestantism, but
what can one say— as far as complex emotions are concerned— of his rela-
tionship with the young Swiss Fatio de Duillier, and of the depression that
but
followed their break?'^' In Faraday the aggressive element is not evident,
on the other hand we know how intensely he courted the woman who was to
76 History and Psychoanalysis
become his wife, Sarah.'" As for Rutherford, his aggressivity, amply docu-
mented throughout his career, manifested itself already in his student days;'"
and in the course of his life he was intensely involved in the most diverse
causes.
McClelland's hypothesis concerning the artistic preferences of scientists is
Hogarth or other graphic arts."'^^ We do not know how Newton felt about
music, but he is the only one of our three scientists who apparently had no
penchant for poetry or belles lettres.'^^
times who, in one way or another, do not fit into the typology in question; in
such a case, it seems to us, the numerical comparability of the "samples"
becomes totally irrelevant. Let us imagine that someone established the
psychodynamic characteristics of creative musicians basedon a list of
contemporaries, but it turned out that neither Bach nor Mozart nor Beethoven
could fit into the typology; would we have to add a whole series of other names
to make our refutation convincing?
One can use the same reasoning for the positive demonstration (i.e., the
confirmation) of a typology. Let us take example of composers once again,
tlie
and suppose that the study included not only Bach, Mozart, and Beethoven
but also Schubert, Brahms, Schumann, Wagner, Berlioz, Ravel, and Debussy.
Let us further suppose that the data converged so that we could define a type of
composer's personality. We could then present this incomplete series as a
typological hypothesis, on the grounds that the choice of composers uni-
versally recognized to be among the greatest made the addition of further
names unnecessary; but such a case the proof always hinges on some major
in
contradiction, and in the last analysis it is only intuitively that one can decide
to what extent a series is sufficiently representative— or, conversely, to what
extent a refutation is conclusive.
As an example of a positive demonstration, let us take the type of the
political "hawk," who in the technical terminology of game theory is known as
the "defector." In the case of most conflicts, game theory divides the possible
The first question we must ask is obvious: can we find, among the major
political figures of the contemporary period ( 1 9th and 20th centuries) any who
systematically opted for a poUcy of "defection" throughout their career? Are
we, in other words, justified in speaking of a typology on the basis of the
historical material available? The answer is yes, and we have chosen fourteen
political figures who seem to us to have systematically opted for this kind of
policy (with the exception of a few marginal situations) throughout the course
of their career: Napoleon Bonaparte, Napoleon Clemenceau, and Poin-
III,
care for France; Theodore Roosevelt, Forrestal, and Dulles for the United
States; Crispi for Italy; William II and Hitler for Germany; Beck for Poland;
Palmerston, Duff Cooper, and Churchill for England. In most of these cases,
the choice of a policy of "defection" operated not only on the level of interna-
tional affairs, but also in the domestic affairs in which these men were
involved. In certain cases, one finds the same attitude even when the men in
question were in the opposition.
Once we have identified this type of politician, the second question we must
ask is whether certain personality traits are found in the majority of the
"defectors," based on the historical data available. Here again the answer is
positive, and we can discern the repetition of the following characteristics: a
rebellious attitude toward authority when the person in question finds himself
in a position of inferiority, and the intransigent, quasi-dictatorial exercise of
authority when the person is himself in a position of authority; a preference for
violent solutions and the use of violent language in a conflict situation;
timidity, at least during the years preceding the rise to positions of power, and
harmonious interpersonal relations; in
in general a difficulty in establishing
disposal, we have iried to set up a complete typology, in other words one whose
evolutionary aspect can be documented and made explicit. In the political
figures we have one finds two distinct developmental contexts, most
studied,
of the time separate but occasionally combined in strange configurations: in
one context, the mother's role and authority predominate, due either to the
father's absence or to his weakness; the other context is essentially authori-
tarian in the classic sense of the term. In at least one case, that of Adolf Hitler,
Is Psychoanalytic Biography Possible? 79
the second (authoritarian) context dominates until the age of thirteen, and is
then replaced by the dominance of the mother after the father's sudden death.
The first context, in which the mother is dominant due to the absence or the
weak character of the father, can generally lead to a fixation on the mother and
therefore to a submissive and self-effacing personality, but it can also lead—
and it is the latter case that interests us here — to a process of compensatory
masculinity: since the child has no clearly defined male model to follow but is
at the same time pushed by the demands of the society toward masculine
behavior, he will naturally tend to exaggerate the masculine traits of his
personality, emphasizing the elements of domination, force, competition,
etc.'^^ This in turn leads to a "defector's" behavior as we have defined it.
Mother of the gods and of men, of the stars and of ants, of com and of agave,
Tonantzin-Guadalupe was the Indians' imaginary compensation for the or-
phaned state into which the conquest had cast them. Having seen their priests
massacred and their idols destroyed, their links with the past and with their
supernatural world broken, they took refuge in the bosom of Tonantzin-
Guadalupe: the bosom of the mother-mountain, the bosom of the mother-ocean.
The ambiguous situation of the New Spain led to a similar reaction: the Creoles
sought in Tonantzin-Guadalupe their veritable mother. A natural and super-
natural mother, made of American earth and European theology. For the
Creoles, the brown Virgin represented the possibility of rootedness in the earth
of the Anahuac. She was both the womb and the tomb: to become rooted is to
penetrate into the earth. For the half-castes, the feeling of abandonment was
. . .
and remains more total and more dramatic. For the half-caste, the question of
origin is primordial, a question of life or death. In the imagination of the half-
castes,Tonantzin-Guadalupe has her infernal counterpart: Chingada. She is the
raped mother, exposed to the outside world, torn apart by the conquest: the
Virgin Mother, on the other hand, is intact, invulnerable, and carries a son in her
womb. The secret life of the half-caste oscillates between Chingada and
Tonantzin-Guadalupe.
their place in the symbolic network which includes the culture as a whole.
81
82 History and Psychoanalysis
But would be only the end of the road; in the meantime, in order to
this
way. Our manner of proceeding will be, in a sense, circular: beginning with the
analysis of stable homogeneous groups, where culture and society coincide in
a limited and isolated sphere, we shall go on to the necessarily more frag-
mented analyses of temporary homogeneous groups and heterogeneous
groups, ending up with the global analysis of the cultures (and mentalities) of
heterogeneous groups. Along the way, we shall stop to consider the particular
problems posed by the study of generational age groups and of the various
stages of personality development in different historical periods. These are all
Collective Phenomena 83
cases that put psychohistorical investigation to the test, allowing one to see its
possibilities as well as its limits.
Homogeneous Groups
us, we have chosen two studies that are more clearly historical in character. In
the first case, the homogeneity of the group is reinforced by the domination of
a "total" ideology that influences every aspect of existence: the group here is
that of the New England Puritans of the 1 7th century, more specifically the
inhabitants of Plymouth Colony, studied by John Demos.* In the second case,
that of the black slaves in the American South, the study we shall discuss'
emphasizes not the relationship between primary institutions and the person-
ality, but rather the phenomena of identification with, and internalization of,
the norms of the masters; this, despite the fact that the family organization of
84 History and Psychoanalysis
the slaves could have been related to the black personality in this type of
society.
According to Demos, the Puritans of Plymouth Colony believed in great
severity toward children, starting at the time of the child's first interest in the
world around him and his first manifestations of independence, between the
ages of one and two years. The first expressions of the child's will were
interpreted as a trace of original sin and of man's rebelHon against God. Thus,
in his second year of life the Puritan child experienced an essentially repres-
sive environment. This second year was also, in most cases, the one in which
the child experienced a more or less pronounced loss of affection, for it was
around then that the next child was bom in those very large families.
Using Erikson's model. Demos points out that excessive severity toward a
child or a withdrawal of affection in the second phase of his evolution are likely
to fixate the child in an attitude of doubt and shame instead of allowing for the
harmonious development of individual autonomy. Aggressivity, directed
toward oneself or others, becomes a dominant characteristic of the personahty
In light of this, what do we observe among the adult Puritans of Plymouth
Colony? Contrary to what was long believed, it is not sexual problems that
constituted their major preoccupation, but rather problems linked to aggres-
sivity —
more precisely still, situations that concerned matters of honor ("face-
saving"), and that were obviously closely Hnked to shame and doubt: "Such
considerations," writes Demos, "are manifest, for example, throughout the
legion of Court cases that had to do with personal disputes and rivalries. Many
—
of these cases involved suits for slander or defamation where the issue of
public exposure, the risk of shame, was absolutely central. Moreover, when a
conviction was obtained, the defendant was normally required to withdraw his
"
slanderous statements, and to apologize for them, in public.
We know that, acco'-ding to Erikson, the fixation at a particular stage of
development implies, later on, a strong preoccupation with certain specific
aspects of social organization. Corresponding to the second stage of develop-
ment is the concern for "law and order." And of course, "few people have
shown as much concern for 'law and order' as the Puritans."'"
Here then is a stable homogeneous group, due to its cultural unity, its
relative isolation in relation to the outside world (at least during the first
decades of its settlement in New England), the absence of major social sub-
divisions, and above all the domination of a "totalitarian" ideology in the
genuine sense of the term: the Puritan religion. The result was a set of specific
mothering and child-rearing practices which had a decisive effect on the
development of the personality, and consequently on certain important as-
pects of adult behavior — consequences that, according to John Demos, were
also manifest in a certain conception of the social order and of the role of
institutions.
Itmust be said, however, that the univocal causal relationship Demos
establishes between certain mothering practices of the group and character-
istics such as the preoccupation with "law and order" is not altogether
justified. The Puritan religion itself implied a concern for "law and order," and
^
Collective Phenomena 85
any attempt to find a psychoanalytic explanation for it is superfluous. On the
other hand, the aggressive behavior of the inhabitants of Plymouth Colony is
less easily explained by Puritanism alone; similarly, the strong emphasis on
questions of honor can be identified as a characteristic of a significant "basic
personality." Still, one must note that when Kardiner and Linton studied the
Alorese or the Comanches, the relations they found between primary institu-
tions, the basic personality and the secondary institutions formed a detailed
and complex configuration, one that was sufficiently idiosyncratic so that it
could not be attributed to general and commonly observable sociocultural
conditions. This is not true in the case of Plymouth Colony. Only a compara-
tive study of several groups of this type would allow one, perhaps, to resolve
the problem.
On the other hand, Stanley Elkins' study of black slaves in the United
States could have resulted in a more convincing explanation than the one he
proposes, he had invoked the influence of a specific family structure on the
if
tions eased the existence of the slave and made him partially independent of
his master, and the "closed system" of slavery practiced on the plantations of
the South, in which nothing could weaken the total dependence of the slave on
his white master. According to Elkins, the slave entered this closed system
after having experienced the basic psychological shock of being torn from
Africa and from his ancestral culture; as a result, he knew no other values or
other meaningful norms than those imposed on him by his masters. Like
certain prisoners of the Nazi concentration camps, the black slave internalized
the norms of the master and accepted, paradoxically, the latter as his "father,"
identifying with him and regressing, in relation to this cruel father, to the
emotional stage of the child. This accounted for the appearance of the specific
personahty of the black American slave, "Sambo." Elkins writes: "Sambo,
the typical plantation slave, was docile but irresponsible, loyal but lazy,
humble but chronically given to lying and stealing; his behavior was fiill of
infantile silliness and his talk inflated with childish exaggeration. His relation-
ship with his master was one of utter dependence and childlike attachment: it
was indeed this childlike quaUty that was the very key to his being."'
Elkins' "closed system" endows the slavery of the American South with
one of the essential characteristics of homogeneous groups, but the absence of
any systematic reference to the primary institutions raises the question of the
slave family. For that matter, the very etiquette of plantation life removed even
the honorific attributes of fatherhood from the Negro male, who was addressed
as "boy" —until, when the vigorous years of his prime were past, he was allowed
We can see here the outlines of a unique family structure, in which the
problem of the identity formation of the black male child was to become, of
necessity, the focal point of intense neurotic conflicts.^'' It seems to us
plausible to consider this family structure as an essential factor in the
formation of the personality of the black slave, whether of the Sambo type or
not. It would have been important to analyze the relationship between this
kind of "basic personality" and various aspects of the black subculture on the
plantations; the results would doubtless have suggested that we were dealing
with a stable homogeneous group, characterized by the interaction between
culture and personality. This kind of analysis would still have allowed Elkins
to utilize the conceptions of Sullivan and those of role theory, but the specifi-
cally psychoanalytic part of his study would have been strengthened, even
while allowing him to answer a question that one carmot fail to raise after
reading his book: How is it that temporary institutions, such as those that
Elkins used as models, could give rise to a personality as stable in its essential
characteristics (over several generations, moreover) as that of Sambo? Why
not look, in trying to answer this question, at the most stable of institutions,
that of the specific family structure?
The homogeneous groups that interest the historian are few in
stable
number, and the method of analysis that we propose to apply to them here is
clear. It is evident that the essential characteristics of the basic personality of
such a group must be found, with all of its idiosyncratic elements, in a
significant number of individuals belonging to the group. We can therefore
formulate the verification criteria for the psychohistorical study of stable
homogeneous groups one SQWiQncQ: Any psychohistorical explanation con-
in
cerning these groups must beformulable in terms of typology and verifiable
in terms of biography.
Collective Phenomena 87
of an obsession in the absence of a dominant personality (more exactly,
without the continuous presence of a dominant personality'') seem to be
governed by an identical mechanism: the members of the group seem to
renounce their individuality, and the injunctions of the dominant personality
or of the obsessive ideology, like the norms of the total institution, often
lead them to the most aberrant and sometimes even the most criminal
behavior without their manifesting the least resistance, as if they were under
the effect of hypnosis.
In the category of groups dominated by a personality, we recognize the
prophet and his disciples or the head of a sect and its members, ready to follow
their leader even into death; such groups include the millenarians of the late
Middle Ages,'^ as well as Hitler and the "true beUevers" of the Nazi party.'^ If
the leader is replaced by a dominant fantasy, we have the bands of flagellants
or the groups of the possessed (or of witches) in Loudon, in Salem—
multitude of similar examples dot the history of the Western world.'* Al-
though they are more homogeneous than all the others, these groups are
nevertheless astonishingly short-lived. If the dominant personality disappears,
the group disintegrates; if the circumstances change, the collective obsession
suddenly dies down: "normalcy" returns, as if nothing had happened."
We must admit from the start that it is extremely difficult to explain the
behavior of temporary homogeneous groups of this type. The classical
explanation is the one proposed by Freud in Group Psychology and the
Analysis oftheEgo.^^ It is not an acceptable explanation, as we shall see.
Freud too seems to admit that an "idea" can replace a dominant person-
ality and have the same psychic effect on a group, even though he considers
this a minor point. What interests him is the relation of the group to its leader,
and the relation of the members of the group to each other. Two explanations,
which are interdependent, allow him to resolve the problem to his satisfaction.
First, "A primary group of this kind is a number of individuals who have put
one and the same object in the place of their ego ideal and have consequently
identified themselves with one another in their ego."^' In other words, in this
kind of group the members have abandoned their individual superegos (their
ego ideal) in favor of a collective superego, founded on the process of identi-
fication among the various members of the group. Why does this substitution
of the leader's superego for the superego of each member occur? Freud replies
accompany them, may therefore with justice be traced back to the fact of their
primal
origin from the primal horde. The leader of the group is still the dreaded
""
father; the group still wishes to be governed by unrestricted force
Thus, on the group, Freud
in order to explain the influence of the leader
must have recourse to a phylogenetic theory with no basis whatsoever.
with
Furthermore, if one recalls that ideas can impose themselves on a group
88 History and Psychoanalysis
the same power as becomes hard to see how the analogy with the
individuals, it
father of the primal horde can apply. And how would it apply to groups domi-
nated by a woman? Of Freud's explanation, we can retain therefore two
elements: the libidinal nature of the bonds formed between the members of a
group of this kind, and the introjection of the leader's values by each member
of the group. These notions, which are more descriptive than explicative, are
close to what we wrote earlier about the relationship between the charismatic
personality and the group; several possible avenues for psychohistorical
investigation are suggested by it.
Even without knowing the exact nature of the process involved, but simply
after observing that among the members of a group of this type there is a total
introjection of the leader's values or an absolute sharing of the same obsession,
the historian can interpret the basic elements of these shared fantasies in
terms of their unconscious mechanisms, and establish a link between them and
the manifest behavior of the group. This is what I do in
myself tried to
L 'Antisemitisme nazi, in which I showed that the fantasy of the Jew as a germ
was shared by Hitler and his followers, and that this fantasy led to a behavior
of identification and purification (a combination well known to students of
individual obsessions), whose final form was to be the physical elimination of
the Jews, the "final solution."^"
The functioning of total institutions is similar, as one can see from certain
first-person accounts of the evolution of the behavior of inmates in the concen-
tration camps. We may take as an example the one analyzed by Bruno
Bettelheim in The Informed Heart. According to Bettelheim, the aim of the
Nazi concentration camp system was to break the individuality of the
prisoners, "and to change them into a docile mass from which no individual or
group act of resistance could arise."" The various methods employed to this
end by the SS succeeded in a certain number of cases, and the group of
prisoners came to manifest similar psychic characteristics of which the most
important was an infantile regression combined with a more or less strong
identification with the aggressor: "Since old prisoners had accepted, or been
forced to accept, a childlike dependency on the SS, many of them seemed to
want to feel that at least some of the people they were accepting as all-
powerful father images were just and kind."" Bettelheim does not, of course,
suggest that all of the prisoners arrived at that point; but a certain fraction, or
subgroup, did.
Temporary homogeneous groups, whatever the differences between them,
all present, therefore, an identical configuration: at a given moment, an
individual, an idea, or an institution brings together a number of individuals in
a group which, under this influence, adopts a form of behavior due to a sudden
transformation of the personality of the members of the group. But once the
dominant personality, the idea or the institution disappears, the group as a
whole disintegrates and the behavior of its members reverts, most often, to
what it was before the formation of the group.
These empirical data do not lend themselves to a single theoretical
explanation. One can opt for the theory of continuous identification and
Collective Phenomena 89
internalization, but how then can we explain the restructuring of the person-
ality? This restructuring is altogether paradoxical, for it is both unconscious
and profound, yet is at the same time ephemeral. In cases of this kind, the
historian can do no more than attempt a description and a few partial
explanations, such as the influence of the charismatic personality. Taken as a
whole, temporary homogeneous groups are not yet amenable to systematic
psychohistorical analysis."
attempted to do the same for several societies of the past as well, chiefly
through a content analysis of literary and artistic themes. Children's literature
plays an important role in the identification of the degree of the "need for
achievement" in various modem societies, whereas classical literature and
vase drawings play a similar role in the study of Greek society in the Golden
Age.
with the explanation of the origins of the "need for achievement" that
It is
behavior that stimulates the "need for achievement;" this allows us to add a
psychological dimension to Max Weber's famous theory concerning the role
of Protestantism in the development of modem capitalism.
McClelland's theses provoked some controversy, and his quantitative
demonstrations are not always convincing. In this instance, however, what
matters is not the rigorousness of the demonstration but the formulation of the
question, which opens up a whole field of inquiry. To suggest that there is a
relationship between profound psychological attitudes and economic develop-
ment is to open up new horizons for economic
and to demonstrate that
history,
even a phenomenon seemingly as independent of psychology as economic
growth can, through the psychohistorical analysis of a specific attitude (the
"need for achievement") take on a new significance. It goes without saying,
however, that it is in the domain of collective disorders what Georges —
Devereux calls "ethnic disorders" and "typical disorders," linked to a specific
cultural model or a particular social structure" —
that the psychohistorical
study of isolated phenomena will find an immense field of application.
"Every culture," writes Devereux, "allows certain fantasies, drives and
other psychic manifestations to reach and remain on the conscious level, while
repressing others. That is why all the members of a given culture have in
common a certain number of unconscious conflicts."^" We shall return to this
essential notion in discussing the global analysis of cultures, but it is funda-
mental for the study of isolated phenomena as well, for the psychohistorian
will want to investigate the relationship between the global culture and the
predominance of a given fantasy or basic attitude; he will also attempt to
analyze a given characteristic trait in its various stages of manifestation, or
else compare it to a similar trait in a different sociocultural context. Could one
not study, for example, the evolution of paternal authoritarianism in the
German family from the eighteenth century to the present, or else compare the
characteristic traits of this widespread phenomenon in German culture with
the doubtless different traits that it manifests in Russian society? Or again, to
cite another of Georges Devereux's suggestions, could we not examine,
through time, the way in which various cultures "masculinize" their men,
"feminize" their women and make their children "childlike"?^*
If we turn to psychic disorders in the clinical sense of the term, it is again
Georges Devereux who points out most common neurosis in our
that the
societies at the turn of the century involved symptomatic disorders; during the
1930's, it was replaced by characterial disorders, whereas today patients
suffer rather from "an alteration in their sense of their own identity."^* It is
the manifestly irrational or morbid kinds of behavior that provide a rich
material for study. Is not the first task of psychohistory to narrate the history
of, and furnish an explanation for, the evolution of neurotic and psychotic
disorders in various cultures, as a function of the evolution of the global
sociocultural context?"
The great movements of collective irrationality require the same kind of
analysis as the clinical disorders. Among
most evident of such pheno-
the
mena, we may mention the witch-crazes and the witch-hunts,^* or anti-
Semitism and the persecution of the Jews. We shall consider in some detail
Collective Phenomena 91
two of these examples, to show how, in each case, psychohistory can add a
new dimension to the traditional and essential sociocultural analysis.
A few years ago, the British historian Hugh Trevor-Roper published his
study on The European Witchcraze of the Sixteenth and Seventeenth Cen-
turies. His work meets all the traditional canons of historiography, for it
describes perfectly the social and intellectual context of the phenomenon in
question: ancient Manichean notions as well as various pagan traditions sur-
vived in the midst of marginal groups which feudal Christianity had assimilated
only very partially, especially in the mountainous regions of Europe. In the con-
text of a general struggle against heresies, the Dominicans, seeking to delimit
and wipe out these heterodox beliefs, erected an elaborate system out of their
diffuse notions and thus created an increasingly complex mythology con-
cerning the practices of witchcraft and the nature of witches. But as the
mythology of the defenders of the faith became more elaborate, it in turn
attracted psychopaths of all kinds (according to Trevor-Roper), thus contribu-
ting to its own propagation.
It matters little to us what other social, intellectual, and political factors
contributed to the growth of the witch-craze and later to its decline, as long as
the psychological dimension of this immense harvest of collective fantasies is
flame." Here we enter into the obscure dialectic between the sexual fantasies
of the inquisitor and those of the witch herself— a dialectic that doubtless
an altogether different order. For what is the aim of the
reflects conflicts of
inquisitor, asks Danet, if not to dishonor this woman (the witch) and
her
sexuality? But in that case, he asks, what is the "underlying motive for this
operation?" The explanation Danet offers is most suggestive: "Could it be a
question of responding to an obscure cultural movement of masculine revenge,
culture
directed against an Indo-European (Celtic and Germanic) matriarchal
in which the mother had some of the attributes of the priest and the
prophef? A
whole tradition of folklore has persisted over the centuries, heavy with the
92 History and Psychoanalysis
Finally, the Malleus completes this picture with an image of God the Father.
The figure that emerges is that of a divinity full of duplicity and sadism:
Beneath the watchful eyes of such a cunning what can the sons be if not
father,
desperate, impotent men with sado-masochistic tendencies? The image of trans-
gression is linked, in their minds, with that of dissimulation and perversion. The
desire of such sons is directed toward the forbidden fruit, which appears all the
more "infinitely desirable" since it bathes in the fantasy of the unattainable and
is guarded by the interdiction of a wrathful Father. Under the pressure of an
always ill-resolved crisis, man is then tempted to scorn the forbidden pleasure, to
dishonor sexuality. In trying to win the good graces of the Father, he even goes
so far as to practice a certain sadism toward others and ultimately a castrating
masochism toward himself^
As a matter of fact, Amand Danet merely touches the tip of the iceberg, and
one can imagine a much more detailed and in-depth analysis of the same
fantasies. That would have been beyond the scope of an introduction,
however; and in any case, we are far from Trevor- Roper and his explanation of
the demonological system of the inquisitors as part of the "rationahsm of the
period.'"*^ One would like to complete this discussion by an analysis of the
fantasies evoked in Michelet's La Sorciere, but as we suggested earlier, Alain
Besangon's brilliant reading of that text presents a methodological problem
which, as far as we are concerned, is not resolved.
Turning now to another species of collective "craze," that of anti-Semitism,
we note that witches and Jews were amalgamated in the fantastic imagery of
evil. But even at a time when witches and demons had disappeared, the Jew
itself from what is "other." From the sociological point of view, the Jews
represent above all the deviant group that allows a society to define its own
Hmits.''* From a psychological point of view, the identifying function of the
Jew is even clearer: he is the "group's counter-ideal," whose essential function
is to "serve as a negative counterpart to the group ideal, an embodiment as —
an example to be avoided — of everything that the group ideal is not, and must
at all cost avoid being.""*^
But even on the most general level, an explanation of the hostility directed
against the Jew in terms of the latter's double identifying function is insuffi-
cient. We are dealing here with an overdetermined phenomenon, and it is the
effect of overdetermination that explains the stability of this collective attitude
and the endurance of the symbol. The religious and cultural origins of this
negative symbol are well known; they were constantly reactivated on the
Collective Phenomena 93
Oedipal ambivalence is never wholly resolved, the Jew becomes— for cultural
world, of
reasons that are readily understandable— the symbol, in a Christian
father." Indeed, as has often been noted, the Jews are
considered as
the "bad
the representatives of God the Father, in opposition to God the Son, with
whom the Christian child identifies. But God the Father is the Law of
the ancestors, those whom the Christian child readily assimilates to the father.
Thus, the Christian imagination sees (more or less consciously) in the conflict
between the Jews and Christ a reflection of old personal conflicts with the
father, and this conflict comes to symbolize, on an unconscious level, the
Oedipal situation. Certain Jewish practices can only reinforce, moreover, this
identification of the Jew with the father in the Oedipal conflict. Circumcision,
for example, can evoke the threat of castration and even of death, a threat that
is intimately linked to the Oedipal conflict. One finds the trace of these identi-
fications and these fears under the most various forms in Western culture,
from the myth of ritual murder to the image of the Jew as a frightening old man,
as Ahasverus the Wandering Jew or some other similar figure.""
Finally, in general psychological terms the hostility directed against the
Jew serves as an outlet for the projections caused by certain specific defor-
mations of the personality. We obviously have no sufficient data to determine
whether virulent anti-Semites are for the most part neurotic or psychotic
personaHties, but the clinical studies by Ackermann and Marie Lazarsfeld-
Jahoda,^" by Adomo and his associates, by Gough^' and by Loewenstein" tend
to confirm that hypothesis, just as my own brief survey \n L'Antisemitisme
nazi does: the biographies of some twenty notorious anti-Semites, most of
whom lived in the nineteenth and the beginning of the twentieth centuries, seem
in fact to indicate a correlation between a fanatical hatred of the Jews and
various personality disorders. ^^ The correlation, moreover, is not between
—
extreme anti-Semitism and certain specific disorders, but and this confirms
the clinical hypotheses of Ackermann and Jahoda —
between anti-Semitism
and a whole potential range of neurotic or psychotic characteristics.
The identification of the general sociological and psychological functions
of anti-Semitism and the study of their interrelationship does not amount to a
psychohistorical study in the true sense of the term, for the diachronic element
is still missing. That is precisely where specific questions come into play: one
must study the transformation of the general functions in specific, and
changing, historical contexts.
We have already mentioned, for example, the role of anti-Semitism as a
factor of social cohesion in situations ofanomie or crisis. The psychological
dimension of this role is particularly easy to illustrate when the society in
question is undergoing a prolonged crisis or when the identity of the group is
still uncertain: in such cases, the negative symbol serves to emphasize the
by means of contrast. This process,
positive traits of the collective identity,
discernible in various groups of European society during the period of radical
transformation in the second half of the 19th century, was particularly evident
in Germany, where the changes were more rapid and more intense than else-
where and where the formation of a stable collective identity was prevented
by very serious obstacles. Thus, many Germans became conscious of their
own "German-ness" thanks to the imaginary Jew. "The German people,"
wrote the racist anti-Semite Bockel, "must, thanks to anti-Semitism, learn to
be aware of itself once again as the Germanic race opposed to the Jewish
race." Irving Fetscher, who quoted this statement by Bockel, adds: "The
Collective Phenomena 95
of the situations of social change that interest us, is far from being explained by
a single, unanimously accepted sociological theory. The various
theories that
have been proposed can be classified according to the "content" of the change
(theories of progress or of decline)," but a formal classification
is more useful
ifone wants to see to what degree they take account of psychological factors.
We can thus distinguish three fundamental types: 1) theories of "non-
theories ot
change"; 2) theories of progressive and continuous change; 3)
sudden and discontinuous change.
In the first category, we may place the structuralism of Levi-Strauss and its
96 History and Psychoanalysis
the identity of the institution or the group that is changing, structuralism allows
us to analyze the fundamental components of this stable identity. In this
context, the contribution of psychology is clear: the basic structure reflects
certain fundamental aspects of the human mind, whether we are dealing with
formal binary oppositions or with yet another restatement of the incest taboo.
On the level of the analysis of fundamental structures, psychology is pre-
dominant, even if its contribution can be expressed only in general terms. Any
analysis of social change should in fact begin with an attempt to define the
permanent structures of certain symbolic manifestations of the group (for
example), but that is a step that the non-structuralists usually omit; they prefer
to emphasize the permanence of certain institutional or cultural elements
before turning to a study of the processes of transformation themselves.
The modalities of change have given rise to rival theories: in one camp are
those who espouse the theory of gradual and continuous change; in the other,
those who maintain that no genuine change is possible without a sharp break
with the past, a sudden transformation in structure, paradigm, or norms. The
theory of continuous change, in which one can include some of Marx's models
as well as those of Talcott Parsons one remains on the formal level of
if
analysis, is based on the simple idea that the sources of change are found in the
structure of the society itself: the tensions and "dysfunctions" that arise
between elements in the social structure provoke an unstable situation in
which certain elements became maladapted; the system will then tend to
resolve the situation by readapting and transforming its constituent ele-
ments.'* Societies advance, thus, in a continuous movement from one system
of equilibrium to another, passing through necessary temporary stages of
tension and disequihbrium in the process; these stages of disequilibrium can
even be revolutionary crises in the Marxist sense of the term.
According to the theorists of discontinuous change, the processes we have
just described exist, to be sure, but they can lead only to a "reordering" of the
system without any genuine transformation. Genuine change, whether it is
provoked by a social crisis, a technological advance, or the discovery of an
anomaly in the existing scientific concepts, can be none other than a total
break with the past and a sudden mutation of the structure or the paradigm.^'
Some historians are not aware of this theoretical debate,*" but their implicit
or explicitly stated conceptions nevertheless place them either in the camp of
change-through-modification-of-structures, or in thatof sudden-passage-from-
one-structure-to-another. In opposition to the traditional Marxist school of
historians,one can quote, among many others, Emmanuel Le Roy Ladurie.
After having emphasized the coherence which, despite all the variations, one
can find in any given historical structure, Le Roy Ladurie remarks that the
Collective Phenomena 97
can understand the problems of group identity which led to the preservation of
the norm of authority on the political level until the end of the Second World
War, one can also see that the general emotional foundations of this norm
were weakened by the evolution of the family stmcture; the ground was
therefore ready, in an ever-growing segment of the German population, for the
intemalization of the new liberal norms implied by the change in the system
that occurred in 1945. Without this evolution, the Federal Republic might
have suffered the same fate as the republic of Weimar. These hypotheses will
have to be confirmed by a series of systematic analyses; but for psychohistory
there can be no definitive explanation of the social change that has taken place
in Germany over the past few decades without an in-depth study of the
changes toward authority in the German family, and of the reper-
in attitude
Age Groups
quarrel over dates is a minor matter. What matters is that we understand the
historical and cultural variations imposed on some of the most important
developmental phases of our existence. Depending on the society, certain
developmental phases can be blocked or eUminated; conversely, some socie-
ties will create, as Kenneth Keniston has noted, developmental phases that do
not exist in others.*' This fact naturally leads to various hypotheses; thus,
according to Keniston, "in societies where adolescence does not occur many
of the psychological characteristics which we consider the results of an
adolescent experience should be extremely rare: for example, a high degree of
emancipation from the family, a well-developed self-identity, a belief system
based upon a reexamination of the cultural assumptions learned in childhood,
'"'^
and, perhaps, the cognitive capacity for formal operation. This type of
correlation is not self-evident, but it is the kind of question that the historian
can ask about age groups in various societies. In fact, the historian ought to
establish the give-and-take between the age group and the society at large,
explaining the characteristics of the former by the evolution of the latter, and,
conversely, examining the possible influence of the age group on some of the
attitudes of the society. Thus, in his study of childhood in France in the
seventeenth century,^' David Hunt shows both the particularities of the
behavior toward children in the society, and the influence of this behavior on
certain aspects of the society itself.
are— together with the formation of the xdenWiy— those whose ejfects on the
social behavior of the adult are the most readily identifiable. In primitive
societies or in certain homogeneous groups as we have defined them, it is
possible to discover in adult behavior the consequences of a specific manner of
resolving the problems of the firstdevelopmental stage (the oral stage, with its
antithetical attitudes of trust and suspicion), or the consequences of the mode
of resolution of the Oedipal conflict. The complex social organization of
also suggest some possible comparisons between the German case and certain
Collective Phenomena 103
kinds of youthful behavior in more recent times, notably in American society
during the 1960's.
Regardless of the exact period when adolescence and early youth emerged
as a culturally distinct stage in the developmental cycle, it is only at the end of
the nineteenth century that one finds the first expressions of the psychological
and cultural exigencies of youth as youth, that is as a group with its own
values, a distinct generation in the sense in which Karl Mannheim defined the
term.''^ As several scholars have noted, most of the "rebellions of youth" up to
that time ("Young Italy," "Young Turks," etc.) had been fought in the name of
universal revolutionary ideals, rather than with the deliberate aim of ex-
pressing the aspirations of youth as such.''^
Among the sociological criteria that characterize this age group, we must
distinguish between the general criteria that define the function of youth in the
global structure of modem on the one hand (these criteria, being
societies
"universalistic" in nature, do not allocate status and roles in terms of family or
clan membership), and the social conditions of conflict between youth and the
society at large on the other hand; this latter criterion is the more important
one from our point of view.
Generally speaking, one can consider adolescence and youth in modem
societies as the age during which the individual separates himself from the
familial norms that defined his existence until then, without at the same time
integrating himself into so-called "adult" society and accepting all of its
norms. The adolescent tends to seek the company of his peers in organizations
of various kinds, and to use these groups as environments in which to prepare
for adult hfe. Naturally, not all such groups provide adequate preparation for
adult life, and some provide very inadequate preparation indeed: nevertheless,
it is in these groups that the adolescent can experience a whole series of roles
that will be necessary for his integration into adult society. By definition, then,
all kinds published by the various factions, as well as in their songbooks and
in
the novels, the poetry and the painting that they adopted, one finds the same
fears and aspirations despite their apparent diversity.
"The time of the Wandervogel' s foundation," writes the first historian of
the movement, Hans Bluher, "was characterized by a struggle of young people
against the worid of adults."*^ Recently, some writers on the subject have tried
the
to minimize the importance of this aspect of the movement, claiming that
youth of the Wandervogel were not in principle opposed to the worid of their
fathers and that their apparent rejection of it was only true of a few
theoreti-
cians within the movement.** In fact, allthe evidence suggests the contrary:
the movement was first of all an attempt to liberate young people from the
Their
worid of adults, a worid whose values and customs they rejected.
opposition to that worid was intense, so much so that during the
war many
young people demanded the exclusion of the first members of the movement—
106 History and Psychoanalysis
culture, a clean way of life unmarked by the use of alcohol or tobacco, and,
above all, a common existence that could rise above self-interest and shabby
party politics."*^ Thus
was the lies, the routine, the often sordid character of
it
that were rejected. But this radical refusal, to which one should add a
systematic anti-materialism and the horror of large modem cities, was
accompanied by specific themes that were quite strange but quite important
from our point of view. Here was a group of young people who, in the great
majority, revolted against the "impurity" of the adult world in a very precise
sense: they rejected alcohol and tobacco, but they also rejected the "impurity"
of adult sexual life. The evidence for this is massive.
Among the favorite novels of the members of the youth movements,
Wiltfeber was ambiguous on the question of the rejection of "impurity," but
Helmut Harringa was a veritable call to arms against alcohol and eroticism.*'
But let us look, rather, at the writings of the Wandervogel or the Biinde
themselves, and above all at members. "One of the
the behavior of their
principal targets of the attacks of the youth movements," writes someone who
knew the movements first-hand, "was bourgeois social life, especially the
coarseness of sexual mores both public and private, which assailed their deep
longing for chastity at practically every streetcomer. Disgusted by the abject
omnipresence of these corrupt morals, the young people, in their need for
purity, at first saw no other solution than a total rejection of all sexu-
ality. ..."'" In his introduction to a volume of writings of the youth move-
ments, Theodor Wilhelm, while voicing skepticism about the role of the
"generation conflict" in the constitution of the movements, maintains that
"sexual asceticism" was one of their essential characteristics. But in reading
the texts themselves, one is astonished by the arguments employed by these
youth-movement members of forty years ago. Their rejection of sexuality was,
they claim, a reaction against the "corrupt" morals of adults, but also an
ordinary consequence of the fact that the young girls who founded their own
groups, distinct from the male groups, were not very attractive!" Curious
Whatever one thinks of them, the rejection of a sexual
rationalizations, these.
freedom that today would be considered normal and desirable characterizes a
considerable segment of the German youth movements of the beginning of the
century, and (although to a lesser extent) of the 1920's as well. "Young
people," writes Wyneken, "found no other solution to their sexual problem
than to profess sexual abstinence and set up comaraderie as the relation
between the sexes. ."'^ This statement, which seems to be a criticism, is in
. .
involvement with the group, the exaltation of comaraderie and the community
of young men that marked the Wandervogel and the movements that followed
it. Much has been said about the homosexual character (either latent or active)
us consider the core of the movements: the community of peers and their
leader.
The community, the group, was itself a program: as one of their manifestos
declared, "Where lively people are together no one needs a programme. . .
There is nothing more wonderful and fruitful than communion in a small circle
of confidants where no plan and no 'order of the day' hems in spontaneous
vitality and the spirit 'blowing where it listeth.' ""' Or again, as one of the
. . .
participants, Wilhelm Stahlin, put it: "The new instinct that awoke, the
instinct of community, found its perfect realization in the bonds of friendship
within these small groups But without a leader, group action was
"'^
impossible: the idealized, inspired leader was the center, the uniting bond and
the activating element of each section of the movement.
It was a relationship of this kind that existed between the first
Wanden-ogel
and Karl Fischer, and it was the same relationship that united the
their leader,
members of the successive groups that made up the movements and those who
led them: "At a time when democracy is conquering the whole
world." wrote
one of the leaders, Robert Oelbermann. in 1922. "at a time when the masses
when the value of a person judged by his pocket-
think they can rule and is
"''
The mystical and erotic character of the bonds
youth movement
noted by
between the group's leader and his young followers, which has been
"Oh,
Bluher and others, incontestably reflects a deep emotional involvement:
my leader," writes a young man beset by sexual problems which seemed to
These
him irresolvable, "do not turn away from me. help me to be pure!""*
on the
young "rebels" were waiting for a savior, on the personal level and
collective one as well.
108 History and Psychoanalysis
movements of the first three decades of this century, were in fact the amplified
echo of the fears and aspirations of a large segment of German society or — at
least of German youth —
at the time. Antimaterialism, the loss of confidence in
the values of the bourgeois world, the determination to break out of the
authoritarian straitjacket of the family and the larger social institutions (even if
associated with the hierarchical framework both on the general and the
familial level, this falling-off being itself due to the intrusion of egalitarian
norms imposed by industrial society as well as to the incipient transformation
of the German middle-class family. In the framework of rural life or in the
world of small craftsmen, the authority of the father was that of someone who
was present at every hour of the day; in the framework of the new industrial
society, that authority belonged to a man who was absent more and more of
the time: it became more arbitrary, more blind, but more feeble as well.
Furthermore, the ease of access to education gave the sons a sudden advan-
tage over the fathers. Thus, the psychological foundations of revolt appear
evident.
Collective Phenomena 109
Before attempting to interpret them, let us recall the essential aspects of this
revolt: 1 ) young in an autonomous culture that emphasized the
isolation of the
particular values of youth (Jugendkultur); 2) an insistence on ascetic ideals
with a more or less strong homosexual coloration— in general, an idealized
homosexuality; 3) the cult of the peer group and a quasi-mystical submission
to the authority of the leader.
The isolation of the young
an autonomous culture appears as an obvious
in
form of rejection of the surrounding reality, and at the same time as an extreme
manifestation of the narcissistic regression that marks the normal develop-
ment of the adolescent. But in this case we can speak of a narcissistic fixation,
evidenced by exaggerated attitudes of self-admiration: the idealization of the
values of youth within an autonomous culture; the idealization of the
beauty of young bodies and of the physical environment of youth in the
But the asceticism of the youth movements has, I believe, yet another
chaos— and chaos meant death.'"' The symbol of chaos in The Cabinet ofDr.
Caligari is the carnival where Caligari hides out and from where Cesare sets
out to strangle his victims. Thus, the disaffection with the authoritarian
the
structure of the family and of society triggered revolt, but it also threatened
individual with fatal disintegration due to the chaotic irruption of instinctual
forces that a weakened superego could no longer contain. Against
this threat,
image of the members themselves; that in turn allowed them to face certain
real problems that the leader chose to bring up for discussion or to confront
directly.
3) A
compromise between asceticism and libidinal needs. The leader
helped the young men to turn their backs on debauchery and became himself
the object of the erotic desire of the members; these desires were then
sublimated, their energy placed at the service of the group.
We may note, finally, that two of the principal psychological traits we have
attributed to the members of the youth movements — latent homosexuality and
the fear of instinctual chaos, whence the need for discipline and order— are
characteristic traits of the "authoritarian personality," whose development is
"alienated" youth will adapt to the society around them; but the particular
way in which they live their youth remains significant: whereas at the
beginning of the century the opposition of the young led to ideology (even if
the ideology remained ill-defined) and to the desire to become involved in
some kind of struggle, today their opposition seems to be leading to indif-
ference, to personal disinvolvement. One could, of course, simply say that we
live in an era that has seen the "end of ideology,"'^' so that disengagement is,
for many people, the only logical stance possible. That may be so, but in that
case we have to ask whether this development is not also due to unconscious
causes, over and above the simple rejection of the idols of the past and the
obvious effects of a consumer society.
Kenneth Keniston has studied the psychological structure of "uncom-
mitted" students in several American universities during the 1960's. These
young people emerge as "rebels without a cause," incapable of defining the
positive values to which they are attached, searching for an uncertain
identity.'"^ Their case histories are marked by a very clear repetitive pattern:
strong attachment to the mother, whom they see as a victim, a woman who was
not able to realize all her potential; a scornful attitude toward the father, who
for the most part appears weak, incompetent, and always distant. The mother
is not considered responsible for her own failures in life; the father, on the
other hand, is.'"' In the psychoanalytic interviews and the projective tests
given to these young people the predominant themes are oral, which corres-
ponds to an attachment to the mother; but these oral themes are themes of
dependence and passivity in relation to women. This dependence can be
dangerous, for the fantasies that come up imply a struggle with the male rival;
although the outcome of the struggle is always victory for the young hero, it is
accompanied by guilt feelings and a profound fear of the conquered mother,
whose demands the young man
be unable to meet.'"*
will
One can ask whether these attitudes, however extreme they may be, are not
linked to a fundamental transformation of family structures in Western
society— specifically, to a change in the sex roles of the two parents. In the
German family at the beginning of the century, but also, to a somewhat lesser
extent perhaps, in the American family, the central role of the father was an
undisputed fact— this despite the reaction against various forms of authority
on the part of the young people of the period. Admittedly, the social evolution
that eventually led to the "disappearance" of the father had already begun, but
until the Second World War the father's central position was only shaken,
not
group allowed young men to submit to authority, but the particular nature of
the ego ideal he represented allowed for a remarkable compromise between
rebellion and submission.
The definitive displacement of the father from his central role can be
explained as the result of a clear sociological trend. As Alexander Mitscher-
lich has convincingly demonstrated, the father, who in traditional society was
constantly present and visible, a source of authority but also a living example,
has become more and more cut off from the family because of the demands of
professional advanced industrial societies.*"' In fact, one can distinguish
life in
three successive and distinct phases in this transformation: the phase of close
physical and cultural proximity between father and son, which is the phase
where paternal authority was accepted and assimilated in the context of a
continuous tradition and a feeling of reciprocity; the phase of physical and
professional distantiation between father and son, which manifested itself
more clearly during the second half of the nineteenth century than during the
first half, and in which the absence of reciprocity, of continuous exchange
between father and son gave rise to a seemingly arbitrary and distant authori-
tarianism as well as to the first signs of rebellion on the part of the sons, a
rebellion which became widespread at the beginning of the twentieth century;
finally, the third phase, which is the phase of the disappearance of the father:
he becomes, in his son's eyes, a ridiculous personage and the object of scorn
(since, as Keniston showed, he is so easily vanquished and displaced from his
position near the mother), a phenomenon that exists not only in America but
in the West in general.
The level of the history of mentalities is the level of the ordinary and the
automatic; it lies outside the control of the individual subjects of history because
it reveals the impersonal content of their thinking: what Caesar and the last
it is
of his soldiers, Saint Louis and his serf, Christopher Columbus and the sailor of
his fleet have in common. The history of mentalities is to the history of ideas
what the history of material culture is to economic history. The reaction of the.
men of the fourteenth century to the plague, that divine punishment, grows out of
the age-old, unconscious message of Christian thinkers from Saint Augustine to
Collective Phenomena 113
Saint Thomas Aquinas; it can be explained in terms of the equation
between
illness and formulated by the monks of the late Middle Ages, but it does
sin,
away with every kind of logical articulation, every subtle form of reasoning, and
keeps only the rough cast of the idea. Thus, the utensils of everyday life and the
clothing of the poor derive from prestigious models created by the surface
developments of the economy, of fashion and of taste. The style of a period lies
below that, on the deep level of ordinary Hfe."°
It is not surprising after this to learn that the word "mentality" is not listed in
United States, one could reply, is a special case, and the ethnic differences
that persist despite the pressure of the American "melting pot" suggest
precisely that it makes sense to study national character. Such is
not the
opinion of Riesman, however: "There are Jews who are very 'Irish'
114 History and Psychoanalysis
'The' Swedes were 'warlike' not so many generations ago; now they produce
peacemakers. 'The' EngUsh have gone through fantastic transformations from
EHzabethan times to the present. From Merrie England to the Cromwellian
sobersides, from eighteenth-century license to mid- Victorian rigidity, and
from this to mid-twentieth century 'spontaneous collectivism' these are —
immense shifts of the emotional center of life for miUions of people.""''
Important as it was at the time it was written because it tempered the —
excesses"* of the studies on national character Riesman's statement is —
nevertheless incorrect. The notion of national character or collective men-
tality does not imply stability over time: mentalities change, just as the
sociocultural contexts that underliethem change. As for the objection con-
cerning social divisions, Louis Dumont once remarked that "proletarians and
capitalists speak French in France, otherwise they couldn't confront their
ideas; in general, they have much more in common than they think, in
comparison to a Hindu, for example."'"
As a matter of fact, this common denominator is implicit in the very notion
of culture; there is a necessary link between the coherence of a social structure
(which can be the structure of a whole nation), the coherence of the culture
that expresses it, and the coherence of certain characteristics of the collective
mentality that is a manifestation of it. And since every society must confront
certain specific problems linked to the manner in which it adapts to general
human and natural limitations, as well as to specific human and natural
"a closed system of questions and
limitations, a culture will necessarily be
answers concerning the universe and human behavior."'^" A collective men-
tality corresponding to a given culture can be recognized as much by the kinds
of questions it asks as by the manner it formulates them and the answers it
gives to them. When Serge Moscovici tells us, with brilliant concision, that
"through every century there runs an essential questioning which mobilizes its
vital forces," and goes on to remark that "the eighteenth century can be said to
have been set in motion by the political question. the nineteenth century . . ,
emphasizes the social question [and] the two currents converge in our century
to raise the natural question, "'^' then one sees what is perhaps the common
denominator of modem Western culture. The "sub-questions" that result
from these great interrogative currents will be reflected in a collective
mentality on the level of this transnational culture, which is more vast even
than the culture of the Christian Middle Ages, but is no less real. Just as there
exists a hierarchy of social and culture contexts, so one must take into account
a hierarchy of essential questions and a hierarchy of traits in collective
mentalities.
Now questions and answers are formulated not only on the conscious level.
Every fundamental answer is expressed in symbolic terms, and the latter
to Study both the conscious level and the level of the unconscious foundations
of a culture or a collective mentality? And first of all, what documents can the
historian use?
We have already mentioned the variety and the polysemous character of
psychohistorical documentation, but it goes without saying that every subject
has own privileged sources. As concerns the study of mentalities, Lucien
its
characterize, over a very long timespan, a whole cultural area, such as the
"tarantism" that Ernesto Martino has so masterfully described and
De
analyzed. This rite not only illustrates the specific ritual context elaborated by
a culture in order to allow for the expression and, eventually, for the reinte-
gration of certain idiosyncratic psychic disorders, but also tells us a great deal
about the underlying mental characteristics of a Mediterranean culture which
experienced, and still experiences, the clash between Christianity and pagan
'^''
orgiastic cults.
Literary' 2^ and documents are an inexhaustible source for thematic
artistic
analysis, but it may be even more useful to study the characteristic forms (or
styles) of the art of a period, relating them to other essential currents in the
collective sensibility in order to discover their common underlying signi-
ficance. '^^ Finally, one must attempt to discover, through a study of its
historiography, the vision that a society has of itself and of the world. As
Alphonse Dupront has noted, "An inventory of the types of historical nostalgia
for an original past would provide us with an extraordinary document on
. . .
the ways the human imagination has conceived of the notion of return; it
would
also provide a rich psychic documentation on the modes of refusal to live in
116 History and Psychoanalysis
one's own time. The temporal horizon of a period and of a society is like a code
indicating its need for balance, its particular emotional resources, and its
awareness of its own existence. Societies with a long history and societies with
a short history constitute two general types of collective behavior toward the
past; the same is true of societies that live in the eternal — and naturally, in the
surging diversity of the human, of all the intermediary types in between."'^"
This enumeration of documentary sources, which is by no means exhaus-
tive, method of investigation.
brings us back to the essential question: the
One method, obviously, is simply to describe surface phenomena. Some of
the best historians have stopped at that level, Huizinga's The Waning of the
Middle Ages being a classic example.'^' Perhaps a purely descriptive stage is
necessary even if one aims for a more in-depth analysis, for it is description
alone that preserves the impalpable "je ne sais quoi" which characterizes the
phenomena of collective mentality. Even on this level, however, one must ask
the "unifying" questions and discover the "style" of the period, of the culture
or of the mentality one is studying: Huizinga, for example, speaks of the
"bittersweetness of and sees in that particular emotional contrast the
life,"
themselves.
The first of the two methods we ourselves are about to propose is somewhat
hazardous: it risks falling into the simplistic approach of studies on the basic
personality, even though the heterogeneous context makes such an approach
invalid.'" The method involves an analysis on three distinct levels: first, the
definition of the characteristics of the group's "modal personahty;" second,
the analysis of certain common elements in the primary institutions; third, an
interpretation of thedominant elements in the symbolic expressions of the
community. An attempt at synthesis would consist in interpreting the traits of
the modal personality as the consequence of typical emotional reactions
aroused by certain dominant elements in the group's network of symbolic
expressions, and possibly as the consequence of certain common character-
istics in the group's primary institutions.
The term "modal personality" is meant here in the sense proposed by
Inkeles and Levinson: "It appears unlikely that any specific personality
" ^
development (in the Eriksonian sense). '^^ We could perhaps add to this list the
typical attitudes toward existential situations such as love, illness, or death.
Emmanuel Le Roy Ladurie recently noted the fundamental differences
between the contemporary attitude of Western cultures toward death, and their
attitude two centuries ago. He also noted the widespread interest of European
historians in the phenomenon of death, even though nothing of the sort was
apparent in American historiography.^^^ Could that be the symptom of more
profound differences on the level of mentalities?
Whereas the comparison between contemporary mentalities is essentially
the work of anthropologists and sociologists, the historian will concern himself
above all with comparisons between periods in the past, either in the context of
a single culture or in different cultural contexts.
Parallel to the comparative study of manifest attitudes, the historian will
undertake a comparative study of social structures, as well as family struc-
tures and modes of childrearing, aiming once again to pinpoint significant
differences among groups.*^^ If it turns out that, over and above the differences
due to the social subdivisions within each heterogeneous group, certain child-
rearing practices existing on the level of a complex sociocultural entity can be
distinguished from the practices of other entities of the same kind, then one can
venture a hypothesis relating a given characteristic of the modal personality to
a given socio-familial context. At the same time, one must always be aware of
the influence of socialization processes outside the family, which may be of
decisive importance.*^*
The correlationsbetween the group's primary institutions and the char-
acteristics of the modal personality would be only a first step; it would
have to
be followed by an examination of how the dominant elements of the group's
symbolic system can in turn determine certain characteristics of the modal
personahty, even if the origins of the symbolic system itself remain unclear. /I
synthesis relating these three levels of investigation to each other would,
as
we mentioned earlier, constitute the most complete global analysis one could
undertake of the unconscious foundations of a "collective mentality,
'"
whether on the national or on some other level
personality to the
If the attempt to relate the characteristics of the modal
118 History and Psychoanalysis
overcome it. That was not their aim. They developed an ideology of ac-
ceptance and a philosophy of self-sacrifice which is not the most vital part of
their work, but which covers up and rationalizes their veritable motive: to
relive, in tears and terror, that incandescent moment of human life. They come
fearlessly close to Oedipus, but only in order to savor the experience. . . . They
use the Pantocrator and the Tsar, the cruel facts of serfdom and of the
patriarchal world, everything that is specific to their culture and their nation,
in order to play out a drama perpetually re-enacted by all of humanity. Their
works, so specifically rooted in a time and place, acquire thereby a universal
resonance. They did not change Russian history, but transmuted it into
song. ."'"2
. .
It was from this context, argues Besangon, that the Russian Revolution
derived its particular form: despite a certain development, the Revolution
Collective Phenomena 119
seems have encountered an obstacle, and its first phase, that of parricide,
to
was never surmounted; but in this instance, it is the Russian people who are
paying the debt, not the tyrant.''''
Alain Besangon obviously does not deny the possibility of interpreting
Russian culture in sociological terms, but he proposes another interpretation,
another meaning, independent of the sociological one: "I have taken special
care," he writes, "to separate the two levels: on the one hand, the level of
economic, and social history, which obeys its own laws; on the other,
political
running parallel to the first and accompanying it in counterpoint, this other
.""•''
history, marching to a different drummer. . .
Can we not say that we have just defined the problem of psychohistory
itself?
Conclusion
What, then, is the value of psychohistory? The preceding pages are full of
hesitations, warnings, expressions of approval immediately qualified by reser-
vations. It is time to pronounce a more definite conclusion.
We may give a general reply to the question by considering the term
"psychohistory" in its broadest theoretical sense, not as the current appli-
cation of psychoanalysis to history. If one defines psychohistory as the
utilization of psychological theories in history, without considering the present
state of these theories but rather their possible future development, whatever
that might be, then one can reply that the value of psychohistory is the same as
the value of a systematic explanation of human behavior applied to an under-
standing of the past. For those who do not reject a history of this kind, tending
toward generalizing explanations, psychohistory thus defined offers an un-
limited field of possibilities. In such a case, the reply about its value must be
positive, without qualification. But in fact, it is not with the abstract principle
of psychohistory that we are dealing here. Our question concerns the utili-
121
122 History and Psychoanalysis
been implicitly adduced throughout this book, but they must now be made
explicit. First of all, psychohistory throws a new light on traditional problems;
second, it makes possible the study of new problems; finally, it makes an
important contribution to the integration of various historical methods into a
global approach tending toward a total history.
For the reader of this book, the first reason I have mentioned should require
no demonstration. One can argue, to be sure, about the validity of psycho-
historical explanations, but it seems incontestable that, in the field of biog-
raphy as in that of collective behavior, psychohistory can approach traditional
subjects from a new perspective. We need but recall the hypotheses con-
cerning the structure of Wilson's personality and its influence on his political
behavior, or the relationship between childrearing practices and adult be-
havior in Plymouth Colony, or again the relationship between family structure
and the "need to achieve" in certain societies. We may also recall the demon-
stration of possible links between personality disorders and virulent anti-
Semitism and the significance of this phenomenon for the explanation of anti-
Semitism in general, or the possible psychohistorical explanation of witch-
hunts, or the explanation that psychohistory can provide for certain peer group
phenomena, or, finally, its explanation of the underlying significance of a
"collective mentality."
The second reason must not be confused with the first: here we are no
longer dealing with a new conception of traditional historical problems, but
rather, thanks to psychohistory itself, with the formulation of altogether new
questions. Thus, two recent new fields of inquiry probably owe their develop-
ment to the preoccupations of psychoanalysis: the history of childhood and of
the family, and the history of sexual mores. But have we not also suggested a
history of the authority relations between fathers and sons in a given society,
or a history of mental disorders or of collective neuroses? Could we not have a
more in-depth history of attitudes toward death? Can we not envisage, thanks
to psychohistory, the rehabilitation of biography and the systematic study of
types (either historical typology or the historical verification of empirically
derived types)? More and make
generally, doesn't psychohistory suggest
possible the comparative study of the psychological phenomena of the past?
The third reason, concerning the contribution of psychohistory to the
elaboration of a total history, introduces a wholly different dimension.
Throughout book we have above all insisted on the interdisciplinary
this
nature of history, on the possible modes of convergence between history,
sociology, and psychoanalysis. But this is only a step in the direction of an
even more encompassing historical inquiry: the complete investigation of an
individual or social phenomenon is, in eflect, possible only if the explicative
approach, the view from the outside — in other words, the approach of syste-
matic history — supplements and complements the intuitive approach, the
view from the inside. Systematic explanation must not replace intuition, it
must complete it. Only a dual approach of this kind can be called total history:
the understanding of a phenomenon both as a network of data accessible to
systematic inquiry a«^ as the existential, irreducible reality of a person or of a
123 Conclusion
valuable indeed, opening vast perspectives for future development and the
breaking of new ground. But there remains one last problem which bodes less
major portion of one's time to clinical work and be able to acquire, at the
same time, a solid historical background. It is thus up to historians who are
well informed about psychology in general and psychoanalysis in particular to
124 History and Psychoanalysis
historians who undertook and finished an analysis both for personal and for
professional reasons, the development of an intense "ideological" extremism.
This dilemma appears unresolvable, and only future works in psycho-
history will show whether certain historians are able to find the necessary
equilibrium between analytic experience and critical detachment. It is not
merely for the sake of paradox that I would suggest, in conclusion, that the real
difficulties of psychohistory do not reside only in the nature of the subject, in
the state of psychoanalysis, or in the problem of proofs and criteria for
verification; they are inherent in the ambiguous situation of the psycho-
historian.
.
Notes — Introduction
1. Lucien Febvre. Combats pour Vhistoire, p. 235 (Febrve's italics). (Unless otherwise
indicated, all translations from French works cited in this book are by Susan Suleiman.)
2. Frank E. Manuel, "The Use and Abuse of Psychology in History," Daedalus, no. 100
(winter 1971): 192. Along the same lines. Gaston Bachelard quotes Remy de Gourmont who
found that "as one reads the ."
Chants de Maldoror, consciousness slips away, slips away. . .
5. This is the distinction established by Leopold von Ranke: "The writing of history cannot
be expected to possess the same free development of its subject which, in theory at least, is
expected in a work of literature." (Quoted in Fritz Stem, The Varieties ofHistory from Voltaire
to the Present, p. 57.) The same distinction was particularly well made by Fred Weinstein and
Gerald M. Piatt in their article, "History and Theory: The Question of Psychoanalysis." The
Journal oflnterdisciplinar}' History 2, no. 4 (spring 1972). We cannot, however, invoke here the
psychoanalytic arguments used by Weinstein and Piatt, for that would be circular.
6. The notion of the unconscious, for example, is already to be found in antiquity, notably
in the Upanishad and in Greece. See on this subject L. L. Whyte, The Unconscious before Freud.
1. Jean Piaget, Epistemologie des sciences de I'homme, pp. 93ff.
Reichenbach, "Probability Methods in Social Science." in Daniel Lemer and Harold D. Lasswell,
The Policy Sciences: Recent Developments in Scope and Method.
10. Paul Veyne, Comment on ecrit Vhistoire. pp. 1 1 Iff., 203-205; for the phrase about
13. Abraham Kaplan, The Conduct of Inquiry: Methodology for Behavioral Sciences.
14. See in particular on this subject Raymond Aron. Introduction to the Philosophy of
History, p. 49; and Maurice Mandelbaum, The Problem of Historical Knowledge, pp. 64-66.
15. Among French specialists in psychohistory, one can mention the example of Alphonse
Dupront, who in the course of a few years evolved from a very "classical" position on the question
125
126 History and Psychoanalysis
16. William L. Langer, "The Next Assignment," in Bruce Mazlish, Psychoanalysis and
History, pp. 89-90.
1 7 See especially Lewis Namier, Personalities and Powers, as well as Lewis Namier and
John Brook, Charles Townshend. As for E. R. Dodds, his two chief works in this context are The
Greeks and the Irrational and Pagan and Christian in an Age ofAnxiety.
18. Gushing Strout, "Ego Psychology and the Historian," History and Theory, 7, no. 3
(1968), p. 281.
19. Alan Bullock, for example, recently declared that he found Erikson's book on Luther
less instructive than most of the other works he had read on the subject. Generally speaking, he
found the results obtained by the use of psychoanalysis in history disappointing, and only some
fruitful applications of the method in question would, according to him, confirm its validity
20. Jacques Barzun, "The Muse and Her Doctors," The American Historical Review 11,
no. 1(1972).
25. Garl E. Rogers, "Toward a Science of the Person," in T. W. Wann, Behaviorism and
Phenomenology: Contrasting Bases of Modern Psychology, p. 109.
26. For an excellent illustration of the possible overlapping between various psychological
theories, see Gardner Murphy, "Psychological Views of Personality and Contributions to Its
Study," in Edward Norbeck, Douglas Price-Williams, and William M. McCord. The Study of
Personality: An Interdisciplinary Appraisal, especially pp. 24ff. In fact, the problem of the
diversity of explicative theories is not unique to psychology. It also exists in economics, and
economic history is none the worse for it. Quoting Henri Guitton. Jean Bouvier writes that the
multitude of theories of economic crisis can "make one dizzy. . .
." At the same time, "all of the
theories (including Marxist ones) have allowed us to bring out some of the principal traits of
industrial-capitalist economic development. ." (Jean Bouvier. "Problematique des crises
. .
economiques du XIX^ siecle et analyses historiques: le cas de la France." in Jacques Le Goff and
Pierre Nora, Faire de l'histoire. II. Nouvelles approches, p. 27.
27. There exist currently several volumes of essays devoted to psychohistory. but with the
exception of Alain Besangon's. they are all. in our judgment, too heterogeneous. The reader will
nevertheless findsome useful insights in the following: Bruce Mazlish, Psychoanalysis and
History; Benjamin B. Wolfman, The Psychoanalytic Interpretation of History: Hans-Ulrich
Wehler, Geschichte und Psychoanalyse: Alain Besangon, Histoire et experience du moi The
volume by Alain Besangon. although it too is a collection of the author's previously published
articles, offers a coherent and brilliant demonstration of the possibilities of a psychoanalytic
reading of historical texts, as well as of the possibilities of a method of interpretation that can be
qualified as "psychoanalytic structuralism."
. )
examples as well. Their limited importance, however, is due to the fact that they are unrelated to
each other, that they explain only very limited phenomena, and that often they simply define more
cleariy ambiguous aspects of a phenomenon that is already understood. We may note that
H. Stuart Hughes, who is among those contemporary historians most interested in the possible
application of the social sciences to history, reached the same negative conclusions concerning
experimental psychology, although for slightly different reasons (see H. Stuart Hughes, "The
Historian and the Social Scxtniisi" American Historical Review 66, no. 3 ( 1 960]: 34).
2. Robert Coles, "How Good is Psychohistory?" The New York Review of Books.
March 8, 1973.
3 On the relation between Piaget's theories and psychoanalysis, see the very detailed study
by P. Wolff, "The Developmental Psychology of Jean Piaget and Psychoanalysis," Psycho-
logical Issues, 1960.
4. The validity of these criteria was "confirmed" when I discovered that they corres-
ponded almost exactly word for word to the criteria formulated by the historian Robert F.
Berkhofer, who was attempting to define the conditions for the application of the behavioral
sciences to history. (See Robert F. Berkhofer, Behavioral Approach to Historical Analysis.
5. Sheldon's theories, like those of Le Senne. can nevertheless provide secondary confir-
mations, and sometimes they throw light on certain characteristics that psychoanalysis, for
example, hardly treats at all. Thus Anthony Storr's psychoanalytic interpretation of Churchill's
personality is also based on some of Sheldon's concepts. (See Anthony Storr, "The Man," in
A. J. P. Taylor et al., Churchill Revised: A Critical Assessment, p. 236.) Generally speaking, the
traits are as old
attempts to establish a correlation between bodily characteristics and personality
127
128 History and Psychoanalysis
as psychology itself. Having mentioned the American Sheldon and the Frenchman Le Senne, we
must in the interest of fairness mention the German Ernst Kretschmer, whose best known work is
Kbrperbau und Charakter (Body Structure and Character).
6. The necessary convergence of the most diverse disciplines and methods in the syste-
matic study of the personality is cogently argued in Edward Norbeck, Douglas Price-Williams,
and William M. McCord, The Study ofPersonality.
7. One would like to have Sartre in one's camp in this enterprise, and yet. . . . When he tells
example, that Baudelaire, at the age of six (my italics), finding himself alone and rejected
us, for
upon the remarriage of his beloved mother, instead of "passively supporting" his isolation,
"embraced it with fury and, since he was condemned to it hoped that at any rate his
. . .
condemnation was final," we cannot but wonder at the precociousness of the boy; the same is true
when we are told that "this brings us to the point at which Baudelaire chose the sort of person he
—
would be that irrevocable choice by which each of us decides in a particular situation what he
will be and what he is. ."{Jean-Paul Sartre, Baudelaire, trans. Martin Tumell, p. 18). And what
. .
would have happened if Caroline Baudelaire had gotten remarried when young Charles was only
two years old? He could not, in that case, have consciously assumed his destiny, but is it certain
that he would not have reacted? We know that very young children who experience powerful emo-
tional frustrations fall ill and sometimes die. We also know that an "abandonment" of the kind
—
experienced by Baudelaire if it takes place at the age of two or three years— often provokes
immediate somatic reactions and can subsequently leave neurotic traces that last a lifetime. The
rejection of unconscious processes leads Sartre to elaborate developmental schemata that are
empirically indefensible, at least from our point of view.
9. Hans Meyerhoff, "On Psychoanalysis and History," Psychoanalysis and the Psycho-
analytic Review 49, no. 2 ( 1 962), p. 5. For a more systematic study of the "historical" character
of psychoanalytic therapy, see Samuel Novey, The Second Look: The Reconstruction of
Personal History in Psychiatry and Psychoanalysis.
10. Philip Rieff, "The Meaning of History and Religion in Freud's Thought," in Bruce
Mazlish, Psychoanalysis and History, p. 25. The "historical" conception of psychoanalysis is
not accepted by everyone, however; Page Smith, for example, has noted the repetitive character of
the Freudian interpretation of certain collective phenomena (77?e Historian and History, p. 1 28).
But this criticism confuses Freud's metahistorical theories, which can easily be rejected without
any repercussions for psychoanalytic theory, with the use of psychoanalytic theory itself in
historical explanation on the individual or collective level. Smith has also argued that the notion of
Oedipal conflict is ahistorical, for it implies a break between father and son, whereas history is
founded on the transmission of values from father to son {The Historian and History, p. 130).
This strange argument shows that the ignorance of historians in matters of psychoanalysis is at
least as great as the ignorance of psychoanalysts in matters of history. The fact is that the
resolution of the Oedipal conflict leads to the formation of the superego, which is precisely the
internalization of paternal values by the son.
Admittedly, other historians, much more knowledgeable about psychoanalysis, have pointed
out the ahistorical character of the interpretation of a specific situation by reference to an
unvarying Oedipal conflict that would somehow exist outside of time (Carl E. Schorske,
"Politique et parricide dans I'lnterpretation des reves de Freud," Annates ESC 28 [March-
April, 1 977], p. 328). The Oedipus complex can, in itself, be considered as an invariable psychic
conflict, but there are as many ways of experiencing it as there are individuals. A different analysis
of the dreams in The Interpretation of Dreams would have allowed Schorske to perceive the
specific, historical character of this vision of the conflict between father and son in Freud himself
11. I am assuming here that the reader is familiar with the essential principles of the
psychoanalytic theory of the personality, or if not that he can familiarize himself with them by
consulting one of the many works available on the subject. For a very complete description of the
principal schools of thought that dominate contemporary psychoanalysis, see Ruth L. Munroe,
Schools of Psychoanalytic Thought. Orthodox Freudian theory is well presented in a large
number of textbooks, to wit: Charles Brenner, An Elementary Textbook of Psychoanalysis;
Notes— Chapter One 129
13. Anatol Rapoport, "Various Meanings of Theory," The American Political Science
Review 52, no. 4 (1958), p. 982.
14. The number of publications devoted to this subject is immense; I shall of necessity
mention only the most important arguments, giving a minimum of references.
15. Cf. Philip E. Vernon, Personality Assessment, p. 121.
17. This is in fact the opinion of a great many psychoanalysts, including Ernst Kris,
Lawrence Kublie, Gittelson and others. See Bjom Christiansen, "The Scientific Status of
Psychoanalytic Clinical Evidence," Inquiry, no. 7 ( 1 964): 64.
18. Michael Martin, "The Scientific Status of Psychoanalytic Evidence," Inquiry, no. 7
(1964): 32.
19. Ibid., p. 24.
22. Paul E. Meehl, Clinical versus Statistical Prediction: A Theoretical Analysis and a
Review ofEvidence.
23. See in particular McKeachie and C. L. Doyle, Psychology, p. 448, and Harrison H.
Gough, "Clinical versus Statistical Prediction in Psychology," in Leo Postman, Psychology in
theMaking, p. 576.
24. The number of publications on this subject is considerable. For a relatively old but very
systematic evaluation of experimental studies of psychoanalytic concepts, see Robert R. Sears,
Survey of Objective Studies ofPsychoanalytic Concepts; for a study that tends more toward the
justification of psychoanalysis on these grounds, see E. Pumpian-Mindlin, Psychoanalysis as
Science. For a very recent synthesis, see Ernest L. Hilgard, "Psychoanalysis: experimental
studies"; see also GermaldBlum, Psychodynamics: The Science of Unconscious Mental
S.
Forces, pp. 25ff.; Philip E. Vernon, Personality Assessment, p. 92; and especially I. Samoff,
Testing Freudian Concepts: An Experimental Social Approach.
25. worth mentioning, however, that over the past few years some quasi-experimental
It is
studies on young children, and especially in ethology, "have gradually confirmed some analytic
theories that seemed to be purely speculative" (Anthony Storr, Human Destructiveness, p. 78;
see also I. Samoff, Testing Freudian Concepts).
26. Robert Waelder, Basic Theory ofPsychoanalysis, p. 1 9.
29. Saul E. Harrison, "Is Psychoanalysis 'Our Science'? Reflections on the Scientific
Status of Psychoanalysis," Journal of the American Psychoanalytic Association 18 (1970),
p. 132.
3 1 Certain psychoanalysts have attempted to bypass the whole problem of the scientific
status of psychoanalysis, by proposing a "semantic theory" of psychoanalysis: the patient's
symptoms and various aspects of his behavior are not "caused" by such and such an event or by a
past situation, but rather they constitute a language that the patient creates but does not
understand; it is the analyst's task to interpret this language, to say clearly what the patient says, as
it were, in code. (See especially, on this subject, Charles RycToft,Psychoanalysis Observed.) The
problem of causality, of explanatory theory, seems thus to be surmounted; but it is surmounted in
appearance only, for the psychoanalyst cannot decipher the patient's language without referring,
explicitly or implicitly, to a theoretical system that will provide him with the key to the code. This
theoretical system brings us right back to the problem of the scientific verification of psycho-
analytic propositions.
32. The basic concepts of ego psychology are discussed in most general works on
psychoanalysis (see note For more complete theoretical discussions, see the following
1 1 above).
classic works: Anna Freud, The Ego and the Mechanisms of Defense; Erik H. Erikson,
Childhood and Society. Heinz Hartmarm, Ego Psychology and Problems ofAdaptation; and, by
the same author. Essays on Ego Psychology: Selected Problems in Psychoanalytic Theory.
35. Ludwig Binswanger's study on "the case of Ellen West" is justly famous. It is perhaps
the best example of the possible contribution of existential analysis to psychohistory. (See Ludwig
Binswanger, "The Case of Ellen West: An Anthropological-Clinical Study," in Rollo May et al.,
Existence: A New Dimension in Psychiatry and Psychology. ) The major difficulty of existential
analysis remains, however, unchanged: such analysis falls easily into vagueness, imprecision, and
purely intuitive procedures. If one had to point to an equivalent of this kind of analysis in France
one that exhibited both its strongest and its weakest points— the name that would most readily
come to mind is that of Minkowski.
37. Georges Devereux would doubtless disagree with this point: in his From Anxiety to
Method in the Behavioral Sciences, he discovers the distorting effects of unconscious counter-
transference even in the relation between the experimental scientist and his subject. Devereux is
right in theory, but in practice this kind of countertransferential distortion is often so minimal that
we can speak of objective analysis.
article, "On the Nature of Psychohistorical Evidence: In Search of Gandhi," Daedalus, no. 97
(summer 1968), p. 713.
42. Milton Singer, "A Survey of Culture and Personality Theory and Research," in Bert
Kaplan, Studying Personality Cross-Culturally, p. 19. Concerning mental disturbances,
Georges Devereux has convincingly shown that, even if every culture has its own way of
expressing deviant behavior, the distinctions between normal and abnormal derive from universal
criteria. (See Georges DevcTeux.Essais d'ethnopsychiatrie generate. )
43. Anne Parsons, "Is the Oedipus Complex Universal?" in Werner Muensterberger and
Sidney Axelrad, The Psychoanalytic Study of Society.
44. Bronislaw Malinowski, Sex and Repression in Savage Society.
45. The Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund Freud,
published by James Strachey (with the collaboration of Anna Freud), vol. XI, pp. 63fF. (All
subsequent references to this edition will be indicated as SE).
. . . .
46. This was a common practice without any particular individual significance, unless one
can show the existence of thematic repetition in the unfinished works, in opposition to the finished
ones. Freud made no comparative analysis of this kind. Dominique Fernandez, on the other hand,
arrives at some interesting results along these lines in his study of Michelangelo. See his I'Arbre
jusqu'aux racines: Psychanalyse et Creation, pp. 140-141.
47. Abraham Kaplan, The Conduct ofInquiry, p. 3 1 4.
48. Jean Laplanche and J.-B. Pontalis, The Language of Psychoanalysis, trans. Donald
Nicholson-Smith, p. 292.
49. Ibid.
51. Fritz Schmidl, "Psychoanalysis and History," Psychoanalytic Quarterly 31, no. 4
(1962), p. 539.
52. Alexander L. George and Juliette L. George, IVoodrow Wilson and Colonel House: A
Personality Study.
53. Arthur S. Link, Woodrow Wilson, vol. 1 , The Road to the White House, pp. 90-9 1
54. For an interesting example of a repetitive structure of behavior, as well as a brief
discussion of the methodological questions implied by the use of this type of psychohistorical
proof, see Richard L. Bushman's article on Benjamin Franklin: "On the Uses of Psychology:
Conflict and Conciliation in Benjamin Franklin," History and Theory 6, no. 1 (1966).
55. See especially Alfred L. Baldwin, "Personal Structure Analysis: A Statistical Method
for Investigating the Single Personality," Journal of Abnormal and Social Psychology 37
(1942).
56. The methodology in question is too technical and too varied to be discussed here. The
interested reader will find examples of the various approaches in George Gerbner et al.. The
Analysis of Communication Content. The difficulty, ft-om our point of view, is that the analysis of
content or the analysis of the logical structures of individual communication cannot be univocally
correlated with a particular type of personality.
57. Marrou, The Meaning of History; p. 81. Obviously, it is the traditional type of
H.-I.
personal documents— letters, diaries, etc.— that form the bulk of the documents to be used by the
psychohistorian, especially in the domain of biography and typology. The use of such documents
has always been considered and one would do well to consult the study by Lx)uis
difficult,
Gottschalk, Clyde Kluckhobi, Robert Angell, The Use of Personal Documents in History,
Anthropology and Sociology. Even more important from our point of view is the study by Gordon
W. Allport, The Use ofPersonal Documents in Psychological Science.
Nietzsche's Wayward Disciple, p. 6). We will return to this problem in the next chapter.
66. Dominique Arban, Dostoievski par lui-m'eme. p. 22. The interpretation of literary
documents becomes even more uncertain when one is dealing with texts that are on the surface
theories. The
"revelatory," but that were written by writers familiar with psychoanalytic
in a sense
interpretation of Kaflca's work, for example, in terms of a father-son conflict
is
132 History and Psychoanalysis
obligatory; Do5 Urteil (The Judgment) occupies a central place in this kind of interpretation, and
is often cited. Kafka himself, however wrote in his. Diaries, precisely about Z)as Urteil: "Many
emotions carried along in the writing, joy, for example, that I shall have something beautiful for
yidCiCsArkadia, thoughts about Freud, of course . .
." vol. 1 p. 276.
,
67. This uncertainty is increased further by the fact that the symbolic significance of the
mare cannot be proven, except by the similarity in structure between the signifying sequence and
the signified sequence. Contrary to the position advanced by The Interpretation of
Freud in
Dreams, I believe that there is no fixed relation between a given symbol and a specific
unconscious configuration. The choice of symbols is always subjective, and therefore itself subject
to interpretation. This variable and purely subjective relation between signifier and signified
eliminates certain recent arguments against psychoanalytic interpretation, notably those de-
veloped by Dan Sperber in his book. Rethinking Symbolism.
68. On this subject, seeBruceMazlish, "Clio on the Couch," f^cou/zrer 31, no. 3 (1968).
69. Thus Durkheim relates a high suicide rate to the absence of religion, bachelorhood, or
living in an urban environment; he establishes, in other words, a correlation between the tendency
to suicide and cohesion, or the degree of the individual's social integration. But, as Jean
Maisonneuve notes, "does this give us an explanation of suicide? No, for we must still under-
stand ... the psychological mechanisms whereby cohesion or the absence of cohesion restrain
one from, or push one to, suicide." (Jean Maisonneuve, Introduction a la psychosociologie,
p. 10.) See also, on this subject, the article by Alex Inkeles, "Personality and Social Structure," in
75. Neil J. Smelser, Essays in Sociological Explanation: and Robert S. Wallerstein and
NeilJ. Smelser, "Psychoanalysis and Sociology: Articulations and Applications," International
Journal ofPsycho-analysis 50 ( 1 969).
76. Wallerstein and Smelser, "Psychoanalysis and Sociology." p. 694.
77. Much has been written about the way Freud interpreted the past and envisaged history.
We shall mention only those points that are immediately relevant to our discussion; for a more
general treatment, see Paul Ricoeur, Freud and Philosophy, and Philip RiefT. Freud, the Mind of
the Moralist. It is Alain Besangon. however, who offers the best introduction to the subject in the
first chapter of his book, Histoire et experience du moi.
82. See especially, on this subject, Gerard Mendel, La Revolte contre le pere. pp. 15fF..
pp. 144ff.
83. Gerard Mendel. La Crise des generations, p. 57. The same hypothesis is convincingly
presented by Georges Devereux in hisEssais d'ethnopsychiatrie generate, especially pp. 143ff.,
and p. 160.
84. See Roger Dadoun. Geza Roheim et I'essorde I'anthropologiepsychanalytique, p. 48.
87. Norman O. Brown. Life against Death, pp. 292ff. The reader will find dozens of
similar examples, applied to every conceivable field, in Robert Bastide, Sociologie et
Psychanalyse.
Notes— Chapter One 133
88. Hanns Sachs, "The Delay of the Machine Age," P.yvc/ioo«a/>7/c 5«or/er/v 4 no 2
(1933):404ff.
89. Kurt R. Eissler, Medical Orthodoxy and the Future ofPsychoanalysis, pp. 230fT. It is
amusing to see Eissler's simplemindedness on this point criticized, in the name of historical rigor,
by another psychoanalyst, Robert Waelder, who then turns around and explains (in the name
of the same historical rigor, no doubt) the collapse of Austrian allegiance to the imperial institution
in terms of a "castration complex." See Robert Waelder, "Psychoanalysis and History:
Application of Psychoanalysis to Historiography," in Benjamin B. Wolman, The Psycho-
analytic Interpretation ofHistory, pp. 4, 24.
91. Talcott Parsons, "Psychoanalysis and the Social Structure," Psychoanalytic Quar-
terly 19, no. 3 (1950), pp. 312-315.
92. The structuralist paradigm of psychohistorical explanation has few adherents at
present, and as far as know the only studies attempting to develop this mode of inquiry are those
I
published in France. The works of Alain Besangon represent, in this respect, the most complete
statement of a conception that one also finds, on a more restricted level, in the work of other
French psychoanalysts. Despite its limited field of application, this model of psychohistorical
explanation seems sufficiently original and coherent to be considered as a separate category.
95. See, for example, the definition of structure according to Piaget: "Le probleme de
I'explication," in Leo Apostel et al., L 'Explication dans les sciences, p. 9.
96. See in particular the criticisms formulated by Edmund Leach, in his book, Levi-
Strauss. Leach himself is a convinced structuralist, but his analysis of various Biblical texts,
although brilliant, does not altogether dispel one's doubts about the structuralist method. (See
Edmund Leach, Genesis as Myth and Other Essays. )
97. The difference between formal structures and thematic configurations, or even config-
urations of object relations, represents all the difference between structuralism 5mc/« sensu and
psychoanalytic structuralism. It is obvious, contrary to the thesis advanced by Janine Chasseguet-
Smirgel, that a given configuration of any individual's object relations is understandable only in
terms of content. As
concerns the similarities and differences between Freud and Levi-Strauss in
their conception of the unconscious, see especially Ino Rossi, "The Unconscious in the Anthro-
pology of Claude Levi-Strauss," American Anthropologist 25 (1973).
98. It is we proposed some definitions: 1 ) A society is a group of individuals (a
high time
group of variable whose members have established mutual relations that differentiate them
size),
in some way from those not belonging to that society; generally, what is distinctive about a society
is the elaboration or the assimilation of a specific culture. 2) A culture corresponds, here, to the
set of representationsand symbolic expressions (language, institutions, norms, art, religious and
philosophical system, etc.) of a society. (The definitions of culture are, of course, legion.) 3) The
term "collective behavior" designates two different types of behavior: on the one hand, the
behavior of the members of a group, conscious of belonging to that group and acting according to
certain common perceptions and goals; on the other hand, the behavior of individuals who have
thesame perceptions and act in similar ways, without necessarily identifying themselves as
members of the same group. It goes without saying that, in both cases, the conscious perceptions
and goals can also have an unconscious meaning. Thus, in the broadest sense, it is a certain unity
in perceptions, behavior and goals among a small or large number of individuals that allows us to
speak of "collective behavior."
99. This term, current in American sociology, will be explained in chapter 3.
1(X). The relation between culture and personality has become a vast field of research, a
good part of which has nothing to do with psychoanalytic theory. Milton Singer's article, "A
Survey of Culture and Personality Theory and Research," contains an excellent summary of the
various kinds of research in this field.
134 History and Psychoanalysis
101 The aim of this formulation, as of the pages that follow, is to allow for a synthesis (a
rather unusual one) between the conceptions of Erik H. Erikson and those of Abram Kardiner and
Ralph Linton. For Erikson's theses on this point, see especially Childhood and Society; for the
theories of Kardinerand Linton, see their two works: The Individual and His Society and The
Psychological Frontiers of Society.
I am aware of the considerable differences between Erikson's notions and those of
perfectly
Kardiner, as well as of the fact that Erikson can be considered as part of the mainstream of
psychoanalytic thought, while Kardiner is always characterized as a neo-Freudian. Yet, in the
perspective of our paradigm, the inherent logic of their analyses is almost identical.
102. Mike! Dufrenne, La personnalite de base, p. 1 28. We may recall that in France the
importance of studies on the basic personality as a unifying ground between psychoanalysis and
sociology was already noted in the 1 950s by Roger Bastide (cf. his Sociologie etpsychanalyse).
107. John Bowlby, "The Nature of the Child's Tie to Its Mother," IntemationalJoumal
ofPsycho-analysis 39 (1958).
108. See Talcott Parsons, Social Structure and Personality. As concerns the relation
between social structure and the specific activity of the id, one can cite some studies on dreams in
various societies: it is not only the manifest content of these dreams that varies from society to
society, but— insofar as the kind of classical analysis that can be used is correct— their latent
content as well. It has been noted, for example, that Americans and Japanese suffer from
different anxieties, manifesting themselves differently on the level of dreams— hence on the level
of primary processes of the id. See R. Burke, "Histoire sociale des reves," Annales ESC 28
(March-April 1973): 332.
As ego by means of successive internalizations of idealized objects,
for the formation of the
notably of the idealized characteristics of the parents, Heinz Kohut's recent studies on narcissim
confirm the essential character of this process. See especially Kohut's The Analysis of the Self A
Systematic Approach to the Psychoanalytic Treatment ofNarcissistic Personality Disorders.
109. Fred Weinstein and Gerald M. Piatt, Psychoanalytic Sociology: An Essay on the
111. The paradigm I shall propose here is inspired only in part by the one that Fred
Weinstein and Gerald M. Piatt presented The Wish
to be Free: Society, Psyche and Value
in
Change, and in Psychoanalytic Sociology. Their conception taken as a whole seems in effect very
much open to doubt. In our perspective, the id remains, on the whole, an area inaccessible to the
process of internalization, whereas in Weinstein's and Piatt's second book (Psychoanalytic
Sociology) the generalized character of processes of internalization ata// levels of the personality
practically eliminates the need for a psychoanalytic study of social change.
112. I use the general term "affective needs" for the sake of convenience; it is evident that
we are dealing here with the result of complex interactions implying, in particular, various com-
promises between the instinctual tendencies and the demands of the superego and the ego of the
members of the group.
1 16. One finds this notion expressed, in one form or another, in a great many articles.
Among the latter, we may cite: Ernest Hartmann, "The Psychophysiology of Free Will: An
Example of Vertical Research," in Rudolph M. Loewenstein et al.. Psychoanalysis as a General
Psychology, pp. 52 Iff.; John Hospers, "Free Will and Psychoanalysis," in W. Sellers and
J.Hospers, Readings in Ethical Theory, pp. 560ff.; Samuel D. Lipton, "A Note on the
Compatibility of Psychic Determinism and Freedom of Will," InternationalJoumal of Psycho-
analysis 36, no. 2 ( 1 95 5 ).
117. Erik H. Erikson, Identity, Youth and Crisis, p. 109.
119. Merton Gill and G. S. Klein, The Collected Papers of David Rapaport, pp. 22-23.
120. Ibid., pp. 352, 294, 830. An ahnost identical notion is convincingly expressed by
1 See Herman Nunberg and Ernst Fedem, Minutes of the Vienna Psychoanalytic
Society. I.1906-1908; II. 1908-1910
2. Sigmund Freud, "Leonardo da Vinci and a Memory of His Childhood," SE, vol. 1 1 A .
few years later Freud devoted a very brief psychobiographical study to Dostoevsky: "Dostoevsky
and Parricide," SE, vol. 21. The very first psychobiographical interpretation made by Freud
came well before these two essays, however; it was in a letter to Fliess, June 20, 1898, in which
Freud spoke about the novelist Konrad Fredinand Meyer. (See Sigmund Freud, The Origins of
Psychoanalysis: Letters to Wilhelm Fliess, Drafts and Notes, pp. 256-257.)
3. Sigmund Freud and William C. Bullitt, Thomas Woodrow Wilson, Twenty-Eighth
President of the United States: A Psychological Study.
4. Psychobiographies of all sizes come by the hundreds; the fact that most of these
literally
studies are now forgotten is no reflection on psychohistory Readers with a collector's or archivist's
.
bent will find some of the titles of psychobiographies published during the First World War and
the 1920's interesting. (See John A. Garraty, The Nature ofBiography, pp. 1 Many
15ff., 230ff.)
historians (see J. H. Plumb. "The Wolfs Clothing," The New York Review of Books. Dec. 14,
1972).
136
..
8. Sibylle K. Escalona and Grace Heider, Prediction and Outcome: A Study in Child
Development, p. 9. This fundamental continuity found in every individual manifests itself
particularly strikingly in personalities that have experienced "conversion." It was Lucien
—
Goldmann who, as we shall see, cannot be accused of a bias in favor of biographical studies—
who gave an excellent demonstration of the unity of Pascal's quest, for example, despite Pascal's
famous conversion (see Lucien Goldmann, The Hidden God). From our point of view, the
continuity is not only that of form and style, but is expressed through essential characteristics and
tendencies of the personality.
9. The most recent study on this subject is David Shapiro's Neurotic Styles.
12. Gertrud M. Kurth, "The Jew and Adolf Hitler," in Sandor Lorand, The Yearbook of
Psychoanalysis 4 ( 1 949), pp. 266ff.
13. Georges Devereux, "La psychanalyse appliquee al'histoirede Sp&Tte,'' Annates ESC
(Jan.-Feb. 1965), p. 29.
15. Rudolph Binion, "Research Note," Newsletter: Group for the Use of Psychology in
will not mention the numerous factual errors, and above all the unfounded suppositions contained
in Langer's work; these are for the most part attributable to the early date ofits writing. For a
critique of Langer see Hans W. Gatzke, "Hitler and Psychohistory," American Historical
Review 18,no. 4 (1913).
17. According to many historians, however, this decision was made in March or April
1941.
18. Robert C. L. Waite. "Adolf Hitler's Antisemitism," in Benjamin B. Wolman. The
Psychoanalytic Interpretation ofHistory, pp. 203ff.
1 9. Saul Friedlander, L 'Antisemitisme nazi: Histoire d'une psychose collective, pp. 1 33ff.
20. This is also the age at which some future political leaders compose plays and poems,
whose importance for psychobiography is evident— as is amply shown by Saint-Just's Organt or
De Gaulle's Une Mauvaise rencontre.
21. "A problem, once suggested, carries its own impetus," writes a biographer of
Nietzsche, "and the thinker is driven on by it to new problems and solutions. To understand these,
we must follow the development of his thought— and that is best done separately from the survey
of his any joint treatment will almost inevitably suggest a false notion of causal relationship
life, as
between life and philosophy." (Walter Kaufmann, Nietzsche, Philosopher, Psychologist. Anti-
christ, p. 21.) The dichotomy between life and work is too sharply drawn, but Kaufmann makes
clear the nature of the indeterminacy that the biographer must confront.
23. See on this subject the excellent biography by Quentin Bell: Virginia Woolf(2 vols.).
26. Lord Moran, Winston Churchill: The Struggle for Surx'ival, 1940-1965.
27. Edwin A. Weinstein, " Woodrow Wilson's Neurological Illness," Journal of Ameri-
can History 57 (1970-1971).
28. Edwin A. Weinstein, "Woodrow Wilson's Neurological Illness."
Serge Doubrovsky, The New Criticism in France, trans. Derek Coltman. p. 94.
3 1
see the
32. For a more complete picture of the various currents of "la nouvelle critique."
138 History' and Psychoanalysis
excellent volume containing the proceedings of the Cerisy colloquium, Les Chemins actuels de la
critique.
Vermeer's finest interiors. Although one may use works of art to illustrate the history of
. . .
civilization, one must not pretend that social conditions produce works of art or inevitably
influence their form." (Kenneth Clark, Civilization: A Personal View, p. 213.)
38. Janine Chasseguet-Smirgel, Pour une psychanalyse de I'art et de la creativite, pp. 44-
46. 60-62. The same thesis is stated, among others, by Yvon Beleval in his preface to the study by
Anne CldLTicieT, Psychanalyse et Critique litteraire, p. 19.
39. Kofman, L 'Enfance de I'art, p. 1 27.
40. Chasseguet-Smirgel, Pour une psychanalyse de I'art, p. 62. One finds this necessary
synthesis between the structuralist and genetic methods in biography in the most unexpected
places. Thus, in his inaugural speech at the Academic Frangaise, Claude Levi-Strauss. paying
homage to his predecessor, Henry de Montherlant, began with a structural analysis of Monther-
lant's works — an analysis that led, according to him, to an evident conclusion whose "internal
logic" manifested itself in "the need to short-circuit the mediation of the mother: the carnal act,
performed either actually or figuratively, results in a metaphoric or actual death. And life,
understood in this metaphoric or actual sense, can result only from a renunciation of the carnal
act, either actually or figuratively."
Levi-Strauss then turned to a direct thematic analysis, taking into account the biographical
origins of the work: "The plot ofLo Peine morte (The Dead Queen) lays bare. I believe, this well-
spring of my predecessor's thought. To the question 'Who
dead Queen?' few spectators
is the
would hesitate to reply: Ines de Castro. Is she not seen, after all, at the end of the last act, dead and
wearing a crown? Yet, during the play itself the words of the title appear only once, and they refer
to another woman: the dead wife of Ferrante, who says to his son: 'From the time you were five
years old to when you were thirteen, I loved you tenderly. The Queen, your mother, died very
young.' The ambiguity here is more than a matter of chance. Pedro, therefore, is a son without a
mother, like Philippe in Les Jeunes Filles and Alcacer in Don Juan, like the son that Alban
invents for himself at the end of Z,e Songe or the one to whom is addressed the Lettre d'un pere
{Letter from a Father), or the one who engages in a dialogue with the stranger of L 'Equinoxe de
septembre; just as Celestino's daughter is a daughter without a mother, her mother having "died in
giving her birth.' But. unlike the author, who. as is well known, always rejected marriage. Pedro
succeeds in replacing his mother, who died while he was a baby, by a wife: Ines, who, as if to
confirm this continuity, becomes in turn the dead Queen. She must die, in fact, not only in order to
reproduce the Queen mother, whom she replaces (we must not forget her belly, which alone bears
the crown), but also and above all because the author, even more than Ferrante. wants to eliminate
the solution chosen by Pedro —a solution he rejects, to a problem that is also his own. . .
."
creativite.
.. .
51. Marie 'Qona^arie, Edgar Poe, sa vie, son oeuvre, Etude analytique, pp. 763-764.
Other scholars have arrived at similar conclusions. Thus, Leopold Bellak establishes a dis-
tinction between writers who constantly treat the same story in various forms (extreme subjec-
tivity) and those who are able to express several themes (see Leopold Bellak, "Somerset
Maugham: A Thematic Analysis of Ten Short Stories," in Robert W. White, The Study ofLives.
p. 157.) When, in the case of a writer with a single theme, the theme is very often reworked, the
historian can attempt to capture its essence by using the method of the superposition of texts
advocated by Charles Mauron. For a very clear summary of Mauron's method, see his essay,
"Les origines d'un mythe personnel chez Tecrivain," in Critique sociologique et Critique
psychanalytique, pp. 9 Iff. For a systematic and detailed demonstration of the method, see
Mauron's book, Des metaphores obsedantes au mythe personnel: Introduction a la psycho-
critique.
53. In certain cases, which are by definition rare, the fundamental problem is so particular
that it is possible to determine rather exactly its influence on the level of the work. Thus, Marc
Soriano has admirably demonstrated, in the life and works of Charles Perrault, the importance of
Perrault's having been a twin. See Marc Soriano, Les Contes de Perrault, Culture savante et
Traditions populaires.
60. Preface by Jean-Frangois Lyotard to Anton Ehrenzweig, I'Ordre cache de I'art: Essai
sur la psychologic de I'imagination artist ique. p. 2.
psychanalvse.
62. Ismond Rosen, "Etude psychanalytique de la sculpture," in Entretiens sur I'art et la
psychanalyse.
63. Anton Ehrenzweig, I'Ordre cache de I'art, p. 109.
64. We may add that, although Ehrenzweig's work is impressive by its originality, it
nevertheless raises some theoretical problems that it does not resolve. Even if one admits the
validity of his conception of the primary processes, one soon notices that his thesis, which is easily
demonstrated in the case of modem painting, sculpture, and music, is less convincing in the case of
"classical" music (despite a few examples) and applies barely if at all to literature (with the
possible exception of the nouveau roman). Furthermore. Ehrenzweig does not quite succeed
in
explaining how. according to his system, "normal" artistic creation differs from the production of
schizophrenics. Finally, one can ask why the presence of the "hidden order" at the heart of
the
primary processes did not give rise to serial music or abstract painting in the seventeenth century,
not obliged, in the end. to reinstruduce the structuring function of the ego
as a
for example, are we
determining element in artistic creation?
68. This notion is similar to that of Leo Spitzer, who considered the "stylistic deviation"
from the linguistic norm as an expression of the writer's personality; on the other hand, it is hard to
see why Spitzer sought to interpret this deviation also as the sign of an evolution in the "collective
soul." One remains unconvinced by his example of the use of the phrase "a cause de" in Charles-
Louis Philippe's novel, Bubu de Montpamasse (see Leo Spitzer, Linguistics and Literary
History, pp. 11-15).
69. Jean-Paul Sartre, Search for a Method, trans. Hazel E. Barnes, pp. 62-63.
70. Sidirohm^)^., Le Relation critique, p. 102).
72. For a more detailed theoretical discussion, see Fred \. Greenstein, Personality and
Politics. As its title indicates, Greenstein's book is concerned with the psychoanalytic bases of
political behavior; he examines, in greater detail than I am able to do here, the problem of the
relation between role and personality. Greenstein has also published an important volume of
texts treating the influence of personality factors on political behavior; historians will find the
theoretical discussions in the volume pertinent to their own concerns. ( See Fred I. Greenstein and
Michael Lemer. A Source Book for the Study ofPersonality and Politics.
75. Stanley Hoffmann and Inge Hoffmann, "De Gaulle as Political Artist: The Will to
Grandeur," in Stanley Hoffmann, Decline or Renewal? France Since the 1930's, p. 202.
76. Hans Gerth and C. Wright Mills, Character and Social Structure. The Psychology of
Institutions, p. 419.
77. We could complicate the problem further: granted that the personality influences the
mode of execution of a role considered from a subjective viewpoint — in other words, as a series of
norms internalized by the individual who performs the role — that would not be the case one if
considered the role in a broader perspective, not only in terms of internalized norms but also in
terms of objective limits independent of individual We might add that it is precisely on the
will.
political level that these objective limits are most strongly felt, often leaving a very narrow margin of
choice and maneuvering to the person who makes the decisions. This notion is reinforced by recent
studies concerning the influence of bureaucratic organizations on decision making, notably in the
field of foreign policy, where there appeared to be much more leeway for choice than in domestic
policy. (See, for example, Graham T. Allison, The Essence of Decision: An Analysis of the
Cuban Missile Crisis.) The reply to this kind of argument can be stated in brief and simple terms:
the argument is not entirely false when the political process follows what can be called a "normal"
course; but as soon as a crisis situation occurs, the limits imposed on individual decision-making
by the weight of various objective factors, especially by organizational and bureaucratic
constraints, are broadened, and the political leader finds himself free to choose between war and
peace, resistance or submission, compromise or confrontation. Whether he finds support for his
decision is another matter. Crisis situations allow one to see, more forcefully than ever, the
essential role of personality factors in the context of political decision-making.
78. Among the important works in this category, we may note the biographies of the
English General Clinton and of the American politician, Charles Sumner. See William B.
Wilcox, Portrait of a General, Sir Henry Clinton, in the War of Independence; Da\id Donald,
Charles Sumner and the Coming of the Civil War.
79. Besides the Georges' study on Wilson, we should mention Fawn M. Brodie, Thomas
Jefferson: An Intimate History: Lewis J. Edinger, Kurt Schumacher: A Study in Personality and
Political Behavior; Arnold Rogowjames Forrestal: A Study ofPersonality, Politics and Policy;
Robert C. Tucker, Stalin as Revolutionary, 1879-1929: A Study in History and Personality, as
well as the more limited but nevertheless very interesting study by Peter Loewenberg, "The
Unsuccessful Adolescence of Heinrich \\\mm\Qr" American Historical Review 76, no. 3 ( 1 97 1 ),
pp. 612fr.
80. Sigmund Freud and William C. Bullitt, Thomas Woodrow Wilson, pp. 6-7.
. . . . " 1
8 1 Alexander L. George and Juliette George. Woodrow Wilson and Colonel House: A
Personality Study, p. 114.
83. This verification is made possible by the fact that a number of previously unpublished
sources, notably the "deliberations of the Big Four," have been published since the Georges"
study appeared.
84. C. Seymour (ed.). Intimate Papers of Colonel House, p. 119
85. Sigmund Freud and William C. Bullitt, Thomas Woodrow Wilson, p. 116.
90. Les Deliberations du Conseildes Quatre (24 mars-28 juin 1919), vol. 1, p. 187.
94. See Freud and Bullitt, Thomas Woodrow Wilson, pp. 80-8 1
99. Fred Weinstein and Gerald M. Piatt, Psychoanalytic Sociology, pp. 68, 75,112.
102. Erik H. Erikson, Young Man Luther: A Study in Psychoanalysis and History,
p. 262.
103. Erik H. Erikson, Gandhi's Truth: On the Origins ofMilitant Nan- Violence, p. 401 .
109. See, among many others, Harold D. Lasswell, Psychopathology and Politics;
description of these typologies, see the previously cited works by Fred I. Greenstem.
1 12. Edward Shils, "Authoritarianism. Right and Left," in Richard Christie and Marie
of
David McClelland, The Roots of Consciousness. "The Psychodynamics
the
115.
Creative Physical Scientist," pp. 146ff.
142 History and Psychoanalysis
116. McClelland bases his argument on Robert Merton's theory — highly contro- itself
versial — about the relationship between Puritanism and science (see R. K. Merton, Social Theory
and Social Structure). In fact, if any religion is over-represented in the scientific domain in our
day, it is the Jewish one.
1 19. See 'WiWia.ms, Michael Faraday, pp. 8, 96, 99, 100, 358, and J. Ag&s%\, Faraday as
Natural Philosopher, p. 15, as well as Bernard S. Finn. "Views of Faraday." Science 176
1 28. See especially Frank E. Manuel's detailed discussion on this subject in A Portrait of
Isaac Newton.
129. Ibid.
1 30. For a summary of the research on this subject, see Kenneth W. Terhune. "The Effects
of Personality in Cooperation and Conflict," in Paul Swingle. The Structure of Conflict.
131. On this subject, see Saul Friedlander and Raymond Cohen. "The Personality Origins
of Belligerence in International Conflict: An Analysis of Historical Cases," Journal of Com-
parative Politics, January 1975.
1 32. This behavior pattern has often been studied: see in particular H. B. Biller and L. J.
and Social Psychology2 ( 1 965); D. B. Lynn and W. L. Sawrey. "The Effects of Father-absence
on Norwegian Boys and Girls," yourna/ ofAbnormal and Social Psychology 59 ( 1 959).
.
meaning, we can cite as examples the sanatorium, the prison or the concentration camp, the
boarding school or the monastery. ( See Irving Goffman,Asylums: Essays on the Social Situation
ofMental Patients and Other Inmates, esp. p. 16.)
143
144 History and Psychoanalysis
tentative. In fact, these aggressive themes are essentially linked to orality, which seems to lead
back to the first stage in Erikson's model, unless one opts instead for a Kleinian interpretation.
(See John Demos, "Underlying Themes in the Witchcraft of Seventeenth-Century New
^x\g\and" American Historical Review 75, no. 5 [1970].)
1 1 Elkins' study provoked a great deal of controversy, the essential issues of which are
summed up in Ann J. Lane, The Debate over Slavery: Stanley Elkins and His Critics. But on the
whole the controversy was over the interpretation of the facts, not over the essential facts
themselves. More recently, however, it is the basic data concerning black slavery in the United
States that have been contested: the slave society has been described as a stratified society, with
economic competition and a definite degree of individual development among its members. (See
Robert William Fogel and Stanley L. Engerman, Time on the Cross: The Economics ofAmerican
Negro Slavery.) Since the debate remains open and since Fogel's and Engerman's thesis is far
from being accepted by most historians, we may consider that, in the absence of definite proof to
the contrary, the traditionally accepted facts about the life of black slaves in the United States are
correct.
1 2. Elkins, Slavery, p. 82. To explain the formation of the Sambo personality, Elkins uses
three convergent theories: the psychoanalytic theory of internalization, H. S. Sullivan's theory of
interpersonal relations, and role theory.
1 4. In its most general form, this problem has not escaped the attention of other scholars.
See especially Harold R. Isaacs, The New World of Negro Americans, and Charles Silberman,
Crisis in Black and White.
15. Every collective obsession requires a first gesture, a first narrative account, an initial
setting in motion by a few magnetic personalities. See on this subject the clinical case histories
reported in Georges Heuyer, Psychoses collectives et suicides collectifs.
1 6. On this subject, see especially Norman Cohn, The Pursuit of the Millenium.
1 7. Saul FriendVander, L'Antisemitiseme nazi, esp. pp. 146ff.
18. See the general study by Julio CaroBaroja, The World of Witches, as well as Michel de
Certeau'sLcf Possession de Loudun and Chadwick Hansen's Witchcraft of Salem.
19. From this point of view, the phenomenon closest to us, and perhaps the most
astonishing one, is the quasi-disappearance of Nazism with the death of Adolf Hitler. But Norman
Cohn already showed that the disappearance of the "prophets of the millenium" led to the
disappearance of their sects. Similarly, possession as a phenomenon disappeared from Salem and
Loudun practically overnight.
20. Sigmund Freud, Group Psychology and the A nalysis ofthe Ego.
21. Ibid., p. 48.
27. We are obviously dealing here with phenomena that one would tend to qualify as forms
of collective hypnosis — even though that term does not take us very far — or, other times, as in
forms of "collective possession" — which takes us even less Hypnosis and possession are both
far.
described as phenomena that involve profound, but generally temporary, changes (even though in
the case of possession the change can be, as we know, irreversible). In any event, the role of the
34. Ibid., p. 5.
37. There exist numerous documentary sources for this kind of study: for example, the
importance accorded to a particular symptom or disorder in the clinical literature, as well as in
literature in general; hospital archives, especially those of psychiatric hospitals; the
archives of
various commissions or groups studying the mental health of a population; finally, the private
archives of psychiatrists or psychoanalysts. In his Madness and Civilization, Michel Foucault
has given us a brilliant history of the evolution of mental disorders and of the attitudes toward them
in a given culture. One can envisage an additional psychohistorical dimension to
a study of this
kind.
38. If one studies a particular group behavior involving a paroxystic collective phenome-
non of short duration, one is in fact dealing with a temporary homogeneous group (as in the
examples we mentioned earlier of witchcraft in Loudon or Salem). If, on the other hand, one
considers the witchcraze as an irrational attitude that manifested itself over a period of close to
two centuries, then one is studying an isolated phenomenon in the sense in which we are discussing
it here.
39. Hugh R. Trevor-Roper, The European Witchcraze of the Sixteenth and Seventeenth
Centuries, p. 160.
40. Henry Institoris and Jacques Sprenger, Le Marteau des Sorci'eres (with an intro-
duction by Amand Danet).
41 Danet, Introduction to Le Marteau des Sorcieres, p. 8.
42. Ibid.
45. For a discussion of the "identifying" role of marginal or deviant groups, see Kai T.
Erikson, Wayward Puritans: A Study in the Sociology ofDeviance.
46. Georges Devereux, "La psychanalyse appliquee a Thistoire de Sparte." p. 32.
numerous studies, of which the best known are those of Ernst S\mme\, Antisemitism: A Social
Disease; Rodolphe Loewenstein, Psychanalyse de I'antisemitisme: Henry Loeblowitz-Lennart,
"The Jew as Symbol," Psychoanalytic Quarterly 16, no. 1 (1947); Bela Grunberger, "The
Antisemite and the Oedipal Conflict," InternationalJoumal ofPsycho-analysis 45 ( 1 964).
1 46 History and Psychoanalysis
Herman Huss and Andreas Schroder, Antisemitismus: Zur Pathologie der Biirgerlichen
Gesellschaft.
56. One point, however, deserves clarification. Anti-Semitism has been defined as an
attitude allowing the anti-Semite to distinguish Good from Evil, the Pure from the Impure, and so
on. In order for this function to be maintained, isn't the survival of the Jews essential to the non-
Jewish society? But Nazism, the paroxystic form of anti-Semitism, made ever>' effort to annihilate
the Jews. Isn't there a fundamental contradiction implied in this? The answer is relatively simple: if
the Nazis annihilated the Jews physically, they proceeded at the same time to elaborate a detailed
and fantastic version of the myth of the Jew, in other words of the counter-ideal of the mythical
"in-group." Furthermore, in a context of racial hierarchy other inferior races can fulfill the
physical and concrete function of the visible counter-ideal, while the myth of the Jew preserves its
function as the "ideal" incarnation of Evil.
59. Emphatically defended by Robert Nisbet (who borrowed some of his notions from
Radciiffe-Brown), the theory of change through "rupture" is particularly well known and has been
most often discussed in the context of scientific change, since the publication of Thomas S. Kuhn's
The Structure of Scientific Revolutions.
60. Robert Nisbet, it is true, included several essays by historians in his volume on social
change.
63. On this subject, see in particular David Schoenbaum, Hitler's Social Revolution:
Class and Status in Nazi Germany, 1933-1939.
64. Neil J. Smelser," Social and Psychological Dimensions of Collective Behavior," in
66. Ibid.
70. Keniston, ibid., p. 342. The same hypothesis has been formulated in particularly
emphatic and univocal terms by Lloyd de Mause, in the framework of what he calls the
"psychogenetic theory of History." According to de Mause. the specific traits of a culture depend
on the particular configuration of childhood in that culture. This kind of theory, which is partially
correct as far as homogeneous groups are concerned, becomes reductionistic when applied to
heterogeneous groups, as we have shown. For a full statement of de Mause's views, see his
introduction to the collective volume. The History ofChildhood.
.
74. Ibid., p. 158. The qualification of "tosome extent" is in this case essential, for once
again we are not dealing with a homogeneous group.
75. Ibid., p. 192.
79. Kingsley Davis, "The Sociology of Parent- Youth Conflict," American Sociological
Review 5 (\9^Q), p. 5Z5.
80. Muzafer Sherif and Hadley Cantril, The Psychology of Ego Involvements: Social
Attitudes and Identifications, pp. 205ff.
8 1 See Robert Jay Lifton, "Protean Man," in History and Human Survival
82. See above, p. 103.
83. Besides the various volumes of writings by members of the youth movements to which
we shall be referring frequently in what follows, the two most complete historical studies on this
subject are Howard Becker's German Youth, Bond or Free, and Walter Z. Laqueur's Young
Germany: A History of the German Youth Movement.
84. German youth movements counted around 15,000 members. (See George
In 191 1, the
Mosse, The Crisis of German Ideology, p. 171.) According to Fritz Jungmann. the various youth
movements that grew out of the IVanderx'ogel had a total of 40,000 members in 1914. (See Fritz
Jungmann, "Autoritat und Sexualmoral in der Jugendbewegung." in Max Horkheimer, Studien
iiber Autoritdt und Familie, p. 670.)
85. Hans Bliiher, "Geschichte des Wandervbgels," in Werner Kindt, Grundschriften der
Deutschen Jugendbewegung, p. 41.
86. Kindt, Grundschriften, p. 10.
89. The impact of a work such as Helmut Harringa was immense. Already before the first
World War it had sold 400.000 copies. (See Fritz Jungmann, "Autoritat und Sexualmoral in der
Jugendbewegung," p. 67 1 .)
90. Elisabeth Busse-Wilson, "Liebe und Kameradschaft." in Kindt. Grundschriften.
p. 329.
Grundschriften, p. 153.
94. The role of active homosexuality in the German youth movements has been con-
siderably overestimated, due to Biuher's books and to the practices of a deviant fraction within the
movements, which drew public attention and provoked scandal. According to Jungmann. overt
homosexuality within the movements was not more widespread than among German youth in
general. On the other hand, the youth movement encouraged friendship with erotic overtones, or
"sublimated" homosexuality between members, and especially between the members and the
its
leader. (See Fritz Jungmann. "Autoritat und Sexualmoral in der Jugendbewegung," pp. 676-
677.)
148 History and Psychoanalysis
95. Quoted in Howard Becker, German Youth, Bond or Free, p. 97.
97. Quoted in Harry Pross, Jugend, Eros, Politik: Die Geschichte der Deutschen Jugend-
verbiinde, p. 286.
100. For an extremely subtle thematic analysis of German films between the war and the
Nazi seizure of power, see Siegfried Kracauer, From Caligari to Hitler.
101 As concerns the youth movements, the instinctual freedom one
Ibid., pp. 84ff., 96ff.
finds in a group such as Muck-Lamberty's "Npue Schar" does not mean very much, given the
limited and ephemeral character of the phenomenon. What seems far more significant was the
rejection of expressionism and the choice of a highly stylized kind of painting, such as one finds
from the very start in the illustrations of the youth movements' publications.
102. One cannot fail to note that several of the psychological characteristics we have just
mentioned have often been identified as being particular to the "fascist personality." Further-
more, it has often been noted to what a great extent fascism idolized youth and was itself a "youth
movement." George Mosse, who has placed particular emphasis on this aspect of fascism, notes
that the fascist leaders themselves were for the most part men who were still young: "Mussolini
was 39 when he became Prime Minister, Hitler 44 on attaining the Chancellorship. Leon Degrelle
was in his early thirties, and Primo de Rivera as well as Codreanu were in their late twenties. . . .
Indeed, when they inveighed against the bourgeoisie they meant merely the older generation
which could never understand a movement of youth." (George L. Mosse, "The Genesis of
Fascism,'' Journal of Contemporary History l,no. 1 [1966], pp. 18-19). Robert Brasillach and
Drieu La Rochelle practically equated youth with fascism: in the thirty-year old Brasillach, who
has just discovered the marvels of fascism, we recognize all the major themes that inspired the
adolescents of the Wanden'ogel, but in an extreme form. (See Robert Brasillach, "Notre avant-
guerre," in Une Generation dans I'orage, p. 205ff.). A study of the deep psychological
connections between fascism and youth remains to be written.
103. See especially two articles by Walter Laqueur, "Reflections on Youth Movements"
and "The Archeology of Youth," reprinted in his book. Out of the Ruins ofEurope.
104. This assertion is not based on a formal survey, but rather on an intuitive evaluation of
the situation, based on my observation of various university settings both in the United States and
in Europe.
1 05 Daniel Bell. The End ofIdeology: On the Exhaustion ofPolitical Ideas in the Fifties.
106. Kenneth Keniston, The Uncommitted: Alienated Youth in American Society,
pp. 102-103. We should point out that in Keniston's study the totally "uncommitted" student
appeared to be an exception. I am suggesting, however, that this is an "ideal type" which
reflects the tendency of a very large segment, if not the majority, of American youth.
1 10. Jacques Le Goff, "Les mentalites: Une histoire ambigue," in J. Le Goffand P. Nora,
Fairede I'histoire. vol. 1, p. 80.
1 16. David Riesman, "Psychological Types and National Character," American Quar-
terly, no. 5 (1953), p. 329.
117. Ibid., pp. 330-332.
118. As examples of oversimplifications in this domain one can cite the numerous works of
Geoffrey Gorer, the best known of which is The People of Great Russia (in collaboration with
John Ryckmann).
1 19. Louis Dumont, Homo hierarchicus: Essai sur le systeme des castes, p. 15.
121. Serge Moscovici, Essai sur I'histoire humaine de la nature, pp. 5-6.
128. Popular literature is perhaps more important in this instance than "great" literature.
Robert Mandrou has provided an excellent demonstration of its importance in his hook.De la cul-
ture populaire aux XVI f et XVIlf siecles: La Bibliolheque de Troves.
129. On this subject, see Anton Ehrenzweig's remarks on modem art in L'Ordre cache de
I'art, pp. 102. 162ff. For the analysis of contemporary mentalities, the study of films is essential.
The significance of a popular film is equal to that of the most widely read book, due to the direct
impact of the image and the interaction between the spectator and the screen, which is just as deep
as the one between the reader and the printed page. But only a thematic analysis of a great number
of films can overcome the inherent obstacles posed by the composite nature of this mode of
expression. For this reason, the conclusions drawn by Gregory Bateson from his analysis of the
Nazi film. Hitlerjunge Quex, are not very convincing: the same can be said of Erikson's analysis
of the Soviet film, The Childhood of Maxim Gorky. For a summary of Bateson's analysis, see
Margaret Mead and Rhoda Metraux. The Study of Culture at a Distance, pp. 302 ff.: for
Erikson's study, see the \as\c\\&p\tr o^Childhood and Society. The comparative study by Martha
Wolfenstein and Nathan Leites, presented in their book. The Movies: A Psychological Study, is
methodologically far superior, despite some of the simplistic parallels the authors draw between
the present and the distant past.
133. Marc Raeff. to cite one example, was not able to avoid this pitfall in his otherwise
extremely suggestive study on the collective mentality of the Russian nobility in the eighteenth
century. Origins of the Russian Intelligentsia: The Eighteenth Century Nobility. For a very
pertinent critique of Raeffs work, especially in the perspective we are adopting here, see Michael
Confino, "Histoire et psychologie: a propos de la noblesse russe au XVIII siecle," Annates
ESC, vol. 22, November-December 1967.
134. Alex Inkeles and Daniel J. Levinson. "National Character the Study of Modal
Personality and Sociocultural Systems." in Gardner Lindzey and Elliott Aronson, The Hand-
book of Social Psychology, vol. 4, p. 427.
J 50 History and Psychoanalysis
135. For this range of choices, see in particular Inkeles and Levinson, "National Char-
acter." p. One of the chief weaknesses of the volume on culture and personality edited by
447.
Margaret Mead and Rhoda Metraux (see note 129) is precisely that the essays included in it are
not comparative studies devoted to a few central problems, but rather dispersed monographs
that do not allow one to draw any conclusion based on the only valid basis, which is inter-
cultural comparison. It should be noted, however, that the problems posed by such intercultural
comparisons are not easy to resolve; they have generated. a large number of methodological
studies, not only in sociology and anthropology but in social psychology. We shall not enter into a
detailed discussion of these technical questions.
137.The comparative study edited by Margaret Mead and Martha Wolfenstein, Child-
hood Contemporary Cultures, suffers from the absence of common points of reference. This
in
notwithstanding, the analogous conclusions reached by several studies referring to the same
general theme and presented by several co-authors of the volume for example, Martha —
Wolfenstein's and Frangoise Dolto's studies concerning the differences between French and
American children — are not lacking in importance.
1 38. For a particularly suggestive study on the relation between the global social context,
the forms of child-rearing and certain characteristics of the American mentality, see David M.
Potter, People ofPlenty: Economic Abundance and the American Character.
1 39. We could in fact add a fourth level of analysis, that of particular modes of thought (in
the formal sense), which some scholars believe they have discerned through an analysis of the
divergent structures of languages. See, for example, Benjamin L. 'Whori, Language, Thought and
Reality, Edward Sapir, Language, Culture and Personality; Hagime Nakamura, The Ways of
Thinking ofEastern Peoples.
1 40. Alain Besangon, Le Tsarevitch immole, pp. 72ff.
141. Ibid., p. 78.
144. Ibid.
145. In his contribution to the collective volume, Faire de I'histoire, Alain Besangon
repeats this interpretation of Russian culture through an analysis of Chemyshevsky's What Is To
Be Done? and Dostoevsky's A^o/e^/rom Underground. (See Alain Besangon, •'L'inconscient:
L'episode de la prostituee dans Que faire? et dans Le Sous-Sol, " in Le Goff and Nora, Faire de
I'histoire, vol. 3, p. 31). But in a previous essay. Besangon implicitly reversed the roles of the
mother and the father, so that it was the dangerous, castrating woman, the Oedipai mother, whom
the Russian man had to confront. (See Alain Besangon, "Fonction du reve dans ie roman russe,"
in Histoire et Experience du moi. )
Bibliography
151
152 History' and Psychoanalysis
Barber, James D. "Adult Identity and Presidential Style: The Rhetorical Emphasis."
Daedalus, no. 97 (summer 1968).
Barbu, Zevedei. Problems of Historical Psychology. London: Routledge and Kegan
Paul, 1960.
Baroja, Julio Caro. The World of the Witches. Trans. Nigel Glendinning. London:
Weindenfeld and Nicolson, 1964. Orig. ed. Las brujas y su mundo. Madrid:
Revista de Occidente, 1961.
Barthes, Roland. Michelet. Paris: Ed. du Seuil, 1954.
Barzun, Jacques. "The Muse and Her Doctors." The American Historical Review
77, no. 1(1972). (T)
Bell, Daniel. "National Character Revisited." In Edward Norbeck et al., The Study of
Personality. New York: Holt, Rinehart and Winston, 1968.
Bettelheim, Bruno. The Informed Heart. New York: Free Press, 1967.
and Morris Janowitz, Social Change and Prejudice. New York: Free Press,
1964.
Biller, H. B. and L. J. Borstelmann. "Masculine Developement: An Integrative
Review." Merrill-Palmer Quarterly 13(1 967).
Binion, Rudolph. Frau Lou: Nietzsche's Wayward Disciple. Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 1968.
. "Research Note." Newsletter: Group for the Use ofPsychology in History 1,
Edgar Poe, sa vie, son oeuvre: Etude analytique. Paris: Presses universitaires
de France, 1958, 3 vols. (B)
Bibliography 153
Bowlby, John. "The Nature of the Child's Tie to Its Mother." InternationalJoumal
ofPsycho-analysis 39 (1958).
Brasillach, Robert. "Notre avant-guerre." In Une generation dans I'orage. Paris:
Plon, 1968.
Brenner, Charles. /1/7 Elementary Textbook of Psychoanalysis. New York: Double-
day, 1957.
Brodie, Fawn M. Thomas Jefferson: An Intimate History. New York: Norton, 1971.
(B)
Brown, Norman O. Life against Death. London: Rutledge & Kegan Paul, 1 959.
Payot, 1971.(1)
1973.
Confino, Michael. "Histoire et psychologic: a propos de la noblesse russe au XVIII^
s\Qc\t." Annales ESC 22 (Nov.-Dec. 1967).
Payot, 1972.
Davis, Kingsley. "The Sociology of Parent- Youth Conflict." /I mencaw Sociological
Review 5 {\9A0).
Uni-
Delay, Jean. The Youth of Andre Gide. Trans. June Guichamaud. Chicago:
versity of Chicago Press, 1963. Orig. ed. La Jeunesse
d'Andre Gide. Paris:
Donald, David. Charles Sumner and the Coming of the Civil War. New York:
Knoof. 1960.
Dostoevsky. Fyodor. The Diary of a Writer. Trans. Boris Brasol. New York:
Octagon, 1973.
. Crime and Punishment. Trans. Constance Gamett. New York: F. Watts,
1969.
Doubrovsky, Serge. The New Criticism in France. Trans. Derek Coltman. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1973. Orig. ed. Pourquoi la nouvelle critique?
Critique et Objectivite. Paris: Mercure de France. 1966.
Dufrenne, Mikel. La Personnalite de base. Paris: Presses universitaires de France,
1966.(1)
Duijker, H. C. and G. H. Frijda. National Character and National Stereotypes.
J.
(T)
Edel, Leon. Henry James. 4 vols. Philadelphia: J. B. Lippincott, 1953-1972 (B)
Edinger, Lewis J. Kurt Schumacher: A Study in Personality and Political Behavior.
Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1965. (B)
Bibliography 155
(T,B)
. "Introduction a la psychobiographie." Incidences de la psychanalyse 1
(1970).
Fogel, Robert William and Stanley L. Engerman. Time on the Cross: The Economics
ofAmerican Negro Slavery. Boston: Little, Brown, 1974.
Freud, Sigmund. Group Psychology and the Analysis of the Ego. Trans.
James
Stachey. London: Hogarth Press. 1948.
The Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological IVorks of Sigmund
.
Imago,
1887-1902. Trans. Erich Mosbacher and James Strachey. London:
1954.
Twenty-Eighth
Freud, Sigmund and William C. Bullitt. Thomas Woodrow Wilson,
Boston: Houghton
President of the United States: A Psychological Study.
MifHin. 1966.
/ 56 History and Psychoanalysis
Gottschalk, Louis, Clyde Kluckhohn and Robert Angell. The Use of Personal Docu-
ments in History, Anthropology and Sociology. New York: Social Science
Press, 1945.
Hoffmann, Stanley. Decline or Renewal? France since the 1930's. New York: Viking
Press, 1974.
. History as Art and as Science. New York: Harper & Row. 1 964. (T)
Huizinga, Johan. The Waning of the Middle Ages: A Study of Forms of Life,
Thought and Art in France and the Netherlands in the 14th and 15th
Hunt, David. Parents and Children in History. The Psychology of Family Life in
Early Modern France. New York: Basic Books, 1970. (C)
Isaacs, Harold R. The New World of Negro Americans. New York: Viking Press,
1963.
Jaspers, Karl. Strindberg und Van Gogh: Versuch einer Pathographischen Analyse
unter vergleichenden Heranziehung von Swedenborg und Hblderlin. Berne:
Bircher, 1922.
Jones, Ernest. The Life and Works of Sigmund Freud. New York: Basic Books,
1961.
— . Essays in Applied Psychoanalysis. Lx)ndon: Hogarth Press, 1951.
Jungmann, Fritz. "Autoritat und Sexualmoral in der Jugendbewegung." In Max
HorVhtimtr, Studien iiber Autoritat und Familie. Paris: Alcan, 1936.
Kafka, Franz. Diaries. Ed. by Max Brod. Trans, by Joseph Kresh. New York:
Schocken, 1965.
Kaplan, Abraham. The New World ofPhilosophy. New York: Random House, 1961.
.The Conduct of Inquiry: Methodology for Behavioral Sciences. San Fran-
cisco: Chandler, 1964.(T)
Kohut. Hein/. I'he Analysis of the Self: A Systematic Approach to the Psychoanalytic
Bibliography 159
Treatment of Narcissistic Personality Disorders. New York: International
Universities Press, 1 972. (T)
Kracauer, Siegfried. From Caligari to Hitler: A
Psychological History of the
German Film. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1947.
Kretschmer, Ernst. Physique and Character. Trans. W. J. H. Sprott, London:
Routledge & Kegan Paul. 1949.
Kris, Ernst. Psychoanalytic Exploration in Art. New York: International Univer-
sities Press, 1964. Orig. ed. London: Allen &Unwin, 1953.
Kuhn, Thomas S. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1970.
Kurth, Gertrud M. *'The Jew and Adolf Hitler." In Sandor Lorand, The Yearbook of
Psychoanalysis 4 ( 1 949).
Lafaye, Jacques. Quetzalcoatl et Guadalupe: La Formation de la conscience
nationale au Mexique. Paris: Gallimard, 1974.
Lagache, Daniel. Lo Psychanalyse. Paris: Presses universitaires de France, 1969.
Lane, Ann J. The Debate over Slavery: Stanley Elkins and His Critics. Chicago:
University of Illinois Press, 1971.
Lange-Eichbaum, W. The Problem of Genius. London: Kegan Paul. 1931.
Langer, Walter C. 77?^ Mind of Adolf Hitler: The Secret Wartime Report. New
York: New American Library, 1973.
Langer, William L. "The Next Assignment." In Bruce Mazlish, Psychoanalysis and
History. Englewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall. 1963. {AHR 63 [Jan. 1958],
pp. 283-304.) (T)
Leach, Edmund. Genesis as Myth and Other Essays. London: Jonathan Cape. 1 969.
Le Goff. Jacques. "Les mentalites. Une histoire ambigue." In Jacques Le Goff and
Pierre Nora, Faire de I'histoire. Vol. Ill, Nouveaux Objets. Paris: GalHmard,
1974.
and Pierre Nova. Faire de I'histoire. 3 vols. Paris: Gallimard. 1974.
Leites, Nathan Constantin. The New Ego: Pitfalls in Current Thinking about
Patients in Psychoanalysis. New York: Science House, 1971.
Le Roy Ladurie. Emmanuel. Le Territoire de I'historien. Paris: Gallimard. 1 973.
Bihlio<iraphy 16
Mead, Margaret and Rhoda Metraux. The Study of Culture at a Distance. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press. 1953.
Merton, Robert K. Social Theory and Social Structure. New York: The Free Press,
1968.
et al. Sociology Today: Problems and Prospects. 2 vols. New York: Harper
Meyerhoff, Hans. "On Psychoanalysis and History." Psychoanalysis and the Psy-
choanalytic Review 49, no. 2 (1962).
Mitscherlich, Alexander. Society Without a Father. Trans. Erich Mosbacher. New
York: J. Aronson, 1974.
Mitzman, Arthur. The Iron Cage: An Historical Interpretation of Max Weber New
York: Knopf, 1970.
Moran, Lord. Winston Churchill: The Struggle for Survival, 1 940-1965. London:
Constable, 1966.
Moscovici, Serge. E^ai sur Thistoire humaine de la nature. Paris: Flammarion,
1968.
no. 1(1966).
. The Crisis of German Ideology. New York: Grosset & Dunlap, 1964.
Munroe, Ruth L. V. Schools of Psychoanalytic Thought. New York: Holt, Rinehart
and Winston, 1955. (T)
Murphy. Gardner. "Psychological Views of Personality and Contributions to Its
Study." In Edward Norbeck, Douglas Price- Williams and William M. McCord.
The Study of Personality: An Interdisciplinary Appraisal. New York: Holt,
Rinehart and Winston, 1968.
Nagel, Ernest. "Methodological Issues in Psychoanalytic Theory." In Sidney Hook,
Psychoanalysis, Scientific Method and Philosophy. New York: New York
University Institute of Philosophy, 1959.
Nakamura, Hagime. The Ways of Thinking ofEastern Peoples. Honolulu: University
of Hawaii Press, 1964.
Nisbet. Robert. Social Change. New York: Harper & Row, 1 972.
Norbeck, Edward, Douglas Price- Williams and William M. McCord. The Study of
Personality: An Interdisciplinary Appraisal. New York: Holt, Rinehart and
Winston, 1968.
Novey, Samuel. The Second Look: The Reconstruction of Personal His tor}- in
Psychiatry and Psvchoanalysis. Baltimore: John Hopkins University Press.
1968.
Nunberg, Herman and Ernst Fedem. Minutes of the Vienna Psychoanalytic Society.
New York: International Universities Press, 1 962, vol. 1 ; 1 967. vol. 2.
Painter. George D. Proust. Boston: Little. Brown & Co., 1959. (B)
Parsons. Anne. "Is the Oeidpus Complex Universal?" In Werner Muensterberger
and Sidney Axelrad. The Psychoanalytic Study of Society. New York: Inter-
national Universities Press, 1960-1972; 1964. vol. 2. (T)
Bibliography 163
Picard. Raymond. New Criticism or New Fraud? Trans. Frank Towne. Washington
State University Press. 1969. Orig. ed. Nouvelle critique ou nouvelle impos-
ture. Paris: Pauvert, 1965.
Plumb, J. H. "The Wolfs Clothing." The New York Review ofBooks, Dec. 14. 1972.
Ricoeur. Paul. Finitude and Guilt. Trans. Charies Kellbey. Chicago: Gateway
Rieff. Philip. Freud: The Mind of the Moralist. New York: Doubleday. 96 1 1
Thought." In Bruce
"The Meaning of History and Religion in Freud's
Prentice-Hall. 1963.
MazMsK Psychoanalysis and Histor)'. Englewood Cliffs:
Character." American Quar-
Riesman, David. "Psychological Types and National
terly 5 (1953).
Character.
Riesman. David et al. The Lonely Crowd: A Study of Changing American
New York: Doubleday. 1 953.
genie et son double." Preuves. Feb. 1 968.
Robert. Marthe. "Vincent VanGogh. le
164 History and Psychoanalysis
Sachs, Hans. "The Delay of the Machine Age," Psychoanalytic Quarterlv 4, no. 2
(1933).
Sapir, Edward. Language, Culture and Personality. Berkeley: University of Cali-
fornia Press, 1956.
Schapiro, Meyer. "Leonardo and Freud: An Art Historical Siudy." Journal of the
History^ of Ideas 17(1 956).
Schmidl, Fritz. "Psychoanalysis and History." Psychoanalytic Quarterly 31, no. 4
(1962).
Schoenbaum, David. Hitler's Social Revolution: Class and Status in Nazi Germany,
1933-1939. New York: Doubleday. 1966.
Schorske, Carl E. "Politique et parricide dans TInterpretation des reves de Freud."
Annales ESC 2S iMaTch-Apn\ 1973).
Shapiro, David. Neurotic Styles. New York: Basic Books, 1965.
Sears, Robert R. Survey of Objective Studies of Psychoanalytic Concepts. New
York: Social Science Research Council, 1943.
Bibliography 165
Sherif, Muzafer and Hadley Cantril. The Psychology of Ego Involvements: Social
Attitudes and Identifications. New York: Wiley, 1947.
Shils, Edward. "Authoritarianism, Right and Left." In Richard Christie and Marie
"
Jahoda, Studies in the Scope and Method of "the Authoritarian Personality.
Glencoe: The Free Press of Glencoe, 1954.
Silberman, Charles. Crisis in Black and White. New York: Random House, 964. 1
Singer, Milton. "A Survey of Culture and Personality Theory and Research." In
Bert Kaplan, Studying Personality Cross-Culturally. New York: Harper &
Row, 1961.
Smelser, Neil J. Theory of Collective Behavior. New York: The Free Press, 1 963.
Spitzer, Leo. Linguistics and Literary History. Princeton: N.J.: Princeton University
Press, 1948.
Stem, Fritz. The Varieties of History from Voltaire to the Present. New York:
(1968). (B)
Terhune, Kenneth W. "The Effects of Personality in Cooperation and Conflict." In
Paul Swingle, The Structures of Conflict. New York: Academic Press. 1 970.
Thomas, Keith. Religion and the Decline of Magic. London: Scribner. 1971.
Thompson, Clara. Psychoanalysis: Evolution and Development. New York: Gross
Press, 1957.
Vovelle, Michel. Mourir autrefois: Attitudes collectives devant la mort aux XVI f et
XVIII^siecles. Paris: Gallimard, 1 974.
Waelder, Robert. Basic Theory of Psychoanalysis. New York: International Uni-
versities Press, 1962.
Index
169
1 70 Index
Index 1 71
82 Meta-history, 82
Language of Psychoanalysis, The (Laplanche Meyer, Konrad Ferdinand. 43
and Pontalis), 22 Michelangelo, 57-59, 64
Lansing, Secretary of State, 67 Michelet:
Laplanche, Jean, 22 fantasies of, 18-19,92
Laqueur, Walter, 106 study on, 56
La Rouchefoucauld, 2 Micro-history, 82
La Senne, personality theory of, 10 Mitscherlich, Alexander, 1 12
Lasswell, Harold, 74 Modal personality, defined, 1 16-1 17
Lazarsfeld-Jahoda, Marie, 94 Moran, Lord, 49
LeGoff, Jacques, 112, 113, 115 Morell, Dr.,49
Lenau, Freud on, 43 Moscovici, Serge. 1 14
Lenin: Moses and Monotheism (Freud), 32
illness of, 49 Murphy, Gardner, on theory, 10-1
and typology, 73, 74 Mutation, and change, 97
"Leonardo da Vinci" (Freud), 2
Le Roy Ladurie, Emmanuel, 96, 1 17
Levinson, Daniel 116
J., Namier. Sir Lewis. 4
Levi-Strauss, Claude, 30, 34, 52, 95-96 Napoleon Bonaparte:
Lewin, Kurt, 10 self-crowning. 63
Libidinal index, of civilization, 33 andtypology. 75.76, 78
Link, Arthur S., on Wilson, 24, 66-68 Napoleon III, and typology, 78
Linton, Ralph, 36, 85 Narcissism:
Lodge, Henry Cabot, 65 and charisma, 70
Loewenstein, Rudolf, 94 and peer group, 109
Luther (Fthwe), 1 regression in. 1 10
Luther, Martin, psychobiography of, 27, 44, and self. 1
Index 173
Neurosis. See also Psychoanalysis Possessed. The (Dostoevs\iy), 1 19
and art, 54 Possony, Stefan. 73
and history, 1 1-12 Pourunesociologiedu roman (Goldmann). 5
and Oedipus complex, 3 1-32
Privatism, and society, 104
and personality, 44 Projection, of Hitler. 46-47
Nisbet. Robert, 96, 97 Proust, 2,56
Nomothetic sciences, 3 Psychoanalysis. See also Freud, Sigmund:
Psychobiography
Oedipus complex. See also Freud, Sigmund; and art. 52fT.
Psychoanalysis and biography:
and anti-Semitism, 94 problems. 5, 21-22
and art, 53 scientific verification. 22fF.
and fixation, 21-22 branches of, 1
and Hitler, 47 and charisma, 70-73
intensity of, 32 and empiricism, 12-16
interpretations of, 15, 19, 20 historians on, 1,4
as model, 34 and history, aims, 1 1-12
and neurosis, 31-32 hypotheses, basic. 29-30
and Russians, 18 1 opposition to. 4. 14-15
and society, 102 and prediction. 1
variations in, 20 and psychological, theory, 6
Oedipus Rex, 53 and sociology, 3
Oelbermann, Robert, 1 07 structuralism, 33fF.
Oral stage, and society. 102 and unconscious. 18
Overdetermination: value of. 123
example of, 29 Psychobiography:
meaning of, 22-23 aims of. 30. 44
and art, 50ff.
Painter, George, 56-57 and collective identity. 69-73
Palmerston, Lord, 78 and political behavior. 62ff.
Panofsky. 59 problems of. 45 ff.
Paradigms, in psychohistory, 29fF. and psychoanalysis, 2 1 ff., 43fT.
Parricide, and sexuality, 53 and typology, psychohistorical. 73fr.
Parsons, Talcott: Psychological theory, multiplicity of, 6-7.
levels of analysis, 33, 96 See also Psychoanalysis
on personality, 30, 3 1 ,38 Puberty rites, primitive, 18
Paz.Octavio, 81
Peak experiences. 41 Quantitative analysis, as scientific criterion, 25
Pecuchet. 2 QuetzalcoatI, and Saint Thomas. 1 15
Petain, Marshal Henri, 63
Peter the Great, 118 Racine, and personality, 5
Phaeton, punishment, 58.59 Rapaport. David. 40. 41
Phenomenological psychology, 6, 9. See also Rapoport. Anatol. 12
Existential psychology Raskolnikov:
Phylogenesis, and ontogenesis, 32 dream of. 27-29
Physiological psychology, use of, 9 and Porfiry, 119
Piaget, Jean, theory of, 9-10 Rattner. Sidney. 6
Picard. Raymond. 50, 5 Raw Youth. A (Dostoevsky). 1 19
Picasso, 59 Reaction formation:
Piatt, Gerald, 38, 70 in art. 57