657998
657998
657998
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
Springer is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Theory and
Society
THOMAS BURGER
Southern Illinois University at Carbondale
Fleeing the Iron Cage, which should more properly be called "Facing
the Iron Cage," presents social science inspired, not by a vision of intel-
ligent beings acting under the naturalistic impact of the general con-
straints inherent in their own human nature and in that of social organi-
zation, but of meaning-seeking beings wanting to do the right thing
under the historically developed specific circumstances whose ines-
capability constitutes their "fate." Scaff, obviously in sympathy with the
latter approach, makes no attempts to defend its merits and liabilities;
the considerable accomplishment of his excellent book consists rather
in suggesting an interpretation that goes a long way toward identifying a
coherent structure and rationale in Weber's work. Scaff finds Weber's
diagnosis of the realities of the modern situation more than confirmed
by later developments; as to Weber's prescription, Scaff is as mum as
many other commentators, perhaps because it is a lot easier to feel ill-
at-ease with it than to conceive of a convincing alternative. Convenient-
ly, however, the issue is addressed in Harvey Goldman's Max Weber
and Thomas Mann: Calling and the Shaping of the Self,7 an interesting
book that can serve as a complement and addition to Scaff's.
Goldman attributes the salience, for Weber, of the search for the right
attitude toward life to his problematic relationship (shared with
Thomas Mann) to himself and his class of origin: He identified with the
bourgeoisie, whose role he considered crucial in the determination of
Germany's future, yet could not find in it, in its present condition, a
model of action, ethos of work, or pattern of meaning that could
sustain him personally and that would ensure the political and cultural
effectiveness of the class as a whole. This profound dilemma engen-
dered a life-long concern, fundamental to his work (as to Mann's), with
the foundations of personal identity and worth. It issued in the adop-
tion and advocacy of an updated version of the idea of the calling as the
basis for meaningful orientation in modern life, an outcome Goldman
considers to be quite non-accidental. For he believes that Weber's and
Mann's individual difficulties with self-acceptance mirror the crisis of a
bourgeoisie disconnected from the source of its specific strength, that
both authors reveal their attachment to and confinement within the
seem senseless and valueless; living 'out of duty' provides the means for
living despite the loss of a 'taste' for life" (122). This is the experience
of self-alienation, i.e., of the personal and social unacceptability and
worthlessness of one's own (natural) self; liberation from oppression by
this self is then sought through a battle whose actions combine a
successful struggle against both the obstacles of the external world and
the resistance of the intolerable inner self, aiming at the former's
mastery and the latter's erasure and replacement. The conception of
the calling is attractive to someone involved in such a struggle as it
supplies a model and strategy for overcoming the hated (natural) self in
disciplined and effective service. Yet the dangers of this strategy,
Goldman thinks, become all-too-clear in the writings of Thomas Mann.
before the "world" that is the object of their love, i.e., the bourgeois
class. Thus they do not really mend the split in the internally divided
self but rather institutionalize it in the form of a highly unstable com-
promise. Their redemption is only a quasi-redemption as they remain
suspended between two worlds and suffer from the lack of reconcilia-
tion.
service" (202). For the cause to which the self is to be devoted does not
have the power to bring it back to a new life. Work in the calling has
ceased to be natural and needs to be willfully stimulated through active
effort. The cost involved in this undertaking is fearsome. Death in
Venice describes, unbeknownst to its author, the revenge of the real self
and inner man that were put to death in the name of a calling (art). "It is
revenge because the personality, the reborn self of art, is now a coffin
for the soul and nothing more.... The religion of suffering ... does not
recognize that the suffering is the product of the choice for the death of
life among the living, but believes in this death as the source of its
heroism, as a form of nobility, as the meaning of its life" (204).
Goldman thinks that for both Mann and Weber, the calling functions as
a magical device through which (their) personal rejection and loss are
transformed into impersonal and sanctified service, creating in the indi-
vidual a sense of grace and purpose. Yet, in the calling, work is denied
as a source of self-satisfaction or of the satisfaction of craftsmanly
desires, as the fulfillment of talents or as satisfying involvement with a
loved activity. Instead, it is made to serve the needs of self-definition,
self-justification, and identity (110). The calling thus is an elaborate con-
trivance to overcome nature: natural limits of strength, doubts about
life, negative judgments by others, and one's self-image as unsoldierly
and unfaithful to one's ancestors, one's descendants, or one's task. Yet
neither Mann nor Weber ever stopped to examine this calling for its
worth, meaning, function, and effect on the self and the world, or for its
real purposes (205). Accordingly they could never fully discover or
accept the self as it truly is or may be, with its strengths, weaknesses, and
needs. Nor could they ever understand the personal and social reasons
for their belief that the self must be fashioned and redeemed through a
calling. By relying instead on an inherited ascetic self-discipline rooted
in religion and in the bourgeois class, they foreclosed to themselves the
insight into the deeper nature of Europe's and their own crisis (210).
Weber's concern with finding his bearings in life is also central to Alan
Sica's Irrationality and Social Order,9 albeit with less encouraging
results. Sica is much bothered by the "totemic status" (4) of "rational-
ity" in contemporary American sociology. He notes the odd contrast
between scholars' free admission of a considerable, even overwhelming
irrational component in social behavior, and their almost exclusive
theoretical preoccupation with its rational aspect. He thinks that in
slighting the irrational, mainstream American sociologists have fol-
lowed the lead of Weber's penchant for rationalistic idealization,
strongly legitimated - at the expense of Pareto's perspective - by
Parsons's early interpretation, and he argues for a major shift in focus.
For he believes that "increasingly, rationality as a component of social
action and as a valued quality of personality is becoming inversely
related to meaning in human life; that is, zweckrational behavior and
the major institutions it is usually thought to dominate no longer hold
the appeal for social actors that they are believed to have held in an
earlier period.... In turn, those institutions previously deemed less vital
to social order (e.g., the aesthetic, supernatural, or recreational) are
being invested with much more personal energy... in the pursuit of
meaningful experience...." (33). If social theory is to capture what
makes their existence important (i.e., "meaningful") to individuals, what
people might do to enhance their lives in ways that were anathema to
Weber, namely eudaemonistically, and what makes actors behave other
than "rationally," it must incorporate more than a rationality assump-
tion in its models of personality and social action. "I hope," announces
Sica, "to find analytic concepts which are not in themselves alienated
from the nature of contemporary humankind, a nature still apparently
encumbered by demons of nonrationality" (33).
Sica's assertion that Weber knew life's genuine and innermost core to
be wrapped in irrationality is based on a complete misunderstanding of
Weber's interpretation of the cultural dialectics characterizing a civili-
zation in which ordinary, routine, everyday life is in the grip of ration-
alization, and in which the extra-ordinary is associated with
"irrationality": to the extent to which in such a culture the extra-ordina-
ry is viewed as the realm of life-enhancing charismatic powers, the irra-
tional "appears" as the real kernel of life.'l However this may be, Sica
proceeds on the assumption that Weber acknowledged the domination
of "life as lived" (16) by irrationality, i.e., by spurs to action located on a
level not reached by societal and self-repression and therefore outside
and beyond predictability (223). The puzzle posed, on this premise, by
the rationality-emphasizing formulations in Economy and Society is
resolved in the claim that Weber's psychodynamics foreclosed the pur-
suit of any fundamental alternative. The ensuing question of just how
Weber managed to suppress what he knew, namely the centrality of
irrationality to personal and social life, Sica answers through meander-
ing discussions suggesting four major ploys on Weber's part. The first
consists simply in his dogmatic espousal of rationality as the essence of
humanity, serving him to reject - not really refute - the idea embraced
by Knies and others, that the irrationality of the personality is the true
source of human dignity. The second consists in the designation of
instrumentally rational (zweckrational) action as the prototype of all
meaningful conduct. The third consists in the narrowing of sociology's
subject-matter to understandable, that is, meaningful, behavior, there-
with instituting "rational interpretation" as its pre-eminent task and
eliminating the concern with the irrational. The fourth consists in a
rationalistic dressing-up of essentially irrational phenomena by
stretching the meaning of terms, using "rational," "logical," and kindred
epithets in an incantational fashion, and by concocting fanciful pseudo-
rational constructions. "An overview of the entire Religionssozio-
logie ... discloses a single unmistakable tendency... coercion ... of even
the most constitutionally irrational religious beliefs and practices
into some form of rational explanation. This reaches ludicrous
extremes at times, though for the most part Weber saves himself from
clumsy rationalism with his usual arrangement of qualifications
coupled with linguistic craftiness" (218).
Both Weber's presumed dilemma, i.e., the conflict created by his insight
into, and simultaneous denial of, the irrationality of the true center of
life, and the strategems used for dealing with it, are artifacts of Sica's
misinterpretations. At their root are two never scrutinized axiomatic
The source of Sica's failure to maintain the first and third distinctions is
the result of yet another of his projections onto Weber: of his own
usage of "meaningful" as "existentially significant," "subjectively satis-
fying," of "central to the individual's identity and justification of self."
("Meaning ... can be understood as 'whatever subjectively defined
qualities of one's life make active persistence appealing'" (6, note 6).)
Weber, of course, when he declared the subject-matter of sociology to
be subjectively "meaningful" action did not use the term in this
emphatic sense but quite blandly in the sense of "understandable" or
"intelligibly motivated." Sica, attributing to him the emphatic version,
gets off on the entirely wrong track; the ensuing disaster is of enormous
proportions. This error produces not only an entirely distorted overall
reading of Weber's sociology as the effort of a man driven to deny the
significance of the irrational in human existence because he could not
conceive of any meaningful life for himself except a compulsively
rational one; it also transmogrifies the work into a monument to stag-
gering incoherence. Thus, Sica constantly throws up his arms at
rational type (162, 205, 229). (7) Weber associated the incalculability
of action with an animal-level of existence, with insanity, and with a
freedom-threatening subjection to the blind forces of nature (180,
181). (8) Weber was reluctant to investigate irrationality-drenched
issues such as ethnicity and nationalism (217). (9) Weber's compulsive
dependence on, and incantational invocation of, the rationality-irra-
tionality dichotomy is indicative of some great private meaning it held
for him.
None of this, of course, sits well with Sica, the ultimate sources of
whose unhappiness with Weber must be gleaned from a few rudimen-
tary remarks strewn through his book. As one might suspect and fear,
nothing less than the nature of human freedom is at issue. Sica appears
to believe that sociology must analyze society as the site where the
essence of humanity is on display and manifests itself. This essence -
the specific hallmark of the human being's dignity - for him is by no
means "rationality" as conceived by Weber. He does not accept the
model that implicitly informs Weber's statements on the matter, and
that might be described as follows: Action is an actor's contextually
conditioned dealing with objects in a manner intended to satisfy the
instrumental requirements of his or her situationally predominant
action impetus. This impetus is not necessarily irresistible, but the actor
may be more or less able to control it, that is, may be able to interpose a
reflective stage between the ascendancy of the impetus and its imme-
diate precipitation into action. Weber is silent on the mental "mecha-
nisms" involved, but it is fair to say that he attributes three major effects
to their operation, amounting overall to a transposition of the impulse
from a level of dim feeling and undifferentiated immediate experience
to a level of conscious awareness and objectification. These effects are
(1) clear insight into the impulse's specific identity; (2) increased
control over nature and direction of the impulse's impact on the course
of action; and (3) harnessing of the impulse and its impact on conduct
to personal and cultural values and meaning patterns. This processing
of the impulse life by the objectifying, analytic and synthetic, cognitive
and normative structuring powers of the intellect using its cultural
resources Weber associates with "freedom," i.e., with the actor's capac-
ity to assert, in the structuring of his or her conduct, the influence of the
actor's "'own' 'deliberate considerations' (Erwdgungen) undisturbed by
'external' coercion or irresistible 'affects'...."'15
ual to find a cause that makes his or her life a worthy one, and system-
atically, comprehensively, and continuously to choose and to structure
activities in accordance with its demands. From this perspective, the
kind and manner of behavior that most directly reflect involvement in
the cause may be said to be (existentially) the most meaningful for this
person. Sica, too, presumes existentially meaningful behavior to be
autonomous, i.e., to follow a course plotted by the individual, and this
involves, for him, its governance by the actor's self-defined calculus of
satisfaction. Conversely, existentially meaningless actions for him are
those whose performance is imposed on individuals through external
constraints; such actions are not fulfilling in terms of the personal cal-
culus of satisfaction. Thus, it can in this sense be quite "rational," for an
actor to disregard and withdraw from institutionally pre-plotted kinds
and courses of action. Sica, who says nothing about the "inner" sources
of action orientations' dimness, perturbation, and weakness so central
to Weber, believes that an empirically adequate sociology requires a
tenable conception of the relationship between personality and social
structure, "that juncture where subjectivity, or organized experience,
enters the rigidity of social structure and struggles to overcome, tran-
scend, or alter it in pursuit of its own goals" (129). Weber, in his
opinion, has it all wrong: Instead of treating rationality as the impulse
toward a meaningful existence that is thwarted by running into the
barriers of socially and culturally imposed patterns, he views it as a
matter of impulse control with the help of these patterns, and therefore
of increased calculability of behavior. This kind of "rationality" glorifies
the fetters placed on the search for meaning, i.e., the disciplining of
"those intra-psychic forces which resist cultural rationalization" (116),
for the sake of calculability.
The books reviewed here converge in the assumption that Weber's con-
cern over the possibility of a meaningful existence structured his socio-
logical perspective, and that one gains access to this sociology as one
grasps his outlook on the problem of meaning in life. Scaff's book is
proof of the soundness of this interpretive strategy, yet only because it
is careful to separate the question of the validity of Weber's arguments
from the question of the circumstances of their genesis. For certain
purposes it may be interesting and revealing to treat an author's
writings as documents of the distinctiveness of an age, a class culture, a
type of thought. Yet their documentary value should not be confused
with their value as arguments. If sociology is to be more than intel-
lectual history, crypto-moralizing, or politics in a different guise, its
focus must be on the scrutinizing of the validity of its claims. Assuming
for the sake of argument that Weber opted for the construction of
rational ideal types because of his emotional problems, that he adopted
the view of life as a calling because of his confinement within a bour-
geois horizon - what conclusions should be drawn by those interested
in promoting sociology as an empirical science? That the precondition
for better or valid theory is a healthy mind and a social location
guaranteeing distortion-free vision?
based on the assumption that events in that realm are inherently subject
to constraints and thus form discoverable and solid general structures.
Yet, whereas positivists ontologize these into "necessity" and "laws," he
speaks of (historical) "fate" and "inherent logic" (Eigengesetzlichkeit).
This divergence is crucial as it involves profound disagreement on how
to deal with the meaningful aspect of action phenomena. One may not
be satisfied with Weber's solution, but there should be little doubt that
it cannot be easily dismissed.
Notes
1. Lawrence Scaff, Fleeing the Iron Cage. Culture, Politics, and Modernity (Berkeley:
University of California Press, 1989).
2. Max Weber, Gesammelte Aufsiitze zur Wissenschaftslehre, 3rd ed. (Tiibingen:
Mohr, 1968), 598; Hans H. Gerth and C. Wright Mills, editors, From Max Weber
(New York: Oxford University Press, 1964), 143.
3. Max Weber, Gesammelte Politische Schriften, 3rd ed. (Tiibingen: Mohr, 1971);
Max Weber, "The National State and Economic Policy" [1895], Economy and
Society 9.4 (November 1980): 428-449.
4. Politische Schriften, 12; "National State and Economic Policy," 437.
5. From Max Weber, 156.
6. Wissenschaftslehre, 589; From Max Weber, 135.
7 Berkeley: University of California Press, 1988.
8. Quoted in Max Weber and Thomas Mann, 122.
9. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1988.
10. Max Weber, Gesammelte Aufsdtze zur Religionssoziologie, vol. I (Tiibingen: Mohr,
1920), 560; From Max Weber, 347; Irrationality and Social Order, 196.
11. Max Weber, The Methodology of the Social Sciences (Glencoe: Free Press, 1949),
52-53; Wissenschaftslehre, 149; Irrationality and Social Order, 151-152.
12. See Weber's discussion in Wissenschaftslehre 67f.; Max Weber, Roscher and Knies:
The Logical Problems of Historical Economics (New York: Free Press, 1975), 125f.
13. Irrationality and Social Order, 175f.
14. Wissenschaftslehre, 129-130; Roscher and Knies, 189-190.
15. Wissenschaftslehre, 13; Roscher and Knies, 191.