Max Webers Elective Affinities
Max Webers Elective Affinities
Max Webers Elective Affinities
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at http://www.jstor.org/page/
info/about/policies/terms.jsp
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of content
in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms of scholarship.
For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
The University of Chicago Press is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to American Journal of
Sociology.
http://www.jstor.org
This content downloaded from 147.91.1.45 on Sun, 13 Mar 2016 18:39:58 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
University of Illinois
use of the term "elective affinity," yet nowhere has the term received
cited and discussed. Next, the place of elective affinity in his order of
"affinity" and "inner affinity," are examined and brought into rela-
would have served to answer the question, How is social science pos-
order of discourse.
has often been sensed as a crucial term, most notably by Gerth and Mills
(1946), Stark (1958), and Mayer (1975). And rightly so. For under-
standing Weber's idea of history and thus the logic of his social science no
term is more crucial than "elective affinity." For Gerth and Mills, elective
affinity is "the decisive conception by which Weber relates ideas and inter-
ests" (1946, p. 62); for Stark, elective affinity is Weber's theoretical alter-
(1958, p. 256); for Mayer, Weber's thought moves generally "in concepts
707). Yet, despite this sense of its importance, Weber's use of elective af-
founded. Certainly the glosses of these scholars do not begin to exhaust its
potential, for it would yield as idea the 'possibility of social science alto-
within the bounds of Kant's pure reason. To be sure, few if any of Weber's
Weber was heir has largely been lost on succeeding generations of social
1 This paper grew out of a seminar conducted by Robert Alun Jones at the University
of Illinois in the fall of 1975. To him and to my wife, Marcia Kirkpatrick, I am grate-
This content downloaded from 147.91.1.45 on Sun, 13 Mar 2016 18:39:58 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
work are altogether rare (1904a, pp. 29, 34 [1949, pp. 56, 61]; 1905a, p. 54
[1958, pp. 91-92]; 1906a, p. 148 [1949, p. 118]; 1906b, p. 347; 1910, pp.
581, 596; 1916, pp. 19, 20 [1946, pp. 284, 285]; 1918, p. 76 [1968, p.
1429]; 1922, pp. 183, 270, 780, 795, 796, 815 [1968, pp. 341, 472, 1160,
1180, 1208]). His usage is diverse and moreover quite informal. Nowhere
Some instances of his usage are striking enough in context to draw a second
look, but even there the term defines its contexts so much more strikingly
than those contexts condition the term that little can be gleaned from those
contexts alone. Thus, his use of the term has continued to fascinate while
of the helplessness with which mere exegesis confronts the order of a dis-
course other than its own. It is one thing to sense the term's importance,
another to establish it, and yet another to find its locus in the order of his
thought. No reading of his work alone, be it ever so close, could ever accom-
plish all this, and least of all would pseudoetymology (see Gerth and Mills
suffice (see Stark 1958, p. 257). The problem is one for history and not for
exegesis (see Skinner 1969; Jones 1977). To discover what elective affinity
meant to Weber is to discover its place in the order of his discourse. The
term "elective affinity," as it was known to Weber, has its source in the
chemistry of the 18th century. From there it entered into literature, above
all through Goethe, and into an order of intellectual discourse, where it was
and with Kant's idea of reason which he had termed "affinity" (Afinitdt).
his order of discourse, the other by that rare combination of erudition and
insight which was Max Weber himself. Then as now, the potential of that
intersection has remained more virtual than actual. With what alchemy
the transmutations of its elements into the idea of Weber's social science
as one within the bounds of Kant's pure reason was accomplished is the
object of the present inquiry. Such an inquiry has no fear of the counter-
factual, of inference in the subjunctive mood. For only thus can elective
affinity be brought into its full relief. In the light of the virtual-the
the order of Weber's discourse becomes just visible within his own work as
INSTANCES
367
This content downloaded from 147.91.1.45 on Sun, 13 Mar 2016 18:39:58 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
discussing the sources and the inevitability of conflict in the arena of social
the truth remains wholly intact that as to which Weltanschauung the in-
A few pages later, this time by way of explaining the equal inevitability
similar ideals will . . . allow the circle of [its] contributors to hold together
and to recruit new members, and this will stamp the journal . . . with a
typical of the informality with which XVeber uses elective affinity. The term
But a year later, closing the first installment of the "Protestant Ethic"
with a caution to his readers, he states that, ". . . in view of the immense
social and political organization, and the intellectual and spiritual contents
of the cultural epochs of the Reformation, one can proceed only by first of
between certain forms of its religious faith and its work ethic are discern-
ible. Thereby and at the same time, the manner and the general direction
significance. Within the chaos that the social scientist confronts, there is
an order; this order exists not only for himself but also for the actors in
history and largely affects history's course. The logic of history would be
Weber used elective affinity twice more in connection with the "Prot-
581), while in the second he speaks of the "elective affinity of the bour-
World Religions" of the elective affinities between the various social strata
2All translations are my own, with the single exception of the quotation from Berg-
man. References to the available translations of Weber's works have been provided in
368
This content downloaded from 147.91.1.45 on Sun, 13 Mar 2016 18:39:58 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Econowiy and Society he speaks of the lack of any such elective affinity of
uity (1922, p. 795 [1968, p. 1180]); and of the "inner elective affinity"
of the structural principles of the early Protestant sects with the structure
But Weber's use of elective affinity was not restricted to his studies of
sia" that it was "utterly ridiculous to attribute elective affinity with 'de-
affinity between 'chance' and 'freedom of the will'" (1906a, p. 148 [1949,
p. 118]).
what he may have meant by the term, despite the significance given it in
concrete economic forms, that is, concerning whether and how strongly they
[1968, p. 341]). These brief remarks can only suggest that for Weber the
sole significant universal propositions that social science could make would
possibility of social science would rest on the logic of elective affinity. But
why this would be so and what that logic would be for materials as diverse
else did he elaborate upon the term. But then, he had no need to. His
369
This content downloaded from 147.91.1.45 on Sun, 13 Mar 2016 18:39:58 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
ORDER OF DISCOURSE
referential networks of meanings which are their histories and thus their
thus to the larger order of the German language as well. The most authori-
tative codex of that order, the Grimms' Deutsches WIrterbuch, has the
term (see vol. 13, cols. 597-99) entering German in 1779 as the translator
Weigel's neologism for the Swedish chemist Torborn Bergman's term "at-
letters through Goethe, who appropriated the chemical meaning of the term
as the root metaphor for a novel, The Elective Affinities ([1809] 1951),
But the place of elective affinity in the general order of the German
language was never so secure, as may be discerned from its fate in the
Goethe, whose recent novel the entry mentions (1811, p. 542). It is not in
(1910, p. 803). Paul's lists it (1908, p. 1199), while Kluge's does not
by Goethe. More thorough treatment had to wait until the vast enterprise
of the brothers Grimm, begun in 1854, reached the letter "W" in 1922, just
elective affinity was a marginal word, though its position had improved
somewhat by the decade before the First World War. Acquaintance with it
could be presupposed only for those familiar with the history of chemistry
or for the somewhat larger circle of those who read the German classics.
was small indeed. To have known the meaning of elective affinity was to
have been part of a very special order of discourse: the discourse of the
humanistically educated elite (see Wehler 1973, pp. 124-29; Ringer 1969).
To the rest, the word could well have seemed a contradiction in terms.
370
This content downloaded from 147.91.1.45 on Sun, 13 Mar 2016 18:39:58 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Krug's (1829), but it does appear in the supplement to the second edition
may have been due to Schmidt's other interests: that same year he pub-
refers the reader back to the entry for affinity (Affinitdt), which states that
". . . the Law of A[ffinity] (principle of the continuity of the forms) bids
via the stepwise increase in multiplicity (Kant)" (1912b, p. 9). From there
the reader is referred back to the entry for elective affinity, with the usual
mention of chemistry and Goethe, thus closing a circle and opening a net-
Elective affinity was unknown to the handbooks and lexica of the social
made use of the term, writing that ". . . one of the most remarkable monu-
ments to the elective affinity of the North German coastal states with the
(Grimm and Grimm, vol. 13, col. 599). And Treitschke too had used the
term, writing that ". . . the Romans were truly intimate only with the old
Roman world; the Germans were drawn by a feeling of elective affinity to-
ward the Hellenic genius" (Grimm and Grimm, vol. 13, col. 599). Treitsch-
junior heard his lectures at the university (Marianne Weber 1926, pp. 42,
102), while later on the Webers, Max and Marianne, were frequent guests
such as this, the company of men of letters and learning, a familiarity with
the meaning of elective affinity could be taken for granted, and Weber did
just that when he wrote. The term was a touchstone, even of itself, of the
set it apart.
GOETHE
If elective affinity had entered the order of the German language through
through literature and Goethe. Like few others-perhaps like Schiller, like
371
This content downloaded from 147.91.1.45 on Sun, 13 Mar 2016 18:39:58 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
haustible fund of raw materials for philological industry as well. That in-
dustry was no respecter of the disciplines. Kuno Fischer, the leading figure
of the Kant revival of the 1860s, produced a number of shorter studies and
and then two books (1906, 1913); Gundolf, Weber's connection to the
charismatic circle around the poet Stefan George, wrote what became a
classic study of the poet (1916); even Weber's colleague Rickert wrote
man Weber set himself apart from his contemporaries by judging Schiller
the better poet, noting in a letter to his cousin Emmy that "the exaggerated,
exclusive Goethe worship" of his friends had spoiled their taste in literature
and made them unjust to other poets (Marianne Weber 1926, p. 164). In
one-sided view of life; Goethe was ". . . sensitive to the debased as such
only when it was at the same time the hateful and trivial; he had, on the
1926, p. 164). That judgment was made when Weber was 23. He had
first encountered the elective affinities nine years before while reading
through, "hidden under his desk during class, all forty volumes of the Cotta
Eduard's; and Ottilie, Charlotte's young and beautiful niece. As the novel
opens, Eduard and Charlotte are busy with the renovation of Eduard's
country estate. Eduard proposes that the captain join them to help with
third but wishes one herself: her niece Ottilie. The third arrives, and the
fourth too; and, as might be expected in any novel with such an opening
situation, Eduard falls in love with his wife's niece, Charlotte with her hus-
band's friend. The novel develops the unhappy consequences of these elec-
tive affinities.
Goethe was not only a poet, he was also a scientist with an interest in,
"It appears that the author's continued studies in the physical sciences have
occasioned this strange title. He would like to remark that in the study of
nature one very often makes use of moral imagery in order to bring closer
372
This content downloaded from 147.91.1.45 on Sun, 13 Mar 2016 18:39:58 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
origins" (von Wiese 1951, p. 621). A year earlier, during the composition
of the novel, he had told his friend Riemer that "his idea for the new
ments was "astonishing, for a work by Goethe" (Kolbe 1968, p. 30, n. 55).
Jacobi called it "an ascension of evil lust" (von Wiese 1951, p. 645). By
the end of the century, such judgments had been tempered, if not forgotten.
Cotta's Goethe editor, Karl Goedeke, whose prefaces appeared in all the
later editions, took note of them, writing that "the name of the novel de-
rives from the chemical designation of the process wherein different sub-
stances united with one another break out of their union in favor of another.
had attempted to deny the law of free will and to justify a waywardness
caught in conflict with civil morality as a law of nature. He did just the
opposite" (Goedeke 1885, p. 4). However they judged its morality, the
degree of elective affinity between the novel and the problematics of Web-
er's contemporaries was strong. Whether the analogy between natural and
moral and social processes was to suggest that nature itself was somehow
"ensouled" (Zeitler 1918, p. 511) or rather that the soul of man stood
under the sway of nature (Gundolf 1916, p. 553), the problem it posed was
the central one of the relationship between the order of nature and the
moral and social orders. And so, however tangentially, the novel touched
upon the question of how a social science would be possible if society were
a realm of freedom.
CHEMISTRY
Goethe took the metaphor of the elective affinities from chemistry, indi-
"the moral symbols in the natural sciences, for example, that of 'elective
affinity,' discovered and employed by the great Bergman" (von Wiese 1951,
p. 621). But here Goethe errs, for while Bergman may well have been the
the 18th century, he was not its originator. The history of elective affinity
Max Weber may have known that history, as evidenced in the opening
373
This content downloaded from 147.91.1.45 on Sun, 13 Mar 2016 18:39:58 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
where he speaks of "... the most complete layman ... [who] has read the
pendia on chemistry, say on atomic weights and equivalences and all that
goes along with that; on the concept of 'solutions' as opposed to the 'com-
p. 575). This most complete layman who had read compendia on chemistry
he may in fact have read. And he may also have read in Ostwald's own
survey of the field (1902), with its lengthy extracts from the sources.
the older part of the expression. It appeared in the 13th century in the work
of Albertus Magnus, which was printed in the 16th century. By the 17th
century the term was used with some frequency (Kopp 1843-, 2: 288).
In 1648 Glauber discussed the fact that "a body did not have the same
this led to various attempts to order the elements according to their dif-
fering inclinations to combine with one another. In 1718 these efforts bore
with one another are combined with one another and a third which has
more affinity for one of the two is added, then it will combine with that
one and exclude the other" (Ostwald 1902, p. 21). This is elective affinity
in everything but the name. Geoffroy backed his proposed law with a table
order. The remainder of the century saw the production of many revisions
The climax of the theory of elective affinity came with Torborn Berg-
tables of affinity for all 51 elements known then. His work was soon widely
electiva (Grimm and Grimm, vol. 13, col. 597). In his book, Bergman
saturation (this union I shall call Ac), should, upon the addition of b, tend
strongly than c, or to have a stronger elective attraction for it; lastly, let
the union of Ab, upon the addition of a, be broken, let b be rejected, and
374
This content downloaded from 147.91.1.45 on Sun, 13 Mar 2016 18:39:58 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
pp. 6-7]
This became the classic formulation of elective affinity, the one that ap-
one that Goethe used to weave the definition into the after-dinner conver-
sation of the characters of his novel, where Weber and his contemporaries,
even those who had never read compendia on chemistry could find it spelled
Even in its late 18th-century heyday, the theory of elective affinity had its
year earlier, the critic Buffon had complained of the chemists that they
"assume just as many little lawlets of affinity as there are special cases of
association and dissociation" (both in Ostwald 1902, pp. 29-30). Over and
above the strivings of these early chemists, there loomed the for them as
sity knew no need for "little lawlets." So it is not surprising that Immanuel
Kant, who had heard of Bergman (see Kant 1902-, 9:198; 10:219, 234)
esteem.
In his Metaphysical Bases of Natural Science, Kant stated that "in every
nounced his judgment that ". . . chemistry can never become anything more
ity ... ." (1902-, 4:471). Accordingly, chemistry must content itself with a
ment which is space, and psychology, the pure description of inward en-
And yet this mixed position which Kant assigned to chemistry came later
tical Reason: "To follow that same path [of analysis] in the treatment of
the moral capacities of our nature, that example [mechanics] can counsel
us and give us hope for a similarly good success. We do have the examples
375
This content downloaded from 147.91.1.45 on Sun, 13 Mar 2016 18:39:58 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
ing the empirical from the rational which may be found within them, can,
through repeated trials . . . make both known to us, purely . . . and with
been the common language name for chemistry then, a play on words which
Goethe later also made ([1809] 1951, p. 273), and only through an equally
artful divorce had Kant been able to argue the possibility of man as a moral
agent, for only after such a divorce of the empirical from the rational could
reason rejoin and order anew what its critique had put asunder.
AFFINITIES
maxim of reason, which is to say, an idea. Kant introduced the term first
for any single thing to be possible, its predicates must include, positively
From this it follows that ". . . every thing is referred to a common corre-
in the idea of one single thing, would prove an affinity of everything pos-
(1902-, 3:356n.). Once this has been established, the idea of affinity is
itous under higher species; (2) through an axiom of the variety of the
unity, it adds, further, (3) a law of the affinity of all concepts, which bids
a continuous transition from every single species to every other via the
ciples "regulative," for the ideas underlying his reason form no part of his
the philosophical and the chemical affinities was not to be missed. The first
concepts, that they have certain features in common with other concepts
. . . that certain features of the pure concept are one and the same with
certain features of the other concepts.... The concept of the alkaline salts
376
This content downloaded from 147.91.1.45 on Sun, 13 Mar 2016 18:39:58 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
is, for example, that they are salts which have a sharp, burning, uremic, but
not sour taste. . . . The alkaline salts and calcareous earths have . . . in
their concepts a common feature through which they are affine to one
another . . . namely, that they both absorb or can unite with acids" (1797,
pp. 89-90). Mellin went on at once to discuss "the logical law of the affinity
of all concepts" and its treatment by Kant, and then, true to the order of
tions of Greek and Roman letters standing not for chemicals but for con-
closing pages of the entry, however, provide a key to those letters with
Over the course of the next 100-odd years, the philosophical idea of
affinity fared no better but perhaps no worse than its chemical counterpart
tioning beside the philosophical and chemical affinities the ones of aesthetics
and ethics (1838, pp. 406-7). Kirchner's ignores affinity altogether, just
hand, is replete with citations from Kant (1899, p. 20). Fritz Mauthner's
language (1910, pp. 14-15). Then there is Schmidt's, already cited, with
Thus, affinity too in its technical sense was a marginal word, a marker
would have known that sense of the word through Kuno Fischer, whose
mornings of 1882 (Marianne Weber 1926, p. 70), if not directly from read-
ing Kant, which he had done from boyhood on (Marianne Weber 1926, p.
63). Among his Heidelberg colleagues, neither Windelband nor Rickert nor
Lask dealt with the term as their teacher and grand-teacher Kuno Fischer
may also have served as text for the lectures he heard (see Windelband
1897, p. 6), the place of affinity as an idea of reason in Kant's critique was
for Fischer a crucial one. Through Kant the Platonic doctrine of the ideas
had suffered a radical change. No longer were the ideas to relate to the
things as their concepts and their archetypes. Now the ideas were to serve
knowledge, not its object. As an idea of reason, affinity stood as an ideal for
concept formation, a maxim for the conduct of intellect (see Fischer 1869,
pp. 592-97). A similar conception would hold for his pupil Weber also. In
377
This content downloaded from 147.91.1.45 on Sun, 13 Mar 2016 18:39:58 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
INNER AFFINITY
culture,' then this thought construct, analyzed into judgments, means only
[innere Verwandtschaft] .. . with one another, but never that they follow
from one another with any kind of lawfulness. In other words, they are a
accord with the infamous schema 'All men are mortal; Caius is a man;
therefore, he is mortal'" (1904b, pp. 440-41). While the term here is "inner
serve to connect this passage with the later one in Economy and Society,
forms to one another (1922, p. 183 [1968, p. 341]). But equally, if not
more, important here for the logic of elective affinity in Weber's usage are
his reference to the analysis of constructs into judgments and his denial of
yield the framework for the idea of elective affinity; the latter, its locus in
As with so many points of epistemology and logic, it was his friend and
explicitly display everything that was already conceived within the con-
be analyzed and whose predicates form the features . . ." ([1888] 1915,
... we know that the logical ideal of our knowledge consists of a complete
knowledge with a net of threads in which the fixed knots represent the
concepts; the threads, on the other hand, which go from one knot to the
other are to delineate the connections between the concepts, that is, the
judgments.... Human thought ... could never "envisage" this net in its
totality, but could only traverse it in that it now forms concepts from out
378
This content downloaded from 147.91.1.45 on Sun, 13 Mar 2016 18:39:58 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
of the elements connected to one another, that is, the judgments, now
analyzes these concepts back into judgments. . . . just as the knots in the
net consist only of threads, concepts are nothing else but the transition
That then is the logic of any typology, Weber's included. Where the judg-
between the terms is defined. Where two or more of those terms share a
or, in the sense of Mellin's table of conceptual affinities and Kant's idea
But these inner affinities hold not only for Rickert's "net" of constant,
hold for the words themselves in the referential networks of their ordinary
thought out in Gottl's Dominance of the Word (1901), Weber made note
ness of its 'intended meaning.' The actor vaguely 'feels' it rather than
knowing it. . . . Actually effective, that is, fully conscious and clear mean-
ingful action is in reality always only a limiting case. . . . But that is not
If the concepts of sociology are the limit cases of possible intended mean-
ings of the words, and if the words are "inner affine" to one another, then
the inner affinities of the words will be reflected at their limit in those
concepts. Whether inner or elective, in the meanings of the words the af-
MUNDUS INTELLIGIBILIS
"Action," said Weber in the most basic of his definitions, "is . . . to mean
follows at once that every meaning in the lexicon of the actors represents
a possible action and that, conversely, every action portrays the meaning
379
This content downloaded from 147.91.1.45 on Sun, 13 Mar 2016 18:39:58 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
intended from objectively valid 'meaning,' which Simmel not only does
for the fourth edition of his Limits of Natur al Scientific Concept Formation,
published the year after Weber's death but no doubt composed and dis-
cussed while he was still alive, Rickert states that ". .. 'incorporeal' need
belong neither to the corporeal nor to the events of the soul . . . nevertheless
are directly known to everyone and therefore may also not be situated in a
as the same thing" (1921, p. 405). That solves the epistemological problems
of verstehen by fiat. But with the unanimity which for Rickert here defined
grammar and even with some apparatus of coercion (see 1913, p. 287). But
language community overall. Insofar as this situation is the case, the affini-
actions of its menibers. But just as that lexicon is structured by the inner
then does each such point of intersection, each such inner affinity, present
of his universe of meanings. For the actors of Weber's sociology have that
choice. Very late in its history and much circumscribed in scope, Kant's
meaning and of sociology as "a science that seeks to understand social action
4]). But for Weber, as for Kant, "that intervention of the intelligible char-
380
This content downloaded from 147.91.1.45 on Sun, 13 Mar 2016 18:39:58 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
senses. First, and most familiarly, in the sense of the value neutrality of his
social science: "An empirical science can teach no one what it is he ought
of possible actions the actor will make in his traversals of his universe of
by the inner affinities of the elements of his lexicon. Just as these structure
actions into constellations. And the more and with the greater constancy
his actions are oriented to his ultimate values, the more they fall under the
values is beyond the ken of social science. Therefore, Weber denies necessity
despite all adequacy or inner affinity. But with that denial comes a second
one: without that necessity there could be no a priori foundation for the
chemistry of the 18th century, social science could never be anything more
than a systematic art based on a divorce of the empirical from the rational.
That yields the locus of elective affinity in the order of Max Weber's
thought.
ELECTIVE AFFINITY
values that renders Weber's social science problematical within the Kantian
bounds of his order of discourse, even as this freedom derives from that
Kantian frame. The logic of elective affinity would provide a solution. Here
a metaphor may be of use. Values are related to meanings as are the constel-
lations to the stars. They are not their source and in no way could knowledge
of meanings determine choice of values. For the elements of the mundus in-
telligibilis are multivalent. Their affinities are manifold and may be of three
kinds. They may join the elements of the mundus intelligibilis to one
those elements from one another through a like intersection with change
of sign. There may be no intersection, but through the former all meanings
are joined, however indirectly. A meaning in total isolation from the rest
between two elements vis-a-vis the total possible number, the more strongly
381
This content downloaded from 147.91.1.45 on Sun, 13 Mar 2016 18:39:58 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
are the elements joined. That is their "degree" of elective affinity. The
higher the meaning, the greater would be its elective affinity for all the rest.
The highest are values. But the lexicon of possible actions, of meanings, is
may be to behold the bear and the dipper at once upon the northern sky;
but very possible to serve at once the Reformation's work ethic as well as
its faith.
Weber's usage, from the elective affinity of concrete forms of social action
with concrete economic forms to the elective affinity of similar ideals. Here
Weber's erudition and insight would meet with his order of discourse. From
chemistry and Bergman would come the basic paradigm of elective affinity;
from literature and Goethe, its application to the portrayal of social rela-
tionships; from philosophy and Kant, the art of divorce of the empirical
from the rational and the affinity of all things in their possibility. As a
maxim for the conduct of scholarship, elective affinity would suggest the
trace in their elective affinities the actors' choices of possible actions. That
as idea.
POSTSCRIPT
Weber never worked out the logical consequences implicit in his own usage
of elective affinity. But despite the informality of his usage, these conse-
quences can be inferred from its diversity through recourse to the order of
discourse which formed its substrate. For Weber, in the great tradition of
order of a society. The elements of that order were the meanings of the
words in their ordinary usage by the actors in history. Viewed from within
the Kantian bounds of his order of discourse, those actors are free in their
choice of actual actions. Thus, history would be a logical chaos were it not
for an order in the universe of the meanings to which those actors orient
the greater or lesser extents to which they possess inner affinity through the
actions which makes his social science possible. The actors' choices of pos-
sible actions are given by the elective affinities of their universe of meanings.
The order of the actual, the course of history and the structure of society,
382
This content downloaded from 147.91.1.45 on Sun, 13 Mar 2016 18:39:58 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
is to be read from this order of the possible. The task of Weber's science is
REFERENCES
Brunn, H. H. 1972. Science, Values, and Politics in Max Weber's Methodology. Copen-
hagen: Munksgaard.
Burger, Thomas. 1976. Max Weber's Theory of Concept Formation: History, Laws, and
Campe, Joachim Heinrich. 1811. W&rterbuch der deutschen Sprache. Vol. 1. Braun-
schweig: Schulbuchhandlung.
Eisler, Rudolf. 1899. Wdrterbuch der philosophischen Begriffe und Ausdrucke. Berlin:
Fischer, Kuno. 1869. Geschichte der neueren Philosophie. Vol. 3. 2d ed. Heidelberg:
Basserman.
Gerth, Hans, and C. Wright Mills. 1946. Introduction to From Max Weber: Essays in
Sociology, translated and edited by Hans Gerth and C. Wright Mills. New York:
Gottl, Friedrich. 1901. Die Herrschaft des Wortes. Jena: Gustav Fischer.
Grimm, Jakob, and Wilhelm Grimm. 1854-1971. Deutsches Worterbuch. Leipzig: Hirzel.
Jones, Robert Alun. 1977. "On Understanding a Sociological Classic." American Jour-
Weiss.
Trubner.
Kolbe, Jurgen. 1968. Goethes "Wahlverwandtschaften" und der Roman des 19. Jahr-
Kopp, Hermann. 1843-. Geschichte der Chemie. Braunschweig: Viehweg & Sohn.
Mauthner, Fritz. 1910. Wdrterbutch der Philosophie: Neue Beitrage zu einer Kritik
Mayer, Carl. 1975. "Max Weber's Interpretation of Karl Marx." Social Research 41
(4): 701-19.
1. Leipzig: Fromann.
383
This content downloaded from 147.91.1.45 on Sun, 13 Mar 2016 18:39:58 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
Rickert, Heinrich. [1888] 1915. Zur Lehre von der Definition. 2d ed. Tubingen: Mohr.
bingen: Mohr.
Ringer, Fritz. 1969. The Decline of the German Mandarins. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard
University Press.
stitut.
Skinner, Quentin. 1969. "Meaning and Understanding in the History of Ideas." His-
Stark, Werner. 1958. The Sociology of Knowledge. London: Routledge & Kegan Paul.
28 (6): 433-70.
. 1905a. "Die Protestantische Ethik und der 'Geist' des Kapitalismus." Archiv
. 1905b. "Roscher und Knies und die logischen Probleme der historischen
. 1906c. "Roscher und Knies und die logischen Probleme der historischen Na-
81-120.
253-94.
. 1946. From Max Weber: Essays in Sociology. New York: Oxford University
Press.
. 1949. The Methodology of the Social Sciences. Glencoe, Ill.: Free Press.
1958. The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism. Translated by Talcott
384
This content downloaded from 147.91.1.45 on Sun, 13 Mar 2016 18:39:58 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions
. 1975. Roscher and Knies: The Logical Problems of Historical Economics. New
Wehler, Hans Ulrich. 1973. Das deutsche Kaiserreich: 1871-1919. G6ttingen: Vanden-
Windelband, Wilhelm. 1897. Kuno Fischer und sein Kant. Hamburg: Voss.
385
This content downloaded from 147.91.1.45 on Sun, 13 Mar 2016 18:39:58 UTC
All use subject to JSTOR Terms and Conditions