Global Political Economy
Global Political Economy
Global Political Economy
an informa business
ISBN 978-1-03-214750-5
www.routledge.com
Edited by
V. Upadhyay and Paramjit Singh
First published 2022
by Routledge
2 Park Square, Milton Park, Abingdon, Oxon OX14 4RN
and by Routledge
605 Third Avenue, New York, NY 10158
Routledge is an imprint of the Taylor & Francis Group, an informa business
© 2022 selection and editorial matter, V. Upadhyay and Paramjit Singh; individual
chapters, the contributors
The right of V. Upadhyay and Paramjit Singh to be identified as the authors of the
editorial material, and of the authors for their individual chapters, has been asserted
in accordance with sections 77 and 78 of the Copyright, Designs and Patents Act
1988.
All rights reserved. No part of this book may be reprinted or reproduced or utilised
in any form or by any electronic, mechanical, or other means, now known or hereafter
invented, including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or
retrieval system, without permission in writing from the publishers.
Trademark notice: Product or corporate names may be trademarks or registered
trademarks, and are used only for identification and explanation without intent to
infringe.
Print edition not for sale in South Asia (India, Sri Lanka, Nepal, Bangladesh,
Pakistan or Bhutan)
British Library Cataloguing-in-Publication Data
A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
A catalog record for this book has been requested
ISBN: 9781032147505 (hbk)
ISBN: 9781003240921 (ebk)
DOI: 10.4324/9781003240921
Typeset in Garamond
by Arpit Printographers, Delhi
Contents
Preface 5
Introduction 7
1. Introduction to Historical Materialism: A Theory
of Society and History 37
Anjan Chakrabarti
2. Essential Concepts in Marxian Political Economy 72
Surinder Kumar
3. Notes on Marx’s Critique of Classical Political Economy 93
Prabhat Patnaik
4. Capitalist Mode of Production: A Basic Interpretation 104
Paramjit Singh
5. Contemporary Capitalism 127
Greg Albo
6. Reserve Army of Labour 140
Deepankar Basu
7. Political Economy of Employment-Unemployment in
Capitalism 158
Satyaki Roy
8. Can Capitalism Survive the High Degree of Automation?
A Comparison with Thomas Piketty’s Argument 179
V. Upadhyay
9. The Agrarian Question a Century After 1917: Capitalism
in Agriculture and Agricultures in Capitalism 192
Samir Amin
4 Global Political Economy
events, that may never see a full recovery. In that sense, some parts
of the economy might be lost permanently.
This health crisis combined with the unprecedented panic-
stricken reaction is also likely to alter people’s consumption and
saving behaviour. Excessive consumption on the part of people is
an essential requirement for the functioning of the present capitalist
system. But the psychological effects caused by the fearful experience
of the health crisis are certain to make people much more risk-
averse in the future. This is certain to dampen the pace of capital
accumulation, and in turn, reduce the capitalist economies’ growth
potential.
Totalitarian Surveillance
The response to the COVID-19 crisis has been in the form of
lockdowns across most countries. In many places, the state resorted to
prison-like restrictions on people’s freedom of movement, assembly
and expression that brought civil life, and political and economic
activities to a virtual standstill. The state used unprecedentedly
authoritarian methods to control and dictate people’s behaviour in
the name of securing health safety. But quite often, it was evident
that governments used the corona crisis as a cover to seize new
powers that had not much to do with the health emergency. New
dangerous surveillance technologies such as technologies to track
were pressed onto service to monitor people’s movements as well as
to manipulate their behaviour. The dictatorial tendencies developed
during the coronavirus crisis are likely to persist even after the health
crisis is over.5
PART IV
The present volume covers a wide range of issues from conceptual
questions to empirical investigation of the major challenges posed
by contemporary capitalism. The sequence of the papers nowhere
reflects the importance of one paper over the other. All the papers
are equally important to understand the theoretical foundations and
major challenges posed by contemporary capitalism.
Anjan Chakrabarti’s paper is a methodological one which
presents historical materialism as a method of inquiry of economy
and society. In the present scenario, it is essential to understand
the concept of historical materialism and method to expose the
exploitative nature of capitalism and role of the superstructure in
shaping the economy and society as per the requirements of the
capitalist mode of production. Surinder Kumar’s paper explains the
basic concepts of Marxian political economy which are important
to set the foundation for detailed analysis. Prabhat Patnaik’s
contribution explains the Marxian critique of Classical Political
Economy. This paper highlights in the Marxist framework the misery
of classical political economy to understand the accumulation logic
of capitalism and nature of capitalist production. The contributions
by Paramjit Singh and Greg Albo explain the capitalist mode
of production and the nature of its contemporary phase. Both
contributions are important to understand the basic structural
principles of capitalism and how it has evolved in recent decades.
The next three contributions explain the questions of employment
and unemployment under capitalism. Deepankar Basu’s paper,
along with a theoretical exposition, has empirically tested Marx’s
conception of the reserve army of labour. The paper by Satyaki Roy
is rooted in Marxian political economy that traces the employment-
unemployment phenomenon under capitalism that is an outcome of
the nature of the capitalist production process. V. Upadhyay’s paper
examines the nature of technological progress under contemporary
capitalism and its implications for labour and employment growth.
The next two papers deal with the agrarian question that has
not been appropriately addressed by the Marxist political economists
32 Global Political Economy
of the Global North in general and has not been part of the global
political economy curriculum in particular. The paper by the late
Samir Amin is a detailed analysis of the agrarian question under
capitalism. It addresses one of the key dimensions confronting the
Russian and Chinese revolutions, that of the agrarian question for
the peasantry which constituted popular majorities in each of these
countries at the time of their revolutions. Amin argues that the new
agrarian question is the key issue to be addressed in the processes of
building socialism in the 21st century. The contribution by Goran
Durfeldt discusses capitalist and family farming, fetching illustrations
from India and China, Sub-Saharan Africa and occasionally also
South America. He has challenged the widely held view of ‘big is
beautiful.’ He has presented sound reasons why family farming is
still thriving in the age of global capitalism.
The next five contributions cover the major themes which
expose historical and contemporary dimensions of the exploitative
nature of capitalism. John Bellemy Foster’s contribution defines
monopoly capitalism as a special stage of capitalist accumulation. It
traces monopoly capitalism and its various dimensions covered by
the leading political economists since Hilferding. The explanation
followed by the rich sources would be of immense worth to those
students and researchers who want to explore various dimensions
of the monopoly phase of capitalism. Paul Zarembka’s contribution
challenges the conception of “accumulation of capital” that is
generally propagated by scholars based only on Marx’s work. He
argues that accumulation of capital requires an in-depth analysis.
He has argued that the complete understanding of accumulation of
capital requires for Marxist scholars to build upon Marx’s works and
understand the concept in a horizontal manner by incorporating the
contribution of Rosa Luxemburg. Gerald Epstein’s contribution is
important in the sense that it clarifies the much debated concept
of “financialisation”, the term that had been developed long before
the crisis of 2008 but, understandably, became even more popular
since the crisis. He discusses various theoretical contributions in
order to provide a comprehensive understanding of financialisation.
Along with this, he argues that there are still many conundrums and
Introduction 33
REFERENCES
Boushey, H., J.B. Delong and M. Steinbaum (eds.) (2017), After Piketty,
Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.
Chomsky, N. (2020), Interview with Pressenza Athens, March 30, 2020,
Pressenza.com.
Dagdeviren, H., Rolph van der Hoeven and J. Weeks (2004), Redistribution
Does Matter: Growth and Redistribution for Poverty Reduction,
in Anthony Shorrocks and Rolph van der Hoeven (eds.), Growth,
Inequality and Poverty—Prospects for Pro-poor Economic Development,
London: Oxford University Press.
Delong, J.B., H. Boushey and M. Steinbaum (2017), Capital in the
Twenty-First Century: Three Years Later, in Boushey et al. (eds.), After
Piketty, Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University Press.
FAO (2017), The State of Food Security and Nutrition in the World, Rome:
Food and Agriculture Organisation of United Nations.
Goldhammer, A. (2017), The Piketty Phenomenon, In Bosuhey et al.
(eds.), After Piketty, Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University
Press.
Grewal, D.S. (2017), The Legal Constitution of Capitalism, in Boushey et
al. (eds.), After Piketty, Cambridge, Massachusetts: Harvard University
Press.
Introduction 35
capacity to labour and not labour per se, two conceptually different
things) and means of production (all material forces besides labour
power). Like the means of production, labour power is devoid of
any specific social content and is to be considered as a stock of
brains and muscles (inclusive of skills and knowledge they possess)
that can be deployed for production. Labour power is considered
more important than the means of production; even if the means
of production are destroyed, the retained knowledge to produce
enables the labourers to recreate the means of production. At times,
the technology (broadly here the technical ways and means of
producing goods and services which clearly embodies knowledge)
and its autonomous accumulation is taken as a rough index of FOP
and its development.
If FOP emphasise the material condition, the relations of
production (ROP) highlight (social) relations between people in
the process of producing goods and services with the help of a
given stock of FOP.7 More particularly, ROP takes a specific social
form, that of class relations which following Cohen is the basis/base/
foundation of society. More on ROP later. In HM, the Primacy
Thesis states that FOP is assumed to be exogenously given and
determines the ROP and everything that appears subsequently. The
primary relation in HM is thereby marked by FOP or technological
determinism.
One qualification before proceeding further. Scholars interpret
Marx as having used mode of production in different ways (Hindess
and Hirst, 1977; Cohen, 1978 and Harvey, 2010). For one, mode
of production is seen as the actual methods and techniques used
in production under the given forms of specialisation and division
of labour (material mode of production). Second, the mode of
production captures the social properties of production process in
the form of direct producer’s surplus labour and mode of exploitation
(social mode of production). Third, Marx would practically refer to
society (for example, in his work on ‘Grundrisse’), its entire technical
and social configuration, as a mode of production (the mixed mode
of production). Fourth, the mode of production is interpreted as
the specific articulation of FOP and ROP without incorporating
42 Global Political Economy
conferred or not. Those who have economic powers over the means
of production and labour power are assumed to have real or imputed
(as if ) ownership rights over them as well.
What about surplus labour and exploitation? While property
relation is predicated on economic power as we saw, exploitation (and
for that matter, surplus labour, without which exploitation cannot
be located) too is reducible to power relations. A correspondence
emerges: the class which more or less exercise economic power
necessarily exploits the class (i.e. excludes the direct producers
from the appropriation of surplus) who do not have that power.9
By reducing exploitation to relations of power structure, Cohen
displaces the focus upon exploitation per se by rendering the effects
and mechanisms flowing directly from the processes of surplus
labour as passive, waiting to be derived from, or reflected by, other
categories (property, power, etc.).
Cohen defines ‘economic structure’ as the sum total of coexisting
ROP. However, typically in HM, one class ROP is considered to
be dominant, with the others subordinated to it. The economic
structure of a society thereby comes to be designated by the dominant
ROP. The explanation of what happens to that society, its function
and the transition it undergoes is reducible to the extant dominant
ROP and its effects to which the other ROPs are subordinated, and
consequently the society gets its designated name from the identified
dominant ROP.10 For example, a feudal/capitalist society is one in
which the feudal/capitalist ROP is predominant. Or, to say that
the Indian economy is capitalist is to say so by the same reasoning.
Superstructure: Superstructure consists of only those political,
legal and cultural aspects of society (institutions and apparatuses of
state, law, education, religion, etc.) that enable the reproduction of
ROP. While FOP provide the natural/material foundation of ROP,
in turn ROP is the (economic) foundation on which culture and
political rises. For example, law facilitates the capitalist ROP by
securing for “capitalists effective power over means of production.
What confers them that power on a given capitalist, say an owner
of a factory? On what can he rely if others attempt to take control
of the factory away from him? An important part of the answer is
Introduction to Historical Materialism 45
this: he can rely on the law of the land, which is enforced by the
might of the state…The content of the legal system is explained by
its function, which is to help sustain an economy of a particular
kind” (Cohen, 1988, 9). However, to be careful, not everything is
part of the superstructure (such as singing among friends or art per
se if disconnected from a relation with ROP).
The significance, theoretical and practical, attached by Marxists
to the state has been extensively discussed. Whether wholly or
partially (with relative autonomy), the state is seen as an instrument
of political organisation of the ruling class, especially when it comes
to securing capitalist society. In many Marxian approaches it is at
times offered as a collective embodiment of all other elements of
superstructure. In those treatments, the objective of the state is
to create, regulate and control social institutions that will reflect,
justify, protect, serve and uphold the existing class relationship.
Lenin’s insistence on the centrality of the state in securing capitalist
ROP and the counter force of vanguard party needed to institute
a delinking between the two by capturing the state on behalf of
the working class was a benchmark moment in the history of the
20th century. However, without subsuming the entire superstructure
to the state, Cohen’s approach insists on maintaining the distinct
features and roles of each of the elements in the superstructure.
Nevertheless, the importance of the state in capitalist society is
flagged in his treatment.
Others such as, to name a few, Lukacs, Gramsci, Althusser,
Frankfurt school and Jameson have highlighted the importance of
cultural apparatuses pertaining to institutions of education, religion,
art and entertainment, advertisements, etc. These apparatuses create
a socialised system of production and dissemination of meanings,
symbols, rituals, morality, etc. that help rationalise and justify the
dominant ROP, say the capitalist ROP. The subjects are embodied
within these apparatuses, and their consciousness, history and
texture, constituted by their effects. Somewhat sidestepping Lenin’s
insistence on the centrality of the state, Gramsci in particular
insisted that it is these social apparatuses and their effects, and not
the state per se, that constitute the first and immediate firewall
46 Global Political Economy
between the forces and ROP within each complex society leads,
via class struggle to a process of selection of another type of ROP
conducive to the development of the FOP and subsequently new
superstructure and social consciousness that arises on the basis of
it. That is, contradiction in each society is resolved to give rise to a
new complex society—a higher form of the society that assimilates
the previous society—and subsequently develops another round
of contradiction within it. This new complex totality is a higher
moment in the qualitative sense that the FOP are freer to develop
and hence achieve higher material prosperity as compared to the
previous stage.
Clearly, this way of looking at history is teleological meaning
that parts of the structure/whole, of their relationship to one another
and of their transition, have an underlying purpose. This teleological
conception of transition induces a historicist logic: a rational,
ordered, progressive movement of society from a preordained origin
to a predestined end. The rational element is the essence—here,
the FOP; its development signals progress which is coterminous
with a higher order of society and this progressive movement starts
from a given point—primitive communism—and moves with a
law like ordered motion to end where history is destined to reach,
finally—communism. Steered on by the iron logic of functionalist
explanation, the transitional process is guided by an underlying
purpose of the development of the FOP such that, prodded by
it, every turn, bend and shift in stages comes to be explained in
terms of the more general journey of the society towards its destined
end—communism; ‘progress’ is judged by the proximity of a stage
to communism. That class is deemed revolutionary which drive the
movement of society forward and the one named reactionary is by
virtue of its intention to retain the existing one.
Can stages be skipped (say, skip stage 2 to go straight from 1 to
3)? Cohen argues against that possibility by defending the rationale
of the following proposition in Marx’s Preface: “No social formation
ever perishes before all the productive forces for which there is room
in it have developed; and new, higher ROP never appear before the
material conditions of their existence have matured in the womb
56 Global Political Economy
place a new class ROP that will provide ample scope for the arrested
FOP to develop freely once again and thus allow the new ruling
capitalist class to achieve a desirable level of surplus extraction. As
the previous revolutionary capitalist class becomes the new ruling
class, its ROP secures the rise of a new revolutionary class, the
working class; conflict between the two classes emerges. Thus, as
FOP changes, so does the class relationships of production, so does
the new elements of superstructure conducive to the new class ROP
leading to newer forms of class struggle and conflict in the new
society born out of the womb of the old and so history moves on
till its final station.
ROP is also laying down the working class interest that provides
it with the collective will for directing its specific course of action
along that line. Classes now become actors for class interests—
class-for-itself. In the historical plane, class actors with preformed
interest struggle with one another—clash of classes is a clash of class
interest—to fulfil their assigned goal and role in society and history.
The basic contour comprising the problem of class formation
in HM is then this linkage:
Structurally Given Class Position → Pre-Given Interest → Class
as Social Actors → Class Struggle.
From a different but related angle, the presence of working class
consciousness and actual consciousness of individual members of
working class signals a dichotomy that present a further complication.
Ideally, working class consciousness would automatically translate
into the consciousness of individuals holding that class position.
This is the concept of ‘imputed consciousness’ i.e. consciousness
reflecting the true (working class) interest that in turn is structurally
given. Since the working class is derived from a structural disposition,
the imputed consciousness reflects the intelligibility flowing from
the working class interest. Imputed consciousness is thus said to
have an objective basis. The problem is that while interest is said
to have an objective or structural basis it may not be necessarily
recognised by those whose interests they are presumed to be. The
actual consciousness may be in discord with the desirable true
interest personified in imputed consciousness. This difference is false
consciousness whose extent for any individual is a function of the
difference between true and false interest. The individuals holding
working class positions and hence belonging to the working class
may not recognise the “truth” of their class interest and consequently
of what their social and historical role ought to be.20 Class identity
as social actor with a collective will cannot be formed i.e. the class
formation problem from class in itself to class for itself cannot be
resolved in the presence of false consciousness.
Marxist practitioners working with some variant of HM model
with dual class dichotomy—starting from Lenin, Luxemburg,
Gramsci and Lukacs to many in contemporary times—have long
62 Global Political Economy
Conclusion
As stated in the introduction, my expansion of Cohen’s work to
present a prototype deterministic model was to unpack carefully
some of the basic positions and modes of analysis of HM. Variants
of this prototype HM model, more or less similar to it, have
flourished in Marxism and we have also recorded some line of
extensions, deviations and debates. Another embodied purpose had
been to prepare the readers to self-identify the channel through
which they can start to make sense of how and why deterministic
Introduction to Historical Materialism 65
6. Absorbing lessons from all the three broad approaches, thinkers and
practitioners from the erstwhile colonial countries have combined
what they find relevant in them with critical indigenous literature
and experience to highlight the importance of outside (say, world of
the third) in the constitution of (global) capitalism (Cesaire, 2010,
Chaudhury, Dhar and Chakrabarti, 2000, Dhar and Chakrabarti,
2019, Chakraborty, Chakrabarti, Dasgupta and Sen, 2019). We can
call theories emphasising this constitutive connection as world of the
third Marxism. In this paper, we do not pursue this brand of Marxian
theoretical field.
7. Alternatively, how FOP and ROP combines captures a critical
dimension of human-nature relation that is central to the reproduction
of both human life and natural life; this has given rise to a rich eco-
socialist literature in recent times (Saito, 2018).
8. Economic base is not to be confused with the essence of society (to
which we will come later).
9. See Resnick and Wolff (2006) and Chakrabarti and Cullenberg (2003)
for why this correspondence would not be true in a non-reductionist
class theory.
10. One of the richest formulations and debates on the issue of transition
and subordination of one ROP by another in the early 20th century
and the role of the nation-state in it has come from Japan (Walker,
2016).
11. This is not to say that Althusser, undisputedly influenced by Gramsci,
did not differ from him; for one, he did not accept the idea of
hegemony that Gramsci proposed.
12. Organic intellectual is not the same as vanguardism (to be discussed
later).
13. See Althusser (1969), for instance.
14. Interestingly, this puzzle is also acknowledged at the level of mode of
production and superstructure by Althusser (1969, 1975) who tries to
resolve the primacy of the former and the important role of the latter
through concepts such as ‘determination in the last instance’ of the
economic, ‘effectivity’, ‘relative autonomy’ and ‘reciprocal action.’ His
detailing of the mode of production can be found in Althusser (2014).
15. An example given by Cohen might be helpful for a preliminary
understanding of functional explanation. ‘Birds have hollow bones
because hollow bones facilitate flight.’ The functional explanation is:
68 Global Political Economy
That birds having hollow bones facilitate flight is explained by the fact
that it has the effect of facilitating flight.
16. This emphasis on human rationality in the face of scarcity bears
an uncanny affinity with the liberal tradition, particularly in the
neoclassical economics.
17. Cohen’s reduction of class ROP and class struggle to FOP was
criticised by many scholars of HM. They insisted on the primacy
of class struggle to resolve which ROP will appear as central in the
Marxian theory of history (for example, Brenner, 1986).
18. It must be said though that Cohen does not have much use for the
category of contradiction. In him, the aspect of (sub)optimality is a
good enough way of depicting the social (in)stability. I still use it here,
without compromising on Cohen’s rendition, to make the readers
aware of the manner of usage of contradiction in the historical sense
in deterministic Marxian theory.
19. Cohen argues that the changes in ROP, when they come, would be
revolutionary although it is not clear why his version of orthodox
Marxian would not be consistent with the revisionist approach in
Marxism. From the late 1890s onwards, Eduard Bernstein, especially
in Evolutionary Socialism and The History and Theory of Socialism
forwarded his revisionist Marxist approach, directing another path
of socialism, a peaceful road, which has had a lasting influence in
many parts of the world (Laclau and Mouffe, 1985). Following
Bernstein, the politics of socialism, influenced by Marx or otherwise,
became split into two roads: the revolutionary and the reformist path.
Following Bernstein, (i) socialism does not follow from the collapse of
capitalism (rejects inevitability), (ii) history is not an objective process
but interaction between objective and subjective (will) factors and (iii)
socialism is achieved through party programmes that requires an ethical
and not entirely scientific decision. This requires the autonomy of
ethical subject. The ethical subject is a (transcendental) subject. How is
it possible then to have a unification of economic and political? Here,
Bernstein forwards his evolutionary thesis entailing that the ethical
subject is also transcendental subject guided by, and adapting to the
laws of evolution. Thus, revisionism collapses into gradualism, and a
peaceful parliamentary path towards socialism within the purview of
the nation-state follows. For a critique of Bernstein’s position, see Rosa
Luxemburg’s Reform or Revolution.
20. Misrecognition is not the same as non-recognition, a difference we do
Introduction to Historical Materialism 69
not discuss any further except to say that the latter becomes important
in the literature on hegemony.
21. The vanguard party was assumed to uphold the pure interest of the
working class. As a result the interests of the working class and the
vanguard party became synonymous. Since the totality of the subject
directly translates the objective interest of the working class, the interest
of an individual holding a working class position should coincide with
that of the working class as a whole and the vanguard party. The
subject is represented by a working class that, in turn, is represented
by the vanguard party. Any dissent or revolt against the vanguard party
is considered a revolt against the working class and its true interests.
I leave it for the reader to count the effects and consequences of this
correspondence relation.
22. Lenin maintained historical subjects as personification of classes that
entails the presence of pure class identity. Luxemburg in “Mass Strike,
The Political Party and the Trade Unions” argued that one cannot
take, fix, a priori the meaning of the strike or party as moments in
the socialist transition; instead it is in the process of revolution—
through overdetermination of many struggles—that the unity of the
working class is achieved. Once the meaning of social events has
been unfixed, we get a unity—involving spontaneity—that cannot
be reduced to any necessity attributed to social and individual actions
derived from their structural position. Class identity cannot be taken
as given. However, Luxemburg still maintains that this composed
unity, achieved through overdetermination of many struggles, at
the political sphere is a class unity even though why it should be
referred to as so is not clear. This essentialism of class is also present in
Gramsci. Sharply distinguishing between the economic and political
sphere, he uses the conception of hegemonic articulation of non-class
and class relations in the formation of class subjects and politics. Yet,
he continues to maintain the reduction of this hegemony to the class
core in the economy (Laclau and Mouffe, 1985, Chapters 1 and 2). As
we understand, while both Luxemburg and Gramsci correctly identify
the problem and take the first basic step to break out of it (the same
is true for Althusser later on), the framework of historical materialism
within which they operate holds them back from resolving the
matter decisively. While the economy in the last instance haunted
their framework it is nevertheless true that the extraordinary phase
of political thought has in turn led to a fertile territory over which
theories, questions and debates continue to appear till today.
70 Global Political Economy
REFERENCE
Althusser, L. (1969 [1965]), For Marx, trans. Ben Brewster, Allen Lane:
The Penguin Press.
Althusser, L. and E. Balibar (1975), Reading Capital, London: Verso Books,
Indian edition (2013), Delhi: Aakar Books.
Althusser, L. (2014), On the Reproduction of Capitalism: Ideology and
Ideological State Apparatuses. London: Verso.
Brenner, R. (1986), The Social Basis of Economic Development, In J.E.
Roemer (ed.), Analytical Marxism, Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press.
Césaire, A. (2010 [2000]), Discourse on Colonialism, Translated by Joan
Pinkham, Delhi: Aakar Books.
Chakrabarti, A. and S. Cullenberg (2003), Transition and Development in
India, London and New York: Routledge.
Chakrabarti, A and A. Dhar (2017), Transition, In Brennan D., D.
Kristjanson-Gural, D.C. Mulder, and E. Olsen (eds.), Routledge
Handbook of Marxian Economics, New York and London: Routledge.
Chakrabarti, A. and A. Dhar (2019), Non-Violent Socialism: Marx and
Gandhi in Dialogue in Chakraborty A., A. Chakrabarti, B. Dasgupta
and S. Sen (eds.), ‘Capital’ in the East: Reflections on Marx, Singapore:
Springer Nature.
Chakrabarti, A., A. Dhar and S. Kayatekin (2020), Marx, Marxism and the
Spiritual, New York and London: Routledge.
Chakraborty A., A. Chakrabarti, B. Dasgupta and S. Sen (eds.), (2019),
‘Capital’ in the East: Reflections on Marx, Singapore: Springer Nature.
Chaudhury, A., D. Das and A. Chakrabarty (2000), Margin of Margin:
Profile of an Unrepentant Postcolonial Collaborator, Kolkata: Anushtup.
Cohen, G.A. (1978), Karl Marx’s Theory of History: A Defence, Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Cohen, G.A. (1986a), Forces of Production and ROP, In J.E. Roemer
(ed.), Analytical Marxism, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Cohen, G.A. (1986b), Marxism and Functional Explanation, In J.E. Roemer
(ed.), Analytical Marxism, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Cohen, G.A. (1988), History, Labour and Freedom, Oxford: Oxford
University Press
Dhar, A., and A. Chakrabarti (2019), Praxis in World of the Third
Contexts: Beyond Third Worldism and Development Studies, In E.
Introduction to Historical Materialism 71
The depression of the 1930s sent alarm signals and the neo-
classical economic theory was called into question. Keynesian
economics emerged out of that economic crisis. However, since
the 1950s, the ruling classes again restored legitimacy of market
forces and neo-classical economic thinking. However, the economic
and financial crisis of 2008 has again forced economists to have a
close look at the mainstream macroeconomics (Wolff and Resnick,
2012). The political economy approach and Marxian approach to
economic analysis, which have an interdisciplinary framework of
analysis of socio-economic phenomena, are again gaining popularity
in social sciences. Therefore, the need of the hour is to reappraise the
Marxian Political Economy and its method of analysis and explore
its explanatory power of the socio-economic phenomena.
2. Marx’s Method
The methodology evolved by Marx is perhaps his greatest
contribution, along with his study of capitalism. Marx’s method
of analysis was the abstract-deductive method. Concrete cannot
be understood without first being analysed into the abstract
relationships, which make it up. However, our ‘a priori’ construct
must be validated by empirical reality. Further, Marx adopted what
modern theorists call the method of ‘successive approximation’
which consists in moving from more abstract to more concrete in a
step by step fashion removing simplifying assumptions at successive
stages of the investigation so that theory may take into account and
explain an ever-wider range of actual phenomena.
Marx’s objective of study was to discover the ‘economic laws of
motion of capitalist society’. Marx came to an early realisation that
human progress was rooted in the material conditions of life and
anatomy of the civil society is to be sought in political economy.
Marxian formulation of these laws is radically different from
that of non-Marxian schools of thought (it embodies a different
epistemology of human knowledge). Marx retained the elements
of Hegel’s thought, which emphasised dynamics of a process and
development through the conflict of opposed or contradictory
forces (dialectical process). He traced decisive historical conflicts to
Essential Concepts in Marxian Political Economy 75
with other pre-bourgeois societies, then the question to ask is: how
is the process of appropriation of surplus, which is so transparent in
pre-bourgeois societies, effected in a bourgeois society where there is
formal equality, voluntary exchange among “free” commodity owners,
and equivalent exchange under free competition? The answer clearly
cannot be found in the sphere of circulation, which precisely is
the sphere where exchange is carried out among commodity owners
on an equal footing. The answer must lie beneath the sphere of
circulation, in the sphere of production itself. Surplus, Marx argued,
takes the form of “surplus value” in a bourgeois society, which arises
in the sphere of production itself. This surplus value is already
present in the higher value of the commodity capital with which the
capitalist emerges from the sphere of production, compared to what
he had thrown into it; it is realised, i.e. converted into money form,
in the sphere of circulation, through the sale of the commodity
which the production process yields.
Marx’s calling this process of surplus appropriation “exploitation”
has misled many into thinking of Marxism as being based on some
Lockean “natural rights” doctrine. Marx’s theory is often believed
to have postulated that workers are “cheated” out of their “just
share”. Such an interpretation however is incorrect. Marx’s approach
was historical not moral. He held Proudhon’s dictum “property is
theft” to be absurd, since the term “property” referred merely to
the prevalent social rules governing the appropriation of the fruits
of production. There could never be social production without
such rules, i.e. without “property”. The transcendence of capitalism
meant not the abolition of property as Proudhon thought, but the
substitution of socialist property for capitalist property. Likewise
the proposition that society needed capital but could do without
capitalists, so that the latter constituted a bunch of parasites
appropriating a part of the product that “justly” belonged to the
workers, is not a Marxian proposition; it belongs to the theoretical
corpus of Ricardian socialists like Hodgskin. For Marx the concept
of “surplus value” is not based on any postulation of a “norm” or of
a notion of “fair share” relative to which the workers get less. It is a
part of a historical datum.
Notes on Marx’s Critique of Classical Political Economy 95
the two as a linked totality; and hence it could not even properly
pursue its journey beyond “appearances”.
There are three obvious ways that this failure manifested itself:
first, classical political economy could not see surplus value as a
single homogeneous category. Surplus value as such is never visible;
what is visible are the different forms in which it manifests itself,
viz. profit, rent, and interest. It took each of these manifestations as
separate and investigated the determination of each, but did not see
them as forms in which surplus value appears, and hence did not see
the category called surplus value. Secondly, “price” is what prevails
in the market, in the sphere of circulation. Underlying these “prices”
however are “values” which are not visible and which arise from the
fact that any commodity embodies a certain amount of homogeneous
social labour. Commodities do not exchange at their values because
if they did then the rates production would be different, because of
which prices represent a “modification” of values. Instead of seeing
the totality of this inter relationship, classical political economy in
the person of Ricardo (who represented its highest development)
talked eclectically of “two determinants” of prices: the total labour
embodied in a commodity and its time-distribution in the production
of that commodity. In the process therefore it obscured the origins
of value and surplus value, including whatever insights it had itself
developed. Thirdly, this mixing up of levels meant that it could not
locate the origin of surplus value in the sphere of production. In fact
it did not pursue the question of the origin of surplus value, which
prevented its seeing capitalism in the same historical light in which
it had seen pre-bourgeois societies.
If surplus value emerges in the sphere of production, then it
follows that capitalism must be characterised by a duality: on the
one hand like all modes of production it must be characterised
by “production in general” at the core of which is the man-
nature dialectic but in which, since men act socially, the general
needs of social production must be getting met. On the other
hand however there must be the specific capitalist stamp on the
production process, which must be highly sui generis because of the
very opaqueness of the mode of production. This duality which
Notes on Marx’s Critique of Classical Political Economy 97
capitalism came into being, i.e. “the two very different kinds of
commodity-possessors” were originally formed (the process of the
so-called “primitive accumulation of capital” which was based on a
concept of Adam Smith but acquired a precision because of Marx’s
relational approach). He unearthed the antagonistic character of
capitalism (the fact that surplus value accrued to a particular class
behind the facade of equality in the marketplace), and hence its
necessarily transient presence in history. Above all, however, Marx
drew attention to the spontaneous character of capitalism, and the
profound implications of that spontaneous character.
The idea of the bourgeois society being a “self-acting economic
order” (with the implicit inference that it did not interference from
kings and priests) was first advanced by the French Physiocrats
and was taken over by English Classical Political Economy. The
latter conceptualised this economic order differently: the myriads
of decisions taken by individuals, each motivated by self-interest,
produces not chaos but an order, and, what is more, a benevolent
order, which is governed by objective laws independent of human
will and consciousness and capable of being scientifically discovered.
The view that the aggregation of self-interest-based individual
actions yields something unintended by the individual participants,
had once again a clear parallel in Hegelian philosophy: “The
whole is not the sum of the parts.” And implicit in this view was
a recognition also of the spontaneous character of capitalism, its
“self-acting” property.
While Marx took over this basic perception of capitalism as a
spontaneous, law-governed system, his break from Classical Political
Economy made him comprehend the system not as benevolent,
but as anarchic, crisis-prone, and subject to a unique trajectory of
development. Any system of commodity production necessarily
produces differentiation among producers. This is true of capitalism
as well. “One capitalist kills many”. Typically that “one capitalist” is
the one controlling large capital. Large capital in other words drives
out small capitals because of which every capital wishes to become
large through accumulation. Marx, in other words, visualised a
Darwinian struggle among capitalists which makes accumulation an
Notes on Marx’s Critique of Classical Political Economy 99
is not looking for one theory of this kind. His concern is not with
the quantitative trajectory of capitalism, but with its qualitative
trajectory, with changes in its relational aspects. When he is
discussing these, there are no apparent contradictions whatsoever.
Having two different kinds of “laws” is thus in conformity with
Marx’s overall approach.
While capitalism creates the condition for its own transcendence,
the precise manner of that transcendence requires revolutionary
political intervention in a particular conjuncture (when revolution
“comes on the agenda”). The first question that arises in this context
is: when does the revolutionary stage arrive? Marx does not give
a concrete answer to this question (though Lenin was to do so
later). From Marx’s remark that “No social order is ever destroyed
before all the productive forces for which it is sufficient have been
developed”, it might appear as if material circumstances alone
determine whether a revolutionary transformation has appeared
on the agenda; but this is not true. Marx also remarked: “Of all
the instruments of production, the greatest productive power is the
revolutionary class itself. The organisation of revolutionary elements
as a class supposes the existence of all the productive forces which
could be engendered in the bosom of the old society.” This suggests
that the working class’ organising itself into a revolutionary force, a
process intimately linked to the development of its consciousness,
is the true index of the revolution coming on the agenda, a much
more open-ended formulation.
The second question that arises is: how does the working class
acquire revolutionary consciousness? Again, Marx does not discuss
this issue concretely (which Lenin was to do later). But Marx
too drew a distinction between “trade union consciousness” and
“revolutionary class consciousness”. Lenin’s idea that the latter had
to be introduced “from outside” figures already in the Manifesto.
In addition there is the suggestion in The Poverty of Philosophy that
the working class, in the course of its own economic struggles, also
tends spontaneously to develop a political consciousness, in so far as
it is increasingly confronted by state power that comes to the aid of
the capitalists even in the course of economic struggles.
Notes on Marx’s Critique of Classical Political Economy 101
The third question that arises is: why should capitalism be,
according to Marx, the last antagonistic mode of production? If
arrival of capitalism, represented a flawed perspective, then why
should Marxism, which saw the end of capitalism as the end of
antagonism, not be accused of the same error? Putting it differently,
what is so specific about capitalism that its end, unlike the end of
earlier modes of production, signals the end of antagonism? Marx’s
answer to this was as follows: capitalism is the first antagonistic
mode of production where the most directly oppressed class is
simultaneously the most revolutionary class. This fact, which has
to do with the spontaneous nature of capitalism, discussed earlier,
creates a unique situation in human history.
Lenin, as already mentioned, gave concrete answers to many
of these very questions, and did so via his theory of imperialism.
Revolution comes on the agenda in the era of imperialism which is
punctuated by wars that give the working class in each country one
and only one choice: either to kill fellow workers across trenches or
to turn the gun against capitalism in one’s own country. Imperialism
moreover presupposes the completion of the partitioning of the
globe among a handful of imperialist powers; hence all these wars
entail the use of the colonial and oppressed people as “cannon-
fodder” even as they are trained as fighters. They too are given only
one choice: either kill fellow-oppressed people across trenches, or
train the guns on the colonial masters. Not only does the era of
imperialism then signify the beginning of social revolution, but it
generates and brings together two different, independent and inter-
linked revolutionary streams: a workers’ revolution in the metropolis
and an anti-colonial struggle in the periphery. (The recognition of
these two streams is already there in Marx and Engels though they
thought for most of their lives that a European revolution was on
the immediate agenda).
How, it may be asked, do we critique Marx’s critique of
Classical Political Economy today? Marx’s critique is incomplete
in one crucial respect, which, though it might not have appeared
important at the time (when all attention was in any case focused
on a European revolution), cannot be ignored today. And this is his
102 Global Political Economy
Introduction
The financial crisis of 2008, followed by recession in the world
economy, has put a question mark on the stability and working
of capitalist economic system. The debate among the pro-people
intellectuals has once again intensified to expose the real character
of capitalism. There is no better work than Marx’s Capital to
meet this objective. Marx’s Capital is a comprehensive critique of
classical political economy that is primarily concerned with the
working of the capitalist mode of production. The best method
to understand capitalism is to examine what differentiate it from
pre-capitalist societies. Like the pre-capitalist modes (slavery and
feudalism), capitalism is also a class society. The fundamental
difference between capitalism and pre-capitalist societies is that the
method of exploitation in pre-capitalist societies rested upon the
direct domination by the owner of the means of production and
the method of exploitation was quite visible. For example, slaves
were the property of their master and the master exploited the
slaves directly. The relations of production in a slave society were
based on the master’s ownership of the means of production (the
land, instruments of labour, labourers- the slaves). Slaves were not
considered more than just an instrument of production. As Marx
(1970) argued “the slave did not sell his labour power to the master,
any more than ox its service to the peasant. The slave, together with
his labour power, has been sold once and for all to his owner.”
Capitalist Mode of Production: A Basic Interpretation 105
20 yards of linen
1 coat
10 lbs. of tea = Worth 2 ounces of gold
40 lbs of coffee
1 quarter of corn
The important point that one should note is that in the
above discussion of value, Marx reached the most modern form
of value, i.e. the money-form, through conceptual development of
relationships without discussing the historical facts and figures of its
evolution. In a commodity dominated economy, the money-form
appears because the commodity owner does not wish to exchange
his commodity for any arbitrary commodity, but rather for definite,
particular commodities. The overall scheme of the main categories
discussed by Marx in Part-I of Capital Vol. I unfolds as follows:
M=C
CХ > C therefore CХ > M
CХ = MХ therefore MХ > M
The time spent by capital in the production process is the ‘time
of production’. The time spend by capital in the circulation process,
whether in the form of money capital seeking commodity sellers
or as commodity capital seeking buyers, is capital’s ‘turnover time’.
Capital that passes through the above three forms (money capital,
productive capital and commodity capital) is characterised by Marx
as industrial capital. In this sense, capital investment in services also
belongs to the category of industrial capital. The main difference
consists in the fact that the finished product is not a ‘material
object’ acting as independent commodity capital (Heinrich, 2012).
In Marxian scheme this can be written as follows:
MP
M—C—P—MХ
L
In the above process CХ is missing because a service is consumed
simultaneously with its production. Hence pure merchant capital
such as trading capital, commercial capital etc., and interest bearing
capital which includes banking and insurance services do not belong
to the category of industrial capital. These activities appropriate a
share of surplus value, but the production of surplus value does
not belong to their capital function (Heinrich, 2012). Thus, the
economy ruled by the capitalist commodity production, capital
enters into various levels of circuits in order to realise the surplus
value.
Capitalist Production Process and Surplus Extraction
The main objective of the capitalist production process is to extract
the surplus. Within the capitalist process of production, the labour
process exhibits two distinctive characteristics: first, it proceeds
under the control of the capitalist, and second the product of the
labour process is the property of the capitalist. As we explained in
the previous section, the general formula for capital is M—C—MХ
116 Global Political Economy
time. Marx calls this way of enlarging of surplus value the relative
surplus value. The relative surplus value can be intensified by either
lowering the real wages or increasing the productivity of labour,
leading to a reduction of necessary labour time.
There are three visible ways for capitalist to increase the relative
surplus value:
(1) Cooperation among workers in the production process.
(2) Division of labour or specialisation of production activities
in order to enhance the efficiency; and
(3) Speeding up labour or mechanisation of production process.
The first two ways to increase the surplus value have natural
limits. The third way that is the mechanisation of production
process produces the fear of technological unemployment that was
also realised by Ricardo (2006) prior to Marx and Keynes (1933)
after him.5 The change in technical composition of capital, as
Marx (1992) argued, results in the growth in mass of the means
of production, as compared with the mass of labour power. It
changes the value composition of capital by increase of constant
constituent of capital at the expense of its variable constituent. This
process what is prevalent at different scale in different industries
and countries inevitably produces reserve army of labour hourly and
daily. In other words, owing to the introduction of machines in the
production process, demand for labour power declines, that results
in involuntary unemployment. The mass of workers who are willing
to sell their labour power at prevailing wages but are not able find
any work are referred by Marx as the ‘reserve army of labour’.
The labour displacing technology is an important feature of an
economy ruled by capital. In a capital-dominant society, in order
to valorise its produce, an individual producer interacts with other
producers in the market. The circuits of individual capitals intervene
and presuppose one another. The reproduction of an individual
capital does not take place in isolation. The total reproduction of
individual capital is part of the reproduction of total social capital.
The total social capital can be reproduced under the condition that
a certain amount of means of production is required by individual
capitals as a whole, and so as many means of subsistence have to
118 Global Political Economy
they accomplish their task with least expenditure of energy and under
conditions most adequate to their human nature and most worthy of
it.’ This is quite a humanistic and positive conception, which Marx
referred to as the aim of communist society.
The other conception which we have witnessed is communism
as the nationalisation of the means of production and centrally
planned economy. The Soviet Union’s attempt in the 20th century
is regarded as in accordance of this conception of communism. The
collapse of the Soviet Union is falsely propagated as a proof for
the failure of Marx’s idea of communism. However, that was one
attempt (but not the last attempt) towards socialism and can be
called as Soviet style socialism. In The Communist Manifesto of Marx
and Engels and Engels’s Anti-Duhring, one can clearly find that the
nationalisation of production is a first step and never the last to
build a communist society.
Marx’s project of communism was concerned with the
comprehensive emancipation of human beings from the social nexus
and fetish social order that takes on a life of its own and imposes
itself upon individuals as an anonymous compulsion. Not only
should the capital relations as a specific characteristic of exploitation
that generates bad and insecure working and living conditions for
the majority of population be overcome, but the fetishism that
attaches to the products of labour as soon as they are produced
as commodities should also be abolished. Social emancipation, the
liberation from self-produced and therefore gratuitous constraints, is
only possible when the social relations that generate the various forms
of fetishism have disappeared. The members of such a society would
have to regulate their social life, organise production in individual
workplace, coordinate between workplaces, harmonius interactions
as producers and consumers, have harmony with nature, find ways
of dealing with minority positions, different forms of discrimination
and inequality. The communist project which Marx and Engels have
visualised is an outcome of their concrete understanding of working
of capitalism. It is the responsibility of pro-people intellectuals
to explore the real foundation of capitalism and its exploitative
character and work towards and alternative social order.
Capitalist Mode of Production: A Basic Interpretation 125
NOTES
1. This paper is a revised and updated version of article published in
2017 in Critique: Journal of Socialist Theory, Vol. 43, No. 3, pp. 409-
26, titled ‘Understanding Marx’s Capital’.
2. The specific character of particular type of labour can be defined as,
for example, carpentry produces a chair; linen weaving produces a
linen sheet. Concrete labour is the basis on which we differentiate
products of different labour.
3. The term labour power refers to the ability of human beings to
perform labour. So labour is application of labour power.
4. This volume is further subdivided into three parts: The Metamorphoses
of Capital and Their Circuits; The Turnover of Capital; and The
Reproduction and Circulation of the Aggregate Social Capital.
5. It was first highlighted by Ricardo (2006 [1817]) with an argument
that due to the introduction of machinery in production process, no
doubt, the one fund, i.e. net income, from which the capitalist class
derives their revenue in the form of profits, may increase, but other
funds, i.e. gross income from which the labour class is employed,
may diminish. Capital formation or investment in the forms of
introduction of new machinery will reduce the funds to employ
labour. Ricardo’s fundamental proposition was that capitalists do not
employ the new machinery from their shares of profits, i.e. net income
but from the gross part of revenue. The introduction of machinery in
the production process has two effects- one, it reduces the availability
of funds for the employment of labour and second, it also reduces the
requirement of labour for given production unit. Thus, it has a positive
effect of saving labour for the capitalist class along with a negative
effect on working masses in the form of redundancy of labour from
production process. No doubt, the technological revolution during in
19th and beginning of 20th century had resulted in sustained increase
in the material standard of living but fears of adverse employment
consequences of technological advancement had also been aggravated
in the 20th century. This fear was also raised by Keynes during the
era of the Great Depression with a prediction that in the near future
we may be able to perform all the operations of agriculture, mining,
and manufacturing with a quarter of the human effort. But the rapid
change will bring a new disease, namely, technological unemployment
(Keynes, 1963 [1933]).
126 Global Political Economy
REFERENCES
Fine, B. and A. Saad-Filho (2014), Marx’s Capital, New Delhi: Viva Books.
Foley, D.K. (1986), Understanding Capital: Marx’s Economic Theory,
Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Heinrich, M. (2012), An Introduction to the Three Volumes of Karl Marx’s
Capital, New York: Monthly Review Press, Indian edition (2013),
Delhi: Aakar Books.
Keynes, J.M. (1963 [1933]), Economic Possibilities for Our Grand-
children, In Essays in Persuasion, pp. 358-76, London: W.W. Norton
& Co.
Marx, K. (1970), Wage, Labour and Capital, In Selected Works, Vol. I,
Moscow: Progress Publishers.
Marx, K. (1992), Capital: A Critique of Political Economy, Vol. I, London:
Penguin Books.
Marx, K. (1956), Capital: A Critique of Political Economy, Vol. II, Moscow:
Progress Publishers.
Marx, K. (1959), Capital: A Critique of Political Economy, Vol. III, Moscow:
Progress Publishers.
Marx, K. (1961), The Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts, in
E. Fromm (eds.), Marx’s Concept of Man, London: Continuum
Publications.
Marx, K. and F. Engels (2002), The Communist Manifesto, London:
Penguin Books.
Ricardo, D. (2006 [1817]), On Principles of Political Economy and Taxation,
Third Edition, Canada: Ontario: Reprinted by Batoche Books.
Sheikh, A. (1991), Economic Crisis, pp. 160-64, In T. Bottomore et al.
(eds.), A Dictionary of Marxist Thought, London: Blackwell Publishers
Ltd.
Sweezy, P.M. (1942), Theory of Capitalist Development, New York: Monthly
Review Press, Indian edition (2016), Delhi: Aakar Books.
5
Contemporary Capitalism
Greg Albo
Capitalist Development
Development in capitalist societies takes the general form of
accumulated money-capital being continually reinvested in
expanding means of production and the purchase of labour power
for the purpose of increasing the amount of value accumulated as
money. The unending search for profits leads to specific tendencies
of development, or ‘laws of motion’ of capitalism. This accumulation
implies a continual transformation of the commodities, social
relations and class struggles; and thus in the ‘social forms’ which
mediate the tendencies of the capitalist mode of production in
concrete history. A number of these tendencies have figured,
repeatedly, in debates about contemporary capitalism.
First, Marxian political economy identifies the labour process
as the location for the extraction of surplus value from workers, the
organisation of production, the changing form of the subsumption
of workers, the contestation over work-time and the development
of the forces of production. The history of capitalism is defined by
transformations internal to the labour process in terms of skills,
technology, work organisation and conflict over work control
(Braverman, 1974). Thus the development of the modern factory
system or the implementation of Taylorist work organisation and
Fordist assembly-line production have often been hailed as the central
features defining contemporary capitalism and its dominant mode
of capital accumulation. The changes in the labour process from the
adoption of new computer technologies in workplaces, for example,
Contemporary Capitalism 131
is also entails stratification, that is, the increasing role of the state
in ensuring the reproduction of capital through infrastructure,
support for education and research and development and economic
coordination. The social forms of state economic intervention,
the technical organisation of state apparatuses and the relations
between branches of the state vary considerably. For example,
during the post-war phase of capitalism the wage-relation was often
directly inserted into the state via incomes policies and corporatist
institutions such that the nominal reference wage was formed via
political mediations as opposed to market mechanisms. But more
recently, state policies helped recompose the reserve army of labour
and market disciplines were reasserted in wage formation. The self-
expansion logic of capital remains, but the social form of the state
and its political mediations become indispensible in locating the
most contemporary features of capitalism.
Introduction
In any capitalist economy, the total labour force can be divided
into two parts—the active army of labour and the reserve army of
labour. The former consists of those that are currently employed in
capitalist enterprises; the latter, which Marx calls the ‘relative surplus
population’, consists of those that are not currently employed in
capitalist enterprises but are potentially available for employment,
if the need arises.
This dual division of the labour force into the active and reserve
armies of labour is a characteristic feature of capitalism. Other than in
exceptional situations, e.g. during and immediately after the Second
World War in the US and Europe, a significantly-sized reserve army
of labour is a permanent fixture of capitalist economies. In fact, the
reserve army is produced by the logic of capitalist production.
“But in fact it is capitalist accumulation itself that constantly
produces, and produces indeed in direct relation to its own energy
and extent, a relatively redundant working population, i.e. a
population which is superfluous to capital’s average requirements
for its own valorisation, and is therefore a superfluous population”
(Marx, 1992, 782).
The implication of the continued existence of the reserve
army of labour in capitalist economies is striking: these economies
typically do not employ all of its potential labour force. A portion
of the available labour force is almost always left unemployed, or
is marked by different degrees of attachment to the labour force,
Reserve Army of Labour 141
of why this does not come to pass. When capital accumulation picks
up and the demand for labour power rises, the result is an increase
in real wage rates. Rising incomes lead to increasing prosperity of
the working class, which, in turn, increases the fertility rate. As the
population rises, it gradually increases the supply of labour power.
This increase in the supply eventually overtakes the rising demand
for labour power. The excess supply of labour power then pulls
down the real wage rate (Sweezy, 1942).
Marx never accepted the validity of this theory of population,
and he certainly did not use it for answering the above question. With
the benefit of hindsight we can see that the Malthusian population
theory is grossly inadequate in addressing the above question. Over
long periods of time, increasing prosperity has been accompanied
by falling, and not rising, fertility rates. This is exactly the opposite
of the Malthusian claim. Resting on empirically dubious claims, the
Malthusian-Ricardian explanation just does not cut ice.
The Data
The starting point for estimating the reserve army of labour (RAL) is
the civilian non-institutional population (CIV). CIV is an estimate
of every person 16 years and above who is neither in an institution
(prison or mental health institution) nor on active duty in the US
Armed Forces. Based on detailed interviews, conducted on a sample
of roughly 60,000 households every month, the CPS assigns every
person in CIV to either of three pools:
The pool of employed workers (EMP): these are the persons
who reported doing any wage or salary work (either full-time or
part-time) at the time of the interview; or, they reported as having
done self employed work; or, they reported that they had a job but
were not at work currently due to vacation, illness, etc.; or, they
reported that they were doing unpaid family work;
The pool of unemployed workers (UNEMP): These are the
people who reported that they did not have a job currently and had
actively looked for a job in the previous 4 weeks (with reference to
the time of the interview).
The pool of those who are not in the labour force (NLF): These
are the persons who fall neither into the category of employed workers
(EMP), nor can be counted as being unemployed (UNEMP).
While it is obvious that all the unemployed workers would be
part of any measure of the RAL, the question as to which part of the
NLF should be included in the RAL requires some more analysis.
Based on answers to questions in the CPS, the NLF can be divided
into two broad groups: (a) those who reported that they want a job,
and (b) those who reported that they do not want a job. The second
category was by far the largest component of NLF, and was primarily
150 Global Political Economy
Conclusion
A characteristic feature of capitalist economies is the existence of a
part of the labour force as unemployed or precariously attached to
the labour force. The history of capitalism shows that, other than in
exceptional periods, e.g. immediately after the Second World War,
capitalist economies are unable to provide adequate employment,
in terms of quality and quantity, to all those in the labour force.
Mainstream economics tries to explain the existence of what it terms
‘structural’, i.e. long run, unemployment by taking recourse to
various types of ‘frictions’; Keynesian economics sees in inadequate
aggregate demand the reason for short run unemployment. The
Marxist tradition offers an alternative explanation that encompases
both short run and long run factors.
Marxist analysis highlights the division of the labour force in
Reserve Army of Labour 155
any capitalist economy into two parts, the active army of labour
(those employed) and the reserve army of labour (those unemployed
and those attached to the labour force in various degrees but wishing
to be employed). The existence of the reserve army of labour is a
structural necessity of capitalism because this is the key mechanism
through which the system keeps the price of labour power within
bounds necessary for the generation and accumulation of surplus
value. While the reserve army of labour fluctuates with the pace of
capital accumulation, it can never disappear—without undermining
the whole capitalist structure of production and authority.
The continual existence and reproduction of the reserve army
of labour is a severe indictment of capitalism. Unemployment or
precarious attachment to the labour force imposes enormous costs on
individual workers and on the whole of society (Helliwell and Huang,
2014). The fact that even the most advanced capitalist economies
are unable to permanently solve the problem of unemployment
should be part of the arsenal of post-capitalist imaginaries. After
all, socialist economies, with all their problems, had completely
eliminated the problem of unemployment. For instance, there was
virtually no unemployment at the aggregate level in the USSR after
the 1930s (Kotz and Weir, 1997).
Of course, the problem of the reserve army of labour is of an
altogether different magnitude in the periphery of the global capitalist
system. The vast majority of these countries, in what is now referred
to as the developing world, have not even managed to absorb large
fractions of their labour force into the orbit of capitalist production.
The overwhelming majority of working people are ‘employed’ in
various ways in the ‘informal sector’. From a Marxist perspective, a
significant part of the informal sector represents the latent reserve
army of labour. For instance, small-scale peasant production and
petty commodity production outside agriculture, both important
components of the informal sector, represent a large pool of labour
engaged in commodity (or non-commodity) production under
non-capitalist relations of production. It can be drawn on if capital
accumulation picks up.
But various types of structural constraints, both internal and
156 Global Political Economy
The employment of labour force has never been the main concern
of capitalism despite the fact that labour used to be the only source
of value creation. Classical economists as well as Keynes and Marx
held the view that labour is the source of creative activity that adds
value to existing inputs. But a society which is primarily driven
by realisation of exchange value recognises work only when it
creates commodities. Capitalism is a world of commodities where
producers produce goods not for their own use but to sell their
produce in exchange of money that assumes the form of universal
exchange value. Labour is exchanged in the form of labour power
or the capacity to produce some goods or services for sale and that
is the only mode of work recognisable in the world of commodities.
Any work which is an expenditure of mind and energy but
primarily creates use value for the producer is not being counted as
productive value addition in capitalism. Capitalism therefore is not
only a system of producing and exchanging commodities but also
is typical of making labour power a commodity. Employment is the
engagement of labour power as commodity purchased by a typical
employer. In this process of selling labour power or the capacity to
work for a defined time or output based contract, the act of labour
is controlled by the employer and hence the autonomy of labour
as a creative human being seizes to exist. The worker is alienated
not only from the means of production which are owned by the
capitalist but also from the labour process which is controlled by
Political Economy of Employment-Unemployment in Capitalism 159
Capitalism: Employment-Unemployment
Marx begins his magnum opus Capital with the discussion
on commodity as that is the primary unit of capitalist social
construction. Goods and services are produced for sale and exchange
value of the produce predominates and defines its use. A good has
to be useful to others not to the producer, only then it can assume
exchange value. But goods and services produced for the use of
the producer is outside the ambit of capital relations. Similarly, a
human being who is employed by someone else assumes exchange
value and paid wages while if someone works or produces for his
or her own satisfaction would not be considered as employed and
rightly so because the person would not be able to earn a living in
capitalism. Employment therefore refers to a state where a person’s
work is worth for the society and someone is prepared to buy that
work in exchange of money. But what actually motivates someone
to work for others to earn a living? The simple answer is when
the person has no other alternative means to survive. In a self-
sustained community there are relations of reciprocity where people
are dependent on each other where there may be division of labour
but the motivation for production was primarily of community use.
So peasants and artisans, craftsmen and priests all had their defined
roles which were asymmetric but no one was employed by others.
The social hierarchy was visible where the status of men and women
were defined by their position in the occupational structure. To
make people work for others, one should be ripped off from his or
her own way of living, from the community in which the individual
exists and, most importantly, the means of production which s/he
owns. Then only can one be forced to work for others so as to make
both ends meet. Therefore, this particular category of people who
sell their capacity to work to others or need employment to survive
is a historical construct defined by Marx as primitive accumulation
of capital (Marx, 1958). The act was a forcible separation of direct
producers from their means of production which created the
original accumulation of capital. But this process of creating labour
power to be used in capitalist enterprises can be sustained only
Political Economy of Employment-Unemployment in Capitalism 161
and since these two growth rates are determined by factors that are
independent and separated, it is always possible that the emerging
production process would involve less and less direct labour. In
other words, the competitive instinct of capitalists to innovate and
the natural growth of labour force may diverge from each other
giving rise to a structural problem of unemployment.
On the other hand, accumulation in capitalism is driven by
increasing growth of investment often stimulated by growth of
potential markets that kindles the expectation of higher profits.
Capital is essentially a self-augmenting process and can continue as
capital when it expands its value. This creates the unending drive
to internalise non-capitalist space into its own ambit. But the same
process also brings a huge labour force as well as natural resources
which were earlier beyond the access of capital. Whether this labour
force would be employed or not or if employed in what differential
terms depends on diverse historical and conjectural factors. But what
seems to be certain in this erratic process that a huge number of
labour force is at the behest of capital and plays a significant function
in the dynamics of capitalism. Marx calls it relative overpopulation
constituting the industrial reserve army of labour. Expanding
capital with increasing scale of operation recruits more labour in
the process of production but with increasing use of machines and
new technology in the same process also ‘sets free’ existing labour.
Marx contradicts with Malthus that it is not the absolute number
of population that sets limits to production but more importantly
it is the relative overpopulation caused by the ‘inclusion-exclusion’
of the labour force that is crucial for the accumulation process of
capitalism. To quote Marx, “The production of a relative surplus
population, or the setting free of labourers, goes on therefore
yet more rapidly than the technical revolution of the process of
production that accompanies, and is accelerated by, the advance of
accumulation; and more rapidly than the corresponding diminution
of the variable part of capital as compared with the constant. If the
means of production, as they increase in extent and effective power,
become to a less extent means of employment of labourers, this
state of things is again modified by the fact that in proportion as
Political Economy of Employment-Unemployment in Capitalism 165
countries declined from 66.1 per cent in the early 1990s to 61.7
per cent in the late 2000s (IMF, 2017, 127). In the developing
world because of this relocation not many new jobs were created
as expected. This is because the sectors which attracted new foreign
investments are labour-intensive according to Western standards
but not so according to developing country standards. As a result,
relocation in fact increased the average capital intensity of industries
in the developing world.
Moreover, the process of globalisation facilitated concentration
of capital through cross border mergers and acquisitions on the one
hand and fragmentation on the other. MNCs and TNCs control
the production networks in which developing country production
facilities are inserted as a result of which local monopolies are
destroyed and local capital lost control over the production structure
and became junior partners in actualising the imperatives of global
capital. Because of the global integration, technology choices are
hardly available for local industries. The tastes and preferences of
Western markets create hegemonies as a result of which technologies
available in the global shelf are largely incorporated in domestic
production structures to sustain competition. In this process, local
capital prefer to face competition only on the basis of pushing down
wages in order to reduce production costs. This gives rise to a labour
process which increasingly relies on casualisation and informalisation
of labour. In the case of India during the period March 2014 to
July 2015, there had been an addition of 0.32 million in organised
manufacturing. Notable is the fact that out of this total new
employment created in the organised manufacturing, 85 per cent has
been contracted workers. In the case of unorganised manufacturing,
the only segment that recorded growth in employment is the Own
Account Manufacturing Enterprises (OAMEs) which are basically
one person enterprises meaning self-employed who do not hire any
labour and mostly employ unpaid family labour. According to the
NSSO survey on Unincorporated Non-Agricultural Enterprises
(excluding construction), total employment in unregistered
manufacturing increased from 34.8 million in November 2010 to
36.04 million in 2015-16, an increase of 1.24 million in five years
Political Economy of Employment-Unemployment in Capitalism 169
(NSSO, 2017). The rise has been higher in OAMEs to the tune of
1.84 million, while employment declined in establishments that are
relatively larger in size within the unregistered segment that employ
one to ten hired workers, which have employed 0.67 million less
workers during the same period. Increased informalisation and
casualisation was facilitated by rising subcontracting in the domestic
production process which not only reduces the wage costs but also
transfers a part of wage cost to capitalist profits. Although it is not
true that pushing down wages is the only way to remain competitive
in the global market. Competition works rather on the basis of unit
labour cost which is a combined effect of labour productivity and
wages. If the productivity of the worker rises faster than the growth
of wages, unit labour costs tend to decline. In case of India the
return to labour has been squeezed in the organised sector even
though their productivity increased much faster. In fact, such a
trend of relying more on informal contracts reduces the average
productivity over time. In case of India, productivity of labour in
the informal sector is on an average one-seventh of those working
in the formal sector. Thus as informal work contracts increase, a
downward trend in productivity may also set in.
One of the distinctive features of the employment-unemployment
scenario in today’s world is the rising proportion of self-employed
within the workforce. In case of India, it remained consistently
more than half the workforce independent of growth fluctuations
(Roy, 2011). The general perception has been that during high
growth periods, the demand for labour increases and proportion of
wage employment rises within the workforce. On the other hand
slackening of growth reduces demand for labour and proportion
of self-employment rises as many existing workers lose their jobs
and opt for self-employment as a survival strategy. But during the
recent period the weakening of growth-employment linkage has
also disrupted the relation between growth and self-employment.
In other words, the high share of self-employment has become a
structural feature of contemporary capitalism and not only confined
to developing countries anymore. This raises a conceptual problem
as well which is the following. If capitalism accumulates on the
170 Global Political Economy
basis of surplus value and that is extracted from wage labour who
sells labour power as a commodity then how do we appreciate this
high share of self-employed even in situations of high growth? Self-
employment is also portrayed as a rise in entrepreneurship where the
producer has control over the means of production and the process
of production. In spite of the fact that even the self-employed
person apparently carries a sense of autonomy but in countries
such as India, most of the self-employed face greater uncertainty
and vulnerability than the wage employed. For the wage worker, at
least in the medium term payment of wages cannot depend on the
realisation of value or sale of produced goods or services. It is part
of a contract where the worker is supposed to get wages against
work for stipulated labour hours. In case of self-employed this is not
the case. The return of the self-employed can only be realised once
the value of produced goods and services are realised. Furthermore,
self-employment as a non-capital relation does not invoke exchange
based on equivalence of value as it is in the realm of capital relations.
But non-capital can realise its return only through exchanges in
the market. And the return to self-employed articulated through
the market is completely arbitrary and asymmetric vis-a-vis capital
relations.
The rise of self-employment and the informal sector at
large has sometimes been seen as a process of de-capitalisation
or a reunion of the labour to the means of production. Kalyan
Sanyal’s conceptualisation of post-colonial capitalism rests on the
division between accumulation economy and the need economy
(Sanyal, 2007). The accumulation economy is that part of the
economy which contributes to the production, appropriation and
distribution of surplus value. The other part of the vast majority
which constitutes the informal economy has no contribution to the
process of capitalist accumulation. They are the need economy who
survives on the basis of transfer of surplus from the accumulation
economy. Such a characterisation actually undermines the crucial
role of this vast unprotected labour in the process of capitalist
accumulation. There are various dimensions of value capture on
which the current neoliberal regime relies upon. Marx’s discussion
Political Economy of Employment-Unemployment in Capitalism 171
Conclusion
The current phase of capitalism is characterised by high concentration
of ownership together with increased fragmentation of the work
process. On the one hand there are waves of mergers and acquisitions
through which MNCs and TNCs give rise to the global edifice of
capital control, on the other hand it unleashes labour processes
that stretches from large factories to tiny homework integrated at
the global scale. The inclusion/exclusion dynamics of capitalism
176 Global Political Economy
the economy), is not a law in the sense of being derived from any
theoretical framework or abstract model. It is basically an empirical
observation, spanning a very long period of more than two hundred
years.
Piketty estimates the average annual rates of return on capital
in the advanced industrial countries in the late 20th and early 21st
centuries to be around 4-5 per cent and takes this level as the level
likely to prevail in the future as well. His prediction for the long
term per capita growth in the wealthy countries is of 1.2 per cent
(which he calls the median scenario). This is slightly higher than
the prediction of growth made by Gordon (2012) for the advanced
countries including the United States.
According to Piketty’s estimates, the capital-income ratio in
Britain and France in 2010 is roughly 5-6 and is about 4 in the
United States. Based on the trend analysis of the data pertaining
to recent decades in the rich countries, he predicts that the capital-
income ratio is likely to rise in the future.
On the basis of the estimates of r, g and the capital-income
ratio and the current trends, Piketty predicts ‘a durable increase
in capital’s share of national income’ in the twenty-first century,
implying a secular fall in labour’s share of national income.13
One major criticism of Piketty’s approach is that he does not
explain ‘where the rate of return comes from.’ David Harvey points
out that the valuation of capital and calculation of rate of return
are difficult technical problems that have no agreed upon technical
solutions. According to Harvey, one major weakness of Piketty’s
framework is that it does not provide any theoretical explanation
for high rate of return on capital. Harvey’s own explanation for the
phenomenon is:
If the rate of return on capital that is being used is high then this is
because a part of capital is withdrawn from circulation and in effect
goes on strike. Restricting the supply of capital to new investment (a
phenomenon we are now witnessing) ensures a high rate of return
on that capital which is in circulation. This creation of such artificial
scarcity is not only what the oil companies do to ensure their high
rate of return: it is what all capital does when given the chance. This
186 Global Political Economy
is what underpins the tendency for the rate of return on capital (no
matter how it is defined and measured) to always exceed the rate of
growth of income.
Harvey’s criticism here, however, is not valid for two reasons. One,
Harvey’s focus is largely on productive capital whereas by capital
Piketty means wealth. Secondly, Harvey shows high rate of return
on ‘used’ capital, whereas Piketty talks about average rate of return
on total capital, used as well as unused.
As mentioned earlier, Piketty’s estimates of r, g and capital-income
ratio and the predictions about their future tendencies are based
on the analysis of historical observations. There is thus not much
consideration given to production and its linkages to distribution,
technology, productivity and employment and unemployment. The
question of technological unemployment, therefore, does not arise
in his framework. He, in fact, does not appear to be overly worried
about the prospect of unemployment caused by automation as is
clear from his following remarks:
We are free to imagine an ideal society in which all other tasks are
totally automated and each individual has as much freedom as possible
to pursue the goods of education, culture and health for the benefit
of herself and others. Everyone would be by turns teacher or student,
writer or reader, actor or spectator, doctor or patient (Piketty, 2014,
308).
Piketty’s main concern is about rising inequalities caused primarily
by rising share of capital income of total income. ‘The distribution
of capital ownership (and of income from capital) is always more
concentrated than the distribution of income from labour….the
bottom 50 per cent of the wealth distribution owns nothing at all,
or almost nothing (less than 10 per cent and generally less than 5 per
cent of total wealth, or one-tenth as much as the wealthiest 10 per
cent).’14 According to Oxfam, the richest 85 people on the planet
owned as much wealth as the poorest half of humanity. In Piketty’s
view, ‘the growth of a true patrimonial (or propertied) middle class
was the structural transformation of the distribution of wealth in the
developed countries in the 20th century.’15 If the present inequality
Can Capitalism Survive the High Degree of Automation? 187
NOTES
1. This paper was published in Upadhyay, V. (2016), (ed.), Essays on
Distribution, World Systems, Ecology, and Left Politics. New Delhi:
Daanish Books.
2. During the second decade of the 19th century, a group of textile
workers in England, led by Ned Ludd, attempted to destroy automated
looms as they feared that these machines would destroy their jobs. If
technological unemployment is becoming a reality now, then it can be
said that ‘the Luddite moment’ has arrived, even if two hundred years
late.
3. Brynjolfsson and Mcafee, 2014, p. 81.
4. Ibid.
5. This viewpoint is very succinctly expressed by the CEO of a major
Indian IT company in the following words: ‘I want to make a big
mention of automation. Artificial intelligence as a domain is not
very well understood. It is often associated with precipitating...the
irrelevance of humanity. Having studied at Stanford and other places at
the feet of the pioneers of this domain, I see the world fundamentally
differently. Technology has always been about the amplification of
the human being. About augmenting them with new capabilities, not
about making them irrelevant.’ (Infosys CEO, Vishal Sikka, quoted
in The Economic Times, October 17, 2014).
6. In his 1949 article “Why Socialism?” Albert Einstein commented,
“Technological progress frequently results in more unemployment
rather than in an easing of the burden of work for all.”
7. In the early 1980s, W. Leontif warned that ‘the role of humans as
the most important factor of production is bound to diminish in the
same way that the role of horses on agricultural production was first
diminished and then eliminated by the introduction of tractors.’ (W.
Leontif quoted in Brynjolfsson and Mcafee, 2014) However the US
economy’s performance in the area of growth and employment during
the last two decades of the 20th century made people ignore such fears.
8. Robots, automation and 3D printing pose a threat to human
involvement at the workplace not only in the industrialised countries
but also in the emerging economies. In India, for example, for about
two decades, the IT services industry has been a major job provider
to the college-educated. But now the big firms are planning to deploy
automation in a big way, especially in the areas such as software testing
190 Global Political Economy
REFERENCES
Autor, David H. and D. Dorn (2013), The Growth of Low-Skilled
Service Jobs and Polarisation of the US Labour Market, The American
Economic Review, Vol. 103, No. 5.
Brynjolfsson, E. and A. Mcafee (2012), Race Against the Machine,
Cambridge: The MIT Centre for Digital Business.
Brynjolfsson, E. and A. Mcafee (2014), The Second Machine Age, New
York: WW Norton and Company.
Can Capitalism Survive the High Degree of Automation? 191
Introduction
Authored in commemoration of 1917, this article addresses one of
the key dimensions confronting the Russian and Chinese revolutions,
that of the agrarian question for the peasantry which constituted
popular majorities in each of these countries at the time of their
revolutions. These two great revolutions were confronted by three
other major challenges. The first challenge originated in the fact
that these revolutions with socialist goals had triumphed in ‘single
countries’—albeit the size of continents; two countries, moreover,
situated in the peripheries of the global system of capitalism. An
important issue concerned the question of how to progress towards
a perspective with a universal reach, under conditions of permanent
hostility and violence characterising the intrinsically imperialist
processes of capitalist globalisation.
The second challenge concerned the question of democracy. How
to construct practices capable of promoting the democratisation of
society? How to create institutions for a new participative democracy,
which would guarantee a role for all workers in the decision-making
processes at all levels of economic and social governance? How was
this to be achieved without sacrificing personal rights, but, instead,
integrating individual emancipation, through the deployment of
personal liberty and creativity, as a key dynamic in the development
of society?
The Agrarian Question a Century After 1917 193
500 quintals per labourer—to those which are the same as before
this revolution whose production is only around 10 quintals per
labourer. The gap between the average production of a farmer in
the North and that of peasant agriculture, which was from 10 to
1 before 1940 is now from 100 to 1. In other words, the rate of
progress in agricultural productivity has largely outstripped that of
other activities, bringing about a lowering of the real price from 5 to
1. This peasant agriculture in the countries of the South is also well
and truly integrated into local and world capitalism. However, closer
study reveals immediately both the convergences and differences in
the two types of ‘family’ economy.
There are huge differences, which are visible and undeniable:
the importance of subsistence food in the peasant economies, the
only way of survival for those rural populations; the low efficiency
of this agriculture, not equipped with tractors or other materials
and often highly parcellised; the poverty of the rural world (three-
quarters of the victims of under-nutrition are rural); the growing
incapacity of these systems to ensure food supplies for their towns;
the sheer immensity of the problems, as the peasant economy affects
nearly half of humanity.
In spite of these differences, peasant agriculture is already
integrated into the dominant global capitalist system. To the extent
of its contribution to the market, it depends on purchased inputs
(at least chemical products and selected seeds) and is the victim of
the oligopolies that control the marketing of these products. For the
regions having ‘benefited’ from the ‘Green Revolution’ (half of the
peasantry of the South) upstream and downstream, the siphoning
off of profits on the products by dominant capital are very great. But
they are also, in relative terms, for the other half of the peasantry
of the South, taking into account the weakness of their production.
not always the rule. In Egypt, the state agricultural services have
always imposed the size of the plots of land allocated to the different
crops in accordance with their irrigation requirements.
This land tenure system is modern in the sense that it is the
result of the constitution of ‘really existing’ capitalism, starting from
Western Europe (first in England) and from the colonies of European
extraction in America. It was set up through the destruction of the
‘customary’ systems of regulating access to the land in Europe itself.
The statutes of feudal Europe were founded on the superimposing
of rights on the same land: those of the peasant concerned and
other members of the village community (serfs or freedmen), those
of the feudal lord and those of the king. The assault on these rights
took the form of the Enclosures in England, imitated in various
ways in all the European countries during the 19th century. Marx
very soon denounced this radical transformation that excluded
most of the peasants from access to the use of land—and who were
destined to become emigrant proletarians in the town, or remain
where they were as agricultural labourers (or sharecroppers)—and
he classified these measures as primitive accumulation, dispossessing
the producers of the land and the use of the means of production.
Using the terms of Roman law to describe the statute of modern
bourgeois ownership imply that it dates from time immemorial,
that is, the ownership of the land in the Roman Empire, and more
precisely the slave-labour land ownership. In actual fact, these
particular forms of ownership, having disappeared in feudal Europe,
make it impossible to talk of the ‘continuity’ of a ‘Western’ concept
of ownership (itself associated with individualism and the values
that it represents) that has never existed.
The rhetoric of the capitalist discourse—the ‘liberal’ ideology—
has not only produced this myth of ‘Western continuity’. It has
produced another myth that is still more dangerous: that of
an ‘absolute and superior rationality’ of the management of an
economy based on the private and exclusive ownership of the
means of production, which include agricultural land. Conventional
economics does, in fact, claim that the ‘market’, that is, the
alienability of the ownership of capital and land, ensures the optimal
The Agrarian Question a Century After 1917 205
who are more urban than rural and partly of the ‘communities of
poor peasants’. South Africa, for the time being, has not taken part
in this movement. The strips of degenerated para-customary systems
which remain in the ‘poor’ regions of Morocco and Berber Algeria,
as in the Bantustans of South Africa, are suffering from the threat
of private appropriation, encouraged by elements inside and outside
the concerned communities.
In all these situations, the peasant struggles (and sometimes
the organisations that support them) should be identified more
precisely: do they constitute movements and represent claims by
‘rich peasants’ that are in conflict with some state policies (and the
influence of the dominant world system on them)? Or are they poor
and landless peasants? Could they both form an alliance against the
dominant (so-called ‘neoliberal’) system? On what conditions? To
what extent? Can the claims—whether they are expressed or not—
of the poor, landless peasants be ‘forgotten’?
In intertropical Africa, the apparent persistence of these
‘customary’ systems is certainly more visible. Because, here, the
colonisation model took off in a different direction known as the
économie de traite: the meaning of this concept, which has no
English translation, is that the management of access to land was
left to the so-called ‘customary’ authorities, nevertheless controlled
by the colonial state (though genuine traditional chiefs or false ones
fabricated by the administration). The objective of this control was
to force the peasants to produce, beyond their cotton, coffee, cacao.
The maintenance of a land tenure system that did not recognise
private property was convenient for the colonisers, as land rent did
not have to be taken into account in calculating the price of the
products. This resulted in the degradation of the soils, destroyed by
expanding crops, sometimes definitively (as, e.g. the desertification
of Senegal where groundnuts had been cultivated). Here, once again,
capitalism demonstrates that the ‘short-term rationality’ inherent in
its dominant logic is largely responsible for ecological disaster. The
juxtaposition of subsistence food crops and exports crops also made
it possible to pay the work of the peasants at levels close to zero.
For these reasons, to talk about the ‘customary land tenure system’
The Agrarian Question a Century After 1917 209
well be that this is because of the village councils that have been
genuinely re-elected, and it has been necessary because there is no
other way to mobilise the opinion of the majority and reduce the
intrigues of the minorities of profiteers who would eventually benefit
from a more marked capitalist development. The ‘dictatorship of the
Party’ has shown that this has been largely solved through careerism
and opportunism, if not corruption. The social struggles underway
in the Chinese and Vietnamese countryside make their voices heard
in these countries, just as they do elsewhere in the world. But they
remain very much on the ‘defensive’, that is, attached to defending
the heritage of the revolution: the equal right of everyone to land.
Defence is necessary, because this heritage is more threatened
than would appear, in spite of repeated affirmations by the two
governments that ‘the ownership of land by the state will “never” be
abolished for the benefit of private ownership’. But now this defence
requires recognition of the right to do it through the organisation of
those concerned, the peasants.
the poor and those without land. That was the case in Egypt and
in other Arab countries. The reform underway in Zimbabwe risks
ending up in the same way. In other situations, reform is always on
the agenda of what should be done: in India, in South East Asia, in
South Africa and in Kenya.
The progress created by agrarian reform, even where it exists as
an immediate and essential requirement, is nevertheless ambiguous
for its more long-term implications. For it reinforces attachment
to ‘small property’, which becomes an obstacle to the questioning
of a land tenure system based on private ownership. Russia’s
history illustrates this drama. The developments that followed the
abolition of serfdom, in 1861, were accelerated by the revolution of
1905, because Stolypin’s policies had already produced a ‘claim for
ownership’ that was (finally) fulfilled in the radical agrarian reform
after the 1917 Revolution. And, as we know, the new small owners
did not enthusiastically renounce their rights for the benefit of the
unfortunate cooperatives, which were dreamt up at the time, in the
1930s.
‘Another path’ to development, based on the peasant family
economy of the generalised small owners, would have been possible.
But it was not attempted. And what about the regions (other than
China and Vietnam) where, in fact, the land tenure system had not
(yet) been based on private property? This was, of course, the case
of intertropical Africa.
Here we find the old debate. Towards the end of the 19th century,
Marx, in his correspondence with the Russian Narodniks (Vera
Zasulich, among others), dared to say that the absence of private
ownership could constitute an advantage for the socialist revolution,
enabling a leap forward towards a regime for managing the access to
land other than the one governed by private ownership. But he did
not specify what forms this new regime should take, the adjective
‘collective’, correct as it was, being insufficient. Twenty years later,
Lenin believed this possibility no longer existed, eliminated by the
penetration of capitalism and the spirit of private ownership that
accompanied it. Was this a correct assessment? I cannot say, as I do
not know enough about Russia. However, Lenin was hardly able
The Agrarian Question a Century After 1917 213
party that took over this new modern power was also clearly aware
of the challenge and aimed at eliminating the customary forms of
power—which were judged to be ‘reactionary’, if not ‘feudal’. It is
true that this new peasant power, formally democratic (the leaders
were elected), was only as democratic as the state and the party.
However, it did exercise ‘modern’ responsibilities, seeing that access
to land was carried out ‘correctly’, that is, without ‘discrimination’.
It managed the credits, the distribution of the inputs (which were
partially supplied by state trading) and the marketing of produce
(also partially delivered for state commerce). Nepotism and
extortion were certainly not eliminated in these procedures. But the
only response to these abuses was the gradual democratisation of the
state, not its ‘withdrawal’, which was later imposed by liberalism,
through an extremely violent military dictatorship, for the benefit
of the traders (the dioulas).
Other experiences, like those in the liberated areas of Guinea
Bissau, inspired by the theories advanced by Amilcar Cabral, in
Burkina Faso during the Sankara era, have also openly confronted
these challenges and sometimes produced unquestionable advances.
There are now efforts to obliterate them from people’s minds. In
Senegal, the establishment of elected rural authorities constitutes a
response that I unhesitatingly defend in principle. Democracy is a
practice whose apprenticeship never ends, no less in Europe than
in Africa.
What the dominant discourse at the moment means by
‘reform of the land tenure system’ is the exact opposite of what
is required for the building of an authentic alternative based on a
prosperous peasant economy. What this discourse means by land
reform—conveyed by the propaganda instruments of collective
imperialism, the World Bank, many development institutions,
but also a number of NGOs that are richly endowed—is the
acceleration of the privatisation of land, and nothing more. The
aim is clear: to create the conditions that would enable some
‘modern’ islands of agribusiness (foreign and local) to take over
the land they require to expand. But the supplementary produce
that these ‘islands’ could supply (for export or for local ‘effective
216 Global Political Economy
work in the towns. This was what Marx wrote concerning the
pauperisation associated with the accumulation of capital.
The challenge, which is to base development on renewing
peasant societies, has many dimensions. I will just call attention here
to the conditions for constructing the necessary and possible political
alliances that will enable progress to be made towards solutions (in
the interests of the worker peasants, of course) to all the problems
that are posed: access to the land and to the means to develop it
properly; reasonable wages for peasant work; improvement of wages
parallel to the productivity of this work; and appropriate regulation
of the markets at the national, regional and world levels.
New peasant organisations exist in Asia and Africa that are visibly
activating the struggles underway. Often, when political systems
make it impossible for them to constitute formal organisations, the
social struggles in the rural world take the form of ‘movements’
with no apparent direction. These actions and programmes, where
they exist, should be analysed more carefully. Which peasant social
forces do they represent and whose interests are they defending?
The majority mass of the peasants? Or the minorities which aspire
to participating in the expansion of dominant globalised capitalism?
We should mistrust quick answers to these questions that are
complex and difficult. We should be careful not to ‘condemn’ a
number of organisations and movements on the pretext that they
are not mobilising the peasant majorities on radical programmes.
This would be to ignore the need to formulate broad alliances and
strategies by stages. But we should also be careful not to support the
discourse of the ‘naïve alternative world people’ who often set the
tone in the forums and fuel the illusion that the world is on the right
path only because of the existence of the social movements. This
is a discourse that belongs more to the many NGOs—with good
intentions, perhaps—than to the peasant and worker organisations.
I myself am not so naïve as to think that all the interests that
these alliances represent can naturally converge. In all peasant
societies, there are the rich and the poor, who are often without
land. The conditions of access to land result from different
historical experiences which, in some cases, have rooted aspirations
The Agrarian Question a Century After 1917 221
REFERENCES
Amin, S. (2005), Les Luttes Paysannes et Ouvières Face Aux Défis du Xxe
Siècle, Paris: Les Indes Savantes.
———. (2006), Beyond US Hegemony, New York: Zed Books.
———. (2017), October 1917 Revolution, A Century Later, Nairobi: Darja
Press.
Berthelot, J. (2001), L’agriculture, Talon d’Achille de l’OMC, Paris:
L’Harmattan.
Chayanov, A.V. (1966), On The Theory of Non-Capitalist Economic Systems,
In D. Thorner, B. Kerblay and R.E.F. Smithy (eds.), The Theory of
Peasant Economy, pp. 1–28, Homewood, IL: Irwin.
Kautsky, K. (1988 [1899]), The Agrarian Question, Winchester, MA: Zwan
Publications.
Mazoyer, M. and L. Roudard (1997), Histoire des Agricultures du Monde,
Paris: Seuil.
Parmentier, B. (2007), Nourrir l’humanité, Paris: La Découverte.
10
‘Big is Not Always Beautiful’:
Family Farms and Capitalism
Goran Djurfeldt
Land
The first reason for the paucity of capitalist farms is the common
but erroneous inference that capitalist farms are identical to large
landed estates. Such units are seldom constrained to making a profit
on the (imputed) value of the land, either because the land is not
mortgaged at market value and therefore not liable to pay interest,
or because the owners, whether corporate or individual, may have
acquired the land cheaply or free of cost, like inheritance.
Large landed estates often have an interesting history, worth
digging into. Take the Indian case: Simply put, what still remains of
large landed estates after land reforms and other developments since
Independence, either have a colonial background, for example tea
plantations, or a feudal one, like the zamindari and other types of
estates created by the Mughals, by the East India Company, or other
pre-colonial rulers.1 Such estates were often referred to as ‘tax farms’,
because they were created by rulers to facilitate tax collection from
the tillers of the land, by ‘farming it out’ to people with the means,
that is the arms and the men needed to collect taxes on the part of
the ruler. In the process, taxable land was converted, more or less
formally, into private property. Thus, large estates were not created
because they were superior in terms of productivity, or because of
economies of scale.
In fact, outside the plantation sector, economies of scale seldom
obtain in agriculture, which is one reason why capitalist farms,
unlike large estates are rare and a main reason why the Leninist
expectation of the form that capitalism would take in agriculture
was off the mark, both in Europe and in the US.
Labour
Another presumption underlying the expectation that capitalist farms
would prevail in agriculture is that such farms rely on hired labour,
whose wages are formed in a process of free negotiation between the
labourer and the employer. Labour hiring is usually regarded as the
‘Big is Not Always Beautiful’: Family Farms and Capitalism 225
Management
In Andalusia in Spain, as well as in latifundist areas in South
America and also currently in India, there are farm management
firms, taking on large landholdings on the part of their owner
families, proffering professional management of the farms, using
up to date methods, much machinery and recruiting specialised
workers and small ‘armies’ of casual labour. Another variety of this
is firms owning combine harvesters, negotiating directly with farm
owners and moving along a harvest frontier, like South to North on
the Gangetic plain, or in the Yangtse River valley in China.
These arrangements presuppose everyday management by
owner families, or by salaried managers in the case of larger estates;
they do not in any way threaten the family ownership characteristic
of all the mentioned cases. Corporate ownership of machinery, yes,
but corporate land ownership, in no way!
‘Big is Not Always Beautiful’: Family Farms and Capitalism 227
Chayanov’s Principle3
A.V. Chayanov (1888-1937) was a Russian economist, statistician
and sociologist belonging to the so-called zemstvo school who
worked for the decentralised local governments set up as part of
the 1861 reforms under Tsar Alexander II in Russia. Chayanov was
shot 20 years after the Revolution, as part of the Stalinist purges.
Rehabilitated in 1987 during glasnost, Chayanov was introduced to
230 Global Political Economy
Pluriactivity
Family farmers are not always specialised in arable farming,
horticulture and animal husbandry, but more often combine these
activities with others, outside the farm and often outside agriculture.
We refer to this as ‘pluriactivity’, which is a mongrel of a word: with
the prefix ‘pluri’ from Greek and ‘activity’ from Latin. Pluriactivity
refers to a family or household, often spanning more than a
generation; and reliant upon the activities of their members. Thus
the term refers to the reproduction of the whole. Had it not been
for pluriactivity then, the resilience of family farming would have
been much less.
It lies near at hand to think of pluriactive families these
days, when individual members of rural and agrarian families are
migrating all over, nationally and internationally, looking for income
opportunities and for money to send to their families back home.
Internationally, remittances sent home by migrants supersede both
foreign investments and aid received by the migrants’ countries of
origin, or at least they did so till the current crisis (Ratha, 2016).
Think of the giant movements of internal migrants in huge countries
like India and China. When India imposed the Covid-19 lockdown
in the summer of 2020, millions of migrants were caught between
234 Global Political Economy
Conclusions
In sum, big is not always beautiful, especially not when talking
about capitalist farms. There are sound reasons why family farming
238 Global Political Economy
REFERENCES
Athreya, V.B., G. Djurfeldt and S. Lindberg, (1990), Barriers Broken:
Production Relations and Agrarian Change in Tamil Nadu, New Delhi:
Sage Publications.
Bailey, W.R. (1973), The One-Man Farm (ERS 519), Washington, DC: US
Department of Agriculture.
Chand, R., Lakshmi Prasanna and A. Singh (2011), Farm Size and
Productivity: Understanding the Strengths of Smallholders and
Improving Their Livelihoods, Economic and Political Weekly, Vol. 46,
Nos. 26/27, pp. 5-11.
Chayanov, A.V. (1977), The Journey of My Brother Aleksei to the Land
of Peasant Utopia, In R.E.F. Smith (ed.), The Russian Peasant 1920 &
1984, pp. 63-108, London: Frank Cass.
Chayanov, A.V. (1986 [1966]), A.V. Chayanov and the Theory of Peasant
Economy, Madison, Wisconsin: The University of Wisconsin Press.
Coase, R.H. (1937), The Nature of the Firm, Economica, Vol. 4, No. 16,
pp. 386-405.
Deininger, K. and D. Byerlee (2012), The Rise of Large Farms in Land
Abundant Countries: Do They Have a Future?, World Development,
Vol. 40, No. 4, pp. 701-14.
Djurfeldt, G. (1981), What Happened to the Agrarian Bourgoisie and the
Rural Proletariat Under Monopoly Capitalism?, Acta Sociologica, Vol.
24, No. 3, pp. 167-91.
Djurfeldt, G. and S. Sircar (2017), Structural Transformation and Agrarian
Change in India, New York and London: Routledge.
Djurfeldt, G. and C. Waldenström (1996), Towards a Theoretically
Grounded Typology of Farms—A Swedish Case, Acta Sociologica, Vol.
39, No. 2, pp. 187-210.
Dovring, F. (1965 [1955]), Land and Labor in Europe in the Twentieth
Century: A Comparative Survey of Recent Agrarian History, (Third
Revised Edition of Land and Labour in Europe, 1900-1950), The
Hague: Martinus Nijhoff.
Eastwood, R., M. Lipton and A. Newell (2010), Farm Size, In P.L. Pingali
and R.E. Evenson (eds.), Handbook of Agricultural Economics, North
Holland: Elsevier.
Eswaran, M., A. Kotwal, B. Ramaswami and W. Wadhwa (2009), Sectoral
Labour Flows and Agricultural Wages in India, 1983-2004: Has
240 Global Political Economy
Growth Trickled Down?, Economic and Political Weekly, Vol. 44, No.
2, pp. 46-55.
FAO (2014), The State of Food and Agriculture: Innovation in Family
Farming, Rome: Food and Agricultural Organisation of the United
Nations.
Gasson, R. (1987), Family Farming in Britain, In B. Galeski and E.
Wilkening (eds.), Family Farming in Europe and America, pp. 5-37,
Boulder, Col.: Westview Press.
Habib, I. (1963), The Agrarian System of Mughal India, 1556-1707,
Bombay: Asia Publishing House.
Harrison, A. (1975), Farmers and Farm Businesses in England, Miscellaneous
Study No. 62, Reading: Reading University, Department of
Agricultural Economics and Management.
Hayami, Y. and V.W. Ruttan, (1971), Agricultural Development: An
International Perspective, Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press.
Land Matrix (2020), Online Public Database on Land Deals, https://
landmatrix.org.
Lenin, V.I. (1960 [1899]), The Development of Capitalism in Russia,
Moscow: Foreign Languages Publishing House.
Marx, K. (1977 [1887]), Capital: A Critique of Political Economy (Vol. I),
London: Lawrence & Wishart.
Newby, H., C. Bell, C. Rose and P. Saunders (1978), Property, Paternalism
and Power, London: Hutchinson.
Perry, P.J. (1972), British Agriculture, 1875-1914, London: Methuen.
Polanyi, K. (2001 [1944]), The Great Transformation: The Political and
Economic Origins of Our Time, Boston: Beacon Press.
Ratha, D. (2016), Migration and Remittances Factbook 2016, The World
Bank.
Reardon, T., C.B. Barrett, J.A. Berdegué and J.F.M. Swinnen (2009),
Agrifood Industry Transformation and Small Farmers in Developing
Countries, World Development, Vol. 37, No. 11, pp. 1717-27.
Reardon, T., C.P. Timmer, C. Barrett and J. Berdegué (2003), The Rise of
Supermarkets in Africa, Asia, and Latin America, American Journal of
Agricultural Economics, Vol. 85, No. 5, pp. 1140-46.
Schmitt, G. (1991), Why is the Agriculture of Advanced Western
Economies Still Organized by Family Farms: Will This Continue to
‘Big is Not Always Beautiful’: Family Farms and Capitalism 241
Sweezy noted, would have to consider the labour process, which had
occupied such a central place in Marx’s analysis—something that
they did not attempt in what they called their “essay-sketch.” Here
Harry Braverman stepped in with his path-breaking Labour and
Monopoly Capital (1974), making it clear that the degradation of
work brought on by the division of labour, as Marx had described it
in Capital, was in many ways heightened under monopoly capitalism,
with the rise of scientific management (Braverman, 1974). Other
works in this general tradition in the 1960s and 70s included Harry
Magdoff ’s The Age of Imperialism, James O’Connor’s The Fiscal Crisis
of the State, and Stephen Hymer’s The Multinational Corporation.
The Union for Radical Political Economists, organised in 1968,
brought out its first economic crisis reader in 1975, entitled Radical
Perspectives on the Economic Crisis of Monopoly Capital (Magdoff,
1969; O’Connor, 1973; Hymer; 1979, URPE, 1975).
The concept of monopoly capital also had an enormous
influence in the global south. Che Guevara, who met both Sweezy
and Magdoff, and who identified closely with Baran’s argument on
monopoly capital and economic surplus in The Political Economy
of Growth, declared in 1965: “Ever since monopoly capital took
over the world, it has kept the greater part of humanity in poverty,
dividing all of the profits among the group of most powerful
countries (Guevera, 1965).”
Although the notion of the monopoly stage of capitalism played
a key role in the work of most Marxian economists till the 1970s—e.g.
Maurice Dobb in Studies in the Development of Capitalism (1947),
Ernest Mandel in Marxist Economic Theory (1962), and Samir
Amin in Accumulation on a World Scale (1970)—by the late 1970s
the notion of monopoly capital had begun to wane (Dobb, 1947;
Mandel, 1968; Amin, 1974). During what became known as the
“back to Marx” movement, or the growth of fundamentalist Marxian
political economy, it became increasingly common to assume the
ascendancy of free competition throughout the history of capitalism,
and to reject the notion of historical stages of capitalist development
altogether. Along with this came the abandonment (or at least the
downplaying) of notions of concentration and centralisation of
248 Global Political Economy
REFERENCES
Amin, S. (1974), Accumulation on a World Scale, New York: Monthly
Review Press.
Amin, S. (2010), The Law of World Wide Value, New York: Monthly
Review Press.
Baran Paul A. (1957), The Political Economy of Growth, New York: Monthly
Review Press.
Baran Paul A. and Paul M. Sweezy (1966), Monopoly Capital, New York:
Monthly Review Press.
Baran Paul A. and Paul M. Sweezy (2012), Some Theoretical Implications,
Monthly Review, Vol. 64, No. 3, pp. 24–59.
Baran Paul A. and Paul M. Sweezy (2013), The Quality of Monopoly
Capitalist Society: Culture and Communications, Monthly Review,
Vol. 65, No. 3, pp. 43-64.
Braran Paul. A. and Paul. M. Sweezy (2013), The Age of Monopoly Capital:
Selected Correspondence of Paul A. Baran and Paul M. Sweezy, 1949–
1969, Nicholas Baran and John Bellamy Foster (eds.), New York:
Monthly Review Press.
Braverman, H. (1974), Labor and Monopoly Capital, New York: Monthly
Review Press.
Brenner, R. (2006), The Economics of Global Turbulence, London: Verso.
Cowling, K. (1982), Monopoly Capitalism, New York: John Wiley and Sons.
Cowling K. and R. Sugden (1987), Transnational Monopoly Capitalism,
New York: St. Martin’s Press.
Chamberlain, E.H. (1933), The Theory of Monopolistic Competition,
What is Monopoly Capital? 251
Introduction
Marxist political economy very often refers to the “accumulation of
capital” as if it were a transparent concept, one easily understood
from Marx’s work. Commonly, citing accumulation of capital in
a theoretical or empirical analysis suggests a depth of analysis by
an author that does not need further explication. It can read with
a confidence that “gravity” has in a work of physics. The problem
is that, as a concept, it is not clear what accumulation of capital
is to mean. In fact, capital is so often referred to as a means of
production that, following the classical economists, Marxist political
economists do not seem to have broken from Marx’s predecessors
when mentioning the accumulation of capital. I include Lenin in
this characterisation (see Zarembka, 2003).
Marx’s multiple-volume work was not called Capital in order
to refer to means of production. Constant capital, rather, is used
to refer to the means of production, measured in value units. The
entire work of Capital is fundamentally offered to comprehend the
social relations of production in capitalism. Class is the fundamental
issue. Therefore, his accumulation of capital must be understood
with class in mind, not means of production, not constant capital.
Marx himself was a theorist who was constantly evolving, not
a person stuck with his earlier thinking. We can recall how late he
arrived at “labour power” as an important concept, namely around
254 Global Political Economy
global population growth rate was only around 0.5 per cent per
year. If Marx was considering a country, rather than the whole
world, the rate of increase in England was higher, one per cent in
the 19th century, but still not enough to rely on for accumulation of
capital. Marx’s own numerical illustrations of accumulation assume
annual population increases of 10 per cent. Another possibility? The
increased labour power supply for accumulation of capital could
come from continuing penetration of non-capitalist modes, and
not merely a creation of wage labourers within population increase.
While presumption of a fully capitalist world in Capital contradicts
such an understanding, proletarianisation of the world was then and
is still, in fact, proceeding apace. Thus, Pagine Marxiste (November
2004, Year 1, Number 5, p. 5) makes an attempt to record progress,
indicating that the global non-agricultural labour force more than
quadrupled from 1950 to 2000, representing a 2.9 per cent annual
rate of growth, due in part to population growth (about 1.7 per cent
annually) and in part to the ‘process of proletarianisation, linked to
the disintegration of the peasant social framework and to the shift
from the rural to the urban areas’.
Perhaps Marx became quite aware of continuing proletarianisation
(not only the proletarianisation resulting from original transition
from feudalism to capitalism, i.e. ‘primitive accumulation’). Thus,
consider somewhat more deeply the unpublished ‘Results’ section,
which was to have been the conclusion of Volume I. The most
important theoretical concept in ‘Results’ was formal and real
subsumption of labour to capital, following usage beginning in the
Grundrisse. By the concept of subsumption, it can be argued that
Marx ‘clearly wished to imply that as economic relations increasingly
took on a capitalist character, their scale increased and this brought
them even closer to the world market and their point of culmination’
(White, 1996, 191). Yet, by leaving ‘Results’ out entirely as Volume
I went to the publisher, any focus on subsumption was lost. Even
references elsewhere within Volume I to subsumption were almost
completely stricken by Marx, including references to cooperation,
division of labour, and use of machinery as stages of subsumption
(White, 1996, 200; one remaining definitional passage for
Late Marx, Luxemburg, and the Conception... 257
Luxemburg on Accumulation
Marx’s study of the history of capital’s penetration, including its
difficulties, had a successor in Luxemburg’s interest in the question
Late Marx, Luxemburg, and the Conception... 261
Critics
There are several factors underlying the dismissal of Luxemburg’s
work, the upshot of which has been to limit the development of
Marxist theory. First, Lenin had said, point blank, that Luxemburg
Late Marx, Luxemburg, and the Conception... 263
value. The third, not yet final, draft was begun in 1863 and completed
in 1865, including the only draft ever made of what became Volume
3 under Engels’ editorship.
3. After pulling ‘Results’ from Volume I, there is also no record that
Marx later returned to the issue of ‘subsumption’.
4. Marx, judging by a number of his interventions on this issue, seemed
to think that primitive communism resisted capital more than
Luxemburg argued. Examining this disparity is unnecessary for our
purposes.
5. We are at a loss how Bukharin could so distort Luxemburg’s position
by skipping over the sentence reproduced here. He even plays with
the words salto mortale in his own text, getting into the reader’s
subconscious that he, Bukharin, has read her: the reader is expected to
take his word for the fact that, yes, she really does define accumulation
as the amassing of money capital
REFERENCES
Althusser, L. (1970 [1965]), L’object du Capital, in L. Althusser, E. Balibar
and R. Establet (eds.) Lire le Capital, trans. by B. Brewster, The Object
of Capital, in L. Althusser and E. Balibar (eds.) Reading Capital,
London: New Left Books, pp. 71-198.
Bukharin, N.I. (1972 [1924]), Der Imperialismus und die Akkumulation der
Kapitals, trans. by R. Wichman as Imperialism and the Accumulation of
Capital, New York: Monthly Review Press.
Forstater, M. (2005), Taxation and Primitive Accumulation: The Case
of Colonial Africa, in P. Zarembka (ed.), The Capitalist State and Its
Economy; Democracy in Socialism, Research in Political Economy, Vol.
22, pp. 51-64.
Froelich, P. (1967 [1939]), Rosa Luxemburg—Gedanke und Tat, trans. by J.
Hoornweg, Rosa Luxemburg: Her Life and Work, New York: Monthly
Review Press.
Howard, M.C. and J.E. King (1989), A History of Marxian Economics, Vol.
1: 1883-1929, London: Macmillan.
Kautsky, K. (2019 [1902]), Krisentheorien, trans. by D. Gaido and D.
Scattolini as ‘Theories of Crises’ [Sections 3, 4 and 5 only] in P.
Zarembka (ed.) Class History and Class Practices in the Periphery of
Capitalism, Research in Political Economy, Vol. 32, pp. 199-224.
Kowalik, T. (1990), Rosa Luxemburg, In J. Eatwell, M. Milgate and P.
268 Global Political Economy
I. Introduction
For anyone who did not know already, the Great Financial Crisis of
2008 made it completely obvious that finance has become a powerful
force in our economy. Unfortunately, among those largely in the dark
on the eve of the crisis were most of the mainstream macroeconomics
profession as well as many regulators and practitioners operating in
the financial market itself. This is because, in the post-war period,
the thrust of the mainstream analysis was designed to demonstrate
that financial markets were either irrelevant to macroeconomic
outcomes, or, by facilitating the efficient allocation of resources, a
potent force for efficiency and growth (Taylor, 2010; Crotty, 2009).
The idea that finance could cause the virtual meltdown of the global
economy was foreign to their theories and far from their minds.2
For heterodox economists, by contrast, at least since the work
of the late Hyman Minsky, this fact had been well known. In the
1970s, Hyman Minsky introduced the role of financial instability in
the inherent dynamics of the economy and by 1992 had introduced
the term “financial instability hypothesis” to refer to the inherently
contradictory role of borrowing and lending in the course of the
business cycle and on economic crises.3 Over the course of the next
several decades, heterodox economists expanded their analyses of
Financialisation: There’s Something Happening Here 271
finance further. By the 1980s and 1990s, they were acutely aware that
the size, nature and scope of finance had begun to grow enormously
and that it was having much broader impacts on the economy than
simply on the business cycle and economic crises: finance seemed
to be changing the whole character of the economy and possibly
even society itself. Minsky started writing about the rise of “money
manager capitalism” suggesting a whole new phase of capitalism that
was characterised, in particular, by the type of financial relationships
that dominated the economy. Others also began to identify the very
nature of the current form of capitalism with the type of financial
relations that were dominant in them. Some went as so far as to
argue that these financial relations not only structure our economy,
but our very language and culture as well. Gerald F. Davis referred
to a “portfolio society”, “in which the investment idiom becomes
a dominant way of understanding the individual’s place in society.
Personality and talent become “human capital”, homes, families
and communities become “social capital” and the guiding principle
of financial investment spread by analogy far beyond their original
application” (Davis, 2009, 6).
Financialisation” is the latest, and probably most widely used
term by analysts trying to “name” and understand this contemporary
rise of finance and its powerful role. The term had been developed
long before the crisis of 2008 but, understandably, since the
crisis hit, it has become even more popular. This vast and rapidly
expanding literature on financialisation has a number of important
strands. Some of the literature focuses on clarifying the definition
of financialisation, and assessing whether it is a dominant cause of
the ills confronting capitalism or is just a symptom of other, deeper
causes; some ask whether financialisation is a new “phase” of capitalist
development, perhaps a new “mode of accumulation”, or considers
whether it is just one among a number of important developments
along with “neo-liberalism”, “digitisation” and “globalisation” that
are arising in the contemporary world; other literature is focused
on less theoretical and more empirical matters, trying to measure
the nature and extent of financialisation, however defined, and
to describe its institutional and economic dimensions; and still
272 Global Political Economy
these phenomena have all arisen more or less together since the
1980s , it might be impossible, to settle this debate.
Another important debate is on the periodisation of
“financialisation”. Is it only a recent phenomenon, say, important
since the 1980s? Or does it go back at least 5000 years, as Malcolm
Sawyer has suggested? (Sawyer, 2013, 6).5 If it goes back a long
time, does it come in waves, perhaps linked with broader waves of
production, commerce and technology or is it a relatively independent
process driven by government policy such as the degree of financial
regulation or liberalisation (see Vercelli, 2013; Arrighi, 1994;
Krippner, 2012 and Orhangazi, 2008a, 2008b). Arrighi famously
argued that over the course of capitalist history, financialisation
tends to become a dominant force when the productive economy
is in decline, and when the dominant global power (or “hegemon”)
is in retreat. Think, for example of the early 20th century when
Great Britain was losing power relative to Germany and the US, and
the UK economy was stagnating. This was a period also of a great
increase in financial speculation and instability. (See also Orhangazi,
2008a and Pollin, 1996).
This historical discussion has also melded into a more
contemporary discussion of the causes of financialisation. There is
a big debate about whether the current wave of financialisation is
due to the liberalisation of financial markets starting in the 1980s,
or whether it reflects the reduced profitability and stagnation in the
non-financial (the so-called “real”) economy. In the latter case, it is
argued, financiers are forced to find other ways to make profits, and
they turn primarily to dangerous speculation in the financial sphere.
In short, the question is whether financialisation is due to changes
in the nature and regulation of the financial sphere or is it primarily
due to profound structural problems in the non-financial economy,
including foreign trade and relative global power.6
A related argument is whether the current phase of financialisation
is due to the massive increases in income and wealth inequality
which has led to the need for massive household borrowing and
provided the wealth for rich people to invest.
One policy implication of this debate is that if financialisation
Financialisation: There’s Something Happening Here 275
and also private equity firms (Appelbaum and Batt, 2014) and hedge
funds (Dallas, 2012). These financial institutions use access to debt
and financial engineering to extract value in the short run from
non-financial corporations, possibly at the expense of investment,
tax payers and labour.
In short, this strand of literature suggests that “financialisation”
not only affects behaviour in the financial sector itself, but also has
profound effects on non-financial corporations as well.
Conclusion
As this section has shown, financialisation has numerous dimensions,
and has moved in some countries way beyond the “financial sector”
itself. Financial returns, financial motives, widespread use of debt
and short-termism, among other aspects, have become crucial, if not
Financialisation: There’s Something Happening Here 281
Income Distribution
This raises the issue of the overall impact of financialisation on
income distribution. An important issue in this area is where do
financial profits come from? (Pollin, 1996). Are they the result of
provision of services by finance to the rest of the economy, as is
asserted by most mainstream economic theory? Or does much of it
come in this era of financialisation from the extraction of income
and wealth by finance from workers, tax-payers, debtors and other
creditors? Iren Levina proposes that much of financial income comes
from access to capital gains in financialised markets and therefore
does not necessarily reflect a zero-sum game, as is implied by some
who argue that financial returns are extracted rather than result
from increased wealth. (Levina, 2014). This issue of the source of
financial income is extremely difficult to sort out theoretically and
there is no consensus on this topic (see Lapavitsas, 2013).
There has been some empirical work to look at the impact of
financialisation on income and wealth distribution. Descriptive
analysis in the US indicates that the top earners, the 1 per cent
or even .01 per cent of the income distribution get the bulk of
their incomes from CEO pay or from finance (Bakija, et al.
2012). Econometric work looking at the relationship between
financialisation and inequality is also growing. Tomaskovic-Devey
and Lin (2011) present an econometric model indicating that since
the 1970s, between 5.8 and 6.6 trillion dollars were transferred to
the finance sector from other sectors in the economy, including
labour and taxpayers.
Lin and Tomaskovic-Devey (2013), using a sectoral econometric
analysis for the US, find that in time-series cross-section data at the
industry level, an increasing dependence on financial income, in
Financialisation: There’s Something Happening Here 285
V. Conclusion
There is little doubt that the size and reach of financial activities,
markets, motives and institutions has grown enormously in the last
thirty years, relative to other aspects of the economy. There is a great
deal of historical and empirical evidence that, at least to some extent,
this growth has contributed to economic instability, an increase in
inequality, and in some cases, to a decline in productive investment
and employment relative to what might have occurred otherwise.
There is less consensus on whether this constitutes a new epoch,
phase, or mode of accumulation or what exactly is causing this shift:
is it underlying problems in the “productive core” of the economy,
a reaction to broader shifts in the global economy associated with
globalisation, technological changes associated with digitisation, or
primarily due to financial de-regulation as being part and parcel of
neoliberalism?
To some extent, policies or programes aimed at reducing
the deleterious consequences of financialisation depend, to some
extent at least, on the underlying causes of the negative aspects
of financialisation. If the problem primarily stems from issues
of financial regulation, then adopting strict financial regulations
as suggested by many (see, for example, some of the chapters in
Wolfson and Epstein, 2013; or Epstein and Crotty, 2013), imposing
a financial transactions tax to reduce short term trading, prohibiting
destructive stock buy-backs (Lazonick, 2015a), breaking up the large
banks (Johnson and Kwack, 2010), change corporate governance so
that corporations take into account the preferences of stake holders,
and a host of other reforms could well go a long way to taming
financialisation. If, the problems stem largely from the vast and
growing inequality of income and wealth and the political power
that this inequality buys, then deeper reforms of taxation, wages,
and ownership as well as money in politics must be implemented.
If the problem goes deeper to the underlying capitalist dynamics
that lead to financialisation, then we are looking at even more
fundamental reforms. The state of our knowledge does not allow
us to clearly sort out these issues. But, it would not hurt to start
Financialisation: There’s Something Happening Here 287
REFERENCES
Admati, A. and M. Hellwig (2013), The Bankers’ New Clothes, Princeton:
Princeton University Press.
Aglietta, M. and R. Bretton (2001), Financial Systems, Corporate Control
and Capital Accumulation, Economy and Society, Vol. 30 No. 4, pp.
433-66.
Almeida, H., F. Vyacheslav and M. Kronlund (2016), The Real Effects of
288 Global Political Economy
Introduction
History shows that the major economic crises give way to
fundamental transformation in the working of capitalist economic
system. However, all capitalist crises are the outcome of some
fundamental contradictions. The contradiction between capital
and labour is the basic contradiction of capitalism that is inherent
within the production process. The other contradiction arises with
the competition among the free capitalist producers of the same
industry to defeat each other at the marketplace to maximise sale. It
ruins the small and less competitive players. The third contradiction
is between the national capitalist producers producing different
products to expand its size to other spheres of production that
results in the concentration and centralisation of capital at national
level. The last contradiction takes capitalism into a qualitative new
age. It constitutes the contradiction between the national capitalists
of one region or a country with the capitalists of another region or
a country to grab the world market. This last contradiction is the
subject matter of what we call classical theories of imperialism.
The original Marxian theory of imperialism is not given by Marx
rather it had been developed between 1902 and 1917. The publication
of Hobson’s populist version of the critique of imperialism in 1902
led Marxist thinkers to understand the contradictions of industrial
capitalism that had developed among major centres of the capitalist
Reflections on the Classical Theory of Imperialism 295
C—C or C—M—C
The process, presented by Say’s law or Ricardo’s explanation of
it, highlights that in the first circuit the commodity undergoes the
process of metamorphosis into money and in the next circuit the
process of metamorphosis of money into commodity. It is quite
consistent that money is then regarded merely as an intermediary in
the exchange of products. This interpretation of capitalist economic
system has denied the first condition of capitalist production. The
sole purpose of production under capitalism is accumulation of
more and more capital in money form. The capitalist production
process starts with money with a principal objective of valorisation
of capital invested in the form of more money as shown by the
following equation.
M—C—MХ
The logic of capital accumulation which drives the capitalist
economic system depends on realisation of surplus value, the value
over and above the value of labour power. In a closed capitalist
system, production of surplus value is based on conditions that the
wages of workers should be less than the total value produced by
them. This extra value above the ‘necessary labour time’ requires
the market for its realisation. One part of this demand is fulfilled
by the workers as consumers and the other part is fulfilled by the
producers as consumers. It is an established fact that the marginal
propensity to consume of the workers is near to one which means
they consume whatever they earn. However, marginal propensity
of the capitalists is less than one which means they consume less
than their income because they keep a part of their income for
investment. This reinvestment is based on the condition that all
the surplus value extracted during the production process should be
realised in the market. The circuit of capital accumulation cannot be
complete without the realisation of surplus value. Hence, in a closed
economic system the realisation of surplus value is blocked by the
problem of the narrow base of consumption. The capitalist crisis
due to narrow base of domestic consumption can be postponed
through intensification of the domestic market by developing new
production units and employing new workers. But wages which
Reflections on the Classical Theory of Imperialism 299
control over the national market and state apparatuses at the first
stage and the world market at the final stage.
further argued, for the first time the world is completely divided
up, so that in the future only redivision is possible i.e. territories
can only be passed from one ‘owner’ to another, instead of passing
as ownerless territory to an ‘owner’ (Lenin, 2010). The passing
of territory from one owner to another inevitably resulted in war
among the capitalist powers.
REFERENCES
Amin, S. (2013), The Implosion of Contemporary Capitalism, New York:
Monthly Review Press.
Bagchi, A.K. (2002), The Other Side of Foreign Investment by Imperial
Powers: Transfer of Surplus from Colonies, Economic and Political
Weekly, Vol. 37, No. 23, pp. 2229-38.
Bairoch, P. (1974), Geographical Structure and Trade Balance of European
Foreign Trade from 1800 to 1970, Journal of European Economic
History, Vol. 3, No. 3, pp. 557-608.
Baran, P. and P.M. Sweezy (1966), Monopoly Capital: An Essay on the
American Economic and Social Order, New York: Monthly Review
Press.
Bieber, F. (2018), Is Nationalism on the Rise? Assessing Global Trends,
Ethnopolitics, Vol. 17, No.5, pp. 519-40.
Boron, A. (2005), Empire and Imperialism: A Critical Reading of Michael
Hardt and Antonio Negri, London: Zed Books.
Bukharin, N. (2010 [1915]), Imperialism and World Economy, New Delhi:
Aakar Books.
Daudin, G., M. Morys, K.H. O’Rourke (2010), Globalisation, 1870-
1914, In S. Broadberry and K.H. O’Rourke (eds.), The Cambridge
Economic History of Modern Europe Vol. 2, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Fei, H. (1930), Europe: The World’s Banker 1870-1914, New Havana: Yale
University Press.
Hilferding, R. (1981 [1910]), Finance Capital: A Study of the Latest Phase
of Capitalist Development, London: Routledge and Kagan Paul.
Hobsbawm, E. (1994), The Age of Empire, London: Abacus Publications.
Hobsbawm, E. (2013), The Age of Extreme, London: Abacus Publications.
Hobson, J.A. (2017 [1902]), Imperialism: A Study, New Delhi: Aakar
Books.
Hobson, J.M. (1993), The Military-Extraction Gap and the Wary Titan:
The Fiscal-Sociology of British Defence Policy, 1870-1913, Journal of
European Economic History, Vol. 22, No. 3, pp. 461-506.
Kautsky, K. (1970 [1914]), Ultra-Imperialism, New Left Review, Vol. 59
No. 1, pp. 42-46.
Keynes, J.M. (1991 [1919]), The Economic Consequences of the Peace,
Palgrave Macmillan.
322 Global Political Economy
Introduction
What is imperialism, specifically in today’s context? This issue is
discussed here in the framework of Marxist political economy.
Imperialism is also an important subject in other areas such as
cultural and literary studies. Those are, however, outside the scope
of this chapter.
A recent book by Utsa Patnaik and Prabhat Patnaik, A Theory of
Imperialism (2017), published by Columbia University Press, claims
to formulate a theory of imperialism that has relevance not only
for the past, but also in the present era. The authors attempt to
refute those Marxist and other writers who today, explicitly ‘reject
the term “imperialism” insofar as it is taken to mean any systemic
tendency for metropolitan capital to dominate the outlying regions
in particular.’
The Patnaiks identify ‘increasing supply price,’ ‘the value
of money’ and ‘income deflation’ as the three central features of
imperialism:
Imperialism …….. is a coercive relationship exercised by the capitalist
sector on the “outside” world to ensure, first, that it obtains the products
that it needs from the “outside” world and second, that it does so at
non-increasing prices………
…….obtaining goods at non-increasing prices from petty producers
located on the tropical landmass, whose products are not producible
324 Global Political Economy
within the capitalist sector that has grown up in the temperate regions
of the world…….
The curtailment of local absorption within the periphery of goods
produced on the tropical landmass is one way of ensuring that the
problem of increasing supply price does not come into play and there
is no threat to the value of the currency in the metropolis as capital
accumulation occurs there……….
Growing demand for the products of the tropical landmass under
these circumstances—in the absence of income deflation imposed on
the users of such products to curtail their demand, and above all on the
populations of the periphery where such products are produced—will
necessarily cause a rise in prices …………and this rise will pose a
threat to the value of money.
This book contains a commentary from David Harvey (2017) which
is extremely critical of the authors’ central argument of ‘increasing
supply price.’ Harvey argues that agricultural products from
tropical and subtropical regions are of minimal significance as far
as metropolitan capitalism’s survival in this age of highly developed
and diversified industrial structure is concerned. According to him,
a theory of imperialism cannot be sustained on the basis of the
dependency of metropolitan capitalism on products from tropical
areas.
To quote Harvey:
The idea that metropolitan capitalism will collapse because of
price inflation in the strawberries and blackberries that come from
Guatemala in winter and the cut flowers that come from Ecuador
or Colombia or that the lack of haricot vert from Kenya in Paris
markets will bring the French economy to its knees is farfetched. Some
seemingly crucial tropical and subtropical products, such as sugar, are
substitutable……….
The dependency of metropolitan capitalism on products from
tropical and subtropical regions produced by petty commodity
producers is nowhere near as significant as the Patnaiks claim. I
cannot imagine that the Indian peasantry is producing much for the
metropolitan market, for example……..
What is Imperialism? Situating Imperialism in Relation... 325
Such ideas had some relevance during the last decade of the 20th
century, but in the early years of the 21st century, these are of no
significance. The thesis of The End of History has been completely
discarded now. The End of History phase ended around the middle
of the first decade of the 21st century with the onset of the most
serious economic financial crisis since the Great Depression.
What is the Marxist Theory of Imperialism? Callinicos (2005)
defines imperialism in the following way:
The Marxist theory of Imperialism is distinctive in that it does not
treat empire simply as a transhistorical form of political domination
…… but rather sets modern imperialism in the context of the historical
development of the capitalist mode of production. (p.1)
‘The Marxist Theory of Imperialism’ does not have much to do
with Marx.2 It is largely due to Lenin.3 In this respect, Lenin’s book
Imperialism: the Highest Stage of Capitalism (1916) has been the
most influential work in this field. The book has the following two
central themes:
1. Imperialism is the monopoly stage of capitalism.
2. Imperialism became associated with the development of
monopolies.
Lenin writes,
If it were necessary to give the briefest possible definition of imperialism,
we should have to say that imperialism is the monopoly stage of
capitalism.
….that capitalism’s transition to the stage of monopoly capitalism,
to finance capital, is connected with the intensification of the struggle
for the partitioning of the world.
Many writers have pointed out the limitations of this analysis—
arguing that historical capitalism has always been imperialist. And
that, colonialism/imperialism has existed even before capitalism
Lenin did not analyse the impact colonisation had on the
colonies. In that sense, it was not a work on colonialism per se.
But any evaluation of Lenin’s work has to take into account the
historical developments taking place in the early part of the 20th
century.4,5,6,7 The task before us right now, however, is to develop an
What is Imperialism? Situating Imperialism in Relation... 329
→
Imperialism/No →
Globalisation/Global capitalism/ IGNORED
Imperialism/ Unequal Exchange/Monopoly capitalism/
Empire/ Monopoly Financial capitalism/
Direction Reversed Neoliberalism/Multinationals/
Transnationals
Economic Political
Generalised Interventions
Monopoly Capitalism Pre-emptive wars
(of the United States, Great Britain, Japan, Germany, France and a few
others). (Amin 2015, pp. 30-31)
The foregoing analysis shows that the linking of imperialism with
capitalism is the main source of the problematic analysis. This
framework may have served a good purpose in the past but it is
not capable of understanding the horrifying reality of today where
the aggression of the Western powers poses a threat to life itself on
the planet. In my opinion, there is thus a need to rescue the term
‘imperialism’ from the above framework. How that is to be done?
Before I talk about my suggestions, let us look at the Patnaiks’ book
again. The Patnaiks opine that:
———Marxist authors in the advanced capitalist countries have
produced very little analysis of colonialism. And thus it is not surprising
that there is a readiness among them to treat imperialism as no longer
relevant……..
[About Harvey]—it is clear that he is unfamiliar with the concept of
“drain.” Indeed the whole of northern academia and even the present
day Marxists, with very few exceptions [Paul A. Barran and Andre
Gunder Frank and Angus Maddison], have systematically ignored
the large literature on the drain available from the South. It refers
not just to the direction of capital flows but to the phenomenon of
sucking out the surplus of an economy without any quid pro quo……
this “drain” occurred in the form of commodities taken out of these
colonies gratis…..
Are there any major continuities between the colonial period and
now, continuities that are rooted in the nature of capital….? (pp. 196)
There are three important points here:
1. The authors are looking for some continuity over the period
of the last 200 years. As we have seen above, the common
thread they discover turns out to be very weak. In fact, too
weak to hold the weight of the mighty phenomenon of
imperialism.
2. Even the common thread that they discover is not continuous.
It has a break of 3-4 decades in the years immediately after
the Second World War.
What is Imperialism? Situating Imperialism in Relation... 331
Imperialism Today
Imperialism is not dead: It has yet not been dislodged from the
position of captain of the earth ship. Although it is true that Western
imperialism faces new unprecedented challenges in the form of
emerging multipolarity in world affairs, it however still remains a
threat to world peace as ever. The fears posed by Western powers
are the reason why the vast majority of global population is unable
to choose paths of living of their own choice.
A new definition of imperialism is required in today’s context.
Most importantly, imperialism needs to be delinked from capitalism.
Imperialism today needs to be conceptualised in terms of gratis plus
the threats that Western countries pose to the rest of the world
or even to the planet itself. The dimensions in which imperialism
today manifests itself are: colonial, climate change, dangerous
technologies, and economic.
Colonial
After the Second World War, most of the colonies gained
independence from direct Western occupation. In South East Asia,
colonial occupation, however, continued till the mid-1970s; and in
case of Africa, till the mid-1980s. With the dissolution of the Soviet
bloc around 1990, the phase of Western hegemony (unipolarity)
started with the US becoming the ‘sole’ superpower. During the early
phase of unipolarity, the Western imperialist powers (particularly
the USA) generally refrained from pursuing colonial conquests in
the Third World countries.
At the beginning of the 21st century, however, Western
colonial conquests restarted. The West did not want the window of
332 Global Political Economy
Climate Change
The climate change phenomenon has acquired life-threating
dimensions. Excessive consumption of natural resources, especially
of fossil fuels, over a very long period in the West is the major source
of our environmental ills. The United States and the European
countries have historically been the world’s largest emitters of
greenhouse gases.
What is Imperialism? Situating Imperialism in Relation... 333
Dangerous Technologies
New developments in the areas of warfare technology, biotechnology,
artificial intelligence (AI) and surveillance technology, governed by
laws of capitalism accumulation with link to high S&T and pursuit
of economic growth, threaten the very survival of human life on the
planet. These are thus imperialist in character.
Major nuclear powers are now engaged in efforts to modernise
their arsenals. New anti-missile technologies and the plans to build
low yield nuclear weapons are disturbing the equilibrium that has
existed in the post-Second World War period. The United States’
new national security strategy displays a “cold war mentality” with
an “imperialist character” as it refuses to renounce a unipolar world.
The prospects for the continuation of arms reduction talks after
the expiry of the treaties that are presently in force appear quite
bleak.
There is now increasing use of artificial intelligence (AI) in
development of harmful technologies such as advance weapons/
warfare technology and surveillance technology. In the long run,
AI poses an existential threat to the human race. Unregulated
334 Global Political Economy
Economic
One major pillar of America’s imperial power is its currency, the
dollar. The dollar’s present strength is a legacy of the colonial era.
Displacing the British pound, the US dollar has been the world’s
most dominant reserve currency since the Second World War. Most
governments and institutions hold their foreign exchange reserves
largely in dollars (in the form of US Treasury bills). In international
trade transactions/payments and international investments, the US
dollar is the most used currency. This makes America a great financial
super power. Due to near-universal acceptability of its currency,
America continues to exercise enormous control on global economic
matters without much challenge from any quarter, at least, yet.
Given that it has a huge influence over the world economy, the
United States increasingly resorts to the use of economic sanctions
against the targeted countries as a powerful weapon in furtherance
of its strategic interests9. Recently, the United States has enacted
a law, Countering America’s Adversaries Through Sanctions Act
(CAATSAA) that imposed sanctions on Iran, North Korea and
Russia. This law mandates the US administration to punish entities
engaging in significant transactions with certain sectors of these
countries.
What is Imperialism? Situating Imperialism in Relation... 335
and if we cut you off then you collapse.” (see The Economic Times, July
2, 2018).
REFERENCES
Amin, S. (2015), Contemporary Imperialism, Monthly Review, Vol. 13.
Nos. 4 & 5.
Bukharin, N. (1973 [1915]), Imperialism and the World Economy, New
York: Monthly Review Press.
Callinicos, A. (2005), Imperialism and Global Political Economy,
International Socialism, Vol. 2, No. 108.
Hardt, M and A. Negri (2000), Empire, Cambridge: Harvard University
Press.
Harvey, D. (2017), A Commentary on A Theory of Imperialism,’ In U.
Patnaik and P. Patnaik, A Theory of Imperialism, New York: Columbia
University Press.
Hilferding, R. (1981 [1910]), Finance Capital, London: Routledge and
Kegan Paul.
Lenin, V. (2010 [1916]), Imperialism the Highest State of Capitalism, New
Delhi: People’s Publishing House.
Luxemburg, R. (1963 [1913]), The Accumulation of Capital, London:
Routledge.
Patnaik, P. (2008), The Value of Money, New Delhi: Tulika Books.
Patnaik, U. and P. Patnaik. (2017), A Theory of Imperialism, New York:
Columbia University Press.
Smith, J. (2017), A Critique of David Harvey’s Analysis of Imperialism,
MR Online, August 26.
16
Climate Crisis and the Idea of Degrowth1
V. Upadhyay
Global Warming
Global warming is one of the defining issues of our time. The
six warmest years in recorded history have been the past six years
from 2014 to 2019 and 2010-2019 was the hottest decade ever
recorded. Since the mid-20th century, the average temperature of
the earth’s climate systems has been rising at an unprecedented rate.
The climate change crisis caused by rising earth temperature poses
an existential threat to life on the planet. In order to safeguard the
future of human civilisation as well as the existence of other species,
there is an urgent need to find effective ways to deal with the climate
crisis.
The major consequences of global warming include, among
many others, melting of glaciers and artic ice, thawing of permafrost,
extreme weather conditions, extinction of many species, expansion
of deserts, and other catastrophic events such as extended draughts
and floods. There is a large body of literature that analyses the life-
threating consequences of climate change in detail.
The Paris Agreement, negotiated by representatives of 196 state
parties and signed in 2016, requires each country to undertake steps
to mitigate global warming. Climate scientists warn of disastrous
consequences due to climate change if global warming is not kept
below 20 centigrades compared to pre-industrial levels. According
to the Intergovernmental Panel on Climate Change (IPCC), it is
imperative to keep global warming below 1.50 centigrades compared
to pre-industrial levels in order to avoid some irreversible impacts.
340 Global Political Economy
NOTES
1. The earlier version of this paper was published in Upadhyay, V. (2016),
(ed.), Essays on Distribution, World Systems, Ecology, and Left Politics.
New Delhi: Daanish Books. This is an extended and revised version.
2. See Onaran (2010).
3. Capitalism is incompatible with a truly ecological civilization because
it is a system that must continually expand, promoting consumption
beyond human needs, while ignoring the limits of non-renewable
resources (the tap) and the earth’s waste assimilation capacity (the
sink), (Magdoff, 2011).
4. We have now reached a situation where the global capitalist system
poses a serious threat to the very survival of human civilisation. As
Li (2011) puts it, ‘(T)he current historical context is fundamentally
different from any previous movement in capitalist history. After
centuries of relentless capitalist accumulation, the global ecological
system is on the verge of collapse and the developing global ecological
crisis threatens to destroy human civilisation within the twenty-first
century.’
5. ‘…in terms of the immediate crisis our time that began in 2006, the
question of natural limits cannot, on the surface at least, be accorded
primacy of place…’ (Harvey, 2011, p. 78).
6. With reference to the US economy, Magdoff and Yates (2009)
explain this aspect in the following manner: …let us ask ourselves an
important question. Is, the roller-coaster ride that capitalism is, what
we want? Suppose that, in a few years, somehow things got back to
“normal,” with the GDP growing at between 2.5 and 3 per cent, with
official unemployment between 4 and 5 per cent, with wages growing
only enough to keep up with inflation. Suppose even, that we have a
better healthcare system than we have now. What then? The “health”
of US economy now depends on increasing exploitation at work,
supposedly compensated through ever-rising private consumption.
What have been the consequences of this? Longer, harder hours have
compromised the health and quality of life of workers, reducing their
best hours to meaningless drudgery. Rising consumption of more
meaningless “stuff ” has polluted our planet; it has filled our house
with junk we never use; it has forced us to think we need bigger
and bigger houses, which in turn has compelled us to move into the
suburbs and exurbs, wasting power and water, creating vast expanses
Climate Crisis and the Idea of Degrowth 351
REFERENCES
Harvey, D. (2011), The Enigma of Capital: And the Crises of Capitalism.
UK: Profile Books.
Foster, J.B. (2011), Capitalism and Degrowth—An Impossibility Theorem,
Analytical Monthly Review, Vol. 8, No. 7.
Foster, J.B., C. Brett and R. York. (2010), Capitalism and the Curse of
Energy Efficiency: The Return of the Jevons Paradox, Analytical
Monthly Review, Vol. 8, No. 10.
Latouche, S. (2006), The Globe Downshifted, Le Monde Diplomatique
(English Edition).
Levins, R. (2011), Continuing Sources of Marxism: Looking for the
Movement as a Whole, Analytical Monthly Review, Vol. 8, No. 10.
Li. M. (2011), The Rise of the Working Class and the Future of the
Chinese Revolution, Analytical Monthly Review, Vol. 9, No. 3.
Magdoff, F. (2011), Ecological Civilization, Analytical Monthly Review,
Vol. 8, No. 10.
Magdoff, F and J.B. Foster (2010), What Every Environmentalist Needs to
Know About Capitalism, Analytical Monthly Review, Vol. 7, No. 12.
Magdoff, F. and Michael D. Yates (2009), What Needs to be Done: A
Socialist View, Analytical Monthly Review, Vol. 7, No. 8.
Onaran, O. (2010), The Crisis of Capitalism in Europe, West and East,
Analytical Monthly Review, Vol. 8, No. 7.
Wallerstein, I. (2011), Structural Crisis in the World System: Where Do
We Go from Here?, Monthly Review, Vol. 62, No. 10.
17
Capitalism, Ecology and Eco-Socialism
Pritam Singh
Introduction
This paper is an attempt to contribute to an eco-socialist critique of
the widely prevailing theoretical perspectives on capitalism, its crisis
and the solutions offered to this crisis. We will focus on examining
Keynesianism, monetarism/neo-liberalism, traditional Marxism
and the Green perspective. We conclude by arguing that a critical
synthesis of Marxian and Green perspectives best captures the most
dominant form of the current crisis—the global environmental
crisis—of capitalism and offers the most creative way of dealing
with this crisis.
Neo-Classical Perspective
From the 1870s till the Great Depression of 1929-33, the neo-classical
economic theory had held an almost unquestioned hegemony as an
economic doctrine (Bharadwaj 1986). This doctrine preached that
a market-based capitalist economy had an inbuilt mechanism to
keep the economy in equilibrium. This equilibrium, it was argued,
ensured among other things, full employment. Any deviations from
this equilibrium, it was argued, got corrected by the forces of supply
and demand in the market. This comforting belief or world outlook
was rudely shaken by the Great Depression that witnessed major
disequilibrium in the labour and product markets. This led to a
fundamental crisis of the neo-classical economic doctrine that had
for nearly six decades preached the infallibility of the markets.
Neoclassical theorists emphasised scarcity of resources as an
354 Global Political Economy
Keynesianism
The crisis of neoclassical economic theory saw the emergence of
an alternative economic paradigm of Keynesianism. John Maynard
Keynes (1883-1946) developed a critique of neo-classical economic
doctrine by arguing that in a situation of economic recession, the
state needs to take an active part in giving a stimulus to the economy
(Keynes, 1936). A part of this stimulus effort, Keynes believed, was
to redistribute income and raise the level of aggregate demand in
the economy. His idea that redistribution of income would raise
the level of aggregate demand in the economy was based on his
insight that low income individuals and groups were more likely
to spend any additional rise in their income than what the high
income groups were likely to do. Conceptually, this is expressed as:
the marginal propensity to consume of low-income groups is higher
than that of the high-income groups. The rise of Keynesianism
justifying the role of state intervention in a free-market oriented
capitalist economy was a significant development in providing
theoretical foundations for the desirability of a welfare state. The
moral dimension of the welfare state as a protector of the weak and
vulnerable had a long history in the British political, religious and
social traditions (Fraser, 2009; Thane, 1996; Hennock, 2007; Lowe,
2005) but Keynesianism provided an economic dimension. In the
Keynesian framework, the redistributive role of the welfare state was
necessary for economic reasons, i.e. for giving an economic stimulus
to a depressed economy to move towards economic growth. This
economic necessity of the welfare state for economic growth was
what propelled Keynesian ideas to widespread acceptance among
political leaders and economic policy makers. Keynes’s influence on
the move towards welfare state policy approach was most dramatic
in the UK although he influenced, in varying degrees, the policy
Capitalism, Ecology and Eco-Socialism 355
Eco-Socialist Perspective
One major challenge to the reinstatement of expansionary fiscal
policy that is being advocated globally to deal with the recession
emerging from the Covid-19 crisis is that we are simultaneously
faced with a huge and unprecedented ecological crisis. The world
economy has reached a stage where to stop global heating and
climate change, the goal of accelerated economic growth must be
replaced by a more sustainable approach to development (Singh,
2008, 2008a, 2020; Castree, 2010). When the 1929-33 crisis was
resolved by the expansionary fiscal policy inspired by Keynesian
economic policy, there was neither the theoretical knowledge of the
environmental consequences of economic policy nor the material
reality of the scale of climate change which is being witnessed
now. One line of thought that recognises the enormity of global
climate change suggests that instead of the traditional expansionary
policy, our present era needs a green expansionary policy or Green
Keynesianism. Such a green expansionary or a Green Keynesian
policy would entail a drastically changed transport system, energy
policy, housing policy and creation of what are called green jobs.
Undoubtedly, many of these green policies have positive elements
because one could say that green capitalism is better than ungreen
and dirty capitalism, but this approach is evasive on the mode of
production-environmental destruction link (Singh, 2020). It does
not recognise that capitalism is essentially a profit-driven economic
system and is therefore inherently destructive of the environment.
This profit-driven system is based on exploitation of natural
resources (O’Connor, 1998) and continuously needs multiplication
of consumer wants to generate the market for the commodities
produced by the use of natural resources (Panayotakis, 2011).
A fundamental alternative to environmentally destructive
capitalism is the vision of ecological socialism (Singh, 2010, 2010a,
2014, 2020). That vision, on one hand, does not entail the need for
a welfare state because the necessity for the welfare state arises out
of inequalities in capitalism where the poor and the disadvantaged
need to be cared for in some way but, on the other hand, implies
Capitalism, Ecology and Eco-Socialism 371
welfare for all because there would not be a division between the
privileged few and the underprivileged many in the eco-socialist
society. However, that goal is a long term one or a medium term
one, and in the journey towards that goal, the strengthening of
the welfare state is desirable because the idea of the welfare state
recognises the institution of community and the collective effort
required in responding to some needs of the community. Dearlove
and Saunders (1984, 319) have rightly pointed out that “The Welfare
State represents a “Trojan horse” within the citadels of capitalism
in that it rests firmly on a set of values which are fundamentally
opposed to those of capitalism”.
Both neoliberal austerity and Keynesian welfare/stimulus
stratagems are two different forms of governance of capitalism in
response to different phases/cycles of capitalism. The competition
between them is only on which one is more efficient, i.e. which one
generates higher and maximum possible economic growth. Both
are, therefore, anti-ecological. However, from a social equity point
of view, the neoliberal austerity paradigm is far more inegalitarian
than the Keynesian welfare/stimulus one. Eco-socialism is, therefore,
sharply critical of neo-liberal austerity paradigm but has some
degrees of affinity with the ecologically modified Keynesian welfare
paradigm as a basis for building egalitarian future (Singh, 2020).
Eco-socialism is emerging as a new historically necessary response
to the challenges of environmentally destructive growth and increase
in poverty both in the developing capitalism economies as well as in
the developed capitalist economies. The programme of the Green
New Deal is the transitional path to eco-socialism (Singh, 2020).
NOTES
1. I wish to acknowledge that a very fruitful discussion with Liz Perez
was helpful on this point.
2. A good articulation of the external market dimension of Luxemburg’s
theory of imperialism is Patnaik (1972).
3. I have used the word ‘global heating’ instead of the often used word
‘global warming’ because global warming seems to suggest a slower and
less intense process of rise in global temperature than what is conveyed
372 Global Political Economy
level as in some Third World economies. See Singh (2008, 2008a) for
further development of the argument on environmental implications
of the rising economic powers of BRICS economies.
REFERENCES
Amin, S. (1976), Imperialism and Unequal Development, New York:
Monthly Review Press.
Baran, P. (1968), Political Economy of Growth, New York: Monthly Review
Press.
Bernstein, H. and P. Woodhouse (2007), Africa: Eco-Populist Utopias and
(Micro-) Capitalist Realities, pp. 147-69, In C. Leys and L. Panitch
(eds.), Socialist Register 2007: Coming to Terms with Nature, London:
Merlin Press.
Bharadwaj, K. (1986), Classical Political Economy and Rise to Dominance of
Supply and Demand Theories, Delhi: Sangam Books.
Castree, N. (2010), Crisis, Continuity and Change: Neoliberalism, the
Left and the Future of Capitalism, Antipode, Vol. 41, No.1, pp. 185-
213.
Dearlove, J and P. Saunders (1984), Introduction to British Politics: Analysing
a Capitalist Democracy, Cambridge: Polity Press.
Foldvary, Fred E. (ed.), (1996), Beyond Neo-Classical Economics: Heterodox
Approaches to Economic Theory, Cheltenham: Edward Elgar.
Frank, Andre G. (1966), Development of Underdevelopment, London: New
England Press.
Fraser, D. (2009), The Evolution of the British Welfare State, London:
Palgrave Macmillan. Fourth Edition.
Gough, I. (1979), The Political Economy of the Welfare State, London:
Macmillan.
Gough, I. (1997), State Expenditure in Advanced Capitalism, New Left
Review I/92, July-August.
Harriss-White, B. and E. Harriss (2007), ‘Unsustainable Capitalism: The
Politics of Renewable Energy in the UK’, pp. 72-101, In C. Leys and
L. Panitch (eds.), Socialist Register 2007: Coming to Terms with Nature,
London: Merlin Press.
Harvey, D. (2007), A Brief History of Neoliberalism, Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Hayek, F. (1944 [1997]), The Road to Serfdom, London: Routledge.
374 Global Political Economy
Hennock, E.P. (2007), The Origin of the Welfare State in England and
Germany, 1850-1914: Some Policies Compared, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Jacobs, M. (1993), Green Economy, London: Pluto Press.
Keynes, J.M. (2007 [1936]), The General Theory of Employment, Interest
and Money. London: Macmillan.
Konzelmann, Suzanne J. (2014), The Political Economics of Austerity,
Cambridge Journal of Economics, Vol. 38, No. 4, pp. 701-41.
Lenin, V.I. (1930), Imperialism: The Highest Stage of Capitalism,
International Publishers, New York.
Lowe, R. (2005), The Welfare State in Britain Since 1945, Basingstoke/New
York: Palgrave Macmillan.
Luxemburg, R. (1951), The Accumulation of Capital (with an introduction
by Joan Robinson), New Haven: Yale University Press.
Marx, K. and F. Engels (2002 [1848]), Communist Manifesto, London:
Penguin Books.
Niskanen, William A. (1988), Reaganomics: An Insider’s Account of the
Policies and the People, Oxford University Press: Oxford.
O’Connor, J. (1998), Natural Causes: Essays in Ecological Marxism, New
York: Guildford Press.
Panayotakis, C. (2011), Remaking Scarcity: From Capitalist Inefficiency to
Economic Democracy, London: Pluto Press.
Patnaik, P. (1972), A Note on External Markets and Capitalist Development,
The Economic Journal, Vol. 82, No. 328, pp. 1316-323. reprinted in
Patnaik (1995), Whatever Happened to Imperialism and Other Essays,
Tulika, New Delhi.
Piketty, T. (2014), Capital in the Twenty-First Century. Cambridge,
Massachussets; London, England: Harvard University Press.
Radice, H. (2014), Thatcherism and Alternatives: What Future for British
Capitalism? Capital and Class, Vol. 38, No. 2, pp. 277-87.
Rostow, W.W. (1960), Stages of Economic Growth: A Non-Communist
Manifesto, Massachusetts: Cambridge.
Shiva, V. (1989), Staying Alive, London: Zed Books.
Singh, P. (2008), ‘Shifting Balance’, Himal, June, Kathmandu.
Singh, P. (2008a), Contemporary Global Capitalism: Multi-pronged
Crises, Economic and Political Weekly, Vol. 43 No. 41, pp. 36-40.
Capitalism, Ecology and Eco-Socialism 375
greenhouse gas emissions in the United States had fallen 14 per cent
by 2016 (Hausfather, 2017). But the declines gradually stalled and
emissions in 2018 actually increased by more than 3 per cent, the
largest rise in 8 years (Plumer, 2019). A hyperactive transportation
sector, always critical to economic growth, was the leading culprit
behind the latest surge. Recent US experience further reinforces
the notion that large-scale reductions in emissions are virtually
impossible under an economic system that prioritizes growth above
anything else. The unlimited pressure to increase consumption and
production can lead to rising emissions even in the context of macro
level efficiency gains and technological innovations.
For the world as a whole, a strong positive relationship exists
between primary energy consumption and economic growth, and
numerous studies on various countries and regions indicate that this
relationship is fundamentally causal.25 Over the last few decades, the
rate of global economic growth has started to slow down, mirroring
the declining rate of growth in global energy consumption. Some
major economies, like those of Japan and the European Union,
have already entered periods of stagnation associated with very low
growth rates and aging populations. Because these economies are
currently dominated by corrupt financial sectors, they are generating
uneven growth patterns that mostly enrich wealthy capitalists. By
contrast, ordinary people are increasingly drowning in debt so they
can finance the cycles and crises of capitalism (Dickler, 2019).
Economic progress for the vast majority of society has come to a
screeching halt (Desilver, 2018). The global economy may continue
to grow at modest rates for the rest of this century, but the signs are
already evident that our potential for future growth is limited and
constrained by what kinds of energy sources we can collect from the
natural world, as well as by the economic irrationalities of today’s
financialised capitalism.
Capitalism is running out of steam, but not quickly enough to
substantially reduce aggregate emissions. Global carbon emissions
over the last century have closely followed changes in primary energy
consumption. At the start of the decade, optimism about global
warming was high. Greenhouse gas emissions flatlined for several
Energy, Economic Growth, and Ecological Crisis 391
years and the upper echelons of the global economy started to believe
that economic growth could actually be decoupled from harmful
emissions. In 2016, the International Energy Agency triumphantly
declared: “Decoupling of global emissions and economic growth
confirmed.”26 What a difference two years can make. In 2017,
greenhouse gas emissions worldwide saw a sharp spike (Hausfather,
2017). Against a backdrop of increasingly alarming scientific reports
about the dangers of global warming, emissions rose again for 2018,
at a faster pace than the previous year (Carrington, 2018). Even some
advanced economies that had supposedly decoupled growth from
pollution witnessed higher carbon emissions in 2018. Detaching
emissions from economic growth has turned out to be a vastly more
complicated problem than global elites originally believed.
A persistent albatross on this issue is the way that most elites
talk about carbon emissions. When governments and organisations
measure greenhouse gas emissions, they often do so at the point of
manufacture and production. If a US company sets up a factory in
India to produce commodities that are then sold to US consumers,
the emissions coming from that factory are credited to India, not the
United States. This basic process of what is referred to as geographic
substitution, where corporations from the capitalist core transfer
ecologically destructive manufacturing to developing nations with
large pools of cheap labour, has been an important source of the
observed divergence between carbon emissions and economic
growth in the Western world.27 In other words, measuring emissions
from the point of consumption hardly reveals any decoupling at
all. In any case, multinational corporations can only keep shifting
production around so much before they run out of places to go.
There are limits to geographic substitution as well.
Besides comparing aggregate demand to emissions, another
approach for understanding the material foundations of economic
growth focuses on the flow of raw materials on their way to the
final point of consumption. In a landmark 2012 paper, a group of
Australian researchers analysed the aggregate raw materials exchanged
among countries through international trade and introduced the
concept of the material footprint, defined as the global allocation
392 Global Political Economy
2. Marx writes that “The tendency to create the world market is directly
given in the concept of capital itself. Every limit appears as a barrier
to be overcome.” See Karl Marx (1973).
3. For a prominent example of this line of thinking, see Obama, (2017).
Obama writes: “This ‘decoupling’ of energy sector emissions and
economic growth should put to rest the argument that combatting
climate change requires accepting lower growth or a lower standard
of living.”
4. A major issue is the aggregation problem, one of the central weak
points in all of macroeconomics. For an excellent, nontechnical
introduction to the aggregation problem, see Fix (2019). For a more
technical treatment, see J. Felipe and F.M. Fisher (2003): 208–62. The
essence of the aggregation problem is the following question: Under
what conditions can you add up a bunch of stuff and be certain that
you have the right total value? The basic answer is that you can add
things up when you have a stable unit of measurement, like mass or
energy. In a natural science, like physics, unit stability is a critical
requirement for measurement and aggregation. See Gibney (2018)
contrast, aggregation is a meaningless concept with unstable units of
measurement, such as commodity prices in economics. One cannot
define or determine a “real,” inflation- adjusted aggregate through
unstable units. Many economists find supposedly clever ways to get
around this problem. In his famous 1956 paper, Robert Solow flatly
declared: “There is only one commodity, output as a whole.… Thus
we can speak unambiguously of the community’s real income.” In
other words, he brushed aside the aggregation problem by creating an
abstract economy with only one commodity. The flagrant absurdity of
this move is par for the course in neoclassical theory, where ridiculous
assumptions about the world are more common than breathing
oxygen. See Solow (1956).There are other critical concerns with using
GDP as a measure of economic value, such as the fact that it does not
take into account ecological degradation and vital social services. For
more on this line of criticism, see Ward et al., (2017).
5. For a recent example of this conflation, see Moreau (2018) right away
by saying: “Decoupling economic growth from energy consumption is
a widespread attempt to decarbonise economic activities and increase
energy security.”
6. See OECD (2001). For a list of things that are included under
primary consumption in the United States, see the entry “Primary
398 Global Political Economy
REFERENCES
Ackerman F. (2002), Still Dead After All These Years: Interpreting the
Failure of General Equilibrium, Journal of Economic Methodology, Vol.
9, No. 2, pp. 119–39.
Asafu-Adjaye J. (2000), The Relationship Between Energy Consumption,
Energy Prices, and Economic Growth: Time Series Evidence from
Asian Developing Countries, Energy Economics, Vol. 22, No. 6, pp.
615–25.
Bentley, J.H. (2013), Environment Crisis in the World History, Procedia—
Social and Behavioural Sciences, Vol. 77, pp. 108–15.
Bernstein, L. (2018), S. Life Expectancy Declines Again, a Dismal Trend
Not Seen Since World War I, Washington Post, November 29.
British Petroleum (2018), BP Statistical Review of World Energy, London:
British Petroleum.
Buck, T. (2018), Energy Shift Fails to Cut German Carbon, Financial
Times, October 8.
Carrington, D. (2018), Brutal News: Global Carbon Emissions Jump to
All-Time High in 2018, The Guardian, December 5.
Collins, J.M. and K. Walsh (eds.), (2017), Hurricanes and Climate Change,
Vol. 3, New York: Springer.
Davies and B. Doherty (2018), Corruption, Incompetence and a Musical:
Nauru’s Cursed History, The Guardian, September 3.
Desilver, (2018), For Most US Workers, Real Wages Have Barely Budged
in Decades, Pew Research Centre, August 7.
Dennis, B. and C. Mooney (2018), We Are in Trouble: Global Carbon
Emissions Reached a Record High in 2018, Washington Post, December
5.
Dickler, D. (2019), Consumer Debt Hits $4 Trillion, CNBC, February 21.
Felipe, J. and J.S.L. McCombie (2005), How Sound Are the Foundations
of the Aggregate Production Function?, Eastern Economic Journal Vol.
31, No. 3, pp. 467–88.
Felipe, J. and F.M. Fisher, (2003), Aggregation in Production Functions:
What Applied Economists Should Know, Metroeconomica, Vol. 54,
Energy, Economic Growth, and Ecological Crisis 401
Ward, J., et al. (2017), The Decoupling Delusion: Rethinking Growth and
Sustainability, The Conversation, March 12, 2017.
Wernick, A. (2019), Climate Change Is the Overlooked Driver of Central
American Migration, PRI, February 6.
Worstall, T. (2014), When Physicists Do Economics We Seem Not to
Get Economics as the Result, Forbes, October 6.
Wiedmann, T.O. et al. (2013), The Material Footprint of Nations,
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences, Vol. 112, No. 20, pp.
6271–76.
Wu, X., et al. (2016), Impact of Climate Change on Human Infectious
Diseases: Empirical Evidence and Human Adaption, Environment
International, Vol. 86, pp. 14–23.
List of Contributors