On The Intellectual Discussion of Love
On The Intellectual Discussion of Love
On The Intellectual Discussion of Love
This article examines the nature of love and some of the ethical and political
ramifications. For the philosopher, the question “what is love?” generates a host of
issues: love is an abstract noun which means for some it is a word unattached to
anything real or sensible, that is all; for others, it is a means by which our being—our
self and its world—are irrevocably affected once we are ‘touched by love’; some have
sought to analyze it, others have preferred to leave it in the realm of the ineffable.
Yet it is undeniable that love plays an enormous and unavoidable role in our several
cultures; we find it discussed in song, film, and novels—humorously or seriously; it is a
constant theme of maturing life and a vibrant theme for youth. Philosophically, the
nature of love has, since the time of the Ancient Greeks, been a mainstay in philosophy,
producing theories that range from the materialistic conception of love as purely a
physical phenomenon—an animalistic or genetic urge that dictates our behavior—to
theories of love as an intensely spiritual affair that in its highest permits us to touch
divinity. Historically, in the Western tradition, Plato’s Symposium presents the
initiating text, for it provides us with an enormously influential and attractive notion
that love is characterized by a series of elevations, in which animalistic desire or base
lust is superseded by a more intellectual conception of love which also is surpassed by
what may be construed by a theological vision of love that transcends sensual attraction
and mutuality. Since then there have been detractors and supporters of Platonic love as
well as a host of alternative theories—including that of Plato’s student, Aristotle and his
more secular theory of true love reflecting what he described as ‘two bodies and one
soul.’
Table of Contents
1. The Nature of Love: Eros, Philia, and Agape
a. Eros
b. Philia
c. Agape
2. The Nature of Love: Further Conceptual Considerations
3. The Nature of Love: Romantic Love
4. The Nature of Love: Physical, Emotional, Spiritual
5. Love: Ethics and Politics
6. References and Further Reading
1. The Nature of Love: Eros, Philia, and Agape
The philosophical discussion regarding love logically begins with questions concerning
its nature. This implies that love has a “nature,” a proposition that some may oppose
arguing that love is conceptually irrational, in the sense that it cannot be described in
rational or meaningful propositions. For such critics, who are presenting a metaphysical
and epistemological argument, love may be an ejection of emotions that defy rational
examination; on the other hand, some languages, such as Papuan, do not even admit the
concept, which negates the possibility of a philosophical examination. In English, the
word “love,” which is derived from Germanic forms of the Sanskrit lubh (desire), is
broadly defined and hence imprecise, which generates first order problems of definition
and meaning, which are resolved to some extent by the reference to the Greek
terms, eros, philia, and agape.
a. Eros
The term eros (Greek erasthai) is used to refer to that part of love constituting a
passionate, intense desire for something; it is often referred to as a sexual desire, hence
the modern notion of “erotic” (Greek erotikos). In Plato‘s writings however, eros is held to
be a common desire that seeks transcendental beauty-the particular beauty of an
individual reminds us of true beauty that exists in the world of Forms or Ideas
(Phaedrus 249E: “he who loves the beautiful is called a lover because he partakes of it.”
Trans. Jowett). The Platonic-Socratic position maintains that the love we generate for
beauty on this earth can never be truly satisfied until we die; but in the meantime we
should aspire beyond the particular stimulating image in front of us to the
contemplation of beauty in itself.
The implication of the Platonic theory of eros is that ideal beauty, which is reflected in
the particular images of beauty we find, becomes interchangeable across people and
things, ideas, and art: to love is to love the Platonic form of beauty-not a particular
individual, but the element they posses of true (Ideal) beauty. Reciprocity is not
necessary to Plato’s view of love, for the desire is for the object (of Beauty), than for, say,
the company of another and shared values and pursuits.
Many in the Platonic vein of philosophy hold that love is an intrinsically higher value
than appetitive or physical desire. Physical desire, they note, is held in common with the
animal kingdom. Hence, it is of a lower order of reaction and stimulus than a rationally
induced love—that is, a love produced by rational discourse and exploration of ideas,
which in turn defines the pursuit of Ideal beauty. Accordingly, the physical love of an
object, an idea, or a person in itself is not a proper form of love, love being a reflection of
that part of the object, idea, or person, that partakes in Ideal beauty.
b. Philia
In contrast to the desiring and passionate yearning of eros, philia entails a fondness and
appreciation of the other. For the Greeks, the term philia incorporated not just
friendship, but also loyalties to family and polis-one’s political community, job, or
discipline. Philia for another may be motivated, as Aristotle explains in the Nicomachean
Ethics, Book VIII, for the agent’s sake or for the other’s own sake. The motivational
distinctions are derived from love for another because the friendship is wholly useful as
in the case of business contacts, or because their character and values are pleasing (with
the implication that if those attractive habits change, so too does the friendship), or for
the other in who they are in themselves, regardless of one’s interests in the matter. The
English concept of friendship roughly captures Aristotle’s notion of philia, as he writes:
“things that cause friendship are: doing kindnesses; doing them unasked; and not
proclaiming the fact when they are done” (Rhetoric, II. 4, trans. Rhys Roberts).
Aristotle elaborates on the kinds of things we seek in proper friendship, suggesting that
the proper basis for philia is objective: those who share our dispositions, who bear no
grudges, who seek what we do, who are temperate, and just, who admire us
appropriately as we admire them, and so on. Philia could not emanate from those who
are quarrelsome, gossips, aggressive in manner and personality, who are unjust, and so
on. The best characters, it follows, may produce the best kind of friendship and hence
love: indeed, how to be a good character worthy of philia is the theme of the Nicomachaen
Ethics. The most rational man is he who would be the happiest, and he, therefore, who is
capable of the best form of friendship, which between two “who are good, and alike in
virtue” is rare (NE, VIII.4 trans. Ross). We can surmise that love between such equals-
Aristotle’s rational and happy men-would be perfect, with circles of diminishing quality
for those who are morally removed from the best. He characterizes such love as “a sort
of excess of feeling”. (NE, VIII.6)
Friendships of a lesser quality may also be based on the pleasure or utility that is derived
from another’s company. A business friendship is based on utility–on mutual reciprocity
of similar business interests; once the business is at an end, then the friendship
dissolves. This is similar to those friendships based on the pleasure that is derived from
the other’s company, which is not a pleasure enjoyed for whom the other person is in
himself, but in the flow of pleasure from his actions or humour.
The first condition for the highest form of Aristotelian love is that a man loves himself.
Without an egoistic basis, he cannot extend sympathy and affection to others (NE, IX.8).
Such self-love is not hedonistic, or glorified, depending on the pursuit of immediate
pleasures or the adulation of the crowd, it is instead a reflection of his pursuit of the
noble and virtuous, which culminate in the pursuit of the reflective life. Friendship with
others is required “since his purpose is to contemplate worthy actions… to live
pleasantly… sharing in discussion and thought” as is appropriate for the virtuous man
and his friend (NE, IX.9). The morally virtuous man deserves in turn the love of those
below him; he is not obliged to give an equal love in return, which implies that the
Aristotelian concept of love is elitist or perfectionist: “In all friendships implying
inequality the love also should be proportional, i.e. the better should be more loved than
he loves.” (NE, VIII, 7,). Reciprocity, although not necessarily equal, is a condition of
Aristotelian love and friendship, although parental love can involve a one-sided
fondness.
c. Agape
Agape refers to the paternal love of God for man and of man for God but is extended to
include a brotherly love for all humanity. (The Hebrew ahev has a slightly wider
semantic range than agape). Agape arguably draws on elements from
both eros and philia in that it seeks a perfect kind of love that is at once a fondness, a
transcending of the particular, and a passion without the necessity of reciprocity. The
concept is expanded on in the Judaic-Christian tradition of loving God: “You shall love
the Lord your God with all your heart, and with all your soul, and with all your might”
(Deuteronomy 6:5) and loving “thy neighbour as thyself” (Leviticus 19:18). The love of
God requires absolute devotion that is reminiscent of Plato’s love of Beauty (and
Christian translators of Plato such as St. Augustine employed the connections), which
involves an erotic passion, awe, and desire that transcends earthly cares and obstacles.
Aquinas, on the other hand, picked up on the Aristotelian theories of friendship and love
to proclaim God as the most rational being and hence the most deserving of one’s love,
respect, and considerations.
The universalist command to “love thy neighbor as thyself” refers the subject to those
surrounding him, whom he should love unilaterally if necessary. The command employs
the logic of mutual reciprocity, and hints at an Aristotelian basis that the subject should
love himself in some appropriate manner: for awkward results would ensue if he loved
himself in a particularly inappropriate, perverted manner! Philosophers can debate the
nature of “self-love” implied in this—from the Aristotelian notion that self-love is
necessary for any kind of interpersonal love, to the condemnation of egoism and the
impoverished examples that pride and self-glorification from which to base one’s love of
another. St. Augustine relinquishes the debate—he claims that no command is needed
for a man to love himself (De bono viduitatis, xxi). Analogous to the logic of “it is better to
give than to receive”, the universalism of agape requires an initial invocation from
someone: in a reversal of the Aristotelian position, the onus for the Christian is on the
morally superior to extend love to others. Nonetheless, the command also entails an
egalitarian love-hence the Christian code to “love thy enemies” (Matthew 5:44-45). Such
love transcends any perfectionist or aristocratic notions that some are (or should be)
more loveable than others. Agape finds echoes in the ethics of Kant and Kierkegaard, who
assert the moral importance of giving impartial respect or love to another
person qua human being in the abstract.
However, loving one’s neighbor impartially (James 2:9) invokes serious ethical
concerns, especially if the neighbor ostensibly does not warrant love. Debate thus begins
on what elements of a neighbor’s conduct should be included in agape, and which should
be excluded. Early Christians asked whether the principle applied only to disciples of
Christ or to all. The impartialists won the debate asserting that the neighbor’s humanity
provides the primary condition of being loved; nonetheless his actions may require a
second order of criticisms, for the logic of brotherly love implies that it is a moral
improvement on brotherly hate. For metaphysical dualists, loving the soul rather than
the neighbor’s body or deeds provides a useful escape clause-or in turn the justification
for penalizing the other’s body for sin and moral transgressions, while releasing the
proper object of love-the soul-from its secular torments. For Christian pacifists, “turning
the other cheek” to aggression and violence implies a hope that the aggressor will
eventually learn to comprehend the higher values of peace, forgiveness, and a love for
humanity.
The universalism of agape runs counter to the partialism of Aristotle and poses a variety
of ethical implications. Aquinas admits a partialism in love towards those to whom we
are related while maintaining that we should be charitable to all, whereas others such as
Kierkegaard insist on impartiality. Recently, Hugh LaFallotte (1991) has noted that to
love those one is partial towards is not necessarily a negation of the impartiality
principle, for impartialism could admit loving those closer to one as an impartial
principle, and, employing Aristotle’s conception of self-love, iterates that loving others
requires an intimacy that can only be gained from being partially intimate. Others would
claim that the concept of universal love, of loving all equally, is not only impracticable,
but logically empty-Aristotle, for example, argues: “One cannot be a friend to many
people in the sense of having friendship of the perfect type with them, just as one cannot
be in love with many people at once (for love is a sort of excess of feeling, and it is the
nature of such only to be felt towards one person)” (NE, VIII.6).
2. The Nature of Love: Further Conceptual Considerations
Presuming love has a nature, it should be, to some extent at least, describable within the
concepts of language. But what is meant by an appropriate language of description may
be as philosophically beguiling as love itself. Such considerations invoke the philosophy
of language, of the relevance and appropriateness of meanings, but they also provide the
analysis of “love” with its first principles. Does it exist and if so, is it knowable,
comprehensible, and describable? Love may be knowable and comprehensible to others,
as understood in the phrases, “I am in love”, “I love you”, but what “love” means in these
sentences may not be analyzed further: that is, the concept “love” is irreducible-an
axiomatic, or self-evident, state of affairs that warrants no further intellectual intrusion,
an apodictic category perhaps, that a Kantian may recognize.
The epistemology of love asks how we may know love, how we may understand it,
whether it is possible or plausible to make statements about others or ourselves being in
love (which touches on the philosophical issue of private knowledge versus public
behavior). Again, the epistemology of love is intimately connected to the philosophy of
language and theories of the emotions. If love is purely an emotional condition, it is
plausible to argue that it remains a private phenomenon incapable of being accessed by
others, except through an expression of language, and language may be a poor indicator
of an emotional state both for the listener and the subject. Emotivists would hold that a
statement such as “I am in love” is irreducible to other statements because it is a
nonpropositional utterance, hence its veracity is beyond examination.
Phenomenologists may similarly present love as a non-cognitive phenomenon. Scheler,
for example, toys with Plato’s Ideal love, which is cognitive, claiming: “love itself…
brings about the continuous emergence of ever-higher value in the object–just as if it
were streaming out from the object of its own accord, without any exertion (even of
wishing) on the part of the lover” (1954, p. 57). The lover is passive before the beloved.
The claim that “love” cannot be examined is different from that claiming
“love” should not be subject to examination-that it should be put or left beyond the
mind’s reach, out of a dutiful respect for its mysteriousness, its awesome, divine, or
romantic nature. But if it is agreed that there is such a thing as “love” conceptually
speaking, when people present statements concerning love, or admonitions such as “she
should show more love,” then a philosophical examination seems appropriate: is it
synonymous with certain patterns of behavior, of inflections in the voice or manner, or
by the apparent pursuit and protection of a particular value (“Look at how he dotes upon
his flowers-he must love them”)?
If love does possesses “a nature” which is identifiable by some means-a personal
expression, a discernible pattern of behavior, or other activity, it can still be asked
whether that nature can be properly understood by humanity. Love may have a nature,
yet we may not possess the proper intellectual capacity to understand it-accordingly, we
may gain glimpses perhaps of its essence-as Socrates argues in The Symposium, but its
true nature being forever beyond humanity’s intellectual grasp. Accordingly, love may
be partially described, or hinted at, in a dialectic or analytical exposition of the concept
but never understood in itself. Love may therefore become an epiphenomenal entity,
generated by human action in loving, but never grasped by the mind or language. Love
may be so described as a Platonic Form, belonging to the higher realm of transcendental
concepts that mortals can barely conceive of in their purity, catching only glimpses of
the Forms’ conceptual shadows that logic and reason unveil or disclose.
Another view, again derived from Platonic philosophy, may permit love to be
understood by certain people and not others. This invokes a hierarchical epistemology,
that only the initiated, the experienced, the philosophical, or the poetical or musical,
may gain insights into its nature. On one level this admits that only the experienced can
know its nature, which is putatively true of any experience, but it also may imply a social
division of understanding-that only philosopher kings may know true love. On the first
implication, those who do not feel or experience love are incapable (unless initiated
through rite, dialectical philosophy, artistic processes, and so on) of comprehending its
nature, whereas the second implication suggests (though this is not a logically necessary
inference) that the non-initiated, or those incapable of understanding, feel only physical
desire and not “love.” Accordingly, “love” belongs either to the higher faculties of all,
understanding of which requires being educated in some manner or form, or it belongs
to the higher echelons of society-to a priestly, philosophical, or artistic, poetic class. The
uninitiated, the incapable, or the young and inexperienced-those who are not romantic
troubadours-are doomed only to feel physical desire. This separating of love from
physical desire has further implications concerning the nature of romantic love.
Those who consider love to be an aesthetic response would hold that love is knowable
through the emotional and conscious feeling it provokes yet which cannot perhaps be
captured in rational or descriptive language: it is instead to be captured, as far as that is
possible, by metaphor or by music.
5. Love: Ethics and Politics
The ethical aspects in love involve the moral appropriateness of loving, and the forms it
should or should not take. The subject area raises such questions as: is it ethically
acceptable to love an object, or to love oneself? Is love to oneself or to another a duty?
Should the ethically minded person aim to love all people equally? Is partial love
morally acceptable or permissible (that is, not right, but excusable)? Should love only
involve those with whom the agent can have a meaningful relationship? Should love aim
to transcend sexual desire or physical appearances? May notions of romantic, sexual
love apply to same sex couples? Some of the subject area naturally spills into the ethics
of sex, which deals with the appropriateness of sexual activity, reproduction, hetero and
homosexual activity, and so on.
In the area of political philosophy, love can be studied from a variety of perspectives. For
example, some may see love as an instantiation of social dominance by one group
(males) over another (females), in which the socially constructed language and etiquette
of love is designed to empower men and disempower women. On this theory, love is a
product of patriarchy, and acts analogously to Karl Marx’s view of religion (the opiate of
the people) that love is the opiate of women. The implication is that were they to shrug
off the language and notions of “love,” “being in love,” “loving someone,” and so on, they
would be empowered. The theory is often attractive to feminists and Marxists, who view
social relations (and the entire panoply of culture, language, politics, institutions) as
reflecting deeper social structures that divide people into classes, sexes, and races.
This article has touched on some of the main elements of the philosophy of love. It
reaches into many philosophical fields, notably theories of human nature, the self, and
of the mind. The language of love, as it is found in other languages as well as in English,
is similarly broad and deserves more attention.
Author Information
Alexander Moseley
Email: [email protected]
United Kingdom