SHELDON. The Fugue As An Expression of Rationalist Values
SHELDON. The Fugue As An Expression of Rationalist Values
SHELDON. The Fugue As An Expression of Rationalist Values
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide
range of content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and
facilitate new forms of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of the Terms & Conditions of Use, available at
https://about.jstor.org/terms
Croatian Musicological Society is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend
access to International Review of the Aesthetics and Sociology of Music
ABSTRACT
* The author gratefully acknowledges the support given him by Western Michi-
gan University in the form of a Faculty Research Fellowship and Grant.
period from the 1600's to the present, but viewed from afar o
development of knowledge concerning how we perceive, a knowledge
engendered by parallel developments in science and mathematics. Quite
obviously, the tools which we have invented to understand the world
around us have been used to good advantage to understand ourselves and
our art. Just as obvious is the fact that our view of art and the artistic
process itself is to a large extent contingent upon, and one might al
limited by, our view of the world. Our cognitive tools and the world
they provide come largely from the tradition of scientific rationalis
The understanding of the aesthetic attitude of a particular period
demands a consideration of all cultural factors, but principally that period's
perception of the world around it, as well as its beliefs regarding man's
purpose within it. To begin by studying the aesthetic literature of the
period in question, particularly of the artistic genre in question, is of
course the safest and most accepted approach. But what about a period
such as the Baroque, and an art such as music? On can hardly speak of
an aesthetic literature here. Even by the late eighteenth century, mu-
sicians and musical theorists were far more concerned with the practical
matters of how to compose or how to perform than with considerations
of aesthetic process and purpose. To be sure, a theory having to do with
composition already had a long tradition by the 1700's, and enjoyed an
interaction with the emerging science of acoustics. But due to its origins
as a branch of Pythagorean mathematics and medieval numero-mysticism,
it was often still somewhat self-indulgent, ignoring broader aspects of form
and intent in favor of arcane pitch classifications and relationships. Even
the extensive practical and theoretical writings on music published during
this period all tend to focus on the vertical, or momentary event.
The musical literature of the seventeenth and early eighteenth cen-
turies which might qualify as aesthetic has to do mainly with music's
relationship to a text. The impetus here came from a renewed interest in
the tradition of classical rhetoric, and had its greatest impact on vocal
composition in such forms as opera, cantata, and oratorio. The result was
a rather universal but by no means systematic agreement on how to
achieve the general mood or affect of the text. Although the focus of this
literature was on music's fidelity to its text and represented the general
moral-didactic concern of the time, it did provide music with an orien-
tation. That this orientation was not truly aesthetic can be seen when one
turns from vocal music to the growing body of instrumental music. It
was instrumental music that forced the eighteenth century to think
aesthetically, albeit most often initially in negative terms. Through pro-
longed confrontation, however, the Age of Reason eventually provided the
Romantic Period with the means by which it could justify instrumental
music as its chief vehicle of expression.
The purpose of this paper is to provide the reader with a general
exploration of rationalist thought in seventeenth- and eighteenth-century
7 Writers have been quick to point out the fallacy in rationalist thought of
equating unity with indivisibility. See John V. BURNS, Dynamism in the Cosmology
of Christian Wolff, Exposition Press, New York 1966, p. 7.
8 Obviously, therefore, Leibniz did not subscribe to the widely-accepted atomist
theory of substance. One might note, too, that the antimaterialism of Leibniz, based
on metaphysical principles, is thus quite in contrast to that of Bishop George Berkeley,
which was the result of an extreme extension of empiricism.
9 Bare monads have perception without consciousness; animal monads (animal
souls) have conscious perception, and even memory, but no self consciousness. Only
human minds (rational souls) have clear knowledge, self consciousness, and some
insight as to the Divine Mind. See H. W. CARR, Leibniz, pp. 129-130.
10 According to this view, the entire future of the world is contained in its
present, completely predetermined in every detail. This provided the basis for the
so-called )>pre-formation? theory in the biological sciences, a theory which ruled
out any sudden or haphazard changes in evolution, and which postulated that in
Eve were all the ova of all future generations of humanity. See Herbert WENDT,
In Search of Adam, trans. by James Clough, Houghton Mifflin, Boston 1956, pp. 86-91.
11 Leibniz is in agreement with Hume and other empiricists in his acknowl-
edgment that perception of the external world is a mere representation of reality.
The composite effect of our perception is illustrated by Leibniz's analogy of stones
being thrown into a pond. What we perceive, at least consciously, is not the clear
circles made by each of the stones, but rather the >>con-fusion(( of all the individual
circles into one composite effect. See N. RESCHER, Leibniz, pp. 1 13!-114.
among these >,free<< agents however is not a truly reciprocal one.'2 For
example, although every monad perceives all the others, each perceives
more clearly those that are closer or more important to it. One substance
(monad A) represents another (monad B) more fully than vice versa, if
it more clearly and distinctly defines the form they commonly exhibit.13
Therefore no real causal interaction exists among monads, only a recip-
rocal >>perception<. This special reciprocity is built into their mutual
accord by a pre-established harmony. God, as the supreme Monad, is com-
pletely non-intervening.'4 Yet because of His supreme perfection and
wisdom, all the monads act in complete harmony as though they were
influenced by each other. This concept of a pre-established harmony, based
upon the Principle of Perfection, is very important in the thinking of
Leibniz, and would provide the basis for any rationalist aesthetic.15
The best or most perfect world for Leibniz is a world in which there
is a maximum of diversity governed by a minimum of laws. That is to
say, a world in which there is the greatest richness of phenomena, both
quantitatively and qualitatively, but one controlled by the simplest of
principles; a world where almost infinite variety is harmonized into
virtual unity.16 The notion of an infinite variety of possible forms nec-
essarily leads to that of formal continuity. Indeed, such continuity in
the world can be viewed as a mode of its perfection. It is no surprise that
as one of the inventors of the calculus, Leibniz ruled out conceptual leaps,
not only in physical motions and mathematical functions, but in meta-
physical truths as well.17 Typically, natural and mathematical laws served
Leibniz as the basis for the conceptual order of all things. Very important
here is the assertion that if two substances differ by a finite amount there
must be a continuous series of intermediate substances, each of which
12 Monads are >free< to the extent to which they have the opportunity to realize
their natural (i.e., predetermined) powers of self expression and distinct perception.
13 Representation can be defined as the inverse of perception: B is represented
in A insofar as A perceives B. In this instance A can be designated as the more
active monad, and B the more passive.
14 As opposed to the active role of God in the theories of direct causation and
occasionalism (Divine Intervention).
15 The mutual accord provided by pre-established harmony is a contingent
truth, necessary for only the best of all possible worlds, unlike compossibility, which
is a purely logical accord of world substances in the minimal sense of mutual com-
patibility. See N. RESCHER, Letbniz, p. 66.
16 This so-called mini-max principle can be described in physical terms as the
greatest effect produced by the least expenditure. A favorite example used by Leibniz
concerns a drop of water, which, if left undisturbed, will take the form of a sphere,
a shape which has a maximum volume with a minimum of surface area.
17 A line in mathematical terms is a real continuum, with any point merely
ideal. Metaphysically, only the ultimate constituents of the world (i.e., monads) are
real, and any continuum to which they might give rise is merely phenominal.
22 Wolff uses the analogies of a watch and a human body to demonstrate that
the essence of any compound substance differs radically from the attributes of the
simple elements which comprise it. See J. V. BURNS, Wolff, pp. 45-46.
23 The ambiguity of Wolff's thihking here is clear from his classification of
motor force. Although it is >>modifiable and pendurable<< (as a true, simple substance),
it is still a phenomenon arising from the forces of its constituent simple substances.
Wolff therefore classifies it as a quasi-substance rather than a true substance.
Leibniz was apparently more inclined to regard it as a true, albeit still incomplete,
substance. See J. V. BURNS, Wolff, pp. 74, 76.
24 BURNS (ibid., pp. 69-70) points out the rationalist fallacy of identifying
resistance (ability of bodies to oppose one another) with inertia (inability of a body
to change itself).
25 As professor of poetry and philosophy at the University of Leipzig throughout
his entire teaching career (1730-66), Gottsched virtually dictated the intellectual
life of that city, and exerted great influence on 18th-century German letters in
general.
26 Seven editions were published by 1762.
27 For the rationalists the laws of nature = the laws of reason (Vernunft).
28 The rational faculty most important in this process is the understanding
(Verstand), one which Gottsched postulates as a sixth sense (or sensum communem),
and one which becomes central to Kant's theory of aesthetic judgment. See Johann
Christoph GOTTSCHED, Versuch einer Critischen Dichtkunst, B. C. Breitkopf,
Leipzig 17511; reprint ed.: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, Darmstadt 1962, p.
123 esp.
29 See Joachim BIRKE, Christian Wolffs Metaphysik und die Zeitgeniossische
Literatur- und Musiktheorie, Walter de Gruyter, Berlin 1966, p. 34.
3O Interestingly, Gottsched also defines the human emotional cry as the original
impulse (Ursache) of poetry. See ibid., p. 35.
31 One is reminded here not only of the contingent truth of Leibniz's pre-estab-
lished harmony, but also of the rationalist belief that the very essence of compounds
is determined by the order and arrangement of their combining elements.
32 Gottsched does not elaborate beyond the notion of similarity. One can presume
perhaps that in literature generally, as well as in music, continuity is implied in
his conception of Ahnlichkeit.
33 In Gottsched's words, >>Every order possesses its own rule<<. As quoted by
J. BIRKE, Christian Wolffs Metaphysik, p. 42.
34 Other than constantly to refer to the >ground of perfection for all things<
(i.e., the imitation of nature).
35 For Gottsched's German translation of Horace's important work, together
with copious notes and the original Latin text, see J. C. GOTTSCHED, Versuch,
pp. 2--4.
link in this regard features Johann Adolph Scheibe. The title alone of
Scheibe's important periodical, Critischer Musikus, which appeared in
Leipzig from 1737 to 1741, is enough 'to demonstrate the strong influence
that Gottsched had on him.65 Most certainly the two came into direct con-
tact during Scheibe's time as a student in jurisprudence at Leipzig Uni-
versity. Johann Birke substantiates beyond any doubt the close similarity
between the aesthetic ideas of Gottsched and Scheibe.66 For example,
Scheibe's necessary qualities of a composer (Witz, Scharfsinnigkeit, and
Einbildungskraft) are obviously a direct borrowing of those qualities which
Gottsched looks for in a poet.67 Scharfsinnigkeit is specified as important
in the discovery of similarities which are >,new, wonderful, and not com-
mon or known.< Scheibe claims Einbildungskraft as the most important
quality, however, along with a reasonable memory.68 Not unlike Gott-
sched's view of the poetic process, the naturalness of a musical work for
Scheibe depends on the observation of the rules of music for the attain-
ment of the determined goal. These rules guarantee the agreement of the
manifold and make the imitation reasonable; whereas nature sets the
limits, the intent (Absicht) prescribes the rules within these limits.69 Mel-
ody and harmony are described as the characteristics (Eigenschaften) of
music, with melody defined as ,,a well-ordered series of various tones,
which are heard one after the other.<70
a skip up of a fourth (from scale degree 5 to 1), the answer most likely
would alter the interval to that of a fifth (from scale degree 1 up to 5).79
Also, if the subject ends with a modulation to the dominant tonality (that
of scale degree 5), the answer is altered so that it will conclude back in the
tonic, or central key area.
When all the participating parts have presented their respective sub-
jects and answers, usually in strict alternation, the first and most impor-
tant formal unit of the fugue is completed.80 It should be noted that the
subject (and answer) forms do not vary at all, at least in this initial expo-
sition (Repercussio, or Wiederschlag). Also, neither subject nor answer
form appears two (or more) times in succession, and neither the subject
nor the answer should appear in the same voice two or more times in
succession.81 These and other rules too numerous to cite here are all intend-
ed to guarantee the thematic-tonal unity of the fugal texture.82 In fact, the
provide a high degree of order and clariity, sufficient reason for their u
while maintaining an even flow and distribution of the main thematic
material. Obviously there is no better example of continuity anywhere
in music.
Nothing which Scheibe says concerning this initial exposition is rea
new. Of interest, however, is what he has to offer concerning the fu
process (Verfahren) after this point, for in the Critischer Musikus we
perhaps the first attempt to describe the fugue in its entirety. Of gr
importance, for example, is the detailed description of the episodes (Z
schensdtze) which alternate between the initial and later expositions. H
the subject is not stated in its entirety. Rather, >certain portions< of it
>developed< (durcharbeitet) in >free imitation.8ss This process gives ri
to the invention of ,>brand new phrases< (ganz neue Sdtze) which wer
the subject >undetected< (ungeachtet) all along. Scheibe points out, furth
more, that if the subject is long and the number of imitating voices ma
79 This is the so-called tonic-dominant rule, which specifies that the tonic pitch
(1) is answered by the dominant (5), and vice versa. See MARPURG, Handbuch,
p. 311.
80 Here the >rules< of fugal writing seem most stringent and well defined, even
to the extent of specifying the order of appearance of the imitating voices. The most
common, as well as most favored, order is that of soprano, alto, tenor, and bass, i.e.,
a >natural<< sequence of entries from very highest to very lowest. See F. W. MAR-
PURG, Handbuch, pp. 326-327.
81 Marpurg is very explicit in this regard. See ibid., pp. 324-326.
82 As mentioned above, after an entering voice has completed its subject (or
answer) statement, it provides contrasting counterpoint to the next successive subject
(or answer) statement in the imitating voice. Although this harmonizing counterpoint
often varies from voice to voice, it is not uncommon for it to maintain its own
identity as a secondary or >counter-subject< (Gegensatz). Scheibe points out the
possibility of this contrasting counterpoint giving rise to as many other fugu
subjects (and therefore, independent fugues) as there are participating voices. Se
J. A. SCHEIBE, Critischer Musikus, p. 468.
83 Ibid., p. 467. Scheilbe specifies that these subject fragments must be accom
panied by counter-subject material.
Scheibe points out that after all the ,numerous variations< evenly
distributed among all the voices, the subject should appear as it did in
the very beginning, but with its countersubject and in full harmony with
the other voices. This subject statement must proceed in such a natural
way as to make the conclusion an absolute necessity (unumgdngliche Not-
wendigkeit), and that every listener can clearly hear that the final cadence
is sufficient to be able to bring the work to a necessary, free, and con-
vincing conclusion.96 In the remarks of F. W. Marpurg, who details the
form of the fugue more than does Scheibe, the culminating aspect of the
fugal process at this point is somewhat more explicit. He describes the
conclusion as a place >where one works over the subject in yet different
ways, now whole, now fragmented, with all kinds of imitation, especially
close canonic imitation, and where one can finally end emphatically, with a
pedal point if so desired~.97 Elsewhere Marpurg states that the largest, most
ambitious passages must remain at the end of a fugue while the smaller
must precede these. This principle, he observes, >,is based on the reminder
of a great composer that the beginning be good, the middle still better,
and the end excellent<.98
96 Ibid., p. 471.
97 F. W. MARPURG, Handbuch, p. 337.
98 Ibid., p. 3'3'5. Most likely the >great composer(< referred to is J. S. Bach, whose
fugal style served Marpurg as a model, and with whom he had personally talked.
Marpurg had provided the 1752 edition of Bach's Art of Fugue with a long foreword.
See Hans T. DAVID and Arthur MENDEL, The Bach Reader, W. W. Norton, New
York 1'96,6, pp. 266-268.
99 See MARPURG, Handbuch, p. 336. This is a point made more clearly by
Mattheson. Cf. J. MATTHESON, Capellmeister, pp. 388-389 esp.
100 See both fugues in b-flat minor (no. 22). See also fugues no. 5 (D major)
and no. 7 (E-flat major) in Bk. II.
101 One is reminded of Carl Philipp Emanuel Bach's remark that when his
father heard the beginning of a fugue he would at once state what contrapuntal
devices it would be possible to apply, and which of them the composer by rights
ought to apply. See H. DAVID and A. MENDEL, The Bach Reader, p. 37. Also, pp.
30, 324-325.
Sa,etak