10.1515 - Culture 2019 0042

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 9

Open Cultural Studies 2019; 3: 494-502

Research Article
Martin Brückner*

The Place of Objects and Things in the Age of


Materiality
https://doi.org/10.1515/culture-2019-0042
Received January 8, 2019; accepted January 30, 2019

Abstract: This essay reprises the status of objects in relation to critical conversations that favor things
and thing studies over other methodologies of material culture studies. Recent discussions have dismissed
objects as passive foils that lack in meaning. Glossing the factor of representation, however, these
discussions have also glossed over a factor crucial in shaping the way in which the distinction between
objects and things is made accessible in theory and practice. Two examples taken from eighteenth-century
American literary culture, an anecdote by Benjamin Franklin and a sales ad published by the Pennsylvania
Gazette, illustrate how in the process of representation objects become imbued with significance that
reaches beyond mere signification and object classification. Once conceived as ‘material signs,’ objects
become participants in cognitive environments in which seemingly meaningless symbols foster meaningful
engagement with materiality.

Keywords: objects; representation; material culture studies

As the essays collected in this special issue explore new paths for navigating the at once conceptually exciting
and confounding space in which materials become meshed with realities, they also re-examine the status of
“objects” and how this affects current critical conversations about material culture studies. Throughout the
issue, the essays implied definition of “objects” is conceived in the broadest terms possible. As if invoking
W.J.T. Mitchell’s understanding that “objects are the way things appear to a subject—that is, with a name,
an identity, a gestalt or stereotypical template, a description, a use or function, a history, a science” (156),
the essays’ selected objects run the full gamut: from the hard, easy-to-see, easy-to-name piano forte, naval
tableware, or photograph, to the more protean, functional rather than empirical materiality of electric light,
money, seeds, or water and its constitutive elements hydrogen and oxygen.
On first sight, pairing the above object definition with the essays’ object choices points to a conceptual
as well as practical conundrum familiar to students working in the field of material culture studies.
Regardless of what is being scrutinized, and I purposefully avoid the terms “anything” or “everything,”
each and all fulfill the form or function of objects, be it as physical matter or the intangible, as a spatial
or temporal configuration, or as something particular or a system. While the objects’ material range can
be baffling, academic conversations treat this ambiguity as a virtue of material culture studies (Candlin
and Guins 1-5; Miller 1-8), and unlike in many other fields of inquiry, the definitional latitude surrounding
“objects” has invited interpretations shaped by a plethora of theories and methodologies. Not surprisingly,
the issue’s playfully spelled title “MatteReality” anticipates the way in which the essays engage with a
highly diversified discourse that has been shaping material culture studies in recent years, activating Igor
Kopytoff’s object biographies, Michael Fried’s forms of objecthood, Bruno Latour’s actor-network theory,
Daniel Miller’s view on stuff, or Jane Bennett’s vibrant materialism. Above all, as the authors marshal the
at times dizzying array of concepts and voices—and significantly, before fully leaning into their respective

*Corresponding author: Martin Brückner, University of Delaware, Newark, DE, United States E-mail: [email protected]

Open Access. © 2019 Martin Brückner published by De Gruyter. This work is licensed under the Creative Commons Attributi-
on 4.0 Public License.
 The Place of Objects and Things in the Age of Materiality   495

object examples—many take a moment to reflect on the relationship of their objects to “things” and the
discussions spurred by Bill Brown’s “thing theory.”
Since the early 2000s, to engage with the field of material culture studies has meant to engage with
the conceptual tension between objects and things. As even the most cursory survey of recent publications
reveals, many projects—too numerous to list here—have done so with gusto. Delving into theories launched
in fields ranging from philosophy, art, and art history, to anthropology, literary studies, and environmental
humanities, reading the above essays comes at the critical moment when “things” are held up less as
an intellectual proposition but more as a consensual maxim perhaps best formulated by Jean-Francois
Chevrier when he states “every object is a thing, but not every thing is an object” (117). Invoking Martin
Heidegger’s “thingliness,” Jacques Lacan’s “unnamable or unknowable” thing, Latour’s “Dingpolitik,” or
Bennett’s “thing-power,” the perception of a “thing”—be it a shoe, a desire, a missing mass, or a heap of
trash—is that it stands for more than an object, for something categorically broader and more essential. The
“thing” differs from the object because it is inherently more autonomous, self-supportive, and above all
self-assertive; in our age of neoliberal ideology, things have come to embody attitudes and experiences like
independence or resistance; indeed, short of assigning them the capacity for acting according to their free
will, things are cited for having unique agency and a life force of their own.11
By contrast, “objects” are measured in opposite terms and described as being dependent, unhelpful,
accepting, subordinate, incapable of standing apart. Unlike things, “objects” are passive, easy to know,
operative foils that lack in meaning and significance precisely because unlike things, to paraphrase Bill
Brown, objects lie inside the “grid of intelligibility” and can never quite leave the “order of objects” (“Thing
Theory” 5). However, as the essays pick their way through their respective disciplinary fields ranging
from literature and cultural studies to ecocriticism and art history, looming in the background are critical
frameworks not content with the passive object status, in particular those developed by proponents of
an object-oriented ontology or speculative realism (Bennett; Morton; Harman). According to the latter’s
precepts, things become part of the object definition because they effectively inhabit “a world where the
object, whether thing, tool, commodity, thought, phenomenon or living creature, has regained its rights,
freed from the subject’s determining mind, body and gaze” (Hudek 16).
Notice the syntactic slippage that at once reshuffles and equalizes things along with objects, the
human, or the nonhuman? For contemporary artists, as suggested by Antony Hudek’s volume The Object
(2014), the thing-object binary appears to have lost its oppositional fix and has become recalibrated,
subordinating things to a larger object world defined at once by materiality and immateriality rather than
by the entrenched juxtaposition of agency and passivity. Backed by Latour’s actor-network theory and the
poststructuralist perspective that the material world is in flux rather than contingent on human subjectivity,
things are now reconsidered to be part of a continuum defined by their object disposition. On the one hand,
in an intellectual world writ large by materiality, objects wield the kind of vitality described by Bennett:
“if matter itself is lively, then not only is the difference between subjects and objects minimized, but the
status of the shared materiality is elevated” (12). On the other hand, such an object world defined by shared
materiality does not propose another return to thingly alterity or hypostatized objecthood. Rather, the
speculative return to objects proposes a participatory model populated by “almost-objects” and “almost-
subjects,” both of which are circulating in and out of systemic networks, energy flows, or states of being.
To say that the essays of this issue argue for a return to objects as the guiding principle for doing the
work of material culture studies would be an overstatement. But to emphasize objects over things—as many
of the issue’s contributors do—in a critical field that has become increasingly defined, even dominated, by
thing studies is to make a case for the objects’ participatory disposition and its attending practices revolving
around accessibility and legibility. In current efforts that rethink the status of objects, these factors are key
to both the definition of the object and the future of material culture studies. But in contrast to theories of

1 For summaries of how “things” resonate in critical debates see Mitchell (156) and Hudek (14). The conversation about things
is similar to that surrounding the concept of materiality. “According to the new materialism, if everything is material inasmuch
as it is composed of physicochemical processes, nothing is reducible to such processes, at least as conventionally understood.
For materiality is always something more than ‘mere’ matter: an excess, force, vitality, relationality, or difference that renders
matter active, self-creative, productive, unpredictable” (Coole and Frost 9).
496   M. Brückner

speculative materialism, which ultimately dismiss “philosophies of access” because all paths promising
better understanding are inherently compromised by anthropocentric values (Harman; Meillassoux 5),
most of the critical practices surrounding the study of objects and material culture are inextricably bound
up with theories and practices of mediation. As the collected essays show, objects from the piano to money,
from the photograph to water, can only become the focus of attention because as much as they are non-
human actants performing variable roles inside networks of materiality, they are inadvertent participants
in material practices predicated on the processes of representation.
Indeed, representation informs even the most intricate theoretical argument parsing the status of things
or objects. Although the unspoken premise seems to be that we have unmediated access to things like a
Berlin key or postmodern artwork or to objects like a vase or a collection of vases, theorists from Latour to
Brown to Bennett can only make their case using verbal and/or visual representations, ranging from single
word entries to lengthy verbal descriptions, from hand-drawn sketches to high gloss photographs.2 The same
is true for the essays in this special issue. Turning to the media landscape that informs them, the example
of the piano illustrates how its discussion as an object hinges on two different modes of representation. The
printed word “piano” and the photographic image showing it are the sole source for communicating the
piano in all its materiality and attending attributions of significance. According to current conversations
about the thing-object nexus, the piano’s representational formats would do nothing more but reify its
classification as a “mere” object because it is beholden to systems of signification (word, image) that cannot
stray much beyond the coordinates of orthography and semantics, or iconography and semiotics. But as
this essay will show below, as soon as objects are reclassified in terms of their participatory disposition their
very representation becomes a materially constituted act of signification.
For the seasoned practitioner of material culture studies the place of representation is nothing new.
After all, as Kenneth Haltman observes, “Material culture begins with a world of objects but takes place
in a world of words.” Summarizing the critical methodology developed by Jules Prown (“the Prownian
method”), he writes “while we work ‘with’ material objects, i.e. refer ‘to’ them, the medium in which
we work as cultural historians is language. When we study an object, formalizing our observations in
language, we generate a set of carefully selected nouns, adjectives, adverbs, prepositions, and verbs which
effectively determine the bounds of possible interpretation” (Haltman 4). In this line of reasoning, all
objects are products of sign systems that, predicated on words or images, will render objects like the piano
unambiguous, predictable and unresponsive, thus fulfilling the critical expectation, to invoke Brown, that
objects are indexical constructs at best, and locked inside “the grid of intelligibility” or as symbolic icons
inside the “order of objects.”
This referential approach to objects does not square well with some of the basic understandings of
more recent studies in material culture according to which “the world of objects, however ordinary, is a
trove of disguises, concealments, subterfuges, provocations, and triggers that no singular, embodied and
knowledgeable subject can exhaust” (Hudek 14). One disguise or provocation to be reckoned with is the
fusion between the objects’ materiality and their representation. The piano, the dollar bill, the drop of
water, and for that matter even the “thing” is fundamentally woven into a “material” sign system in which
the object’s representational reach is as much connected to as it is capable of moving beyond the grid of
intelligibility. Or, to build on the older literary turn in material culture studies, if we transpose language and
description into semiotic terms the material sign of the “piano” would stand for an equation that looks like
this: sign (signifier/signified) + X (n1). While the letters “p/i/a/n/o” encompass the object’s representational
sign, the “X” stands for the materiality of the object, and the multiplier “(n1)” for its passive or active
participation in relationships marked by material use, social rituals, emotive attachments, economic
activities, and so forth—in short, the combination “X(n1)” marks the surplus of signification resulting from

2  It is fascinating to observe that thing studies often uses literary works as explanatory evidence but in so doing skips over
the question of mediation and mediality as factors shaping our understanding of material life or materiality as such. Take for
example Bruno Latour’s praise of literary theory in Reassembling the Social, where he argues that unlike empirical data fiction
provides a more liberal (“freer”) environment through which to explore material life, but glosses over the fact that literary form,
tropes, figures of speech are not only products of language but bound up with representation (Latour 54).
 The Place of Objects and Things in the Age of Materiality   497

the object’s material encapsulation in its usage and attachment, circulation and accessibility.3
Materiality in itself does not guarantee access to objects. On the one hand, and fundamentally, the
semiotically constructed sign can easily transcend the grid of intelligibility because it is always baffled by
the object’s own residual materiality; that is, the object’s mass, material composition, gravity, or friction—
the “X” factor—will always fail to register in words or images, and is thus likely to turn the object into an
incomprehensible thing without a material code and thus push it beyond the comprehension of materiality.
But on the other hand, when we consider the space that opens up between the object’s matter and its
medium of representation, the object itself becomes a material sign offering an interpretive model that
takes into account the objects’ materiality, because, as suggested by anthropologist Lambros Malafouris’s
study How Things Shape the Mind (2013), it “operates on the principle of participation rather than that of
symbolic equivalency” (97). If meaning is “the ongoing blending between the mental and the physical,
in the case of material signs, we do not read meaningful symbols; we meaningfully engage meaningless
symbols” (117). In this participatory understanding, objects and their representation provide an alternative
way of fusing empirical and historical evidence. Addressed as material signs, objects are participants in the
process of cognition itself; or, as Malafouris writes, “The material sign instantiates rather than symbolizes.
It brings forth the concept as a concrete exemplar and a substantiating instance” (97).
Two examples from the early American media landscape—a biographical anecdote and a newspaper
advertisement from the eighteenth century—showcase how objects become material signs capable
of jumping interpretive frames or representational grids. In both examples, objects emerge from the
triangulation of materiality, participation, and representation. But as the examples will show, letting named
objects intersect with the rules of signification and the habits of interpretation just as easily complicates
their object status as it also plots out new paths towards understanding objects as they emerge from within
the interstices of materiality.
The first example is derived from an anecdote told by Benjamin Franklin to Thomas Jefferson about
the creation of a shop sign and the literary process of making a verbal sign become material. According to
Franklin the sign emerged from the following process:

When I was a journeyman printer, one of my companions, an apprentice hatter, having served out his time, was about
to open shop for himself. His first concern was to have a handsome sign-board, with a proper inscription. He composed
it in these words, ‘John Thompson, Hatter, makes and sells hats for ready money,’ with a figure of a hat subjoined; but
he thought he would submit it to his friends for their amendments. The first he showed it to thought the word ‘Hatter’
tautologous, because followed by the words ‘makes hats,’ which show he was a hatter. It was struck out. The next observed
that the word ‘makes’ might as well be omitted, because his customers would not care who made the hats. If good and to
their mind, they would buy, by whomsoever made. He struck it out. A third said he thought the words ‘for ready money’
were useless as it was not the custom of the place to sell on credit. Every one who purchased expected to pay. They were
parted with, and the inscription now stood, ‘John Thompson sells hats.’ ‘Sells hats,’ says his next friend! Why nobody will
expect you to give them away, what then is the use of that word? It was stricken out, and ‘hats’ followed it, the rather as
there was one painted on the board. So the inscription was reduced ultimately to ‘John Thompson’ with the figure of a hat
subjoined. (Jefferson)

On first glance, the anecdote seems to locate the shop sign inside older object definitions as well as traditional
approaches to objects fostered by material culture studies. The sign emerges from a process circumscribed
by the basic rules of signification and legibility. The visual “figure of a hat” painted on the board remains
constant, serving as a kind of sign vehicle whose distinctive graphic shape relates to material forms much
like a token or replica of the same type: here the image of the hat stands for all objects called “hat” (Eco
178ff). But if the hat image makes up half of the sign’s signifier, its other verbal half—the signified—does
not necessarily correspond. As Franklin’s impromptu media critics weigh the value of each descriptive word
(“John Thompson, Hatter, makes and sells hats for ready money”), they never entertain using the linguistic

3 Here I build on Timothy Morton’s observation that we hear “the piano as object... [Its] Strings... have been liberated from
telling a human story. They tell their own story, pronounce their own doom” (167). As the piano-object tells its story it enters a
process in which “an object [is] seen from a standpoint that is 1+n dimensions lower than the object’s dimensionality” (Morton
72-73).
498   M. Brückner

equivalent to the painted hat and all its associated qualifiers, nor do they opt for adding Mr Thompson’s
picture. Instead, after a process of elimination rather than substitution they settle on the name of the shop
sign’s owner, “John Thompson.”
Of course, the material (physically “real”) object of the “sign-board” is absent. But in its narrative form—
and considering the various narrative frames with their respective relationalities and temporalities—the
piece of wood containing a painted image and two hand-painted words transforms the figure of the hat into
more than a conventional object. By the same token that the image will not fool readers into thinking the
sign stands for the person of “John Thompson” or vice versa that the name becomes a synonym suggesting
the man is a hat, the material sign of the “hat” conceals as well as triggers a host of social conventions and
relationships: while the story is clear about what will happen to hats, namely that they are commodities
or saleable goods, the hat sign invites gestures of material speculation on what else is being disguised,
whether the sign also represents gift objects, pawned goods, damaged hats, fashionable souvenirs, and
so forth—all of which will only become fully accessible through the named object, “John Thompson,” the
sign’s owner and, for prospective shoppers, the hats’ interlocutor.
In the course of this anecdote Franklin outlines the workings of material signs: upon its completion,
the sign-board not only contains word (name) and image (hat) as well as subject (name) and object (hat),
but also its materialities consisting of wood, paint, and an implied though unspecified mass of hat fabrics.
Thus constituted, the material sign here moves the shop’s significance (trade and the object sphere of other
shop signs) into a much broader representational sphere (the “n1” factor). It embodies the process by which
meaningless symbols become meaningful through participation; the representation of the hat contains
a host of negotiations that come with sourcing raw materials, labor, and designs that go into the hat’s
production as both the real and imagined object. In the end, Franklin’s anecdote engages with objects that
if they are considered as material signs will rattle the perceived order of representation; at least in narrative
accounts like this, the object is no longer transfixed by a singular sign but instead fosters alternative routes
towards object legibility.
In the example of Franklin’s anecdote, the material sign of a shop advertisement carefully constructs
the object of the hat as a singular representation that at once substantiates its meaning and makes
manifest its imbrication in the cognitive processes of representation. Expanding on this anecdote, the
second example—lifted from the advertising pages of eighteenth-century newspapers like the Pennsylvania
Gazette—illustrates how objects, including hats, were able to register as “material signs” en masse in the
everyday discourse of material culture. Between the 1730s and 1770s, and thus during the time of Franklin’s
hat anecdote, the Pennsylvania Gazette ran hundreds of sales ads, posted by shipping agents, wholesale
merchants, and small shopkeepers, that addressed objects using the signs of the printed word without
the representational benefit of pictures. Many of these ads took on the shape of epic lists similar to this
transcription of an advertisement posted by The Pennsylvania Gazette on November 1, 1744:

JUST imported from London,… Superfine broadcloths in suits with compleat trimmings, low priced 6 qu. broadcloths
with superfine black, blue and scarlet in pieces; bear skins, friezes, kerseys, halfthicks, duffils, strouds, lintseys, strip’d
flannels, plain white and scarlet ditto spotted and mix’d, rugs, blankets, bedquilts, womens scarlet and coloured short
cloaks, fine camlets, cheverins, damasks, flower’d russels, black coloured callimancoes, temmings, stript camletees,
with silk ditto, grassets, starrets, cypress crape, worsted check, double and single allapines, sagathees, everlastings,
mill’d shalloons, barragons, corded druggets, flour’d silk and incles for womens gowns, strip’d turketies, an assortment
of buttons and mohair of all colours, white jeans; coloured, tufted, and double ribb’d fustians, glaz’d linnens, cotton
counterpains, wadding, haircloths, dimities, and fine flour’d demothoys, floor and bed-side carpets; mens, womens and
childrens worsted stockings, mens low pric’d yarn ditto, worsted, cotton and silk caps, a neat parcel of womens worsted &
silk shoes, childrens morocco pumps, mens london shoes and pumps, cherryderries, spittlefield indians for gowns, black
granderel for mens vests broad and narrow, silks, sergedusoys, womens diaper’d sowed petticoats, burying crapes, tiffany,
womens newfashion’d capuchin cloaks, black laces for hoods and mantelets, leghorn hats […]. (Pennsylvania Gazette 4)

The list of saleable goods goes on, doubling the number of items tallied above, but I stop at the referent
for the objects called “Leghorn hats” to examine the efficacy of material signs for bridging the gap
between the objects’ representational form and their materiality. The objects called “Leghorn hats” were
wide-brimmed, finely plaited straw hats originally made from a special kind of wheat found only in Italy
 The Place of Objects and Things in the Age of Materiality   499

(Figure 1).4 While the list entry “Leghorn hats” has modern readers scramble for dictionaries and online
hand books describing eighteenth-century textiles and fashions, the ad’s choice of wording “Leghorn
hats” suggests these objects were unambiguous and fully legible to eighteenth-century American readers
(or listeners). Indeed, considering the fact that the ad is listing fairly specialized clothing articles without
additional explanation or description indicates that the objects’ verbal signs not only made them legible
but activated knowledge of material characteristics, production processes, and the contexts of their usage.
Placed inside the text of a commercial advertising, the entry “Leghorn hats” here becomes a material sign
in that it engages the object and the subject in a two-way “scriptive” process of accessibility, a process that
unlike older material culture approaches that focus on the unmediated object now calls attention to the
“reading” of the object (here in list form) as a phenomenological endeavor complete with the inferences of
relationality and personal selection, aesthetic evaluation and economic pricing.5

Figure 1. Poke bonnet worn by Mary Ann Williams (Mrs. Preece) in 1828. Courtesy of Wikimedia Commons.

The question is, how does a set of printed words like “Leghorn hats” enable objects to jump their lexical
grid and become material signs indicative of a participatory materialism and the experience of materiality?
Named items like “broadcloths,” “damasks,” “jeans,” or “silks” invoke a representational system in which
the meaning of signs is at once specific and differential. While the single word “broadcloths” could be
applied to a whole range of objects and still not differentiate them, the ad writer provides one more term
to give it definition. Adjectival qualifiers like “superfine,” “compleat [with] trimmings,” “black, blue, and

4 On examples of Leghorn hats in other American records, see Baumgarten (118); for a visual referent to a hat explicitly called
“Leghorn hat,” see the example posted by the Boston Museum of Fine Arts at https://www.mfa.org/collections/object/a-leg-
horn-hat-65599. The hat shown in Figure 1 is a “poke hat” which has a slightly different shape but is still made of Leghorn straw.
5 Robin Bernstein’s concept of “scriptive things” is helpful for recasting the status of objects. According to her, “A scriptive
thing, like a playscript, broadly structures a performance while allowing for agency and unleashing original, live variations that
may not be individually predictable. Items of material culture script in much the same sense that literary texts mean: neither a
thing nor a poem (for example) is conscious or agential, but a thing can invite behaviors that its maker did and did not envision”
(12).
500   M. Brückner

scarlet,” and so forth turn generic broadcloths into singular objects whose textile materiality projects their
future use and bodily engagement. The same logic applies to the words “Leghorn hats”—to just write “hat”
would have meant little by way of differentiation; but to add the Italian place name “Leghorn” gives the
object semantic depth and distinction within the order of objects.
Lacking further description, the term “Leghorn hats” invokes a simple visual understanding of objects.
As if invoking a one-to-one correspondence between the present words and the absent material object, the
term works like a metaphoric placeholder and as such would have enabled American readers to navigate
the list of goods similar to the way in which modern readers today browse online shopping catalogs. In
this understanding, and here I take the Greek word metaphor literally, the term enacts a “change of place”
conflating the denotation of the hat with its connotation. If we were to look at modern illustrated sales
catalogs, the objects of “Leghorn hats” would have also emerged from photographic images and thus at the
intersection of two meanings, which according to Roland Barthes, comprise the “denoted message, which
is [the object’s] analogon itself, and a connoted message, which is the way in which society represents, to a
certain extent, what it thinks about the analogon” (6). While the word entries in the Pennsylvania Gazette’s
were not pegged to actual images and considering the laconic enumeration of list entries, advertisers seem
to have approached objects true to the modern critical expectation that “we look through objects” (Brown,
“Thing Theory” 4). Each object entry—from “broadcloths” to “Leghorn hats”—emerges from a deep and
abiding structure of representation in which word signs make transparent the objects’ radius of significance
(or, to keep the analogy to semiotics in play, this is the factor of “n1”). In the case of the ad, the addition of
one word renders valences defining the denoted object in relation to gender, class, even racial connotations;
by way of differentiation, they hint at social rituals like those revolving around cultural refinement or
funerary customs; indeed, in this reading the whole lot of objects is nothing but an assemblage of material
coordinates (call it “artifact” or “commodity”) predictably pointing out familiar frames of social reference,
the most prominent one being economic and spelled out by the ad itself: all objects are “to be sold very
cheap for ready money, or short credit.”
Yet, by the same token that the linguistic representation of “Leghorn hats” reaffirms the narrow
definition of objects, their object status changes from the moment that we allow Leghorn hats, or for that
matter any of the other listed objects, to register as material signs. Readers would not only have looked
at the words “Leghorn hats” but would have engaged with them by touch, holding the paper’s edges or
rubbing their fingers over the printed words. The tactile engagement with linguistic signs automatically
includes the material experience of the sign’s materiality, here the inked printing paper (or to recall the
first example, the painted surface of a wooden board). In 1744, newspapers like the Pennsylvania Gazette
were using low quality paper whose coarse surface would on occasion reveal bits and pieces of the paper’s
raw material, the paper pulp made of discarded textile rags.6 Represented on rough paper, named objects
like “Leghorn hats” bear the imprimatur of the remembered touch and other sense memories.7 The tactile
experience of rubbing fingers over smooth or rough paper surfaces recalls other bodily memories of wool,
linen, or for that matter, straw. Such sense memories may include remembered images of different straw
hats; mental images of gold-colored wheat; the anticipated fit of the hat; the imagined head and body
posture when wearing it; the anticipation of trimming the hat with decorative accessories (see Figure 1); the
social events and emotional experience when showing off the hat; in short, as a material sign, the simple
words “Leghorn hats” here embody hat-induced associations (call it disguises), cued by the idiosyncrasy of
subjective experience, bodily engagement, and cognitive behaviors such as proprioception.
In view of these two samples—the shop sign and the Leghorn hats—the materiality of representation is
an inherent part of the objects’ calculus of interpretation. According to this calculus the object translates
itself into immaterial form while at the same time the absent, immaterial object translates itself into material
forms like newspaper ads or painted signs. Once addressed as material signs, the meaningful engagement

6 Paper quality depended on the quality of the rags “finest and whitest linen-rags are always the best, because, the finer the
thread is, the more easily it is whitened,” while “Woollen and silk rags are only used for brown paper.” See “The Art of Making
Paper,” 12. On eighteenth-century paper production, see Hunter; Hills; and Krill.
7 See Smith; Classen.
 The Place of Objects and Things in the Age of Materiality   501

with seemingly meaningless symbols enables objects to exceed their verbally and visually prescribed
sum of referents. I have purposefully channeled the discussion of objects through structuralist theories of
language because they best reflect the current attitude towards objects; because signs are relational and
meaning emerges via differentiation, each and every object is captured and thus made legible from within
a linguistic grid dotted with a finite set of assignations. If we were to stay in the representational world of
advertising, the structuralist assessment of mediated objects would uphold the passive definition of objects.
In this case, what matters most in printed ads and wooden or painted signs in the eighteenth century is
the position of objects in relation to each other; what does not matter is the relationship of advertising
signifiers to real-world referents, but rather the differentiation of each sign from the others to which it is
related. But in the world of the reexamined object, the ads—like many of the essays in this issue—appear to
approach objects as much through their materiality as through their representational formats. As material
signs, objects are thus as much part of the process of signification as they are sign vehicles defined by
co-materiality. This is not another form of fetishization (a critique frequently leveled at object-ontological
thinking) or another instance documenting experience, such as hyperesthesia (a condition invoked when
calling out things in opposition to objects). On the contrary, what the examples of the shop sign and the
Leghorn hats show—and this extends to the above essays’ discussions of pianos, money, or water—is that
we cannot discuss objects in a vacuum defined by abstraction only, but must consider their participation in
material representations. We have to reckon with the objects’ immersion in the materiality of signification.
As material signs, objects allow us to brook the gap that separates them from things and subjects by looking
“with” or “into” objects rather than “through” them.

Works Cited
“The Art of Making Paper,” The Universal Magazine of Knowledge and Pleasure, Vol. X, XXX, and XXXII (March, 1762 to April,
1763): 12.
“JUST imported from London.” The Pennsylvania Gazette, vol. 7, no. 828 (1744): 1-4.
Barthes, Roland. The Responsibility of Forms. Hill and Wang, 1985.
Baumgarten, Linda. What Clothes Reveal. The Language of Clothing in Colonial and Federal America. Yale University Press,
2002.
Bennett, Jane. Vibrant Matter. A Political Ecology of Things. Duke University Press, 2010.
Bernstein, Robin. Racial Innocence. Performing American Childhood from Slavery to Civil Rights. New York University Press,
2011.
Brown, Bill. A Sense of Things. The University of Chicago Press, 2003.
---. “Thing Theory.” Things, edited by Bill Brown, The University of Chicago Press, 2004, pp. 1-22.
Candlin, Fiona and Rayford Guins. “Introducing Objects.” The Object Reader, edited by Fiona Candlin and Rayford Guins,
Routledge Press, 2009, pp. 1-18.
Chevrier, Jean-Francois. The Year 1967: From Art Objects to Public Things, Or Variations on the Conquest of Space. Fundacio
Antoni Tapies, 1997.
Classen, Constance. Worlds of Sense: Exploring the Senses in History Across Cultures. Routledge Press, 1993.
Coole, Diana and Samantha Frost. “Introducing the New Materialisms.” New Materialisms. Ontology, Agency, Politics, edited
by Diana Coole and Samantha Frost, Duke University Press, 2010, pp. 1-43.
Eco, Umberto. A Theory of Semiotics. Indiana University Press, 1976.
Haltman, Kenneth. “Introduction.” American Artifacts. Essays in Material Culture, edited by Jules David Prown and Kenneth
Haltman, Michigan State University Press, 2000, pp. 1-10.
Harman, Graham. Speculative Realism. An Introduction. Polity Press, 2018.
Hills, Richard L. Papermaking in Britain 1488-1988. A Short History. Athlone Press, 1988.
Hudek, Antony. The Object. Whitechapel Gallery and The MIT Press, 2014.
Hunter, Dard. Papermaking. The History and Technique of an Ancient Craft. Dover Press, 2012.
Jefferson, Thomas. “An Anecdote of Doctor Franklin.” Letter from December 4, 1818. http://tjrs.monticello.org/letter/27
Krill, John. English Artists’ Paper. Renaissance to Regency. Oak Knoll Press, 2002.
Latour, Bruno. Reassembling the Social. An Introduction to Actor-Network-Theory. Oxford University Press, 2005.
Malafouris, Lambros. How Things Shape the Mind. A Theory of Material Engagement. The MIT Press, 2013.
Meillassoux, Quentin. After Finitude. An Essay on the Necessity of Contingency. Continuum Press, 2008.
Miller, Daniel. “Materiality: An Introduction.” Materiality, edited by Daniel Miller, Duke University Press, 2005, pp. 1-50.
Mitchell, W.J.T. What Do Pictures Want? The Lives and Loves of Images. The University of Chicago Press, 2005.
502   M. Brückner

Morton, Timothy. Hyperobjects: Philosophy and Ecology after the End of the World. University of Minnesota Press, 2013.
Smith, Mark M. Sensing the Past: Seeing, Hearing, Smelling, Tasting, and Touching in History. University of California Press,
2008.

You might also like