Dema
Dema
Dema
https://archive.org/details/modernsocialtheo0000unse
Modern Social Theory
An Introduction
Edited by
Austin Harrington
OXFORD
UNIVERSITY PRESS
OXFORD
UNIVERSITY PRESS
Great (]arendon Street, Oxford OX2 6DP
Oxford University Press is a department of the University of Oxford.
It furthers the University's objective of excellence in research, scholarship,
and education by publishing worldwide in
Oxford New York
Auckland Bangkok Buenos Aires Cape Town Chennai
Dar es Salaam Delhi Hong Kong Istanbul Karachi Kolkata
Kuala Lumpur Madrid Melbourne Mexico City Mumbai Nairobi
Sao Paulo Shanghai Taipei Tokyo Toronto
Oxford is a registered trade mark of Oxford University Press
in the UK and in certain other countries
Published in the United States
by Oxford University Press Inc., New York
:1'.J Oxford University Press and Anthony Elliott
2005 The moral rights of the author have been
asserted Database right Oxford University Press
(maker)
First published 2005
All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced,
stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or hy any means,
without the prior permission in writing of Oxford University Press,
or as expressly permitted by Jaw, or under terms agreed with the appropriate
reprographics rights organization. Enquiries concerning reproduction
outside the scope of the above should be sent to the Rights Department,
Oxford University Press, af the address above
You must not circulate this book in any other binding or cover
and you must impose this same condition on any acquirer
British Library Cataloguing in Publication Data
Data available
Library of Congress Cataloging in Publication Data
Data available
ISBN 0-19-925570-9
10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2
Typeset by Newgen Imaging Systems (P) Ltd., Chennai, India
Printed on acid-free paper by
Antony Rowe, Chippenham, Wiltshire
■ ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
A.H.
■ OUTLINE CONTENTS
DETAILEDCONTENTS IX
GLOSSARY OF TERMS
BIOGRAPHIES OF THEORISTS
317
REFERENCES
331
INDEX
345
365
DETAILED CONTENTS
LIST OF BOXES
xvi
NOTES ON CONTRIBUTORS
xvii
A NOTE TO THE READER: THE SCOPE OF THISBOOK
xx
Introduction:What is Social Theory?
Austin Harrington
QUESTIONSFORCHAPTER 1 37
x DETAILED CONTENYS
FURTHER READING 38
WEBSITES 39
The tragic consciousness in Weber and Simmel: links with Nietzsche and Freud 82
Conclusion 84
QUESTIONS FOR CHAPTER 3 84
FURTHER READING 85
WEBSITES 86
Functionalism in anthropology 88
Robert Merton: manifest and latent functions 90
Talcott Parsons: functionalism as unified general theory 92
Parsons's 'voluntaristic theory of action' 93
Social systems and the 'problem of order' 93
Power, values, and norms 95
Structural differentiation 97
Criticisms of functionalism: objections and alternatives 100
Conflicttheorv 100
Marxist criticisms 101
Rational actor approaches 104
'Neo-functional1sm' 105
Conclusion 107
QUESTIONS FOR CHAPTER 4 108
FURTHER READING 108
WEBSITES 109
1. Modernity and the capitalist economy: Albert Hirschman, Karl Polanyi, and Eric Hobsbawm 25
2. Postcolonial criticism and 'Orientalism': Frantz Fanon and Edward Said 34
3. Hannah Arendt and Zygmunt Bauman on totalitarianism and the Holocaust 36
4. Karl Marx's concept of alienation 47
5. tmile Durkheim on suicide: a sociological case study 52
6. tmile Durkheim's concept of anomie 55
7. Max Weber on bureaucracy and the modern state 74
8. Georg Simmel on fashioo and the Stranger 78
9. Georg Simmel's essay 'The Metropolis and Mental Life' 82
10. Talcott Parsons on the nuclear family: a functionalist approach 99
11. David Lockwood on 'social integration' and 'system integration' 102
12. Feminist criticisms of Parsons 103
13. David Riesman's The Lonely Crowd 119
14. Peter Berger and Thomas Luckmann's The Social Construction of Reality 121
15. Seymour Martin Upset on political stability and instability 138
16. Reinhard Bendix on power and conflict 142
17. Michael Mann on the sources of social power 148
18. Ernst Bloch on hope, ideology, and utopia 158
19. Max Horkheimer's essay 'Critical and Traditional Theory' 161
20. Marxism in the 1980s: responses to the collapse of communism 171
21. Sigmund Freud's Civilization and its Discontents 178
22. Psychoanalysis in Marxism and functionalism: socialization and the 'authoritarian personality' 180
23. Roland Barthes on myth and the 'death of the author' 199
24. Michel Foucault on surveillance, biopower, and the Panopticon 210
25. Anthony Giddens and international relations theory 720
26. Pierre Bourdieu's Distinction.· A Sooal Critique of the Judgement of Taste 225
27. Pierre Bourdieu and the sociology ofeducation 226
28. Nancy Fraser on Habermas and the public sphere 242
29. Judith Butler on discourse and the sex-gender distinction 244
30. Anne Mclintock on feminism and 'commodity racism' 249
31. Daniel Bell on post-industrial society 257
32. Scott Lash on postmodernization and the information society 262
33. Postmodernity, fragmentation, and religious fundamentalism 269
34. Social theory and the revolutions of 1989 278
35. Alain Touraine on social movements and collective agency 282
36. George Ritzer on 'McDonaldization' 299
37. The Eurovision Song Contest: cultural imperialism or local syncretism? 306
. NOTES ON CONTRIBUTORS
Lisa Adkins is Reader in Sociology at the University of Manchester, UK. She is the author of
Gendered Work: Sexuality, Family and the Labour Market (Open University Press, 1995) and Revisions:
Gender and Sexuality in Late Modernity (Open University Press, 2002). She is co-editor of Sex in
Question: French Materialist Feminism (Routledge, 1996), Sex, Sensibility and the Gendered Body
(Macmillan, 1996), and Sexualizing the Social: Power and the Organization of Sexuality (Macmillan,
1996). She has published articles on gender, sexuality, and feminist social theory.
Samantha Ashenden is Senior Lecturer in Sociology at Birkbeck College, University of London, UK.
She is the author of Governing Child Sexual Abuse: Negotiating the Boundaries of Public and Private,
Law and Science (Routledge, 2004) and co-editor of Foucault contra Habermas: Recasting the
Dialogue between Genealogy and Critical Theory (Sage, 1999). She has published articles on feminist
theory, child sexual abuse, and the work of]iirgcn Habermas.
Gerard Delanty is Professor of Sociology at the University of Liverpool, UK. His books include
Inventing Europe (Macmillan, 1995), Social Science beyond Constructivism and Realism (Open
University Press, 1997), Social Theory in a Changing World (Polity Press, 1998), Modernity and
Postmodemity (Sage, 2000), Citizenship in a Global Age (Open University Press, 2000), Challenging
Knowledge: The University in the Knowledge Society (Open University Press, 2001), Community
(Routledge, 2003), and Nationalism and Social Theory (Sage, 2002) (with Patrick O'Mahony). He is
the editor of the European Journal of Social Theory and co-editor of The Sage Handbook of
Historical Sociology (Sage, 2003).
Anthony Elliott is Professor of Sociology at the University of Kent at Canterbury, UK. His books
include Social Theory and Psychoanalysis in Transition (Blackwell, 1992), Psychoanalytic Theory:
An Introduction (Blackwell, 1994), The Mourning of John Lennon (University of California Press,
1999), Concepts of the Self (Polity Press, 2001), Critical Visions: New Directions in Social Theory
(Rowman & Littlefield, 2003), Subject to Ourselves (Polity Press, 1996), and Social Theory since
Freud (Routledge, 2004). He is editor of The Blackwell Reader in Contemporary Social Theory
(Blackwell, 1999).
Austin Harrington is Lecturer in Sociology at the University of Leeds, UK. He is the author of
Hermeneutic Dialogue and Social Science: A Critique of Gadamer and Habermas (Routledge, 2001), Art
and Social Theory: Sociological Arguments in Aesthetics (Polity Press, 2004), and Concepts of Europe in
Classical Sociology (Routledge, 2006) (forthcoming). He is co-editor and translator of The Protestant
Ethic Debate: Max Weber's Replies to his Critics, 1907-1910 (Liverpool University Press, 2001) and
co-editor of the Routledge Encyclopedia of Social Theory (Routledge, 2005) (forthcoming). He has
published articles on hermeneutics, aesthetics, and German social thought.
John Holmwood is Professor of Sociology at the University of Sussex, UK. He is the author of
Founding Sociology? Talcott Parsons and the Idea of General Theory (Longman, 1996) and co-author of
Hxplanation and Social Theory (Macmillan, 1991) (with Alexander Stewart). He is editor of Social
Stratification (Edward Elgar, 1996) (three volumes) and co-editor of Constructing the New Consumer
Society (Macmillan, 1997). He has published articles on functionalism and evolutionary theory,
theories of the welfare state, feminist epistemology, and gender and critical realism.
Robert Holton is Professor of Sociology at Trinity College Dublin, Ireland. He is the author of The
Transition from Feudalism toCapitalism (Macmillan, 1985), Cities, Capitalism and Civilisation (Allen &
Unwin, 1986), Economy and Society (Routledge, 1992), Talcott Parsons on Economy and Society
(Routledge, 1986), and Globalization and the Nation-State (Macmillan, 1998), and co-author of Max
Weber on Economy and Society (Routledge, 1989) (with Bryan Turner). He has published articles on
xviii OHS 01\i COtHRIBUTOR<;
migration, class, global networks, historical sociology, and rational choice theory. His research
on globalization is funded by the Irish Research Council for the Humanities and Social Sciences.
Douglas Kellner is George F. Kneller Professor for the Philosophy of Education at the University of
California, Los Angeles, USA. His books include Herbe,t Marcuse and the Crisis of Marxism (University
of California Press, 1984), Critical Theory, Marxism, and Modernity (Johns Hopkins University Press,
1989), Jean Baudril/ard (Stanford University Press, 1989), Television and the Crisis of Democracy
(Westview Press, 1990), The Persian Gulf TV War (Westview Press, 1992), Media Culture (Routledge,
1995), Grand Theft 2000: Media Spectacle and the Theft o(a11 Election (Rowman & Littlefield, 2001),
From 9/11 to Terror War: The Dangers of the Bush Legacy (Rowman & Littlefield, 2003), Media Spectacle
(Routledge, 2003), and co-author of Postmodern Theory (Macmillan, 1991) (with Steven Best).
Anthony King is Reader in Sociology at the University of Exeter, UK. He is the author of The End of
the Terraces: The Transformation of English Football in the 1990s (Leicester University Press, 1998),
The European Ritual: Football in the New Europe (Ashgate, 2003), and The Structure of Social
Theory (Routledge, 2004). He has published articles on the work of Talcott Parsons, Pierre Bourdieu,
and Anthony Giddens.
William Outhwaite is Professor of Sociology at the University of Sussex, UK. He is the author of
Understanding Social Life: The Method Called Verstehen (Allen & Unwin, 1975), Concept Formation
in Social Science (Routledge, 1983), New Philosophies of Social Science: Realism, Hermeneutics and
Critical Theory (Macmillan, 1987), llabermas (Polity Press, 1994), and co-author of Social Theory,
Communism and Beyond (Blackwell, 2005) (with Larry Ray). He is editor of The Habemias
Reader(Polity Press, 1996) and co-editor of The Blackwell Dictionary of Twentieth-Century Social
Thought (Blackwell, 1993).
Antonino Palumbo is Lecturer in Political Philosophy at the University of Palermo, Italy. He is the
author of Etica egovernance (Ila Palma-Athena, 2003). His publications also include 'Weber, Durkheim
and the Sociology of the Modern State', in R. Bellamy and T. Ball (eds.), The Cambridge History of
Twentieth Century Political Thought (Cambridge University Press, 2003) and 'Administration, Civil
Service and Bureaucracy', in K. Nash and A. Scott (eds.), The Rlackwe/1 Companion to Political
Sociology (Blackwell, 2001).
Gianfranco Poggi is Professor of Sociology at the University of Trento, Italy. He is the author of
Images of Society: Essays on the Sociological Theories of Tocqueville, Marx and Durkheim
(Stanford University Press, 1972), Calvinism and the Capitalist Spirit: Mt1x Weber's Protestant Ethic
(University of Massachusetts Press, 1983), The State: Its Nature, Development and Prospects (Polity
Press, 1990), Money and the Modern Mind: George Simmel's Philosophy o( Money (University of
California Press, 1993), Durkheim (Oxford University Press, 2000), and Forms of Power (Polity Press,
2001).
Alan Scott is Professor of Sociology at the University of Innsbruck, Austria. He is the author of
Ideology and New Social Movements (Unwin Hyman, 1990) and co-author of The Uncertain
Science: Criticism of Sociological Formalism (Routledge, 1992). He is editor of The Limits of
Globalization (Routledge, 1997), co-editor of The Blackwell Companion to Political Sociology
(Blackwell, 2001), and co editor and transl;-1tor of (;cOIS Si111111d 1111 lie111/Jra11dt: An Ls.1<1;: in the
l'hilosophy of Art (Routledge, 2005). He has published articles on protest, labour contracts, trust, and
the works of Max Weber, Emile Durkheim, and Karl Polanyi.
Barry Smart is Professor of Sociology at the University of Portsmouth, UK. His books include Michel
Foucault (Tavistock, 1985), Modern Conditions: Postmodern Controversies (Routledge, 1992),
Postmodemity (Routledge, 1993), Facing Modernity (Sage, 1999), Econom>j Culture and Society: A
Sociological Critique of Neo-liberalism (Open University Press, 2003), and The Sports Star: ACultural and
Fco1w111ic 1\1111/y5is of .\p11rt111s,'c< /c/11ity (Sag,', 200.S). Hl' is co-,·ditor of the fh111dbook o(Social
Thea,y (Sage, 2001) and Resisting McDona/dization (Sage, 1999).
" xix
Dennis Smith is Professor of Sociology at the University of Loughborough, UK. He is the author of
Conflict and Compromise: Class Formation in 1:nglish Society 1830-1914 (Routledge, 1982), Barrington
Moore (Macmillan, 1983), The Chicago School: A Liberal Critique of Capitalism (Macmillan, 1988),
Capitalist Democracy on Trial: Tile Transatlantic Debate from Tocqueville to the Present
(Routledge, 1990), The Rise of Historical Sociology (Polity Press, 1991), Zygmunt Bauman: Prophet of
Postmodernity (Polity Press, 1999), and Norbert Elias and Modern Social Tl1eory (Sage, 2001). He is
the editor of the journal Current Sociology.
A NOTE TO THE READER: THE SCOPE OF THIS BOOK
This book provides a comprehensive introduction to leading topics, theorists, and debates
in modern social theory. It is suitable for undergraduate foundational courses in sociology
and cultural studies and related disciplines of the social sciences and humanities, as well
as for the general reader. The book is not primarily an introduction to social research
methods or to empirical sociology. It has been designed as a guide to problems and
traditions of analysis in modern social thought. ft is appropriate for introductory courses in
the prin ciples of sociological enquiry, or for what is often called the 'sociological
imagination'.
Topics and theorists I:ave been chosen for their relevance to the most frequently dis
cussed themes in contemporary social and cultural studies.While it is true that many of the
most influential figures in modern social theory have been male European or North
American authors, a particular c;onsideration of the book has been to incorporate the
many important challenges to mainstream social science that have arisen in recent decades
from the sides of feminist, postcolonial, and multicultural criticism. Social theory is by
defini tion a pluralistic discipline which must reflect the diversity of cultural, political, and
methodological standpoints characterizing debate about society today.
The book begins with a short Introduction to the most important questions of method
ology in social theory. Chapter 1 introduces the theme of modernity in social theory,
together with eighteenth- and nineteenth-century currents of social thought. Chapters 2
and 3 expound the cJassical sociological legacies of Karl Marx, Emile Durkheim, Max
Weber, and Georg Simmel. Chapters 4 to 14 trace the development of concepts, problems,
debates, and research programmes in sociology and social theory from the early twentieth
century to the present day. Separate chapters cover functionalism and its critics (Chapter
4), interpretive and interactionist theory (Chapter 5), historical social theory ( hapter 6),
Western Marxism (Chapter 7), psychoanalyticsocial theory (Chapter 8), French structural
ist and post-structuralist theory (Chapter 9), theories of structure and agency (Chapter 10),
feminist social theory (Chapter 11), postmodernism and its critics (Chapters 12 and 13),
and theories of globalization (Chapter 14). Much of the emphasis of the book falls on
later twentieth- and twenty-first-century social theory as the more classical period of
1890-1920 is amply covered in numerous currently available guides. The book does,
however, also include three key chapters on the foundational ideas of Marx, Durkheim,
Weber, and Simmel and their eighteenth- and nineteenth-century intellectual forebears.
The reader should note that the book is dedicated to theoretical thinking about social life
in its broadest sense. It is not only concerned with technical concepts and vocabularies in
the discipline of sociology. Social theory is closely related to the discipline of soc10logy
and is usually studied as a subsection of this discipline. Indeed social theory is often also
thought of as synonymous with the term 'sociological theory'. However, a slight difference
of nuance should be noted between these two terms. 'Sociological theory' generally refers
to theories propounded solely within sociology as an established discipline. 'Social the
ory', in contrast, generally refers not only to theories propounded within sociology but also
to more general contexts of social thought to be found in other disciplines. Social theory is
A NOH TO THi: RfADti< THI: :;(OPE' OF TH''. 0001' xxi
Social theory can bedefined as the study of scientific ways of thinking about social life. It
encompasses ideas about how societies change and develop, about methods of
explain ing social behaviour, about power and social structure, class, gender and
ethnicity, modernity and 'civilization', revolutions and utopias, and numerous other
concepts and problems in social life. This Introduction addresses some of the leading
questions that arise when we start to think about the very idea of a 'science of society'.
We begin by discussing the meaning of the word 'theory' and its various implications
for 'method' and 'methodology' in social research. We also consider questions about
the relationship of social theory to 'common sense', about the role of 'facts', 'values',
and 'objectivity' in social research, and about the relation of sociology to other
disciplines of the social sciences and the humanities such as political theory,
psychology, anthropology, history, and philosophy.
2
politics, in the context of other modes of understanding, and in the context of the finitude
and mortality of human life. The neglect of theoria in modern times was a particularly
important concern for the Jewish-German philosopher Edmund *Husserl, founder of the
movement of philosophical thought known as *phenomenology. Writing in the 1930s,
Husserl argued that inless tht:: s<.:ienu:sxernllected their source of origin-ation ;-nd m_ ;;-;
ing for everyday life,_ in t_t:1e *'lifeworL<L.as..h.c.calledit,.they would be doomed.to extinction
(Husserl 1936). Either the ciences would become wholly absorbed into the production of
technologies of mastery_Q:'.e_ Jure qr_ they would (fo olve in a \,y<,IVe of r vqlt gainst ;ir ..
ra_tional think_in_g_t (!t C(!U'!: Unfortunately, the rise of fascism and militarism in Europe
in the 1930s and 1940s confirmed Husserl's fears, and the only remaining role for science in
European society in this period remained as an instrument in the production of machines
of war and persecution.
In a similar spirit, the Jewish-German emigre philosopher Hannah*Arendt argued that
theory in the modern age comes to be increasingly subordinated to the search for techno
logical control over physical and social life (Arendt 1958). Writing in the 1950s, Arendt
suggested that where the original vita contemplativa or 'contemplative life' of the ancient
Greeks had been intimately bound up with what the Greeks saw as the vita activa or
'active life' of public political participation, the 'active life' of the modem age no longer
has the sense of practice and deliberation informed by contemplative reflection. Instead,
modern consciousness of the world becomes increasingly oriented to control and
productivity, where science serves the development of technology and where theory and
philosophy serve at most as 'handmaidens' to science. In contrast, 8-_!en<!t wanted to see
a world in which theory and philosophy not only assist science hut also remind science of
its moral and political responsibilities., in..tbe face o.f the fragility of the.earth's. r
smuces and the human_li
mortality of
On one level, all social science is a search for facts, for 'social facts'. The Latin root of our
word 'fact' means 'something made' or 'something done', from factum, the participle of
the verb facere, 'to make'. In addition, our modern sense of the word 'fact' refers to any
state of affairs that is real, definite, and incontrovertible.
In these two senses of the word 'fact', it is a fact that six million Jews died in the
Holocaust; and it is also a fact that ten thousand Palestinians died in the founding of
the state of Israel in 1948. What is important in these two historical facts is less the
exact numerical statistic than the fact that something real, definite, and
incontrovertible happened and was made to happen by human agency. The Shoah and
the Nakba (the evacuation of Palestine) are not legends, myths, or fantasies; they are
facts. They did not happen of their own accord or by the agency of supernatural forces
or spirits; they were done and made by real human actors acting in definite social-
historical conditions which can be documented, observed, analysed, and interpreted.
However, the problem of facts for social science is that facts only ever appear to us
laden with values. The Shoah and the Nakba are significant to us from the standpoint of
moral and political values: they stand out to us precisely because they are an affront to
human values. They concern us because they are events involving sufferings and crimes
which ought not to have occurred. Here the difference between facts and values can be
under stood as the difference between the world as it is, or was, and the world as we
would like it to be,or not to be. How the world is is one thing; how the world ought to be,
or how it might be made better, is another. One way of responding to the world is
'descriptive'; the other way of responding is 'prescriptive'.
But the problem for social science in the real world is that facts cannot be separated
from values. If we had no values, if we had no interest in value in the world, we would
not be interested in any particular facts. We would not be struck by any particular facts as
calling out for attention and demanding investigation. Although we are generally able to
distin guish statements that claim to 'describe' how the world is from statements that
'prescribe' how the world ought to be, we cannot extract facts from values in any pure
way. We cannot put all our values to one side in order to observe the world purely as a set
of facts, undis torted by our frames of perception and feeling about what is right and
wrong with the
world. _Social facts are meaningful to us only insofar they are valuecladen, and we only
come to be engaged with these facts insofar as we have values about how the world ought
to be or ought not to be.
This explains why researching social facts almost always produces a diversity of points
of view, which compete and often conflict with one another. Different social parties have
different and often conflicting values about how the world should be, and different parties
struggle with one another for the most authoritative account of the events and issues of
the day. In the case at hand, numerous accounts exist of the causes of the Holocaust, and
a broad spectrum of contested views reign about the causes and consequences of the
found ing of the state of Israel. Social science therefore has to consider a diversity of
accounts, which very frequently turn out to be backed up by different sets of reasons
worthy of consideration in their own right. In consequence, it is often very difficult, if not
imposs ible, to speak of any one 'fight answer' in the study of social affairs.
This raises a profound problem. If all research is possible only from value-laden points
of view, how can research be 'objective'? How can there be agreement about the accuracy,
validity, or insight of any particular piece of research?
There are ways of answering this question which need not lead us to think that
value conflict is fatal for the possibility of validity in research. If facts cannot be
separated from values, it does not follow that evidence about social life cannot be
collected, analysed, and interpreted in transparent and methodical ways. The events of
the Holocaust and the Nakba are both capable of being submitted to transparent
techniques of scrutiny-for example: techniques of analysing documents and statistics,
interviewing of witnesses, and the like-and although many different accounts of these
events still remain, and are still bound to remain, it does not follow that no valid
knowledge can be established about them. Furthermore, the impossibility of
separating facts from values does not mean that researchers cannot realistically aim to
work out procedures by which disagreements can be hammered out and rationally
debated. Ifl am able to show you how I arrive at my position, giving reasons for each step
and explaining to you how I believe these reasons to account for the matter under
consideration, and if you are able to do the same, we at least have a minimal basis for
discussion, which we can develop further through continued critical communication.
Value conflict need not therefore entail that any statement by a party to a discussion has
to be deemed as good as another, or that no agreement or no mutual critical discussion of
any kind is possible. And it certainly does not follow that someone who denies that the
Holocaust or the Nakba took place maintains as valid a position as someone who
demonstrates that they did, by adducing evidence and methodically examining and
explaining this evidence.
Objectivity therefore remains a realistic and rationally desirable goal for research. But it
is important to emphasize that o ectivity need not be seen as the only or ultimate goal or
motive of research. Different schools of social theory take differing views about the
purpose and relative importance of objectivity. Some schools view it as an end in itself,
while others tend to view it as -a means towards o h_er1 mo_re practical ends-such as
social justice and *emancipation, or liberation from oppression. In general, schools that
emphatically subordinate objectivity to the pursuit of moral and political ends of social life
are usually described as having a *normative orientation of thought. The word 'normative'
here refers to attitudes that give priority to the 'ought' above the 'is', to determining how
the world
g
should be made better, rather than solely to observing how it is. We will encounter many
examples of such attitudes in the course of this book. But it should be stressed that numer
ous midway positions exist between the attitude of normative engagement on the one
hand and the attitude of objective detachment on the other hand. All schools of social the
ory in fact advocate combinations of involvement and detachment, of both practical
moral-political dedication and scientific distance. Social theory remains distinct from
political activism but it is not a purely disinterested affair of reflection. As the German
theorist Norbert *Elias (1983) counsels, pure involvement without detachment would be
dogmatic and moralistic; but pure detachment without involvement would be pointless
and meaningless.
We have now discussed a range of issues with a broad general relevance to all disciplines
of the humanities and social sciences. These issues are particularly prominent in
sociology and social theory but they are not, in principle, ones that only social theorists
and sociolo gists are concerned with. The remaining sections of this Introduction will
therefore try to provide some further characterization of the specific subject matters that
social theorists and sociologists are concerned with. We end by looking at three main
areas of overlap and difference between social theory and other domains: first, social
theory and political theory; second, the relation of social theory to psychology; and third,
the relation of social theory to humanities disciplines, such as anthropology, history,
literary and art criticism, philosophy, and theology.
interest in religion in society. But sociologists are not centrally concerned with the internal
propositions of religious belief systems or with the ways in which religious beliefs express
contexts of scripture and sacred writing. Mostly they are concerned with the ways in
which religious beliefs interact with social and political institutions and powers.
Consequently, social theorists and sociologists are not as well equipped as theologians to
deal with questions of the meaning of ideas of the absolute or transcendental or infinite in
human experience. The question of whether God exists, or of how God exists, or of why
evil exists, or why the universe exists, are not questions that can be adequately framed or
pursued (let alone answered!) from the standpoint of social-scientific enquiry alone.
Conclusion
We have seen that social theory is the study of ways of thinking about society
scientifically. Further, we have also seen that it is the discipline of thinking about how far
it is possible for society to be studied scientifically. Social theory is at once a source of
explanatory concepts in social science and a source of ways of evaluating the point or use
or meaning of such concepts. To theorize about social life is not only to develop scientific
models of observable social processes. It is also to think critically about the conditions of
possibility of scientific constructs. If all social analysis were purely theoretical, it would
be merely speculative. But if all social analysis were purely empirical, it would be
forgetful of its relationship to questions of meaning and practical purpose in human social
life. In the most basic and ancient of senses, we can say that theory is reflection on the
place and function of science in human existence.
2 How much does social science hol9 in common with natural science7
3 Are there any acts of social research that can be carried out without the aid of theories or
theorizing?
4 If all facts relevant to social research are value-laden, what does it mean for social research to
seek to be objective? Can there be any social research that does not seek to be objective?
5 How important are objectivity and detachment in relation to practical values of liberation and
emancipation in social knowledge and social life7
All chapters of this book contain guidance on further reading for specific topics. In addition, various
general reading sources can be recommended. These can be grouped into the following categories.
13
Among some of the most tried and tested textbooks in empirical sociology are James Fulcher and
John Scott's Sociology (Oxford University Press, 1999), Anthony Giddens's Sociology (Polity Press,
4th edn. 2001), Tony Hilton's Introductory Sociology (Palgrave, 4th edn. 2002), Mike Haralambos
and Martin Holborn's Sociology: Themes and Perspectives (Collins Educational, 6th edn. 2004), and
Peter Kivisto's Key Ideas in Sociology (Pine Forge Press, 1998). Some useful textbooks concentrating
on cultural studies are Chris Barker's Cultural Studies: Theory and Practice (Sage, 2000). Other useful
textbooks combining sociology and cultural studies are the following four books in the
'Understanding Modern Societies' series of the Open University Press: Stuart Hall and Bram
Gieben's Formations of Modernity (1992), John Allen, Peter Braham, and Paul Lewis's Political and
Economic Forms of Modernity (1992), Robert Bocock and Kenneth Thompson's Social and Cultural
Forms of Modernity (1992), and Stuart Hall, David Held, and Tony McGrew's Modernity and
its Futures (1992). Books designed as introductions to empirical social research with accessible
theoretical elements include Tim May's Social Research (Open University Press, 3rd edn. 2001),
Zygmunt Bauman's Thinking Sociologically (Blackwell, 1990; 2nd edn. with Tim May 2001), MarkJ.
Smith's Social Science in Question (Sage, 1998), and David Goldblatt's Knowledge and the Social
Sciences (Routledge, 2000).
Other guides to social theory that overlap with the present book in various ways include George
Ritzer's Sociological Theory (McGraw-Hill Education, 6th edn. 2003), Classical Sociological Theory
(Higher Education, 4th edn. 2003), and Modern Sociological Theory (McGraw-Hill Education, 6th
edn. 2003), Bryan Turner's Companion to Social Theory (Blackwell, 2000), George Ritzer's Companion
to Major Classical Social Theorists (Blackwell, 2003) and his Companion to Major Contemporary Social
Theorists (Blackwell, 2003), George Ritzer and Barry Smart's Handbook of Social Theory (Sage, 2001),
Ian Craib's two volumes Classical Social Theory (Oxford University Press, 1997) and Modern Social
Theory (Harvester Wheatsheaf, 2nd edn. 1992), John Hughes, Peter Martin, and Wes Sharrock's two
volumes Understanding Classical Sociology (Sage, 1995) and Understanding Modern Sociology (Sage,
2003), Bert Adams and Rosalind Sydie's two volumes Classical Sociological Theory (Pine Forge, 2002)
and Contemporary Sociological Theory (Pine Forge, 2002), Patrick Baert's Social Theory in the Twentieth
Century (Polity Press, 1998), Alex Callinicos's Social Theory: A Historical Introduction (Polity Press,
1999), and Pip Jones's Introducing Social Theory (Polity Press, 2003). Edited collections of profiles of
individual theorists include Anthony Elliott and Bryan Turner's Profiles in Contemporary Social
Theory (Sage, 2001), Anthony Elliott and Larry Ray's Key Contemporary Social Theorist (Blackwell,
2003), and Rob Stone's Key Sociological Thinkers (Macmillan, 1998). Books concentrating solely on
the classical social theories of Marx, Durkheim, Weber, and Simmel are Ken Morrison's Marx,
Durkheim, Weber (Sage, 1995), Larry Ray's Theorizing Classical Sociology (Open University Press,
1999), and Anthony Giddens's Capitalism and Modern Social 11ieory (Cambridge University Press,
1971), as well as the already mentioned volumes by Craib (1997), Ritzer (2003), Hughes, Sharrock,
and Martin (1995), and Adams and Sydie (2002).
Collections of readings
Some useful edited collections of extracts from the famous primary texts of major social theorists
known as 'readers'-include Anthony Elliott's The Blackwell Reader in Contemporary Social Theory
(Blackwell, 1999), Charles Lemert's Social Theory: The Multicultural and Classic Readings (Westview
Press, 1999), The Polity Reader in Social Theory (Polity Press, 1994), The Polity Reader in Cultural
Theory (Polity Press, 1994), James Farganis's Readings in Social Theory (McGraw-Hill, 1993),
Jeffrey Alexander's Mainstream and Critical Social Theory (Sage, 2001), Jeffrey Alexander and Steven
Seidman's The New Social Theory Reader (Routledge, 2001), and Roberta Garner's Social Theory:
Continuity and Confrontation: A Reader (Broadview Press, 2000).
14
Some useful books treating epistemological and methodological issues not usually addressed at
length in textbooks on social research methods are MarkJ. Smith's Soda/ Science in Question (Sage,
1998), Malcolm Williams and Tim May's Introduction to the Philosophy of Social Research (University
College London Press, 1996), Norman Blaikie's Approaches to Social Enquiry (Polity Press, 1993),
Gerard Dclanty's Social Science beyond Constructivism and Realism (Open University Press, 1997),
and William Outhwaite's New Philosophies ofSocial Science (Macmillan, 1987). A useful collection of
read ings in this area is Gerard Delanty and Piet Strydom's Philosophies of Social Science: The Classic
and Contemporary Readings (Open University Press, 2003).
Some good introductions to the neighbouring field of political theory are Will Kymlicka's
Contemporary Political Philosophy (Oxford University Press, 2002), Jean Hampton's Political
Philosophy (Westview Press, 1997), Jonathan Wolff's An Introduction to Political Philosophy
(Oxford University Press, 1996), Raymond Plant's Modern Political Thought (Blackwell, 1991), and
Robert Goodin and Philip Pettit's edited A Companion to Contemporary Political Philosophy
(Blackwell, 1993).
Useful reference sources in A-Z format include William Outhwaite (ed.), The Blackwell Dictionary of
Modern Social Thought (Blackwell, 2002), David Jary and Julia Jary (eds.), The Collins Dictionary of
Sociology (HarperCollins, 3rd edn. 2000), George Ritzer (ed.), The Sage Encyclopedia of Social Theory
(Sage, 2004), Austin Harrington, Barbara Marshall, and Hans-Peter Mi.iller (eds.), The Routledge
Encyclopedia of Social Theory (Routledge, 2005), Edward Craig (ed.), The Routledge Encyclopedia of
Philosophy (Routledge, 1999), and Neil Smelser et al. (eds.), The International Encyclopaedia of the
Social and Behavioural Sciences (Elsevier, 2002), also accessible on-line by institutional subscription
and free of charge in partial form at www.ie bs.com
A few recommendations can be made about sources in the non-specialized public media.
Academic books and journals are not the only relevant sources. In the English-language media,
this author particularly recommends the Landan Review of Books (fortnightly), the New York
Review of Books (fortnightly), Le Monde diplomatique (monthly) (available in English as well as
French, and other languages), Radical Philosophy (bi-monthly), and New Left Review (bi
monthly). In Europe and North America, some of the more independent-minded newspapers
and magazines which regularly publish interviews and articles by leading world intellectuals on
social and political affairs are Le Monde (in France), El Pais (in Spain), Die Zeit (in Germany,
weekly), Die Frankfurter Allgemeine Zeitung (in Germany), La Repubblica (in Italy), The Guardian (in
Rritain), and The Nation (in the USA, weekly). The British weekly magazine The Economist is also
useful for information on world economic affairs. A further general piece of advice to the reader
is that wherever you are able to read a publication that is not written in the English language, it is
generally good to do so. The English language currently enjoys a glohal intellectual hegemony
which it is often good to resist, wherever you are able to do so. There are thousands of excellent
books, journals, magazines, newspapers, and websites which never find their way into English
translation, partly as a consequence of the cultural domination of Anglo-Saxon business inter
ests in the global publishing market.
15
■ WEBSITES
Our word 'modern' derives from the Latin modus, from which we also derive our word
'mode'. In a most basic sense, modernity is the mode of our time: that which is 'here and
now', rather than 'then' or 'past'.
It has been remarked that our word 'modern' has its roots in the late fifth century AD,
after the fall of the Roman Empire, when the Latin w_prd modernus came to be used to
refer to a new present era of Christianity, in contrast to a pagan past under the tutelage of
the Romans. However, the first known occurrence of the word 'modernity' as an abstract
noun is to be found in much more recent times. It appears in an article by the French poet
Charles Baudelaire for the newspaper Le Figaro in 1863. Baudelaire here wrote of the
experience of modernity in modem art and literature and the modern city as the
impression of 'the transitory, the fugitive, the contingent' (le transitoire, le filgitif, le
contingent) (Baudelaire 1863: 12). Baudelaire imagined the modern artist as someone
who experiences time as a line rushing inexorably forward into the future. As each
moment of the present is cast into the past, the modem artist tries to save the present
from its obsolescence as the present becomes immediately past and 'outmoded'.
Modernity in this sense evokes the idea of radically changing times.*Modernism
usually refers to specific cultural and intellectual movements of modernity that dramatize
this experience in various ways. Modernization usually refers to the process of
emergence of modernity.
Modernity is often thought of as a period, with a heginning at a certain point in time. For
some, modernity begins in the late eighteenth century with the onset of the Industrial
Revolution in European ountries a_rJd the spread of the ideas of the French Revolution and
:of
------
the S0:caifed-Age *EJ1Jightenment. For others, modernity begins earlier, with the
_ Renaissance in Italy in the fifte,cnth century, or with the Protestant Reformat_ion of the
--, -- -
- -- - --
sixteenth century, or with the revolutions in science and mathematics of the seventeenth
18 !\USTHJ !iAr
century. For still others, modernity is a more diffuse term that cannot be located in any
definite period and is not limited to European historical developments.
Disagreements about when exactly modernity might be thought of as beginning suggest
that modernity is not always best thought of solely as a 'period'. It is also possible, and in
many ways more desirable, to think of modernity in a more open sense as a distinctive
kind pf a_tJjJude.lo...ti.me-. In this sense modernity refers to an attitude of critical reflection
on the past and critical distance from the past. It encompasses an orientation toward active
shap ing of the future through forms of collectively determined, rationally intended
action. According to the historical theorist Reinhardt Koselleck (1979), modernity is the
attitude in which society comes to objectify its past as 'history'. Modernity is the time in
which society reflects on its past as a definite sequence of events culminating in the
present, not as a rep etitious cycle. 'Our time' becomes 'new time'; and 'new time' becomes
that which places the 'Middle Ages' in between 'our time' and 'antiquity'. Time thus
becomes something that society seeks to master and to make its own 'project'. In the
words of Koselleck, modernity sees itself as determining its own future, as continually
expanding its 'space of experience' under more and more ambitious 'horizons of
expectation'.
Modernity is frequently contrasted with what is called 'tradition' or 'traditional' ways
of living, or 'traditionalism'. Ou!. worg_t!ad_ition com s_Jr()m the Latir1:verb_tz:adere. 'to
hand over' to 'to hand down'. It signifies the idea of accepted, taken-for-granted ways of
thiriking and acting. Appropriate ways of behaving tend to be set by precedent and
example, by the way things have 'always been', by what the priest or the father says or by
what the ancestors did.
One of the most influential ways of distinguishing between 'modern' and 'traditional'
societies in social theory was established in the middle decades of the twentieth century
by the American *functionalist theorist Talcott *Parsons. Parsons distinguished between
tra ditional social structures based on what he called 'ascription' and modern social
structures based on 'achievement'. By 'ascription', Parsons sought to refer to the way in
which social advantages of wealth, power, and status in traditional settings are for the
most part ascribed to individuals at birth, by inheritance and by upbringing in a
particular *social class or social 'stratum', in which for the most part remain for the rest
of their lives. In contrast, by 'achievement', Parsons sought to refer to the way in which
social advantages of wealth, power, and status in modern settings are increasingly
achieved by individuals, irrespective of the initial privileges or lack of privileges with
which they begin at birth. In modern settings, the positions of individuals in the *stratified
structures of advantages and disadvantages are by no means entirely determined by
achievement: ascription through inheritance of a privileged or non-privileged class
background still plays a major role. But the tendency in modern settings is increasingly
towards greater social mobility as individuals gain or lose their positions in the distribution
of advantages by intended planned action oriented to formal education and a professional
career (see Parsons 1951).
Traditional societies are often vaguely thought of as being 'undeveloped' in various senses.
A traditional society might be one with a simple subsistence-based economy, or one with
no advanced uses of production technology, or one with no complex political institutions.
Traditionalism is often associated with so-called 'primitive' or tribal social forms, or with
medieval society, or with the societies of the 'dark ages'. Sometimes traditional ways of
I. 19
living are blandly and problematically associated with all 'non-Western' cultures. There
are, however, at least two reasons for being careful with the word traditional in these
instances.
First, it is not really the case that traditional societies show no particularly developed
uses of production technology. It is quite possible for societies to possess developed sys
tems of material production and transportation and still to remain traditional in most
important respects. According to the influential view of Max *Weber, societies do not neces
sarily cease to be traditional when they start to produce large quantities of material goods
or to create armies or develop technical inventions. Rather, according to Weber, societies
only cease to be traditional when they acquire a particular ethos of methodical conduct of
life, when they acquire a distinctly calculative, planning, and *rationalizing attitude to
ways of organizing and ethically justifying and codifying social life (Weber 1920a,
1920h). In this sense, Weber argued that the civilization of ancient China remained for the
most part traditional in its ways of life, even though ancient Chinese civilization already
possessed many of the technical inventions that the West only acquired over a thousand
years later in the Middle Ages (notably gunpowder). In Weber's view, the distinctive
feature of Western Europe in the fifteenth and sixteenth centuries was that it began to
adopt a pecu liarly rationalizing attitude to ways of defining moral and political values,
even though it did not start to produce large quantities of goods or to invent machines of
production until much later.
Secondly, it is important to note that societies can very often possess both traditional
attitudes in some respects and modern or modernizing attitudes in other respects, at
one and the same time. Societies and social forms can, for example, have both
modern or modernizing attitudes toward legal, political, and economic organization
and distinctly traditional attitudes toward interpersonal relations of authority and
toward gender roles. We might think today of the mafia business family, operating by
*patriarchal codes of honour and subordination and at the same time remaining
entirely in touch with mod ern technology and the modern economy. Many
contemporary nation-states also go to considerable lengths to preserve what they believe
to be their 'cultural traditions', such as elements of their religious institutions-the
Catholic Church in many countries-or their political institutions (the monarchy in
Britain, for example) (compare Hobsbawm and Ranger 1983; Anderson 1983). We
can also say that many contemporary Islamic societies are both modern in some
respects and traditional in others; and we can say the same of American society in the
1950s, and of]apanese society in the nineteenth century, and soon.
lt is difficult, therefore, to speak confidently of any definite period of time when all or
most cultures of the world ceased to be 'traditional' and became, entirely and
unequivoc ally, 'modern'. Both the word traditional and the word modern refer
primarily to attitudes and habits of mind and behaviour, rather than simply, or solely, to
clearly definable periods and regions of world history. The social transformations that
took place in Europe after the fifteenth century give us an exemplary insight into the
ways in which social relations can become modem. But they are not the only contexts
in which modem and modernizing processes can be observed; and European
developments are hy no means in themselves unambiguous cases of what is called
'modernity'.
20 AUSTIN HARRINGTON
With these points in mind, we can turn now in detail to the exemplary case of European
modernity from the fifteenth century onwards. It is this case that most preoccupied the
founding figures in sociological analysis in the nineteenth and early twentieth centuries. It
is possible to refer to this case as the prototype of Western modernity or ocddental
modernity.
Western modernity
It is helpful to approach the structure of Western modernity in terms of three more or
less distinct dimensions of social change: first a cultural dimension, encompassing the
rise of science and the decline ofreligion; secondly a political dimension, encompassing the
rise of the state, civil law, and ideas of democracy; and thirdly a socio-economic
dimension, encompassing the rise of an international capitalist economy, bound up with
processes of industrialization and urbanization.
the Church or the Bible says that heexists, but because God's non-existence is not
logically conceivable. In this regard, the fundamental intellectual feature of Western
modernity is that the rationally thinking 'I', the ego, or the *Subject, comes to occupy the
centre of the universe. In the development of European philosophy after Descartes,
the 'Subject' becomes the last instance of authority before God.
The fifteenth-century Italian Renaissance and the sixteenth-century Protestant
Reformation in northern Europe are significant because they set in motion the rise of the
idea of *autonomously thinking individuals, who are personally responsible for their own
destinies and their own salvation. Renaissance artists and scientists such as Michelangelo
and Leonardo da Vinci, together with the Protestant religious teachers Martin *Luther
and Jean *Calvin and humanist political writers such as Thomas *More, *Erasmus of
Rotterdam, and Michel de *Montaigne, all played their part in the generation of a
sequence of developments lasting over several centuries to which we today refer by the
name of *secularization.
Secularization denotes the diminishing power and influenceof formal religious institutions
over social and political life. From the sixteenth century onwards, a distinction gradually
comes to be introduced in Western European society between precepts set down by the
Church and precepts gained through independent reading of scripture by individuals or
through science and philosophy. It is this gradual process of separation between different
sources of cultural authority that leads to the slow retreat of religion from the realms
of education, art, philosophy, politics, and public discourse during the seventeenth,
eighteenth, and nineteenth centuries in Europe. In the nineteenth century, Charles
*Darwin's Origin of Species of 1859 represents one of the most emblematic moments of
this process of secularization.
Although religious beliefs today may not appear to have diminished in prominence in
public life, religion in the Western world no longer possesses anything like the same
legally and politically sanctioned sovereignty over social organization that it enjoyed five
hundred years ago. In the Western world today, despite the reversion to Creationism in
the teaching curricula of some US high schools, the intellectual authority of religion over
definitions of the physical universe and of the social world has been replaced,
definitively, by that of science.
Elements of cultural and intellectual modernity and the spread of secularization are
closely bound up with aspects of political modernity. It is to these concurrent political
dimensions of modernity in Europe that we now turn.
actions-notably the Civil War in England and the Thirty Years War in Germany, as well
as the Dutch Protestant revolt against the Spanish empire at the end of the sixteenth
century. It was in reaction to these kinds of events that a conception of the highest
sovereignty of the state in maintaining law and order came to be developed in the writings
of political philosophers such as Niccolo *Machiavelli and Thomas *Hobbes. This
conception is often known as the doctrine of 'reason of state'. A conception of toleration,
or state protection for freedom of religious conscience, in return for obedience to the laws
of the state, occurred later in the writings of]ohn *Locke. In eighteenth-century France,
Locke's influence joined with increasing calls in public life for constitutional reform and
for limitation of the pow ers of both the monarchy and the Church. These calls eventually
culminated in revolution in 1789, abolition of the monarchy, and an attempt by Napoleon
to spread the revolution to the rest of Europe in the early years of the nineteenth century.
In the New World, the men who met in Philadelphia to draft the Constitution in 1787
appealed to these same principles of separation between Church and state, and between
the powers of the legislature, the executive, and the judiciary. They invoked the principles
of representative democracy, of popular sovereignty and 'rights of man'. A key political
idea of Western modernity is here that the state receives its authority to rule not by divine
sanction-descending through a monarch, an emperor or a pope-but solely from the
collective will of the people, or the 'nation'. According to this world-view, the people are
endowed with inalienable rights, and the people alone resolve to vest authority in a sover
eign power. In this connection, the French revolutionary slogan 'liberty, equality, and
fraternity' finds its counterpart in Thomas *Jefferson's 'life, liberty, and the pursuit of
happiness'.
Ideas of representative democracy and popular sovereignty emerged from the 'Age of
Reason' or 'Age of Enlightenment' in eighteenth-century Europe. The writers of the
*Enlightenment saw themselves as standing for rational scrutiny, enquiry, and, above all,
'critique'. In Prussia in the 1780s, the philosopher Immanuel *Kant titled his three chief
works of philosophy The Critique of Pure Reason (1781), The Critique of Practical Reason (1788),
and The Critique offudgement (1790). In an essay of 1784, 'An Answer to the Question: What
is Enlightenment', Kant spoke of 'man's *emancipation from his self-incurred immaturity'
r- -(Kant 1784). By 'immaturity' Kant meant uncritical submission to authority, at the
expense of individual reflection, responsibility, and autonomy. Man's immaturity was
'self-incurred' because man had not yet found the courage to use his own innate faculties
of reason. M_ii_n
had instead surrendered control of his life to powers of questionable legitimacy=-to
t, -..monarchs and priests.
The ideas of French Enlightenment philosophers such as *Voltaire, *Montesquieu,
*Rousseau, and *Diderot included the precept that all people are equal before the law
and are innocent until proved guilty. They also included the insistence that illness and
misfortune are not symptoms of divine malediction but have natural and social causes,
and that religious and *metaphysical ideas develop from definite historical customs, not
from timeless essences. Throughout the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries, these ideas
led to numerous projects of reform and rational administration of the institutions of social
life, including the foundation of state schools, hospitals, prisons, and police forces.
We now turn to the last feature of processes of modernization in the West concerning
changes in the economic structures of society.
23
:I. Free-trade policies, based on the removal of state tariffs on imported goods. These
mark the definitive end of all barter trading and the universal use of money as an
abstract bearer of exchange value. Wealth is seen as increasing not by hoarding within
the confines of a nation-state (a doctrine known as 'mercantilism'), but by its
continual free circulation as capita!.
4. Urbanization, marked by large industrial cities linked to trading ports and tied
into a global economy. The cities grew from influxes of migrants from Lhe
countryside unable to find work on the land after processes of enclosure.
S. Population growth, arising from the demand for large industrial labour forces. Low wage
levels meant that nuclear family units needed to rear greater numbers of working
children to ensure a family's survival.
Processes of industrialization and urbanization and ideas of democracy and enlightenment
were all central considerations for eighteenth- and nineteenth-century social critics and
thinkers. In the next section we tum to the ways in which these eighteenth- and
nineteenth century writers developed ideas that were to become key objects of attention
for canonical figures in social thought such as Marx, Durkheim, and Weber and thus
helped to lay some of the foundations for the discipline we know today as 'sociology'.
to satisfy their own interests. Adam Smith famously spoke of a 'hidden hand' of the
market that coordinates private individual action through a collective mechanism of
wealth distribution.
A little later, mostly in the first decade of the nineteenth century, the movement known
as *utilitarianism developed out of the ideas of the political economists and the French
Enlightenment critics, gaining currency mostly in early nineteenth-century Britain. ·1 he
utilitarians maintained that traditional forms of philosophy and theology re,ted on irra
tional and unscientific assumptions. They believed that if ,ociety wa, to make progre,, ,m d
find practical benefit in its intellectual pursuits, it had to replace philmophical '>peculation
by the scientific study of utility. Utilitarianism is chiefly associated with the writings of
the English philosopher Jeremy *Bentham, who contributed to the foundation of the
Univer,ity of London as England's first entirely secular university. Bentham
famomly ,tated that the purpose of government was to guarantee 'the greatest happine,, of
the greates.t numher' (Bentham 1789). A rational society was one that maximized the
aggregate weirheTriio(it, members by dispensing with wasteful or luxury pursuits for the
few (such as high art and classical learning) and using the proceeds of these savings to
satisfy the material needs of the greatest mass in society. Bentham and the utilitarians
also emphasized that the purpose of the treatment of criminals by the state should be not
only to pun hh hut al,o to reform them. Bentham desi th m- d -p;:{; n-
;;_,hich- lie caTlecl (he 'Pa;;-ptiZc;n', allowing all prisoners to be surveyed and
supposedly cared for by pri,on guards from the same vantage point. In addition, the
utilitarians placed particular import ance in medicine and the scientific study of health and
illness. They insisted that society had to rid itself of all association of disease, deformity,
and insanity with religious and superstitious notions of punishment for sin or demonic
possession.
Closely linked to political economy and utilitarianism was the spread of the movement
throughout the nineteenth century known in very broad terms as liberalism.
The British Marxist historian Eric *Hobsbawm provides an illuminating periodization of modern social history in his four books
The Age of Revolution 1789-1848, The Age of Capital 1848-1875, The Age of Empire 1875-1914, and TheAgeofExtremes 1914-
1991 (Hobsbawm 1962, 1975, 1987, 1994). First
comes a period of highly charged political agitation between the first French Revolution of 1789 and
the defeated European revolutions of 1848. Then comes a period of both capitalist expansion and
colonial aggrandizement in which the European states increasingly turned toward colonial market
places for the products of their industrial economies. This created the series of imperial rivalries which
exploded in the outbreak of the First World War. Hobsbawm characterizes the period 1914 to 1991 as
the 'short twent ieth century', in contrast to the 'long nineteenth century'. In his synopsis, the twentieth
century effectively came to a close with the fall of the communist regimes of the Eastern Bloc and the
end of the Cold War.
27
Over the course of the nineteenth century, the right to vote was slowly extended to less
wealthy sections of the population in various parts of Europe, based on a lower
property franchise. We must, however, bear in mind that truly universal suffrage,
including crucially the extension of the vote to women, did not arrive until the
twentieth century. And we must not forget that in the nineteenth-century USA, where
European immigrants enjoyed more rights than they had done in the Old World, black
Americans remained slaves until the Civil War and did not gain full civil rights until
the 1960s.
In France in the 1830s, in the period of the Restoration of the monarchy after the 1789
revolution and the defeat of Napoleon, one of the most influential political commentators
on liberalism was Ale_xis de*IarqueyiLle..Tocqueville was a civil servant of the French state
under the constitutional monarchy of Louis-Philippe. Today he is chiefly celebrated for his
book Democrqcy i!1 ne_'-irn of 1835, as well as for a later study Tile Ancien Regime and the
Causeso[Riv lutio11.infrance of 1856. Tocqueville's main concern in his treatise on
America was to evaluate the factors contributing to social stability in the New World
compared with old Europe. Tocqueville reflected on calls for democracy and reform in
eighteenth-century French society. These calls never found realization in France until the
turbulent years of the 1790s when they soon degenerated into dictatorship under the terror
of the despotic revo lutionary Robespierre. Tocqueville contrasted this violent
introduction of democracy in France with the more peaceful society of the United States.
Because American society pos sessed no *stratified structure led by aristocratic elites with
high status and no monarchy, it was less vulnerable to violent overthrow by mob rule. In
Tocqueville's observation, *solidar: ity in American society arose from the presence of
'voluntary associations' based on small dusters of individuaJs abte to triist and cooperate
with one another for mutual interests. He saw these voluntary associations as having their
roots in the Protestant s ns of th(;.uriginal English settlers. They provided the basis for
the spirit of *egalitarianism and personal self-
-reTiarice in nineteenth-century American life.
Tocqueville's writings have been influential for contemporary liberal thinking about
pluralism and mutual cooperation in civil society (compare Putnam 2000). However, it is
important to note that Tocqueville's view of American society was not uniformly positive.
Tocqueville conjectured that as the American economy and population grew larger
and more complex, Americans would forfeit the safeguards that had once protected them
from
problems of masspopular dlctat rsh.ip based on a 'tyranny of the majority'. His fears have
not be;;:;-p o ed i:-o-be wfioTiy misplaced in the more recent twentieth- and twenty-first
century history of the USA.
Alongside liberalism, a further predominant intellectual movement in nineteenth
century society was *positivism. Positivism is particularly represented by the thought of
Auguste *Comte and Herbert *Spencer.
same principles set down by the already established natural sciences. Comte believed that
empirical positive science would serve definite social purposes. Once human beings had
found scientific answers to the world, they would be able to apply these answers to the
removal of suffering, violence, and conflict.
Comte claimed to show that all societies evolved over time by laws of progress. Societies
evolved towards higher stages of *integration in which social arrangements were reached
by peaceful and rational means. Comte spoke of a 'law of three stages'. First r_ri_e a
'theological stc1ge.' in which human beings mistake. the natural world for themselves. The
theological stage is characterized by beliefs in spirits and supernatural forces, where
human beings project onto the natural world their own habits of thought, like children who
treat inan imate objects as though they are animate creatures. Second came a 'metaphysical
stage' which humanity overcomes superstitious habits and mystical images of its world
by means of abstract concepts. Thirdly and finally came a 'scientific stage' in which
humanity replaces abstract speculative concepts with empirical knowledge based on
unbiased obser vation. In his late writings Comte spoke of the overcoming of traditional
religions through a new 'religion of humanity'. This was to be a secular civil religion in
which human beings would recognize themselves as the authors of their own existence.
Human beings would find ethical communion with one another not in the Church but only
in the state as the most authentic representation of their social belonging.
Herbert *Spencer in England developed similar ideas in the later nineteenth century. In
his The Principles of Sociology of 1882-98, Spencer propounded a theory of social
evolution influenced partly by the writings of Charles *Darwin. Spencer held that liberal
demo.c.@fY and limited government were the best adapted systems of resolving conflict
in soci ty and of distributing goods to its members. Tyrannies or oligarchies were vulnerable
in relation to their social environments. Democracy, in contrast, was more stable in the long
run. Democracy was better adapted and therefore more likely to survive, to be 'selected'
through history.
Spencer's ideas did not directly reproduce Darwin's theory of the 'survival of the fittest'.
Darwin had developed this theory strictly with reference to biological reproduction in the
animal and plant kingdoms and had never thought to apply it to historical-social
affairs. Nevertheless, Spencer's suppositions reflected many popular misconceptions and
prejud ices of the time about the social implications of Darwin's theory and the
evolutionary superiority of European society. Both Spencer's and Comte's
philosophies are in these respects shot through with chauvinistic prejudice. Their
writings are read today mostly for historical interest and are no longer taken seriously as
social theories. Nevertheless, their various concepts of 'evolution', 'adaptation',
*'differentiation', and *'integration' later came to be developed by more sophisticated
theorists in rigorous and non-chauvinistic ways. These notably included *Durkheim
around the turn of the nineteenth century and Talcott *Parsons in the 1930s.
However, over the course of the century, written defences of liberalism show increasing
signs of response to the rising tide of socialism as a political current. Karl *Marx and
Friedrich *Engels were later to emerge as the most dynamic spokesmen of this movement
with a massive impact on politics and society in the twentieth century-even though Marx
himself did not establish a hegemonic movement around himself in his own lifetime.
An increasingly vociferous claim of the period is that the purely formal concepts of
liberty, citizenship, and rights upheld by liberalism had to be made substantive. Several
socialist writers argued that political equality of persons before the law had to become
real social and economic relations of equality, through abolition of exploitation of the
poor and reform of a state that served only the interests of the rich. This critique was
central to the socialist view of the French Revolution as a bourgeois revolution serving
the interests of the middle classes. In the socialist view, civil society essentially meant the
rule of the bour geoisie. In France, the Comte de *Saint-Simon and Pierre-Joseph
*Proudhon as well as the English Chartists took similar views in the 1830s and 1840s, and
there were kindred voices in Russian social thought, notably in the writings of the
anarchist writer Mikhail Bakunin.
Nineteenth-centurysocial consciousness became increasingly marked by emergent class
tensions and conflicts as a result of processes of industrialization and expanding interna
tional trade. Much nineteenth-century social thought can consequently be read in terms
of an attempt to preserve the framework of liberal politics in response to rising fears of
the breakdown of social order and the claims of socialism. Yet at the very end of the
century, both liberalism and socialism began to receive a series of highly sceptical
diagnoses in the works of three writers chiefly recognized today as theorists of social
elites. These are the Italian-born writers Gaetano *Mosca, Vilfredo *Pareto, and Robert
*Michels.
Mosca, Pareto, and Michels wrote at a time that saw many challenges to the nineteenth
century system of liberal political consensus. These include the emergence of workers'
movements and trade union movements, as well as conservative religious movements.
The three elite theorists questioned the ability of civil society to contain and resolve these
movements' mutually conflicting claims. They also doubted the sincerity and integrity
of the moral and political ideologies governing these movements' representatives. Taking
their cue from *Machiavelli, they speculated that it was the drive for power that
explained the repeated failure of workers' parties to maintain an egalitarian structure and
constantly to relapse into hierarchical structures led by elites and oligarchies.
In his book The Ruling Class, publish d QJ:iginally in 1896, Gaetano *Mosca analysed the
ways-fri. which members of certain narrow social strata manage to reproduce themselves
as seffperpetuapngruling cliques, while at the same time passing themselves off as
represent atives of the 'people' and of popular interests. Mosca subjected Marx's principles
of histor ical *materialist explanatio·n based on 'class struggle' to an analysis of the
behaviour of socialist groups and parties themselves. He concluded that social-democratic
and popular
ment move s such as socialism never achiev their- objectives ithout the
certai
-
--
leadership
n elit of a
e class of intellectuals who speak on behalf of the mass but who at the same time
... -
stand estra rom t
,Jlli.lSS-.
_Michels, in his study Political Parties (1911), applied this analysis directly to
th; organizati--;;-n of tricte u ioris an.cf socialist parties. Mjchels spoke of an 'iron law of
olig_a_r 'Jn_vyhich political organizations, through the internal necessities of discipline
-;nd ad111inistrative cout_inuity, i evita_!:,ly become closed self-perpetuating cliques.
IJO
Vilfredo Pareto, in his treatise The Mind and Society_(:Jf 1916 (originally titled Trattato
di sociologia generale), claimed to discern two basic propensities of human social group
behaviour. The first propensity of social groups was to optimize their pursuit of material
interests, even at the cost of conflict with other groups. The second propensity of social
·groups was always to be led by small dynamic elites, however egalitarian the groups may
feel themselves to be in their initial aspirations. Pareto claimed that all human social
behaviour is driven by certain basic dynamics that he called 'residues' and 'derivations'.
These essentially stemmed from the pursuit of power and material intere;;t, dressed up in
the language of morality. Following Machiavelli, Pareto classified some social movements
as 'foxes' and some as 'lions'. 'Foxes' were short-term opportunist movements skilled at
combining diverse interests and seizing power through cunning strategies. 'Lions' were
long-term movements based on a principle of persistent 'aggregation', either of a conserv
ative religious kind or of..a revolutionary socialist kind.
Pareto's theories are the arguments of a speculative cynic.They rest on a certain
stubborn idea of the basic dynamics of 'human nature'. They lack sensitivity to different
self descriptions of human actors in-changing cultural and historical contexts. They also
bear a certain intellectual complicity with the rise of fascism in Italy after 1920. However,
there are certain elements in his work, together with that of Mosca and Michels, which
find more sophisticated expression in other early twentieth-century theorists. Max Weber
in particular is close to their work and was himself a teacher of the young Michels.
Despite their conservative and sceptical outlook, the elite theorists also left a mark on the
thinking of the Italian Marxist theorist Antonio *Gramsci; and they have had a wide-
ranging impact in con temporary political science, especially in *rational choice theory.
The last sociological thinker we must now consider in this overview is the German writer
Ferdinand *Tonnies.
We have now explored two basic aspects of the theme of modernity in social theory.
first, we have discussed some leading substantive dimensions of modernizing processes
in Western society, grouped around the three analytical areas of 'cultural modernity',
'political modernity', and 'socio-economic modernity'. Second we have looked at some
leading theories and discourses of modernity in nineteenth-century European social
thought, represented by the movements of political economy, utilitarianism, liberalism,
positivism, and socialism and by the names of Smith, Mill, Tocqueville, Comte, and
othcrs.
We now turn to the two complex questions signalled at the outset of this chapter. The
first is the question of how far these Western aspects of modernity have applicability to
all cultures and societies of the globe Is there one general paradigm of modernity that can
be applied to all societies, or are there many different ways in which societies can be
modern? The second question concerns whether there are any darker sides to the claims
of eighteenth- and nineteenth-century social thinkers about 'progress', 'science',
'reason', and 'enlightenment'. We have already referred to some notable ideologies and
prejudices of nineteenth-century thought, and we must now took at these more closely.
Put simply, can the application of rational and scientific principles to social life and social
organization
be regarded as in every respect a 'good thing'?
We take up these questions in turn, beginning with the issue of Western-centred bias.
32
A product of modern European civilization studying the problem of universal history is bound
to ask himself, and rightly so, to what combination of circumstances the fact should be attributed
that in Western civilization, and in Western civilization only, cultural phenomena have appeared
which (as we like to think) lie on a line of development having universal significance and validity.
(Weber 1920c 13)
( These words of Weber should be treated with some care. Weber himself did not believe
that other regions of the world either should or would necessarily develop in the same
way as the WestJ·-le was fascinated by the sociologically relative position of the West in
world history, devoting a significant part of his work to comparing intrinsic differences
between the West and other civilizations of the world, including notably the ancient
civilizations of
33
India and China. But in his concern with non-Western civilizations, Weber was to some
extent exceptional among the canonical sociological theorists of the early twentieth
century. By the time of the emergence of American modernization theory in the 1950s in
the *structural-functionalist school developed by Talcott Parsons, the possibility that
other cultures beside the European-North American bloc might represent alternative
instances of modernity and modernizing processes was not seriously considered.
The assumption that only one basic paradigm of modernity exists, that this paradigm is
represented by Europe and North America, and that all other societies of the world can
and must reproduce this paradigm insofar as they become modern at all, has been
challenged in recent decades by new generations of scholars concerned with problems of
ethnocentrism in social theory and research) Since the withdrawal of the European powers
from their former colonies in the 1950s and 1960s and the rise of increasingly
multicultural societies, new sensitivities have arisen toward the relevance of different
sociological explanations for different regions of the world. Sociologists have shown how
different cultures and civiliza tions can be modern in different ways, at different times,
and in different combinations of the features invoked by classical social thought. It need
not follow that largely agrarian societies-such as large parts of India, Asia, and Africa-fall
squarely outside the framework of modernity, or that the only respect in which they might
enter processes of modernization is by undergoing industrialization processes on the
model of nineteenth- and twentieth century Europe and North America. There are many
ways in which societies become modern, and some of these may share features in
common with Europe, while others may not. There are no fixed certainties in theories of
social change, and tpere is no nni)ine r
s:-9u..r2e..thxol,lg_h, .""..hkh aJl_soch::.ti.e.s...ncrd-µass in .order to becomi;...DJ..Qggrn. To borrow a
phrase developed in recent years by the Israeli historical sociologist S. N. *Eisenstadt,
there can be multiple trajectories of modernization, or 'multiple modernities' (Eisenstadt
2002). From the side of *postcolonial, or anti-colonial, interventions in dominant
Western discourses about modernity and rationality, two significant writers have been the
Algerian writer Frantz *Fanon and the Palestinian writer Edward *Said. Their works are
discussed
in Box 2.
A new area of intellectual partisanship in recent decades has been what is loosely termed *'postcolonial
studies'. Postcolonial criticism has influenced many aspects of contemporary historical, literary, social,
and cultural studies. It has arisen partly as a consequence of ongoing ethnic diversification in both
Western and non-Western societies after European decolonalizat1on and increasing globalization in
world affairs. Two influential postcolonial theorists have been Frantz *Fanon and Edward *Said.
Frantz Fanon was active in the 1950s as a black Algerian writer In the war of independence for his
country against French occupation. In Wretched of the Earth (1961) Fanon wrote of the effects of col
onization and racism on the material welfare and the psychological health and mental outlook of
African people. In this work, Fanon demonstrates the oppressiveness of colonialism not only in terms
of its control over territory but also in its hold over indigenous African contexts of self-expression. Fanon
shows how Western societies have enjoyed *hegemony not only In respect of political and economic political power but als
The Palestinian writer Edward Said develops a similar position in his influential book Orienta/ism (1978), a study of the i
physically exhausting manual labour. We also cannot forget that our modern idea of
a rationally organized state, guaranteeing universal education, health care, and social
security for the elderly, the infirm, the young, and those in the process of seeking work,
owes its inception to the ideas of the Enlightenment. A fundamental principle of modern
criminal and civil justice systems is that the function of laws of state is not to wreak
vengeance on guilty parties but to reprimand and reform them and to compensate the
victims or injured partie . This too we owe to the social philosophers of the eighteenth
century. Likewise, all modern ideas of 'civil rights' and 'human rights' derive entirely from
the eighteenth-century Enlightenment. In all these respects, the idea of the value of apply
ing enlightened scientific enquiry to political and socio-economic organization is not
something we can lightly dismiss. It is the linchpin, the governing presupposition, of our
modern civilization.
On the other hand, many sinister consequences of this confidence in reason and science
have become evident to us over the past century. Today we realize that technological
Clf S<;IC-Al f'CIAL HiEOR'f, i 35
invention-, are not emancipatory for human beings in every respc<.t or in any um quivo<.al
,cnse. Western medicine has been beneficial for society in many respects but not in every
H''-pcct The rnmmerual application of bi<Khemical scilme to agriculture and industry
has not alleviated hunger, malnutrition, and ill health in any unambiguously positive way.
',<1t/J'f'h•. .,,,,lf,111·',ldl! fJ<,rth, fr(·( flldfk1·t l1,1\lw1·r1dlJi'r)('fJ(J;tliJw·11cyr,!ll1JmiJflW\'ll
being in all regards. Hospitals, clinics, prisons, and s<.hools have not in every respect fur
the•ed <,ecurity, health, education, and knowledge for society. In some respects these
imtitut1om have served fumtions of control, <focipline, rc.gimentation, and surveillance in
modern societies. Projects to realize utilitarian ideals of the 'greatest happiness of the
greatest number' have fr<:quently endangered rather than safeguarded values of freedom
of thought, enquiry, belief, expression, and creativity in modern social history. )
As wil. bec.:ome clear in latn chapters of this book, numerous modern social theorists
ha·1e heavily cri ized the more optimistic assumptions of cighte:enth- and nineteenth
century soc.ial thought. Many writers point to ways in whi<.h ideas that appear rational
can aho be deeply irrat10nal. Many emphasize that what is healthy and normal from one
point of view can also be deeply pathological from another point of view. Many writers
demon ',trate that soence does not necessarily contribute to the increase of human
happiness and is n<1t neceHanly superior to myth or religion as a system of
understanding.
< >nt of the mo<,t horrific <..ase of the inc.r1tical social acceptance of science and techno
logy that has been of repeated interest to twentieth-century social theorists and philo
-,r,r,iir-r-,1, t Ii< rn<,·<-rit 1r,n a/Jc! U'>l'. r,f th,- n tH lc·ar hrJmh. I ,Jday tht prw,1h1lity rJf hum an gtnetic
, 1oning may represent a new case of defective moral public restraint of the uses of science
;,,,,; t,-, hr.,,J, ,g::_ Ji,,t ht tJ,.-,,. c ,1,1·, rqir<:'>(·r1t dtepl y pr<Jblemat1, 1 n,tantt'> oft hl·application
of natural -science knowledge to social and political life But social theorists have also been
intt're<,ted in num€'rous misuses and misapplicat10ns specifically of social-science know
J,-d,-s<·tr,·,,,, 1;;/ anrJ P' ;l1t Jr.al lif<·. r ,r it 1c, hav(· fl'Jlflttd trJ tht way, in which g(Jvern mtnh and
•,1;,1,-·, r,ur·,,m1,-s pr,Jir ir·, rJ<-rivr·rl di rte tly frr,m rJi,uplin(·<, ,uch a tumr1mi,,, p,ychology,
rr- r,;,;z,·rri<·rit ·,t 1di•·,, and f1u,; n<·,, ,t urJi(:'> tan v,muimt, IJ\.'. rl'.'>J)'Jn,iblt lr,r dehumanizing
,,r •1,-,hn1,rruf1r, uit1u,-, ,,f ;,;,,- urianu· 1r1 vAi<:ty. \\'h<:n govunm<:nt, and ,tatt, exploit
-,,,r);J! r)r-ri, ,. h11,•:,l<·rlg•· fr,r fJ'Jlir ie:, ,,ril'.ntuJ rJV<:rwhclmingly trJ <Jbje,tivt, of rfficiency,
proriurtiv1ry, rmkriirw,\, anrJ ,y\/ernutir ity-at the: txpeme: ,,f open mrJral and political
public debate-ther( is a danger that social members become treated as pure objects of
admin
istratirin. fhert 1s a danger that social citizens become treated like patients of a social
'/ Jl:r, t iii, , /. pr·r mwri' in · r,, 1a) tngrntermg', t<J bt umtr<Jlled in fltd'>'> numh(•r . Lat tr chapttr
of this brJOk will discu s the development of such critiques of science, modernity, and
w ,-,,-r 1i;;1,,, 1 r1 t rw ,,-;r,rk ,,/ .\11 ax \'.'<:!Ju!( J1aptu - ;,Ill "v\ e,t<:rn \1Mxi ,m (< ,hapttr 7 ), JrJ
th<: 1,J,·c1', ,,f '>1;,;rnund 'I r<:urJ l(,h;iptn ½;, in thi: wrJrk 1Jf \1ilhe:I •1-,,ucault /Chapter 9),
in ftm ir,1-,1 -,r,r i;;I I fwr,r:, II ,haptr-r J l /, JrJ 'pr,,tJTHJ(Jernhm /(_haptu, 12 ;ind 1 ). and
,tvcral other
context .
/ J ,,r rri;.,11 v -,,,, i:J! t hr:r,r J ',h, r ,m: r,f m, ,,t drc:adful in ,tanll'> <Jf th l'. unre,tfili ncd applicatifJn
./ nf 5cient1f:c rationalizing principles to social organization is the rise of *totalitarianism)
in £Jropt in the 1930s, and in particular in the "-azi Holocaust of the Jews. This case is
;;,., ,, :,1·11 brir-fly 111 B,,x . •Mth rduu,u t<J the \\1,rk ,,f Hannah ',\rtndt and Zygmunt
Bauman.
36 AUSTIN HARRINGTON
The Holocaust has preoccupied numerous social theorists not only for the Nazis' barbaric use of chem
ical technology-lethal gas as a method of mass extermination. It has also concerned social
theorists for the Nazis' use of planned, calculated, and scientific methods of controlling and
organizing social agents. For many critics, the Holocaust is a terrible case of the misuse of both
natural science and social science-specifically of social science perverted into the science of
mastery Over people. Two notable theorists in this regard have been Hannah * Arendt and
Zygmunt *Bauman.
In her report on the trial of Adolf Eichmann, secretary of the planning commission for the Final
Solution, published as Eichmann in Jerusalem in 1963, and also in her larger book The Origins of
Totalitarianism of 1951, Arendt argues that the Holocaust was more than a purely contingent historical
crime perpetrated in Germany in the 1940s against the Jewish people. Without diminishing the enorm
ity and historical specificity of the Jewish people's suffering, Arendt argues that the Holocaust demon
strates a universal tendency towards barbarism latent in all modern mass societies. Her thesis is that
when science and technology and rational techniques of planning and calculation are used for the sole
and overwhelming purpose of gaining political and commercial control over mass numbers of people,
society descends into barbarism. In her view, the two cardinal types of totalitarian regime represented
by Hitler's fascism and Stalin's Soviet communism are only the most virulent examples of a tendency
toward totalizing technical control over human beings latent in all modernity-including our own
allegedly 'free' societies oriented to liberal democracy and market capitalism. Arendt argued that
when violence is routinized, sanitized, and taken for granted in any society, the possibility of the
perpetration of evil acts becomes banal. To the extent that Eichmann routinely followed orders and
fulfilled the duties of hig office, he behaved in principle no differently from any ordinary functionary
of the modern state or of the modern business corporation. According to Arendt, Eichmann's shared
personal responsibility for the Holocaust gives us a lesson in the 'banality of evil'.
Zygmunt Bauman's Modernity and the Holocaust (1989) develops Arendt's thesis in notable
ways Bauman argues that 'civilization' and the *'civilizing process' do not mean the removal of
violence.
They mean only the control of violence, its concentration in the hands of a sovereign power. In this
sense, it was the Nazis' highly 'civilized' use of rational bureaucratic principles of organizational
Conclusion
Modernity canbecharacterized as a distinctive kind of social attitude to time. Modem atti
tudes to time tend to involve processes of critical reflection on the past with a view to pro
jects of collective determination of the future. Traditional attitudes tend to be marked by
forms of acceptance and preservation of the past, without a developed belief in rational
social agency over the future.
ClASSICAl SOCIAL TiffORV. I 37
What is a 'modern' attitude to life? What is a 'traditional' attitude to life? Are there any
'modern' forms of life that can at the same time be described as 'traditional'?
2 What features of social-historical change best characterize the Western experience of
modernity' In what sense is it appropriate to speak of 'the West'? Are there any experiences of
modernity which are not Western?
38 ; usn,J rlAll RINCTO N
4 What are some of the strengths and weaknesses of eighteenth- and nineteenth-century
European social thought for discussion today?
5 What is meant by 'the Enlightenment'? Is the Enlightenment a legacy for which we should
be thankful?
6 Is it possible to speak of reason and progress in history? Is it possible not to speak of reason
and progress in history?
FURTHER READING
For some good overviews of the makings of nineteenth-century and early twentieth-century
European social thought, the following titles can be recommended: Stuart Hughes's Consciousness
and Sodety: The Re-orientation of European Social Thought (Knopf, 1958), Geoffrey Hawthorn's
Enlightenment and Despair: The Making of Sociology (Cambridge University Press, 1976), Donald
Levine's Visions of the Sociological Tradition (University of Chicago Press, 1995), Wolf Lepenies's
Between Literature and Science: The Rise of Sociology (Cambridge University Press, 1988), Johan
Heilbron's The Rise of Social Theory (University of Minnesota Press, 1995), Steven Seidman's
Liberalism and the Origins of European Soda/ Theory (Blackwell, 1983), John Burrow's The Crisis of
Reason: European Thought 1848-1914 (Yale University Press, 2000), and Raymond Aron's Main
Currents in Sociological Thought (Penguin, 1965; 1968) (in two volumes).
An accessible encyclopedic introduction to European history and civilization is Norman Davies's
Europe: A History (Oxford ,University Press, 1996). For an introduction to the culture of the
European Renaissance, try Peter Burke's The European Renaissance: Centres and Peripheries (Blackwell,
1998). For sur veys of the eighteenth-century Enlightenment, a good reference source is Alan C.
Kors's Encyclopaedia of the Enlightenment (Oxford University Press, 2002). For more in-depth
discussion of debates about the rise of the West and the emergence of capitalism, industrialization,
and the nation-state, see Chapter 6 of this book by Dennis Smith. See also the titles cited in the
further reading for Chapter 6. For Max Weber's views on the rise of the West, see Chapter 3 of
this book by Gianfranco Poggi, and also Wolfgang Schluchter's The Rise of Occidental Rationalism
(University of California Press, 1981).
The further debates mentioned in this chapter about modernity, science, myth, civilization,
tech nocracy, rationality, and irrationality are developed at length in this book in Chapter 7 by
Douglas Kellner (on Western Marxism), in Chapter 8 by Anthony Elliott (on psychoanalysis), in
Chapter 9 by Samantha Ashenden (on structuralism and post-structuralism), in Chapter 11 by
Lisa Adkins (on feminist theory), in Chapter 12 by Barry Smart (on postmodernism), and in
Chapter 13 by Gerard Delanty (on modernity after postmodernism).
For an introduction to the work of Hannah Arendt, see Phillip Hansen's Hannah Arendt (Polity
Press, 1993). For a collection of extracts from Arendt's writings, try The Portable Hannah Arendt, ed. Peter
Baehr (Penguin, 2000). For an introduction to postcolonial studies, see Robert J. C. Young's
Postcolonialism: An Historical Introduction (Blackwell, 2001). See also Henry Schwartz and Sangeeta
Ray (eds.), A Companion to Postcolonial Studies (Blackwell, 2000), and Henry Louis Gates and
Kwame Anthony Appiah's Dictionary of Global Culture (Penguin, 1998).
39
- WEBSITES
Karl *Marx and Emile *Durkheim differ profoundly in their views about society.
Durkheim was 24 on Marx's death in 1883 and rarely refers explicitly to the earlier
thinker. Marx, for his part, did not subscribe to Durkheim's later nineteenth-century vision
of a liberal impartial study of society, and on the few occasions where he used August
*Comte's term 'sociology', which had limited currency in the mid- to late nineteenth
century, it was to pour scorn on the pretensions of a bourgeois science of society. Yet
despite these profound differences of outlook, Marx and Durkheim were both centrally
concerned with the emergence of modern capitalism, and in particular with the rise of the
modern system of the *division of labour and the evolution of a market society. Both
approach these devel opments by focusing on the effects that the spread of market
relations had on *solidarity and on society's ability to reproduce itself. Both therefore had
to engage with the causes and implications of key developments-the Industrial Revolution
in particular-as well as key events such as the French Revolution. Both sought to revise
the simplistic and apolo getic accounts of capitalist society commonly found in
nineteenth-century social thought. Where they differ most strikingly is in the conclusions-
the lessons-they draw from their intellectual engagement with modernity.
This chapter provides an overview of the main intellectual projects of Marx and
Durkheim, treating each thinker in turn. We consider how both Marx and Durkheim
produce accounts of the nature of the modern division oflabour and the nature of the
state and *civil society that in some respects are comparable and in other respects
radically divergent. We begin with Marx.
In Britain, Marx and Engels continued to involve themselves in the politics of the
Communist League with the aim of convincing the communist movement to adopt their
scientific approach. It was in London that Marx devoted himself to historical and
economic research, famously in the British Library. His mature works are marked by a
shift away from the philosophical influences of his youth-of which he had already been
critical-towards economic theories. His attention focused increasingly on Scottish and
English political economy, notably the theories of Adam *Smith and David *Ricardo. It
was his engagement with political economy that was to mark the highpoint of his
thought and enable him to develop a general theory of capitalism. The 1850s and 1860s
saw the publication of the key works of Marx's economic theory, including the much
delayed publication of n)lume 1of C1pit<1/ (Di1s K,1pit,1/) in 1Sb7. \Lin.\ health decli1wd in
the 1s:-o and it was only after his death in 1883 that the second and third volumes of
C.1pital appeared, edited by Engels.
The first important event in the development of Marx's thinking is his engagement with
German idealist philosophy. It is with this that we begin.
had called the *'species-being' of humanity. Capitalism degrades the essentially social
nature of human beings into a merely selfish, egmstic nature. From Hegel and Feuerbach,
Marx quickly moved to a who) sale critique of philosophy as a potential instrument
of social change and emancipation. In his 'Theses on Feuerbach' of 1845, he famously
stated that 'philosophers have only interpreted the world in various ways; the point is to
change it' (1845: 423).
Yet despite his antagonistic relation to Hegel, Marx was to remain deeply indebted to
German idealist philosophy. From Hegel, Marx retained a *teleological conception of his
tory in which historical facts are connected to each other in a scheme driven by an
ultimate goal or 'telos'. Marx's thinking consistently embodied Hegel's conception of a
dialectic in which social change is seen as the outcome of attempts to solve inherent
contradictions between opposing historical forces. Similarly, Marx also incorporated
important elements of the philosophy of Hegel's main intellectual predecessor, Immanuel
*Kant. When Marx insisted that science is the work of aitique, he borrowed the concept of
'critique' from Kant. 'Critique' for Kant had meant examination of the 'conditions of the
possibility of experi ence'. In Marx's view these 'conditions of the possibility of
experience' were not only logical or intellectual; they were also material and social.
We now consider how Marx elaborates these ideas in the context of economic theory
and the critique of capitalism.
• feudalism, based on relations of bondage between owners of land and landless serfs
or peasants;
• capitalism, based on relations of exploitation between owners of property and
propertyless workers; and
44 ANTONINO PALUMBO AiliO ALAN SCOTT
Marx believed that the inherently exploitative nature of capitalism and its inevitable
self-destruction could be demonstrated from within the standpoint of political economy
itself. His refutation of political economy and his more general critique of received social
thought were to crystallize around six key themes:
The developments that made the rise of capitalism possible were acts of confiscation of
church land and property by the state, enclosure of common lands into private estates,
dismantling of the medieval system of *guild occupations, and sy ematic destructi of_
!ra_ditional customs and relations qf authority. These changes had the effect of creating a
n w system in whi h s of the ited class in society are left with virtually
no direct access to the means necessary to ensure their material well-being, or to what
Marx called the 'means of production'. Where peasants in the feudal system had access to
land by which to feed themselves, the new type of worker under capitalism possesses only
a sum of money, a wage. *Exploitation based upon principles of personal subjugation and
obligation has been replaced by the seeming obj>ctivity of the labour contract and by the
'cash nexus'. Marx thus sought to show that class relations are inherently conflictual
and that the capitalist mode of production rested on the systemic exploitation of one
class by another class-the proletariat by the bourgeoisie. This explanatory framework
was then used to unmask the ideological nature of bourgeois social, legal, and
political arrangements. Marx's hope was that theory would contribute to the
development of a revolutionary political movement that would, eventually, abolish
class divisions and *emancipate the
individual.
estrangement appears not only in the fact that the means of my life belong to another and that my desire is
the inaccessible possession of another, but also in the fact that all things are other than themselves,
that my activity is other than itself, and that finally-and this goes for capitalists too-an inhuman power
rules over everything. (1844b: 366)
Marx's conception of alienation has exercised a profound influence in modern social theory. It
has found many echoes in the neo-Hegel1an thinking of figures such as Gyorgy *Lukacs and Ernst
*Bloch and the *existentialist Marxism of Jean-Paul *Sartre. To a certain extent, it can also be
compared with Max *Weber's and Georg *Simmel's writing on the 'iron cage' of modern
capitalism, bureaucracy, industry, and technology.
persons is transformed into a social relation between things' (1858: 157). In volume 1 of
Capital, Marx refers to this transformation of relations between persons into relations
between things as*'commodity fetishism'. In a society that comes to fetishize the objects
of its production as objects of consumption, the workings of human *agency are mystified
and *'reified'. It is this pseudo-objectivity that gives capitalism its opaque quality and
makes it seem incapable of abolition or transformation.
constantly tor new markets and cheaper and more efficient sourcesof labour, and new
means of reducing labour costs. 'Modern industry never views or treats the existing form
of a production process as the definitive one,' Marx writes (1867: 617). Capitalism
remains in a constant state of flux. Modern capitalist societies generate change,
innovation, and develop ment as their very mode of social reproduction. Once the energies
of modern industrial capitalism have been unleashed, vigorous development of the means
of production and destruction of the old and creation of the new all constantly transform
bourgeois society. In The Communist Manifesto Marx and Engels declare:
,-In thebourgeois political state, individuals live out their desire for freedom and sociability,
which in fact remain beyond earthly reach under the capitalist system. The secular
state
1 appears to be a sort of pathway to Heaven, but is just as illusory as the ideas of Heaven
propagated by traditional religion. -4
Marx's more general thought about religion here epitomizes the militant side of
enlightenment. Marx argues that by shedding light on the actual workings of this world,
historical materialism will expose the illusion of a life beyond death. Marx maintains that
since religion represents an 'ideological reflex' of actual economic relations, its critique
represents the necessary precondition for the unmasking of all other ideological forms. In
the short 'Contribution to the Critique of Hegel's Philosophy of Right', Marx famously
refers to religion as the 'opium of the people' (1844a: 244). Like a misused drug, religion
administers to true needs in false ways. Religion promises something that the system it
serves has no ability ever to deliver. Religion is at once 'the expression of real suffering
and a protest against real suffering'. It is 'the sigh of the oppressed creature, the heart of
a heartless world, and the soul of soulless conditions':
The abolition of religion as the illusory happiness of the people is the demand for their real
happiness. To call on them to give up their illusions about their condition is to call on them to give
up a condition that requires illusions. The criticism of religion is therefore in embryo the criticism
of that vale of tears of which religion is the halo. (1844a: 244)
illusion that the state is the opposite of prh ate property, or that it is a means for the
revoca tion of property in general. Political freedom here becomes merely freedom of
pri\·ate individuals from social constraints on their right 'to pursue their own interests
in their own ways', in.John Stuart *Mill's phrase. Political liberalism perpetuates a
situatwn in \\·hid1 communal life is confined to an ideal political realm. ll'hile merely
freeing pri\·,1te indi\·idu als to pursue their egotistic interests without thought of others as
members of a communitr. This leads Marx to a more general critique of the discourse of
rights, of both chi! rights and human rights. He comments that 'the so-called rights of
man, as distinct from the rights of the citizen, are quite simply the rights of the
members of chi! societ), i.e. of egotistic man, and man separated from other men and
from the community' (1843: 229). Marx concludes that the 'practical application of the
right of man to freedom is of man to private property' (1843: 229). In this picture,
security or 'police' (Polizei) be omes 'the supreme concept of civif society', ensuring that
'society is only there to guarantee each of its members the conservation of his person,
his right to property' (1843: 230). In The Communist Manifesto Marx goes so far as
to describe the state as little more than a 'committee for managing the common affairs
of the whole bourgeoisie' (Marx and Engels 1848: 82). In Tile Eishteenth Br11111,1ire
o(Louis Bo11t1pt1rte \1852) :\larx oh\erwd the pl)puli t dictatorship of the French leader of
the Second Empire, Napoleon III. He demonstrated
how the imperial French state dedicated itself to the defence of the property interests of the
French middle classes. Thus in Marx's view, the state remains intimately im·ol\·ect in the
reproduction of property relations. It does not represent the general public interest but
only the particular propertied interests of the ruling class. Marx argues that true human
emancipation will occur only with the dissolution of the distinction between state and
civil society and with it the rights of the private individual.
Marx also voices similar objections against all socialist movements whose goal is not
the revolutionary overthrow of capitalism but merely its political reform. Marx ,;ees
revolu tionary processes as having the function of making individuals aware of their
ondition as members of an exploited social class. This awareness entails a transition from
what fan: calls the 'class-in-itself to the 'class-for-itself', that is, to a class with a
co11scio11sncss of itself as a class (Marx 1858: 177-8). This idea comes to the fore in
TheGerman Ideolog)', where he proclaims that,
Both for the production on a mass scale of this communist consciousness, and for the success of the
cause itself, the alteration of men on a mass scale is necessary, an alteration which can ontv
take place in a practical movement, a revolution; this revolution is necessar), therefore, not on!)
because the ruling class cannot be overthrown in any other wav, but also because the class
ovrrthrowing it can only in a revolution succeed in ridding itself of all the muck of ages and
become fitted to found society anew. (Marx and Engels 1846: 94-5)
Auguste *Comte, although he did not share Comte's implicit *metaphysical and *teleolog
ical assumptions about morally superior stages of civilization. In The Rules, Durkheim
attempted to bridge the gap opened up within positivism between prescriptive and
descriptive statements by suggesting a distinction between 'normal' and 'pathological'
dimensions of social life. This distinction found a practical application in Durkheim's
work on suicide, which can be seen as a showcase of Durkheim's principles of empirical
method. It is discussed in Box 5.
In addition to methodology, a general concern of Durkheim's early work was to formu
late a theory of social change capable of supplying sound scientific analyses of features of
modern industrial societies and of suggesting adequate solutions to problems of social
conflict and inequality. In this regard, he grew increasingly dissatisfied with the confident
*utilitarian agendas and methodologies of figures such as John Stuart *Mill and Herbert
*Spencer. He sought to adhere to scientific principles of detachment in a way that might
also yield moral advice for attempts at improving social life. 'Because what we propose
to study is above all reality', he wrote, 'it does not follow that we should give up the idea
of improving it' (Durkheim 1893: p. xxvi). This concern underpins his first major work of
substantive sociology, The Division of Labour in Society (1893), to which we now turn.
to a normal way of life, where normality refers to a functioning role in the division of
labour. --- -- _, ··· - ·· ·· -
Echoing Marx, Durkheim presents the modem division of labour as an epoch-making
event. The passage from the old order to the new entails a process of liberation of the
individual from tradition and the emergence of a new kind of consciousness affirming the
primacy of individual personal identity. Like Marx, Durkheim argues that the modern
division of Jabour was possible onJy because of the collapse of the previous
so.c;Jal.Ql.d.cr. What pushed people to specialize was the increase in 'social density'
caused by the disinte gration of older segmentary forms of society and the struggle for
survival that this higher density generated. Durkheim postulates that 'the progress of
labour is in direct proportion to the moral or dynamic density of society' (1893: 201). The
increase in social density is not due to simple demographic growth but to the fact that
people belonging to separate social groups come to interact more frequently and on a more
permanent basis-most notably in the city and in every larger urban spaces.
In disagreement with Marx, however, Durkheim !11 i_ntains that.the.divisiQn of labour is
not a _vehicle o_f class exploitation. Rather, it is to be viewed as a source of solidarity that
is better adapted to modern conditions. Durkheim secs class division and conflict only as a
side effect of the pace of social change, as a pathological product of modern society, but
not as a fundamental contradiction inherent in modernity. This leads Durkheim to
advocate a different course of action from that of Marx's proletarian revolution.
In The Division of Labour in Society and throughout his later works, Durkheim
suggests that while the old world is dying, if not dead, the new world has not yet been
born. He sees Europe as still standing at the point of transition between the pre-modern
and the modern worlds, and such times of transition are times of hazard. The speed of
social change creates the danger that pre-modern mechanical solidarity might
disappear before modern organic solidarity is fully in place. Durkheim wrote that
'over a very short space of time very profound changes have occurred in the structure of
our societies. They have liberated themselves from the segmentary model with a speed
and in proportions without precedent in history. Thus the morality corresponding to
this type of society has lost influence, but without its successor developing quickly
enough to occupy the space left vacant in our consciousness' (1893: 339). The major
problems Durkheim sees in this shortfall of solidarity in modern societies lie in what
he calls anomie, which is discussed here in Box 6.
Durkheim defines :,a _ffile..as a state of *normlessness_arising from.social fragmentation and lack of
!ut o itat1ve social institutions capable of regulating social interaction. He writes that anomie, 'this malady of infiniteness which we
Civic Morals (1950), he deals with problems of anomie affecting the modern nation-state and
secular societies in general
What Durkheim calls anomie derives from the fact that the division of labour can have Qegative
eff_ ot only for th.e working classes but also for all those involved in the productive process and for
society 1n general. What he calls 'forced division of labour' is more specifically comparable to Marx's
conception of alienated labour. Forced division of labour consists in 'the fact that the working classes
do not really desire the status assigned to them and too often accept it only under constraint and force,
not having any means of gaining any other status' (1893: 293). In large-scale industry this imposition
goes together with two further constraints: the regimentation of workers and their physical separation
from the social environment and the routinization of working practices that transforms the worker into
·a lifeless cog'.
awareness and appreciation of interdependence can solve the modern anomic crisis; and
that only those rules and roles that are felt to be just and fair will provide the necessary
restraints on individual passions and desires. He particularly stresses the_!9le of *norIT!S. fl.
9
moral dl cipl I_;:! . !ructuring individual action and fostering healthy perSO!Hlities.
D-tirkheim's proposed remedies for anomic consist in the creation of institutions capable
of establishing common goals and identities by reinforcing channels of communication
between individuals and coordinating social functions. Durkheim looks especially to
the role of occupational groups, to the role of a corporatist state, and to the role of a
secular
moral education system as possible solutions. He sees two vital functions played by these c\.,'.'-(\ · ,·
>'
intermediary agencies: that of mediating between the individual and the state or _the · · ,c
ollefQ e b?dy, and th.i!t-Qf,s;p_ cating people into recognizing interests prior to and more
g neri:ll_t_han their own St;'lfi IJ i.rl.! !" sts. By 'occupational groups' Durkheim means
such things as trade unions and other professional associations. He argues that such
groups must have a democratic internal structure allowing people direct participation in
decision making at the local level and a well-defined constitutional role assuring them
direct influence in the public sphere. In contrast to the medieval *guilds or the fascist
system of corporations, Durkheim views these occupationally based social arrangements
as inherently democratic. They represent social spaces where people with common
interests and con cerns can gather together, cstahlish direct lines of communication, and
form collective identities. They are not markets in which agents meet with competing
preferences.
56 ANTONINO PALUMBO AND ALAN SCOTT
that 'not only is individualism not anarchical, but it henceforth is the only system of
beliefs which can ensure the moral unity of the country' (1898: 50). As society
becomes more differentiated, less bound to territory and to tradition, its values have to
become more un_r ersaL People cannot hold on to local traditions in a context in
which horizontdl differentiation breaks down locality and *particularistic values.
Durkheim writes that 'we make our way, little by little, towards a state, nearly achieved
by now, where the members of a single social group will have nothing in common
among themselves except their humanity' (1898: 51). If the universal is all that people
have in common, they must treat this as the sacred source of social cohesion. In what are
today called'multicultural societies', people cannot hope to find common agreement on the
basis of purely particularistic belief systems. But they may, according to Durkheim, hope
to find agreement on matters that are
t.h C J!l._1:1_?-01: property of all t.he compqnt;nt eJements, even though these of necessity
will J2e.s_,f an abstract aml.highly general nature. Durkheim is thus committed to a
form of
*cosmopolitan *universalism.
Conclusion
Although they share more in common than is often recognized-especially by those who
falsely identify Durkheim with conservatism-we must be aware that Marx and Durkheim
arrive ultimately at very different conclusions from one another. Marx's goal throughout
his life's work was to expose the underlying logic of capitalism from its birth to what he
saw as its inevitable self-destruction. Durkheim does not share this orientation.
Durkheim's understanding of the relationship between science and politics remains
wholly different. His liberal political views are illustrated by his stance in the *Dreyfus
affair in France in the 1890s, where he aligned himself with the progressive liberals, as
well as in his essays on socialism and his patriotic response to the First World War in
which he lost his only son. If Marx is the representative figure of the social theorist as
firebrand, Durkheim represents the social theorist as moral educator.
In the history of sociology, Durkheim's conception of society as a complex whole com
posed of interdependent social facts has led him sometimes to be aligned with
*functionalism; that is, with the doctrine that societies are more than the sum of their parts
and that social integration is achieved through mutual dependencies characterizinga complex,
differentiated social system (for full discussion of functionalism see Chapter 4 of this
book).
In this general respect, Durkheim shares with Marx an interest in analysing society as a
*totality of material forces vastly greater and more powerful than the beliefs that any
given individual may entertain about his or her world. It should, however, be noted
that when Marx's thought is compared to that of Durkheim-and even more so when it
is compared to that of Max Weber-Marx tends to underestimate the significance of
cultural and mental practices beyond the sphere of purely material economic relations.
It can be said that Marx retained some of the prejudices of political economy
concerning the
60 . NTOIIJINO PALUMBO AND ALAN SCOT'!
How compatible are the accounts of the modern division of labour given by Marx and
Durkheim? Where do they agree and where do they diverge?
2 How does Durkheim's concept of anomie differ from Marx's concept of alienation?
3 Marx and Durkheim both criticize individualist explanations of social phenomena. Where do
their critiques differ?
4 Is religion anything more than the 'the opium of the people', in Marx's phrase?
5 Is civil society merely a sphere of competing self-seeking individuals (Marx), or is it a necessary
component of a democratic and pluralistic society (Durkheim)?
Ci.A5SiCAl SOCIAL JHEOIW. I' 61
6 Is the state a 'committee for managing the common affairs of the whole bourgeoisie' (Marx), or
a regulative moral authority in which social interests can, and should, attain their highest
expression (Durkheim)?
■ FURTHER READING
The best starting point for reading Marx is The Communist Manifesto, available in Penguin (1967), or
in a new edition with an introduction by Eric Hobsbawm (Verso, 1998). There are excellent selec
tions from Marx in David McLellan's Karl Marx: Selected Writings (Oxford University Press, 2nd edn.
2000) and Jon Elster's Karl Marx: A Reader (Cambridge University Press, 1986). The essential source
for Marx's economic theories is volume 1 of Capital (available in Penguin, 1976), especially chapter
1 on 'The Commodity'. Also important is the chapter in Marx's Grw1drisse (available in Penguin,
1973), titled 'Chapter on money'. (Note that Marx's German word Grundrisse, meaning 'founda
tions' or 'outlines', is usually left untranslated in references to this book.) The best insight into
Marx's early philosophical ideas can be found in his Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts of
1844, which is available in Penguin under the title Karl Marx: Early Writings (1975). An excellent
straight forward account of Marx is David McLellan's Karl Marx: His Life and Thought (Papermac,
1987). A more entertaining account is by the journalist Francis Wheen, Karl Marx (Fourth Estate,
1999). A good analytical discussion is Shlomo Avineri's The Social and Political Thought of Karl
Marx (Cambridge University Press, 1968). For Marxian terminology, see Tom Bottomore et al.
(eds.), A Dictionary of Marxist Thought (Blackwell, 1985). For a survey of recent academic thinking
about Marx, see Karl Marx's Social and Political Thought: Critical Assessments, in four volumes, ed.
BobJessop and Charlie Malcolm-Brown (Routledge, 1990).
Four influential studies in 'analytical Marxism' (discussed further in this book, Chapter 7, pp. 168)
are G. A. Cohen's Karl Marx's Theory of History: A Defense (Oxford University Press, 1978), Jon
Elster's Making Sense of Marx (Cambridge University Press, 1985), John Roemer's Analytical
Foundations of Marxian Economic Theory (Cambridge University Press, 1981), and Alex Callinicos's
edited Marxist Theory (Oxford University Press, 1989).
For an introduction to Hegel, try Raymond Plant's Hegel: An Introduction (Blackwell, 1983), or
Charles Taylor's Hegel and Modern Society (Cambridge University Press, 1979) and Shlomo Avineri's
Hegel's Theory of the Modern State (Cambridge University Press, 1972).
The four core works of Durkheim are The Division of Labour, The Rules of Sociological Method, Suicide,
and The Elementary Forms of Religious Life (to be read roughly in this order). Try to use the newer
and better translations by W. D. Halls of Rules (Macmillan 1982) and Division of Labour (Free Press,
1984), and Karen Fields's translation for Elementary Forms (Free Press, 1995). Some well-chosen
collections of extracts from all four of these books with other notable texts by Durkheim are Emile
Durkheim: Selected Writings (Cambridge University Press, 1972) and Durkheim on Politics and the
State (Polity Press, 1986), both edited by Anthony Giddens, as well as Emile Durkheim: Sociologist
of Modernity, ed. Mustafa Emirbayer (Blackwell, 2003). Durkheim's political concerns can be seen
in his article 'Individualism and the Intellectuals', in Emile Durkheim on Morality and Society, ed.
R. N. Bellah (University of Chicago Press, 1973).
The standard intellectual biography of Durkheim is Steven Lukes's Emile Durkheim: His Life and
Work (Penguin, 1973). At a more basic level, try Kenneth Thompson's Emile Durkheim (Ellis
Horwood, 1982), Anthony Giddcns's Durkheim (Fontana, 1978), or R. A. Jones's Emile Durklieim: An
Introduction to Four Major Works (Sage, 1986). Also useful are Gianfranco Poggi's Durkheim (Oxford
University Press, 2000) and Stephen P. Turner (ed.), Emile Durkheim: Sociologist and Moralist
(Routledge, 1993). See also The Radical Sociology of Durkheim and Mauss, ed. Mike Gane and Keith
Tribe (Routledge, 1992). Durkheim's political sociology is discussed by Antonino Palumbo and Alan
Scott in 'Weber, Durkheim and the Sociology of the Modern State', in The Cambridge History of
Twentieth-Century Political Thought (Cambridge University Press, 2003). For the French reception of
Durkheim, see Philippe Besnard (ed.), The Sociological Domain (Cambridge University Press, 1983).
for instructive applications of Durkheim's analyses in the field of anthropology, see Jeffrey
Alexander's edited volume Durkheimian Sociology (Cambridge University Press, 1988). For compar
isons of Marx and Durkheim at a high analytical level, sec David Lockwood's Solidarity and Schism
(Oxford University Press, 1992) and Albert Hirschman's article 'Rival Interpretations of Market
Society' in the Journal of Economic Literature, 20/2 (1982).
WEBSITES
The Marxist Internet Archive (MIA) at www.marxists.org Display numerous excerpts from
writings by Marx, with commentaries and accounts of debates.
Marxism Page at www.anu.edu.au/polsci/marx/ Presents texts by Marx, Engels, Lenin, Trotsky, and
others.
The Durkheim Pages at www.relst.uiuc.edu/durkheim/ Contains a useful biography with
summaries of Durkheim's key texts and a glossary of terms.
Emile Durkheim Page at www.emiledurkheim.com Provides a good biography, pre enting parts
of Durkheim's major works (in the original French), a few quotations (in English), and a
bibliography.
The Emile Durkheim Archive at http://durkheim.itgo.com/main.html Contains sections on key
Durkheimian concepts, with a glossary and links to similar sites.
3 Classical Social Theory, Ill:
Max Weber and
Georg Simmel
Gianfranco Poggi
In the early 1890s Weber devoted his first major writings to the study of Roman law,
dealing with agricultural estates and commercial partnerships and companies in medieval
Italy. His doctoral dissertation examined directly the meanings of the terms socius and
societas 'commercial partner' and 'commercial partnership',or 'company', or 'society'-in
medieval trading law (Weber 1889). Sub equently, he entered the field ol sociology proper
(at first without naming it so) by analysing in depth the data yielded by empirical
enquiries into the conditions of agricultural workers in the eastern parts of Germany.
After 1900, Weber entered the so-called Metflodenstreit, or 'methodological dispute', a
lively and protracted dispute among German scholars active in various 'sciences of
culture'-chiefly history, theology, law, psychology, philosophy, and economics (Weber
1903, 1903-6). The dispute concerned the appropriate ways to conceive and practise those
disciplines. The basic issue was whether, how, and to what extent such practice should
model itself on that of the natural sciences.The central dispute was: Can human events
and arrangements be the object of general laws? Can the scholars studying them produce
objectively grounded results, given that as human beings they are unavoidably implicated
THEORY ill 65
in the subject matter of their researches? Three key ideas informed Weber's thinking
on this question, which we explore in turn. The first concerned the concept of
'understand ing' or *verstehen; the second concerned the role of values in research;
and the third concerned the role of what Weber was to term *'ideal types'.
It should not lead to an interference between the scholar's value judgement (Werturteil)
and the judgements of fact to he construed from the data of the matter at hand. These data
must he established in such a manner that the relative judgements can also command the
assent of other agents who do not share the researcher's value position.
If this distinction is observed (but its observance is always a matter of degree), then the
results of the research can become a public reality and serve as background and
inspiration for establishing further facts and attempting new interpretations of them. In
this manner one can, on one hand, recognize that the 'sciences of culture' involve a
particular, un avoidably value-laden relation between the scholar and the object of study,
and on the other hand demand of them, as from the 'sciences of nature', a commitment to
producing results which can be publicly recognized as valid.
Weber confronts in the same manner a related issue: to what extent does the practice of
the sciences of culture involve the formation and employment of general concepts?
Weber rejects the view that significant human phenomena are always and exclusively
'historical'; that is, that they gain their significance only from the precise where, when,
and how of their one-off occurrence. Instead Weber argues that all scientific discourse
employs more or less general concepts, such that individual cases can be examples of
general recurrent phe nomena. But as concerns the sciences of culture, he adds two
significant qualifications. First, concepts used in the cultural sciences do not aim at the
formulation of general laws of human conduct, much less of laws of historical
development. Secondly, the concepts appropriate to the sciences of culture differ from
those employed in the sciences of nature. Concepts in the cultural sciences are*ideal-
typical concepts. Weber states that ideal-typical concepts, or 'ideal types', make up
possible bunches of concepts or typologies, which can be used by the scholar to analyse
and categorize particular features of the subject matter under consideration. Ideal types in
this sense are tools for ordering information and for drawing out comparisons and
differences between observed phenomena. They are, however, merely tools of
analysis:they do not expressa judgement about what is 'ideal' in a phenomenon in the
sense of intrinsically worthy and admirable. With respect to the typology of forms of
social action, Weber employs an ideal type of 'traditional action' (action motivated by
received customs and traditions), an ideal type of 'affective action' (action motivated by
emotions and impulses), and an ideal type of 'purposive-rational action' or action motiva
ted by conscious methodical calculation of available means for achieving desired ends.
The point of Weber's ideal types is to provide conceptual benchmarks for the analysis of
individual situations, where components of contrasting types are often mixed. They
convey what could be called the bounded variety of cultural phenomena, allowing schol
ars to 'compare and contrast' systematically whole ranges of diverse yet interrelated
aspects of social experience.
as his last unfinished magnum opus Economy and Society, published posthumously in
1922, and several other key texts which will occupy us shortly. The discussion that
follows concentrates first on Weber's writings on capitalism, religion, and modernity.
Then we turn to his contributions to the theory of politics, power, *stratification,
bureaucracy, and
*rationalization.
The governing principle behind Weber's massive and creative work on the sociology of
religion is the following. Until relatively recent history, one of the most powerful agencies of
social bonding and social transformation has been religion. Generally, Weber says, religion
has a 'stereotyping' effect. That is, it stabilizes social arrangements, sustains the identity
of social groups, and maintains the structure of the contexts in which groups contend with
one another. In this manner, different religions can play a role in constituting and preserv
ing different cultures and civilizations, as well as in changing and transforming them.
One can connect this theme with Weber's argument about the necessarily 'interpretive'
posture of the human being. Although interpretive processes necessarily take place in the
minds of individuals, individuals are normally induced by social arrangements to accept
as valid certain pre-existent schemes and understandings of the world and its patterns of
activity. World-views and institutions align the practices of discrete individuals with those
of one another. In this manner, a plurality of such individuals may turn into a collectivity,
a social entity capable of joint action on behalf of shared interests of whatever kind.
Weber's generic expression for such an entity is Stand, generally translated in English as
*'status group'.
The concern of Weber's Protestant Ethic study is primarily with the role of a particular
religious world-view in 'authorizing' major social change. In most of his other main essays
on the sociology of religion, his concern is primarily with the role of religion in grounding
long-run differences between civilizations. But it is important to note that in neither of
these cases does Weber assume the role of religion to be the only decisive factor. On the con
trary, he argues that religious factors always interact "INith other cultural and social factors,
including the important material factors of military and political power, economic and
technological change, and legal relations, as well as the physical environment.
-;;: -: ._.;.,.. 2- ..:1 :::_ _ 'I'. - ._:: .i;'riear r-0 be a totally arehgious
- .-.. -:ic_,_-_ ; _,..1 _1 _:-_£"" "!. ::5 ..: w d ti" ities 1,;vh1ch
1 :-:J1...
w:;s. 1-"
.. t±:..cC. '· ,: . .. a.:..:L"-"'ttir-= cf 'pre<lesti:J..ation'
- ·-:..: t'--,..:. '.:l ar '-,s-::-;-ut.:;.b[e and unchange:ible
...i.:.,.it ,,, m the afterL.fe. ot even a
.,:-7i;,_-, , r :-- ..:..."'. :,,;.::': • "',;,:-ic. Pl "- t"'e -impehlll,; sense of
' - :-:,.:. - - the
'< - t"·- - .i_.::-"- ti-:. • t.H::: dI' a '::e SF'...nse of anxiety.
s...1..r "'!s::,...t...:.
.:_-c -.::a:.·-- ...:.-.::-.:: :c-.,:tm-.:c. to tl°'n:'ugh
.;,..:ts,_ :,uc acts. g()(l(i deeds or
Calvinism
·-- .:-,-'- c-..: _--.:,-r- .:es; j us1-.: : r' us. :he anuety can, how1;5e::,
H.-- - • L .:... ._ ·--::-, ... l.:.-..i::t. m \ 'ere be e,;ers commit all of
---..:-r-- :r--...:--
...... - - .
that no trace of traditionalism remained in the Calvinist Puritan conception, where the
elect could gain some sense of their election only by tinkering relentlessly with all
existing arrangements, by pursuing mastery over themselves.
4. Calvinist doctrine had not expressly authorized and encouraged believers to
translate this new asceticism into a 'spirit of capitalism'. But that translation, Weber
argued, was inevitable. The dogma of predestination placed a religious premium on ways
of acting in the world which conferred moral dignity on entrepreneurship. It turned
entrepreneurship into a test of one's moral worth. It allowed the systematic pursuit of
gain to be practised by the protagonists of early capitalist development, as Weber put it,
with 'an amazing good conscience'. This ethos was epitomized, Weber argued, in the life
and works of the eighteenth-century American statesman, inventor, and entrepreneur,
Benjamin *Franklin.
5. Yet this unintended internal link, or 'elective affinity' (Wahlverwandschafr) as Weber
called it, between Calvinist religiosity and capitalist entrepreneurship has had paradoxical
consequences. Over the generations, capitalism began to change the world in irresistible
ways, to loosen and discredit traditional constraints on business conduct, and eventually
to
*secularize Western culture. Thus the pursuit of gain through entrepreneurship began to
dispense with its earlier religious warrant. It has become )elf-sustaining and self-
justifying, cut free from its earlier religious meaning and content. In fact, the capitalist
spirit itself became dispensable, once the capitalist system had won the day. Today,
Weber argues, the system demands of individuals-and not just of entrepreneurs but also
of workers-the same commitment which it had originally derived from its moral
significance. Today, Weber writes, we find ourselves confronted with an 'iron cage' or
'steel-hard casing' (stah/hartes Gehause), marked by obligations to work and to fulfil our
profe)sional vocations, but no longer with any encompassing ethical or metaphysical
meaning. Weber declares:
The Puritan wanted to be a person with a vocational calling; today we are forced to be. For to the
extent that asceticism moved out of the monastic cell, was transferred to the life of work in a
vocational calling, and then commenced to rule over this-worldly morality, it helped to construct
the powerful cosmos of the modern economic order. Tied to the technical and economic conditions
at the foundation of mechanical and machine production, this cosmos today determines the
style of life of all individuals born into it-not only those directly engaged in earning a living. This
pulsating mechanism does so with overwhelming force. Perhaps it will continue to do so until the
last ton of fossil fuel has burnt to ashes. According to Baxter, the concern for material good)
should lie upon the shoulders of his saints like 'a lightweight coat that could be thrown off at any
time'. Yet fate allowed a steel-hard casing to be forged from this coat. To the extent that asceticism
attempted to transform and influence the world, the world's material goods acquired an increasing
and, in the end, inescapable power over people-as never before in history. (Weber 1920b: 123-4)
Looking back over the entirety of Weber's study, we can see that Weber's central
question is: did religious factors contribute to the genesis of capitalism and thereby to the
central economic component of the onset of modernity? Weber's answer is that Calvinism
played a significant role in the formation of the spirit of capitalism, and that this 'spirit of
capitalism' in turn played a significant role in the emergence of capitalism itself. Weber
thus contradicted all previous interpretations of the rise of capitalism, beginning with
Marx's, which had invoked only material factors and had treated the religious aspects of
modernization as merely derivative and secondary.
World religionsand socio-economicchange
In hisother comparative essays in the sociology of religion, concentrating on
Confucianism, Taoism, Hinduism, Buddhism, and Judaism, Weber addresses similar
general questions to those at stake in The Protestant Ethic. He shows the extent to which
these religions prevented the civilizations of China, India, and ancient Israel from
encouraging or allowing develop ments analogous to Western modernization, and
particularly the sustained *rationalization of all manner of social affairs, beginning with
the economic and political dimensions. These essays date from 1914-19, carrying the title
'The Economic Ethics of the World Religions'. They appeared originally in a series of
three volumes on the sociology of religion, also containing the second revised edition of
the Protestant Ethic of 1920.
The scope of the argument calls on a whole range of factors besides those of religion.
For instance, Weber's discussion of imperial China underlines the so-called 'hydraulic'
factor: the maintenance of agriculture, and thus of civilization, required a centralized
system of political control over floods and irrigation. In tum, such a system hindered the
develop ment of autonomous status groups analogous to those which played a leading role
in Western modernization.
Within this broad framework, the core argument of the essays engages with the social
consequences of religious forms represented in imperial China, pre-Raj India, and ancient
Israel. Weber's argument is the following. The religions in question played a significant
negative role as concerns the formation of anything like the spirit of capitalism. They did
not put a spiritual premium on individuals' efforts to prove their moral stature by achiev
ing a dynamic mastery of their worldly vocation. They discouraged or even condemned
any detachment from tradition and any sustained commitment to innovation in business
practices. At most, they allowed or encouraged the members of privileged status groups to
develop not a rationality of mastery over reality, but a rationality of adaptation to reality,
a recognition of and homage to its intrinsic harmonies. Weber demonstrates this
difference particularly in the case of the Mandarins of imperial China, trained in the
classic texts of
*Confucius and his followers and engaged in the empire's administration. In this account,
Confucianism strongly enjoined respect for tradition, valuing above all the correctness of
behaviour.
A similar argument applies to st.atus groups associated with the other Oriental religions,
in particular the Hindu Brahm ins and the Buddhist monks. These two constituencies
were also trained in bodies of religious doctrine, and their commitment to religious values
im parted a rationalistic tone to their existence. But such rationality was applied in the
pursuit of ritual purity and in the rejection of any serious engagement with the illusory
realities of this world. Thus their doctrines too, in different ways, prohibited the
emergence of something like the Puritans' worldly asceticism. They discouraged a
commitment to take seriously the things of the material world and to tramtorm these
things in everyday practice.
Weber concedes that ancient Judaism encouraged a commitment to worldly affairs
similar to tll,Jt of the Pu ntam. But he points out that this commitment focused chiefly on
the pursuit of military and political power in the contest with Gentile peoples. In this
sense,Judaism had a strongly *particularistic intent, based on advancement of the
interests of the in-group ('us') over against the out-group ('them'), the non-Jews or
Gentiles. Weber
(Li S<,lfAl ',O(IJH THrORY, fll 71
shows how this attitude found expression in the economic sphere. Typically, each Jew, in
trading with and working for other Jews, was expected to respect ethical constraints in his
dealings with other Jews but not in his economic relations to Gentiles. For this reason, the
Jews, despite their pre-eminence in trade and banking, failed to exert anything like as
pervasive an influence on the wider economic relations of society as that of the Protestant
Calvinists of early modern Europe.
We may notice here that Weber's was not so much a sociology of religion as a
sociology of religions, in the plural. Weber did not ,tudy religion in the abstract, as
Durkheim did in The Elementary Forms of Religious Life. Rather, Weber studied specific
historical religions. He took on board the doctrinal content of different religious traditions
and the associated differences in organizational structures, emphasizing their
differential impact on the way believers positioned themselves within the cosmos. He
was interested in the way different religions answer crucial questions about life before and
after death and conceive of the Deity.
We now turn to the second key focus of Weber's thinking, concerning the domain of
politics. We have seen that Weber is acutely aware of the sigmficance of religious
doctrines and the role of the personnel-prophets, priests, monks-who articulate these
doctrines and elaborate the related practices. This concentration should not, however,
lead us to think that Weber attributes to religious factors a general priority over other,
qualitatively differ ent kinds of factors. At the end of The Protestant Ethic Weber
emphasized that it was not his intention to set out 'a one-sided spiritualistic analysis of the
causes of culture and history in place of an equally one-sided *"materialistic" analysis'
(Weber 1920b: 125). On the con trary, Weber argues that individuals can attribute
significance to their lives with reference to several very different kinds of value
schemes-not only religious values but also eco
nomic, political, intellectual, aesthetic., and erotic values.
Weber points out that dominant *status groups can orient their mutual activities by
advancing partic.uJar mat<:rial inkn.:'>l, and ,ceking trJ makl' thl',l' intue,h prl'vail rJVer
competing one,. Jn thi, rl'gard, he empha,iZl''> that brJth 'idcaJ interl''>h' and 'matl'.rial
interests' play a part in shaping social action and s0cial movements through history. In one
revealing pa\'>agl'. Wl'.hu l'XJlfl'\'>l''> thh point with the mt:taphrn r,t \witchml'n' rm a
railway line. Material interests are like trains on railway lines whose movement is
unstoppable but who,l'. dirl'ction can hf.: changl'd hy 1dl'a<,, likl' the fJlficu, whr, rJptratl' thl'
,witchl'.'> at thl' point,: ''.\"ot idea,, but rnatl'rial and ickal inttrl''>h, dirl'ctly govun men\
UJnduct. Yl't vuy frl' quently the "world image," that havl' bu:n ueated by "idea," have,
like ,w1tchm\."n, dl'tu mined the: track'> alrmg which actifJn ha, bc:c:n pu,hul by the
dynamic r,f mtue<,t' !WdJl'r
1920d: 280).
Much of the essence of Weber's thinking in these regards appears in his last great work
Economy and Society, publi,hc:d in two parh in 192() and prJ,thumrrn,ly in 1922. Of kl'y
importance for Webu int hi, late wr Jrk arl' at lc:a,t three, Lardinal fac trJr,: the /act()f of power;
the, factor of stratification in ,rJCial ,true.lure, accurding trJ memhu,hip c la,,l', and \tatm
group,; and thl' factor of type, of lc-xitimutc 'dominution. We irJok at thl''>l' th rel' fallrJr, in
turn.
72 GiANFRANCO POGGI
• Legitimacy is traditional if the ground offered and accepted for obedience is chiefly
that what has happened in the past has every right to keep happening in the present and
future. Whoever commands in the present is regarded as the lawful descendant of the
people commanded in the past. Thus the commands given repeat and re-enact those
given in the past. Traditional legitimacy is typically to be found in the case of medieval
monarchies, where a monarch is regarded as the legitimate descendant of a blood line and
is owed allegiance by a company of loyal followers or patrons drawn from the nobility,
who administer the monarch's realm in its outlying provinces.
• Legitimacy is charismatic if, on the contrary, the commands issued break with
tradition but do so because the person issuing them demonstrably embodies extraord
inary compelling forces which are entitled to introduce innovation. Charismatic legit
imacy is typically provided by the warrior hero or by the prophet or breakaway religious
leader.
• Legitimacy is legal-rational if the commands issued find obedience by virtue of
being instantiations of general norms, where these norms are valid in turn because they
are enacted according to recognized principles and procedures. Such principles and
procedures authorize the issuing of commands by individuals as holders of offices, not in
their personal capacity. Legal-rational legitimacy describes the structure of modern
bureaucratic states.
The creative aspect of Weber's theory of legitimate domination is its insight that
other significant aspects of domination typically vary with the nature of the legitimacy at
stake. Weber shows how a whole range of political practices will be associated with a
given
*polity's type of legitimacy, including its different ways of empowering the rulers and
constraining the subordinates, of handing out justice, of producing norms, and raising and
74 GIANFRANCO POGGI
expending economic resources. Among the practices Weber considers most significant
are those concerning a polity's staff; that is, the relatively large number of individuals
who administer it, who interpret and implement its policies on a day-to-day basis and
mediate between its summit and its social base, between its centre and its periphery.
The key questions Weber raises in his analysis of political personnel concern how such
individuals are typically recruited, trained, assigned tasks, financed, controlled. His
answers make up a masterful set of ideal-typical concepts, spelling out the ways in
which staffs have been constituted throughout history. Traditional polities are typically
administered either by a *patriarchal staff, involving personnel standing in a relationship
of personal dependence to the ruler, or by a*patrimonial staff, that is, personnel who put
to the ruler's service resources which they control, formally or informally, in their own
right,
Cl ASSICAL sor1 l TH"ORY 111 75
By 'rationalization' Weber means that in all manner of social pursuits actors rely
increasingly on a deliberate search for the mo t efficient means lo achieve goals, optimizing
their achievement and making the costs and outcomes of pursuits as predictable as
possible. Calculation of the most efficient means of achieving desired ends takes
increasing precedence over reflection on the ultimate ethical meaning of these ends
themselves. In the most general sense, Weber sees technical efficiency, capitalism, and
administration as gradually usurping the place of religion, myth, and metaphysics in the
emergence of the modern world. This process is a demonstration of the development he
famously calls 'disenchantment of the world' (Entzauberung der Welt), brought about
by the rise of modern systems of social organization. As discussed in Chapter 7 of
this book, the members of the *Frankfurt School of social research were later to describe
this process in terms of the rise of *'instrumental reason', drawing on Weber's concept
of means-end rationality or 'purposive rationality' (Zweckrationalitat).
Weber developed this thinking about rationalization in two essays known as the
'Intermediate Reflections' and the 'Preface' (or 'Author's Introduction') to his collected
three volumes of writings on the sociology of religion (Weber 1920c, 1920e), as well as in
two famous lectures given in Munich in the winter of 1918-19, 'Science as a Vocation'
and 'Politics as a Vocation' (Weber 1919a, 1919b). In these texts, Weber is preoccupied
with the systematic rationalization of diverse spheres of social life or what he calls 'value-
spheres'. He concentrates particularly on the spheres of the economy, science, law, politics,
morality, the arts, and erotic life. Each sphere comes to develop in an autonomous fashion,
evolving its own independent logic of validity. Each sphere comes into sharp conflict with
the claims of other spheres and cannot be reconciled with them. Science, politics, and the
economy come into conflict with religion, while art and the erotic life also come into
conflict with morality.
76 GIANfRANCO POGGI
Some of Simmel's best essays analyse numerous apparently minor forms of sociability which the
established sciences of culture do not normally address. In the case of the distinctively modern
phenomenon of fashion, Simmel (1905) points out that fashion expresses two contrasting and
complementary needs of the individual. On the one hand, 1 div1duals signal the1r.1nterit to-ili'slii5'gwsh
themsel\es, to emphasize their individuality, by keeping ahead of the crowd and exploring experiences
not universally accepted. On the other hand, by virtue of appearing fashionable, individuals affiliate
themselves with other individuals like themselves and express a need for bonding and social belonging.
With the same intent, Simmel also discusses such figures as the pauper and, most notably, the
Stranger. Simmel shows how these figures are socially constituted, how they consist in relations
between individuals patterned by consistent though not expressly communicated understandings. The
essay on 'The Stranger' (1908b) conceptualizes perceptively the position of Jews in Western society as
excluded outsiders, but it also makes some more general points. Simmel memorably describes the
Stranger as the person who 'comes today and stays tomorrow'. The Stranger is distinguished from the
traveller or the vagabond. The Stranger embodies two basic and contrasting relations of individuals
to space, namely staying put and moving on. This holds not only in purely physical terms but in
the typical relations between the Stranger and the locals or natives. The Stranger generally seeks
only limited\
I acceptance, rna1nta1ns some degree of detachment and 'otherness'. In turn,"11il: n /;;"w n complex
reactions in the locals: on the one hand, curiosity'. a sens_e that they have something to learn or acquire
I from the stranger; and on the other hand, negative feelings, often extending to outright hostility.
OCiAl Tri:'OP"r
Iii 79
J
negative has in fact a number of positive effects (Simmel 1908a: 118-69, 1908c). But as the
analysis progresses, one realizes that it elaborates a rather obvious proposition, namely
that
: two conflicting parties may be brought together by their conflict with a third party. We may
( think of the old Arab proverb: 'me against my brother; my brother and myself against our
cousin; my brother, my cousin, and myself against our neighbour'.
notwant the subordinate to be wholly subjected to the superior's will, for such a subjection
would in the end induce inertia, and the superior needs the subordinate to be more than
inert. In this sense the superior can rely on the subordinate only if the latter is not
entirely at the mercy of the superior. This conception recalls the idea of a 'dialectic of the
master and the slave', originally formulated by the philosopher G. W. F. *Hegel and also
echoed by authors as different as Marx and some contemporary feminist and postcolonial
critics. In this thinking, a slave is progressively empowered by the fact that he has learned
more and more and can challenge a master who is disempowered by the fact that he
depends on the slave's labour.
More generally, Simmel's argument is that all social relations involve reciprocity or
reciprocal effect. Simmel's German expression Wechselwirkung is often translated simply
as 'interaction'; but the German term Wechsel specifically means 'exchange'. It suggests
that we consider all social relations, including those apparently most remote from market
and commerce-such as intimate relations-as involving exchange and reciprocity. In
the mid-twentieth century, Peter Blau's Exchange and Power in Social Life (1964) derived
much of its general theory of the social process from Simmel's metaphor of exchange.
In exchange, ambivalence is particularly marked, for it involves giving as little as possible
of something to get as much as possible of something else. Some parallels can be
discerned here between Simmel's thinking about reciprocity and the work of the early
twentieth century French anthropologist Marcel *Mauss on 'the gift' (Mauss 1924).
ontrast, the groups to which an individual belongs overlap. His or her membership of
such groups is e]ecti:ve, expressing the deliberate, contingent choices of the individual. As a
result, individuals are likely to associate with some partners in onegroup and with others
in another group. They are shielded from the incessant monitoring of any single set of
associates and can develop a sense of autonomy. Individuals can weave a 'web of group
affiliations' of their own (Simmel 1903d). It is the idiosyncratic content of each web that
grounds individuals' sense of personal distinctiveness, and this distinctiveness
increases as individuals'
_memberships multiply and vary over time. This contrast between concentric and
overlap ping sets of groups is another example of Sirnmel's geometrical imagery of social
life.
A second theme in Simrnel's idea of modernity is its conception of a link between
economic action and the concept of renunciation. Simmel considers how renunciation
differentiates economic action from robbery and piracy and the like insofar as it involves
exchange; that is, a giving up something for something else. Exchange raises for the
participants a question that is both quantitative and qualitative: a giving up how much
of what for how much of what? Both aspects of the question are best handled when
exchange goes beyond barter and becomes monetary. For money is intrinsically
quantitative, and it can be given and taken in exchange for anything. Nothing is
intrinsically money; anything can be money. What functions as money is thus the critical
question, which can be solved only institutionally, through publicly sanctioned
arrangements. Yet these arrangements need to be backed by public confidence, by
what is called 'trust'.
In the highly developed money systems of modern cities, social life evinces the
prevalence of instrumental over against expressive relations. It displays abstractness, a
heightened significance of quantity over quality, and at the same time an awareness that
everything is related to everything else. The characteristics of the modern money system
are anonymity of possessions and people and a tendency toward unceasing movement. All
these properties powerfully shape modern society, imparting to it its relentless dynamism.
In arguing this, Sirnmel to an extent agrees with Marx's views about the centrality
of economic phenomena, but he also problematizes Marx's account. F J,J.!P,EJ._,fl, the
_illa_ffi!11ent of vJ!lue tO fil!_Qdsjs !:!s.Jed gn_5.uf?j_ c!!_ve cu)twal p_roc s ef of
(;... nootnthaemount of socially necessary labour po er invested
in producing
such goods.
One of Simmel's most often cited essays which complements The Philosophy of Money is
his essay of 1903 'The Metropolis and Mental Life'. This is discussed in Box 9.
metropolitan life threatens individuals with restless stimulation and excitement. To protect themselves
from nervous exhaustion, 1nd1v1duals must adopt practices such as holding otfiers al a c!istan;:E;
_and attitudes of blase indifference. In turn, these practices and attitudes, necessary as they are,
deprive
i 1duals of an opportunity to appreeiate deeply the obJects and people they efi_ OUD1 Jo for1:17
authentic associiltions. The anonymity of life in the larger city protects individuals from the close mon
itoring nd sanct10;; of other people, allowing them to develop their personalities; but at the same
time it engenders loneliness and alienation. In the USA, Simmel's writings on the city exerted an import
ant impact on the *Chicago School of Sociologists, as discussed in Chapter 5 of this book, pp. 115-6.
ennoble us. But this process does not often attain its goal. According to Simmel's late
tragic vision, mastering the makings of the products of culture requires an effort which
most individuaKcannot bear to sustain. They baulk at the effort, contenting themselves
with a vague acquaintance of the works of the past or displaying a shallow
connoisseursh.ip of them. If this happens, a true process of cultivation fails to take place.
Simmel calls this the 'tragedy of culture', which is relentlessly intensified in modern times
as the objective world of social-c11ltural institutions becomes an insuperable mass
beyond any possibility of organic assimilation by a single individual. Above all in the
metropolis, the sheer accumu lation of the products of human agency-
technological,economic, political, and artistic multiplies the occasions for cultivation open
to the individual, but at the same time overwhelms the individual with multiplicity,
variety, and restless change.
ln these last reflections, Simmel shares several attitudes in common with Weber
concerning the fate of the 'old European' cultural world-view. In the final section of
this chapter we turn to some commonalities between Weber and Simmel in relation to the
near-contemporary thinking of Friedrich *Nietzsche and Sigmund *Freud.
one aspect of the late nineteenth century: its complacency about progress, its shallow
assurance about the solidity and superiority of the current era. On the other hand,
Weber does not express any backward-looking lamentation about the ravages of
modernity. His view is that society must embrace the present, in all its contradictions
and paradoxes.
Conclusion
Weber and Simmel share an understanding of social reality which emphasizes its
intrinsically historical nature. Both appreciate the necessity of approaching social reality
'hermeneutically'; that is, with an eye to the subjective processes orienting the conduct of
individuals. They also agree that in those processes, a given individual's activity intersects
with and accommodates the results of the activities of many other individuals, both
present and past. In these respects, Weber and Simmel contrast with Marx and Durkheim.
Where the latter think of society and social change above all in terms of structures and
systems, involving objective forces and dynamics operating above the heads of
individuals, Weber and Simmel underscore the importance of meaning, individual action,
and subjectivity.
At the same time, the orientations of the two thinkers differ markedly. Weber is chiefly
interested in the continuities and discontinuities of historical events and the different
sensitivities, competences, and action orientations generated across the human
species. Weber is concerned with the historical diversity of ways of experiencing and
evaluating reality, of constructing institutions and motivating and justifying action.
Accordingly, his sociological work aims to conceptualize sharply the different value
constructs and diverse sets of institutions constraining human activities, ranging across
such fields as law, reli gion, politics, science, the economy, and the arts. Simmel, in
contrast, focuses attention on the ways in which individuals-especially modern
individuals-negotiate their exist ence in any social context, according to the patterns of
interaction they weave in encountering each other. It is, so to speak, not the what of the
socio-historical process that attracts his attention but the how of that process. Simmel
has as keen a sense for conflict, contradiction, and tragedy, as Weber does; but where
Weber emphasizes contrasts between material and ideal interests and between values,
Simmel explores the import of the 'unsociable sociability' of human beings and the
dynamic tension between the self and the other person as mutually interrelated,
mutually differentiated members of shifting social forms. Read together, these two
authors suggest how diverse the sociolog ical enterprise can be.
What methodological precepts distinguish Weber's vision of social science from that of
Marx and Durkheim? Why is 'value relevance' important to Weber?
2 Why does Weber attach importance to religion in his account of the rise of capitalism and the
emergence of the modern world?
CLASSICAL SOCIAl TH EORV Ill 85
3 What does Weber mean by 'legitimate domination'? What is the significance of legal-rational
domination for modern social organization?
5 What does Simmel regard as the driving forces of modernity? How do Simmel's reflections on
money compare and contrast with Marx's and Weber's theories about capitalism?
■ FURTHER READING
The best place to begin reading Weber is The Protestant Ethic and the Spirit of Capitalism, either in
the classic translation of 1930 by Talcott Parsons (published by Routledge, with an introduction by
Anthony Giddens) or in the more accurate translation of 2001 by Stephen Kalberg (published by
Blackwell), which includes some useful notes explaining Weber's difficult historical vocabulary.
Another translation is available by Peter Baehr and Gordon Wells, published by Penguin in 2002,
though this translation is based on the first edition of 1904-5, not on the revised and expanded
edition of 1920. Most of Weber'sother key shorter texts and extracts are available in From Max Weber:
Essays in Sociology, ed. H. H. Gerth and C. Wright Mills (Routledge, 1948), and in a more recent
and more accurate collection The Essential Weber, ed.Sam Whimster (Routledge, 2003).
For Weber's conception of the relation between 'interests and ideas' or between 'material factors
and ideal factors' in religion and culture, see (in Gerth and Mills) 'The Social Psychology of the
World Religions', alias (in Whimster) 'Introduction to the Economic Ethics of the World Religions'.
For Weber's conception of rationalization, see the 'Author's Introduction' to Talcott Parsons's trans
lation of The Protestant Ethic, alias 'Prefatory Remarks to the Collected Essays in the Sociology of
Religion', in Stephen Kalberg's translation; also (in Gerth and Mills) 'Religious Rejections of the
World and their Directions', alias (in Whimster) 'Intermediate Reflections on the Economic Ethics
of the World Religions'. For Weber's methodological views, read his essay 'The "Objectivity" of
Knowledge in Social Science and Social Policy', in The Essential Weber, together with 'Basic
Sociological Terms', in Weber's Economy and Society, chapter 1. But do not attempt to read the rest
of Economy and Society without having first read Weber's shorter and more accessible pieces.
Weber's dense and erudite style of writing can be difficult to read on a first attempt. For some good
secondary introductions, see Dirk Kasler's Max Weber: An Introduction to his Life and Work (Polity,
1988), Ralph Schroeder's Max Weber and the Sociology of Culture (Sage, 1992), Martin Albrow's Max
Weber's Construction of Social Theory (Macmillan, 1990), and Reinhard Bendix's Max Weber: An
Intellectual Portrait (Methuen, 1966). On the Protestant ethic, see Gianfranco Peggi's Calvinism and
theCapitalist Spirit:Max Weber's Protestant Ethic (Macmillan, 1983), Gordon Marshall's In Searcho(the
Spirit of Capitalism (Hutchinson 1982), Randall Collins's 'Weber's Last Theory of Capitalism',
reprinted in Collins's Weberian Sociological Theory (Cambridge University Press, 1986), and also
Weber's replies to early criticism of the text from 1907-10 in The Protestant Ethic Debate: Max
Weber's Replies to his Critics, 1907-1910 ed. David Chalcraft and Austin Harrington (Liverpool
University Press, 2001). For Weber's ideas in relation to politics and power, see David Beetham's Max
Weber and the Theory of Modem Politics (Allen & Unwin, 1974) and Wolfgang Mommsen's The Age of
Bureaucracy (Blackwell, 1974) and Max Weber and German Politics, 1890-1920 (Chicago University
Press, 1984). For an overview of Weber's methodology, see Sven Eliaeson's Max Weber's
Methodologies (Polity Press, 2002). For Weber's relation to Marx, see Karl Lowith's Max Weber and
Karl Marx (Allen & Unwin, 1982). For Weber's relation to 'cultural pessimism', see Lawrence Scaff's
Fleeing the iron Cage (University of California Press, 1989), Arthur Mitzman's The Tron Cage: An
Historical Interpretation of Weber (Knopf, 1970), and Roger Brubaker's The Limits of Rationality
(Allen & Unwin, 1984).
86
Accessible collections of essays and extracts from Simmel in English are Simmel on Culture,
ed. Mike Featherstone and David Frisby (Sage, 1997), Conflict and the Web of Group Affiliations, ed.
Kurt Wolff and Reinhard Rendix (Free Press, 1955), and Georg Simmel on Individuality and Social
Forms, ed. Donald Levine (Chicago University Press, 1971). ltis worth beginning with Simmers
essay 'The Metropolis and Mental Life', in Simmel on Culture. In Simmel's The Philosophy of Money
one of the most interesting chapters is the last, titled 'The Style of Life'. Simmel's 1908 Soziologie is
available in abridged form in English as The Sociology of Georg Simmel, ed. Kurt Wolff (Free Press,
1950). Also important is Simmel's essay at the beginning of the 1908 Soziologie, titled 'How ls
Society Possible?', available in English in Georg Simmel, 1858-1918, eel. Kurt Wolff (Ohio State
University Press, 1959). For Simmel's writings on women, see Chapter 11 of this book, p. 236, as
well as Georg Simmel on Women, Sexuality and Love, ed. Guy Oakes (Yale University Press, 1984).
Some good secondary studies of Simmel are David Frisby's short Georg Simmel (Routledge, rev.
edn. 2002) and longer Sociological Impressionism: A Reappraisal of Georg Simmel's Social Theory
(Routledge, 1981) and hisFragments ofModemity (Polity Press, 1985). Also good are Gianfranco
Poggi'sMoneyand the Modem Mind (University of California Press, 1993), Donald Levine's Simmel
and Parsons (Arno Press, 1980), and Lewis Coser's Georg Simmel (Prentice-Hall, 1965). On Simmel
on art, see 'Georg Simmel: Money, Style and Sociability', in Austin Harrington's Art and Social
Theory: Sociological Arguments in Aesthetics (Polity Press,-2004), 150-4.
WEBSITES
This chapter discusses the legacy of *functionalism in modern social theory. Functionalist
theorists argue that society should be understood as a system of interdependent parts. They
believe that there are specific requirements-functional prerequisites-that must be met in
all social systems and that these can provide the basis for the comparative analysis of
social institutions. Functionalism came to prominence in North American sociology in
the 1950s. This was a period of affluence, consolidation, and growth in Western
capitalism. At the time, several commentators-including notably Daniel *Bell-believed
that the pros perous post-war years marked an 'end of ideology' (Bell 1962). By this they
meant that the once defining conflict of nineteenth-century capitalism-between a
bourgeois ideology of radical 'individualism' and a socialist ideology of 'collectivism'-had
lost its relevance. The North American functionalist theorists affirmed this view of the
obsolescence of
88 JOHN HOLMWOOD
ideological struggles between classes and collective social movements.They were frequently
liberal in their political outlook, and the ideas of Marxism, which continued to exert a
significant impact on sociology in Europe, played little role in their work.
This was the context in which Talcott *Parsons and Robert *Merton came to
prominence. Parsons and Merton sought to distinguish sociology from other disciplines,
such as economics and psychology, and to celebrate its relevance to the new social
problems of affluent capitalism. For Parsons (1949a), the 'end of ideology' heralded a 'new
age of sociology'. Parsons's claim was far-reaching in its implications. He argued that
sociology was entering a 'post-classical' phase (Parsons 1937). Functionalism could
provide a frame work that would integrate the insights of *Durkheim and *Weber but
would otherwise draw a line under sociology's past in creating the foundations for future
development.
In this chapter, we first consider the origins of functionalist thinking in anthropological
research from the early decades of the twentieth century. Then we look in detail at the
key contributions of Merton and Parsons. The final parts of the chapter discuss
various criticisms of functionalism, associated with rational actor approaches and with
what came to be called 'conflict theory'.
Functionalism in anthropology
Although functionalism mainly came to prominence as a school in the 1950s, its origins
can be traced to an earlier generation of writers working in the field of anthropology.
These included notably the British-based anthropologists Bronislaw *Malinowski and
Alfred
*Radcliffe-Brown. Elements of a functionalist way of thinking can also be traced to the work
of Durkheim.
A central methodological precept of the early twentieth-century anthropologists
was that social actions are not to be explained by the immediate meanings they have
for indi vidual actors. They are to be explained by the function they serve for wider social
groups. On this view, meanings for individual actors cannot be understood
independently of a wider system of collective practices and beliefs within which they are
embedded. These collective practices are to be explained in tui:n by the functions they
serve for the system of social life as a whole. Different elements of social life depend on
each other and fulfil functions that contribute to the maintenance of social order and its
reproduction over time.
We can illustrate this mode of analysis by looking at a typical piece of explanation
in functionalist anthropology. For many years, anthropologists had observed how the
Hopi tribe of North America engage in a complex series of rituals and dances prior to
the planting of their crops. The Hopi were well known for their rain dances. For
anthropolo gists, it seemed clear that the Hopi dances could not be understood as
instrumental action intended directly to produce the rains. At the same time, it did not
seem right to suggest that the Hopi were behaving irrationally. The claim that they
were behaving irrationally looked suspiciously like a judgement from the perspective of
modern Western beliefs in the superiority of scientific knowledge.
The functionalist response to this puzzle was to suggest that the Hopi rain dance was not
a form of instrumental activity but rather a form of expressive activity. This expressive
tUNCTIONAUSM AND ITS CRITICS 89
activity served to reinforce the bonds of *solidarity among the group. It had the function
of generating group cohesion. Such cohesion was important because the Hopi lived in
dispersed shelters, and so the dances brought them together. In their other activities, such
as planting and harvesting their crops, the Hopi showed themselves to be competent at
organizing instrumental activities too. The Hopi rain dances were thus explained by the
function they fulfilled in the life of the tribe as a whole. The function in question was that
of the reinforcement of group solidarity.
It is a small step from this to suggest that all social relations fulfil certain functions and
that all social groups need to meet certain universal functional requirements-even if these
requirements are handled differently in different societies (compare Malinowski 1944).
Examples of such 'functional prerequisites' could include sexual reproduction, economic
subsistence, social control, socialization and education of new generations, and the
management of sickness and death, as well as 'group solidarity'.
We should note here that in a typical case of functionalist explanation, the existence of
a phenomenon or the production of an action is not explained by its direct efficient causes
but rather by its indirect effects in relation to an environment. Functionalism departs
from the traditional logic of causal argument where a cause precedes its consequences.
Functionalists instead reverse this sequence and assign causal powers to effects (see
further Isajiw 1968). Durkheim captured this distinction when he stated that 'when ... the
explanation of a social phenomenon is undertaken, we must seek separately the efficient
cause which produces it and the function it fulfills' (1895: 95). In this respect, the func
tionalist anthropologist who asks 'why do the Hope dance for rain?' looks for an answer
not in factors that immediately cause the Hopi to dance on a particular occasion. Rather,
the anthropologist considers the effects or consequences of the Hopi's dancing for all the
other elements of the Hopi's way of life, noting that these effects have a positive function
for those other elements. The functionalist concludes that if the rain dance did not have
this positive function, the dance would not be reproduced. Therefore the dance is
explained by its function, by its effects in an environment of diverse other elements of a
social system.
One problem for functionalism is that explanations of phenomena by reference to
effects in an environment can often degenerate into scientifically illegitimate kinds of
*teleology, where that which is described as the 'function' of a phenomenon is tacitly
assumed to be the 'purpose' or 'goal' of the phenomenon. The function is implicitly
described as something necessarily good, or alternatively it is imagined as marking an
end-state to which the phenomenon tends to develop over time. These were the kinds
of *metaphysical problems that infected much nineteenth-century thinking about social
evolution. Most notorious were the assumptions of writers influenced by Darwinist
notionsof 'natural selection' and the 'survival of the fittest', as applied to history and
society. For this reason, the British anthropologist Radcliffe-Brown sought to distinguish
sharply between *'diachronic' and *'synchronic' analysis: between the analysis of change
in a sys tem and the analysis of interaction among parts of a system at any given moment
in time. According to Radcliffe-Brown, the task of anthropology (and sociology) lay
primarily in synchronic analysis. Anthropology and sociology were not to make any
illicitly diachronic assumptions about the positive, beneficial, or progressive unfolding of
functional systems over time. He wrote that 'any social system, to survive, must conform
to certain conditions. If we can define adequately one of these universal conditions, i.e.
one to which all human
90
societies must conform, we have a sociological law ... [An] institution may be said to
have its general raison d'etre (sociological origin) and its particular raison d'etre (historical
origin). The first is for the sociologist or social anthropologist to discover' (Radcliffe-Brown
1952: 43). Sociology and anthropology were to aim at impartial scientific analysis of the
recurring properties of social systems. They were not, however, to speculate on the
meaning of the historical development of social systems over time.
There are some problems with functionalist explanations among early twentieth
century anthropological writers. The division between 'synchronic' and 'diachronic'
analysis is something that came to haunt functionalism. This and other problems were
directly addressed by the American sociological theorists who came to prominence in the
1950s, including particularly Robert *Merton. It is to Merton's work that we tum first.
non-literate societies show a high degree of integration, but it is illegitimate to assume this
would pertain to all societies. Moreover, it is possible that what is functional for society,
considered as a whole, does not prove functional for all individuals or for some
subgroups within the society. Conversely, what is functional for an individual or group
may not be functional for the wider society. Merton suggested that alongside the concept
of function, it was necessary to propound a concept of dysfunction, where the objective
consequences of an item are negative for some individuals or groups. For example,
inequality may have the function of motivating individuals to perform at their different
job tasks, but high degrees of inequality may give rise to the alienation of some
individuals and groups.
The second postulate of universal functionalism refers to what was a rather old debate
in anthropology concerning 'survivals'; that is, practices that have no present role but
are understood in terms of the past history of a group. This was used by some
anthropologists to construct highly speculative evolutionary histories. Merton argues that
if we accept that there are degrees of integration, then practices can 'survive' if they are
functional for some individuals or groups, most typically for those groups who are
dominant in the social sys tem. This identifies power and coercion as important issues.
Merton writes: 'far more useful as a directive for research would seem the provisional
assumption that persisting cultural forms have a net balance of functional consequences
either for society considered as a unit or for subgroups sufficiently to retain these forms
intact, by means of direct coercion or indir ect persuasion,' (Merton 1949b: 86).
Merton's final postulate of indispensability was directed as a criticism of Malinowski's
view that every item fulfils a vital function and represents an indispensable part within a
working whole. Merton comments that such an assumption makes unclear whether it is
the function that is indispensable or the particular item held to be fulfilling the function.
Merton argued that once this is clarified, it is evident that it is necessary to distinguish
between functional prerequisites-preconditions functionally necessary for a society-and
the particular social forms that fulfil those prerequisites. In Merton's view, while the pre
requisites are for the most part indispensable, the particular forms or items that meet those
functions are not indispensable. There are always alternative ways of meeting any
particular function. Thus Merton points out that 'just as the same item may have multiple
functions, so may the same function be diversely fulfilled by alternative items' (Merton
1949b: 87-8). Each of Merton's qualificationsof anthropological functionalism is designed
to transform the postulates into *variables that can be the objects of empirical research.
Furthermore, by identifying the possibility of dysfunction and by suggesting that practices
can have differ ent consequences for individuals and groups, depending on how they are
placed within a social structure, Merton explicitly made power and conflict central
issues for research within a functionalist paradigm. This is in line with another of
Merton's ideas about how sociological theory should be built. He reiterated that theory
and research belong together and that topics should be carefully chosen for lying in what
he called a *'middle range' between minor working hypotheses of routine research and
all-inclusive *'grand theory'
(Merton 1949c).
One problem with Merton's essay, however, was its terminology. Merton's reference to
both 'latent functions' and 'manifest functions' was unfortunate since his actual concern
was to distinguish only between latent functions and manifest motives. His terminology
92 JOHN HOLMWOOD
encouraged critics to think that sociological functionalism neglected agency, just when
agency was being identified as a central concern in American sociology. At the same
time, Merton's proposed codification of social enquiry in terms of an analytical distinction
between 'subjective motive' and 'objective function' was also the solution that Parsons had
proposed. The further elaboration of Merton's critique of anthropological functionalism
led him directly onto terrain occupied by Parsons concerning the relationship between
actors' intentions and the objective consequences of their actions. It was this that took
functionalism in the direction of all-inclusive 'grand' or *'unified' theory and away from
the 'middle range'. Thus what in fact came to be identified as functionalism in American
sociology did not develop in the way proposed by Merton. Instead it developed as a single
all-embracing theoretical system, as set out by Talcott *Parsons. It is to Parsons's general
theory that we now tum.
In 1927 Parsons took up a position at Harvard University where he would remain for the
rest of his career until his death in 1979. Commentators commonly identify three phases
in the development of his work: an early, a middle and a late phase. In the early phase,
begin ning in the 1930s, Parsons sought to develop a rigorous theory of the nature and
structure of social action. In the middle phase, from the 1940s and 1950s, he was
concerned with the structure and functioning of social systems. In the later phase, he was
more concerned to set out processes of structural differentiation and a typology of
different stages of social development. However, the core assumptions of his approach
remain throughout.
Almost from the outset, Parsons's intention was to produce a scheme of general
categories that would form the necessary foundation for social-scientific enquiry.
Identifying these categories was the objective of his first major work, The Structure of
Social Action (1937), a work that came to define European social theory for subsequent
generations of North American sociologists. In this book, Parsons described how the
classical generation of European social theorists active in the years 1890-1920 had
brought about a decisive break with the past. The most important thinkers he addressed
were Weber and Durkheim, but he also wrote extensively on the English economist
Alfred *Marshall and the Italian theo rist Vilfredo *Pareto. He did not consider it
necessary to treat Marx because he believed that Marx belonged to a redundant stage of
social thought whose insights had essentially been recuperated in the best way possible by
Weber. Parsons argued that while no single one of these theorists presented all the
elements of an appropriate general scheme, taken together they provided an early
intimation of the functionalist synthesis of sociological theory, which Parsons would
present as the basis of professional sociology. Parsons continued to develop and refine the
scheme in all his subsequent writings. He was, in the words of the Preface to his middle-
period treatise The Social System (1951), 'an incurable theorist'.
We begin with the following account with Parsons's analysis of action in The Structure
of Social Action, before turning to his later more elaborate conceptions of social structures,
functions, and systems.
r rw ITS CF.ITICS 93
This further generalization of the scheme is linked to what Parsons sees as emergent
properties of systems of action. These are properties that arise in the coordination of
actions and are not reducible to analysis in terms of unit acts alone. Here Parsons espouses
a key methodological position which marks his explicit attachment to methodological
*ho/ism, rather than to methodological individualism. He writes that 'action systems have
propert ies that are emergent only on a certain level of complexity in the relations of unit
acts to each other. These properties cannot be identified in any single unit act considered
apart from its relation to others in the same system. They cannot be derived by a_process
of direct generalisation of the properties of the unit act' (1937: 739). The concept of
emergent prop erties serves to identify the 'elements of structure of a generalised system of
action' (1937: 718), and these elements of structure are to be further analysed in terms of
their functional relations; that is, in terms of the logical relations established in the
theoretical system. This is what underlies Parsons's use of the analogy of an organism:
'the very definition of an organic whole is one within which the relations determine the
properties of its parts. The properties of the whole are not simply a resultant of the latter'
(1937: 32). It can be seen here that Parsons was very much preoccupied with the idea of
systems of action in his early work, no less than in his later work in which he comes to
use the word 'system' more and more frequently.
The idea of emergent properties of systems of social action is at the heart of what
Parsons refers to as the 'problem of order'. Parsons here refers to the thought of the
seventeenth century English political philosopher Thomas *Hobbes, author of Leviathan
(1651), written in the context of the English Civil War of the 1640s-1650s. Hobbes had
sought to answer the question of how it is possible that a society of self-interested
individuals does not end up in a state of 'war of all against all', which Hobbes also
described as the *'state of nature'. Hobbes's answer was to postulate an external
authority-the sovereign-to whom the power to enforce agreement is voluntarily given.
For Parsons, this answer was too bleak and too directly focused on coercive power.
Hobbes's mechanistic idea of the human animal neglected the *normative regulation of
social relationships through aspects of cultural communication. Parsons did not intend to
make the opposite kind of mistake by neglecting power. He acknowledged that
sometimes social relationships do indeed descend into a war of all against all. Just as the
English Civil War impressed itself on Hobbes, so Parsons was concerned with the rise of
fascism in Europe and its terrible consequences (1942a, 1942b). But in his approach to
such cases of disorder, he wanted first to set out a few basic sociological principles
within an all-embracing theory that could account adequately for the everyday routine
phenomenon of social order, through what he called 'normative integration', or through
what is more commonly known as 'civil', 'normal', 'acceptable' social behaviour.
Parsons's way of solving this problem was to point to various mechanisms capable of
securing the coordination of action. Action occurs in systems and these systems have an
orderly character. There are two aspects of order, identified by Parsons. These are what
we can term personal order and interpersonal order. Personal order involves a recognition
that any given act is, for the actor, one among a bunch of other chosen and possible
actions with a variety of different ends and different requirements for their realization.
Interpersonal order involves a recognition that actions occur in contexts that include, as
Parsons put it, 'a plurality of actors' (1937: 51).
Where means are scarce relative to ends, any individual actor will maximize outcomes
by the most efficient selection of means and by placing his or her ends in a personal
hierarchy of preferences. The ends of actors are determined by their preferences and values,
but actors' cognitive reflection on the means to their ends is also governed by what
Parsons terms a 'normative standard', namely a 'norm of efficiency'. In this regard, one of
the most signific ant emergent properties of personal order is 'economic rationality' (1937:
288 ff.). As Parsons put it, 'economic rationality is thus an emergent property of action
which can be observed only when a plurality of unit acts is treated together as constituting
an integrated system' (1937: 40).
Fundamental issues of social theory arise for Parsons when systems of social action
involving multiple actors are the focus. These are the issues of interpersonal order. It is
here that Parsons confronts, directly the Hobbesian problem of social order. Interpersonal
order concerns the coordination of systems of action where these systems include the
activities of a number of actors. The actions of any given actor form the conditions
and means of other actors in the system. Just as there is an interdependence of acts
within the means-end chains of an actor's system of personal order, so there is an
interdependence of acts and means-end chains among the interactions of a plurality of
actors.
resources within the system, and therefore the actions by which those resources are pro
duced and reproduced, must be governed by some legitimizing principles or norms.
The fact that most people, generally, most of the time, do not freak out, commit murder
or rape in the streets, cannot simply be attributed to the fact that if they were to do so, they
would be punished with physical force by representatives of a system of state laws.
Individuals internalize the threat of physical punishment for deeds they ought not do.
Sanctions restrain individuals from carrying out such acts before they even contemplate
them. But individuals are restrained from so acting not simply by sublimated fear of the
consequences. Rather, they come to develop a sense of the intrinsic normative
illegitimacy of such acts, based on an understanding that such acts are 'wrong' or 'evil',
'indecent' or 'distasteful', and so on, in an ethically significant sense. It is in this manner
that Parsons by a similar route to Durkheim-arrives at a sociological understanding of our
ideas of morality and civilization. What is called 'moral', 'civil', or 'lawful' behaviour in
ordinary laypeople's language is explained sociologically by reference to processes of
socialization that involve a fusion between elements of coercion on the one hand and
elements of common value understandings on the other.
As Parsons developed this theory-chiefly in The Social System (1951) and after-he went
on to offer further distinctions between different levels of analysis. He distinguished
between the level of the personality, the level of the social system, and the level of culture
(later adding a fourth level of the 'biological organism'). These levels correspond to the
analytical distinctions made in his earlier statement of the action frame of reference.
• The level of the personality corresponds to the individual actor viewed as a system.
As well as conscious motivations, it includes unconscious motivations or what Parsons
calls 'need dispositions'. The latter are important for understanding how sanctions
operate. Actors respond not only to positive rewards, as economists suggest, but also to
internalized feelings of guilt, anxiety, and the need for approval.
• The level of culture refers to symbols and meanings that are drawn upon by actors in
pursuit of their personal projects and in their negotiation of social constraints and
facilities.The three key features of the cultural system are 'that culture is transmitted, it
con stitutes a heritage or a social tradition; secondly, that it is learned, it is not a
manifestation, in particular content, of man's genetic constitution; and thirdly, that it is
shared. Culture, that is, is on the one hand the product of, on the other hand a determinant
of, systems of human social interaction' (1951: 15).
• The level of the social system corresponds to the level of interaction among a
plurality of actors which was Parsons's primary focus concerning the 'problem of order' in
The Structure of Social Action. The social system is a structure of positions and roles
organized by normed expectations and maintained by sanctions.
Parsons proposes that each of the three levels forms a system in its own right, where the
characteristic of a system is logical coherence in the relations among its parts. At the same
time, each system functions in relation to other systems and *'interpenetrates' with them.
And in turn, this 'interpenetration', or interdependence, also constitutes a system. This is
what Parsons had previously referred to as the 'total action system'. In his middle-period
work, Parsons sees the total social system as having four basic functional prerequisites
FUNCTlorrnusiv: ANDIT'" CRITICS 97
which are necessary to its constitution and operation. Parsons describes these in the
following four-part scheme, which he terms the AGIL scheme:
• The first prerequisite is adaptation (A). This refers to the relationship of a system to
its external environments and the utilization of resources in pursuit of goals.
• The second prerequisite is goal attainment (G). This refers to the directedness of
systems toward collective goals.
• The third prerequisite is integration (I). This refers to the maintenance of
coordinated relationships among the parts of the system.
• The fourth prerequisite is pattern maintenance or latency (L). This refers to a society's
symbolic order as a generalized series of mutually reinforcing meanings and typifications.
Once again, Parsons does not argue here that actual, empirically existing social systems
manifest integration and interdependence in the way described in the analytical theory.
The functional imperatives only identify general tendencies generated by concrete sys
tems, namely tendencies toward integration and interdependence-although these ten
dencies are never fully realized in actual empirical systems. The functional imperatives
supply the axes of the two-by-two tables that proliferate throughout Parsons's later writ
ings. Figure 4.1, taken from Parsons's late text titled Social Systems and the Evolution of
Action Theory (1977a), presents his idea of the subdivisions of the social system, defined
by prior ities accorded to one or other of the functional prerequisites in its organization.
Structural differentiation
A final key element in Parsons's functionalist theory is his conception of 'structural differenti
ation', which is entailed by the fourfold AGIL scheme of functions. In this conception,
A -----RESOURCE------+ G
ADAPTIVE SUBSYSTEM MOBILIZATION .
(the economy) ------SYSTEM------
L
+LOYALTY -----SOLIDARITY------------.
PATTERN-MAINTENANCE ----- COMMITMENT----- l ITEGRATIVE SUBSYSTEM
(locus of cultural and ------SYSTEM-------------. (Law [as norms] and
motivational commitments) social control)
(fiduciary system) (societal community)
persed across institutions. With the rise of processes of industrialization, economic needs were met by
paid employment that took place outside the family household. Authority was mediated through politi
cal institutions where office holders were elected or chosen on ment. It seemed that the functions of
the family were very much reduced to those of the regulation of sexuality and the socialization of
children. In Western society since the nineteenth century, the form of the family was changing, becoming
much more focused on the nuclear family-the nexus of father, mother, and their children-with fewer
obligations to extended kin (Parsons 1949b, 1949c, 1956, 1977a).
When Parsons first turned his attention to the sociology of the family in the 1940s, there was something
of a moral panic about the family in American society. Commentators had seized upon a rising divorce
rate and a falling birth-rate to suggest that the family was in crisis, deriving in part from its loss of func
tions. Perhaps unsurprisingly, Parsons concluded that the problems had to do only with transition,
and were not fundamental. The functions of the family were fewer but they were no less important.
Divorce rates had increased but they were stabilizing, and rates of remarriage remained high,
indicating that marriage continued to play a meaningful role at the centre of people's lives.
As Parsons developed his arguments about the nuclear family, he was concerned to demonstrate
how its internal structure reflected its more restricted functions. He identified how male and female roles
were concentrated respectively on instrumental and expressive aspects. The male role was concerned with
the , external linkage of the family to the world of occupations and paid work, while the female role was
more associated with the rearing of children. Although housework was an instrumental task, its menial
charac ter was alleviated for women through the emotional significance with which it was invested.
According to Parsons, the family produced the human personality through child socialization. It was
therefore important that the family remained an environment on which a child could fully depend
and in which it could invest all of its emotional resources. But it was also important that the family
did not become too isolated. The family was 'a differentiated subsystem of a society, not itself a "little
society" or anything too closely approaching it' (1956: 19). Family members needed other roles
outside the family. The most important one according to Parsons was the father's occupational
role.
Alongside the socialization of children, the family also had a secondary function of stabilizing adult personalities.
The marriage pair was more concentrated when compared with extended kin relation ships. In both cases children
were important to parents insofar as they allowed for an element of acceptable 'regression' in which parents could
express 'childish' elements of their own personalities. In
this regard Parsons accepted some of the insights of psychoanalysis and sought to incorporate them in
his own theory.
Parsons's analysis of the family soon came to be criticized by feminist sociologists for its inadequate
theorization of the position of women in families. These important critiques are discussed later in this
chapter in Box 12.
100 JOHN HOI.IVIWOOO
Criticisms of functionalism:objections
and alternatives
Parsons's theory is subtle and complex, but it is certainly not without problems. In
some cases, criticisms of his work have rested on simple misunderstandings. In other
cases, they have pointed to some genuine deficiencies. Here we must bear in mind that
Parsons's critics did not always represent a unified position. Frequently they criss-crossed
between different and mutually exclusive criticisms as their own positions unfolded. We
now look at four main bodies of criticism from the late 1960s onwards. These are (1)
conflict theory, (2) Marxist criticisms, (3) rational actor or rational choice approaches, and
lastly (4) 'neo-functionalist' approaches. In Box 12 we also discuss some feminist
responses to Parsons's analysis of the family. We begin with conflict theory.
Conflict theory
For C. Wright *Mills (1956), James *Lockwood (1956), Ralf *Dahrendorf (1958), John *Rex
(1961), and Randall Collins (1975), the problem with Parsons's theory was straightforward: it
was too one-sided. Parsons's language of systems gave far too much weight to
interdepend ence and integration, neglecting independence and contradiction. It also
seemed to give greater emphasis to values and norms than to power. These 'conflict
theorists', as they came to be called, drew inspiration from Marx and Weber, to whom
Parsons had indeed failed to give proper at tcntion in The Structure of Social Action,
especially Marx. It was true that Parsons had not merely excluded Marx from the founding
sociological generation of 1890-1920 for reasons of chronology. More especially, he had
believed that Marx's writings were tied to a moment in capitalism that had been
superseded and that the German thinker's ideas had been too influenced by the ideological
formations of early capitalism to be relevant to the mid-twentieth century (Parsons
1949d). Conflict theorists did not greatly disagree with Parsons's judgement on Marx and
the superiority of Weber in this regard. Dahrendorf, Rex, and Wright Mills certainly
tended to draw more inspiration from Weber than from Marx. But they felt that Weber
owed more to Marx than Parsons had allowed for and that Parsons's attempt to synthesize
Durkheim and Weber had meant that the more conflict-oriented aspects of Weber's
writings had been lost. It was Durkheim's approach, with hb emphasis on order and social
*solidarity, that dominated Parsons's interpretation of the classics.
In his essay 'Out of Utopia' (1958), Dahrendorf disagreed with .\.1erton's implied judgement
that the problem with Parsons's scheme was that it was too generalized. The problem was
rather that Parsons was insufficiently explicit about the values that informed his approach.
For Dahrendorf, the 'consensus' model with its emphasis on synchronic analysis and on
processes tending toward integration was part of a long-standing conservaiive tradition in
social thought reaching back to *Plato. It was utopian in the sense that it rested on a model
of society in which change and conflict are wholly absent. As Dahrendorf suggested, 'it
may well be that society, in a philosophical sense, has two faces of equal reality: one of
sta bility, harmony, and consensus, and one of change, conflict and constraint. Strictly
speak ing, it does not matter whether we select for investigation problems that can be
understood only in terms of the equilibrium model or problems for which the conflict
model is required.
101
There is no intrinsic criterion for preferring one to the other' (1958: 127). The problem,
then, was that Parsons had placed consensus above conflict for no good reason. A similar
argument was put forward by Rex, who argued that while 'perfect cooperation' and
'perfect conflict' are polar theoretical cases, 'all actual cases lie somewhere along the
continuum between perfect cooperation and perfect conflict' (1961: 54). Like Dahrendorf,
Rex argued that 'Durkheim and Parsons have unduly restricted the scope of sociology to
the study of forms of perfect co-operation' (1961: 54). Dahrendorf, Rex, and Mills all
recommended that sociological attention should be redirected toward conflict.
The criticisms of the conflict theorists struck a chord. Yet their own position was unsta
ble for a number of reasons. Parsons had in fact sought to account for both power and con
sensus in his model. Therefore it was difficult to argue that the two models could be kept
entirely apart and used separately for different purposes. In Parsons's actual thinking, the
issues of conflict and cooperation, and power and legitimation, were very much inter
twined. This was Parsons's argument when he set out to synthesize positivism and
idealism in The Structure of Social Action. He repeated this in his response to the conflict
theorists (1971b: 385) and especially in his opposition to C. Wright Mills's book The
Power Elite (1956), which he saw as resting on an inadequate 'zero-sum' view of power,
where a gain in power for one group is wrongly automatically equated with a loss in
power for another group (Parsons 1967).
On the whole it can be said that the conflict theorists were more successful in pointing
out the empirical significance of conflict within systems-in terms of the power of classes
(Dahrendorf 1958) or the power of elites (Mills 1956)-than they were at finding a way of
expressing this in the general language of analytical theory. In Box 11 we consider a more
subtle extension of conflict theory in the work of David *Lockwood.
Marxist criticisms
To a large degree, the fate of conflict theory was overtaken by more radical approaches.
By the late 1960s, the USA was embroiled in the Vietnam War and opposition to it was
grow ing. Along with the anti-war movement, there was an increasingly radical movement
of civil rights for black Americans, while the women's movement and feminism waited in
the wings to emerge in the 1970s as a powerful force for change. The growth of
universities and favourable employment opportunities for sociologists were conditions
that encouraged disciplinary transformation (compare Turner and Turner 1990). A
younger generation of sociologists influenced by the new social movements promoted
radical sociologies in op position to the functionalism of their seniors. They were on the
side of dissent and change, not the side of the system and order (compare Becker 1967).
While their own sympathies lay with Weber rather than Marx, the conflict theorists had
contributed to a re-evaluation of the relation between Marxism and academic sociology.
In the changed social and political circumstances of the 1960s, many sociologists were
now open to a more explicit appropriation of Marxism. By the early 1970s, conflict
theory appeared insufficiently radical and its theoretical arguments less sophisticated than
those of Marx. It was not just that the Durkheim-Parsons axis of theorizing was called
into ques tion but that the whole generation of 1890-1920, including Weber, was seen to
represent a 'bourgeois reaction' to Marxism (Therborn 1976).
102
contradiction. Simply put. Parsons had no place for the idea that the parts of a social.system may
con tain tendencies toward mal-integrat1on--<Jr contradiction. According to Lockwood, those
tendencies may eventually come to the surface ,n the form of oppos tional interests and conflicts
among actors, and these conflicts may or may not be contained by the *normative order. Rather
than proposing two separate models, then, lockwood argued that it was necessary to cons der the
question of coopera
tion, conflict, and social change in terms of two distinct but interrelated sets of processes. One
concerned normative processes of social
integration; the other concerned material processes of system
integration. The problem was that Parsons had conflated the two types of integration and had
overemphasized the aspect of mut ality between the two corresponding sets of processes. The task for
sociologists was to be more aware of contradictions within the system and of how they were managed
at the level of social integration.
Lockwood's argument can be seen as returning to and reinforcing Merton's statement of
funaionalism. Merton had argued for the importance of recognizing the role of 'dysfunctions', which
is similar to what Lockwood meant by problems of 'system integration'. At the same time, while 1t 1s
apparent that the idea of 'function' lends itself to general expression, it is not clear that the same is true
of 'dysfunc- , tion' or contradiction. Dysfunctions and contradictions seem to be specific to particular
cases, rather than to have a general form. If this is so, Lockwood's argument, properly understood,
would reinforce Merton's turn away from general theory towards middle-range theory. Indeed, when he
returned to the
themes of his earlier article in a book-length discussion of Marx and Durkheim and the 'problem of dis
order', Lockwood (1992) declared himself to be uncomfortable with the way in which such
discussions tended to conclude with a new general framework of social theory, rather than with
specific pro grammes of substantive research.
Parsons himself suspected that his functionalist analyses of women, work, and the family were
oversimplified. For example, he was aware that many women were in paid employment, although
he correctly observed that the tendency was for women to be found in jobs that mirrored their family
roles and for competition for jobs between men and women to be restricted. 'In general,' he
observed, 'the woman's job tends to be of a qualitatively different type and not of a status which
seriously competes with that of her husband as the primary status-giver or income earner' (1956: 14).
Nonetheless, he was rather insensitive to the asymmetry between men and women, where men
were enjoyed a primarily public role and women were restricted to dependency in the domestic
sphere.
In the period of the emergence of second-wave feminism 1n the 1960s, several feminist writers began to
point to the changed fertility conditions that meant that a large part of women's lives would be spent
with out dependent children in the household. This would involve new social problems, including
female poverty on divorce or in old age, given increasing female longevity (Myrdal and Klein 1956).
Parsons had written that the fact that 'the normal married woman is debarred from testing or
demonstrating her fun damental equality with her husband in competitive occupational achievement
creates a demand for a
*functional equivalent' (1949e: 193). Parsons had accepted that housework was a relatively menial task,
suggesting that women might instead develop specialized interests in matters of taste relating to personal
appearance, furnishing, and the like-although he acknowledged that these could frequently be ex
pressed as neuroses. Once again, this was something that feminists also came to argue, but in a much more
radical way, notably in the influential book by Betty *Friedan The Feminine Mystique (1963). Increasingly,
feminists were to identify such 'dysfunctions' in a more systematic and rigorous way. Much like the conflict
theorists, they would see functionalism as an obstacle rather than a means to a fruitful understanding
of the family. They pointed out that dependency within the family was increasingly a reflection of
power relationships, and that far from being a place that stabilized adult personalities, the family was
frequently a site of violence and abuse. Women were tied to unsatisfactory relationships precisely because
the gender segregation of employment and lower pay for women meant that they were economically
dependent.
Some feminists have suggested that Parsons was correct 1n his description of the nature of the
family household and its relation to the occupational sphere (Johnson 1989). However, there is no
doubt that he lacked a feminist sensibility and that the weight of his analysis was to emphasize the
positive functions for society of the nuclear family, rather than its dysfunctions for women (see Barrett
1980). Yet it should be acknowledged that Parsons was one of the first male sociologists to write of the
close interconnections between age, sex, family, and social *stratification. The more usual
response by male sociologists even those of a radical persuasion-was to concentrate on the class
relationships of the occupational sphere and to regard the household and gender as secondary
matters For a more detailed overview of feminist interventions in social theory, see Chapter 11 of
this book.
104 JOHl\i HOLf;IIWOOO
of en concerned with explaining individual behavior' (1991: lJ. for this reason, while he
iH r !·r;tr·rJ I hdt < r JJl(_fl"\f ,r J( Jdl w,ttm, dfl' Wfldl '-,( ,, 11,Jr ,g1 '-,1', \\ilfl t tr J r·xplilll J, ( .( ,l,·111,lJI
argU(·d that it 1s rational actor thinking that offers the best building birAks with which to
wmtru<.t ilrl r·xr,lar1atr,r: th<:r,ry that J'-, dJru tly ,upp(Jrt,-rl l;y f'fllJJlfl( al (·VJd<•IJ( (•. J-r,r
(•Xilfnplr·, vvh1l<· trust may be important in maintaining stable S0cial relationships, it is
vulnerable to actors defaulting on it. Coleman therefore argued that rather than
comtructing an analytical th• Jr:: th2it rn;;h:, tru,t d u:11trdl prl·,upp<,,1t1r,n 1,f v,c Jal r,rdc·r, JI
'MJ1Jld lw lwttl'r 1,, c·xMnim· the different empirical circumstances that serve to sustain or
undermine trust. This will be f:i· Jlitat<:d IJ: th<: u,,: ,,f mr,dr:1'> dl·,uJIJing clilr·mma, faC/:d IJy
rdti<,nal act<,r-, in IJ<:havmg altruistically when confronted with the possibility that other
actors may 'free-ride'; that is, fail to live up to an expectation or take self-interested
advantage of the altruism of others.
Over the years, the debate between functionalists and rational choice theory has been
continuous (see further Turk and Simpson 1971, Coleman and Fararo 1991). Although there
21r<· c,tr,,ng ad\'/Jlat<:, ,,f ratirmal act<,r appr,,adJc,, many ,,,u,,lr,g1,h frncl thr:,l· apprr,achr:,
'Neo-functionalism'
'fo;o of the strands of criticism directed at Parsons lead back to his starting place. Conflict
th..,,r;, ,r:t ,Jut;:, duali',tJl appr<Mch tr, ,r,cir,I/Jg1cal pr<,bl<:m<,, whuc f'arvm, had v,ught tr,
,:;ntr1c,i1:r: th•· dui.tli·,m, mr:<Jiating br:twr:cn pr;,itivi,m and idcali'>m and between pr,wu
anri u,n,<:n'>U'>. I r,r Jt, part, ratir,nal ilel'Jf t h("<,ry pr<,m<Jtt:cJ thr: utili tariiln schtmc: <Jf
il<.tirm a', the miur,Jr,girill fr,unrfatir,n fr,r iJ ,u<:ntific VJ(irJ]rJgy, which /'ar,rm, had alrtady
uiti c.iz,,rl in The Structure: of Social Action. Yt:t many uJtJc, dirJ n1,t rt:uJgnizr: this a,
/'arson,\
,;•sn ,ta rt in g pr,i n t. f h 1:y u <,Ua I ly v1r:wr:rJ v ,c irJI ,,gi Cil I fun Ui r;nal1,rn a, a pr;,i ti vi ,tic.
,y,tr:m, apprrJar.h that nr:gl<:ctuJ ar.tJrJfl. /Int hrmy '( 1iddr:m\ uitichm h typical: 'thtrt i,
nrJ actirm rn l'a!V;W,' "ac tir,n fram,'. rJf rdur:nu:", ,,nJy hr:havi<;ur which i'> prr,pr:llcd by
n<:c:d rJi,pr,,J
tir,n,, r,r r<,I<: txpr:ctatirm, .....'vlcn d<, nr,t appr:ar Jn [l'arsrm,\ writin ,j a, skill<:d and
knr;·1;J,:dgcc1hh· agf:nh, a,ill l<:a,t tr, ,,Jmt: r.:xtr:nt ma'>lc·r, rJf thr:ir <JWll fat<:' 11976: 16, 7(JJ.
106 JOHN HOLMWOOO
A similar view of functionalism was taken by Jurgen *Habermas, whose work is discussed
at length in Chapters 7 and 13 of this book (pp. 164-5, 279-83). In his The Theory of
Communicative Action, Habermas (1981b) argued that social enquiry had been unhelpfully
divided between two conceptual strategies, one taking the standpoint of 'systems', which
'ties the social scientific analysis to the external perspective of the observer', the other
taking the standpoint of the *'lifeworld', which 'begins with members' intuitive know
ledge' (1981b: 151). According to Habermas, 'the fundamental problem of social theory is
how to connect in a satisfactory way the two conceptual strategies indicated by the
respect ive notions of "system" and "lifeworld" ' (1981b: 151). Habermas offers his own
theory as just such a generalized integration of categories.
Several contemporary theorists have proposed general theories as alternatives to
Parsons, arguing that their schemes avoid his problems because they incorporate
action from the start. However, it can be argued that what they propose is very similar in
conceptual structure and intention to Parsons. This can be illustrated briefly with reference
to the work ofGiddens, whose contributions are discussed in greater detail in Chapters 10
and 13 of this book (pp. 217-20, 287-9). Although Giddens argues vigorously that his
own theory of
*'structuration' has no 'functionalist overtones at all' and has declared that it would be
helpful to 'ban' the term altogether (1981: 16, 19), he proposes certain universal 'structural
features' that are remarkably similar to those of Parsons. Giddens identifies four basic
struc tural principles, with similar points of reference to Parsons's four functional
imperatives. Giddens calls them 'signification', *'legitimation', 'authorisation',and
'allocation'. He argues further that two aspects of these principles can be identified as
follows: 'one is how far a society contains distinct spheres of "specialism" in respect of
institutional orders: differentiated forms of symbolic order (religion, science, etc); a
differentiated "polity", "economy" and "legal/repressive apparatus". The second is how
modes of institutional articulation are organised in terms of overall properties of societal
reproduction: that is to say "structural principles" '(1981: 47-8). This is very similar to
Parsons's AGIL scheme.
A common pattern in contemporary discussion is that each critic of functionalism is
careful to distance hisor her position from that of Parsons, but has little difficulty in
accusing others of converging with his scheme (see further Holmwood and Stewart 1991;
Holmwood 1996). Thus Giddens (1982: 158-9) accuses Habermas of converging with
Parsons, while Archer (1988: 87) offers the same criticism of Giddens.Jeffrey*Alexander
(1988) takes these convergences as indications of a 'new theoretical movement' back to
functionalism, which he calls 'neo-functionalism'. In the 1980s Alexander set himself
the self-conscious task of reviving functionalism through the project of a four-volume
rewriting of Parsons's The Structure of Social Action, each volume devoted respectively to
nineteenth-century positivism, Marx and Durkheim, Weber, and Parsons (Alexander
1982a, 1982b, 1983, 1984). According to Alexander, Parsons's approach was deficient in
its detail but correct in its fundamentals. Current social theory is converging on a
reinvigorated functionalist paradigm that recognizes action alongside function (Alexander
1985, 1998; Colomy 1990; Munch 1987). Alexander argues that Merton's middle-range
approach is insufficiently ambitious. What is required is a revised exercise in unified
general theory.
Yet one may reasonably question whether neo-functionalism is anything more than
a restatement of the standard approach which retains its problems. From Parsons's
perspective, if empirical circumstances are less than fully integrated, this implies that there
107
must be relevant factors that operate in addition to those represented within the
general theoretical statement. For Habermas, Giddens, Alexander, and Margaret Archer,
such fac tors are assigned to actors, thought of as acting concretely, while the
structural-system point of view is bracketed or taken as a given. This is what is promoted
by Alexander when he defends neo-functionalist analysis against the older
functionalist paradigm's overex tension of the concept of system. Alexander writes
that functional analysis 'is concerned with integration as a possibility and with deviance
and processes of social control as facts. Equilibrium is taken as a reference point for
functional systems analysis, though not for participants in actual social systems as such'
(1985: 9). Yet despite Alexander's claim for a fully integrated theoretical statement, it can
be argued that his project rests on an unsatis factory unreconciled dualism between
grand theory construction on the one hand and empirical data input on the other hand.
Conclusion
There is some validity in Kingsley Davis's (1959) assertion that functionalism is integral
to sociology. The concepts, issues, and problems of functionalism are not easily avoided.
Simple oppositions between functionalist and action approaches are inadequate because
the most elaborate and extended forms of functionalist argument are themselves based on
a highly developed concept of action. In the case of Parsons, they incorporate the very
action assumptions that are often taken to express an opposition to functionalism. This is
why Parsons's writings have retained lasting significance, no matter how difficult they
may be to read. Taken as a whole, they contain one of the most sophisticated statements
of problems that have beset sociological enquiry since the earliest days.
While the project of general theory remains attractive to some sociologists, there can be
no doubt that it has been increasingly singled out for criticism. For some *postmodernist
commentators, it is an example of inappropriate 'grand narrative' (for further discussion of
this theme, see Chapter 12 of this book). For some feminist writers, it is an expression of a
masculine taste for abstraction. In light of this, other sociologists have been attracted by
the promise of rational actor theory to provide a science of society capable of reuniting
theory and research. Where conflict theorists argued that functionalism overemphasizes
consensus and social order, neglecting conflict and power, rational actor theorists argue
that functionalism overemphasizes systems and neglects individual actors. The rational
actor theorists argue that there is no such thing as a social system, that only individual
actors interact with each other, and that the motives and calculations of individuals can
and should be taken as the building blocks of general social theory.
Yet the rational actor theorists' ambition to produce a deductive system of interlocking
laws and propositions-after the fashion of Homans and Coleman-seems almost as
unlikely to win general support as Parsons's original ambition in unified functionalist the
ory. In all of the approaches that have followed in the wake of functionalism, what seems
to be missing is some evidence of direct integration between theory and empirical
research. Parsons's own contribution was directed toward establishing sociology as a
collective collaborative enterprise. Yet in retrospect, it seems that Parsons probably did
more than
108 JOHN HOLMWOOD
anyone else to establish theory as an activity for autonomous 'grand theorists', separated
from immediate empirical research programmes. This has certainly not helped to improve
the poor public image of 'theory', in contrast to 'research' which tends to be seen as some
thing more open to new findings. In the early 1960s, the arguments of Merton and
Lockwood were seen as being insufficiently ambitious in their aspirations and too much
preoccupied with discrete empirical issues. Today, however, it can be argued that the most
I ikely context in which functionalism might flourish again is not as an all-embracing the
oretical scheme but as an empirically grounded enterprise directed at specific explanatory
problems.
What are the advantages of explaining social life in terms of systems and functions?
3 What is 'social order'? How satisfactory is the functionalist explanation of social order?
5 Does rational actor theory provide a better basis for sociological explanation than functionalism?
FURTHER READING
Talcott Parsons's writings are numerous. Particularly important to read are his first book
The Structure of Social Action (McGraw-Hill, 1937) and his middle-period work The Social
System (Free Press, 1951). But these will be difficult to approach without first reading some
of the secondary guides. Useful introductions and studies are Peter Hamilton's short Talcott
Parsons (Tavistock, 1983), Neil Smelser and A. J. Trevino's edited Talcott Parsons Today:
His Theory and Legacy in Contemporary Sociology (Rowman & Littlefield, 2001), Uta
Gerhardt's Talcott Parsons (Cambridge University Press, 2003), Guy Rocher's Talcott Parsons
and American Sociology (Nelson, 1972), Jonathan H. Turner and Alexandra Maryanski's
Functionulism (Benjamin Cummings, 1979), and John Holmwood's Founding Sociology?
Talcott Parsons and the Idea of General Theory (Longman, 1996), which considers conver
gences between Parsons and the more recent work of Anthony Giddens, Jeffrey Alexander,
and Jurgen Habermas from a critical perspective. A study of the politics of functionalism is
W. F. Buxton's Talcott Parsons and the Capitalist Nation State: Political Sociology as a Strategic
Vocation (University of Toronto Press, 1985). Other notable studies include Jeffrey
Alexander's Theoretical Lo:,:ic i11 Sociolog}', iv: Tl,e Modern Reco11struaio11 of Classical Thought:
Talcott Parsons (University of California Press, 1984), Donald Levine's Simmel and Parsons
(Arno Press, 1980), Bernard Barber and Uta Gerhardt's Agenda for Sociology: Classic
Sources and Current Uses of Parsons's Work (Nomos, 1999), Thomas Fararo's Social Action
Systems:
FUNCTIONALISM AND rrs (RITICS 109
• WEBSITES
structures, the writers to be discussed in this chapter are more interested in the
micrological elements of meaning, action, and interaction.
Simmel and Weber drew on a nineteenth-centuryline of discussion which moved from a
concern with the interpretation of literary texts to a rethinking of the foundations of
history, economics, psychology, and the other human sciences. Wilhelm *Dilthey and
other German historical philosophers developed what we would now call a research pro
gramme for history and the other human sciences based on the distinctiveness of
human psychic expressions and the under<;tanding of those expressions. In a move which
was to become a definitional feature of later interpretive social theory, Dilthey
emphasized the continuity between everyday understanding and more formal processes of
interpretation. His distinction between the natural sciences and the human sciences
was developed in large part in opposition to Auguste *Comte's *positivism. In a
parallel formulation, two German *Neo-Kantian philosophers, Wilhelm *Windelband
and Heinrich *Rickert, ar gued that the study of culture is essentially concerned with
individual and unique or 'one off' processes. The cultural sciences relate these processes to
shared human values, whereas the natural sciences are concerned with general laws
about objects which are essentially remote from questions of value. We are interested,
for example, in the French Revolution not just as a member of a class of revolutions
exhibiting certain common features-this would be, for Rickert, a natural-scientific
mode of approaching it-but as a unique event, emhodying, and perhaps also violating,
certain crucial human values. Rickert in particular was a major influence on Max Weber.
At the time of Weber's death in 1920, the main intellectual elements of interpretive so
cial thought and the styles of research corresponding to it were already in place. Simmel
and Weber had taken theories of 'understanding'-still often referred to by the German
word *verstehen-out of the philosophy of history, philology, and Biblical *hermeneutics
and had put them at the centre of the relatively new discipline of sociology.
On the other side of the fence, in opposition to hermeneutical and idealist thinking,
there was now a more aggressive variant of posithism. This was the logical *empiricism
or 'logical
*positivism' of the *Vienna Circle, in whose 'unified science' the statements of all
sciences were seen as reducible to material-object language or to statements in physics.
According to one member of the Vienna Circle, Otto *Neurath, verstehen was of no more
importance than 'a good cup of coffee' which revives the flagging scientist (Neurath 1973).
The next sections of this chapter trace the main developments in interpretive thinking
after 1920. We begin with the work of Alfred *Schutz.
with Weber's *ideal types was not that they were insufficiently scientific but precisely
the opposite: Weber was too quick to impose them on the phenomena he described,
paying insufficient attention to their grounding in acts of typification performed
by ordinary members of society. For Schutz, the social scientist merely constructs
additional or second-order typifications based on those already carried out by ordinary
people in every day life:
The observational field of the social scientist-social reality-has a specific meaning and
relevance structure for the human beings living, acting, and thinking within it. By a series of
common-sense constructs they have pre-selected and pre-interpreted this world which they
experience as the real ity of their daily lives ... The thought objects constructed by the social
scientists, in order to grasp this social reality, have to be founded upon the thought objects
constructed by the common-sense thinking of men [sic] livingtheirdaily life within their social
world.Thus, the constructs used by the social scientist are, so to speak, constructs of the second
degree, namely constructs of the constructs made by actors on the social scene, whose behaviour
they scientist observes and tries to explain in accordance with the procedural rules of his science.
(Schutz 1962a: 59)
Schutz refers to everyday life as the *'lifeworld'. This term, like many of Schutz's
main concepts, is taken from Edmund *Husserl's phenomenological philosophy.
Phenomenology in Husserl's original sense meant an approach to knowledge which
focuses on our experience of things, bracketing out the issue of whether or not they really
exist or are optical illusions, or of what they are made of. The lifeworld in this sense
means the world of common-sense perception, before it is subjected to theoretical analysis
by sci entists. In Schutz's more informal use of phenomenological terminology, it refers to
the so cial world which we interpret and make meaningful through our 'typifications'
(Schutz and Luckmann 1973). A person comes to the door in a police uniform; we
assume he or she is a police officer and behave accordingly. We may of course be wrong
in our assump tion; the person may be a robber impersonating a police officer, or
someone going to a fancy-dress party. But the point, for Schutz, is that we make sense
of the world through what he calls our 'stock of knowledge' at hand which we do not
normally problematize. One of Schutz's most famous essays, 'The Stranger' (1962b), is
about persons finding their way around in unfamiliar surroundings and negotiating social
situations in which they are not 'at home'. We inhabit multiple social realities, based on
the nature of our knowledge of people, places, and so on. We can construct
concentric circles of people we know intimately, people we recognize or whose names
we know, people we have seen only on TV, and soon.
Schutz was not a full-time academic, and he wrote mostly essays. He was, however, very
influential, and can now be seen as an important figure linking Simmel and Weber to
more recent and radical developments in interpretive social theory. Some of the appeal of
interpretive social theory after the 1960s derived from the radical forms of political protest
in the student and 'alternative' movements. A focus on small-scale or micro-interactions in
everyday situations may have wider implications for social structural analysis. Schutz
believed that systematic theorists like Parsons could be criticized for neglecting or
denying the need for social theory to be grounded in attention to the 'subjective point
of view' (see Schutz and Parsons 1978). But Schutz himself was by no means radical in
either a
114 lill!i..UAM OUYHWAIH
Erving Goffman obtained his doctorate at Chicago with a thesis based on fieldwork
in the Scottish Shetland Islands. He remains perhaps best known for his first book, The
Presentation ofSelfin Everyday Life (1956). For Goffman, the notion of 'performing' social roles
means just that: we are 'on stage' in our everyday lives, moving between 'front stage' and
'back stage', dressing to create an impression, even if only an understated one, and
constantly
monitoring the impression we create. We are constantly engaged in 'interaction rituals' .
Sometimes, as in our homes, the stage metaphor is almost literal, as we admit visitors to
some rooms or parts of rooms and not others. On the other hand, it serves in Goffman's
presentation as a guide to a more fundamental issue. As he stresses at the end of the book,
The claim that all the world's a stage is sufficiently commonplace for readers to be familiar
with its limitations and tolerant of its presentation, knowing ... that it is not to be taken
too seriously ... This report ... is concerned with the structure of social encounters-the
structure of those entities in social life that come into being whenever persons enter one
another's immediate physical presence. The key factor in this structure is the maintenance of a
single definition of the situation, this definition having to be expressed, and this expression
sustained in the face of a multitude of potential disruptions. (Goffman 1956: 246)
INHRPRETIVISM AND INTERACTIONISM 117
In a later book, Frame Analysis (1974), Goffman shows how situations can be shaped
by a variety of alternative perspectives. We must use 'frame clues' and 'frame conventions'
to know-or rather guess-whether someone is joking or serious, blinking or winking,
polite or sarcastic, unaware of a social convention or deliberately flouting it. We are
confronted with multiple realities in the form of a choice between alternative
perspectives. And these interpretations may be self-fulfilling; to misidentify a look as rude
or hostile and to act accordingly may land you in hospital.
Goffman is often criticized for portraying a rather sad social world without sincerity or
spontaneity, where people are constantly monitoring their performances and calculating
their effects. Are all cultures as obsessed with impression management as he suggests, or
is he falsely universalizing particular features of advanced capitalist societies? The
evidence of cross-cultural studies suggests that Goffman may have been right in his
assumptions. Certainly the model of *'dramaturgical action', as he called it, should be put
alongside that of norm-directed and economically rational action as part of the repertoire
of social theory. In his book Asylums (1961), Goffman coined the term 'total institution',
placing prisons in one and the same category as hospitals, care homes, clinics, army
barracks, boarding schools, ships, and monasteries. Goffman's preoccupation with the
intensely self-contained character of 'total institutions' is movingly conveyed in the
1970s film One Flew over the
Cuckoo's Nest, starring Jack Nicholson. In Asylums Goffman writes that
A total institution may be defined as a place of residence and work where a large number of
like-situated individuals, cut off from the wider society for an appreciable period of time,
together lead an enclosed, formally administered round of life. Prisons serve as a clear example,
providing we appreciate that what is prison-like about prisons is found in institutions whose
members have broken no laws....
Every institution captures something of the time and interest of its members and provides
something of a world for them; in brief, every institution has encompassing tendencies. When
we review the different institutions in our Western society, we find some that are
encompassing to a degree discontinuously greater than the ones next in line. Their
encompassing or total character is symbolised by the barrier to social intercourse with the outside
and to departure that is often built right into the physical plant, such as locked doors, high walls,
barbed wire, cliffs, water, forests, or moors. (Goffman 1961: pp. xiii, 4-5)
everyday interaction. But where Parsons had been concerned with the conditions of
war and peace at the level of entire societies (following the seventeenth-century
English philosopher Thomas *Hobbes), Garfinkel was interested in the maintenance
of order in microcosmic interactions. Third, Garfinkel realized that the implicit rules that
guide social interaction could be identified through studying situations where they are
breached, and that he and his students could deliberately cause these rules to break
down.
Garfinkel coined the term *'ethnomethodology' to describe the study of the reasoning
processes routinely followed in everyday life. He documented these in studies of a trial
jury and other sites of 'mundane reasoning'. He noted that conversational exchanges were
marked by what linguists call 'indexicality': by the use of expressions like 'I', 'you', 'here',
and 'now', which are given meaning solely by space-time context. Elliptical expressiom
like 'the next lecture will be in the other room' can be unpacked by listeners with the
necessary background knowledge to mean: 'the next lecture in this series will be in the
second of the two lecture theatres which we are using this semester'. Forcing people to
spell out what they mean by shorthand references of this kind is perceived as irritating and
rude. One of Garfinkel's experiments involved asking people what they meant when they
asked 'How are you?', and offering an unexpectedly detailed response. In another
experiment, which demonstrates how we try to produce order and meaning in puzzling
situations, a researcher posing as a counsellor gave a random succession of 'yes' or 'no'
responses to the victim's requests for advice, leading him or her into more and more
contorted attempts to recon struct the logic of the 'counsellor's' replies. Garfinkel draws
the theoretical conclusion:
In accounting for the stable features of everyday activities, sociologists commonly select
familiar settings such as familial µouseholds or workplaces and ask for the variables that contribute
to their stable features.Just as commonly, one set of considerations are unexamined: the socially
standard ized and standardizing, 'seen but unnoticed', expected, background features of
everyday scenes. The member of society uses background expectancies as a scheme of
interpretation. With their use, actual appearances are for him recognizable and intelligible as the
appearances-of-familiar-events. Demonstrably, he is responsive to this background, while at the
same time he is at a loss to tell us specifically of what the expectancies consist. When we ask him
about them he has little or nothing to say. (Garfinkel 1967: 36)
Interpretive social theory is also represented in popular and theoretically unpretentious works such as
David *Riesman and his colleagues' enormously influential book on American society, The Lonely
Crowd
! (1950). Riesman had been a student of the critical social philosopher and psychologist Erich *Fromm.
He applied his model of social character to the history and present condition of the USA in the 1940s
and 1950s. Riesman traced the development of American character through three successive ideal
types:
By 'other-directed' Riesman did not mean 'altruistic'; and by 'inner-directed' he did not mean
'selfish'. The 'other-directed' character reflected a type of person from the affluent metropolitan
suburbs, typi cally employed in the services professions, and typically surrounded by friends and
colleagues as mem bers of loose-knit networks of sociability. The 'other-directed' person is both
more in touch with the feelings of other close associates and at the same time beset by a
loneliness, by an anxiety to appear normal and to join with the crowd.
Although the authors conducted some interviews, they relied on more informal data sources. They
declared that 'mainly ... this book is based on our experiences of living in America-the people we
have met, the jobs we have held, the movies we have seen' (1950: 5). The Lonely Crowd can be
The concept 'ideology' reflects the ... discovery ... that ruling groups can in their thinking
become so intensively interest-bound to a situation that they are simply no longer able to see certain
facts which would undermine their sense of domination ...
The concept of utopian thinking reflects the opposite discovery ... that certain oppressed
groups are intellectually so strongly interested in the destruction and transformation of a given
condition of society that they unwittingly see only those elements in the situation which tend to
negate it. (Mannheim 1929: 36)
Mannheim's work and other German approaches, including particularly the work of
Schutz, reached English-speaking audiences in the 1960s and 1970s, through the impact
of Peter Berger and Thomas Luckmann's influential book The Social Construction of
Reality of 1966. This is discussed in Box 14.
In the 1960s the two Austro-German-born authors Peter *Berger and Thomas *Luckmann argued that
the sociology of knowledge in the early twentieth century had been too concerned with formal belief
systems and political ideologies. Taking their point of departure from the phenomenological sociology of
everyday
Alfred Schutz, they argued for a reorientation of the sociology of knowledge towards
common
sense knowledge, promoting the slogan of the 'social construction of reality'. Among many
formulations, they expressed this difference between formal knowledge and everyday knowledge as the
difference between the knowledge of the criminologist and the knowledge of the criminal. The one has
a set of theoretical principles; the other has a practical know-how, born of experience, from life on the
streets.
Berger and Luckmann were explicitly relativistic in their approach, arguing that the sociology of
i knowledge should be concerned with 'whatever passes for "knowledge" in a society' (Berger and
Luckmann 1966: 15). Society in their view is both an objective and a subjective reality. As an
objective reality, society results from subjective processes of definition and conceptualization. In this
sense Berger and Luckmann reinvigorated the phenomenological tradition in sociology, linking it to
more substantial conceptions of society derived from Durkheim. They saw sociological analysis as
involving a task of har monizing two basic propositions: on the one hand. the proposition that 'society
exists only as individu als are conscious of it'; on the other hand, the proposition that 'individual
Durkheim tells us: 'The first and most fundamental rule is: Consider social facts as things.' And Weber observes:
'Both for sociology in the present sense, and for history, the object of cognition is the subjective
meaning complex of action'. These two statements are not contradictory. Society does indeed possess
objective facticity. And society is indeed built up by activity that expresses subjective meaning. And,
incidentally, Durkheim knew the latter, just as Weber knew the former. It is precisely the dual character of
society in terms of objective facticity and subjective meaning that makes its 'reality sui generis'. (Berger
and Luckmann 1966: 30)
This approach provided a strikingly new analysis of the *legitimation of belief systems and the
main tenance of 'symbolic universes'. Berger and Luckmann showed how the idea of *reif1cation
introduced by Marxist writers can be seen as involving a 'forgetting' of the socially constructed
character of reality. They affirmed that 'if the integration of an institutional order can be understood
only in terms of the "knowledge" that its members have of it, it follows that the analysis of such
"knowledge" will be essential for an analysis of the institutional order in question, (1966: 82-3).
122 WILUAM OUTl-lWAITE
of social organization and different belief systems. In his The Elementary Forms of Religious
Life of 1912, Durkheim had shown, for example, how Australian *totemic religion could
be explained by the tribal and clan organization of aboriginal societies. Representations of
the cosmos could be shown to reflect the spatial organization of settlements, which in turn
reflected their social structure. All religion was 'about something'. Religion was too
pervas ive in human societies to be simply based on illusion. It was actually the form in
which human societies celebrated themselves and their solidarity.
More fundamentally still, Durkheim suggested that sociology could resolve the
long standing dispute between *empiricists and rationalists over whether knowledge
comes just from experience or also from categories of thought pre-loaded into the
human mind. Durkheim maintained that Immanuel *Kant's conception of *a priori
categories of thought supplied by the human mind was essentially correct. But
Durkheim also main tained that these categories are themselves shaped sodally and that
they derive from sodety in a certain sense. A Durkheimian approach to knowledge and
cognition was developed further by the French structural anthropologist Claude *Levi-
Strauss, who is discussed in Chapter 9 of this book.
In more recent times, the British anthropologist Mary *Douglas studied the way in
which societies categorize the world in simple oppositions between, for example, 'clean'
and 'dirty', where dirt means 'matter out of place' (Douglas 1966). Following the
Durkheimian school, Douglas saw these as the key to our understanding of the most
fundamental opposition in social life between the 'sacred' and the 'profane'. It is in this
sense that creatures or substances that fall outside familiar categories or that fall in
between categories can be at once dangerous, or poisonous, and special or sacred.
Transsexuals, for example, may be suspect because they are 'neither one thing nor the
other'. An unusual creature, or people born with deformities, may be objects of
abomination or they may be objects of special veneration. 1t is in this connection that we
can understand the literal meaning of the Hebrew word 'holy' as 'set apart'. Douglas and
those working with her became increas ingly interested in the political implications of this
model, in relation to internal power struggles within cultures and in relation to public
policy controversies. Her model is Durkheimian in its stress on the need for cultures to
preserve themselves by rituals of *soli darity and punishment for deviants. It is neo-
Durkheimian in the sense that cultures are also seen as divided and 'adversarial' (Douglas
2002).
In the USA in the 1970s, the anthropologist Clifford *Geertz developed a notion of
'thick description' as a programme for *ethnographic practice. By 'thick description'
Geertz meant detailed immersion in the relationships and 'webs of significance' spun by
actors in particular contexts of interaction. Geertz found inspiration in the work of the
British philosopher Gilbert *Ryle who had been concerned with the sort of sensitive
description that can differentiate between someone who intentionally winks and someone
who unintentionally blinks or twitches. In a particular social context-such as a school
classroom full of boys playing a prank on the teacher-the wink may function as a sign
with a particular meaning, which it is the ethnographer's task to decipher. Thus 'thick
description' for Geertz is a way of proceeding in social science which brings in the cultural
context and makes sense of what is observed. It emphasizes that explanation in the social
sciences is not often a labour of simplification-like, say, Einstein's simple elegant equation
E = mc2 but rather one of 'substituting complex pictures for simple ones while striving
I NTERPRETIVISM AND I NYERACTIONi5M 123
somehow to retain the persuasive clarity that went with the simple ones' (Geertz 1973:
33). In his book The Interpretation of Cultures (1973), Geertz writes:
In finished anthropological writings ... [the] fact-that what we call our data are really our
own constructions of other people's constructions of what they and their compatriots are up
to-is obscured because most of what we need to comprehend a particular event, ritual, rustom,
idea, or whatever is insinuated as background information before the thing itself is directly
examined. (Geertz 1973: 9)
Geertz in this sense illustrates the way in which ethnography can be pursued as a work of
narration where social relations are read like a text.
Kuhn's idea of 'paradigms' can also be compared to what the French theorist Michel
*Foucault termed 'epistemes' in his book The Order of Things of1966, a brilliant study of
forms of scientific thought in Europe in the eighteenth and nineteenth centuries
(discussed at length in Chapter 9 of this book, pp. 206-8). In contrast to simple models of
enlightenment in which dialogue and truth undermine illegitimate power, Foucault
bound the two ideas of knowledge and domination together, stressing the involvement of
disciplinary power in what he termed 'regimes of truth'. Along with the work of French
his torians such as Georges Canguilhem (1977) and Paul Veyne (1971), the ideas of
Kuhn, Feyerabend, and Foucault challenge us with some fundamental questions about
what counts as true in different cultures and different historical worlds.
Since the 1970s Kuhn's work has inspired a variety of projects in what has come to
be known as 'social studies of science', also broadly understood as contributions to
*'social constructionism'. Thes·e projects are united by a rejection of triumphalist or
*Whiggish notions of the emergence of truth from error. They favour a more sensitive
reconstruction of historical and social contexts of scientific discoveries in relation to the
emergence of new disciplines. In this vein, the French anthropologist Bruno *Latour
showed in his influential ethnographic study Laboratory Life (Latour and Woolgar 1979)
how the chaotic mess on a scientist's desk, made up of research reports, photocopied
articles, equations written on the back of old plane tickets, and so forth, is gradually
shaped into the scientific paper. Together with Michel Callon, Latour subsequently
developed an 'actor-network theory', in which scientific knowledge is socially
constructed by a variety of 'actors', including its objects themselves, such as the
molluscs of a Breton fishing port or the research objects and equipment in a laboratory.
In this sense Latour's ethnographic approach to knowledge challenges long-standing
*metaphysical distinctions in Western philosophy between conscious intentional
human agents, supposedly belonging to a realm of 'culture', and non-conscious
physical objects or forces, supposedly belonging to a realm of 'nature'. In Latour's
work, the scientists' materials, instruments, and institutional spaces of research can be
just as much 'actors' as the scientists themselves.
In Britain, the so-called Edinburgh school of the sociology of science pursued a similar
programme in the 1970s. Barry Barnes (1974, 1977) emphasized the need for interpretive
charity in relation to alternative conceptual schemes, while David Bloor (1976) stressed in
a Durkheimian manner the social constraints exercised by scientific communities. The
image of social construction was fed back into much of the sociology of natural scientific
knowledge, with the idea that natural entities, since they are conceptualized in human
languages in ways which vary over time and space, are basically social constructions. It
was argued that the sociology of scientific knowledge should be methodologically
relativistic and should not privilege whatever conceptions might happen to be favoured at
the time of writing. This 'strong programme' of the sociology of science, as it came to be
called, affirmed a position of neutrality between currently accepted scientific views and
alternative or historically outmoded conceptions, regarding neither as in principle more
valid than the other. Further variants of a social constructionist approach to science have
been developed by Ian Hacking (1999).
A further broad element in the sociology of knowledge is the rise of *postmodernism
in the 1980s, as proclaimed among others by the French theorist Jean-Frarn;:ois *Lyotard.
Lyotard's influential book The Postmodern Condition: A Report on Knowledge (1979) gave
INTER PR ETIVISM AND IIHERAlTION I SM 125
In general, it can be said that interpretive approaches in social theory get under way by
reflecting on similarities between the understanding of human social processes and the
understanding of texts. Understanding the rules and relations of conduct that underpin a
particular social situation is like learning a language and reading a text. And if
understand ing a society is in this way like learning a language, it may also require us to
learn a language or to use it in a specialized way. In the 1930s Austrian philosopher
Ludwig Wittgenstein, who had begun with a simple conception of the way language maps
onto the world, came to develop a more complex idea of 'language games' in which
certain moves have meaning and make sense. In a religious language game, for example,
words like 'prayer', 'sacred', 'holy', 'salvation', and so on, have a specific meaning which is
given to them only by and in this context.
One important effect of Wittgenstein's philosophical legacy in social science was the
introduction of the concept of *'speech-acts' and *'performatives'. This was developed in
the 1960s by the analytical philosophers John*Austin (1962) and John *Searle (1969).
They showed how, for example, when a priest says 'I pronounce you man and wife', or the
rector of a university says 'I confer on you the title of Bachelor of Arts', the priest and the
rector instantaneously create the social fact of marriage or graduation for the couple or
student concerned. This way of analysing linguistic performances and competences has
been taken up by a variety of theorists in recent years, from Jacques Derrida and Jurgen
Habermas to feminist theorists such as Judith *Butler (for further discussion, see Chapters
9, 11, and 13 of this book, pp. 202-6, 243-5, 279-83).
We conclude our discussion here by looking at several writers influenced by
Wittgenstein and by other ideas about language. Three of these are the British writer Peter
*Winch and the German philosophers Hans-Georg *Gadamer andJiirgen *Habermas.
argument partly in support of .\fax Weber and partly in opposition to him. He claimed that
Weber had been wrong to suggest that understanding needed to be complemented by
causal analysis. For Winch, knowing a society meant learning the way it is conceptualized
by its members. He thus revived a central principle of nineteenth-centuryGerman *histor
icism, according to which every age must be understood in its own terms. Winch directly
identified himself with the German idealist tradition by insisting that social relations
are 'like' logical relations between sentences in language (1958: 126).
Winch's book and a subsequent article by him, titled 'Understanding a Primitive Society'
(Winch 1970), sparked off a debate in Britain in the early 1960s about *relativism and
anti-relativism in social science.The debate focused on Winch's discussion of the work of the
British anthropologist Edward *Evans-Pritchard, who had studied the beliefs and practices of
the north African tribespeople, the Azande and the Nuer (1937, 1940). At issue was
essentially what we mean if we saythat witchcraft is real to the Azande people. A relativist is
likely to say that what counts is the Azande's beliefin the reality of witchcraft, and that it is
irrelevant to add that back home in Oxford or Paris most people no longer believe in
witchcraft or do not consider it scientificallyproven·or provable. Anti-relativists-suchas Ernest
*Gellner (1985) are prone to insist that there is a fact of the matter about whether witchcraft
works, that in fact it does not work, and that the role of the social observer is to try to explain
the reasons for the prevalence of such false beliefs.
In the same period, the German philosopher Hans-Georg *Gadamer introduced the
concept of 'philosophical hermeneutics', which also found its way into social-science
discussions. In his book Truth and Method, first published in 1960, Gadamer extended the
traditional scope of hermeneutics, which had formerly been limited to the theory of
interpretation of texts, including particularly the Bible. Gadamer insisted on a practical
dimension of interpretation, conceived in the philosopher Martin *Heidegger's sense of an
'encounter' between the 'horizon' of the interpreter and the 'horizon' of the text itself.
Gadamer's philosophical hermeneutics was conceived in opposition to the methodological
emphasis of traditional hermeneutic theories that had been concerned predominantly with
accuracy, technique, and impartiality. Gadamer's aim was to describe the underlying
process, the existential encounter between two perspectives or 'horizons of expectation',
which makes interpretation possible. Understanding is not only a matter of immersing
one self imaginatively in the world of the historical actor or text. It is an at once reflective
and practical process which operates with an awareness of the temporal and conceptual
distance between the text and the interpreter and of the ways in which the text has been
and contin ues to be reinterpreted and to exercise an influence over us. For Gadamer, this
'effective history', as he called it (Wirkungsgeschichtc), which traditional historicist
hermeneutics had tended to see as an obstacle, is an essential element which links us to the
past and to other cultures. Our 'pre-judgements' are what make understanding possible.
Pre-judgements, or 'prejudices', do not necessarily limit understanding, though they may
do so.
The conception of hermeneutics espoused by Gadamer became central to the early work
of the German critical social theorist Jiirgen *Habermas, whose work is discussed at
length in later sections of this book (Chapter 7, pp. 164-5, and Chapter 13, pp. 279-83). In
his early text Logic of the Social Sciences (1967), Habermas welcomed Gadamer's critique of
historical objectivism, which he saw as the equivalent of positivism in natural science.
However, Habermas also maintained that Gadamer's stress on the fundamental nature of
language-expressed in
11\iHRPRETIVISM AND !fHFHACTiQl''l,M 127
his claim that 'Being that can be understood is language'-amounted to a form of 'linguistic
idealism'. In Habermas's view, Gadamer's stress on the value and wisdom of past historical
tra ditions and his rehabilitation of the category of 'prejudice' suggested a conservative
approach. Habermas argued that this conception of interpretation failed to deal with the
possibility of systematic distortions in relations of dialogue between subjects, due to the
effects of power,
*domination, and *ideology. Habcrmas and Gadamer debated these issues in the late
1960s and early 1970s. On the one side stood Gadamer's idea of tradition and openness to the
world views of past cultures and ancient classical civilizations. On the other side stood
Habermas's idea of *enlightenment, *emancipation, and ideology critique. More recent
theorists have tended to stress compatibility between hermeneutics and Hahermasian
critical theory, rather than conflict between them. Several writers have espoused a conception
of 'critical hermeneu tics' (Thompson 1981; Outhwaite 1987; Hoy and McCarthy 1994;
Harrington 2001).
Hermeneutics and critical theory can also be brought into relation with the school of
*realist philosophy of science developed in Britain by Mary Hesse, Rom *Harre, Roy
*Bhaskar, and others. For Hesse and Harre, science is an attempt to produce models of
real entities and processes in the world, aiming particularly at causal relations. Where
Harre (1993) combines this realism about natural science with a social-constructionist
social psychology, Bhaskar (1979) is more sympathetic to theories such as Marxism, as
well as to Anthony *Giddens's theory of *'structuration' (on Bhaskar's and Giddens's
work, see, Chapter 10 of this book, pp. 217-20, 227-8). For both Harre and Bhaskar,
meanings are real and have causal effects. Bhaskar has sought to overcome positivism in
social science with out at the same time acquiescing in cultural relativism or an idealizing
overestimation of the significance of texts and linguistic constructs in social life.
All of these more critical responses to hermeneutics can be seen as attempts to
reconcile the rival claims of causal 'explanation' with meaningful 'understanding' in social
science-just as Weber had attempted to reconcile them at the beginning of the twentieth
century. In general, hermeneutics in a broad sense continues to exist as a major research
tradition in the humanities and social sciences; and social scientists who might not sign
up to an explicitly hermeneutic programme mostly accept at least the importance of
hermeneutic issues today.
Conclusion
The approaches discussed in this chapter all possess what Wittgenstein called a
certain 'family resemblance' to one another. Although they have very diverse origins
and traject ories of development, several common themes unite the broad fields discussed
here under the brackets of phenomenological sociology, interactionism, sociology of
knowledge, and philosophies of language and hermeneutics. We may not be able to
identify a single proposition or set of propositions to which all these fields would
subscribe, but they share a general orientation or style of theorizing. All the approaches
focus in various ways on themes of meaning, understanding, action, interaction,
language, context, and everyday knowledge. These themes point us to a shared
general outlook which marks out these approaches in opposition to positivism.
A common general I:> ue m,"t'r' · the st;ltu ·d ·,h.it '-' rt \!..:rt,,·- ,·..ul<c'I..: •;",:,'" J."•-'
l
'L'Ut:sider· knO\\ k'lt c. !'ht: C ,p, ,, It: ,,n ,. p It lt 1:ru, ,.,. li l'O hJ. 'ti_) l'fc'
insider in order t1) 1mdast.m.i .u ,_,,h::,? ·\. tn.•n 1, , t · ''-'lL' l t,•••,l tl' '-ut t"-.:- r'- u.
from under thE feet of interpreti\'e tht.'1.'T\ lt \\'l.)l ·,c., tl-i,lt the l'llh .1.l,l. !1:' \W '-J.n
reallv understand is our L'wn nllture rhh w, · l t: Hl\1. t1,· \\ ,l\ ,t th•'' 1.r 1.. 1
the 0th er hand. the idea that Llll}\' Ullll1\ L'I\'-"., (, ' t:I\.' tt.'l.i l'Ut' ,h,•r. \..lll" 'pr,•r :r \ ,du
free social re:-t, Kh, ,md th.lt then.•t,,:.: f\'-. ·,m.ht ·, ,h,,uld t>.: ,t n.,i .l"=' t 1r: -.tu...,u\
th eso c ia l conte'\t'- the,· knL''' ,t. h,1, ,,mt k, t,1,h1,,1, l I· th ..u ·t ,'11, ,,....i, lt "''-" t
seem that it s not nece ·sar, tl1 t>t• ,m ins.i, er in ,,rcler t I llthie . t.1nd ,"'c l:'ii,t 1t" 1 ' t· '
appc>ar th;it there car> be no pul\.'h d.iT1ten.·,tt'li r , ttlm fn,n "h1;!', J.1 1
:u t1::v,
can be obs<.'rYed in a reli.ible w.1y It w1.,llld ,1p:-...•,u th.lt .ti. m11k•,p1,h•1_ m .1. ,Y- ·_-n• -,
require . and enabk-s. .it least SLm1t cr1r h' ·, 1 J; ,n'nt\\ltt- tt> :-uti :t "1
pretation ought tL' nll)fe oneL'f ;1 critil.·,tl "hc-rnh.'n.:-utk di,ll-' u1..•" l"'t'tWt"<'•l th • ,tJ.P,'I,,· 't
of the pec,ple l,ne h. tmh in .rn,1 the ,t,m,ip,.,;nt ,t ,,n,•\ ''"ilu1lture
The relation between intt'rpn:'th t' and N1'er ,1rrn.,Kh,·, h.i· tr,ld t.<'11,tl'v t:,,;,,_.n tr "1c i
be t>etwet>n ;,··11.:1cst,mdm{.ind ·e,p!.Pl..lt ,m·. !'hen:- is. hl'" ' r.
in terms of a .:-ontr,tst
thing unsatisfa<.toff ,1bout set\· -:- tn·ngs t,p in th · \\,l\. f,,r ,b \\ m,h .lrh. l; -
indifferent w1ys. some mterrn:•· "- des, ripti,,ns ,, t''-i .nut ,r, ..tt k,1,t t'l 1 ,..........,.,
inaff ense Oftt:n what \\E ,·all, xr1,m,1tilm in the tl · ·1i::nu,s the, 'tm l'ts \\
S<X ",
,,t,sen,:'ti
ing a pos<b .e rea,on ,,mt tfh:\. s ,'-(\.urn. t.'X"' ,., t, '"" J.I\.'
wh
inherent! open-ended. '>lnle ;t 1s ,1h,,1,--,; 1.'r,c'Il tl' ,,t1'.e tl) t·s lter,1,1t.w c ,( i
s_1,:.
tion or to argue that the,ft1.'{'t has t>rt>n misdes, n ,1 [)ur' he im d1,tr.h·ter·,n,·.1•,· t-, ...te--.t
to l-nl'ck do,,-n a small numl>t?r ,f p<..'. ,ible e'\pl,Put•.<'lls and th.:-..., -.u t>,t •r.1t ,h "..l' th.:-
011I·possible one. but hh •rit11..'1\\ thn,u h thh m,,, E ,pl,m.ttll'n' .1;'- -t ..i, ,c11.-: • ,t.:
can tend to be in·l1rpl'rat intl) tht' des•rip!tl'D (>f th<:' t''1tit, l)r e,t·nt. rJth • J. th,
molecular structure o• dtl,mh. wt>1_,:ht tif ,t thenu\.,ll :ul,st.m.. t'n\•mes 1 ,l •1n ,k' i..t,
propert\ of it.
It is possible to l,m1bme the- JprR1,1, h.:- d ,cu ,t,1iP thb,.._ .1r•u in "'utu.)[I\ -r • ,,tl , J\:
In particular. s\mtx,li, interal'til,m n, <•. '1<::111.) ,l r l , , ,,,•i l,, v t't •................ ,
l
-.ti ;.1n
a cl ,,er attention to l,111 1.1 t' fthmm11:.'thlx1,,1.,,0 in t'11:. l,f l;,u• '-.c' •1..'1 'U 1 .t" i
"'-'
others ·s a major ex.mtple t'f this enndunent. Smu irl\ 1.3 1..t ttP,;,'r\ ·wn,,p l,f tl'>t. .i · <'ll, •
hor; •1ns' form a u,dul..:orn.Ytin? t,1 \\'inch's r.1dk.1l rd.lt ,,,,,, L 1' " .s<:'. tt P!l\ us,.....,,
complement interpretn-e appro,tdk JS d whl1le w1th m,,re trn,·tur.tl r"'-' .-r-.:.,:tt' -- ,1. 1,, 1
from *critic.tl theory. •,tn1cturatll'll tht'\.1n. *ret1<:''\I'"' 1.'l."11. l,•0 ,1r •rt·,1lts1n. lntt'r,1 t• ,r ·i•1
is ,·a'.ued bY mam· ,L-x·ial ,.:-knti ts a a ·,en,1tizin,>!·t ·::-.t ttw. t'\ f" 11' the\ ht,>' ·w •t-, lt t
need to be c,m1plementt.'l.i b\' m,'rt' -.tern l\.tst.'1.1 J.I1.1h ""' Th repn,lu, t ,, 1 l,t ,l t:-,. J.•J
gender s, rel.1tions in 1:n•rnia · lin 'U-,!k CL,mmunic,1t1L1n i,;. c'.e1m.1, r 1d.1' '+ t , m. · •
tion but structural maten.11 ! apJ W$tt>mk . - tJ., d, n..t"'h"' ,nll 11, · r it-,
nequ.tl1fa. :"1·.:.h ... '_,- \,::-..:, _ ,_-
t.1}......
: ,,.h·...-. .
1 ::... ,,,'\.·:... · .. .., ;,.·, ;t,:. : .',,............
_: • ..
.... - .........
t1.nr,h· r-1....,1it .,:.J '-',_ c.' i .,l ';,· - I:' .! : :-:·. : \, ,' :;' "''- \.-: :-- : •... : :
: :··<. ,:c: .:.:· ..''--, ...---· .l - --- : , ..
>
forms of may be d nig,.., ec ;., in,;,,rc''!' \\\l\:. a, '-"L'm 1,,p· ,.,,, ·•• '-"I' 'r!J.t ,·t•
knowledge
iNTERPRETIVISM Arm INTERACTIONISft'I 129
How far are all social actors amateur sociologists? What is the relation between this 'lay
sociology' and more formal social theory?
2 What similarities and differences can be discerned between European and North American
traditions of interpretive and interactionist sociology?
3 What it does it mean to have 'empathy' for the experiences of another person or people7
5 What does it mean to say that all knowledge is 'relative' to social contexts7 Is there a problem
of 'relativism' in the sociology of knowledge?
6 Must one be a member of the oppressed to be able to understand the oppressed? Is experience
of suffering a necessary precondition for explaining suffering sociologically?
7 Are there any elements of social reality for which interpretive and interactionist thinking fails to
account adequately?
■ FURTHER READING
For a broad overview of interpretive approaches to social enquiry, see William Outhwaite's article
'The History of Hermeneutics', in the International Encyclopaedia of the Social and Behavioral Scienr es
(Elsevier, 2001) (www.iesbs.com). For a good overview of these and other issues in social theory, see
MarkJ. Smith's Social Science in Question (Sage, 1998). Some good collections of extracts by
influen tial interpretive writers are Fred Dallmayr and Thomas McCarthy (eds.), Understanding and
Social Inquiry (University of Notre Dame Press, 1977), Kurt Mueller-Vollmer (ed.), 'fhe
Hermeneutics Reade,
130 IA'ILUAIVi OUTHWAlrE
(Blackwell, 1986), and Josef Bleicher (ed.), Contemporary Hermeneutics (Routledge, 1980). Studies
showing how interpretive perspectives can be combined with other approaches in social theory are
Anthony Giddens's New Rules of Sociological Method (Polity Press, 2nd edn. 1995),John Thompson's
Critical Hermeneutics (Cambridge University Press, 1981), William Outhwaite's New Philosophies of
Social Science (Macmillan, 1987), and Gerard Delanty's Social Science beyond Constructivism and
Realism (Open university Press, 1997). See also Zygmunt Bauman's Hermeneutics and Social Science
(Hutchinson, 1978). An illuminating account of hermeneutics in relation to literary theory is David
Hoy's The Critical Circle: Literature, History and Philosophical Hermeneutics (University of California
Press, 1978). Peter Winch's short book The Idea of a Social Science and its Relation to Philosophy
(Routledge, 2nd edn. 1990) can be recommended as an elegantly written classic. Gadamer's work is
best approached through Georgia Warnke's guide Gadamer (Polity Press, 1987) and Kurt Mueller
Vollmer's The Hermeneutics Reader (Blackwell, 1986). For a critique of the theme of 'hermeneutic di
alogue' in Gadamer, Habermas, and other German writers, see Austin Harrington's Hermeneutic
Dialogue and Social Science: A Critique of Gadamer and Habermas (Routledge, 2001). See also
Gary Schapiro and Alan Sica's edited Hermeneutics: Questions and Prospects (University of
Massachusetts Press, 1984).
For a collection of writings in phenomenology and sociology, see Thomas Luckmann's edited
Phenomenology and Sociology: Selected Readings (Penguin, 1978). A good place to begin reading Schutz
is his essay 'Common Sense and Scientific Interpretation of Human 'Action', in Alfred Schutz:
Collected Papers, vol. i (ed.) M. Natanson (Nijhoff, 1966). See also Nick Crossley's lntersubjcctivity: The
Fabric of Social Becoming (Sage, 1997), which deals with Schutz, Mead, Merleau-Ponty, and Foucault.
For a comparison between Schutz and ethnomethodology, see Burke Thomason's Making Sense of
Reification: Alfred Schutz and Co11structionist Theory (Macmillan, 1982).
A good introduction to the Chicago School is Martin Bulmer's The Chicago School (University
of Chicago Press, 1984). A useful textbook in symbolic interactionism is Robert Prus's Symbolic
Interaction and Ethnographic Research (State University of New York Press, 1996). For an
informative account of symbolic int'eractionism, see HansJoas's article 'Symbolic Interactionism', in
Anthony Giddens and Jonathan Turner (eds.), Social Theory Today (Polity Press, 1987), as well
asJoas's longer study G. H. Mead (Polity Press, 1985). Two primary works in the area are Ken
Plummer's edited
collection of papers Symbolic lriteractionism (in two volumes) (Edward Elgar, 1991) and Herbert
Blumer's papers Symbolic lnteruclionism (Prentice-Hall, 1971).
Goffman is a very readable author. It is good to start with The Presentation of.Self in Everyday Life
(Penguin, 1971) or Asylums (Penguin, 1991). For secondary guides, see Tom Burns's Erving Goffman
(Routledge, 1992) and Peter Manning's Erving Goffman and Modem Sociology (Polity Press, 1992).
Garfinkel's use of technical jargon may seem off-putting at first, but his accounts of experiments
make lively and entertaining reading. A good secondary guide is John Heritage's Garfinkel and
Ethnomethodology (Polity, 1984). For a collection of readings, see Roy Turner's Ethnomethodology:
Selected Readings (Penguin, 1974).
The field of the sociology of knowledge is helpfully tackled through Peter Berger and Thomas
Luckmann's very clear and accessible The Social Construction of Reality (Penguin, 1966). Karl
Mannheim's work can be approached through David Kettler, Volker Meja, and Nico Stehr's Karl
Mannheim (Horwood, 1984) and Volker Meja and Nico Stehr's Knowledge and Politics: The Sociology
of Knowledge Dispute (Routledge, 1990). Try alsoJohn Law (ed.), Power, Action and Belief: A New
Sociology of Knowledge (Routledge, 1986), or more recently Doyle McCarthy's Knowledge as Culture:
The New Sociology of Knowledge (Routledge, 1996). In the field of social studies of science, see Steve
Fuller's Science (Open University Press, 1997) and Steve Woolgar's Science: The Very Idea (Horwood,
1988). See also Micheal Lynch's Scientific Practice and Ordinary Action: Etlrnomcthodology and Social
Studies of Science (Cambridge University Press, 1993). For the idea of social constructionism, try Ian
Parker (ed.), Social Constructionism, Discourse and Realism (Sage, 1998).
INTERPRETIVISM AND INTERACTIONISM 131
..C WEBSITES
However, in their actual work, historians and sociologists regularly combine both
ideographic and nomothetic elements.
The major works of classical social theorists such as Marx, Weber, and Durkheim are
deeply embedded in a historical understanding of society, oriented to explanations for
similarities and differences between processes of macro-social change in different his
torical epochs and in civilizations, in the East as well as the West. What today is
called 'historical sociology' only appears to be a sub-specialism of social theory
because of the rise to prominence in the mid-twentieth century of a search for
recurrent social univer sals discoverable at all times and places. This search was given
a large boost by Talcott
*Parsons's attempt to restructure sociology in terms of invariant propositions reminis
cent of economics. Today this kind of project is reflected in the influence of *rational
choice theory.
Historical social thought in the West began to take a recognizably modern form during
the eighteenth century. As the power of organized religion gradually weakened,
especially among the educated classes, scholars took up a task of providing 'rational' and
'scientific', explanations for the character and development of human societies,
explanations that aimed to replace the narratives provided by the Bible. Although many
scholars had fairly clear ideas about what kinds of social arrangement were 'good' and
which were 'bad,' his torical sociology borrowed an ideal taken from natural science. This
ideal was to examine what 'is' in as clear-sighted a way as possible, without allowing
perceptions to be distorted by value-laden assumptions about what 'ought to be'.
Thinkers such as David *Hume, Adam *Smith, Adam *Ferguson, *Montesquieu,
and Alexis de *Tocqueville were linked by their commitment to a shared ideal. They
sought to examine comparative data about social arrangements in the past and present
in order to establish generalizationsabout human nature, social order, and change. The
object of mak ing these generalizations was to give men and women knowledge relevant
to their attempts to make themselves and their societies better, within the discoverable
limits of possibility. The agendas of historical social thinkers in the nineteenth and
early twentieth centuries were dominated by themes such as:
• the origins of social solidarity and conflict;
• the nature of social hierarchy and interdependence, as illustrated, for example, by
slavery and the market;
• the dynamics of social change; for example, the origin and nature of war
and revolution;
• the nature of empires and civilizations and the causes of their rise and fall;
• the rise of rational bureaucracies, especially the state, and the different forms taken
by the state, such as dictatorship and democracy;
• the development and spread of capitalism;
• the relationship between the West and the rest of the world.
The writings of historical social thinkers from Adam Ferguson in the late eighteenth
century to Weber and Durkheim in the early twentieth century constitute a first 'long
HISTORICAL SOCIAL THEORY 135
wave' of historical sociology. This wave came to a halt in the period between the two
world wars of the twentieth century. It can be said that a consensus broke apart as
political and social life in the West in this period came to be dominated by a bitter
contest between three ideologies that were far more concerned with the future than with
understanding the past. The three ideologies were communism, under the leadership of the
Soviet Union, fascism, led by Hitler's Third Reich, and capitalist democracy, led by the
Western European colonial powers of Britain and France as well as the USA. Over half a
century later, we can observe that it was this third system of capitalist liberal democracy,
spearheaded by the USA and Western Europe, which won the long war of attrition-the
Cold War-against the Soviet Union, after the earlier defeat of fascism.
The Allied victory in 1945 generated an intellectual climate in which historical social
thinking could flourish once more. Yet by this time, the agendas of social science were
strongly influenced by the determination of the USA and the Western powers to show
that capitalism and democracy could be combined to generate social and political arrange
ments superior to available alternatives. Capitalism and democracy thus climbed to the
top of the agenda in the second long wave of historical sociology that began in the late
1940s. It is to this body of work that we now turn.
was 'a general directional factor in the change of social systems' (Parsons 1951: 499). He
also argued that change was often accompanied by 'strains' due to the resistance of vested
interests and the fact that society's established expectations were challenged and disrupted
(Parsons 1951: 513).
Neil *Smelser, a student of Parsons, developed the Parsonian idea that the key to
understanding social change was structural *differentiation, meaning an increase in
the number of subsystems in a society and a shift to a higher degree of complexity in
the relationships between these subsystems. Smelser sought to inject a more explicit
historical dimension into the Parsonian approach in ways that echoed some of the
emphases of the conflict theorists on change and discontinuity, but without the
conflict theorists' general hostility to Parsons's functionalist thinking (see Chapter 4 of
this book, pp. 100-1). Smelser applied this approach in his book Social Change in the
Industrial Revolution (1959). His subject was the Lancashire cotton industry between
1770 and 1840, the time of the English Industrial Revolution. Smelser argued that
structural differentiation typically happened as a result of two conditions. First, key
social agents became dissatisfied with what Parsons called the 'goal-achievements' of
the social system, i.e. its capacity to deliver desired resources and commodities.
Secondly, they saw the 'prospect of facilities ... tocorrect this imbalance', i.e. the
chance to change social arrangements. Subsequently, social control mechanisms
through the family, religion, and the police ensured that disturbances were handled in
such a way that resources such as money and human energy were mobilized. As a result,
innovations were brought about that satisfied societal demands, and the new norms of
action became routinized.
Smelser analysed several empirical examples of structural differentiation. Looking at the
textile industry (Smelser 1959: 69-128), he argued that the spread of Methodism in the
manufacturing districts strengthened values legitimizing manufacturers' complaints
about bottlenecks in the existing industrial structure. Disturbances caused by industrial
difficulties were handled and channelled through the lawcourts. Tolerance for new ideas
was shown by the Patent Office, and there were innovations in the machinery of industrial
production. Smelser also considered other aspects of social change in the textile districts,
especially in family structures.
Structural-functionalist theory was able, Smelser wrote, 'to relate a multitude of
complex social phenomena to a single set of analytical propositions without varying the
logic of the propositions themselves' (1959: 384). One serious problem with Smelser's
work, however, was that it did not test the assumptions of his theory against competing
theories, other than that of structural functionalism. Instead of 'telling it like it is',
according to a range of diverse empirical data, Smelser tended to present his subject 'like it
had to be', according to a pre-established model.
In a similar manner to Smelser, the Israeli historical sociologist Shmuel *Eisenstadt
examined the development of specialized political institutions and movements that
resisted traditional values and practices. In his book The Political Systems of Empires
(1963), Eisenstadt investigated large pre-industrial societies, especially what he called
'historical bureaucratic empires', including ancient Egypt, China, Rome, Byzantium,
and the major European states during the period of *absolutist rule. He sought to
define the conditions under which specialized political systems developed in these
societies
HISTORIC.Al SOCIAL THi:ORY 137
and how they were perpetuated, avoiding collap,e or being owrthrown. He argued that
such political systems developed when rulers began to follow their own plans, rather
than accepting traditional values and goals. Other factors included new types of social
actors created by the growth of towns, by new religious movements, and by the spread of
the market. These 'free-floating resources' became 'a reservoir of generalized power'
(1963: 27).
The ruler and the bureaucracy were part of a three-way structure of conflict and
com promise in these empires. Powerful traditional groups such as landowners
competed with new urban, commercial, and religious interests, and both had a tense
relationship with the central government. Rulers were often committed to traditional
values at the same time as pursuing their own goals. On the other hand, the new social
interests resisted attempts by the ruler and bureaucracy to restrict their independence
and to tax them heavily. \1eanwhile, government bureaucrats were liable to become
corrupt, to line their own pockets, and build up their own power. These conflicts
created constant pres sure for change: sometimes marginal or 'accommodable',
sometimes total, bringing about a fundamental alteration of ,ociety and government.
One outcome of total challge was the modern state, the result of an increase in
structural differentiation. In modern states, government and society are very closely
interwoven. Such states may be either de,potic and *totalitarian or more democratic,
allowing different groups to participate in the political process.
The strength of Eisenstadt's work is his analysis of structural tensions in societies that
in various ways stand in between what we like to call 'tradition' and 'modernity'. Like
Smelser, Eisenstadt sees a historical pattern of stability and disruption, followed by
re,tmed ,tability. But where Smeher ,tresse, tendencies to restored stability, Eisenstadt
<,tre,,e, recurrent di,ruption. And unlike Smelser, Eisenstadt sees these conflicts as being
'>(JCiety-wide, rather than contained within 'subsystems' such as the family. Where
Smelser was concerned with specialized institutions and changes over decades, Eisenstadt
examined changes in whole societies and over centuries. In The Political Systems of
fmpires he end'> with the suggestion that historical bureaucratic empires stand at the
c.rossmad'> between modern dictatorship, and modern democracies. That thought con
nect, [i<,emtadt\ work to the writing, of another sociologist who applied structural
functionalist ideas to government and politics. This is the US writer Seymour Martin
Upset, whose work is discussed in Box 15.
In his later work, Eisenstadt ceased to write in a structural-functionalist mode. In the
J9i:>O, he completed a wide-ranging comparative ,tudy of ancient and modern civiliza
tirm, influenced by Weber and by the ideas of the German philosopher Karl *Jaspers
rnncerning 'axial age civilizations'. In hi, la,t work, Eisenstadt introduced the import
ant theme of 'multiple modernitie'>', as an alternative to Western-centred conceptions
of mrJdernity wch a, the rather US-centred Parsonian theory of modernization which
dominated in the 1950s. The theme of multiple modernities represents a self
consciously globalized understanding of sociology which can be contrasted to
7
[urocentric developmentali',t thought in nineteenth-century evolutionary theory,
,uch as that of Augmte *Comte and Herbert *Spencer (as discussed in Chapter 1 of this
book, pp. 32-3).
138 DENNIS SMITH
In Political Man (1960), the American sociologist Seymour Martin *Lipset set out to determine historical
preconditions for democracy. He classified societies according to whether they were 'stable democra
cies' or 'unstable democracies or dictatorships'. He tabulated various key indices such as urbanization,
education, industrialization, and wealth. These enabled him to demonstrate that those societies with
the highest scores were 'stable democracies' (see Upset 1960: 31-8). In The First New Nation
(Lipset 1963), Upset applied this argument to the American case, discussing it from comparative and
historical perspectives. The book was written at a time when the British, French, and other
European empires were breaking up and American politicians were concerned that the ex-colonies in
Africa and elsewhere might acquire communist-influenced governments.
Lipset's analysis placed emphasis on political institutions together with the strategies adopted
by elites and especially values and national character. In his analysis, American history had produced a
spe cific set of 'structured predispositions' for 'handling strains generated by social change' (Lipset 1963:
207). They included a stress on achievement and belief in equality. The tension between these two
ideals was
kept in check by a strong sense of nationhood. This was reinforced by a stable two-party system. This
argument was presented cautiously, as a possible hypothesis. However, it was clearly playing to
an American audience that was highly sympathetic to its main proposition. This was, to put It crudely,
that America would remain strong as long as its citizens held fast to the principles of the
Declaration of Independence. Like Neil Smelser, Lipset assumed that within industrial societies,
especially if and when they became more like the United States, there was a natural tendency for the
social system to solve all problems that it was set. Mainly, these problems turned out to be technical
matters that needed prag matic adjustments to fix them. This approach led to partial blindness with
respect to endemic American problems such as the persistent discrimination against African-
Americans. More recently Lipset revisited this analysis in his book American Exceptionalism: A
Double-Edged Sword (1996).
the British case where the rise of citizenship, with its equalizing tendency, had coincided
with the rise of capitalism, which tended to produce inequality. In Britain, civil rights,
including the right to own property, to make contracts, and to speak freely, advanced
strongly in the eighteenth century. Political rights, especially the right to vote, expanded
in the nineteenth century. In the twentieth century, great progress was made with respect
to social rights such as the right to welfare, health care, and education.
Marshall's problem, however, concerned the question of how the polarizing effects of
the market were to be reconciled with the equalizing effects of citizenship. How could
one tell when there was 'too much' inequality in the market place? To summarize the
central problem: the rights and obligations created by contracts in the markets, including
the right to get rich and make others work for low wages, were both dependent on
principles of citizenship-including especially the right to protection for property-and
challenged by citizenship principles, including especially social rights which implemented
ideals of social justice and fairness. The tension between these two sets of principles was
felt sharply in the education system, since by acquiring qualifications at school and in
university, school-leavers and graduates felt a 'right' to a job of a certain income and
status-and often the market denied their expectations.
pri,ate inn'stors and intci the hands ut J cL'ntr,11 pulilic ,1utl1L1ritY. S,:humpc'h'r l,l,uld St'<:'
certain ad,antages in this. Sl1c1et\· \\·l1uld Ill1t h,1,·e tc1 Sllf'PL'ft ,in 1dk lt'bure d.iss. \\·,1stetul
n1mpctition ,n1uld lw abt1lishe,I. Planning 11\1uld ,11·(,1d tht' need t,1 m,mir1uL1te intt'fc'St
rates. Irr:1ti,mal n1nt1icts bet,wen the publi,· ,md pri,,1tl' sphere,s,·l1uld l1t' kit l1t'hind.
Sncia.lism might eYen be democratic as lL1ng ,1s pl1lit1cuns Wt're rwt ,·L1rrupt. it l1urt',1ucr,1ctt'S
"ere strong and efficient, and if go,ernment rt'siskd t lw tt'mputil1n tl1tn· tl, run c'\.t'n-t h in_,::.
\\"hen Schumpeter surYeYed ll1ng-run tendt'rKies in tht' dt·,·elL 1['l11c'nt ,1t ,·.1r1iUlism ,11hi
democracy, he concluded that it was difficult to achiew advances in knowledge and
rationalitY witlwut the danger t1f a stifling ,,f indi, idu,JI CTL',1ti,·it,· in the l1usiness w,,rld
and elsewhere. A rather similar view was taken bv Friedrich *Hawk.
ethos of British capitalism in the nineteenth ,·enturY. ln his ,·ie,,. 1t l1rL1u,s::ht pr,1sperit\·,m,i
po\\-er to British socit'ty, a flrnn'ring L1f l'ntt'rprhe ,md science.. md h1_,::h e:,,.p,'ct,lt1L1ns .,h,ut
the future. This era then came to an end with the great world recession of the 1930s, which
Ha,·ek recognized as gi,·ing Sl1cialbm its d1,mce. B1· s(,ci,1lism. !Lnt'k mc',lllt l1urt',w,·r,1t1,·
planning in a similar sense to Schumpeter's use t1f the' tl'rm. But in H,l\"c'k's ,ic'\1·. t lw 11l.mnc'rs
belieYed mistakenly. that theY could create rules ,ind institutiL)[lS th,it "·,1uld Ukc' l1,·er
.
fr,,m the market, or at least interfere with it on a large scale, producing wealth, inwsting
this
\\'ealth rational!\·, and distributing it in ,1 just ,1·aY. ln H,1n'k·s d:,Jpwsi,. such wh,1k,,1Ie s,1d,,l
engineering ,vas a disaster. Socialistic planning could not work because there was no way to
determine correct principles of social justice-planners were always bound to disagn:>e
furthermore, if the m;uket ,ras distorted L1f ,lbL,lished. peL1ple \1,,uld Ile' l,1ng,'r re,·ei, e th,'
.JC· curate and unbiased J..:.no1rledge abL1ut supply ,md dem,md th,lt \\·,1s prL'Yi,ied l1Y tht'
rrice sys. tern. It was far better to let indi\iduals make their own economic and other decisions
Hithout being commanded by a central authority liable to make mistakes.
In the early 19-l0s, when Hayek wrote this book, it seemed likely that Britain would soon
elect a Labour gl1,·ernment. ,Jdl1pt ,rhuks,11l' pLmning. ,md lc,st' the ,llh ,mu,:e 1t h.1,i H:
herited from its nineteenth-centun- industrial glL1n·. In fact. ,1ne l,t the likt'l,· ,,utCl'Il1l'S ,,t
socialist planning, HaYek bt'lieYed. 1\·,1s resentment ,mwng the' pett, b,1urgeL'lSlt' .m,i serY
ice classes, ll'ading tl, incre:1sed suppL1rt for fascist pL1litic,il n1c1,·emt'llts. He eYen te.Ht'd th,lt
Britain might go the way of Germany in the 1930s.
Hayek became fashionable among economists and politicians in the 1980s on both sides
of the .\tlantlc \\·hen his argument,, \\'1:re 111\ Liked t,1 justif, the dism,mtlm_,:: ,,t num i,JC,'t
()f public o\\·1wrship. gi,ing a freer Jund tL1 big business. He' \\·,Js t',HtlcuL1rlY ,lP['Lluded
t,y the Thatcher and Reagan administrations in Britain and the USA.
An influential counter-blast to Hayek came from the LS economist J K *Galbraith.
lialbraith h:1d been influenced b, Schumpeter"s general ,1ppr,1,Kh ..1greeing th,1t h_,::h1 1-
ness had bt'ct1me dL,minant within capitalism. In his Dl L,k 1:_-,,,1l1mi,, ,111,/ th, fz1hk
f,1,r,,_-,· lllJ73), he emisaged the 1-wssibilit, lit ,1 thriYin_,:: small bminess se,·h r run h
indi,1chul
entrt'preneurs \\·lw ,,·t1uld pw,•ide 1wn-stand:Hdized prl1ducts .ind ser,1ces 111 .1 cre.1tiYt'
HISTORICAL SOCIAL TllEOR'i 141
way. But Galbraith strongly disagreed with Hayek, and with Haye k's close follower,
Milton Friedman. In his books The Affluent Society (1958) and The New Industrial State
(1967), Galbraith pictured consumers in a Hayekian world of private affluence and public
squalor, imagining them going out for the day to 'picnic on exquisitely packaged
food from a portable icebox by a polluted stream' and then going on to camp in 'a park
which is a menace to public health and morals ... on an air mattress, beneath a nylon tent,
amid the stench of decaying refuse' (1958: 204). In other words, making the planners
redundant meant making life in modern industrial society unbearable for most people.
The decades of the 1960s and 1970s were a watershed for much of the intellectual self
understanding of Western societies. While African-Americans protested at their lack of civil
rights and the women's movement gathered strength, the United States suffered
humiliation in Vietnam. The British empire in Africa crumbled, while oil producers in the
Middle East asserted their independence. The assumptions and structures on which post-
war capitalist democracy had been based were placed under threat. Historical
sociologists responded by giving more prominence in their analyses to questions of
power, class, and conflict, and they became more aware of the global context in which
historical processes occurred. Two writers who stand at a point of transition between the
earlier and later phases are the German emigre sociologists Reinhard *Bendix and Norbert
*Elias. Bendix and Elias had a sense that there was a strong historical tide running in the
direction of capitalism and democracy, but they were very sensitive to counter-currents to
this trend and to the central significance of power and conflict. Bendix's work is discussed
in Box 16. Elias's work is discussed in the following section.
Like Reinhard Bendix, Norbert *Elias came to prominence in the 1960s and 1970s,
although he had been writing as early as the 1930s. Elias was keen on finding explanations
for social processes not simply from a detached interest but from a deep involvement in
the fate of humankind. Having lost his parenb and other Jewish relatives to Auschwitz,
Elias kept up a faith in wanting to improve humanity's capacity to shape the course of
social processes, or at least to avert their worst consequences.
Elias offers a powerful and influential vision of how human beings and societies inter
connect and develop. At the centre of this vision are at least seven key ideas:
• The human capacity to exercise agency, to wield power, and to experience a sense
of identity, self, and belonging is the result of being embedded in human social
relationships. In this sense, power and identity are fundamentally relational.
• Social life takes place in complex networks of interdependence amongst people, groups,
and institutions. Elias's term for these networks of interdependence is figurations.
Figurations include patterns of kinship, class relationships, or structures of government.
• Figurations undergo change over time as a result of long-term, and largely unplanned,
social processes which have a discoverable pattern or structure. The concept of 'process'
is thus key to sociological analysis.
142 N ' N l'i SM 1TH
ing its mark. Bendix saw this complexity as an important resource for historical sociologists, whose task
was to investigate a society's ideologies in association with its key social structures in order to find
clues about how problems were managed in the past.
Comparison between societies showed that similar problems could be solved in different ways; it
reduced the perception that the solutions adopted in one single society, such as the USA, were the
necessary and inevitable ones. This approach can be seen in Bendix's Nation-Building and
Citizenship (Bendix 1964; see also Bendix 1956, 1984). Here Bendix confronted at least indirectly the
structural functionalism of Parsons, Eisenstadt, and Upset, whose premises he did not accept. Bendix
retrieved the moral concerns that Eisenstadt had pushed aside in the name of scientific objectivity. At
the same time, he believed that Upset had neglected the historical dimension, notably by assuming that
other nations in the twentieth century could follow a road towards independence of the kind taken by
the United States in the late eighteenth century under very different circumstances.
Bendix paid more attention than Upset to the shape and dynamics of historical processes, especially
the development of the central relationships between state and citizens in the course of nation-
build ing. In Nation-Building and Citizenship, he pursued this strategy in the cases of Western Europe,
Russia, Japan, and India. In the case of Western Europe, he traced the rise of patrimonial social
order domin ated by ,-oyal power, examining the way powerful monarchies of the early modern
period defeated local resistance and established absolutist regimes. He investigated the rise of
processes of bureaucra tization and democratization in the nineteenth century, marked by the demands
of mass popular move ments to become part of the political process through extensions of voting
rights, as well as the
develops over centuries through complex interactions between elite groups and the
whole of the society.
• One of the challenges of the human sciences is to foster people's capacity to
exercise reasonable (non-repressive) control over themselves, by supplying
knowledge about historical social processes and figurations that shape people's
social existence.
• European social development in the past thousand years hasbeen characterized by a
long-run tendency-frequently interrupted and reversed-towards the development of
increasingly dense and complex figurations in which relatively stable power
monopolies appear and entrench high levels of self-control. These include the royal
courts and central state bureaucracies.
• The processes by which men and women acquire increasing self-control and
interdependence in relation to increasingly stable power monopolies make up an
overall *civilizing process. Civilizing processes can be detected across the course
of history in diverse social-cultural contexts. But interruptions and reversals may
also occur, leading to the onset of decivilizingtendencies that move toward
decreasing control and increasing instability.
Elias sees sociology as a science of human figurations and long-term social processes.
Its aim is to produce knowledge capable of eroding the fears and illusions endemic to
relations between individuals, groups, and nations. It should be 'a destroyer of myths' (Elias
1970: SO). Elias's sociology is deeply rooted in his intuitive sense for the character and
subtle 4ualities of social relations. He has a strong feeling for interconnectedness and
growth, for processes of integration and expansion, and for the intertwining processes
of disarticulation and fragmentation that always accompany them. At the same time,
Elias can empathize with those who stand apart, feel sequestered, or look at life
through a glass screen. He under stands the appeal of an apparently well-defended and
protected existence, such as in a royal court, in a bourgeois household, in a university
college or an academic department, or within the self.
Elias's sociological understanding of the world revolves around a central tension: between
merging and separation, between involvement and detachment, between inhibition and
expression, between being 'part of' and being 'apart from'. Both these aspects of his vision
come through in his most important work, The Civilizing Process, first published in 1939. By
the 'civilizing process' Elias means a long-term development, with some reversals, charac
terized by increasing pacification and self-control. Elias draws his evidence from Europe
be tween the Middle Ages and the early twentieth century. Through the civilizing
process, human beings are drawn into ever-denser relations of mutual interdependence so
that their fates become intertwined. Individualsgradually acquire a civilized 'habitus', or
psychologi cal make-up, which is expressed in inhibition, self-awareness, detachment, and
a calculat ing manner. Civilized people keep their emotions under control. Such an
orientation to civility, 'good manners', 'polish', 'discretion', and the like would not have
been conceivable in the less regulated societies of early medieval Europe when aggression
and fear primed people to engage in battle or flight at a moment's notice. External controls
and self-control were both intermittent and unstable before the later Middle Ages.
144 PENNIS SMITH
ln contrast, Elias describes how, in the early modern period, more stable and long-
lasting forms of central power monopoly gradually came into being, especially through the
for mation of the royal courts. As kings pacified their territories, warlords were forced to
attend court, to disavow violence, and to learn the skills of etiquette and political
manipulation. It was the only way for the nobility to survive and advance. As pacification
encouraged trade and industry, and as interdependence increased, the civilized habitus
spread from the court to the counting house, and from the upper classes to the people at
large. Elias traces these processes at the level of personal behaviour by showing how
manners grew more pre cise and delicate over the centuries. Among many other detaUs,
he investigates the rise of table manners, including the proscription of belching and farting
and other bodily indis cretions. This analysis is also developed in his book The Court Society
(1969), a specific study of the seventeenth- and eighteenth-century absolute monarchy in
France and its influence on French cultural manners and mores.
ln addition to his master concept of the civilizing process, Elias argues that a typical and
recurring pattern in social history is tension between establislzmmts,able to define and defend
standards of civilized behaviour, and outsiders, who arc stigmatized for failing to meet those
standards. Another key distinction is between an attitude of detachment, which allows one to
observe and interpret events without being swayed by emotional responses, and an attitude of
involvement, which both intensifies and distorts perception in the sense that events are felt
and interpreted in an emotional way. A final concept Elias developed later in his career, espe
cially in his last major study The Germans (1989), was that of 'decivilizing processes'. These
entail a reversal of previous tendencies towards reasonable political centralization and pacifi
cation. In a society undergoing a decivilizing process, such as Germany under the rise of
Hitler, violence increases as society fragments into warring groups acting with greatly reduced
restraint. The desperate centralization of the Nazi state was a reaction to the breakdown of
civil society in Germany.
One weakness of Elias's work is the other side of its strength. This is the very great,
per haps excessive, attention he pays to the aristocracy and court society acting as social
pace makers, as a vanguard for the civilizing process. Elias tends to downplay other
causes of self-restraint in social change. One factor he should have paid more attention to
in the emergence of distinctly controlled rationalized social conduct is the factor of
religion, which Max Weber had examined in the case of the Protestant ethic. But together
with Bendix, Elias made an important hreak with the structural-functionalist tradition,
opening the way for a new phase in the development of historical social theory. The new
phase came to place much more emphasis on power, coercion, and conflict, especially in
relation to the state and revolution. It is to this new phase that we now turn.
By the 1970s there was a strong upsurge of historical social theory dealing with the topics
of violence and revolution, exploitation and class, the rise of nation-states, and the rise of
the West as a whole. These themes preoccupied writers such as Barrington Moore, Theda
Skocpol, Charles Tilly, Perry Anderson, Immanuel Wallerstein, and Michael Mann. In the
following section we look first at the work of Moore, Tilly, and Skocpol.
HISTORICAL SOCIAL THEORY 145
Tilly shows how the demands of constant war-making led rulers to extract resources
from unwilling populations. Constant struggles over how much tribute should be paid to
the state and what the state might do in return shaped the central organizational structures
of the European national societies. A key factor was the extent to which a territory was
either coercion-intensive, that is, able to support strong government pressure over the
population, or capital-intensive, that is, economically productive and prosperous. Capital-
intensive territ ories such as Italy and Holland tended to be highly urban, with a thriving
merchant class. Coercion-intensive territories such as Prussia and much of Habsburg Eastern
Europe tended to be much more rural and dependent on repressive forms of agriculture,
sometimes based on serfdom. Tilly shows how where capital was plentiful, systems of
fragmented sovereignty developed. Government remained relatively decentralized and
sometimes took the form of city-states. Where conditions favoured coercion, large
tribute-based empires tended to develop. By the sixteenth century, nation-states had an
advantage in times of war because they could support large standing armies drawn from
the countryside, while at the same time having the advantage of being able to tax their
cities. The most successful nation-states, such as France and Britain, combined coercion and
capital in what Tilly calls 'capitalized coercion'. Tilly points out that the success of the
nation-state as a form of government only seems inevitable to us in retrospect. As late as
1650, empires such as the Habsburg Empire and fed erations of city-states such as the
Dutch Republic maintained a notable grip on territorial power in Europe. But Tilly shows
how nation-states eventually prevailed, drawing on his other research on contentious
behaviour and social protest. He shows how several European states gradually yielded a
variety of rights to their populations and accepted a widening
variety of tasks. One problem not explored at length by Tilly, however, is the question of the
extent to which hisgeneralizationsapply outside Europe, such as in the US/\ or Asia. We may
ask whether there is something distinctive about nation-state formation in Europe, perhaps
asa result of the specific pattern of interstate competition between Britain, France, Spain,
the Dutch, and so on. How would the USA fit into Tilly's model? Perhaps it would be best
described in terms of 'fragmented sovereignty' along the 'capital-coercive path'.
civil war. In all three cases, she shows how rulers and aristocracies jointly ran the old
regimes. These agencies shared, and squabbled over, the surplus gained from tax and rent.
In all three cases, the old regime faced a sudden challenge from foreign states with greater
economic and military strength. Faced with this challenge, the ruling establishment,
which was internally divided, did not manage to respond effectively. At the same, in all
three cases there were widespread lower-class rebellions, especially among the peasantry.
This led to 'mass-mobilizing political leaderships' which were able to 'consolidate revolu
tionary state power' (1979: 41). In each case, the outcome was a 'centralized, bureaucratic,
and mass-incorporating nation-state with enhanced great-power potential in the interna
tional arena' (1979: 41). The influence of the aristocracy was abolished in rural society
and central government. The new regimes brought the masses into the political system and
created systems of government that were more rationalized and centralized than before.
Skocpol's strategy of comparison between France, Russia, and China is to show that
despite much dissimilarity between the cases, especially in their different levels of techno
logical development, they all experienced the same distinctive phenomenon of social
revolution as a result of the same distinctive set of causal factors. Here we may note that
Skocpol's central argument partly resembles the argument made by Shmuel Eisenstadt in
The Political System of Empires. The two analyses share in common an emphasis on endemic
structural conflicts between the ruling power and traditional interests (the aristocracy), as
well as on disputes among powerful groups about control over 'free-floating resources'
(such as tax and rents). Both writers examine the resolution of those conflicts in favour of
the state after a major structural transformation, involving greater centralization, bureau
cratization, and involvement of mass populations in the *polity. Both authors also deliber
ately bracket the values, intentions, and motives of the major participant groups through
the use of a self-consciously scientific framework.
capacity to integrate peoples and spaces into dominant configurations' (1986: 31). This includes the
capacity to make resources operate in a way that is useful to those who control them. Societies are
'organized power networks'. Mann analyses four principal sources of sooal power: (1) economic
power. (2) ideological power, (3) political power, and (4) military power. None of these has ultimate
primacy. Different combinations predominate according to the world-historical context. For example,
Mann believes that during the nineteenth century the role of political power in the internal workings
of national states declined with the disappearance of aristocratic classes. He proposes that
ideological power also grew less important in that period, especially in comparison with the great
influence of Christianity during the Middle Ages in Europe.
In Mann's view, two types of configuration have recurred throughout human history. One of them
consists of empires of domination, which used concentrated military coercion to control large territories
with a centralized state. The Roman Empire is a classic example. The other type consists of multf-
power actor civilizations, a notable example being the city-states of ancient Greece. In the latter case,
economic
' and ideological forms of sornl power predominated. Empires of domination had a tendency to fragment
and to become decentralized. By contrast, multi-power-actor civilizations tended to move towards
greater centralization.
A third historical tendency noted by Mann is that there was a steady drift by the leading edge of
sooal power away from the Mediterranean towards the North Sea and the Atlantic. For example,
the Scandinavians began to open up the Baltic Sea in the north at about the time that the Roman
Empire collapsed. There was nothing inevitable about this drift. It was the result of 'a gigantic series
of acci dents of nature linked to an equally monstrous series of historical coincidences' (1986: 540).
By the eighteenth century, Europe was integrated by four closely connected institutions· the
capitalist mode of production; industrialism; the national state; and 'a mult1state, geopolitical,
diplomatic civilization' (1986: 471) In other words, Europe had become a modern form of multi-
power-actor civilization (see also Mann 1988)
Anderson argues that the feudal aristocracy faced difficulties as European societies
became more peaceful and more commercialized. In place of the old system in which the
lower orders were expected to fight or pay feudal dues to their masters, the market was
penetrat ing into the countryside and providing a new basis for exchanging goods and
services. The aristocracy's hold over the peasantry was loosening. It found greater
difficulty in obtaining goods and services from the peasantry. In these circumstances, the
absolutist ruler pro tected the class interest of the feudal aristocracy by ensuring it
continued to benefit from the surplus produced by the peasantry. The task of extracting
such surplus, by force if nec essary, was moved upward from the local manorial court run
by the local feudal lord to the central state apparatus. The crown, so to speak, 'took the
aristocracy under its wing'.
This pattern differed between Western Europe and Eastern Europe. In the West, by the
fourteenth century, the strength of the towns and a shortage of agranian labour made it
possible for the peasantry to throw off their feudal bond of serfdom. By contrast, in the
East the state in conjunction with the larger landowners responded to a labour shortage by
imposing serfdom on the peasantry for the first time. One reason the landowners were
able to do this was that the towns were much weaker in the East and could not support
those peasants that tried to protest.
with Germany as a whole) moved into the semi-periphery. The periphery expanded to
include Russia, the Ottoman Empire, India, and West Africa. During the twentieth
century, the USA asserted its leadership of the core. After the Second Worid War, the USA
shared the core with the USSR, Japan, and the European Union. Communist regimes such
as those of Poland and Hungary belonged to the semi-periphery. The periphery consisted
mainly of the Third World.
Wallerstein believes that the widespread protest movements of 1968 signalled the
beginning of a 'revolution in the world-system' directed against domination by the core
(Wallerstein 1989b: 411 ). He saw this revolution as fuelled by six movements: the
Western 'old Left'; new social movements in the West concerned with women, ecological
questions, and ethnic minority rights; the traditional communist parties of the socialist
bloc; new movements for human rights in the socialist bloc; traditional national liberation
move ments in the Third World; and anti-Western Third World movements, often of a
religious nature. Wallerstein recognizes that there was considerable mutual suspicion
between these different 'anti-system' movements, but he thought that by the mid-1980s
this mutual suspicion had decreased in intensity. In the current climate of anti-
globalization movements, or global movements directed against global capitalist
penetration, it appears that at least some of these movements have been joining together
under a common banner.
Conclusion
This survey of historical social theory has travelled from the 1940s through to the last
decade of the twentieth century. Since the collapse of the Soviet Union, the end of the
Cold War, and the apparent triumph of Western liberal capitalist democracy, the agenda
of his torical social theory has been somewhat in disarray. On the one hand, interest in
writers from the first phase such as T. H. Marshall and Talcott Parsons has revived. On
the other hand, globalization has emerged as a new focus of historical social theory as
part of a much larger complex of changes.
Today it would appear that older Western ideologies of communism, fascism, *Keynesian
welfarism, and trust in the problem-solving capacities of science are in decline. As
voter turnout diminishes at successive elections, public political participation appears
under threat, while social relations appear to be ever-increasingly regulated through the
market. Relations between government, business, and civil society today are not the same
as they were in the post-war period. Large multinational businesses have broken free from
the con straints imposed by national planning, just as they have untied themselves from
their once close involvement with colonial administrations based in Europe.
In this context, one theme deserves a high place on the agenda of historical sociology in
the early twenty-first century. It is the fact that despite the hegemonic influence of global
business discourse, the free-market version of capitalism rediscovered during the 1980s is
suffering a process of de-legitimation. *Neo-liberal forms of marketization have become
implicated in the widespread fragility and vulnerability of the economies of the global
South. In a great many regions of the world, large business corporations have become less
151
and less responsive to the social constraints once imposed by national goverments. The
relatively cohesive post-1945 political and economic system that preoccupied many of the
writers discussed in this chapter is largely a thing of the past. The system of social
democ racy that developed in Western Europe after the Second World War, founded on a
welfare state offering universal provision, went together with what have been called 'thirty
glorious years' of economic growth (Fourastie, 1979). Since the mid-1970s, the Western
world has seen the end of this period of stability and the emergence of a new era of
deregu lated, crisis-ridden, neo-liberal economic policy.
These developments present historically minded social scientists with an important
challenge. The question is whether social scientists will find the courage and imagination
to use their research on long-term social processes to provide independent and insightful
analyses of the structural alternatives available to human societies in a context of
increasing global uncertainty. Here the potential uses of historical sociology have not
changed. They are to help us think through the causes and consequences of long-term
social processes. They are to make us aware of the alternative trajectories of social
development that existed in the past and those that may exist for us in the present. The
ultimate value of historical sociology is that it can improve our knowledge of the ways in
which human beings may intervene in these processes and give societies a push in the
direction we believe to be right.
2 What considerations distinguish the interests of the historical sociologist from the interests
of the historian?
3 According to the theorists discussed in this chapter, what advantages and disadvantages can
be discerned in capitalism, socialism, and democracy as systems of social organization?
4 What factors account for the rise of the nation-state in modern Europe?
5 What factors account for the dominance of the West in world history7
6 What is a revolution?
FURTHER READING
A useful introduction to historical social theory is Dennis Smith's The Rise of Historical
Sociology (Polity Press, 1991). Two recent guides to diverse topics in historical social
theory are Gerard Delanty and Engen !sin's edited Handbook o(Historical Sociolosy (Sage,
2003) and James Mahoney and Dietrich Rueschemeyer's Comparative Historical Analysis in
the Social Sciences (Cambridge University Press, 2003). See also Dennis Smith's shorter
essay 'Historical Analysis', in Melissa Hardy's edited Handbook ofData Analysis (Sage,
2004) and Phillip Abrams's older but still important work Historical Sociology (Open
Books, 1982). Theda Skocpol's Vision and Method in Historical Sociology (Cambridge
University Press,
152 DENNIS SMITH
II WEBSITES
7 Western Marxism
Douglas Kellner
In investigating the genesis of modern societies, Karl Marx and Frirdrich Engels
developed a new *materialist theory of history and society, introducing the concepts of
forces and relations of production, division of labour, *ideology, and class struggle as
keys to under standing society and history. They formulated a conception of history as a
succession of modes of production, charting the emergence of modern bourgeois society
and its future transition to a communist society. The Marxist vision of society and history
first appeared in Marx and Engels's The <:ormmmist Manifesto of 1848 in dramatic
narrative form, pro claiming the rise of capitalism and bourgeois society and its
revolutionary overthrow by an industrial proletariat. Capital (1867) and other classic
Marxian texts developed a critical theory of capitalism, a model of socialism, and a project
of revolution combining political
155
economy, social theory, philosophy, history, and politics that provoked both fervent ad
herence and passionate opposition.
This chapter explores the development of Marxist social thought in the twentieth
century, concentrating on what is called 'Western Marxism'. The term 'Western Marxism'
was first used by the Soviet communist regime to disparage the turn to more diverse
forms of Marxism in Western Europe after the 1920s. Since then, however, the term has
become widely accepted as a generic category used to distinguish more independent and
critical forms of Marxism from the dogmas of the Soviet and Chinese regimes. In this
chapter we trace the spread of Western Marxism in Europe after the Russian Revolution
until the 1960s and the rise of new syntheses between Marxism and other theoretical
approaches since the 1970s under the ambit of 'cultural studies'. Among the key theorists
under discussion are Gy6rgy *Lukacs, Antonio *Gramsci, Ernst *Bloch, Walter
*Benjamin, Theodor *Adorno, Max *Horkheimer, Jean-Paul *Sartre, Herbert
*Marcuse, Louis *Althusser, Raymond
*Williams, Stuart *Hall, and others.
We begin with a resume of the classical Marxist conception of ideology formulated by
Marx and Engels.
Cultural forms in Marxist analysis are seen as emerging in specific historical situations
and as serving particular socio-economic interests and functions. For Marx and Engels,
the cultural ideas of an epoch serve the interests of the ruling class, providing
*ideologies that legitimize class domination. In The Gennan Ideology Marx and Engels had
asserted that 'the ideas of the ruling class are in every epoch the ruling ideas' (1846:
64). Ideology in this sense describes how dominant ideas of a ruling class promote the
interests of that class and help mask oppression and injustices in a given society.
The economic *'base' of society for Marx and Engels consisted of the forces and
relations of production. The 'superstructure' consisted of legal and political institutions,
along with culture and ideology. The goal of Marx's science of society and history was to
grasp the primacy of this economic base in its relation to culture and politics. Marx and
Engels sought to show how ruling ideas serve to naturalize, idealize, and *legitimize the
existing society and its institutions and values. They argued that during the *feudal
period, ideas of piety, honour, valour, and military chivalry expressed the interests of the
ruling aristocratic classes. During the capitalist era, values of *individualism, profit,
competition, and the market became dominant, articulating the ideology of the new
bourgeois class and consolidating its class power.
In this sense Marx and Engels showed how ideologies appear to represent common
sense and are thus often invisible and elude criticism. In a competitive and
atomistic capitalist society, it appears natural to assert that human beings are
primarily self-inter ested and competitive. In fact, human beings and societies are
extremely complex and contradictory, but ideology smoothes over contradictions and
conflicts, idealizing traits like individuality and competition and elevating them into
governing conceptions and values.
156 DOUGLAS KELLNER
After Marx's death in 1883, many different versions of Marxism began to emerge.
The first generation of Marxist theorists and activists tended to focus on the economy
and politics. The second generation ranging from German Social Democrats and
radicals to Russian Marxists focused even more narrowly on economics and politics.
Marxism became the official doctrine of many European working-class movements
and was thus tied to the requirements of the political struggles of the day. In contrast,
later generations of intellectuals after the Russian Revolution developed Marxian
theories of culture, the state, social institutions, and psychology. Where Marxism was
generally associated by the beginning of the twentieth-century with economic,
political, and historical doc trines, a new generation of Marxists began turning
attention to cultural phenomena in the 1920s and 1930s onwards. Many twentieth-
century Marxian theorists employed Marxian·theory to analyse past and present
cultural, political, economic, and social forms in relation to their production, their
imbrications with the economy and history, and their functions in social life.
The term 'Western Marxism' had first been used by the Soviet communists as a label of
derision, aimed at what they saw as defeatist and revisionist thinking. Yet the term
swiftly became adopted by European intellectuals to describe a more independent
form of thinking distinct from that of the party line represented in Moscow. For many
intellectuals active in the 1920s and 1930s, the Marxist movements arising out of
Bolshevism in Russia and the Social Democratic Party in Germany had rested on an
overly dogmatic and *deterministic conception of society. These intellectuals sought
to develop alternative agendas that Jed to tensions between 'scientific' and 'orthodox'
Marxism on the one hand and 'critical' Marxism on the other hand. In a later contribu
tion from the 1970s, the British Marxist historian Perry*Anderson (1976) interpreted the
turn from economic and political analysis to cultural theory in the 1930s as a symptom of
the crushing of the European revolutionary movements of the 1920s and the rise of
fascism. In the 1950s, on the other hand, the French *phenomenological philosopher
Maurice *Merleau-Ponty (1955) provided the term with more positive connotations,
emphasiz;ng the centrality of struggle over culture, art, philosophy, language, and
ideas to material social transformation.
Among two of the earliest partisans of this non-dogmatic conception of Western
Marxism were the Hungarian critic Gyorgy *Lukac and the German theorist Karl
*Korsch. It is to their work that we turn first.
The ultra-Marxist Lukacs of the early 1920s focused intently on developing philo
sophical, sociological, and political dimensions of Marxism before returning to cultural
analysis later in the 1920s. He then went to Russia where he withdrew internally from
Stalinism while working on a series of literary texts that have significant but largely
unappreciated importance for cultural criticism. Lukacs's literary studies employed
theories of the mode of production, class and class conflict to provide economic
grounding for cultural analysis. He saw history as constructed by a mediation of economy
and society, viewing cultural forms in their relation to socio-historical development within
a mode of production. He also demonstrated that cultural and artistic forms themselves
illuminate material historical circumstances, when properly interpreted.
In his most influential work History and Class Consciousness of 1923, Lukacs argued
that the Marxian vision of *totality and its focus on the primacy of commodity forms
provided the best methodological tools with which to analyse capitalist society and to
discover forces that would overthrow it. Lukacs asserted that adopting the standpoint of
the working class enabled one to see how capitalist society produced *reification,
involving the transformation of human beings into things, in all dimensions of society-
from the labour process to cultural production and even sexual relations. Lukacs saw all
domains of society, culture, and even intimate relations as pervaded by economic
imperatives. The proletariat, however, stood in a privileged position to grasp societal
reification and to organize to overcome it. The proletariat became, in Lukacs's typically
Hegelian phrase, the
*'subject-object' of history. Hegel's classic analysis of the relation between master and
slave, in which the slave's practical mastery of the situation leads to an inversion of the
hierarchical relation to the master, was taken up in Lukacs's analysis of proletarian class
consciousness. For Lukacs, every class perspective is necessarily partial and limited, espe
cially the perspectives of the aristocracy and the bourgeoisie. However, the exception to
this rule is the perspective of the proletariat, because the proletariat cannot understand its
own social position without at the same time understanding the society as a whole, as a
'totality'.
In Germany after the abortive revolution of 1918, the political activist and theorist Karl
*Korsch also developed a Hegelian and critical version of Marxism. In Marxism and
Philosophy (1923), Korsch argued that Marxism involved *dialectical thinking, providing
the mental forces to transform bourgeois society through a union of theory and practice. In
a later work, Korsch (1938) asserted the importance of historical specificity to Marxian
theory, maintaining that Marxism provided a historically determinate critique of capitalist
society and alternatives to it (on Korsch, see further Kellner 1977).
Two other early Western Marxist thinkers who were to become influential were
the Italian writer and party activist Antonio Gramsci and the German theological philo
sopher and critic Ernst Bloch. In the next section, we turn to Gramsci's conception of
'hegemony' and the 'philosophy of praxis'. Ernst Bloch's work is discussed in Box 18.
The German theorist Ernst *Bloch also responded positively to the Russian Revolution and the
European revolutionary movements of the 1920s, but he developed a more *messianic and utopian
version of Marxism. Bloch's three-volume work The Principle of Hope (1952-9) provided a systematic
examination of the ways in which fairy tales and myths, popular culture, literature, theatre, and all
forms of art, political and social utopias, philosophy, and religion contain *emancipatory moments. He
showed how these elements of culture project visions of a better life that question the organization
and structure of life under capitalism-or state socialism. In this magnum opus, he analysed the
ways in which hope for a better world exists in everything from daydreams to the great religions,
pointing to anticipatory visions of what would later be systematized and disseminated as socialism.
He concentrated on analysing popular literature, architecture, department store displays, sports,
clothing, and other artefacts of everyday life. He shows how the critique of ideology aims not only
at political texts and manifest political doctrines but also at film, radio and the mass media, and
everyday life in general. For Bloch, ideology contains a utopian dimension, in which its discourses,
images, and figures produce images of a better world and illuminate what is deficient and lacking in
this world and what should be fought for to bring about a freer and happier future. Bloch thus
provided a more 'hermeneutical' account of the ways in which cultural history and socio-economic
development point forward to socialism as the realization of humanity's deepest dreams and hopes.
Bloch developed a type of cultural theory that is quite different from other Marxian models that present
ideology critique as the demolition of bourgeois civilization. Unlike dogmatic Marxist wntIng, Bloch did
not directly equate culture with ideology in a wholly negative sense. This dogmatic model-found in
Lenin and most Marxist-Leninists-had interpreted ideology primarily as a process of mystification and
error, as 'false consciousness'. It had viewed the function of ideology critique as being simply to
demonstrate the illusions of ruling-class interests in cultural objects that are then discarded under the
heavy hammer of the 'scientific' Marxist critic.
Although Leninist Marxism also developed a more positive concept of ideology that viewed socialist
ideas as constructive forces for promoting revolutionary consciousness, Bloch remained wary of those
who stressed the unambiguously progressive features of socialist ideology. Instead, he saw emancipa
tory content in all living ideologies - socialist or capitalist - and deceptive illusory qualities as well. For
Bloch, ideology was'Janus-faced', two-sided: it contained techniques of manipulation and domination
but It also contained a residue or surplus that can be used for social critique to advance *enlightened
pol itics. Bloch rejected what he saw as the denunciatory 'half-enlightenment' of dogmatic Marxism.
Half enlightenment wrongly dismissed as superstition and legend everything that did not measure up to
its 'scient1f1c' criteria. It deluded itself by thinking that truth can be obtained solely by eliminating error
rather than also by offering some alternative vision. Bloch believed that part of the explanation for the
defeat of the Left by the Right in Weimar Germany was that the Left tended to focus on negative
denunc,at,ons of capitalism and the bourgeoisie, while fascism inculcated an apparently more positive
and attractive vision for the masses who desperately sought for a better life.
death in 1937. /\ccording to Gramsci, the ruling intellectual and cultural forces of the
era constitute a form of *hegemony, or domination by ideas and cultural forms that
induce consent to the rule of the leading groups in a society. Gramsci argued that the
unity of prevailing groups is usually created through the state, such as in the American
Revolution
WE STERN M i'tfl )(l"i Y'I 159
or in the unification of Italy in the nineteenth century. In addition, the institutions of *c,vi/
society also play a role in establishing hegemony. Civil society involves institutions of
the Church, schooling, the media, and forms of popular culture. It mediates between the
pri vate sphere of economic interests and the family on the one hand and the public
authority of the state on the other.
In Gramsci's conception, societies maintain stability through a combination of force
and consent, involving obeisance to 'intellectual and moral leadership'. On the one hand,
social orders are founded and reproduced through the agency of institutions and groups
that violently exert power and domination to maintain social boundaries and rules-for
example, the police, the military, or vigilante groups. On the other hand, other institutions
involved in religion, schooling, and the media induce consent to the dominant order
establishing a distinctive type of social system, such as market capitalism or fascism or
communism. Societies also establish hegemony through an institutionalizing of
*patriarchy or male supremacy, as well as through the rule of a dominant racial or ethnic
group over subordinate groups. In his Prison Notebooks (1926-37), published after his death
in various edited selections, Gramsci's key example is Italian fascism. Gramsci showed
how fascism supplanted the previous liberal bourgeois regime in Italy through its control
of the state and through its frequently repressive influence over schooling, the media, and
other cultural, social, and political institutions.
The theory of hegemony for Gramsci involved both analysis of the ways in which
prevalent political forces achieve hegemonic authority and the delineation of counter
hegemonic forces, groups, and ideas capable of contesting and overthrowing the existing
hegemony. One illustration of this Gramscian analysis in recent cultural studies has
focused on the conservative regimes of Margaret Thatcher in Britain and Ronald Reagan
in the United States in the early 1980s. Stuart *Hall (1980a) and others analysed the ways
in which the Thatcher-Reagan regimes promoted a counter-hegemony to social-
democratic politics in the 1970s. In winning power, they achieved a new hegemony of
market individu alism. In the 1980s, conservative groups gained dominance through
control of the state and the media and through the arm of cultural institutions such as
think tanks and fund raising political action groups. They succeeded in presenting the
market not only as the source of wealth but also as the solution to all social problems,
while the state became pictured as a cause of excessive taxation, over-regulation, and
bureaucratic inertia.
In this context Gramsci defined ideology as the 'social cement' that holds together the
dominant social order. He described his own 'philosophy of *praxis' as a mode of thought
opposed to ideology, contesting dominant institutions and social relations and attempting
to generate a socialist counter-hegemony. In his essay 'Cultural Themes: Ideological
Material' (repr. 1985), Gramsci notes that the press in the 1920s had become the dominant
instrument of producing ideological legitimation for existing institutions, but that many
other institutions such as the Church, schools, and socio-cultural associations and groups
al o played a role. He called for sustained critique of the hegemonic forces that
legitimized these institutions and the creation of alternative ideas and movements capable
of challenging the existing system.
Gramsci's critique of dominant modes of culture would be taken up by the Prankfurt
School and later by British cultural studies, to which we turn shortly. It is to the work of
the Frankfurt School that we turn now.
160
The term 'Frankfurt School' refers to the work of members of the Institute for Social
Research ([nstitut for Sozialforschung) established at Frankfurt in Germany in 1923.
Under its first director, Carl Grunberg, the Jnstitute's work in the 1920s tended to be
empirical, his torical, and oriented towards problems of the European working-class
movement. It was the first Marxist-oriented research centre affiliated to a historic
German university. Max *Horkhcimer became director of the Institute in 1930, gathering
around him many talented theorists, including Erich *Fromm, Franz *Neumann, Herbert
*Marcuse, and Theodor W. *Adorno. Under Horkheimer's direction, the Institute sought
to develop an interdisciplinary social theory serving as an instrument of social
transformation. The work of this era was a synthesis of philosophy and social theory,
combining sociology, psychology, culturalanalysis, and political economy. Most members
had Jewish backgrounds and were forced to flee Germany after Hitler's ascendancy to
power. The majority emigrated to the USA where the Institute became affiliated to
Columbia University from 1931 until 1949, when it returned to Frankfurt.
The Institute's first major project under Horkheimer's direction was a systematic
study of authority, an investigation into individuals who submitted willingly but irra
tionally to authoritarian regimes. This culminated in a two-volume work, Studien iiber
Autoriti:it und Familie (1936), and a series of studies of fascism. From the 1930s onwards
the Institute referred to its work as the 'critical theory of society'. The term *'critical
theory' was elaborated by Horkheimer in a seminal essay of 1937, discussed here in
Box 19. For many years, 'critical theory' stood as code for the Frankfurt School's
distinctive brand of Marxism, distinguished by its concern to found a radical
interdisciplinary social theory on Hegelian-Marxian dialectics. The critical theorists
argued that Marx's theories of money, value, exchange, and *commodity fetishism pertain
not only to the capitalist economy but also to all social relations under capitalism. All
human relationships undercapitalism, public and private, can be shown to be dominated
by exchange values and commodity forms.
In a series of studies carried out in the 1930s, the Frankfurt theorists developed
accounts of monopoly capitalism and the new industrial state, focusing on the roles
of technology, giant corporations, and mass communications in the decline of demo cracy
and the erosion of the moral responsibility of individuals. They were to become best
known for theories of 'the totally administered society', analysing the increasing power of
capitalism and bureaucracy over all aspects of social life and the development of new
forms of social control. They propounded research programmes that influenced many
aspects of European Social theory until the 1970s.
In a key article titled 'Traditional and Critical Theory', of 1937, Max Horkheimer argued that
modern philosophy and science since Descartes suffered from abstraction and *objectivism, cut off
from social practice. In opposition to this 'traditional theory' and especially to *positivism, the new
'critical theory' would be grounded in social theory and Marxian political economy. It would mount
a systematic critique of existing society, allying itself to efforts to produce alternatives to
capitalism and the monstrosity of fascism. Horkheimer proclaimed that critical theory would expose
the way 1n which 'the concepts that thoroughly dominate the economy' metamorphose 'into their
opposites: fair exchange into a deepening of social injustice; a free economy into monopolistic
domination; productive labour into the strengthening of relations which inhibit production; the
maintenance of society's life into the impoverishment of the people's' (1937: 247). The goal of
critical theory was to transform these social
industria I organization where mediated objects exhibit the same features as other
products of mass production: *commodification, standardization, and massification. In
their view, the culture industries had the specific function of providing ideological
*legitimation for capitalist society and integrating individuals into its way of life.
Mass culture and communications stood at the centre of leisure activity in an industrial
society as agencies of socialization and mediators of political reality. They were
therefore to be seen as major institutions of modern life with a variety of economic,
political, and cultural effects. In particular, the critical theorists were among the first to
examine the impact of a consumer society on the very classes who were supposed to be
the instrument of revolution in classical Marxism. They analysed the ways in which
consumption and the culture industries function to stabilize capitalism. Accordingly,
they sought for new agencies and models of political emancipation that could serve as
norms for social science.
The two theorists most closely linked with the concept of the culture industry are Walter
*Benjamin and Theodor*Adorno. Although Benjamin was not formally a member of the
Frankfurt School, he exerted a profound influence over it and has been closely associated
with the spirit of its work. It is to his writing that we turn first.
162 DOUGLAS KELLNER
in German in 1947 (based on an earlier manuscript of 1944). They argued that the system
of cultural production dominated by film, radio broadcasting, newspapers, and magazines
was controlled by advertising and commercial imperatives, functioning to instil sub
servience to consumer capitalism. They sketched out a vision of history from the Greeks
to the present that argued reason and *enlightenment turned into their opposite,
transform ing what promised to be vehicles of truth and liberation into tools of
domination. Under the pressure of societal systems, reason became *instrumental,
reducing human beings to objectified things and nature to numerical quantities. Such
modes of abstraction enabled science and technology to develop apace, but at the same
time produced a moral void that led to social psychosis, culminating in the concentration
camps of the fascist and Soviet communist regimes. As science and technology created
tools of extermination, culture degenerated into mass entertainment, while democracy
collapsed into fascism based on mass popular support for charismatic leaders. This
perverse 'dialectic of enlightenment' induced individuals to dominate over their own
bodies and to renounce their innermost needs and desires by assimilating themselves to a
system that turned them into passive agents of war and persecution.
Although many critics have seen Adorno and Horkheimer's approach as too focused on
the idea of manipulation and mass deception, it provides an important corrective to more
populist approaches to media culture that tend to downplay the ways in which media
industries exert power over audiences and tend to induce conformist behaviour (see the
discussions in Kellner 1989a, 1995). We should also note that in sharply criticizing
enlightenment scientism and rationalism in relation to systems of this domination,
Adorno and Horkheimer implicated Marxism to a certain extent in this 'dialectic of
enlightenment'. For in their view Marxism, too, at least in its reductive and dogmatic
forms, affirmed the primacy of labour and instrumental reason in its celebration of
'socialist production' and 'progress'.
After the Second World War, Adorno and Horkheimer returned to Frankfurt to
re-establish the Institute for Social Research in Germany, while Herbert Marcuse and Leo
*Lowenthal and others remained in the USA. In 1966 Adorno published a major work of
philosophical method, Negative Dialectics, in which he sought to redeem Hegel's concep
tion of dialectical contradictions and syntheses as the logical motor of historical change.
Adorno gave qualified support to what Marx had demonstrated as Hegel's *idealist
reifica tion of the material bases of social life. Adorno saw himself as pursuing Hegel's
principle of dialectical 'negativity' in a way in which Hegel himself had betrayed through
support of the Prussian national state as the most authentic agency of social belonging.
Negativity for
/\dorno meant a work of exposing the disparity between the manifest ideals of
society ideals of liberty, equality, fraternity-and the actual reality of social repression.
It meant demonstrating the difference, the 'non-identity', as Adorno called it, between
concepts and things, or between values and ideas on the one hand and the material status
quo on the other. In his last major work, Aesthetic Theory, of 1970, Adorno applied this
conception to an understanding of *modernist art as a possible vehicle of truth and
enlightenment about the 'system of illusions' that was consumer capitalism. Adorno
proposed that in the mod ernist work of art-which he saw exemplified in the work of
experimental composers such as Arnold Schoenberg and Alban Berg and avant-garde
writers and dramatists such as Samuel Beckett-it was possible to discern a mode of
aesthetic experience which threw
164 DOUGLAS KELLNER
light on the way intrinsically sensuous experiences are reduced by capitalist consumerism
to purely functional bodily gratification.
During this period the Frankfurt theorists engaged in frequent methodological and
substantive debates with other social theories, most notably in The Positivist Dispute in
German Sociology, edited by Adorno (1969). In this work they criticized more empirical
and quantitative approaches to social theory, including notably Karl *Popper's
conception of empiricism and 'value-free' science. Against Popper, they defended
their own more speculative and politicized brand of social research.
important role of the media in politic and to ways in which corporate commercial forces
tend to colonize this sphere for their own interests.
Habermas's distinctive version of critical theory introduced elements of linguistic
philosophy and empirical sociological theory that had been ignored by earlier members of
the Frankfurt School. In his second major treatise, Knowledge and f/11,nan lntercsts (1968),
Habermas distinguished between what he called three types of 'cognitive interest' in
science: (1) a 'technical' interest in control and objective causal knowledge, operative in
the natural sciences; (2) a 'practical' interest in hermeneutic historical understanding,
operative in the humanities; and lastly (3) an *'emancipatory' interest at stake in collective
sociologi cal self-knowledge, operative in the critical social science . Habermasargued
that the eman cipatory interest of critical social science brings together the interest of the
natural sciences in causal explanation with the interest of the humanities in historical and
intercultural understanding. In Habermas's model, critical social science views the
theoretical idea of true knowledge about social life as bcing internally linked to the
practical pursuit of justice in political life. Habermas saw this conception of emancipatory
sociological knowledge as exemplified both in Marx's conception of the critique of
ideology and in Sigmund *Freud's conception of psychoanalysis as a work of overcoming
repressive pathological forms of con sciousness. Both Marxian ideology critique and
Freudian psychoanalysis represented forms of cognitive liberation from coercive and
illusory structures of communication.
In later work from the late 1970s onwards, however, Habermas withdrew trom some
central elements of this thesis. His most distinctive break with the earlier Frankfurt
School occurred in his two-volume work The Theory of Communicative Action (1981a,
1981b), which is discussed at length in Chapter 13 of this book.
In surveying the field of critical theory, one observes a heterogeneity of projects loosely
connected by commitment to interdisciplinary analysis and an interest in radical social
critique. In the 1960s the field of critical theory came to be complemented both by more
activist forms of Marxism and by more academic forms. Four particular strands stand
out in this period. The first is the work of Herbert *Marcuse in the USA. The second is
the proliferation of *existentialist and autonomist Marxism in France and Italy. The third
is the emergence of *'structuralist' and 'analytical' Marxism in the 1970s. The fourth is the
rise of 'Cultural Studies' in Britain and the USA since the late 1970s. We now look at
these four strands in turn.
to the dialectical thinking of Hegel, thematizing the unity of theory and practice, or
'praxis' in the popular term of the 1960s. His next book Eros and Civilization, of 1955,
combined Marxism with Freudian psychoanalytic ideas. In this text, Marcuse's emphasis
on polymorphic sexual liberation, play, utopian desire, and cultivation of an aesthetic
ethos anticipated the counter-culture of the 1960s.
In One-Dimensional Man of 1964 Marcuse theorized the decline of revolutionary poten
tial in capitalist societies and the development of new forms of social control. Marcuse
argued that what he called 'advanced industrial society' creates false needs that bind
individuals into the existing system of production and consumption. In this argument,
mass media culture, advertising, industrial management, and liberal discourse reproduce
the existing system and attempt to eliminate critique and opposition. The result is a 'one
dirnensional' universe of thought and behaviour in which aptitudes for critical thinking
begin to wither away. Marcuse here questioned two of the fundamental premises of
orthodox Marxism: the idea of the proletariat as a reliable source of revolutionary opposi
tion and the idea of the inevitability of capitalist breakdown. Rather than locating forces
of revolutionary change exclusively in the working class, Marcuse championed the non
integrated forces of minorities, outsiders, and the radical intelligentsia, hoping to nourish
oppositional thought and behaviour through what he called 'the great refusal'. Where the
old Left had embraced Soviet Marxism in a doctrinaire and puritanical way, the New Left
under Marcuse's influence combined critical Marxism with ideas of participatory democ
racy and an openness to a range of pluralistic alliances, embracing social movements
around issues of gender, race, sexuality, peace, and the environment. Marcuse tirelessly
criticized 'advanced industrial society' with its concomitant militarism, racism, sexism,
imperialism, and its violent colonial intervention in developing countries in the so-called
'Third World' (see also Marcuse 1968, 1969, 1998a, 1998b).
stimulus came in the work of Guy *Debord, author of The Society o{lhe Spectacle (1967) and
the central figure in the anarchist Situationist movement which militated for revolution ary
alternatives to consumerist escapism and pectacular distraction from misery. In these
years many younger French intellectuals turned to the new forms of Marxism, including
Jean *Baudrillard and Jean-Frarn;ois *Lyotard, who would later become part of a *post
structuralist and *postmodernist movement that went beyond Marxism. Influenced by
George *Bataille and other maverick thinkers, Baudrillard's early work developed neo
Marxian critiques of the consumer society, exploring diverse utopian alternatives (see fur
ther Kellner 1989b). In the 1970s, however, Baudrillard declared that the emergence of a
new postmodernity required altogether different forms of theory and politics, thus break
ing with Marxism (for further dbcussion ofl3audrillard's work, see Chapter 12 of this
book, pp. 263-5).
In Italy in the 1970s, a form of Marxism developed known as 'autonomist Marxism',
notably around the work of Antonio *Negri (1976). Autonomist Marxism sought to
develop revolutionary politics outside the official European communist parties as these
were deemed to be compromised by reformist attitudes. Harry Cleaver (1979) criticized
the Frankfurt School and other forms of Western Marxism for exaggerating the power of
capi talist hegemony and underestimating the force of working-class opposition. This
outlook continues in Michael Hardt and Antonio Negri's book Empire (2000), which
presents con tradictions in globalization in terms of an imperializing logic of 'Empire' and
an assortment of struggles by the 'multitude'. Hardt and Negri present the emergence of
'Empire' in forms of sovereignty, economy, culture, and struggle that open the new
millennium to an unfore seeable flow of political surprises and upheavals.
The variety of approaches that have come to be known in the Anglophone world as
'cultural studies' first emerged in Britain in the 1960s at a time of widespread sympathy
for socialism. The historical forms analysed by the earliest phase of British cultural
studies in the 1950s articulated conditions in an era in which there were still significant
tensions in much of Europe between an older working-class culture and newer commercial
kinds of popular culture emanating from the American culture industries. The initial
project of cultural studies developed hy Richard *Haggart, Raymond *Williams, and E. P.
*Thompson attempted to preserve working-class culture against the onslaughts of
commercial mass culture. Thompson's enquiries into the history of British working-class
struggles and the defences of working-class culture by Haggart and Williams were part of
a socialist project that regarded the industrial proletariat as a force for egalitarian social
change. Williams and Haggart supported projects of working-class education, viewing
cultural studies as an instrument of social progress.
The attacks of Thompson, Haggart, and Williams on Americanism and commercialism
in the late 1950s and early 1960s partly paralleled the earlier work of the Frankfurt
School. Yet the British writers valorized a working class that the Frankfurt School had
seen as defeated by fascism in Europe and as unlikely to recover itself as a united class force.
Slightly later in Britain, a second wave of cultural studies emerged at the Centre for
Contemporary Cultural Studies at Ilirmingham University, led by the Jamaican-British
theorist Stuart
*Hall (Hall et al. 1980). The Birmingham School was continuous with the Hoggart
Thompson-Williams 'culture and society' tradition, as well as with the Frankfurt School.
But the 13irmingham School eventually paved the way for a more popuiist of
'postmodern' in cultural studies.
WESTERN MARXISM 169
The Birmingham scholars developed a variety of critical approaches for the analysis
and interpretation of cultural artefacts (see further McGuigan 1992; Kellner 1995). They
came to focus on the interplay of representations of class, gender, race, ethnicity, and
nationality in cultural texts, including media culture. They were among the first to focus
on how audiences actively interpreted media culture in varied ways and contexts,
analysing the factors that guided their responses. Employing Gramsci's model of
hegemony and counter-hegemony, they identified both elements of domination and
elements of resistance, struggle, and creativity.
Like the Frankfurt School, British cultural studies concluded that mass culture
played an important role in integrating the working class into existing capitalist
societies and that mass consumerism represented a new mode of capitalist hegemony.
Both traditions at the same time identified forces of resistance to capitalist society, and
both the Frankfurt theorists and the earlier forerunners of British cultural studies,
especially Raymond Williams, looked to high culture, including avant-garde art and
literature, as critical vehi cles of political consciousness raising. But unlike the
Frankfurt School, the later British writers valorized elements of resistance in popular
media culture and in audience uses of media artefacts. In contrast, the Frankfurt
School tended, with some exceptions, to see mass culture as an undifferentiated,
homogenized tissue of domination-a difference that would seriously divide the two
traditions.
In addition to studies of working-class culture, the Birmingham School focused on the
potential of youth subcultures for resistance to hegemonic forms of capitalist society. The
British scholars considered how popular culture made possible distinct youth identities
and certain potentially counter-hegemonic forms of group membership. They studied
patterns of conformity to dominant political ideologies in dress and fashion codes carried
by members of the upwardly mobile white middle classes, and they demonstrated how
subcultural groups could resist these forms by creating their own styles and identities.
They pointed, for example, to black nationalist subcultures, to the punk movement, and to
Asian and Jamaican-British forms of ethnic contestation (compare Hall and Jefferson
1976; Hehdige 1979). In contrast, the only member of the earlier Frankfurt School to treat
youth culture as a serious political force was Marcuse.
Yet one problem with cultural studies is that it has rarely engaged adequately with
modernist and avant-garde aesthetic movements. In its concern to legitimize the study of
popular media culture, it has tended to turn away from so-called 'high' culture and to
ignore the equally potentially oppositional dynamics of more 'advanced' forms of art,
music and literature. In so doing, it has run a risk of bifurcating the field of culture into
'elite' and 'popular' in way that only inverts the positive/negative connotations of the
older distinction between 'high' and 'low'. We need to be aware that early twentieth
century avant-garde movements such as expressionism, dada, and surrealism sought to
develop cultural forms that would revolutionize society, and that access to the avant-garde
elements of modernist art has not always been simply a privilege of dominant social
classes and groups (compare Burger 1974; Huyssen 1986).
British cultural studies has had a complex relation to Marxism since its beginnings.
/\!though Stuart Hall (1983) and Richard Johnson (1987) grounded cultural studies in a
Marxian model of the circuits of capital (production-distribution-consumption
production), Hall and other figures in cultural studies have not always pursued economic
170 OOUtilAS KHLF.tl1
Conclusion
Whereas the work of Marx and Engels was inspired and shaped by the revolutionary
movements of 1848, the construction and spread of a tradition of Western Marxism in the
twentieth century was promoted by the success of the Bolshevik revolution of 1917 and
then later by the cultural movements of the 1960s. Students and young militants through
out the world sought a version of critical and revolutionary Marxism independent of the
orthodoxies and compromises of political parties and regimes such as the Soviet Union .
They rejected scientistic kinds of Marxism in favour of more open-ended and less
dogmatic thinking. In recent decades, Western Marxism has been supplemented, and to
some extent supplanted, by more diverse forms of theory such as post-structuralism,
psychoanalytic theory, discourse analysis, feminist theory, multiculturalism, and
postcolonial theory. Nevertheless, it continues to be a vital strand of contemporary theory
and research. Writers such as Lukacs, Gramsci, Bloch, Benjamin, Adorno, Marcuse, and
others continue to be of interest. Although they no longer enjoy the same intellectual
hegemony they once held in some circles of the Left, their writings remain an important
component of the tools of con temporary social theory. Marxism continues to provide
insights into multiple contempo rary problems and crises-from globalization to ecology,
terrorism, imperialism, power, technocracy, postmodernism, and the information society.
171
The 1970s saw many debates and developments in Western Marxism. We may note that in 1973
Habermas wrote a study of what he called the *'legitimation crisis' in 'late capitalism', arguing that the
post-war social-democratic policies of wealth redistribution in Western European states could no
longer expect to confer legitimacy on the fundamental tendencies of capitalist economics (Habermas
1973). By the 1980s, however, as the Western European economies seemed to recover from the
industrial disputes of the 1970s and the incumbent governments made a turn toward neo-liberal
free-market policies, this sense of a basic problem of 'legitimacy' in capitalism seemed to retreat from
mainstream public opinion. Political passions were cooling and an era of conservativism was
inaugurated. The collapse of communism in Eastern Europe and the Soviet Union in the late 1980s
and early 1990s presaged a turn away from Marxism in academic social science toward newer
forms of
*postmodernist, *post-structuralist, and multicultural approaches, as well as a turn by many
former leftists to liberal theory and politics.
One characteristic line of argument was taken by Aronson (1995) who maintained that
Marxism's nineteenth-century roots made It difficult to adapt to the changed conditions of the late
twentieth cen tury. Aronson asserted that Marxism had never adequately addressed distinctively
twentieth-century issues of gender, race, sexuality, and other forms of exclusion, focusing too
narrowly on economic factors and questions of class. Classical Marxism's hopes for revolution
had been grounded in the historical forces of its time. But when the political parties and social
classes that been the foundation of its hopes were defeated and the original doctrines could no
longer account for the complexities of reality, it was time, Aronson argued, to move beyond
Marxism to new theories and politics.
Ernesto Laclau and Chantal Mouffe's Hegemony and Socialist Strategy, first published in 1985, helped
shape an influential version of 'post-Marxism' that criticized orthodox models and developed a concep
tion of 'radical democracy' based on 'new social movements'. A later dialogue between Laclau, Judith
*Butler, and Slavoj *Zizek continued to reconstruct the Western Marxist project on post-structuralist
and mult1culturalist lines (Butler et al. 2000).
Several theorists have also sought to explain the collapse of communism from the standpoint
of Marxist premises and to appraise the future of Marxism after the demise of the Soviet Union. Some
writ ers have used Marxism to explain the flaws of orthodox Marxism and the reasons for the Soviet
collapse. Thus Kagarlitsky (1990) argued that Soviet communism betrayed Marxist principles, that it
oppressed and alienated the working class and thus produced its own opposition. Likewise,
Callinicos (1991) argued that the Soviet Union never departed from Leninist and Stalinist
orthodoxy and that it was necessary to return to more authentic modes of revolutionary Marxism
represented by Trotsky. Others argued that the Soviet Union failed to keep up with technological
development while images of a more affluent life in neighbouring capitalist countries created
.
disillusion, opposition, and eventually upheaval (see Blackburn 1991; Magnus and Cullenberg 1995,
Callari et al. 1995).
In general, it has been argued that the collapse of communism cannot be regarded In any simplistic
sense as proof of the error, naivety or obsolescence of Marxist ideas. On the one hand, the long-
lasting political repressions and eventual implosion of the Soviet experiment certainly raise serious
l
questions about the capacity of the Marxist vision of society to inform morally valid ins.titutional
arrangements for the administration of justice and the sponsoring of well-being in society. It has
been argued that Marxism never provided an adequate account of the moral bases of politics, in the
sense of determin ing just institutional arrangements for the recognition and reward of individual
virtue and individual
· continues
172 DOUGLAS i<Ei.lNER
BOX 20 continued
moral responsibility-largely because it has tended to regard existing moral problems in world culture as essentially r
In what ways do the Western Marxists build on the doctrines of Marx? In what ways do
they depart from them?
2 How should the concept of ideology be defined? Is all ideology 'false consciousness'?
If not, why not?
3 In what respects does the Frankfurt School's idea of critical theory diverge from 'traditional
theory' or positive science?
4 Is the Frankfurt School's critique of mass culture 'elitist'? How far do more recent writers
provide a better understanding of cultural life?
5 In what sense has Marxism declined over the twentieth and twenty-first centuries?
FURTHER READING
Some good overviews of Western Marxism are Perry Anderson's Considerations on Western Marxism
(Verso, 1976), Stephen Bronner's of Critical Theory and its Theorists (Routledge, 2002), Russell
Jacoby's Dialectic of Defeat (Cambridge University Press, 1981), Leszek Kolakowski's Main Currents
o( Marxism, 3 vols. (Oxford University Press, 1978), Kevin Anderson's Lenin, Hegel and Western
Marxism (University of Illinois Press, 1995), and Moishe Postone's Time, Labor and Social Domination: A
Reinterpretation of Marx's Critical Theory (Cambridge University Press, 1993).
The key source for Marx and Engels's classical conception of ideology is The German Ideology
(Lawrence & Wishart, 1975). Among numerous discussions of this conception are Stuart Hall's arti
cle 'The Problem of Ideology: Marxism without Guarantees', in Betty Matthews (ed.), Marx:
A Hundred Years On (Lawrence & Wishart, 1983), Abercrombie et al., The Dominant Ideology
11iesis (Allen & Unwin, 1980), Douglas Kellner's article 'Ideology, Marxism, and Advanced
Capitalism', Socialist Review, 42 (Nov.-Dec. 1978), 37-65, and the texts on Gramsci and the
Birmingham School cited below. For an interesting analysis, see also Alvin Gouldner's The Dialectic
of Ideology and Technology (Seabury Press, 1977) as well as Gouldner's TheTwo Marxisms
(Macmillan, 1980).
173
On the work of Ernst Bloch, seeJamie Daniel and Tom Moylan's edited Not Yet: Reconsidering
Ernst Bloch (Verso, 1997). For some uses of Bloch's dialectic of ideology and utopia in
contemporary cultural studies, see FredricJameson's article 'Reification and Utopia in Mass Culture',
Social Text, 1: 130-48, as well as Jameson's Late Marxism: Adorno, Or the Persistence of the
Dialectic (Verso, 1990). On Gramsci, ideology, and hegemony, seeJorge Larrain's The Concept of
Ideology (Hutchinson, 1979) and Marxism and Ideology (Macmillan, 1983), Chantal Mouffe's
edited Gramsci and Marxist Theory (Routledge, 1979), and Carl Boggs's The nvo Revolutions.
Antonio Eramsin and the Dilemmas of Western Marxism (South End Press, 1984). The classic
essays of Walter Benjamin, including 'The Work of Art in the Age of Mechanical Reproduction',
are collected in Benjamin's Illuminations, ed. Hannah Arendt (Cape, 1970). For an introduction
to Benjamin, try Graeme Gilloch's Walter Benjamin: Critical Constellations (Polity Press, 2002). For
an equally pioneering mode of cultural critique similar to Bloch and Benjamin, see Siegfried
Kracauer's The Mass Ornament (Harvard University Press, 1963), based on essays originally
written in German in the 1920s and 1930s.
Some good overviews of the Frankfurt School are Martin Jay's The Dialectical Imagination: A
History of the Frankfurt School and the institute of Social Research, 1923-1950 (Heinemann, 1973)
and Seyla Benhabib's Critique, Norm and Utopia: A Study of the Foundations of Critical Theory
(Columbia University Press, 1986), also Martin Jay's Marxism and Totality (Polity Press, 1984),
Douglas Kellner's Critical Theory, Marxism and Modernity (Johns Hopkins University Press, 1989),
David Held's Introduction to Critical Theory (Polity, 1990), and Rolf Wiggershaus's The Frankfurt
School: Its fiistory, Theories, and Political Significance (Polity Press, 1994). Some good collections of
readings from the Frankfurt School are Andrew Arato and Eike Gebhardt's edited The Frankfurt School
Reader (Continuum, 1976) and Stephen Bronner and Douglas Kellner's edited Politics, Culture and
Society: A Critical Theory Reader (Routledge, 1989). The key collection of Adorno's writings on the
culture industry is Adorno's The Culture Industry, ed. Jay Bernstein (Routledge, 1991). See also Brian
O'Connor's edited Adorno Reader (Blackwell, 2000). Two good introductions to Adorno are Martin
Jay's Adorno (Harvard University Press, 1984) and SimonJarvis'sAdorno: A Critical Introduction
(Polity Press, 1998). For a concise account of the Frankfurt School in relation to art and
aesthetics, see Austin Harrington's Art and Social Theory: Sociological Arguments in Aesthetics
(Polity Press, 2004), chapter 6. Adorno himself is difficult to read. A good place to begin is his short book
Minima Moralia (Verso, 1981).
The best introduction to the early work of Habermas is Thomas McCarthy's The Critical Theory of
Jurgen Habermas (MIT Press, 1978). A good collection of essays on Habermas on the public sphere is
Craig Calhoun's edited Habermas and the Public Sphere (MIT Press, 1992). See also Box 28 in Chapter
11 of the present book on Nancy Fraser's feminist perspective on the public sphere. See also
Douglas Kellner's essay 'Habermas, the Public Sphere, and Democracy: A Critical Intervention', in
Lewis Hahn's edited Perspectives on Habermas (Open Court, 2000). On Marcuse, see Douglas
Kellner's Herbert Marcuse and the Crisis of Marxism (University of California Press, 1984) John
Bokina and Timothy Lukes's edited Marcuse: From the New Left to the Next Left (University of
Kansas Press, 1994). For further sources on Marxism in British and American cultural studies, see
Stuart Hall et al. (eds.), Culture, Media, Language (Hutchinson, 1980), and University of
Birmingham Centre for Contemporary Cultural Studies (ed.), On Ideology (Hutchinson, 1978). See
also Richard Johnson's article 'What is Cultural Studies Anyway?', in Social Text, 16 (1986/7), Jim
McGuigan's Cultural Populism (Routledge, 1992), Douglas Kellner's Media Culture: Cultural
Studies, Identity and Politics between the Modern and the Postmodern (Routledge, 1995), and loan
Davies's Cultural Studies and Beyond (Routledge, 1995). A useful reader is Meenakshi Durham and
Douglas Kellner (eds.), Media and Cultural Studies: Key Works (Blackwell, 2001). For some Marxist
perspectives on postmodernism, see David Harvey's The Condition of Postmodernity
(Blackwell, 1989), Fredric Jameson's Postmodernism, or the Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism
(Verso, 1991), Alex Callinicos's Against Postmodernism (Polity Press, 1990), Steven Best and
Douglas Kellner's Postmodern Theory: Critical Interrogations (Macmillan, I991), and Steven Best
and Douglas Kellner's The Postmodern Adventure:
174 lflOUGil\S !{Hi f\li'll
Science Technology, and Cultural Studies at the Third Millennium (Routledge, 2001). See also the titles in
the Further Reading guidance for Chapter 12 and 13 of this book.
if' WEBSITES
Psychoanalysis, as developed by Sigmund *Freud and his followers, has had a major
impact on social theory and modern sociology. Freud's central discoveries-the uncon
scious, sexual repression, the Oedipus complex, and the like-have been deployed by
sociologists to theorize the self and human *subjectivity, *gender and sexuality, the
family and socialization, language and *ideology, as well as the formation ot cultural
identities and forms of political *domination. Throughout the twentieth and twenty-first
centuries, social theorists have engaged with the psychoanalytic tradition in order to
conceptualize the relation between the individual and society, including the complex,
contradictory ways that human subjects acquire, reshape, and transform the ideas,
values, symbols, beliefs, and
176 ANJHONY HLIOTT
emotional dispositions of the wider society. This has been particularly evident over recent
decades as Freudian themes and psychoanalytic motifs have been used to analyse sexual
politics, issues of identity and lifestyle, and the nature of modernity and postmodernity.
This chapter looks at some of the most important elements of Freud's legacy for socio
logical thinking today. We also discuss some influential post-freudian psychoanalytic the
orists who came to prominence in the 1940s and 1950s onwards. These include the French
theorist Jacques Lacan and more recent figures active since the 1960s, including Gilles
*Deleuze, Felix *Guattari, Slavoj *Zizek and the feminist theorists Julia *Kristeva, Nancy
*Chodorow, and Jessica *Benjamin.
in his late writings on civilization-that has had greatest influence. In his late writings,
Freud comes to see human beings as living under the destructive force of a terrifying
death drive, based on strict cultural prohibitions on sexual desire and enjoyment. These
themes are set out in his magisterial books Beyond the Pleasure Principle (1920) and
Civilization and its Discontents (1930). Civilization, Freud proposes, is repressive. Society
imposes psychic demar:ict upon individuals to achieve cultural conformity, demands that
can produce intense personal misery ana neur6tk suff ring:-----' -
According to Freud, ambivalence is at the core of an individual's relation to itself and to
others. Just as the ego seeks to establish order and control over the disruptive unconscious, so
cultural ideas must incorporate the deeper emotional strivings of social members, pressing the
'pleasure principle' into the service of the 'reality principle'. This is necessary, Freud contends,
for the very reproduction of social life. The development of civilization, of social bonds, and
the injunction to labour, all depend upon self-control. Yet it is precisely at this point, where a
disjunction emerges between individual desire and social necessity, that Freud locates cultural
pathology. The fundamental problem for Freud is that culture tends to rob the individual
su!)ject of unfettered instinctual enjoyn1t,>nt, and places gigantic restrictions on sexuality.
Listening to the anxieties of his bourgeois patients each day in Vienna at the turn of the
nineteenth century, Freud discovered a deep connection between personal, inner desires and
the repressive social forms that engender excessive self-control. The denial of feelings, the
structuring of sexuality into narrow paths of monogamy and marital legitimacy, and the rigid
(male) insistence on genital monosexuality: these are, Freud argues, the oppressive emotional
wounds inflicted by culture. Imposing order on the free flow of unconscious desire is a key
task of civilization; but the balance between desire and order is constantly changing and
can easily become too great burden for individuals and collectivities. When the imposition
of social control, order, and structure results in repressive *closure, cultural life is liable to
self-annihilation.
In his early writings, Freud understands the way in which individuals comet<?_
confront social regulation in terms_of the polar opposites of desire and control, pleasure
and reality, sexuality and ·self preservation. Central to this structuring process of
prohibition and re pression is the Oedipus ·complex; which Freud outlines in his classic
early work The Interpretation of Dreams, of 1900. The intervention of the father into the
child-mother dyad is of key importance for grasping the institutionalization of moral
imperatives, primarily because the paternal role is symbolic and thus su_ggestive of social
regulation. In the an cient Greek myth, the young boy Oedipus is fated to murder his
father and sleep with his mother. In studying the significance of this myth, Freud traced
the origins of collective moral prohibitions back in history to a mythical event. The
theorem of an original parri cide, of a murder of the father, led Freud in Totem and Taboo
(1913) to speak of a collective Oedipal moral imperative. Freud paints a picture of a
'primal horde', a collectivity of brothers dominated by an all-powerful father who
monopolizes women. In anger and frustration, the brothers eventually kill and eat the
father. Due to ambivalence and guilt, however, the brothers come to feel remorse for the
killing. This unconscious anguish induces the brothers to identify with the dead father as a
*'totem', and to invent moral rnstraints against the free expression of sexual desire. Just as
in the Oedipal fantasy itself, the terror of the father is now 'owned' on the 'inside'. The
regulation of society is instituted through a renunciation of desire, registered in the taboo
against incest.
178 ANIHONY ELLIOTT
Freud's most developed account of culture and morality as a work of socially organized
'sublimation' is developed in his late book Civilization and its Discontents (1930). This is
discussed in Box 21.
In Civilization and its Discontents (1930), Freud develops a conception of the 'death -drive' as both the
object and means of a system of repression laying the foundations of culture. Freud's theory of the death
drive entails a radical reinterpretation of the organization of modern culture. By the death drive Freud
understands a will to make clean, to purify, to return to order. Human misery and oppression are no
longer Understood as the outcome of sexual repression alone. Instead, Freud comes to equate culture
with a fundamental constraint on self-destructiveness. Civilization protects against certain essentially
aggressive liabilities of the death drive. 'The main renunciation culture demands of the individual', writes
Paul *Ricoeur (1965: 307) of Freud's metapsychology, 'is the renunciation not of desire as such but of 1
aggressiveness'.
By incorporating this new dualism into his analysis of modern culture, Freud is able to rewrite the
problem of self and society as a contest between love and hate, or between love and death. Love is the
principle of civilized co-belonging. Hatred and the death drive are forces that threaten to tear this apart.
The Freud of Civilization and its Discontents unfolds love and death, eras and thanatos (Greek
words for 'love and 'death', respectively), in the following way:
[C]ivilization is a process in the service of Eros, whose purpose is to combine single human individuals, and
after that families, then races, peoples and nations, into one great unity ... These collections of men are
libidinally bound to one another. Necessity alone, the advantages of work in common, will not hold them
together. But man's natural aggressive instinct, the hostility of each against all and of all against each,
opposes this programme of civilization. The aggressive instinct is the derivative and main representative of
the death drive which we have found alongside Eros and which shares world-dominion with it. (1930:
122)
The pathological compulsions of cultural life are rooted in a repressive structuring of love and
hatred. Freud remains faithful to his earlier view that the reproduction of society depends on sexual
repression; but in his late sociological vision this sexual repression becomes integrated into a
deathly self preservatIon, organized as a destructive assault on the human body, on others, and on
nature. Freud
particularly had in mind the highly authoritarian European societies before the First World War that sent
thousands of young men to their death in 1914. But he also became acutely aware of the
pathologies of fascism, racism, and anti-Semitism in the 1920s and 1930s as a form of breakdown
of civilization, resulting from a transformation or degeneration of sexual repression into a will to
exterminate the alien
and disorderly. Today we may also think of the phenomenon of 'ethnic cleansing', as well as homo
phobia and 'moral panics' about people perceived as deviant.
Freud's writings on the fate of the self in contemporary culture have strongly influenced debates in
social theory, from Herbert *Marcuse (1955) to Michel *Foucault (1976) and many others. Too much
repression, Freud says, leads to intense unconscious anguish, hostility, and rage. At such a point, the
intensification of unconscious desire can release the mental dams of sexual repression in a far-reaching
way. The issue of the subJective seeds of social and political transformation are thus at the heart of
Freud's contribution to sociology and social theory.
179
internalized by human subjects throughout the socialization process. According to Parsons's function
alist appropriation of Freud, the structure of the human personality is the outcome of an internalization
of desired objects, role relationships, and ethico-cultural values that make up the broader social
network. In this approach, it is the linkage of personality structure, the social system, and the cultural
system that is stressed (see Parsons, 1964).
----- --------- continues
PSYCHOANALYTIC SOCIAL THEORY 181
Box 22 continued
Unlike Marcuse's and Adorno's emphasis on social manipulation of the unconscious, Parsons found
a kind of pre-established harmony between the individual and society. While Parsons's attempt to
blend sociological theory with psychoanalysis has few followers today, some aspects of this work have
con tinued to be influential. Another exponent of a fusion of Freudian ideas with socialization theory is
the German sociologist Norbert *Elias (1939), whose work on 'civilization' and *'civilizing processes' is
dis
cussed in Chapter 6 of this book.
the other was commonly regarded as the most important work in this sub-field of modern
sociology. However, from the late 1960s onwards, the impact of French theory,
particularly
*structuralist and *post-structuralist philosophy, became increasingly influential in under
standings of the social dimensions of psychoanalysis.
The key figure in this connection was Freud's French interpreter Jacques *Lacan.
Seeking to rework the core concepts of psychoanalysis in light of structural linguistics,
Lacan argued that the unconscious exemplifies key linguistic features. Lacan famously
stated that 'the unconscious is structured like a language' (1973: 48). The subject, or the 'I',
according to Lacan, is not transparent to itself. Rather, it is located in a system of
signification from which identity is fashioned. For Lacan, linguistic *intersubjectivity is at
the centre of psy chological functioning and its disturbances. Distortions and pathologies
at the level of the self are, Lacan says, located in 'the discourse of the Other'. Among the
most central com ponents of Lacan's work are, first, his conception of the 'Mirror Stage'
in the formation of the ego, secondly his triangular conception of 'the Imaginary', 'the
Symbolic' and 'the Real', and thirdly his distinctive use of the structural linguistic theory
of Ferdinand de Saussure. We look at these three components in turn.
One of Lacan's most influential texts is his essay from 1949, 'The Mirror Stage as
Formative of the Function of the l' (1949). In this essay, Lacan conceptualizes the infant's
initial recognition of itself in a mirror or a reflecting surface, and how this generates a
sense of identity. Through the mirror, Lacan argues, the infant makes an *imaginary
identifica tion with its reflected image, an identification to which the infant reacts with a
sense of jubilation and exhilaration. But the mirror image of the self is, in fact, a
distortion: the mirror lies. The mirror stage is radically 'imaginary', since the consoling
unified image of selfhood which it generates is diametrically opposed to the actual bodily
fragmentation and lack of coordination of the child. According to Lacan, these imaginary
traps and dis tortions are a universal and timeless feature of self-organization. Lacan sees
such illusions as directly feeding into and shaping pathologies of the self in contemporary
culture.
Lacan's thinking in psychoanalysis revolves around three hasic concepts that stand in a
triangular relation to one another: the concept of the Imaginary, the concept of the
Symbolic, and the concept of the Real. By the 'Imaginary', Lacan means the mental
images projected by a particular individual self, a subject, in order to make sense of the
chaos of its impressions, sensations, and desires. By the 'Symbolic', Lacan means the
public code of language, the public order of legitimate standards of sense and reference
and expected norms of conduct. The Symbolic order pre-structures the Imaginary for any
individual subject. A child is inducted into the Symbolic order by its parents, through the
workings of
182 t N,HONY [LLIOYT
the Oedipus complex. B, the 'Real', Lacan means every experience which erupts into
the Imaginary or the Symbolic from the out.side ever} experience of a brute intensity-
such as pain, shock, horror, or the witnessing of death-which defies the subject's ability
to make
sense of it in an ordered structured wav
fo illustrate Lacan's terminology with a recent and rather sensitiw example, we might
sav that the crashing of the two hijacked aeroplanes into the ½orld Trade Center in '.\.ew
York on 11 September 2001 constituted a traumatic irruption of the Real into the taken-for
gran ted routines L1f the .'11111hi/1t L1fder for\:e\1· \ ,1rkers .SL1i11,s .1\1L,u t t ht'i r d.1i l\ \1usiness. l
n
11 September 2001 the ro,1ts ,1i this S\·mb,1lic L,r,kr in .1 cert.I in !111,1.-.:i11.111 pr,1iec"ti,1n ,,f the
invincible freedom and security of the USA were sudden Iv thrown into question (compare
Zizek 2002).
Lacan was as interested in the symbolic dimensions of culture as he was in the imaginary
drafting of the self. Rewriting the unconscious and the Oedipus complex in terms of the
symbolic dimensions of language, Lacan's central theoretical point of reference was the
structural linguistics of Ferdinand de *Saussure. Saussure's lingui tic theories and their
influenn.' on French structur,1\bt thuu,sht are discussed ,It len th in l·11.1 ptt'r '1 ,,t t h1, l1L1,1k.
lPP· 197'-20rn. The specific relt'\':mce ,1i S,1ussure\ thinkin.s t,1 L.1c.m can l1e briefly st.ltt'd
here as follows.
A.ccording to Saussurian linguistics.1.mguage is ,1 S\·stem ,,i intcm.il differences. Si_sns .ire
composed of a *'signifier' (a sound or image) and a *'siguified' (the concept or meaning e\
·ok.ed). Saus,ure asserts that the relation bet11een the s1p11iier ,md the ,ignit1ed h ,1rh trary
not 'natural'. The meaning of a word arises only through its differences from other
\1·mds: the 1wnd ·pencil·. for e:x,1mple. is nc>ttllc' 11·,1rd ·pen·...\ ·b,1,,1,;· is 11L1t .1 ·p,11111,hkt'. 11c1t
a 'magazine', not a 'newspaper' and so on. ½'ords do not directlv refer to their objects in
the sense l)i ·copYing· or 'rL'Sembl ing· them. Lm.sluge t"reate, 111t'Jnin.s ,,nh thr,,ugh .111
Hlter nal play of difference, bet\1·een sp,1ken or writtc'n elemenb. R,1ugh\\· spe.11--ing.
L1CJn\ Snnbulic correspL1nd,; tL1 Sau,,urc'°s CL)iKept L•i /,111_,71<'. and L1c.m·, lnu.sin-1r1·
c,1rrespL1nd, to Saussure's concept of parole.
Lacan accepts the key ideas of Saussure's structural linguistics, but he radicalizes the rela
tion between the ,i.snllkr and the s1,smiieJ. Lh.'an Jc,es n,,t tc,aL111 S.1usSLire's pri111.1r1
search for the 'signified', or concept or reference. Instead, Lacan inYerts Saussure's inter
pretati,111 L1ithe sign. assertin_s that thL' sigmfitr has pnm.11:Y ,,wr th, sigmtlt'd 111 the pre'·
dLKtion L1I meaning. L1ran ,t.1tes th.it ·rw s1gnific,1tit1n c.m be smt.1ined ,,the'r th.m lw
rl'fl'rL'l1Ce tu ,l!Wther si.sniflcattL•n .. \\e ,,·ill tail t,,1ursue thequesti,111 further .is 1,,ng .1,
we cling t,1 the illusi,111 that the' ,igniiier .ms\1ers t,1 the functiL1n L1i representin.s the si.s111-
fied. ,H bl'tter, th.it the signifier has t,1 answer t,1r ib t',istence in the n.mw L'i .m, sip1ific.1-
tion whatever . _ . \Ve are forced ... to accept the notion of an incessant sliding of the
signified under the signifier' (1957: 165, 166, 170).
Lacan goes on to propose that the signifier is itself coterminous \\ith the unconscious.
!'hi means th,lt l.111p1.1,sc. ,1, .1 ,ntem ui diifert?nce . ,,,11'-ritut,·., the> sub1t',·t · rccpressed
desire through and through. The subject, once severed from the narcissistic fullness of
thl' [111,1gin.lf\'. is in,erted intL1 linguistic and \YlllbL1llc ,tructurt'\ th.It b,,th i<',lt'r,ltt' tlw
unconscious and allow for its contents to traverse the intersubjective field of culture. At the
same time, access to ourselves and others is complicated by the fact that desire is itself an
·eftect ,1t till' si.snitier'.•m outL wp L1i the spacings ,1r c1itfrrence ,,r lm ubtic ,tructuro:,.
HOANAlYllC SOC.Al THEORY 183
From this angle, the unconscious is less a realm on the 'inside' of the individual, or
'underneath' language, than an intersubjcctive space he/ween subjects-located in thme gaps
which separate word from word, meaning from meaning. Lacan comments that 'the
exteriority of the symbolic in relation to man is the very notion of the unconscious' (1966:
469). It is in this sense that advertising and consumer culture in general can be read in
terms of schemes of displaced desire, as systems of internal symbolic references that
attempt to manufacture a sense of wholeness, health, happiness, and meaning tor the
subject that is in fact non-existent. These items of culture attempt to paper over conflict,
fragmentation, dissent, pain, and deprivation, through fabrications of unity, consensus,
satisfaction, and contentment.
,t::l·m tr, bt mrm· intt::mally difft::ru1tiatt::d than iih·k H·r r,gr111.r·,. i1ick ,r·r·, Hlr:,,lr,gy a, a
fant;r>y ',ru1arir,, thl: v,lt:: ptHf)(J'>t::<,f whid1 i, tr; fill in <1r, <1w1 ,,vr-r r·lr·rm·nh <>f l,H k. 'f hcrt
i, a pr<,blc-m with thh vir:w in,r,lar a, it tr-nrh t<> flatt1·n r,ut thr· r ,,mplr-x, r 1,ntradir tr,ry
rc, (-[Jt1,,n r,f idr:<Jl<>g1cal f<Jrm, tJy individ11ah. iizr·k ,1·r·, nr, ,ignifi1 ant difff-ru1((· rJctwr:t-n
wh,,t hr:r r,nt:: I'> int h<· grip ()f •idcntity pr JIJ!1< '>,Jf r<-cHling phi Ir,,r ,phy ilnd, l;r,,ir al
Jitcratun· r,r l'.'atching il ·1 V talk-,hr,w hr,,t '>Ulh a, ( Jpr,ih Winfrr:y. ·1 hc·,v ;m· all cqually tr,
be· ,t-l'n a, piu• , ,,f 1dt::<Jl<Jgic;,l fanta,y, aimed at dfar ing th,: v,ur ta,tc· <1f Jar k, gap, and
antilg/Jni,m r,r:r: furthi:r J.lli<,tt 2!J(J21. Jn thh n:,pl·lt, i11t::k ha, a tcndt::nr y t<J pa'>'> <Jvc·r
the multiplt::x
way, in which pt::< ,pl,: UJITT l· t<J c hallr-ngr· JHJl itic al idr·rJl<Jgi(·'>, and tr, t rtat the vtry w<JT,t
and m<J,t ,mi,tl'r idl'<,l<Jgical frJTrnc1tirrn, rJn thr: ,aml' lt::vc·l a, fJthu rtlat1vcly
'prr1grl',,ivl'' or 'intelligent' formations.
·1 h,:,t prrJblr:m, in Ziz<·k can trJ ,rJrnc· cxttnt hr: traced back t<J Lacan\ accrJunt of culturr:.
Li,1an\ linkage <Jt the ,uhject r;f the unuJm<.iou, tcJ thr: idea of tht: arbitrary m1turl: <Jf thl:
·,ign t•·nrh t<J ,;ivt an madl:CJUiltl' acuJUnt <Jf hr,w VJmt: idt<Jl<,giuil and f)(J)itical rnr-;rning,
pruJr,rnmat('. 'AU rJthu, int hr- ,ha ping <Jf t hr.: pt:rv1nal ,phr.:rl:. In sll-ad, 1n Lac.an\ writing,
r ultural drJmmat1rrn is r:quattd with all Janguagr- a, such. A, Utw, (]9i)7J and <Jthl'r critic,
havt ar,;ur:d, /.acan\ rathl:r indhuiminatc· equation rJf languagl: with d<Jmination ,r-ri
r,u,ly rJrJwnplay, the hi,toricu//y 1pr:cific '>latu, r,f p<JWU, iduJlrJgy, and VJC1al in,titution, in
the reproduction of cultural life.
Mothers lead their sons to disengage emotionally from care and intimacy. This
prepares boys for an instrumental and abstract attitude towards the world, an attitudr
which will be expected from them in the public sphere of work and politics.
This account of gender relations suggests that exclusive female mothering produces an
ideology of male domination. The absence of a primary attachment to males in pre
Oedipal childhood leads to an idealization of men and a devaluation of women. The only
way out of this self-reproducing gender system, Chodorow argues, is through shared par
enting. The inclusion of men in early parenting activities should lead to a break-up of
established gender polarity. Both parents would be available to establish a caring, nurtur
ing connection with their children. In this context, children of both sexes would be able to
forge emotional intimacy and autonomy through a primary relatedness to both mother
and father.
Chodorow's work presents a powerful account of those psychosocial forces that distort
gender relations. Her model has exercised great influence (see, for example, Balbus 1982;
Connell 1987). Her claim for a stable gender identity for males and females has proved
attractive to many seeking to understand the persistence of patriarchal domination, and
her arguments about female psychology are illuminating. Of key importance is her
assertion that women want to have children in order to recapture the primary bond of the
mother-daughter relationship. The reasoning is that women's lives are emotionally
drained because men are cut off from sexual intimacy and interpersonal communication.
From this angle, the desire to have a child is rooted in distortions in the current gender
sys tem. Conversely, the abstract traits of male selfhood help to explain the anxieties that
many men experience in relation to intimacy. Masculinity, according to Chodorow,
has come to involve the adoption of intolerance, insensitivity, and emotional
coerciveness. From this angle, male sexual dominance, often involving the use of
violence towards women, has its roots in the damaged, fragile, and precarious nature of
masculine identity.
Chodorow's theory is open to criticism in some respects. There is something too neat
and comfortable in her claim that exclusive female mothering produces asymmetric gen
der roles. She presents a model of woman as primary caretaker, with maternal desire fixed
into either narcissistic or 'anaclitic' modes of identification. But is the institution of moth
ering really so limited to these two psychic categories? What of mothers who encourage
'feminine' modes of expression in their sons? What of the increasing phenomenon of sin
gle-parent, mother-led families? A further problem for some critics is that Chodorow's
con cept of 'core gender identity' returns to a pre-Freudian view of subjectivity, one that
brackets Freud's analysis of infant bisexuality and instead affirms the consoling unity of
personal identity. Consequently, instead of exploring the problematic cultural construc
tion of sexual difference and gender, Chodorow only describes how dominant sex-roles
become interwoven with core masculine and feminine identities. As a whole, her model
resembles a functionalist account of how sexual identities are generated to mirror gender
power in patriarchal modern societies. According to Jacqueline Rose (1986), Chodorow in
this respect fails to get beyond a basic notion of 'gender imprinting'.
A third possible criticism concerns Chodorow's suggestion that under conditions of
shared parenting, men would develop the kind of relational qualities that women possess,
while women would be free to develop personal autonomy. Given Chodorow's own thesis
about gender identity being powerfully shaped in negative and polarizing forms, it is not
so
188 ANTHONY ELLIOTT
clear how women and men might actually liberate themselves from the destructive gender
identities that currently preoccupy them.
In a different manner from Chodorow and Benjamin, Julia *Kristeva's reference point for
situating gender and sexuality is the reading of Freud proposed by Lacan. In her book
Revolution in Poetic Language (1974), Kristeva contrasts Lacan's account of the symbolic
order-the social and sexual system of the Law of the Father-with those multiple psychic
forces which she terms *'semiotic'. According to Kristeva, the 'semiotic' is essentially pre
Ji ngui stic. Semiotic processes include libidinal energies and bodily rhythms experienced
by the child during the pre-Oedipal relationship with the mother. For Kristeva, these
pre-Oedipal forms undergo repression upon entry to the social and cultural processes of
the symbolic order.·1 hat is, the flux of semiotic expenence i channelled into the relatively
table domain of ,ymbolization and language. However, Kristeva contends that the repres
sion of the semiotic is by no means complete. The semiotic remains present in the uncon
scious and cannot be shut off from culture.
Against this p,ychoanalytic backdrop, Kristeva explicitly connects her analysis of fem
ininity with the idea of the maternal. Semiotic longing for the pre-Oedipal mother is part
and pared of Ith()( ·L m.1k:n,: iht'if felt tl':.wud, t..1",lt rl Yt '"' s·;",. ,t",1 s ',,.,,..:t"' ·'
e\·er,ti.lY ,pt'\?l h The-.t -.um 'ti, f,\•1..·e, ,Ut' ,utwer,in• ,\I tht' "' 11 ., ,, dt "' -
wtitt'd in a prt',ratr..irchal t'l.'l1Pt' ·tit,n with the nh,thtr\ h' h. Ht'th the,:..b,I'.' ,, • r
disruptin' p,.>knti,1!d the emil.1tk is d1.)"1..'ly int ••w1..wu ,, ,th temn: · t, rut r ,te,\1
emphasiit'S that it w,)uld ht' ,1 mht,1ke to <...n tlut tht' \t'lllt,•h• t •l,)ngs t'\.,lust''-'h ltl
w,)mt'n. On tht' C,)ntr,1n t ht "emil\tlt' is -i pl't;'-l..),;,lip,11 n.-,1lm ,-f t''-l"' r.ent ' t ti.it (\\•ne,
ulttl h•ing prior to se'\ual dittert'IKt' If the semt,ltil' h 'ft·nnmtlt''. tlu-. i' ,1 ft'm11w11t, tr
..tt 1-. ah •an pt\tentially aYail.1t,''-' tt, tx,th w,,men ,md. me•1111 th 1r l'lt,,rh t,) tran,ft\flll
:,l nttt,
,me. gender pt>wer -\s childre•1 of llt,th sex, initt.111\ \ld1 1,;. ,·,,mt·n- thJt h. ,t 1
wonu 1·s bod,-all 1111..lh tdua ls.ire f.Ked \\ith tht' t'mN ,,n..l 1, t :t.11'\1,hmg ,1 rd iti,'11
to the feminme. Femininit, t·,mnN tie (h,·u,,t'll withllllt 1..
!11.ltt'PlJI
:Kriste,a s s ,rt;,•k t"reati,,n and. lite•.u e'\prt',,hm ,1, I"-' ,itik 1.., nt.tilwr, tl)rtm,r'<-'1 t"1
e'\perience. gi· i g ,;\ 1b1..,\k fl'rm tl) tht' ,cmi,,tK It i, 1p tht'1.·ultrn ,n_..._ldt't" 1..)t ths:.' ,trt1,t
lished meaning......Sht' finds s1Kl't a pt>eth.--.; ·ht st' 1,'tit m the w gs t'•f numt'f\lll"
t)f
,n-aPt-gardt autht)f", )rindp I the French pt'<-'h 'tt'l l.lllt' \!,111.ume. L.mtrt',ltn,,nt. ,md
.-\nt,)nin .-\rtaud. as well ;b _l,1mes 1,,\-( '. \lth,)ugh h1.''-1. h.' ,tll nuk ,tu!h,,f". kri,tt''.t d"
,'lb at length on thea1.'stht'tk stnKture, t)f pt't'tk I.mg 1g1., nd e,l1.tlh 1.'n tht ,h1fttng t'it-
1
J,;. cf ,eP ioti( forces that unlink 1.lll\ 1.)US eamn -s in the,e wntt:•r--, Stie . tre,,e,
th..lt tht'
energy of the pre-Oedipal, 'mi,,t1.:- mhe 'lt•mimnt' ,utk1.1\,1tk,'l 1.l' p e.isurt'. ,1 re.ilm
1..'I st't"rd desire, ,,hid11.ktk · patriarch.1 u ltu "°' ,md l.m'-!-...1-.;:1.
In other WTiting ·. :Kri te,·,1 ,eeks to lend htrth1.. ,,», ent t,) th1.• i,ka ,,f ,<'"li ,ti, sut-n:. r
sitin through the empin,·al studY of motherh,xx t: .u 1e, th,1t ,n pn.'.S::n,m,,. m. " •1
can re-:-oYer a rt'presse,t rel.ttion tt' the semilltl( m.1te al thrl)ti,..:h the pr,,t1.llllll.l !
C'llll'ti,'n,tl t''\perience of ,t, ingbirth. Prep1,m -,- inY1.\!w::. a k,nd ,,f plt,1.._ur,1blt 1.n.',1ti\e
link.·.'g \\itl-t 1.'therne,.·. Inhere ·ay '\\·,,men\ rime·. ,he ,l 'llt'' th.it prt'pl,lllt"\ re 'fl' iu,'\.'S
·the r.hh'tl nrdeal of the splitting of th<' sub;1.Yt. ft'•,foublingd the btxh.,ep,1r.1t1,\Il.,md,
><;'\.,\teth"-' lf
the self and of an 1.1ther ,1f nature and Cl'nscil,ume ··. 1. f ph,··i,)k "' ,md r,'e-, h · t<:>,' c,.
1
200· This mtxlt? of rel,tt ng im•olws ,, ..._ tential l'\.,,,mtrudll1n tlf hum,m ,xial f('
ship,. ont? m whICh .in 'w r"'latw1 tt tht '11 t)f,·1tltl\'. it" rkamres. andit's dh:n.H1 ,
1.1 fi:wd 1.1pp,),ttit,n- can,), erturn xist· ,_.,
mascu ,t ,,lt,1n.'
lore rl;:'('enth·. "n,teYa ha, pt. "!-t , •heD1t?, ,h: 1re-.s11.1n. m,)urmng .md 111eLrn1..·h1.)lt,1
in modern n1lture. In dt>presswn. she suggests. there 1s .m eml't ,mal s 1 ·t, 'lt. ·fl.,m
t." - fttn
a, a result of 11.),t ltwe-suffer fwm a paraly:..h l'f ,y111b,,Jil' actint\. lnef e'-, • -1,, t t,
b tot in or s;ub,titute for what has been It,,;t at tht' I wl ,,f tht' r.nhe .\-. the dt'l'l'\'.
std
pers,)n lo,e, mter.:-,t m thE ,urro1mding world. in l,m,:i.1,l!!t' 1t elf. P"Yth11.. ene , ,i, tt· tt\
a more pnm1t1, e m,1de of l\t'ing. to a nMternal. drive--rd.1ted tpr,11 ,._ f e'\ 'nt n1..
Depression pr,1du'-·e, ,l trauma of wmb,Jhc identifh::,1tion. wh11:h m,1y then Ull t'1 ..l ,n
power of semiotK e1er . Inthefore.:- field 0f the semil,ti -in rh thm ·.1. h,mgt'' in inti.\
nat11.m. sen, •', shift·-1'.ri te, a discerns a mean, t0 l"1..1rreLt the unsrl'l,t'n t''-j.'\.'rtei ,l:'
'Y: r ,,, iJTM rm and ac.+• ,_ .w·nct.(-r -stru2;;)t ,n favr, ir r,f an ab trac.t fT'.a't m<.>d< I <if '><•muJtic
, ..
,:;f-', , ......,,,..,., ff'JW rr·,¢t '>t-Tl'.'-,J!·c.., ,t,ve,.,:,;n'> tran-form ,,, eradiuik 'kxual "·r;!tnce ()T
f/1' f'J"Arap )
I
",,, ..---<1 •J n
f rar,'/1, 11<,tud, a!Jd far '1'lt.., vunda lwtv> art '.1 >'.U '>t.d in Chai:,•er<, ':I
;:;r;'j 2 ,J! •r, _ r,,<,<,'£.J, tb< r<· ha\ t.l( t-n mu' _h ddJat( ab•"J • th, fatc. of •r.1: m• ·d :ia' or 'd(:;1• h
1
,Ji th<'-, ·,J' <n J)"f>trr '11• •n •c.ult•J"· In •h,-,k dl'A'J'>\l'JD'>, ps \.h,anah,ha, pm· .dtd
'/Y , / -1 .-. t;-,, ,,n ,,pt .1.aJ tf.l'J f<Jr qu,,.,•wr·ng and dt• r;n<,truct ng EnlighttPmtnt d .,._
,,..- r,t n• ,r•v r:pr,, ,tfJ:Jt nc.,tablt thb<irat on of? _.-ch,iana y<,1, in thi<
r '1 : h;;• r;(••n c, '( , "JJ,kt.z(•ard 't ,x •(, t•.a•1'< trtat,,eAnt1 OeJpu,, 0' 1972 pn.
'P:' 1 •i,ta tr,,,,a<, J u,ntn J t,<m trJ tht theory ,,t 'c..ap·t;,.'i m and schizophrtn a·.
J ,,
I .x- ( JJ.: :;r .-j (, .J,:i•a•r c ,,, •r nd •hat t!-',- Lacan an tht'J <Jf d.rt, JJl<,cfdr as t b,rtis tht
-.-,lV ( t t<1 tht y,<. .:1; ,,rd•,1rh m tilt 'kr c_,- of rtpH-S)l<1n The;, mai7ta1r. that ps\c.h>
:,.r•iJ',,•Jc ( Lp,-u,!..dn and Lac..ar: ·.an t'Jn function ·!1 tht- intt n. •so• cap tz.J rr> a<-a nd
,,.,,,t(-'x r<,1rr1 1 ,; •h ur([1f')(.J<, \r.1tc'1fTlt<,lxnt•JUtnfs'1apt.lnthun·kw CJilS) wJ
theincestuous sexual realm of the nuclear family. They criticize Freud's and Lacan's
reduc tion of Oedipal prohibitions merely to signifiers which chain desire to normative
represen tations, at the point at which we come to desire what capitalism wants us to
desire. Instead, in a more radical gesture, Deleuze and Guattari seek to uncover this
psychoanalytic privi leging of desire rooted in lack as a product of Law. They argue that
desire in fact precedes representation and self-identity, so that there is nothing at all
personal to the flows of libido, which continually burst out anew. They propose
giving full throttle to flows of libidinous energy, affirming the absolute 'positivity' of
unconcious productions and treat ing schizophrenia as a potentially emancipatory
model.
Anti-Oedipus was a courageous poetic attempt to explode the *normative power of cat
egories like 'Oedipus' and 'castration', using psychoanalytic concepts against the coloniz
ing conceptual logic of psychoanalysis itself. Deleuze and Guattari trace the 'free lines' of
schizophrenic desire as affirmative force, as a series of enabling rhythms, intensities and
transforming possibilities. From this angle, the schizoid process is what enables libidinal
pulsations to be uncoupled from systems, structures, or cultural ohjects, which may in turn
transform the production of the political network, making politics no longer unfold ac
cording to the repressive functioning of Law. Rejecting the rigid and closed worlds of
Oedipus and capitalism, Deleuze and Guattari claim to speak for schizophrenia over neu
rosis, for flows of desire over lack, for fragments over totalities, differences over uniformity.
They write that 'schizophrenia is desiring production at the limit of social production'
(Deleuze and Guattari 1972: 35). Against the Oedipalizing logic of capitalist discourse,
where desire is channelled into prescribed pathways, Deleuze and Guattari argue that the
impersonalized flows of schizoid desire can herald a radical transformation of society.
Similar theoretical directions were taken in the early writings of the French philosopher
Jean-Frarn;ois*Lyotard, whose work is discussed at greater length in Chapter 12 of this book
(pp. 260-2). Lyotard argues that political society is itself secretly libidinal. Whereas Deleuze
and Guattari hold that desire is codified and repressed capitalist arrangements, Lyotard
views contemporary society as an immense desiring system. In Lyotard's picture, the post
modern is a vast libidinal circuit of technologies, a culture swamped with seductive signs
and images. Underscoring the indeterminancy of intensities, Lyotard here effects a shift in
focus away from theories of representation and structures of the psyche toward bodily
intensities and erotogenic surfaces. In his text Libidinal Economy (1974), Lyotard constructs
the excitations of libido on the model of the Mobius strip, conceptualized as an endless
series of rotations, twistings, and contortions. The upshot of this, in political terms, is a
series of proposals about how best to extract libidinal pleasure and intensity from
postmodern culture. 'What would be interesting', Lyotard writes, 'would be to stay where
we are, but at the same time to grab all opportunities to function as good conductors of
intensities' (1974: 311).
The postmodern psychoanalytic thought of IJeleuze, Guattari, and Lyotard emphasizes
experiences of fragmentation, dislocation, and polyvalency in contemporary society. It is
pitted against the view that social transformation might be linked to the undoing of hid
den meanings or discourses-as suggested by theorists such as Marcuse and the early
*Habermas. Instead, truth in postmodern psychoanalysis is located in the immediacy of
libidinal intensity itself. In the postmodern imagination, the unconscious cannot
be tamed or organized. Desire needs no interpretation; it simply is. It is within the diffuse,
PSYCHOANALYTIC SOC.AL TliEOHY 193
perverse, and schizophrenic manifestations of desire that new forms of identity, otherness,
and symbolism can be found.
The issues raised by postmodern psychoanalysis have an interest in light of contempo
rary social transformations such as globalization and new communications technology.
However, it is not apparent that postmodern psychoanalytic theories generate genuinely
sustainable criteria for the critical assessment of social practices, politics, and value posi
tions. As Dews (1987), Frank (1983), and other critics have urged, the dissimulation of li
bidinal intensities enjoined in many currents of postmodern psychoanalysis is something
that can be ideologically marshalled by both progressive and reactionary political forces
alike. One may argue that the idea of desire as something ipso facto rebellious and
subver sive is premised on a naive naturalism, failing to examine realistically the specific
institu tional forms in which unconscious passion is embedded. Here there is little
consideration of the potential harm, pain, and damage that psychical states of
fragmentation and fluid ity may comprise. There is a grave danger of romanticizing
'schizophrenia'.
Conclusion
Postmodern variants of psychoanalytic thinking need to be placed alongside the full
gamut of schools and developments in psychoanalytic social theory discussed in this
chap ter. Postmodern interventions are not understandable other than as polemical side-
shots across the foundational work of Freud and the subsequent contributions of figures
such as Lacan, Marcuse, Fromm, Parsons, and the Frankfurt School, as well as the work
of feminist theorists such as Chodorow, Benjamin, and Kristeva.
We have seen that in Chodorow's work, psychoanalysis is part of an attempt to under
stand the psychic components of female and male socialization, especially in terms of the
unconscious forces that shape gender roles. In Jessica Benjamin's work, psychoanalysis is
deployed to rethink the dynamics of domination and submission within the wider frame
of gender, society, and history. In Kristeva's texts, we find primarily a set of observations
about transformations of the psyche and about how identity splices with disruptions in
cultural life. For Lacan and the various Marxist writers who draw on his work, including
Althusser and Zizek, psychoanalysis is the study of the precarious fabrications of identity
that make up our sense of self in a world shot through with displaced representations of
desire encoded in everyday language and the mass media.
The individual writers discussed in this chapter by no means exhaust the scope of
psychoanalytic social thought. There have been numerous contributors to psychoanalysis
since Freud whose work we have not been able to discuss here. Among others, these
include particularly the Austrian-British psychoanalyst Melanie Klein and the British
psychoana lyst Donald Winnicott, who both exerted a major impact on the study of child
psychology. Alongside these, mention should be made of the work of Freud's daughter
Anna, as well as of the Swiss psychologist Carl G. Jung who applied psychoanalysis to
the study of myth, folklore, and fairy tales, speaking of various 'archetypes' of the soul.
All these develop ments attest to the continuing vitality of Freud's revolutionary work in
contemporary thought, despite its various methodological limitations and problematic
assumptions about the nature of the human animal.
194 f, {HHONY ELUOH
How far are Freud's analyses of psychological illnesses in individual persons applicable to the
study of whole societies and civilizations?
2 What sense can be given to Jacques Lacan's statement that the 'unconscious is structured
like a language'? What does this proposition help explain about social and cultural life?
3 To what extent is psychoanalytic thinking oriented to the goal of social and political
emancipation? How effective are combinations of psychoanalysis and Marxism?
5 How much of Freud's work from the early decades of the twentieth century is relevant to
the study of social behaviour today, in a multicultural or 'postmodern' context? Is the
Oedipus complex still a valid tool of analysis?
FURTHER READING
Some general overviews of psychoanalysis in relation to social theory are Anthony Elliott's four
books Psychoanalytic Theory: An Introduction (Duke University Press, 2nd edn. 2002), Social Theory
since Freud: Traversing Social Imaginaries (Routledge, 2004), Social Theory and Psychoanalysis in
Transition: Self and Society from Freud to Kristeva (Blackwell, 2nd edn. 1999), and Subject to Ourselves:
Social Theory, Psychoanalysis and Postmodernity (Blackwell, 1996). Also useful are Stephen Frosh's The
Politics of Psychoanalysis (Macmillan, 2nd edn. 1999) and Ian Craib's two books Psychoanalysis:
A Critical Introduction (Polity Press, 200l) and Psychoanalysis and Social Theory (Harvester, 1989). See
alsoJohn Forrester's Language and the Origins of Psychoanalysis (Macmillan, 1980).
For some helpful introductions to Freud, try Anthony Starr's Freud (Oxford University Press,
1989), Richard WolJheim's Freud (Fontana, 2nd edn. 1991), and Peter Gay's more detailed historical
study Freud: A Life for our Time (Dent, 1988). See also Paul Ricreur's hermeneutical study Freud and
Philosophy (Yale University Press, 1970) and Philip Rieff's Freud: The Mind of the Moralist (Chicago
University Press, 1979), as well as the essays in Anthony Elliott's edited Freud 2000 (Polity Press,
1998). Two excellent one-volume collections of readings from Freud are Peter Gay's The Freud Reader
(Vintage, 199S) and Anna Freud's The Esm1tials of Psychoanalysis (Penguin, 1986). Freud is probably
best approached first through The Interpretation of Dreams (Oxford University Press, 1999) and
Civilization and its Discontents (Dover, 1994).
Two good introductions to Lacan (with an emphasis on literary and cultural theory) are Malcolm
Bowie's Lacan (Fontana, 1991) and David Macey's Lacan in Contexts (Verso, 1988). The authoritative
intellectual biography is Elisabeth Roudinesco's facques Lacan & Co: A History of Psychoanalysis in
France, 1925-1985 (Free Association, 1990). The work of Zizek can be approached through Elizabeth
and Edmund Wright's edited Zizek Reader (Blackwell, 1999) or through any of Zizek's own lively
books,such as Looking Awry: An llltroduction to Popular Culture through facques Lacan (MIT Press,
1991) or Enjoy your Symptom (Routledge, 1993).
Some good guides to feminism and psychoanalysis are Jane Flax's Thinking Fragments:
Psychoanalysis, Feminism and Postmodcmism in the Contemporary West (University of California Press,
1991), Nancy Chodorow's Feminism and Psychoanalytic Theory (Polity Press, 1989), and Rosalind
Minsky's collection of edited readings with commentaries Psychoanalysis and Gender (Routledge,
1996). A useful collection of readings from Kristeva is Tori! Moi, The Kristeva Reader, ed. Tori! Moi
(Blackwell, 1986). For an introduction to the work of Deleuze and Guattari (who do not write in a
conventionally clear way), sec Ronald Bogue's Deleuze and Guattari (Routledge, 1989) or Paul
Patton's Deleuze and the Political (Routledge, 2000).
195
■ WEBSITES
The movements of thought that developed in France from the late 1950s to the 1970s
known as *'structuralism' and *'post-structuralism' have had a major impact in twentieth
century social science, as well as in the humanities, in aesthetics, and in literary theory.
French structuralist and post-structuralist thinking from the radical decade of the 1960s
and the 'generation of 1968' today stands as a potent source of influences behind such
intellectual developments as feminist theory, *postcolonial theory, *queer theory, film
and media theory, *deconstructive literary criticism, and *postmodernist thinking in the
broadest sense.
It should, however, be noted that structuralism is often used rather loosely as a term and
that the term 'post-structuralism' was eschewed by most of the writers so labelled. Broadly
defined, structuralism can be defined as an attempt to provide a unified method for the
social sciences through the development of a methodology drawn from the structural
197
use the term 'structure'; he used the term 'system'. In his Course, Saussure defends five key
propositions, which we discuss in turn:
I. The sign comprises a signifier and a signified.
2. Signs are arbitrary.
3. Difference creates meaning.
4. Language is to be studied synchronically, not diachronically.
5. The proper focus of linguistics is not speech by individual speakers (termed parole) but
language as an independent objective system (termed langue).
By the *'signifier', Saussure means a sound or image. 13y the *'signified', he means a
concept or mental image to which the signifier refers. Signifier and signified together
make up the 'sign'. Between any given signifier and signified, however, there is no
necessary relation. Saussure demonstrates the arbitrary character of signs by comparing
words with similar meanings across languages, arguing that no particular word is more
appropriate than any other in designating a particular idea. He points out that the concept'
"sister" is not linked by any inner relationship to the succession of sounds s-6-r [sreur]
which serves as its signi fier in French' (Saussure 1916: 67). Similarly, 'the signified "ox" has
as its signifier h-6-f[bm1( in French] on one side of the border and o-k-s [Ochs in
German) on the other' (Saussure 1916: 68). Different societies use words to carve up the
world in different ways. For example, different language communities make different
categorizations of the colour spectrum; Eskimos have many different words for snow,
while Europeans only have one word. Although some words retain partially naturalistic
features, such as onomatopoeic words (words which 'sound like' the things they name),
these are exceptions; and while many Asian languages retain pictorial elements, the basis
of the production of meaning in these languages is not pictorial but relational.
Saussure emphasizes that 'arbitrary' does not imply that individuals can choose any
signifier they like. In order to communicate, individuals have to follow the order of signs
established in the linguistic communities to which we belong. Speakers must know the
rules of language. Saussure comments that 'the signifier, though to all appearances freely
chosen with respect to the idea that it represents, is fixed, not free, with respect to the
linguistic community that uses it' (Saussure 1916: 71).
The key proposition in Saussure's account is that difference creates meaning. Meaning
is a product of internal differences between terms in a language as a system. Saussure
states: 'In language there are only differences without positive terms' (Saussure 1916:
120). Considered separately, signifier and signified are nothing but negations of other
signifiers and signifieds. Only their combination produces a positive fact in the institution
of a particular language. Saussure here reserved the French word langue for the systematic
dimension of language. He distinguished this from the word parole, which he reserved for
written or spoken language-in-me by individual persons. Saussure maintained that whilst
language use only exists in space and time, use of language depends on a set of unstated
rules that make language possible. To focus on /a11s,11e was to focus on language as a
system of these unstated rules of composition.
Saussure proposes that the relations between linguistic terms form two distinct groups.
When we hear someone speak, or when we read something, we have a sequence. This is
the
STRUCTURALISM Allil 199
BOX 23. ROLAND BARTH ES ON MYTH AND THE 'DEATH OF THE AUTHOR'
The writings of Roland *Barthes provided important statements of structuralist method and played an
important role in popularizing structuralist ideas. Barthes applied Saussure's structuralist analysis of
lan guage to all sign systems, including images, gestures, and sounds. His early writings show strong
sim ilarities with the work of Levi-Strauss. In his book Elements of Semiology (1964), one of Barthes's
analysis focuses on the social meanings of eating, treating eating habits and codes in terms of syntag
matic chains. He shows how the arrangement of dishes on a menu is organized along an associative
paradigmatic dimension-through basic oppositions between 'savoury' and 'sweet', and so on-while
the syntagmatic combination of dishes produces a meal, a linear chain (1964: 27-8).
Barthes was concerned to provide an explicitly critical analysis of bourgeois society. To this end, in
his major work Mythologies (1957) his observations examine the manner in which advertising
operates. Barthes observes how the marketing of detergents is conducted in the language of
international con flict, while wine, steak, and fries are portrayed as the 'alimentary sign of
Frenchness' (1957: 36-9, 62--4). Barthes here sees semiology as a science of forms that aims to
denaturalize myths by exposing the conditions of their production. He writes that 'myth is
depoliticized speech' (1957 142-3). Myth turns historical contingencies into eternal and apparently
naturally justified states. Barthes analyses the cover of an issue of the magazine Paris-Match,
showing a young black man in French army uniform saluting the tricolour. He shows how the image
states the fact of French imperialism while operating to convert history into nature (1957: 115, 143).
Barthes's aim is to examine the political interests served by such processes of naturalization.
This concern with questioning the function of processes of naturalization and suggesting the possib-
' ility of alternative patterns of signification especially clearly in Barthes's essay 'The Death of the Author'
(Barthes 1968). Barthes here argues that the author is a distinctly modern figure, one whose function in
literary criticism is to provide an explanation and delimitation of the meaning of a text. He contends that
'linguistically, the author is never more than the instance of writing, just as I is nothing other than the in
stance of saying/' (1968: 145). Barthes attacks cultural institutions that maintain control over the mean
ing of literary texts through recourse to the author as explanation. In place of this, he looks for the
possibility of new interpretations of texts that might be produced by overthrowing the myth of
origins entailed by the idea of the author. Barthes proclaims that the 'birth of the reader must be at
the cost of the death of the Author' (1968: 148).
We can see here how *subJectivity and authorial voice in structuralist and post-structuralist
thinking are not regarded as given but as organized through the *totality of language. Subjectivity is
predicated on differences in linguistic and semiotic structures. Speakers and agents gain access to
themselves and their identities as persons only through the institutionalized totality of language.
This is at the root of the characteristic anti-humanism of structuralist and post-structuralist theory,
where 'anti-humanism' refers to an antipathy toward *phenomenological and *hermeneutical ideas of
the meaning-conferring powers of individual human agents.
empirically observable form of language which Saussure calls its syntagmalic dimension,
characteristic of parole. A syntagm is formed by two or more consecutive units supported
by linearity, by a line of some kind. Phrases and sentences are examples of syntagms.
Within syntagmatic chains, terms gain value through their linear relation to others that are
present. Such chains are distinct from what Saussure calls the associative or paradigmatic
dimension of language, characteristic of /angue. Associative relations are not supported by
linearity.
200 5 MANTHA ASHENDEN
They develop outside the context of spoken utterances or written statements by an indi
\"idual. Unlike the syntagmatic dimension present in parole, the associative dimension
unites terms 'in absentia' (Saussure 1916: 123l. This associative dimension of /angue forms
a background of meaning, making up the 'inner storehouse' of the language spoken by each
speaker (Saussure 1916: 123).
Among the more general ideas bequeathed by Saussure to social and cultural theory is
his conception of the primacy of the whole over the parts. His model of langue is that of
an 'absent totality' which does not itself exist in space or time. The *totality is
instantiated in speech and writing, yet is only discernible beyond any individual act of
speaking or writing. This idea shares something in common with Emile Durkheim's
conception of the social as a 'sui generis reality' that is more than the sum of its parts. It
was to prove important later to both structuralist and post-structuralist theorists, including
notably to Derrida and Foucault, as we shall see shortly. A further influential element of
Saussure's account is that it does not see language merely as a means of expression or
instrument of a speaking subject. Rather, it conceives language as the structuring
precondition of thought, which stands be yond the mental agency of any individual
speaking subject. Language is not seen as some thing merely at the disposal of an indi\
idual person. On the contrary, the subject is seeP as in a certain sense at the disposal of
language. This idea later came to be associated with the theme of the 'decentring of the
*subject' in French structuralist and post-structuralist thought. The theme is especially
prominent in the thinking of Derrida and Foucault, but it is also present in the literary
criticism of Roland Barthes, who famously spoke of the 'death of the author'. Barthes's
contributions to the tudy of myth and popular culture from a structuralist perspec tive are
discussed here in Box 23.
Saussure's work was exclusively in the field of linguistics, but it became central to struc
turalism in social and cultural theory through the work of writers such as Barthes and
Levi Strauss. It is to Levi-Strauss's work that we turn next.
Claude *Levi-Strauss was the first author to disseminate the term 'structuralism' and to
import Saussure's linguistic insights into social science. He made important contributions
to the study of kinship rules, primitive classification systems, *totemism, myth, music, and
art. In each of these fields, he applied the methods of structural linguistics to social sys
tems, aiming to uncover the uni\·ersal rules underpinning the apparent diversity of social
and cultural life.
The initial formative influences on LeYi-Strauss were Durkheim and Durkheim's nephew
!\1arcel '\1auss. In particular, LeYi-Strauss drew on Durkheim's precept that social order
forms a coherent system comprising subsystems, and that social facts precede the indi
Yidual and giw structure to individuality. Levi-Strauss also drew on Mauss's (1924)
account of the role of gift exchange in archaic societies, where exchange establishes
reciprocit)· (see Levi-Strauss 1950). But it was the Russian linguist Roman Jakobson
who introduced Levi-Strauss to the work of Saussure in New York during the Second
World War. Most of LeYi-Strauss's anthropological fieldwork is based on studies of the
tribes of Amazonian
STRUCTURALISM AND POST-STRUCTURALISM 201
South America. His major works are The Elementary Structures of Kinship (1949), Tristes
Tropiques (1955), Structural Anthropology (1958), The Raw and the Cooked (1964), and The
Savage Mind (1966).
Levi-Strauss described structural linguistics as effecting a 'Copernican revolution' in
anthropology and the human sciences in general. He wrote that 'first, structural linguistics
shifts from the study of conscious linguistic phenomena to the study of their unconscious
infrastructure; second, it does not treat terms as independent entities, taking instead as
its basis of analysis the relations between terms; third, it introduces the concept of
system ... finally, structural linguistics aims at discovering general laws' (1958: 83, 33,
emphasis in original). These methodological tenets were to become central to Levi-
Strauss's way of proceeding. We can illustrate them by looking at his work on kinship
systems and at an example from his study of myth.
In The Elementary Structures of Kinship (1949) Levi-Strauss analyses what he sees as certain
fundamental laws of exchange underpinning systems of kinship. He observes that all soci
eties have restrictions concerning appropriate sexual partners, but that these restrictions vary
and that the ways in which they are enforced also vary. He then searches for the
underlying structures governing marriage relations that divide members into two
categories, prohibited partners and possible partners. He argues that this basic *binary
opposition is a product of the universality of the incest taboo and the accompanying rule
of exogamous (non-blood related) marriage. In other words, marriage is misunderstood if
it is thought of purely as an individualized relation between two persons. Marriage is
rather a fundamental form of exchange, which grounds human sociality. This law of
exogamy is 'omnipresent'; it is 'the archetype of all other manifestations based on
reciprocity, and ... it provides the fundamen tal and immutable rule ensuring the existence
of the group as a group' (1949: 481). This is because exogamy 'provides the means of
binding men together'. It superimposes on natural links of kinship artificial links of
'alliance governed by rule' (1949: 480). Levi-Strauss comments that 'the prohibition of
incest is less a rule prohibiting marriage with the mother, sister or daughter, than a rule
obliging the mother, sister or daughter to be given to others. It is the supreme rule of the
gift, and it is clearly this aspect ... which allows its nature to be understood' (1949: 481).
Marriage rules concerning the exchange of women generate a system of alliances and
interdependencies that enable the social group to reproduce itself. Marriage for Levi-
Strauss is thus a fundamental form of exchange that upholds institutionalized relations
between groups. He compares kinship to a linguistic system: 'like a phoneme, a device
having no meaning of its own but helping to form meanings, the incest taboo struck me as
a link between two domains' (1983: 142). Levi-Strauss means the domains of nature and
culture. The incest prohibition and exogamy are necessary to lift human beings out of
biological relations into social relations. Levi-Strauss comments that the prohibition of
incest is 'the prohibition'. It is as universal as language (1949: 493). Levi-Strauss seeks to
determine the laws underlying different systems of marriage by examining relations
between elements as part of a system. His aim is to examine the unconscious activity of
the mind that consists in imposing 'form' on 'content', or shape on matter (1958: 21).
This structuralist aspect of Levi-Strauss's analysis can be clarified further with an
example from his work on myth. Levi-Strauss observes that myths have a storyline, or
syntagmatic dimension. But he argues that to understand a myth, we need to examine
the
202 5(4fwiAN"iHA I SHENDEN
structural oppositions that it embodies, such as between 'nature' and 'culture', or between
time and space, or between the 'raw' and the 'cooked'- food found in the wilderness and
food prepared by the hands of man. He suggests that we read a myth as we read a musical
score, both *diachronically along one axis and *synchronically along another. Read in
this manner, a musical score ceases to be a simple succession of notes; it forms a
meaning ful whole (1958: 212). Using this model, he argues that individual elements of a
myth taken in isolation are meaningless. Their meaning is to be found in the ways in
which they are brought into relation and ordered as a totality. In a similar manner to
Saussure, Levi-Strauss insists on examining myth th rough the totality of the system of
oppositional relations that compose it (1958: 210). Indeed he argues not only that myth is
structured 'like language' but that myth is language. Myth gives symbolic expression to
unconscious aspirations. It express properties of the human mind, and studying these
properties allows us to understand the structural oppositions that operate in the human
unconscious.
In a similar manner to Jacques *Lacan's structuralist psychoanalysis, Levi-Strauss
analy ses the ancient Greek myth of Oedipus: the story of the exiled young boy
condemned by prophecy to murder his father and sleep with his mother. Levi-Strauss
proposes that the Oedipus myth is constructed through a series of recurring oppositions
between the under rating and overrating ot blood relations. These antitheses build a series
of transformations as the story progresses, so that the whole story constitutes an attempt
to mediate between 'nature' and 'culture'. It is an attempt to resolve the contradiction
between the belief that man is autochthonous (born of one principle, born of the earth-
represented by Oedipus on his own, in exile) and knowledge that humans are the result of
union between man and woman (born of two different parents, one male, one female-
represented by Oedipus in the family). The myth is a way of attempting to manage conflict
about where humans come from, about the origins of man (1958: 213-16).
From this brief discussion we can see that Levi-Strauss conceives of cultures and their
myths as totalities ordered through differences between terms. Structural anthropology
aims to dig beneath the variety of human experience in order to uncover certain putatively
uni versal laws governing human sociality and unconscious life'. Levi-Strauss does not
attempt to search for the earliest version of a particular myth, for its 'origin'. Rather, he
regards a myth as consisting in all its manifold versions. The key concern lies not with the
origin but ½ith sym bolic order, and with how symbolic order is structured. As with Saussure,
Levi-Strauss's con cern is not with tracing the history ot our concepts and categories in
order to reveal the most 'primitive' or 'authentic' form. What Levi-Strauss calls the 'savage
mind' is not more prim itive or origirnHy than the Western mind. ln his view, es entially the
same basic logical struc tures can be found among all human groups. Thus, instead of
searching for the most ancient or original or authentic, Levi-Strauss and Sau sure enjoin
us to look for the logical totality through which any individual elements of culture gain
their meaning and validity.
Jacques *Derrida is regarded as the first French theorist to pioneer a turn away from struc
turalism in the classical sense toward what ha come to be called 'post-structuralism',
which
STRUCTURALISM AI\ID POST Si'Fli.lOURAUSIV' 203
what he sees as Western philosophy's privileging of speech over writing (from the Greek
word for 'voice' or 'sound', phone). Speech in Western culture has been regarded as a
capac ity immediately available to a self-present subject, such that writing becomes
derivative, a mere transcription of speech.
The importance of these concepts becomes clear when we consider that Derrida's con
cern is to deconstruct Western metaphysics from within. Against Jogocentrism and phono
centrism, Derrida develops what he calls 'deconstructive'writing. Deconstruction is a form
of criticism that operates through close readings of texts in order to pull apart their internal
logic and destabilize their self-presence. Its aim is to reveal that which is assumed but
repressed by the dominant frame of a text. Thus in Of Grammatology, Derrida examines
Saussure's work to disclose what it cannot describe-what has been excluded in order that
the text be constituted as it is.
A key step in Derrida's proposal for deconstruction concerns what he sees as a rather
problematic aspect of Saussure's distinction between 'signifier' and 'signified'. Derrida sees
this as a metaphysical distinction: a distinction between something regarded as essentially
sensuous or sensible (the signifier) and something regarded as essentially non-sensuous
and ideal or intelligible (the signified). The sensible is said to be exterior to a principle of
interior 'pure intelligibility'. The sensible constitutes merely an 'outside' in relation to an
'inside'. According to Derrida, Saussure's linguistics-and classical structuralism more
generally-remains caught in metaphysics insofar as it relies on what Derrida calls a
'transcendental signifier', an idea of pure intelligibility, which is expected to function as
the origin of all meaning. Derrida highlights the way in which Saussure treats writing as
derivative from, and possibly corrupting of, speech. He quotes Saussure's comment that
'language and writing are two distinct systems of signs; the second exists for the sole
purpose of representing the first' (Saussure in Derrida 1967: 30). Derrida comments that
this attributes to writing 'the exteriority that one attributes to utensils' (1967: 34). Derrida
argues that despite Saussure's conception of langue as an 'absent totality', Saussure views
spoken language as achieving full self-presence. Derrida argues that in this conception the
exteriority of writing threatens to contaminate language by producing an 'eruption of
the outside within the inside' (1967: 34), breaching the apparent self-presence of speech.
The intrusion of writing into the self-presence of speech threatens this self-presence by a
logic of the 'supplement'. In Derrida's view, Saussure wishes to place writing in an 'intra-
linguistic leper colony' to contain the deformations it may produce (1967: 42).
It is in this general sense that Derrida declares famously, and provocatively, that 'there
is nothing outside the text', or 'no outside-text' (il n'y a pas de hors-texte) (1967: 158).
Derrida implies that there can be neither a master speaking subject which precedes any act
of writ ing, nor any pure or natural 'external world' which stands outside the structuring
effects of writing as they are played out in texts. Ideas of 'pure mind' and 'pure world', the
'subjective' and the 'objective', the 'ideal' and the 'real', are metaphysical effects of the play
oflanguage and writing.
history of metaphysics ... is the determination of being as presence in all the senses of
this word' (1968b: 249). He points out the impossibility of thinking the concept of
structure without a centre. The centre refers to 'a point of presence, a fixed origin' that
organizes and delimits the free play of the structure, and yet is 'paradoxically, within the
structure and out side it' (1968b: 247-8). That is, the centre is simultaneously the thing
within a structure that governs the structure's structurality and that which escapes
structurality. 'The center is at the center of the totality, and yet, since the center does not
belong to the totality (is not part of the totality), the totality has its center elsewhere'
(1968b:248).
Derrida's thinking about the centre can be illustrated in several ways. We might think of
the centre as the self, as the ego which arranges the world around itself in its
conscious thoughts. But from a psychoanalytic point of view, the centre is not the
conscious self. The self finds itself 'decentred' in relation to the unconscious. The
centre appears to lie else where, other to the self; it is that on which the self is
dependent, and therefore is not the self's 'own'. The centre turns out to be not 'I' but'It':
the unconscious life of desire, or what Sigmund *Freud called the id. In an often quoted
phrase of the nineteenth-century French Symbolist poet Arthur Rimbaud, 'Je est un autre'
- 'I is an other'. Or as Freud wrote, equally famously:'WoEs war, entstehtdas Jch'-'Where
id was, there ego shall be' (Freud, 1933: 112). We may also think of the concept of
decentring as it has developed in postcolonial theory, notably among writers such as
Edward *Said (1978) and Gayatri *Spivak (1999). The West has historically regarded
itself as the centre-of Culture, Civilization, Rationality-but in order to constitute itself
as the centre, the West has required an 'Other' which is apparently not the centre. And to
the extent that the West depends on this Other in order to be a centre, the West is not
the centre but is 'decentred'. Both these examples attest to Derrida's wide-ranging
influence in cultural theory and criticism.
A further step in Derrida's argument concerns his reading of the idea of 'difference'.
The significance of writing for Derrida is that it is not a transparent means of
representation but a material process governed by a logic of differance, a word he
deliberately misspells in French with an 'a'. The concept of differance is drawn from the
French verb differer,meaning both 'to differ' and 'to defer', which becomes differant in the
French present participle. Derrida argues that Western philosophy's logocentrism depends
on a repressed logic of differance. Against the assumption that signifier and signified form
a transparent and self sustaining unity, he stresses that meaning has no point of origin.
Meaning is always already transitional, deferred through endless chains of signifiers. This
focus on a never-ending process of differance unsettles the *binary logic of structuralism.
It also shows that binary oppositions are typically hierarchical, that one element is
typically dominant, but that this hierarchical opposition is necessarily unstable since the
meaning of each of the terms depends on the 'trace' of the other. We may think of the
binary pairs male-female, mind-body, conscious-unconscious, nature-culture, presence-
absence, and so on.
These aspects of Derrida's thought illustrate his movement beyond classical structuralism.
Where Saussure and Levi-Strauss tend to conceive of language and myth as closed
semiotic systems, Derrida refuses this. Against any idea of the self-sufficiency of signifier
and signi fied, Derrida stresses differance, 'supplementarity', and the 'trace'. He not only
asserts that difference creates meaning but also that this chain of signification extends 'ad
infinitum' (1968b: 249), resulting in no closure. Furthermore, Derrida understands
difference as both spatial and temporal, as extending in a temporal process of deferring, so
that signification
206 iA"iAfHHA A<;IH:r uf
occurs only through 'traces', through moments of difference in an endless chain of signifi
cation. Derrida abandons structuralism's distinction between the diachronic and syn
chronic in favour of an argument that there can be no final reading of a text. Any
reading always generates a supplementary one. In this sense, any remedy to a deficiency
is always a supplement which generates a further deficiency. Therefore there can be
neither begin ning nor end, no centre or point of presence or 'fixed origin'.
Yet while Derrida believes structuralism to be problematically complicit with the
history of Western metaphysics, he does not simply proclaim the bankruptcy or 'end' of
meta physics. He emphasizes that 'there is no sense in doing without the concepts of
metaphysics in order to attack metaphysics. We have no language-no syntax and no
lexicon-which is alien to this history' (1968b: 250). He stresses that deconstruction pre
supposes the tradition that it at the same time contests and unravels.
In general, Derrida's vision of deconstruction seeks critically to radicalize
structuralism's questioning of the idea of the centred autonomous human *subject.
Derrida declares that he does not 'destroy' the subject but that he 'situates' it (1968b: 271).
Against the 'meta physics of presence', he proposes a*'Nietzschean affirmation ... of the
freeplay of the world without truth, without origin, offered to an active interpretation'
(1968b: 264). His philos ophy 'affirms freeplay and tries to pass beyond man and
*humanism, the name 'man' being the name of that being who, throughout the history of
metaphysics or of onto-theology in other words, through the history of all of his history-
has dreamed of full presence, the reassuring foundation, the origin and the end of the
game' (1968b: 264-5).
This concern to 'decentre' and to 'situate' the subject is also key to the work of Michel
Foucault. It is to Foucault's work that we now turn.
Michel Foucault first came to prominence in Parisian intellectual life in the early 1960s
with a work titled Madness and Civilization (1961). This was a study of the rise of modern
medical institutions and discourses oriented to the scientific categorization and incarcera
tion of deviant individuals as clinically insane. In Foucault's thesis, this development sig
nalled the breakdown of an earlier medieval world-view marked by the unregulated
anarchic presence of fools in the community, as wel I as by religious languages of
possession by the devil and spirits.
After Madness and Civilization Foucault's reflections turned to the role of power, know
ledge, and discourse in Western civilization, incl udingthe role of criminology,
psychology, prisons, surveillance, discipline, education, and the state and the role of
scientific institu tions in definitions of the human person, especially concerning. l lis
major works are The Order of Things (1966), The Archaeology o{Knowlelf.'se (1969a),
Vi_ffipline and Punish (1975), and Tile History of Sexuality (1976, 1984a, 1984b) (in three
volumes). I!is writings have had an enormous impact in contemporary cultural and social
research-from philosophy, literature, and the history of ideas to criminology, education,
political theory, psycho analysis, *postcolonial studies, and feminist theory. A
homosexual, Foucault died of AIDS in California iri 1984.
STRUCTuRALiSM AND POST-STiiu- iUfiALISf 207
Together with Derrida, Foucault always rejected the label 'structuralist' and 'post
structuralist' as a description of his work (1966: p. xiv). Like Derrida, Foucault tended to
proclaim that structuralism is characteristic of a system of thought that is about to be
over come. Nonetheless, certain features of his thinking mark it out as 'structuralist' in
orientation. In the following discussion we look first at what Foucault describes as the
'archaeological' approach of the two major works of his middle period, The Order of
Things (1966) and The Archaeology of Knowledge (1969a). Then we look at what he
describes as the more 'genealogical' orientation of his later work on sexuality and
subjectivity.
representation and things of the world was eclipsed by a 'profound historicity' (1966:
p. xxiii). ln particular, Foucault nott>s that with the abandonment of systems of naturalis
tic representation at the end of the eighteenth century, the idea of the expressive
*humanistic subject entered the scene of Western history. Foucault declares that before the
e-nd of the eighteenth ce.n, tu•·-ry- ',-n-a..n. did no. . . t exist' ( 1966: 308). That is, the idea of
.
During the 1970s Foucault studied the formation of the human subject through a series of substantive
enquiries into the relationship between power and the growth of mental and physical capacities. These
are laid out chiefly in his books Discipline and Punish (1975) and The History of Sexuality,
volume 1 (1976). Foucault argues that power and knowledge are mutually productive in the
constitution of human beings as specific sorts of subjects. He considers the entwinement of
power.and knowledge in specific sites, especially 1n discourses of sexuality and in mechanisms of
punishment.
Foucault suggests three maJor sets of practices that constitute subjects: (1) practices of division,
(2) practices of scientific classification, and (3) practices of subJectification. In relation to 'd1vid1ng
practices', Foucault 1nvest1gates various historical examples of schemes of binary oppositions between
people. For example, he examines the exclusion of lepers from medieval and ancient cities. He contrasts
the margin alization of lepers, their separation and rejection into the wilderness, with the
quarantining of plague victims. Unlike lepers, the plague victims were confined and subject to
supervision, as part of a positive attempt to preserve the health of the community (1975: 198-9). In
relation to scientific classification practices, Foucault considers the emergence of scientific categories
and practices that assign and distrib ute individuals to definite positions within a population. In this way,
all members of a population become subject to 'constant surveillance' each 'in an individual way',
thmugh institutional expertise (1975: 199). In relation to sub1ectificat1on practices, Foucault discusses
the ways 1n which individuals turn themselves into subjects. This concerns how 1nd1v1duals come to act
on themselves through such practices as religious confession, psychoanalysis, or sex therapy.
Foucault sums up these three lines of approach in the ;dea of 'biopolit1cs'. 'Biopolitics' refers to
the general form or rationality of modern power. 'Biopower' 1s 'power over life' (1976: 143). It is a
secular ization of the Christian concern with the pastoral relationship, a relationship in which certain
individuals, by virtue of their special qualities-such as closeness to God or possession of scientific
expertise-can lead others to salvation. Biopower combines two axes. One axis is centred on the
individual body as a machine to be made useful through discipline. Foucault speaks of an 'anatomo-
politics of the human body'. The other axis is focused on the supervision and regulation of the body of
the species. Foucault speaks of a 'biopolitics of the population' (1976: 139). These two axes of
power produce new possib ilities of knowledge, involving close 1nst1tutional examination of individual
case histories and the devel opment of statistics relating to demographic patterns. Foucault argues
that such individualizing and totalizing forms of knowledge operate through confessional
technologies as institutional sites for the emergence of new 'sciences of man'. What is distinctive
about biopower is that it exhibits a concern with enhancing life. It 1s bound up with the
development of the modern state in its attempt to manage and enhance its strength. The state has
a definite interest in the health of the population, in the man agement of sexuality and human
reproduction, and in the maintenance of 'normalcy' and the elimination of disease and 'd1sabil1ty'.
Medicine and psychiatry, therapy and surgery, in all senses of these words, become key to the
control and maintenance of a norm of societal well-being.
In Discipline and Punish Foucault elaborates these ideas 1n relation to Jeremy *Bentham's eighteenth
century *ut1l1tarian conception of the 'Panopt1con'. The Panopticon was Bentham's design for a new
type of prison in which individual cells radiate out from a central tower. In Bentham's plan, each cell
was to house one inmate who is permanently visible to the guard in the central tower. The
intended effect was that each prisoner would not be able to tell whether he or she was being observed
at any one moment. Each prisoner would therefore become self-policing. Foucault observes
that abstract
continues
STRUCTURALISM AND ?OST STRUCTURAL·_,'· 211
BOX 24 continue
techniques of power here combine with techniques for the control, supervision, and correction of
specific individuals. Power is linked to the formation of personal capacities and to the training of indi
viduals. These techniques develop in localized institutions with specific concerns, such as 1n control of
the factory workforce, punishment of prisoners, and disciplining of children in schools. Such institutions
function as observatories of individual behaviour and performance, as laboratories determining the
development of practices of correction and reform. Foucault suggests that such institutionalized
techniques make possible a certain kind of knowledge of the individual based on norms and
'normality'. This knowledge is gained by techniques of examination. It 1s one of the peculiarly demonic
features of modern societies that such techniques are organized simultaneously through scientific laws
and through the operation of normalizing judgements (see also Foucault 1980). Foucault's conception
of discipline and surveillance can be compared in some ways with Erving *Eoffman's work on stigma
and 'total institutions' (discussed in Chapter 5 of this book, p. 117)
In his last series of works, his three-volume The History of Sexuality (1976-84),
Foucault examines how a science of sexuality began to develop in Western culture from
the late eighteenth century onwards. He shows how this science of sexuality sought to join
the indi vidual and social bodies together and thereby to provide a new vector of power
over life. In volume 1, devoted to the modern era, Foucault attacks what he calls the
'repressive hypothesis' (Foucault 1976). With this phrase Foucault refers to an assumption
that power necessarily acts on sexuality through a repression of 'natural instincts'. The
assumption sug gests that a 'Victorian' era of repression has gradually been replaced by a new
era of 'sexual lib eration'. Although he mentions no names, it is possible to see Foucault's
target here as being at least partly in the attempts of *Frankfurt School theorists such as
Herbert *Marcuse and Erich *Fromm to synthesize Freud with Marx in an idea of liberation
from repressive control. In general, Foucault is sceptical of the idea that modem
enlightened knowledge about sex necessarily emancipates human societies from the
repressive superstitions of traditional religious teaching about the sins of the flesh. Instead
Poucault suggests that modern 'sexual science' is no less bound up with forms of power
than traditional religious ideas of the body. Foucault argues that power is exercised
through the production of, and incitement to, dis course about sex and sexuality.
Discourses on sexuality produce new mechanisms of power by constituting subjects who
understand themselves in terms of the truth of their sex. A pro liferation of discourses on
sexuality pins us to telling the 'truth of ourselves', of our 'private' 'secret' nature. This,
Foucault argues, constitutes not a freedom from subjection but rather the development of
new forms of subjection. A new 'technology of sex', constituted through medicine,
psychiatry, pedagogy, and psychoanalysis, has become a key clement of modern
institutional power (1976: 116). Through it, individuals come to think of themselves and
their desires in relation to scientific notions of normality. A modem scientia sexualis replaces
more ancient ideas of the ars erotica or 'art of love'.
Foucault's concern in this volume and in volumes 2 and 3 of The History of Sexuality (1984a,
1984b) is to denaturalize certain deep-seated assumptions of modern Western culture. I!is aim
is to re-problematize a dominant problematization, to disturb its naturalness, to shake its hold
over us and to open spaces for thinking and acting differently. In this project we can see
that while one of his early aims was to overcome structuralism, his later arguments and
methods still reflect some of its characteristic principles. In his middle-period writings,
Foucault
212 SAMANYHA ASHENOEN
asserted that structuralism and *phenomenology share common ground, rather than being
opposites to each other. He maintained that structuralist formalization and *hermeneutic
interpretation represent 'two correlative techniques' of the modem human sciences, the
one being to discover structural invariants, the other being to discover hidden meanings
(1966a: 299). Foucault saw structuralism together with phenomenology as destined to
reinstate the 'transcendental-empirical doubling' of modem *anthropocentric culture. But
we can see that Foucault's own work in genealogy exhibits some notable theoretical
continuities with struc turalism and hermeneutical phenomenology. These especially
concern his account of how the human subject is constituted as an object of knowledge. In
his concern to contest fixity and to suggest the possibility of our becoming otherwise than
we are, foucault continued to share ½ith Saussure, Levi-Strauss, Lacan, and Derrida a refusal
to search for 'origins' in order to concentrate on symbolic structures and regimes of
discourse. In line ¼ith structuralist and post-structuralist thinking, roucault continued to
treat the human ;ubject not as a given or as a repository of meaning, but as an effect of
discourse. In his thesis, 'man' as such emerges only with the *Enlightenment. Modem
'humanity' brings with itself a specific prt>dicament that Foucault sees as tying us ever
more closely to the truth of ourselves as a relation of power.
Conclusion
French structuralist and post-structuralist theory has been as influential in the human sci
ences as it is controversial in its attribution to particular thinkers. This chapter has ought
to avoid suggesting any straightforward chronological transition from structuralism to
post structuralism in French thought. Such academic labelling tends to place more
inwstment in the packaging of thought than it does in examining the saliE'nce of ideas.
Post-structuralism cannot be understood either as a simple negation of structuralism or as
some form of repeat of it. If anything, it is perhaps best thought of as a qualified
radicalization of structuralism.
In considering the work of Saussure and Levi-Strauss, we have seen the importance of
the idea that language should be studied as a totality, where meaning is seen as a product
of dif ference. This logical and differential account of meaning provided Saussure with a
method ological solution to the limits of existing historical analyses of language.
According to Paul
*RicCl'ur (1969), it supplied Levi-Strauss with a *'Kantianism without a transcendental sub
ject'. That is, it enabled Levi-Strauss to analyse social life in terms of a universal scheme
of socially objectified concepts, leading him to develop rigorous and encompassing cat
egorizations of a wide range of anthropological material. For Saussure and Le,·i-Strauss,
the synchronic dimension was clearly marked out from and privileged over the diachronic.
In contrast, Derrida and Foucault break with the synchronic-diachronic distinction and
with the idea of totality. Instead, they focus on differ,rnce and on the historical ontology of
specific problematizationsof experience. Yet while both of these mows led away from
struc turalism in the classical sense, Derrida and foucault maintained a typically structural
view of meaning as imposed rather than disclosed, as generated by systems of formal
differencE's between signs. In these respects, all four thinkers provide illuminating ways
nf accounting for the human subject in ways that do not presuppose a prior human essence
or a primordial external reality called 'nature'. Rather, in all four writers, as well as in the
work of Roland
STRUCTURALISM AND ?OS'f HRU(TURALIS"• 213
4 What does Derrida mean by 'deconstruction'? How illuminating 1s his conception of the privilege
of logos in Western metaphys1Cs and the 'priority of speech over writing'?
5 How do Foucault's methodological premises about discourse, knowledge, 'epistemes', and
'genealogy' guide his substantive analyses of the operation of power in modern societies?
6 What are some implications of the structuralist and post-structuralist 'decentring of the subject'
for discussions of human agency in social theory?
7 Why are themes of 'identity' and 'difference' important to social and cultural theory?
■ FURTHER READING
Some useful introductions to structuralism and post-structuralism are John Sturrock's Structuralism
(Fontana, 2nd edn. 1993), Terrence Hawkes's Structwalism and Semiotics (Routledge, 1978), Catherine
Relsey'sPoststructuralism:A Very Shortlntroduction (Oxford University Press, 2002), and Sarup Madan's
An Introductory Guide to Post-structuralism and Postmodernism (Harvester, 1993). Try also John Lechte's
Fifty Conlf'mporary Thinkers: From Structuralism to Postmodernity (Routledge, 1994). A good collection
of readings in structuralism with commentaries is John Sturrock's Structumlism and Since: From Levi.
Strauss to Derrida (Oxford University Press, 1979). A useful general reference source in cultural theory
is David Macey's Dictionary of Critical Theory (Penguin, 2001). More detailed studies are Richard
Harland\ Superstructuralism: The Philosophy of Structuralism and Poststruct11ralism (Routledge, 1991 ),
J. G. Merquior's From PraguetoPari5: ACritiqueofStruct11ralism and Poststructumlism (Verso, 1986), Edith
l<urzweil's The Age of Structuralism: Levi-Stra11ss to Fo11ca11lt (Columbia University Press, 1980),
and Howard Gardner's The Quest for Mind: Piaget, Levi-Strauss and the Structuralist Movement
(Knopf, 1973). fora good comparison between Levi-Strauss, Durkheim, and American functionalism,
see Patrick Baert's Social Theory in the Twentieth Century (Polity Press, 1998). For a cogent critique of
214 SAMANTHA ASHENDEN
post-structuralism from the standpoint of critical theory, see Peter Dews's Logics of Disintegration:
Post-structuralist Thought and tile Claims of Critical Theory (Verso, 1987).
A good short introduction to Saussure isJonathan Culler's Saussure (Fontana, 1976). Equally good
isJonathan Culler's Bart/ies (Fontana, 1983) and the same author's broader study in literary and cul
tural theory Structuralist Poetics (Routledge, 1975). The recommended English translation of
Saussure's Course in General Linguistics is by Wade Baskin (Peter Owen, 1960). For an introduction
to Levi-Strauss, try Edmond Leach's Levi-Strauss (Fontana, 1974). Among Levi-Strauss's most
accessible works are his Totemism (Penguin, 1973), Myth and Meaning (Routledge, 1978), and Tristes
Tropiques (Penguin, 1973). Roland Barthes's Mythologies (Vintage, 2000) is fun to read. See.especially
his essay 'The Death of the Author', in Barthes's Image, Music, Text (Fontana, 1977).
For an introduction to Derrida, try Christopher Norris's Derrida (Fontana, 1987). For an in-depth
literary study, see Geoffrey Bennington's Jacques Derrida (University of Chicago Press, 1993). See also
Roy Boyn e's Foucault and Derrida: Tile Other Side of Reason (Unwin Hyman, 1990). For a small
selec tion from Derrida's voluminous writings, try Peggy Kamuf's A Derrida Reader (Harvester,
1991).Some good places to begin reading Derrida are part I, chapter 2, and part II, chapter 1, in Of
Grammatology on Saussure and Levi-Strauss. See the essays 'Structure, Sign, and Play in the
Discourse of the Human Sciences' and 'Cogito and the History of Madness' (on Foucault) in Writing and
Difference (Routledge, 1978) and the essay 'Differance', in Margins of Philosophy (University of
Chicago Press, 1982). Also useful is the collection of interviews with Derrida titled Positions (University
of Chicago Press, 1982). Some useful introductions to Foucault are J. G. Merquior's Foucault (Fontana,
1991), Lois McNay's Foucault: A Critical Introduction (Polity Press, 1994), and Barry Smart• Foucault
(Tavistock, 1985), as well as the editorial introductions to the three volumes in the Penguin series The
Essential Works of Mid1el Foucault(Penguin,1997-2000). Two verygood collections of essays and
extracts from Foucault are Paul Rabinow's edited The Foucault Reader (Penguin, 1984) and Colin
Gordon's edited Michel Foucault: Powe1/K1rowleJge (Harvester Wheatsheaf, 1980). A good place to
begin reading Foucault is his Discipline and Punish (Allen Lane, 1977). An excellent commentary on
Foucault is Hubert Dreyfus and Paul Rabinow's Michel Fouc,11/lt: Be,l'Olld Str11cturnlism am!
Hm11mez1tics \Uni\·ersity of Chicago Press. 1982). This book also contains an illuminating afterword by
Foucault, titled 'The Subject and Power'. See also Gary Gatting's edited Cambridge Companion to
Foucault (Cambridge University Press, 1994). For a very readable intellectual biography of Foucault, see
James Miller's Tile 1'11,,io11 o(Alic'lre/ Fo11c1111lt (Simon & Schuster, 1993). For an influential
development of Foucaultian ideas in the field of psychology in relation to the concept of
'governmentality',see Nikolas Rose's Powers of Freedom (Cambridge University Press, 1999). For
feminist perspectives on Foucault, see Lois McNay's Foucault and Feminism (Polity Press, 1992). For
Foucault's relationship to the work of Habermas, see Samantha Ashenden and David Owen's edited
Fo11rn11lt contra Habcrmm: Rcc11.,trns tire Ui,1/oguc l><'111·cc11 Gem,//og:,·and Critin1l T/1con (Sage, 1999),
as well as Michael Kelly's edited C, itique and Power: Recasting the Fo11ca11/t/Habem1as Debate
(MIT Press, 1994) and David Hoy and Thomas McCarthy's Critical Theory (Blackwell, 1992).
WEBSITES
Structure and agency are key concepts in social theory. Structure refers to regular,
relatively fixed, objective, and generalized features o( social life. Structure usually refers
to social institutions or 'systems', 'forces', or 'currents'. *Agency, on the other hand, refers
to action. Agency usually refers to the action of human individuals or groups of
individuals. Social theorists generally argue that social tructure is reproduced by the
actions of individuals through the mediation of rules, roles, and other resources broadly
referred to as 'culture'. In this sense, structure refers to social facts that are independent of
the imlividual and are able to determine and constrain individual action. In contra t.
agency refers to the observation that while constrained by the realities of their world,
individuals are capable of choosing alternative courses of action. Individuals can choose
what to do, even though their choices are restricted and shaped in various ways by
structural realities.
216 ANTHONY KING
This chapter discusses the strengths as well as some shortcomings of this general
account of social life. We concentrate mainly on the work of two influential contemporary
the orists: Anthony *Giddens and Pierre *Bourdieu. We also look more briefly at two
other - writers associated with a *realist school in British social theory who also employ
the concepts of structure and agency. These are Roy *Bhaskar and Margaret*Archer. The
chap ter focuses particularly on Giddens's theory of *'structuration' and on Bourdieu's
influen tial concepts of 'practice', *'habitus1, and 'cultural capital'.
One among several contexts of application of Giddens's idea of structuration has been international
relations research. In the 1980s, several reasearchers appealed to the concept of structuration in
an effort to overcome the so-called *'realist' paradigm that had been dominant in international
relations research since the Second World War (see further Wendt 1987). In drawing on the
concept of struc turation, these researchers showed how Giddens's theory could be applied not
only at the level of the actions of individual persons but also at the macrological level of the agency
of whole nation-states in a structural arena of global diplomacy.
Realism in international relations research has followed a different order of priorities from the ideas
signified technically by realism in sociological theory. During the Cold War, international relations
researchers In the realist school argued that international order consisted of strategies by individua l
nation-states aimed at a maximizing interests in power and advantage. The international order was
seen as having a particular structure, resting on a 'balance of power'. A nation-state's position in this
structure was seen as determining the strategies it was most rational for it to pursue.
Towards the end of the Cold War, several international relations theorists became dissatisfied
with this realist approach. They gave more emphasis to the cultural aspects and differences of the
actions of nation-states. They argued that important internal national norms affected the way a state
interacted with other states, and consequently that the international system did not have the rigid
structure affirmed by the realists. They developed a less deterministic account of the international
order, describing their approach as 'constructivist' rather that realist. They appealed to Giddens·s
theory of structuration insofar as it seemed to allow for elements of both individual agency and
structural constraint. Structuration theory allowed individual states more agency than under a realist
paradigm, while at the same time recognizing the existence of a constraining context to which nation-
states themselves con tributed through their actions. The international order was a 'medium' of state
action and an 'outcome' of state action. Individual states could transform the international order in
certain ways, while at the same time remaining bound by its relatively intransigent structure. Their
own transformative actions had the consequence of consolidating the structure, even as the
structure underwent change
In adapting G1ddens's theory in this way, the international relations researchers sought to steer a
middle path between both the *functionalist idea of an all-encompassing, all-determining global
system and the rational choice conception of advantage-maximizing actions by discrete nation-states.
They saw themselves as bringing together the two sides of the dichotomy in a more satisfactory
manner, emphasizing the interdependency of structure and agency and an interlacing of elements
of fixity with elements of transformation.
221
Like Giddens, Bourdieu also sought a way of reconciling objectivist tendencies in social
theory with subjectivist tendencies. The *objectivist emphasis on structure is embodied
for Bourdiru in French *structuralist theory, especially in the work of *Levi-Strauss
(discussed in Chapter 9 of this book). The *subjectivist emphasis on agency is embodied
for Bourdieu in
*phenomenological and *hermeneutical philosophy, especially in the *existentialism of
Jean-Paul *Sartre.
When Bourdieu began propounding his theories in the 1970s, he rejected Sartre's exist
entialism as untenably *voluntarist. Bourdieu emphasized that human social life could not
always be viewed in terms of unique personal choices. But Levi-Strauss's structuralism
was equally problematic, because human culture could not be reduced to a product of
universal
*cognitive templates operating above the heads of individuals. Human agents had to be
seen as capable of recognizing the significance of the cultural products they themselves
create through their actions. Bourdieu therefore sought to develop a social theory that
explained the institutional realities of modern society without either obliterating individ
ual agency or relapsing into subjectivist individualism. Like Giddens's synthesis of func
tionalism and interactionism, Bourdieu wanted to rescue the positive aspects of the work
of both Levi-Strauss and Sartre, to find a critical middle way between structuralism and
phe nomenology.
We begin here by looking at Bourdieu's first systematic treatise from the early 1970s, his
Outline of a Theory of Practice (1972). This grew out of his anthropological studies oft he Ka
byle tribespeople in the 1960s and provided a theoretical basis for all his subsequent research.
We then turn to his influential concepts of the 'habitus', 'field', and 'cultural capital'.
a 'reflexive sociology' is a grasp of the agency of the participant actors under observation,
and of the agency of the researchers who study them.
For Bourdieu, social agents are 'virtuosos' in the sense they are not dominated by abstract
rules but rather know the script so well that they can elaborate and improvise on the themes
it provides (1972: 79). Bourdicu describes social actors as having a 'sense of the game',
referring to footballers and tennis players as examples of this virtuosic sense. These players do
not apply a priori principles to their play-only beginners need to do that. Confronted with
diverse situations, they have an automatic understanding of what is appropriate. They
know, for in stance, when they should run to the net (1980: 66-7, 81). This virtuosic 'sense
of the game' is not individualistic. It arises in social relations and refers to the
understanding that actors de velop about what other group members regard as tolerable.
rlourdieu's discussion of honour among the Kabyle highlights this intersubjectivesense of
the game:
The driving of the whole mechanism is not some abstract principle (principle of isotimy, equality in
honour), still less the set of rules which can be derived from it but the sense of honour, a disposition
inculcated in earlier years of life and constantly reinforced by calls to order from the group.
(Bourdieu 1972: 14-15)
what exist in the social world are relations-not interactions between agents and
*intersubjective ties between individuals but objective relations which exist 'independent of
individual conscious ness and will', as Marx says ... In analytic terms a field may be defined as
a network, or a config uration of objective relations between positions. (Bourdieu and
Wacquant 1992: 97)
Bourdieu's concept of the field is intended to enrich the concept of the habitus.
Bourdieu shows how, in a field, groups struggle for supremacy and social distinctiveness.In
particular, he notes how, in contrast to the middle classes, the working class tend to value
functional clothing and food, making a cultural virtue out of an economic necessity. The
economic position of the working class conditions them to view the elaborate habits of the
bourgeoisie with disdain. Indulgence in certain tastes may come to seem repellent to the
working class.
224
Conversely, upper-class groups typically regard those beneath them in status as vulgar and
uncultured. At the same time, while superior groups try to monopolize certain cultural
prac tices, suhordinate groups attempt to adopt these practices in order to subvert the
status of superior groups. In adopting the practices of superior groups, subordinate groups
under mine the distinctiveness of these groups. We may think, for example, of the ways in
which expensive fashion accessories come to be acquired by middle-income groups in a
desire to imitate the rich and famous, and thereby gradually lose their distinctiveness.
The struggle for social distinctiveness is an empirically verifiable process which
Bourdieu usefully illuminates. One of his most revealing discussions appears in his
influential book from 1979, Distinction: A Social Critique of the Judgement of Taste. This is
discussed in Box 26.
Cultural capital
The habitus of an individual is a product of his or her position in the field. The field
is substantially formed by objective economic factors. The distribution of economic
resources in a society or more specifically the market determines the social hierarchy. In
a parallel to the structuralist Marxism of* Althusser, *Poulantzas, and *Miliband,
13ourdieu here maintains that an economic base finally determines the structural form that
a society can take. Dominant groups are those that monopolize economic resources, and
the *hege monic position of these groups over subordinate groups is a product of their
economic power.
However, in addition to this notion of economic determination, Bourdieu also develops
a concept of *'cultural capital'. Through the habitus, individuals and groups adopt certain
cultural practices. These practices reflect people's economic position, but the habitus and
the culture it imparts do not passively transmit the prior economic position in which indi
viduals find themselves. Through adopting certain kinds of cultural practices, individuals
can earn cultural capital. They can attain a higher status in the social order than their
purely economic position would allow by adopting and monopolizing cultural activities
that are admired and envied. Individuals and groups can develop cultural knowledge
which is arcane and which raises them above other groups, even above those more
economically powerful than them.
Bourdieu argues that intellectuals and artists, while relatively poor, have a rich habitus
that involves a commitment to difficult and time-consuming cultural forms. These groups
may not have the wealth of private sector professionals but they have the time and leisure
to be able to master respected cultural activities, to acquire 'refinement'. This is also true
of the traditional aristocracy. In this way, at least in France-which may or may not be a
spe cial case-possession of cultural capital allows intellectuals and artists to achieve a
social standing superior to their purely economic position.
In this sense Bourdieu's concept of the habitus suggests a formula for social *status. For
Bourdieu, social *status, defined as an individual's position in the social hierarchy, is a
product of an individual's economic and cultural capital taken together. While financiers,
stockbrokers, and bankers all have substantial economic capital, they are not automatically
dominant in the social field because they are low in cultural capital. In contrast, skilled
pro fessionals such as doctors and teachers, as well as state employees such as police
officers and
225
In his book Distinction: A Social Critique of the Judgement of Taste (1979) Bourdieu adopts a
sociolo gical perspective on questions of taste, aesthetic judgements, and preferences in cultural
goods. He elucidates the social conditions that make people's different tastes in art and culture what
they are. His approach can be described as a form of sociological *Kantianism in the sense that his
conception of the habitus functions in an analogous manner to Immanuel Kant's eighteenth-
century philosophical conception of basic organizing *cognitive categories of human intellection
and action.
Writing in the 1780s, Kant had divided the realm of rational intellectual life into three domains:
the domain of theoretical reason (involved in science), the domain of practical reason (involved in
morality), and the domain of aesthetic sensibility (involved in tastes about art). In each domain, Kant
had sought to identify certain transcendental principles which make each of these aspects of
human existence what they are. Kant had proposed that various cognitive categories precede
human perception and make meaningfully ordered experience possible. These organizing
categories essentially make the world what it is for human beings. In Distinction, Bourdieu seeks
to show how these cognitive cate gories arise from prior socio-economic conditions, and that it is
the socio-economic features of these categories that make the world what it is for human actors. He
concentrates particularly on bringing to light the sociological dimensions of the categories involved in
aesthetic sensibilities and cultural tastes in a given society. In this sense, his book can be seen as a
sociological response to the last of Kant's three
philosophical treatises, The Critique of Judgement, of 1790.
Elaborating the habitus empirically, Bourdieu carried out extensive quantitative and qualitative research into the
habits and tastes of social classes in France in the 1970s. He divided French society into four main social
classes; the working class, the petty bourgeoisie (the lower middle class) and the professional classes (the upper
middle class), which he subdivided into private and public sector fractions. He called the private
sector professionals the 'right bank', and the public sector professionals the 'left bank'. This was in
refer ence to the River Seine in Paris. The north 'right' bank of the Seine has historically been
associated with finance and government (the side of the Champs-Elysees). The south 'left' bank has
historically been asso ciated with art and culture (the side of the Latin Quarter and the University). The
right-bank elite consisted of bankers, businessmen, lawyers, and brokers, while the left-bank elite
referred to teachers, academics, intellectuals, artists, and writers. Bourdieu accepted that class positions in
Paris were decisively determined by economic capital. Consequently, the right-bank elite were dominant.
Nevertheless, cultural capital also played an important role in a class's social status. The right-bank elite
possessed extensive economic capital but had little cultural capital. Cultural capital was substantially
monopolized by the left-bank elite. The right-bank elite engaged in 'hedonistic' activities which
conspicuously demonstrated their economic cap ital. They indulged in expensive foods and elaborate
holidays in exclusive locations. The left bank, by contrast, chose activities which did not require
significant economic capital but which demonstrated cul tural sophistication and, above all, the time
required to acquire these arcane tastes. In this way, the left bank distinguished itself from other groups.
The left bank favoured difficult modern music and engaged in inex pensive but personally demanding
sports such as cross-country skiing, mountaineering, and hill-walking.
Although not without its problems, Bourdieu's analysis of the left- and right-bank professionals
is suggestive because it recognizes growing divide between public and private sector professionals in
a context of *post-Fordist employment cultures. By contrast, his account of the working class and
the petty bourgeoisie is less convincing, and has not been seen as providing an accurate sociology of
these groups. It has been argued that Bourdieu exaggerates the extent to which the lower classes' lack
of the economic and educational advantages of elites predestines them to particular ways of lite.
Nevertheless, Bourdieu's book remains one of the most important sociological analyses of class
culture.
226 i rHIIGN\' KING
government officers, and relatively impoverished intellectuals and artists are able to
contest social dominance by the materially rich through their monopolization of
cultural capital. The social hierarchy is thus a product of a struggle between groups on the
basis of both economic capital and cultural capital. Cultural capital is conditioned by
economic capital but is not predetermined by it. For example, a graduate of an elite
university may have come from a wealthy family background, but if the graduate
then makes a successful career in the business world, it is the graduate's cultural capital
acquired at university which must be identified as the prime cause of the graduate's
success, rather than the economic capital of the graduate's family. Another graduate from
the same elite university but not from a wealthy family background might in principle
have the same chance of success, on the strength of the university-acquired cultural
capital alone.
Bourdieu's conception of cultural capital is very clearly illuminated both in his book
Distinction and in his study of the sociology of education, titled Homo Academicus (1984).
The latter text is discussed in Box 27.
In the field of education research, Bourdieu's concept of the habitus has been enduring. When the habitus
refers not to static cultural templates arising automatically from a prior material reality but more
dynam ically to exclusive group culture, 1t is very illuminating. Employing the concept in this way, Bourdieu
makes some interesting arguments about the reproduction of social inequality in schools and
academies. In the postscript to Homo Academicus (1984), his study of the French educational system,
Bourdieu contends that the examinations that students have to pass to receive their all-important
diplomas are not judged purely on objective academic criteria but also to some extent on criteria of social
fitness. In his provocative thesis, the French academy is founded on a system of cultural exclusion
where the values of the middle classes are imposed in the examining procedure. The physical
mannerisms and writing style of students become criteria for grading them, rather than purely impartial
pedagogical judgements. In his analysis of marking schemes, Bourdieu notes that 'the most favourable
epithets appear more and more frequently
as the social origins of pupils rise' (Bourdieu 1984: 198). Consequently, the academy remains closed to the
children of the working classes, while it is conveniently monopolized by the professional classes with the
requisite cultural capital
There are some problems with Bourdieu's argument insofar as he overemphasizes the closure of the 1
academy to non-professional social groups. He allows for no flexibility in the process, just as his formal
227
Both Bourdieu's and Giddens's reflections on structure and agency suffer from various
problems to which we must turn in a moment. But before doing so, we move now to a
third and last set of contributions to be found in the work of the British *realist theorists
Roy
*Bhaskar and Margaret *Archer.
After his seminal contributions to the philosophy of science in the early 1970s, Roy
Bhaskar became a prominent figure in British social theory. In a similar fashion to
Giddens and Rourdicu, Bhaskar understands society in terms of the reproduction of
structure by individ ual agency through the mediation of culture. Bhaskar's realism claims
that society consists of certain dimensions of reality which cannot be understood by
reference to individual activity and belief alone. Social action has emergent properties
which exceed consciousness of the individual. Although no institutions would exist
without individuals to fulfil the roles that compose them, they have properties which
transcend the individuals who create the institutions. For Bhaskar, society consists of
irreducibly real social structures.
Bhaskar endorses Giddens's structuration theory and explicitly relates it to his own
work (Bhaskar 1979: 45). He describes his own realist theory as the 'Transformational
Model of Social Action', and regards this as compatible with structuration. The
transformational model of social action claims that society consists of structure and
agency. Structure precedes indi vidual agency but structure can only be reproduced and
transformed through individual agency. Individuals are confronted by a social structure
which constrains them but which does not finally determine them. In their actions,
individuals can manipulate the structure by reinterpreting their situation and thus developing
new forms of agency. In this way, individu als are able to transform the social structure.
In her 'morphogenetic social theory', Margaret Archer advocates a position close to
Bhaskar's (Archer 1995). Ry 'morphogenetic' Archer refers to the process by which
patterns or 'shapes' are generated in repeated social action. Like Bhaskar, Archer sees
society as consisting of real social structures irreducible to individuals. Archer berates
those social theorists who fail to recognize the dual nature of social reality, who either
collapse struc ture into individuals or assimilate individuals to structure. For her, society
consists both of objective structures and of individual agents. Neither of these two
dimensions can be derived or reconstructed from each other.
Archer maintains that Giddens collapses the objective institutional fact of society into
the individual. Unlike Bhaskar, she sees Giddens's structuration theory as a one
dimensional form of methodological individualism (Archer 1982: 458 ff., 1988: 72). In her
book Culture and Agency (1988), Archer argues that culture emerges out of individual
activity but that once it has been created, especially when it is embodied in physical
artefacts, it has an objectivity which transcends the individual. Architecture, artworks, books,
and mathematical formulas all attain an existence which is autonomous of everyday social
intercourse. According to Archer, the autonomy of culture is decisive in explaining social
reproduction and transformation. Individuals in a society are confronted by a cultural sys
tem which is independent of them. Often individuals draw automaticaily on the most
obvious elements of this culture to perform regular practices which reproduce the syst;;m.
228 ·, I.
However, Archer also argues that the autonomous status of culture facilitates change.
Since the cultural system docs not depend merely on what people here and now believe, it
can be drawn upon in different ways, or forgotten elements within it can be emphasized. In
this way, individuals can develop new forms of practice and thereby transform the
patterns of socio-cultural integration in their society. They can change the institutional
structures of a society by developing new relations to the cultural system. Particular
individuals may note and then eventually act upon potential contradictions between the
cultural system and everyday practice. Individuals can draw on autonomous cultural
resources to direct their everyday practice, producing either change or stasis.
Archer's criticisms of Giddens are not without merit. However, it can be argued that her
own 'morphogenetic social theory' in fact resembles Giddens's theory in certain respects
and arguably shares some of its problems. Her lexicon differs from Giddens's but her de
scription of the autonomy and function of the cultural system follows structuration theory
quite closely. It can be argued that her idea of the 'cultural system' operates in the same
way as Giddens's idea of 'structure'. Archer's 'cultural system' consists of diverse formulas,
rules, and ideas which are autonomous of individuals but upon which individuals must
draw if they are to act in a recognizable fashion. The cultural system mediates between the
institu tions of the social system and the individual. It channels individual practice so that
struc tural reproduction can occur, but it also allows for the transformation of the social
structure through the agency of individuals.
Some of the most general problems with this way of theorizing are brought together
in the next section. These problems can be described in terms of a basic dilemma of
determinism and individualism in debates about structure and agency.
Writers on structure and agency such as Giddens, Bourdieu, Bhaskar, and Archer tend
to face a rather difficult dilemma. This dilemma can be described as having the following
two sides. On the one hand, there is a side of *determinism. On the other hand, there is a
side of excessive methodological*individualism. Let us look first at the determinist
side.
Giddens, Bourdieu, Bhaskar, and Archer argue that social life is to be explained by the
postulate of rules which direct individual action. 13ourdieu claims that the habitus
imposes certain tastes on individuals so that they necessarily adopt social practices
appropriate for their class position. In Giddens's picture, individuals seem to have a more
active say in how they follow the rules of structure. But still, their practices are said
necessarily to instantiate structure and thereby to reproduce the wider social system to
which these rules are attached. In each of these writers, institutional forms are said to be
reproduced in accordance with cultural rules. These rules-be they Bourdieu's 'habitus'
or Giddens's 'structure'-are said to direct or to determine individual action.
The danger here is that if it is said that individuals are directed by rules which impose
on them and of which they are not fully aware, human agency tends to be denied.
229
It seems that individuals no longer consciously choose what to do but are merely directed
by these prior rules. This determinism is clear in Bourdieu's writing. His concept of
the habitus has a tendency to emasculate human agency, to reduce dynamic and
uncertain social interaction to the inevitable reproduction of institutional structures.
The habitus imposes certain forms of conduct on the individual. Individual agents
reproduce the insti tutional structure of the field because they are determined by these
unavoidable cultural predispositions.
The problem is similar for Giddens. Because of Giddens's emphasis on the creativity of
the individual, the determinist implications of his structuration theory are less immedi
ately apparent. But in fact, Giddens is not free from this problem either. Giddens emphas
izes that structure is inexorably attached to the social system and therefore that for the
most part individuals automatically reproduce the system. The implication of Giddens's
theory is that structure ensures that individuals always act in a way which is compatible
with that system. Although he does not explain this relationship, individuals necessarily
act in a way which is consistent with social order.
Now let us look at the individualist side of the dilemma. Giddens and Bourdieu are
right to want to reject determinism. Giddens is at pains to emphasize that his theory
allows for the fact that individuals can always choose alternative courses of action and
that whatever structural imperatives obtain, 'the individual could have acted otherwise'
(Giddens 1984: 75). Similarly, Bourdieu asserts that his theory allows for the persistence
of individual agency in the face of the objectivity of the habitus. Bourdieu has been
incredulous at those critics of his work who have interpreted the habitus in a deterministic
fashion (see Bourdieu and Wacquant 1992: 134). Bourdieu sees the habitus as allowing
room for slip page: individuals, he claims, are not completely determined by the habitus
but can manip ulate the cultural resources available to them to develop new social
practices. He insists that individuals still have agency under the habitus.
Here the danger for Bourdieu and Giddens, however, is that if individuals are free at any
moment to do otherwise, it is possible that structure or habitus do not really constrain
what they do. It is possible that if individuals possess this freedom, structure or habitus are
not really guaranteeing that individuals act in appropriate ways-because at any time,
individ uals could adopt new forms of action at random. And if individuals can do
otherwise some of the time, they could do otherwise all of the time-so that neither
structure nor habitus prevent them from acting randomly. Therefore the danger in
Giddens's and Bourdieu's theory is that individuals only choose to follow structure or
habitus. And if they only choose to follow structure or habitus, they could at any moment
choose not to follow them. Regular social interaction here seems to be explained finally
only by individual choice.
The dilemma is thus this. Either structure-agency thinking tends to emasculate indi
vidual agency, claiming that individuals are determined externally by structures or habitus.
Or structure-agency thinking tends to overassert the agency of individuals, leaving the per
sistence and resilience of regular social institutions impossible to explain and endowing
individuals always with the possibility of acting otherwise. In this sense, structure-agency
thinking tends toward a danger of determinism on the one hand and a danger of
randomness of choices on the other hand. (For further discussions of this dilemma, see
Sewell 1992; Schatzki 1987, 1997; Taylor 1993; King 2000a, 2000b, 2004).
230 - iHrWNY l(IN
structure in any mechanical sense and more in terms of ongoing dynamic interrelations
between aLtors. Human beings do not 'reproduce' structure 'by means of' culture. Rather,
t,,g,'th,'t lium,111 i11tt'r,1ct "1th c.1(11 ,,til,'r b, rdt'rt•nn·tt) sh.ired understandings. l'hrough
these interminable interactions, the social relations which compose a society are sustained
and transformed. Thus a society should not be seen as consisting *ontologically or
metaphysicallv of two basic substanct:s one substance called 'structure' and one substance
called 'agency' Rather, it should be seen as consisting of social relations between individ
ual actor• all ol whom act under \'anous constraints which we call 'institutions', 'forces',
'trends', 'power' or 'powers', and so on. In these webs of social relations, both the regularity
and the ueati\ it) of indi, 1dual action become more explicable. Together, individuals
orient themselves to, ards shared gl als, and together they are able to develop new forms
of practice. !'he social realit) of r lations between human persons should not be reduced to
a static ,md *du.1listic image of indiYiduals confronting objective structures.
Individual
,Ktors d0 not \·0nsult' cultural rul sin their relationship to structures. Rather, they come
t,, mut 11.li 111hkr,t.111d111p ,,f\, lut c,,n titutL'' -1pp1,1pri,1ll' .idi,111, and arc able to bind
each other to these appropriate forms of conduct.
Conclusion
Structure and agencv ha"e been key concept. in social theory In general, it is common
place to aq,'l1e tlldt social structure is reproduced b\ mean of the agency of individuals,
through the mediation of ultural rule and re ources. There are certain problematic
!t'nd,·th 1,·, 111 t111, 11.n ,,t thinking \\·h1d1 111,1, k.1d tu .111 imp,issc bct,1'L'l'I1 O\'erly objectivist
or dftm11i11ist 1ccotmts and owrly subjectiYist or individualist accounts of the dynamics of
,,,,·1.ll l1k. t ru,·tu1, ,1g,·11,, t hinklllg ,'It 11,•r ru11, .i ri,k t1f ,'ma,cul.iting indi,·idual
agency i11 ,,rd,'r t,, cq,l.1111 st rudur.1l rq,r,,duct i,H1. ,,r it ru11s .1 risk pf un·remphasizing
individual freedom and thereby leaving structural reproduction mysterious.
I I 231
Nevertheless, the concepts of structure and agency continue to hold pragmatic value for
empirical social research. The theoretical analyses of Giddens, Bhaskar, Archer, and espe
cially Bourdieu have been fertile for sociologists, and the value of their work particularly
comes into view when structure and agency are not thought of as rigid or static ontological
poles but rather in terms of dynamic contexts of social relations between interacting indi
viduals and groups. Human groups are not determined by rules which impose upon them,
nor do they follow rules in private isolation. Individuals are able to act relatively
predictably and to create social order because they routinely accept certain common
understandings of what is appropriate, and these understandings become binding and
constraining. It is the task of sociologists to analyse the historical significance ofsocial
processes that emerge from these dynamic relations.
How useful are the concepts of structure and agency for social analysis?
2 How similar and how different are the social theories of Giddens and Bourdieu?
4 How illuminating is Bourdieu's assertion that cultural tastes and educational achievements are
functions of 'cultural capital'?
5 What differences are to be noted between the concept of class and the concept of habitus?
FURTHER READING
For useful introductions to the work of Giddens, see Lars Bo Kaspersen's Anthony Giddens:
An Introduction to a Social Theorist (Blackwell, 2000), Kenneth Tucker's Anthony Giddens and
Modern Social Theory (Sage, 1998), Ira J. Cohen's Structuration Theory (Macmillan, 1989), and Ian
Craib's Anthony Giddens (Routledge, 1992). For a good overall account of Giddens's theory of
structuration, seeJohn Parker's Structuration (Open University Press, 2000). The best collection of sec
ondary work on structuration theory is David Held and John B. Thompson's edited Social Theory of
Modern Societies: Anthony Giddens and his Critics (Cambridge University Press, 1989). See also
Christopher Bryant and DavidJary's edited Giddens' Theory ofStructuration (Routledge, 1991) and].
Clark, C. Modgil, and S. Modgil's edited Anthony Giddens: Consensus and Controversy (Falmcr
Press, 1990). For a wide-ranging collection of essays, see Christopher Bryant and David Jary's
edited four volumes Anthony Giddens: Critical Assessments (Routledge, 1996). The key texts for
Giddens's theory of structuration are The Constitution of Society (Polity Press, 1984), New Rules of
Sociological Method (Hutchinson, 1976), and Central Problems in Social Theory (Macmillan, 1979).
For an incisive critique of Giddens, see Alex Callinicos's two articles 'Anthony Giddens: A
Contemporary Critique', Theory and Society, 14 5 (1985), 133-66, and 'Social Theory Put to the Test
of Practice: Pierre Bourdieu and Anthony Giddens', New Left Review, 236 (1999), 77-102.
232 ANlHONY KING
Some good studies and guides to Bourdieu are Derek Robbins's two books The Work of Pierre
Bour,1ieu (Open University Press, 1991) and Bourdieu and Culture (Sage, 2000), David Swartz's
Culture
,111.! /'111-11'1:·1lw.\ociolns_rof l'iem• /lu11ri/i('II (( :hicago University Press, 1997), l(id1ardJenkins'sBourdieu
(Routledge, 1993), Bridget Fowler's Pierre Bourdieu and Cultural Theory (Sage, 1997), and Jen Webb,
Tony Schirato, and Geoff Danaher's Understanding Bourdieu (Sage, 2002). An excellent advanced col
lection of essays on Bourdieu is C. Calhoun, E. LiPuma, and M. Postone's edited Bourdieu: Critical
Perspedives (Polity Press, 1993). In this collection, see especially the contribution by Charles Taylor,
titled 'To Follow a Rule'. See also the discussion in Craig Calhoun's Critical Social Theory (Blackwell,
1995), as well as Richard Shuster man's edited Bourdieu: A Critical Reader (Blackwell, 1999) and Derek
Hol>i>im\ l'ditvd four volunws l'iC'trC' Bourdinr (Sage, 2000). A meful selection from Bourdieu's works
isJohn B. Thompson's edited J,anguage and Symbolic Power: Pierre Bourdieu (Polity Press, 1991), A good
place to begin reading Bourdieu is his book Distinction: A Social Critique of the Judgement of Taste
(Routledge, 1984), as well as his co-written book with Lale Wacquant An Invitation to Reflexive
Sociology (Polity Press, 1992). For further developments in French and American sociology influ
enced by Bourdicu, see Michele Lamont and Laurent Thevenot's edited Rethinking Comparative
Culturul Sociology ( am bridge University Press, 2000).
For a guide to Bntish realist theory, sec Andrew Collier's Critical Realism: An Introduction to Roy
Hhaskar's Philosophy (Verso, 1994)..Margaret Archer's key works are Culture and Agency (Cambridge
University Press, 1988) and Reulist Social Theory (Cambridge University Press, 1995). See also Jose
L6pez and John Scott's useful guide Social Structure (Open University Press, 2000) and Charles
Crothers's Sociul Structure (Routledge, 1996). For a comparative critical study of Giddens, Bourdieu,
Archer, and realist theory, see Anthony King's The Structure of Contemporary Social Theory
(Routledge, 2004).
Iii WEBSITES
Women in classical social theory: the exclusion of women from the social 234
Feminist perspectives on Weber, Durkheim, and Simmel 235
The body as an 'absent presence' in classical and contemporary theory 236
Women and socialization: labour, reproduction, and sexuality 237
Feminism and Marxism 238
Modernity as a gendered construct 239
Constructions of femininity and masculinity 240
The sex-gender distinction 243
Heterosexuality and homosexuality 245
Gender and its relation to exclusion 246
Feminism and postcolonial theory 247
Conclusion 249
There are a number of ways in which the history of feminist social theory has been
thought and told. One of the most often rehearsed is the idea that feminist social theory
has moved away from the ideals of *Enlightenment thought, associated with *universalist
values of rationality, reason, and equality. It has been claimed that feminist social theory
has moved instead towards 'post-Enlightenment' values, associated with ideas of 'differ
ence', 'specificity', and *'particularism'. In this sense it has been suggested that feminist
social theory has contested the ideals that classical social theory both embodied and
contributed towards-ideals exemplified in the work of figures such as Marx, Weber,
Durkheim, and Simmel.
While this narrative is widely told and certainly sheds light on some important traject
ories of feminist social theory, it is misleading to speak of any straightforward shift from
234 £ l'>A AOK rJS
modern, indeed as outside the very object of social theory-the social. This can be
illustrated in various aspects of the work of Weber, Durkheim, and Simmel.
They are often presented as being unable to achieve the mental condition required for
participation in modern forms of social action. In Suicide Durkheim writes that man is
'almost entirely the product of society', while woman is 'to a far greater extent the product
of nature' (Durkheim 1897: 385; see also Sydie 1987: 32). Durkheim also asserts that man's
'tastes, aspirations and humour have in large part a collective origin, while his companion's
are more directly influenced by her organism' (Durkheim 1897: 385; see also Sydie 1987: 32).
This is held to be so even for those women who participate in public life. In
ThcVivisionofLabourinSociety, Durkheim writes of such women: 'Certain classes of women
participate in artistic and literary life just as men ... But, even in this sphere of action,
woman carries out her own nature, and her role is very specialized, very different from
that of man' (Durkheim 1893: 19-20).
In Simmel's two notable essays 'The Relative and the Absolute in the Problem of
the Sexes' and 'Female Culture' (1911b, 1911c), women are similarly positioned as
unable to achieve the capacities for participation in the social. Two aspects can be
observed in these essays. On the one hand, Simmel is unique in classical sociology in his
concern to criticize the equation of masculinity with modernity. For Simmel, women's
experience of life operates as a challenge to the alienating, contradictory, and dizzying
experiences of modernity. Women possess a 'non-differentiated wholeness'; they
remain centred, or 'grounded', in themselves. In contrast, Simmel saw men as
suffering the ill fortune of experiencing all the fragmenting, alienating, and
differentiating forces of modernity. On the other hand, Simmel locates femininity and
women outside the socio-historical time of modernity. They remain outside the socio-
cultural arrangements and experiences his the ory describes. This is the case for Simmel
as the 'non-differentiated wholeness' of women ensures that women do not, and cannot,
experience or achieve the detachment and critical reflection necessary for participation in
the cultural and institutional forms of modernity. In Simmel's social theory, women
cannot transcend their being-a being which Simmel defined primarily in terms of
sexuality-in order to become social agents. Femininity and feminine culture occupy a
zone of 'being', rather than a zone of 'becoming', one of imman ence rather than of
transcendence. As Marshall and Witz comment, in the early socio logical imaginary of
Durkheim and Simmel 'women are locked into and overwhelmed by their corporeality,
whilst men rise above it and are defined, determined and distinguished by their sociality'
(Marshall and Witz 2003: 28; see also Felski 1995; Witz 2001).
idea of a self-fashioned identity fails to take into account certain embocliecl, embedded,
and habituated aspects of identity, especially those connected to gender and sexuality,
which are not straightforwardly available to self-fashioning. Mcl\ay is not suggesting here
that gender and sexual identities arc tixcd. Rather, following 13ourdieu (1972), she argues
that there are aspects of identity which are not accessible to self-conscious transforma
tion. She suggests that sexual desire and maternal feeling are relatively entrenched and
pre-reflexive aspects of identity which are not open to deliberate alteration. McNay
suggests that in emphasizing increased capacities for the self-fashioning of identity and
overlooking issues of habit and embodiment, recent social theory reinstates the idea of an
abstract, disembodied, rational and masculine subject found so commonly in the classical
tradition.
The influence of the classical tradition has been detected in branches of contemporary
theory which at face value appear to break with this legacy. In particular, recent sociologi
cal writing on the body has drawn attention to problems of mind-body dualism in classical
sociology, but has not always sufficiently recognized the gendered aspects of this dualism
(see for example, Turner 1984; Williams and Bendelow 1998). Writers on the body have sug
gested that mind-body dualism can be countered by discovering embodied themes and
subplots in the works of Marx, Weber, Durkheim, and Simmel. Thus Shilling (1993) notes
an embodied subplot in Marx's writings on emerging modes of capitalist modes of regula
tion. Specifically, Shilling suggests that in Marx's writings, capitalist forms of regulation
develop not simply through consciousness (the mind) but also through the body.
Capitalist technology ties and subordinates both working minds and bodies to machinery.
Such contemporary accounb suggest that rather than being entirely absent, the hody is an
'absent presence' in the classical tradition. It is, however, important to emphasize that such
mind-body dualism is also a gendered dualism (Witz 2000). Contemporary sociologists of
the body have not always sufficiently registered the fact that the classical tradition tended
to associate specifically women with the body. As a result, the forms of embodied
sociality that social theory discovers and makes explicit are in danger of remaining
predominantly masculine.
they tend to be concerned largely only with filling in the gaps of maintream research.
They advert to various occluded elementsof women's experience in appropriate ways, but
with out always questioning the fundamental organizing concepts and categories of
main stream thinking. In general, it is possible to qualify this work as 'correctionist' in
character. It represents an attempt to modify an androcentric bias via a strategy of
inserting women into already existing theoretical discourses and narratives. This strategy
continues to be of great importance, but it often tends to leave the major assumptions of
the canon un touched in unfortunate ways. As a consequence, it sometimes fails to
grasp adequately a crucial characteristic of the very narratives and discourses it seeks to
correct, namely, that these narratives are gendered in character.
In contrast, some of the most important feminist work in recent years has sought not
sim ply to include women in modernity, but also to explore what can be called the
*gendering of modernity. In the words of Janet Wolff, such work has raised not simply 'a
question of dis covering women's point of view, or making visible those obscured by a
masculinist view of modernity, or of promoting the hidden features of a "feminine
sensibility" in modern life'. Rather, it has involved a 'project of the critical analysis of the
discourses of modernity, in order to confront directly their constructions of masculinity'
(Wolff 2000: 37-8; see also Harding 1986; D. E. Smith 1987).
In confronting this gendering of modernity, more recent feminist work has moved
beyond correctionist writing in two respects. First, it has registered that the project of
socializing women has tended to rely on a rather problematic dualistic distinction between
'sex and gender'.Secondly, it has shown how the woman who was animated in the project
of the socialization of women was too homogeneous and in particular too exclusively
endowed with white European bourgeois and heterosexual characteristics.
The remaining sections of this chapter discuss three further elements of feminist social
theory in this latter framework: first, the idea of modern culture and society as a gendered
construct; secondly, debates around the meaning of gender and the sex-gender distinc
tion; and thirdly, debates about the relationship of gender to other dimensions of inequal
ity, including 'race', ethnicity, and sexual orientation.
traits. Thus widows, lesbians, and prostitutes are described in Baudelaire as possessing
masculine characteristics and mannerisms. Indeed Baudelaire's 'mixed admiration for the
lesbian has much to do with her supposed "mannishness"' (Wolff 1990: 42).
Yet while the prostitute and the lesbian may have occupied some of the same city
spaces as men, nineteenth-century writings ascribed heterosexual bourgeois women to
entirely different city spaces. These typically included the rapidly developing sites of
bourgeois consumption, notably the department store (compare Reekie 1993). The
department store was an ambiguous space, both in a public and a private sense. The
purchases made there by middle-class women were not simply for themselves but for the
bourgeois family and home. The development of such bourgeois sites of consumption
stemmed from, and was in part constitutive of, the rapidly developing bourgeois private
sphere. As Wilson (1991) points out, in such public spaces middle-class women looked
and were looked at. What counted in such spaces was respectability. The spaces of
consumption and its very process were central to the development of respectable middle-
class femininity (see also McClintock 1995; Lury 1996; Davidoff and Hall 1987).
What is important in these observations of the place and categorization of women in
the literature of modernity is that they make explicit what is often left hidden in canonical
social theory. They reveal that the changes and upheavals which classical social theory
sought to illuminate rested on an increasing separation of public and private spheres of
activity. The rise of sociology itself in the nineteenth century was closely bound up with
this separation. It is important to note that the emergence of forms of differentiation be
tween public and private was both classed and gendered. The backdrop to much classical
social theory was the emergence and legitimation of new bourgeois ideals regarding the
place of men and women in the social, as well new ideals of masculinity and femininity.
The latter concerned the elaboration of ideals of a competitive masculinity and a domestic
nurturing femininity, ideals which were realized in the formation of separate spheres of
public and private. As Felski (1995) points out, while these arrangements were feasible
only for a minority of middle-class households, the model of a *binary opposition
between the sexes crystallized in the notion of separate spheres, underscoring a host of
institutional practices and conventions. The latter included the sexual division of labour
and the sexual division of political rights.
Seen in this light, we may say that the ambivalence displayed towards women who
participated in the public sphere in the nineteenth century, including their very identi
fication and classification as non-respectable women-for instance as prostitutes, widows,
or labouring women-was made possible by new ideals of respectable femininity. We can
understand classical sociology's naturalization of women's place in the domestic sphere,
its romanticization of women's role as nurturing mothers, and its positioning of women
as unable to transcend their corporeality, indeed as corporeality, in terms of a binary
opposition between 'femininity' and 'masculinity'. It is in this sense that classical socio
logy made sense of modernity via 'a deeply gendered analysis of social life'-even as it laid
claim to impartial universal validity (Marshall 1994: 2). While basing itself on a series of
binary distinctions-between public and private, economy and family, universal and
particular-social theory has not often considered the gendered character of its guiding
distinctions. Such distinctions have led to a misleading conflation of modernity with
masculinity, a classification of non-bourgeois women as non-respectableor 'mannish', and
an assignment of bourgeois women to domesticity.
242 i ISA ADKINS
The US feminist Nancy *Fraser has examined an interesting subplot about gender in Jurgen
*Habermas's influential conception of the *'public sphere' (discussed also in Chapters 7 and 13 of
this book, pp. 164-5, 279-83). Referring to Habermas's view of modernization as involving an
uncoupling of 'system' and 'lifeworld', Fraser suggests that Habermas's conception rests on a
gendered subtext which prioritizes masculine identity.
Habermas argues that modernization involves a colonization of the 'lifeworld' by the 'system'.
Criticizing this process of colonization, Habermas argues that the systems of the state and the
mar ket ought to be embedded in, and constrained, by lifeworld institutions. Habermas argues that
the private sphere becomes dominated by the economic system and that the public sphere-the site
and space of political participation-becomes dominated by the state system. He argues that this
domination of the private- sphere takes place via a set of exchanges conducted in the medium of
money. It provides the economy with labour power in exchange for wages and demand for goods
and services (commodities). In Habermasian social theory, as Fraser puts it, 'exchanges between fam
ily and (official) economy ... are channeled through the "roles" of worker and consumer' (Fraser
1989 123)
Intervening in this theory, Fraser points out that these roles of worker and consumer in capitalist
societies are also distinctly gendered. This gendering means that the relations between the private
sphere and the economy must be understood to take place via the medium of modern gender
identity-not only by the neutral medium of money. In capitalist societies, the role of the worker has
been gendered as male, at least until relatively recently (compare Lovell 2000; Adkins 2002). Thus the
role of the worker has been historically associated with masculinity, embodied in struggles for a
fam ily wage. These struggle assumed that a worker is a man with a dependent wife and children.
Given this gendering of the worker as male, women in capitalist societies have typically not been
employed on the same terms as men (compare Adkins 1995; Pateman 1988; Pringle 1988; Walby
1986). As Fraser puts it, there has been 'a conceptual dissonance between femininity and the work
role in classical capitalism [which] confirms the masculine subtext of that role' (Fraser 1989: 125).
Moreover, the role of the private sphere in consumer capitalism is far from neutral: it has historically
been overwhelmingly associated with women. It is women who have been typically charged with
the work of domestic consumption, including the work of domestic display and taste-making, or
what Bourdieu (1979) terms social 'distinction' (see also Delphy and Leonard 1992; Game and
Pringle 1984; Hollows 2000; Lury 1996). Fraser thus concludes that Habermas fails to appreciate
that one of the most important media of exchange in capitalist societies is gender identity. Habermas
only understands the categories of 'worker' and 'consumer' in gender-neutral language of monetary
exchange.
We can see here how Fraser makes several important conceptual moves. First, she shows how
the problem with mainstream social theory is not so much that women have been straightforwardly
excluded from the social but rather that gender remains a hidden and taken-for-granted component of it.
Secondly, in her rethinking of the categories of worker, consumer, and exchange and the relations
between public and private spheres, she does not simply correct the bias of social theory by merely
adding women into an
already existing framework. Rather, she engages in a reconceptualization of modernity along
gendered lines.
FEMINIST SOCIAL THEOR 243
One revealing exposure of a hidden subplot about gender in contemporary social theory
is the work of the US feminist theorist Nancy Fraser in relation to Jurgen Habermas's
con cept of the public sphere. This is discussed here in Box 28.
We turn now to a second object of contention in feminist writing aimed at revising purely
'correctionist' research. This is the distinction between 'sex' on the one hand and
'gender' on the other.
In her classic work The Second Sex, the French feminist philosopher Simone de *Beauvoir
famously declared: 'One is not born a woman, one hecomes one' (1949: 295). for feminist
theorists and sociologists, de Beauvoir's leitmotif has been vital to the project of
socializing women. De Beauvoir explained how the social position, identity, and
consciousness of women are products of a form of interaction which systematically
positions woman as Other to a universal subject, a subject who is unmarked as Man. From
de Beauvoir's standpoint, the hierarchical and antagonistic positioning of men and women
was to be seen as socially produced. It was this injunction that allowed for a modern
feminist concept of gender, a concept which, as Donna *Haraway puts it, was 'developed
to contest the naturalization of sexual difference in multiple arenas of struggle' (Haraway
1991a: 131). The concept of gender was developed as a foil to the view found in much
classical social theory that women exist outside the socio-historical time of modernity,
typically via an association with nature. It was through the concept of gender that feminist
theorists placed women inside the contours of the social and allowed for an elaboration of
the category of woman as both collective and historical. It allowed women to be written
into history.
There is, however, a problem with the concept of gender when it is formulated in this
way, insofar as it relies on a rather problematic distinction between 'sex and gender'.
'Sex' has been defined as anatomical, physical differences between men and women, while
'gender' has been understood as the social meanings given to such differences. Sex has
been understood to be biological; gender has been thought to be cultural. Sex has been
typically understood as a neutral inscriptive surface, onto which external social meaning is
mapped.
It was in this sense that Michele Barrett took issue with feminists in the 1970s whom
she saw as invoking universalizing, ahistorical, and biologistic notions of male
dominance. Barrett argued that such accounts failed to grasp 'the distinction
between sex as a biological category and gender as a social one' (Barrett 1980: 13). In
the 1970s, the social category of gender provided a powerful platform to contest women's
association with corporeality and nature and women's exclusion from the social and
historical.
In retrospect, however, it is clear that the sex-gender distinction suffers from certain
problematic *metaphysical assumptions. Specifically, the sex-gender distinction relics on
a philosophical dualism between mind and body, society and nature, and history and
nature. It associates gender with the mind, consciousness, history, and society; and sex
with the body and nature. What these linkages crucially ignore is the historicity of the
body, the historicity of the categories of sex, and the significance of materiality in the
making of
244 ll5A ADKINS
Following Michel *Foucault (1976, 1984a), Judith *Butler argues that sex is not a simple fact or static
condition. Sex is a regulatory ideal that produces the bodies it governs. Sex Is a discursive construct,
a construct of discourses about the body. It is a regulatory force that has productive power: 'the
power to produce-demarcate, circulate, differentiate-the bodies It controls' (Butler 1993: 1). Thus,
rather than being a given or passive surface upon which gender is imposed, sex is an ideal whose
materialization is compelled through highly regulated practices. Butler invites us to ask the following
questions:
Does sex have a history? Does each sex have a different history or histories? Is there a history of how the
duality of sex was established, a genealogy that might expose the binary oppositions as a variable
construction? Are the ostensibly natural facts of sex discursively produced by various scientific discourses
in the service of other political and social mterests? ... (P]erhaps this construct called 'sex' Is as culturally
constructed as gender ... with the consequence that the distinction between sex and gender turns out to
be no distinction at all. Gender ought not to be conceived merely as the cultural inscription of
meaning on a pre-given
sex gender must also designate the very apparatus of production whereby the sexes themselves are
established. (Butler 1998 279)
Butler concludes that gender is not to culture as sex is to nature. Rather, gender is the cultural means by which
a 'natural sex' is established as pre-discursive, as 'nature'. In challenging the sex-gender distinction, Butler
highlights how the use of this distinction has a purely 'correctionist' character. That is, it leaves the conven
tional philosophical dualisms of society-nature and mind-body untouched.
Repudiating any correctionist strategy, Butler does not simply seek to insert women into the social.
She asks how tis that in Western thought sex is established as pre-discursive or pre-social. In so doing, she does not simply add wo
'gender' (compare Laqueur 1990; Martin 1994). One of the most influential critical voices
in this regard has been the US theoristJudith Butler, whose work is discussed here in Box
29. This significance of the historicity of sex and the body and the materiality of gender
has been underscored by several recent feminist writers. These authors examine
historically changing relations between nature and culture, and in many cases they argue
for a thor oughgoing dismantling of differences between the two. In one notable instance
of this, Celia Lury (2002) examines the process by which a human social type becomes a
consumer 'brand' with definite gendered as well as racialized characteristics. For example,
the iconog raphy of Benetton, the global fashion company, illustrates this process well.
Lury notes how the culturalization of human categories of genre, kind, or type is central to
Benetton's brand image and marketing strategy. Hence in Benetton, the iconography of'
"race" is pre sented not as a matter of skin colour, of physical characteristics, as the
expression of bio logicalor natural essence, but rather of styir'' (Lury 2002: 591).
Differences previously coded as nature are here rewritten as culture, or as Lury puts it 'not
... gender, race and class, but
lifeforms™ and lifestyles TM' (Lury 2002: 599).
What is important about such constructions of boundaries and theirvarious processes of
breakdown is, as Donna *Haraway puts it, that they unsettle the dualisms that 'have been
systematic to the logics and practices of domination of women, people of color, nature,
FEMiNIST SOCIAL THEORY 245
workers, animals' (Haraway 1991b: 177). In her own 'Cyborg Manifesto', Haraway
(1991b) draws attention to a range of boundary and dichotomy breakdowns, including
those between human and animal, nature and culture, organism and machine. These
breakdowns mean that we 'find ourselves to be *cyborgs, hybrids, mosaics, chimeras'
(Haraway 1991b: 177; see also Haraway 1997). ln documenting such boundary breakdowns,
writers such as Haraway and Lury note how new forms of power relations can emerge in
such contexts, showing how the categories of gender, race, and class come to be rewritten
in some surprising ways.
social worlds, or modernization as social differentiation' (Seidman 1997: 96; see also
Fuss 1991; Sedgwick 1990; Weston 1998).
Some contributors have examined certain exclusionary effects of the concept of gender
itself. Several writers have pointed to ways in which the concept of gender sometimes
embodies unexplored dimensions of class and racial privilege. They have argued that
in some cases the concept enacts certain modern ideals of liberalism that have only
been imaginable and desirable for particular women from particular class and racial
backgrounds, most notably from white middle-class backgrounds.
One object of criticism has been the view that the social categories of men and women
are constituted in capitalist societies by indirect patriarchal control of women's labour
power in the paid labour market, expressed in the horizontal and vertical gender segrega
tion of paid work-the phenomenon of 'men's job's and 'women's jobs'. This view, which
rontains elements of both Weberian and Marxist theory, found popularity in the 1980s,
particularly through the work of Heidi Hartmann (1979, 1981). It was the view that the
segregation of women in paid wage labour encourages women's material dependency on
men and hence relative powerlessness and exploitation in the domestic sphere. The main
criticism that can be made of this account is that it fails to address the situation of women
who are arguably not positioned in these ways, either in regard to the labour market or the
domestic sphere. This criticism has particularly been articulated by African-American
feminist writers.
African-American feminists have underlined how the household cannot always be
imagined simply as a site of patriarchal oppression for women. They have shown how the
household has also served historically as a site of resistance and solidarity-a 'homeplace'
to use bell *hooks's phrase (hooks 1990)-against pervasive institutional racism, including
the racism of the labour market. From this point of view, foregrounding women's segrega
tion in paid wage labour only captures the situation of a select number of women, those
who are relatively free to sell their wage labour as a form of alienable property . Such an
assumption overlooks the complex historical positioning of a range of women in relation
to labour as a form of property. Patricia Hill-Collins (1990) shows how the assumption
ignores the historical po itioning of African-American women in the political economy,
including the historical ghettoization ot black women in domestic work who live with and
care for white families. Similarly, Carby (1982) criticizes received concepts of the family,
patriarchy, and reproduction in feminist theory, suggesting that the common assumption
that domestic labour contributes to social reproduction fails to understand the complexity
of the positioning of black women. Carby asks: 'what does the concept of reproduction
mean in a situation where black women have done domestic labour outside of their own
homes in the servicing of white families? In this example they lie outside of the industrial
wage-labour relation but in a situation where they are providing for the reproduction
of black labour in their own domestic sphere, simultaneously ensuring the reproduction
of white labour power in the "white" household' (Carby 1982: 392).
FEMINIST SOCIAL THEOR\' 247
Examples abound of how some uses of the concept of gender can be exclusionary. The
early emphasis in feminist sociology on the social condition of the housewife has been
taken to task for its concern only with the problems of white middle-class Western
women-the women who came closest to living a domestic ideal of femininity. Thus hooks
(1984) criticized Betty *hiedan's (1963) The Feminine Mystique for focusing on the 'plight
of a select group of college-educated, middle and upper class, married white women
housewives bored with leisure, with the home, with children, with buying products, who
wanted more out of life ... careers' (hooks 1984: 1). hooks maintains that a focus on the
condition of the housewife ignores huge numbers of women working in jobs that neither
liberate them from dependency on men nor make them economically self-sufficient.
Similarly, while much basic endorsement has been given to claims that women should
have liberal political rights over their bodies, for instance reproductive rights, including
the 'right to choose' abortions, some critics have emphasized that such claims can some
times rest on a rather problematic notion of ownership of the body-on a liberal notion that
the body is a 'property' of the self. The histories of race and class show that many women
have' been prevented from acceding to such an ideal of 'self-ownership' (compare
Haraway 1991a; Pateman 1988).
In her study Imperial Leather: Race, Gender and Sexuality in the Colonial Contest, Anne McClintock
(1995) examines the emergence of an ideal of white domestic femin1n1ty 1n nineteenth-century European consumer cultu
a white colonial female audience. Mcclintock shows how soap and other domestic products such as
tea and biscuits were often presented in commodity imageries as embodying a colonial mission.
Advertisements routinely located such products 1n colonial landscapes. The usually black people
represented in such images were presented not as subjects but as a frame for the exhibition and
display of commodities. As Lury puts it, the black woman's or man's 'function was to act as cipher,
enabling a white perspective on imperialism to be conveyed' (Lury 1996: 160) McClintock shows
how these advertisements did not display the uses to which the commodities were to be put-
notably for domestic cleaning and laundry. Nor did they thematize the people who would use them,
namely women, both black and white. The advertising imagery related instead to emerging ideals of
bourgeois femininity which figured the proper white middle-class woman as one who did not work-
and espe cially not for profit-and defined housework as a labour of love. In this sense, the
commercial imagery of the nineteenth century can be understood as contributing to a consolidation
of raced, classed, and gendered divisions. Specifically, this imagery wrote the new cult of
domesticity through the script of a colonial imaginary which positioned colonized peoples as
objects for an emerging European consumer culture. The middle-class ideal of white domestic
femininity was figured through a new form of racism, which McClintock terms 'commodity racism'
(see also Ahmed 2000}.
of embodiment *Phallogocentrism was the egg ovulated by the master subject, the brood
ing hen to the permanent chickens of history. But into the nest with that literal-minded
egg has been placed the germ of a phoenix that will speak in all the tongues of a world
turned up side down' (Haraway 1991a: 148).
Conclusion
This chapter has documented three key moments in the development of frminist social
theory. The first involved examining a certain exclusion of women from modernity in the
classical tradition, via an association of modernity with masculinity. The second encom
passed diverse projects of historicizing and socializing women with the aid of the concept
of gender. The third element has involved various attempts to move beyond purely
'correc tionist' thinking in feminist research by foregrounding the idea of the 'gendering of
modernity'. The idea of modern culture and society as a gendered construct has led to
a need to interrogate the guiding philosophical assumptions underlying distinctions
between 'sex' as physical on the one hand and 'gender' as social or cultural on the other
hand. It has given rise to a problematizing of dualisms of mind and body, culture and
nature; and it has led us to see how the concept of gender can itself perform certain
exclusionary effects when it is not adequately theorized, especially in regard to issues of
'race', class, and sexual orientation.
250 LISA ADKINS
We have considered the view that certain forms of Western feminist theorizing enact
discursive structures of hegemony as a consequence of insufficiently reflective reliance on
Western Enlightenment knowledge systems. For some writers, these problems give cause for
mistrust in Enlightenment values and lend support to the view that feminist theorists
should abandon any attempt at general explanatory theories and should instead concen
trate on the particular over the universal, on difference over sameness, and on the
localover the general. However, it is also important to consider the arguments of many
feminist theo rists who, rather than simply reversing the values of the Enlightenment,seek
to rethink the conventions of Western political discourse in a rigorously self-criticil 1
manner. Such essays in reconstruclion demonstrate a need for ongoing elaboration of the
social categories of gender and lay the ground for the future of feminist social theory.
6 Can the history of feminist social theory be described as involving a shift from
Enlightenment to post-Enlightenment values?
■ FURTHER READING
A good general introduction to feminist social theory is Sara Delamont's Feminist Sociology (Sage,
2003). A classic statement in feminist methodology and epistemology is Dorothy Smith's Tile
Everyday World as Problematic: A Feminist Sociology (Open University Press, 1987). Some other guides
and studies are Rita f'elski's The Gender of Modl'rnity (Harvard University Press, 1995), Mary Evans',
Gender and Sucial Theory (Open University Press, 2003), Lois fcNay\ ( ;ender ,md AgfllC)' (Polity
Press, 2000), Barbara Marshall'sE11gcndering Modrrnity (Polity Press, 1994), and Barbara Marshall and
Anne Witz's edited En;1erzdcring t/1e Social: frminist t:ncowrtcrs with So< iologica/ Theory (Open
University Press, 2004). For some analyses of gendered subplots in classical and contemporary social
theory, see Lisa Adkins's Revisions: Gender and Sexuality in Late Modernity (Open University Press,
2002), Michele Barrett and Anne Phillips's edited Destabilizing Theory: Contemporary Feminist
Debates (Polity Press, 1992), Carol Pateman's The Sexual Contract (Polity Press, 1988), and Carol
Pateman and Elisabeth Grosz's edited Feminist Challe11ses: Social and Political Theory (Northeastern
University Press, 1987).
Two useful studies in feminist theorizatiom of patriarchy are Sylvia Walby\ Theorizing Patriarch)'
(Blackwell, 1990) and Anne Witz's Professions and Patriarc/Jy (Routledge, 1992). Among notable
contributions to feminist positions in postmodernism are Sara Ahmed's Differences that Matter:
Feminist Theory and Postmodernism (Cambridge University Press, 1998), Rita Felski's Doing Time:
Feminist Theory and Postmodern Culture (New York University Press, 2000), Donna Haraway's
EMINIST SOClr\l 251
WEBSITES
Since the closing decades of the twentieth century social theorists have been preoccupied
with the possibility that processes of change taking place in key aspects of social, cultural, and
economic life arc symptomatic of a wider transformation in modernity itself. A number of the
orists have sought to underline the historic significance of such transformations by
referring to the emergence of a new relationship to modern forms of life. For some
analysts the trans formations are considered to signify the appearance of relatively novel
social, cultural, and economic forms and the possibility that 'new times' might be emerging.
In some instances the argument has been presented that a qualitatively new social
configuration has been taking
MODERNITY AND POSTMODtRNITY· PAHT I 253
shape. This is the broad context in which conceptions of the postmoclern of*postmodernism
and postmodemity-have proliferated in debates about the character of our times.
This chapter introduces some central debates about *postmodernism and
postmoder nity and the ideas of the theorists most often associated with these terms. We
begin by re viewing several precursors to ideas about a postmodern turn in twentieth-
century culture and society and their relationship to French *post-structuralist thought
from the 1960s. Then we look at the contributions of four well-known theorists of
postmodernity. These are Jean-Franc;:ois *Lyotard,Jean *Baudrillard, Fredric *Jameson,
and Zygmunt *Bauman.
Chapter 13, which follows immediately after this one, introduces a second set of contri
butions to the same terrain of debate from a slightly different set of theoretical traditions.
Both this chapter and the following chapter should be read in conjunction.
Various attempts have been made to clarify the relationship between post-structuralism
and postmodern ism. Commentator have remarked on some affinities between 'postmod
ern currents' and 'post-structuralist theories of desire'. A notion of postmodernism has
been employed to describe a range of approaches that include post-structuralist contribu
tions to literary theory, history, and philosophy, as well as developments in *pragmatist
philosophy and post-positivist philosophy of science, and a textual orientation in cultural
anthropology (compare Lash 1990; Callinicos 1990; Bernstein 1991). However, such
exten sions of the term postmodern ism have been acknowledged to be problematic. It
should be emphasized that post-structuralism and postmodernism are not identical.
According to Andreas Huyssen (1984: 37-8), post-structuralism is to be viewed as
'primarily a discourse of and about modernism'-not postmodernism. Huyssen comments
that the works of the French post-structuralist theorists are more appropriately
described as providing us 'primarily with an archaeology of modernity, a theory of
modernism at the stage of its exhaustion' (Huyssen 1984: 39).
With the notable exception of Jean-Frarn;ois Lyotard, relatively few extended and
explicit uses of the terms 'postmodernism' and 'postmodernity'can be found in the works
of the French figures usually identified with these notions. For example, when invited to
cla rify the relationship between his work and contemporary social thought, Michel
Foucault (1983) indicated that he did not understand what was meant by the term
'postmodern'. In his essay 'What is Enlightenment?', in which he responded to
Immanuel *Kant's famous essay of the same title from 1784, Foucault was
deliberately dismissive of the term. He stressed that 'rather than seeking to distinguish
the "modern era" from the "pre-modern" or "postmodern", I think it would be more
useful to try to find out how the attitude of modernity, ever since its formation, has
found itself struggling with attitudes of counter modernity' (Foucault 1984c: 39).
Similarly, whileJacques Derrida's work is concerned to develop an ethical-political critique
of assumptions intrinsic to modern Western philosophy, it too is not adequately
represented by notion of postmodernism. To assoc.iate Foucault's and Derrida's writings
with postmod ernism in any sweeping way would be to subject them to considerable
misinterpretation (compare Smart 1992, 1993, 1996). In contrast, both Lyotard and Jean
Baudrillard doarticulate a notion of the postmodern, and their contributions will be
discussed shortly. But before we turn to their works, it is necessary to consider some
earlier precursors to ideas about a post modern turn in Western culture-bdore the period in
which these ideas rose to the centre of intellectual fashions in the 1980s.
Precursors to postmodernism
Jt has been argued that various ideas of the postmodern can be traced to currents of
thought in European culture from the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries. In
particular, an idea of the postmodern has been associated with the critical stance towards
Western metaphysics expressed by the German philosophers Friedrich *Nietzsche and
Martin *Heidegger. Both these figures que tioned certain foundational elements of modern
Western thought-notably the assumption that history moves by progressive
enlightenment on a universal stage, or the idea of 'universal history'. Nietzsche and
Z!iS
Heidegger are celebrated for their interrogations of ideas of ultimate guarantees and
unimpeachable grounds for 'reason', 'knowledge', and 'truth'. A certain affinity exists
between their challenges to Western philosophy and the more recent thinking of figures
such as Foucault, Derrida, Baudrillard, and Lyotard (see also Vattimo 1985).
Other early traces have been identified in the works of Max Weber and Georg Simmel.
Both these thinkers have been seen as suggesting examples of a postmodern way of think
ing insofar as they look sceptically at the achievements of modernity as a rational project.
Weber spoke critically of modernity's relentless prioritization of means to ends over ends
themselves, and of processes of inexorable 'value fragmentation' and spiritual 'disenchant
ment'. It has been suggested that Weber's work challenges us to consider 'which kinds of
charisma and *rationalization will shape the "postmodern" world?' (Roth 1987: 89).
Similarly, Simmel hasbeen described as 'the first sociologist of postmodernity'insofar as
he offers analyses of the crisis of modern culture and the exhaustion of modern cultural
forms (Stauth and Turner 1988: 17). The work of the German critical theorist
Theodor*Adorno is also argued to have anticipated 'many postmodern motifs' in his
preoccupation with their rational dynamics of rationalization and the paradoxical
consequences of Enlightenment
*universalism (Best and Kellner 1991: 225).
Since the middle decades of the twentieth century, various references to a postmodern
thematic can be found in disciplines such as literary criticism and architecture, as well as
in sociology, history, and philosophy. A conception of postmodernism was used to
describe developments in the poetry of Spanish and Latin American writers around the
first decade of the century (Calinescu 1977). Writing in the 1940-1950s, the British
speculative histor ian of civilizations Arnold *Toynbee drew a contrast between a
'modern' era of Western his tory, extending from the end of the fifteenth century to the
beginning of the twentieth century, and a subsequent 'post-modern age'. The latter was
seen as commencing with the First World War, which Toynbee described as 'the first
post-modern general war' (1954: 422). Toynbee identified an unparalleled predicament
facing Western civilization arising from lack of correspondence between powerful and
rapid developments in technology and slower, more uneven changes in humanity's
spiritual, moral, and political capacities. Technological innovation was seen as rapidly
outstripping society's ability to adapt to change.
A comparable notion of the postmodern is evident in the work of the American socio
logist C. Wright *Mills. Reflecting at the end of the 1950s on the changing characteristics
of the era, Wright Mills commented that people's basic understandings of social and
cultural life were being 'overtaken by new realities' (1959: 184). Liberalism and socialism
had 'vir tually collapsed as adequate explanations of the world'. The result was that with
increasing rationalization of modern society, 'the ideas of reason and freedom have
become moot' (1959: 184, 185-6). Insofar as events called into question values and
assumptions rooted in the Enlightenment, especially the idea of an intrinsic relationship
between reason and freedom, Wright Mills speculated on 'the ending of what is called the
Modern Age' and the emergence of 'a post-modern period' (1959: 184).
These reflections suggest a degree of continuity between earlier currents of thought and
the wave of interventions from the 1980s more familiarly assembled under the banner of
postmodernism. It is to these more recent commentaries that we turn now.
256 '3A R\' SMART
of social conditions. Humanity appears divided into those facing the problem of
responding to the challenge of increasing complexity and the others who continue to face
the 'terrible ancient task of survival' (Lyotard 1979). Lyotard here draws attention to the
way familiar cultural objects, social roles, and traditions have been destabilized or
'derealized' through the continuing development of the capitalist economy. There is also
confusion about 'taste'. The aesthetic hierarchy implied by distinctions between 'elite' and
'mass' appears to collapse into an orgy of eclecticism in which 'anything goes', creating a
'degree zero of con temporary general culture' (1982: 76).
We look in detail at Lyotard's work in a moment. But first it is necessary to clear up a
few common misunderstandings in uses of the terms 'postmodern' and
'postmodernist'.
statement that 'there is nothing outside the text' or with Michel Foucault's conception of
radical epistemic shifts in 'regimes of truths' through history (discussed in Chapter 9 of
this book). Derrida's and Foucault's writings break decisively with naively empiricist
and positivist assumptions about scientific progress and with complacent ideas about
the advance of reason in human history. But in no sense do these thinkers turn their backs
on the value and moral necessity of rational self-questioning and the idea of
'enlightenment'. In this regard, one example of a rather unfair position on
postmodernism and post structuralism is that taken by the German theoristJilrgen
*Habermas. For Habermas, post modernism represents little more than a conservative
reaction to shortcomings associated with the project of modernity. It constitutes a form of
anti-modernism promoting an aban donment of the 'unfinished task' of Enlightenment
(Habermas 1980, 1985). (For further discussion of Habermas's position, see Chapter 13 of
this book). These views of Habermas do not do justice to the range and diversity of
commentaries on the postmodern. Against Haber mas, it can be argued that a concept of
postmodernity can be upheld in fruitful ways, so long as it is understood as referring to
aspects of critical reflection on the modern and to a critical reworking of our ideas of the
modern. It is in this sense that Lyotard describes the postmodern as 'undoubtedly a part of
the modern ... Postmodernism thus understood is not modernism at its end but in the
nascent state, and this state is constant' (1982: 79). Similarly, a conception of
postmodernity can be legitimately deployed to designate a par ticular relationship to the
moral ambivalence, uncertainty, and lack of secure foundation that is now an intrinsic
feature of modern social life. It is in this sense that Bauman speaks of
postmodernity as 'modernity without illusions' (1993: 32). Bauman refers to
the modern mind taking a long, attentive and sober look at itself, at its condition and its past
works, not fully liking what it sees and sensing the urge to change. Postmodernity is modernity
coming of age, looking at itself at a distance ... making a full inventory of its gains and losses
... coming to terms with its own impossibility; a self-monitoring modernity. (1991: 272)
In these instances, references to the postmodern do not signify that the modern is being
left behind. Rather, they signify that our relation to modern forms of life has been trans
formed, that we now stand in a different relationship to things modern. Postmodernity
does not represent the passing of modernity, for modernity has not come to an end. Any
notion of a radical rupture between modernity and postmodernity should be rejected.
Therefore it is important to emphasize that postmodern analyses do not so much represent
alternatives to modern forms of life as attempts to establish critically how our experience
of the modern project has changed. It is to this more sociologically sensitive meaning of
the term 'postmodern' that attention is directed in this chapter. We move now to the work
ofJean-Frarn;ois *Lyotard.
knowledge in 'highly developed societies' (1979: p. xxiii). Yet Lyotard's use of the term in
this text is somewhat tentative. There is an implication that the term was adopted
because it was already common currency among writers in North America. Lyotard
states that 'the status of knowledge is altered as societies enter what is known as the
postindustria I age and cultures enter what is known as the postmodern age' (1979: 3). The
focus of the book falls on the ways in which culture in general and knowledge in
particular have been transformed since the end of the nineteenth century, concentrating
changes in the way scientific knowl edge is legitimized. Whereas scientific knowledge
formerly achieved legitimacy through appeal to particular *'meta-narratives' or 'meta-
discourses'-such as the progressive eman cipation of reason, or the liberation of
labour, or the enrichment of humanity
*legitimation today seems to be bound up with *performativity. By 'performativity'
Lyotard means control over contexts of information, notably control over reality under the
aegis of science and technology.
Lyotard traces the discrediting of legitimatory 'grand narratives' to a series of develop
ments that gathered momentum after the Second World War. These have included the
continuous dominance of techniques and technologies of social organization that have
deflected public discussion about the ends of action toward an increased preoccupation
with means and instruments. Concern about the intrinsic value of knowledge has dimin
ished as interest in the use of knowledge for optimizing efficiency of performance has
increased. Lyotard comments that 'the seeds of "delegitimation" ... were inherent in the
grand narratives of the nineteenth century' (1979: 38). Lyotard enumerates two main fac
tors for this current 'scepticism toward meta-narratives'. The first concerns crises in the
foundations of scientific knowledge. The second concerns processes of co-option of
knowledge into forms of capitalist *technocracy. We look at these in turn.
individuals are persuaded to '"want" what the system needs in order to perform well'
(1979: 62-4). Refusal to cooperate comes at a substantial cost, including withdrawal of
funding. The postmodern condition of knowledge is thus one of tension between 'the
imaginative development of knowledge' and attempts to subjugate knowledge to criteria of
utility and system performance (1979: 64).
In these respects it is clear for Lyotard that modern values of scientific enlightenment
and democratic struggle remain valid, and that in this sense 'modernity has not come to an
end' (1993: 25). fully in line with his early involvement in 1960s French Marxist circles,
the overriding problem of contemporary social life for Lyotard remains that of capitalism.
Lyotard highlights 'the redeployment of advanced liberal capitalism after its retreat under
the protection of*Keynesianism during the period 1930-60, a renewal that has eliminated
the communist alternative and valorized the individual enjoyment of goods and services'
(Lyotard 1979: 38). In this context he speaks particularly of capitalism's subjugation of
'the infinite desire for knowledge that animates the sciences' to 'the endless optimalization
of the cost/benefit (input/output) ratio' (1993: 25). Capitalism penetrates into language,
turning words into units of information, in tandem with the rise of a hegemonic system of
information technology and an emergent 'computerization of society' (1993a: 27).
Similar reflections on the imbrication of capital ism, information, and technocracy
occur in the work of the British sociologist Scott Lash, who is discussed in Box 32.
Processes of transformation associated with the advent of an 'information age' have been explored by
several sociologists. One wide-ranging approach can be found in Scott Lash's analysis of the impact of
global communication flows on social and cultural life (Lash 2002). Lash notes how modern social
institutions have increasingly been subject to processes of displacement under the rule of a new order
of information. In the transition from a 'national manufacturing society to a global informational
cul ture', there is a shift from 'exploitation' to 'exclusion' as the predominant form through which
power operates (2002: 26, 28). At issue is the way in which social structures become eroded and
displaced by a process of 'postmodern1zation' through flows of 'information, communications,
images, money, ideas and technology' (2002: 28). Lash comments that 'postmodernization involves
the displacement of normatively regulated, more or less unwieldy societal institutions and
organizations(... ) by smaller, value-inscribed, intensively bonded, more flexible cultural forms of life'
(2002: 28). A new order of flex ible enterprise wears away at embedded institutions in the areas of
education, health, legal aid, culture, and the arts. Implied rn this analysis is a shift from manufacturing
capitalism to a neo-liberal capitalism in which service sectors and informational sectors achieve
dominance.
Similar analyses have been developed by Manuel *Castells in relation to the 'network society'
(dis cussed 1n Chapter 14 of this book, pp. 296-7), as well as by Claus Offe in relation to the theme
of 'dis organised capitalism' (Offe 1985), and more broadly by Peter Wagner in relation to a
transition from 'organised modernity' to 'disorganised modernity'. See also Lash (1999), Lash and
Urry (1987, 1994), Urry (2000, 2003), Poster (1990), and Stehr (1994, 2001).
MODERNITY AND PGSH/•ODfRNITY· i>ART 1 263
We turn now to the second French theorist most often associated with postmodernism,
Jean *Baudrillard. Like Lyotard, Baudrillard began his early work under the influence of
Marxism and the French 1968 movement. But in the 1970s Baudrillard came to discard
many of the classical tenets of Marxism in favour of a new type of cultural analysis
indebted to *semiotics and French structural anthropology.
Baudrillard is often viewed as the key analyst of postmodern consumer culture (com
pare Kroker et al. 1989; Kellner 1989; Best and Kellner 1991; Gane 1991, 1993). In his
books The System of Objects (1968) and The Consumer Society (1970), Baudrillard sought
to extend a Marxist critique of capitalism to aspects of social and cultural life 'beyond the
scope of the theory of the mode of production' (Poster 1988: 3). In subsequent works,
commencing with The Mirror of Production (1973), Baudrillard criticizes Marxism for mir
roring the primacy of the economy, claiming that it did not break radically enough with
the theoretical perspectives of capitalist industrial societies. Advocating a more cultural
turn in critical enquiry, Baudrillard argues that categories and concepts drawn from
political economy are no longer meaningful for understanding 'the passage from the
form-commodity to the form-sign' (1973: 121). The important issue in his view is 'the
symbolic destruction of all social relations not so much by the ownership of the means
of production but by the control of the code. Here there is a revolution of the capitalist
sys tem equal in importance to the industrial revolution' (1973: 122). In the consumer
soci ety, individuals not only like to slot into roles and to slot objects into categories, to
enjoy a 'system of objects'-of house furnishings, appliances, gadgets, fashion
accessories, and the like. Consumers also like to consume signs, signs of fashion and
distinction, such as the designer label. The important object of consumption is not the
material sub stance but the image, sign, or symbol, which achieves distinction only by
relations of semiotic difference to other signs-to other brands, other fashion labels,
and so on within a mediated system. ln these connections Baudrillard notes how
consumption, signification, knowledge, and the whole field of culture have been subject
to social ab straction. The work ethic has been dislocated as consumption has become the
'strategic element' and people have been 'mobilized as consumers' (Baudrillard 1973:
140-4). At the same time, while consumption becomes the strategic element in
capitalist survival, it is also 'placed under the constraint of an absolute finality which is
that of production' (1973: 128).
Baudrillard can be seen as critically extending Marx's analysis of the articulation of pro
duction and consumption (compare Smart 2003). But whereas Marx sought to dissect the
distinctive features of a developing industrial society in the nineteenth century,
Baudrillard seeks to make sense of late twentieth- and twenty-first century consumer capi
talism. He comments that whereas it was formerly necessary to socialize 'the masses as
labour power', what is now increasingly required is to 'socialize them as consumption
power' (1970: 82). While industrial production still remains important, Baudrillard
emphasizes how-just as Marx had in fact anticipated-the application of science and
264 BARRY SMART
technology to production entails that wealth creation becomes less and less dependent on
manual labour time or on pure quantities of labour. Whereas industrial capitalist
society was fundamentally a society of production, contemporary capitalist society
especially engages its members in their capacity as consumers.
Baudrillard is also preoccupied with problems arising from the way in which
Western thought since the Enlightenment has presented itself as 'a culture in the
universal' (1973: 88-9). Concepts developed to make sense of modern forms of life-in
the case of Marxism, concepts predicated on the metaphysics of the market economy-
have been transported to other societies in often misleading ways. In Baudrillard's
work, the cul tural turn away from political economy leads to a focus on sign
structures, on multiple symbolic orders and diverse informational networks of
communication (Baudrillard 1987a). It is in this context that a number of references to
the postmodern emerge in his writing. He writes of a 'ciestruction of meaning' and a
'state of excess', leading people to live with 'fatal indifference' to past movements of
liberation (Baudrillard 1989, 1992a). Here there are some similarities between
Baudrillard's comments an banality and 'banal strategies' and Lyotard's statement that
'progress carries on, but the Idea of Progress has vanished ... Such is the banal destiny
of all great ideals in what could be called post modernity' (Lyotard 1986: 236).
Elsewhere, however, Baudrillard comments that it is not clear whether postmodern ism
or the postmodern have any meaning when used purely as labels (see Crane 1993: 22).
and 'mass' or commercial culture, expansion of the *culture industries, and an associated
proliferation of popular cultural forms. There is a 'new depthlessness' exemplified by a
'new culture of the image or the simulacrum', as well as a 'weakening of historicity' and a
simul taneous emergence of new emotional intensities. These motifs are bound up with 'a
whole new technology, which is itself a figure for a whole new economic world system'
(1991: 6). Postmodcrnism arises from 'the bewildering new world space of late or
multinational cap italism' (Jameson 1991: 6). Cultural forms no longer shock, surprise, or
threaten. Where modernism came to be canonized and institutionalized, today
'aesthetkproduction ... has become integrated into commodity production generally'. In
this sense, postmodern cultural forms have become 'one with the official or public
culture of Western society' (Jameson 1991:4).
On the one hand, Jameson discerns a culture of aesthetic modernism dominant largely
in the earlier decades of the twentieth century, which resisted the constitution of cultural
forms as commodities ior consumption and was largely hostile to the rhetoric and reality
of the market. On the other hand, he finds a new postmodern affirmation of the market as
a vehicle for the popular reception of cultural goods. Whereas modernist forms of artistic
ex perimentation and avant-gardism frequently engaged in a critique of commodification,
postmodernism is 'the consumption of sheer commodification as a process' (Jameson
1991: p. x). Jameson traces a connection between the relative displacement of modernism
by postmodern ism and the development of capitalist modes of production from an earlier
munopoly form to what Jameson describes as a 'new multinational and high-tech muta
tion' (1991: 157). Culture and the arts have lost the autonomy and critical distance they
might once have had, or at least strove to achieve.
Jameson here sees a retreat of utopian politics, a disappearing public consciousness
of alternative forms of social life, leading to an endangering of the possibility of critique.
The corollary of processes of commodification is that everything has, in a certain
sense, be come 'cultural' (Jameson 1991: 48). Essential differences between the
'purely cultural' value of an artistic, scientific, or intellectual object and the 'purely
economic' value of a physical object or substance appear to break down. As the
boundaries between art and money become blurred, everything seems to take on the
form of 'culture'. The profit mo tive, long associated with the development of a culture
industry producing entertainment commodities for a mass market, becomes more
prominent in the arts and in public goods. Com modification and the market system give
rise to a new commercial order entering into the heart of the cultural realm.
The Polish-British writer Zygmunt *Bauman has been another prominent contributor to
idea, about postmodernity. In his books Legislators and Interpreters (1987) and Modernity and
tile I lolocau t ( 1989)-discussed in Chapter 1 of this book, Box 3-Bauman describes a
crisis in We tem modernity's understanding of itself as a civilization oriented to universal
values.
MODERNITY AND PO<;TMOO , ,. PART i 267
ambitions' have not been realized. Today there is little widespread belief in the possibility
of an absolutely firm moral code. Bauman therefore explores what he describes as
*'postmodern ethics', taking his inspiration partly from the thought of the French *phe
nomenological philosopher Emmanuel *Levinas. Here Bauman seeks to expose the
impossibility of a 'universal and unshakably founded ethical code' (1993: 10), promoting
the idea of individual moral responsibility as 'the most personal and inalienable of
human possessions' (1993: 250). Such a 're-personalizing morality' means giving recogni
tion to our unique unconditional responsibility towards the other. In this Levinasia vision,
every ethical situation is unique. There are no hard-and-fast rules on which we can rely
for answers to our moral dilemmas. The individual must decide for him- or herself on the
right course of action, in the face of the manifest needs and vulnerability of the Other-of
theother person or people, of the friend orthe anonymous stranger. Yet as Bauman Points
outs, a constant problem under postmodernity is that this ethical freedom of the individ
ual is in danger of collapsing into sheer consumer freedom. The absence of definite
prescriptions about how to act may simply degenerate into egoism.
In later work, Bauman followed the German sociologist Ulrich *Beck in developing his
own version of the thesis of 'second modernity' or 'reflexive modernity' (for full discus
sion of Beck's idea of *'reflexive modernity', see Chapter 13 of this book, pp. 286-7).
Bauman describes the passage from one form of capitalism to another later form as a shift
from a 'solid' to a 'liquid' modernity (Bauman 2000). This represents an acknow ledgement
of the continuing relevance of the analysis offered by Marx and Engels at an earlier stage
in capitalist modernization, presaged in their famous dictum in The Communist Manifesto
that 'all that is solid melts into air' (Marx and Engels 1848: 83). Marx and Engels
described how the competitive character of the capitalist mode of pro duction leads to
continual innovation, bringing about perpetual transformations of 'the whole relations of
society'. There is an 'uninterrupted disturbance of all social condi tions' as established
relations are 'swept away' (Marx and Engels 1848: 83). Prevailing forms of life become
fluid and convertible, through constant processes of moderniza tion. Although in a sense
modernity has always been fluid, the process of modernization did not come to an end
with the displacement of traditional forms by modern forms. Rather, modern institutions
and forms of life have themselves become subject to contin uing rounds of modernization.
One loose assortment of themes that brings together the ideas of Bauman, Jameson,
and other commentators on postmodern ism relates to the renewed rise in religious fun
damentalism as a reaction to feelings of insecurity, fragmentation, alienation, and disaf
fection from the global order. These themes are discussed here in Box 33.
Conclusion
What do the concepts of postmodernism and postmodernity reveal about our relationship to
modern forms of life?
2 Have modern values been discredited by postmodern ideas?
3 What does the term 'postmodern' contribute to debates about the conditions in which know
ledge is produced and consumed?
4 How far is postmodernity a condition in which consumption has become paramount?
5 To what extent are postmodern forms of social and cultural life a corollary of the neo-
liberal restructuring of capitalism?
6 Should contemporary religious groups take account of postmodernism?
MODERNITY AND FOSTM'WERNITY: PART 1 271
Some good overviews of debates about postmodernism and postmodernity are Barry Smart's three
books Postmodernity (Routledge, 1993), Modern Conditions, Postmodern Controversies (Routledge,
1992), and Facing Modernity (Sage, 1999), as well as David Lyon's Postmodernity (Open University
Press, 1994), Gerard Delanty's Modernity and Postmodernity (Sage, 2000),Jim McGuigan's Modernity
and Postmodern Culture (Open University Press, 1999), and Christopher Butler's Postmodernism: A
Very Short Introduction (Oxford University Press, 2002). Also useful is Victor Taylor and Charles
Winquist's edited Encyclopedia of Postmodern ism (Routledge, 2001) and the same authors' four
ed ited volumes of collected essays Postmodernism: Critical Concepts (Routledge, 1998). Some
useful collections of readings are Thomas Doherty's Postmodernism: A Reader (Harvester, 1993),
Joseph Natoli and Linda Hutcheon's A Postmodern Reader (State University of New York Press,
1993), and Lawrence Cahoone's From Modernism to Postmodernism (Blackwell, 1996). Some
valuable critical assessments are Richard Bernstein's The New Constellation (Polity, 1991), Steven
Seidman's Contested Knowledge: Social Theory in the Postmodern Era (Blackwell, 1998), Pauline
Rosenau's Post modernism and the Social Sciences (Princeton University Press, 1992), and Steven
Best and Douglas Kellner's two co-written books Postmodern Theory: Critical Interrogations
(Macmillan, 1991) and The Postmodern Turn (Guilford Press, 1997). See also the Further Reading
section to Chapter 13 of this book.
Informative studies of postmodernism in relation to cultural and religious pluralism are Akbar
Ahmed's Postmodernism and Islam (Routledge, 1992), Couze Venn's Occidentalism: Modernity and
Subjectivity (Sage, 2000), Bryan Turner's Orienta/ism, Postmodernism and Globalism (Routledge, 1994),
and Scott Lash's The Sociology of Postmodernism (Routledge, 1990). Two notable studies of postmod
ern art and literature are Andreas Huyssen's Afrer the Great Divide (Indiana University Press, 1986)
and Hans Bertens's The Idea of the Postmodern: A History (Routledge, 1995). Two illuminating contri
butions have been David Harvey's The Condition of Postmodemity (Blackwell, 1989) and Fredric
Jameson's Postmodern ism, Or the Cultural Logic of Late Capitalism (Verso, 1991), as well as the
shorter article version of this book published in New Lefr Review, 146, Quly-Aug. 1984), 52-92.
Further sources are Zygmunt Bauman's four books Legislators and Interpreters (Polity Press, 1987),
Intimations of Postmodemity (Routledge, 1992), Modernity and Ambivalence (Polity Press, 1991), and
Postmodernity and its Discontents (Polity Press, 1997), as well as Bauman's two books on questions of
ethics, Postmodern Ethics (Blackwell, 1993) and Life in Fragments (Blackwell, 1995). See also Peter
Beilharz's A Bauman Reader (Blackwell, 2001). Baudrillard's writings can be approached through Mark
Poster's edited Jean Baudri/lard: Selected Writings (Polity Press, 1988) or through Baudrillard's own
Simulacra and Simulation (University of Michigan Press, 1994). In Lyotard's The Postmodern
Condition, the reader should begin with the essay appended at the end, 'An Answer to the Question:
What is Postmodernism ?'
WEBSITES
theory to view postmodernism as part of modernity. The idea of the 'end of modernity' is
not to be taken literally. There is a consensus that the notion of a radical rupture between
modernity and postmodernity should be rejected. In general, postmodern ism can bC' best
understood today as a revolt against just one tendency within modernity, rather than as
a movement against modernity as a whole.
The theories discussed in this chapter build on some of the positive gains made by
postmodemism and at the same time go beyond postmodernism. We look primarily at
the work of six theorists: Cornelius *Castoridias, Agnes *Heller, Jurgen *Habermas, Nikias
*Luhmann, Alain *Touraine, and Ulrich *Beck, as well as the later writings of Anthony
*Giddens on *'reflexivity'. We begin with a brief summary of the main criticisms that can
be made of postmodern ism's more extreme formulations.
Three broad evaluative points can be made about postmodernism from the standpoint
of modernity as a normative project. The first is that modernity needs to be seen as an
ongoing process with many dimensions. It is advisable to think of modernity as being 'on
endless trial', as the Polish theorist Leszek Kolakowski (1990) puts it. This is a way of
think ing evident in many of the major names of contemporary social theory. It is even
evident in the work of]ean *Baudrillard who has addressed ideas about postmodernism
not in terms of the 'end of the illusion' of modernity but rather in terms of the 'illusion of
the end' of modernity (Baudrillard 1992h). In many ways it is helpful to see
postmodernism as a cri tique of certain tendencies within modern thought, but not as the
proclamation of an en tirely new kind of society. This is certainlytheway*Foucault and
*Lyotard understood their projects, and it is especially evident in Foucault's emphasis on
what he called 'the permanent reactivation of an attitude', on 'a permanent critique of our
historical era', oriented to finding out 'how the attitude of modernity, ever since its
formation, has found itself struggling with attitudes of "counter-modernity"' (Foucault
1984c: 39).
A second point is that certain tendencies in postmodernist writing in the 1980s-1990s
suf fered from an overemphasis on the idea of societies as texts capable of simple
*deconstruction. Over-relying on literary theory, some kinds or postmodemism have not
been fruitful for sociological thinking and have not dealt adequately with questions of
power and material social structures, as problems that need to be analytically distinguished
from questions about representations, signs, and symholic images. While much
postmodernist writing has opened social theory to new dimensions, it has not always
provided adequate accounts of the distinctive nature of structural social processes. But it
should also be noted that preoccupa tion with exclusively cultural and symbolic matters
has heen questioned even within some strands of avowedly postmodern thinking itself.
Increasingly we find postmodernist thinkers writing about new conceptions of the social
dimensions of affairs, as dimensions to be distinguished from the more narrowly cultural.
One contribution to this redirection is the idea of 'social postmodernism' proposed by
Nicholson and Seidman (1995).
A third criticism is that some postmodernist writers have not always offered plausible
grounds for normative political engagement. In some cases, the idea of a rational foundation
MODERNITY AND ?OSTMODERNITY: FART 11 275
for collective struggles has been uncritically dismissed as an illusion generated by the
European eighteenth-century *Enlightenment. In contrast, many recent feminist and
*postcolonial theorists have demonstrated that while postmodern ism offers a useful start
ing point for critique, not all of its diverse strands have been able to offer guidance for an
*emancipatory political project. This is an observation made in the discussion of feminist
theory in Chapter 11 of this book.
It is worth remembering that postmodernism as a term was primarily a theory of
cultural developments, and that while it was compatible with developments in French
*post structuralist thought, it was never intended to be a social or political theory as such.
Originally, postmodernism was a movement in architecture, literature, and the arts,
expressing revolt against the rigid formalism of aesthetic *modernism, which it sought to
revitalize through an emphasis on emancipating 'content' from the structured and
ahistorical 'form' of the modernist aesthetic (compare Burger 1974). In bringing art and
life closer together, postmodcrnism brought the aesthetic imagination to the brink of
radical politics, but it has not succeeded in demonstrating aesthetics to be a fully self-
sufficient arena for social critique (compare Delanty 2000: 131-55; Harrington 2004: 177-
206).
The renewed theorizations of modernity to which we turn in this chapter take
account of various limitations in the notions of modernization espoused by some
twentieth century social scientists. The theorists under consideration proffer new
readings of his tory in areas as diverse as historical sociology, *world systems theory,
cultural history, international relations, and postcolonial studies. They are critical of
conventional mod ernization theory from the 1950s in the work of Talcott *Parsons and
others, which tended to reduce modernity to a Western-centred view of the world,
neglecting the multidirec tional and conflict-ridden character of modernity. It is in this
respect that several recent commentators have come to speak of 'multiple modernities',
most notably the Israeli his torical sociologist Shmuel *Eisenstadt (whose earlier work is
discussed in Chapter 6 of this book) (see Eisenstadt 2002). These accounts respond
increasingly to the view that moder nity is not exclusively defined by the European
Enlightenment and that there are many routes into and through it (compare Therborn
1995). The implications of globalization in this context will be discussed in the next
chapter, but for the present it can be noted that debates about globalization and related
issues of multiculturalism and *cosmopolitanism provide an important context in which
to approach the ideas of the theorists discussed in this chapter.
We begin by looking at the work of Cornelius *Castoriadis and Agnes *Heller.
In his major work The Imaginary Institution of Society, published originally in French
in 1975, the Greek-born theorist Cornelius Castoriadis shifted debate about modernity
away from an exclusive concern with capitalism, as was typical of Marxist approaches,
and also away from concerns with an all-inclusive power, such as in the work of
Foucault (see also Castoriadis 1990, 1991). For Castoriadis, the defining feature of
modernity is the struggle between the radical project of *autonomy and the institutional
project of mastery. Modernity is defined by a struggle between these two forces, and
cannot be reduced to either of them. To the extent that there is something underlying
these contrary forces, it is the imagination. All societies possess an *imaginary
dimension, since they must an swer certain symbolic questions as to their basic
identity, their goals and limits. Modernity has come to rest on two kinds of imaginary
significations: the imaginary of rational technical control, on the one hand, and the
radical imaginary of autonomy, on the other hand. The purpose of Castoriadis's social
theory is to defend the latter against the former.
Castoriadis does not equate technical control and mastery with capitalism; he sees
them as also including the dis,iplinary regimes of power associated with the modern
bureaucratic state. He argues that the distinctive feature of the radical imagination is
human autonomy, which resists both economic and political power and institutional
systems of *domination. He stresses the dimension of self-confrontation and especially
cre ativity, which can never be fully institutionalized. Modernity contains within it the
vision of an autonomous society. It thereby indicates a condition of perpetual resistance to
insti tutional frameworks which attempt to domesticate the radical imagination and
strip it of its creative agency. The focus on creativity offers an alternative theorization of
modernity echoing the idea of *homo faber in Aristotle and Marx: the idea of society
as an artefact created by human beings.
With this argument, Castoriadis established a route out of the narrower and more
dogmatic forms of postmodernism on the one hand and Marxism on the other.
Where Marxism in his view had a tendency to reduce radicalism to class
*emancipation, postmodernism led to a retreat from autonomy and became obsessed
with denouncing modernity (Castoriadis 1990). He emphasizes that radicalism
involves openness to the future, but is not based on disavowal of the past-for the past
can be a source of creative inspiration. Capitalism, as Marx demonstrated, created the
conditions for some of the most creative struggles in human history. These struggles con
tine to define the modern condition and have spread into wider domains, in the arts and
culture, in the self, in inter personal relations, and politics. But capitalism and class
conflict are no longer the sole ter rain of struggles for autonomy. Some examples of this
expansion in radical politics are the counter-cultural movements of the 1960s and the rise
of 'new social movements' since the 1970s. In these movements we find an expression of
the radical imaginary on the terrains of gender and sexuality, 'race', ethnicity, and
environmental activism, as well as in the arena of class exploitation. In general
Castoriadis's work has led to a new thinking of modernity in terms of a 'field of tensions'
on diverse 'sites of resistance' (compare Amason 1989, 1991; Wagner 1994; Delanty
1999).
The Hungarian-born theorist Agnes *Heller reiterates some of Castoriadis's key
ideas. She especially endorses the idea of a central conflict at the heart of modernity
MODERNITY ANO POSTMODERllilTV· PART II 277
which creates possibilities for freedom but also undermines it. Heller's social theory can
be read as a response to the circumstances of central and Eastern Europe under
communism and is especially pervaded by a sense of the helplessness of *civil society in
the face of powerful institutions. Her early work sees the central conflict of modernity as
lying between institutions and 'everyday life' (Heller 1984). The concept of everyday
life entered modern social thought via the writing of *Heidegger and other *existentialist
philosophers. Heller developed the concept to refer to the primary nature of society
as *intersubjective, which she sees as the basis of the transformative capacity of society.
Modern ideas of universality, critique, and *reflexivity are anchored in the structures
of everyday intersubjective communication and gain their political force in resisting
power.
In A Theory of History (1982), Heller outlined a conception of modernity that stressed
three logics of development. First, there is the capitalist logic of' development, involving
private property, inequality, and domination. This is then confronted, secondly, with
democracy, based on ideas of equality, decentralization of power, and citizenship. These
are the two central logics of civil society and are in tension. However, alongside them
lies a third logic of development, that of state-directed industrialism. By this logic, the state
tries to provide a solution to the problems presented by the conflict between capitalism
and democracy. Socialism has been an expression of this logic in modernity, even though
capitalism in the West has had the upper hand. It is this variable and fluid condition that
constitutes what Heller sees as the basic 'dynamic of modernity' (see Heller 1990). It is
a dynamic of perpetual change and an attitude of questioning that leads to constant
negation of tradition.
In her book A Theory of Modernity (1999), Heller also stresses technology as a key logic
of modernity. Technology is seen as facilitating certain emancipatory possibilities and as
at the same time threatening them. Modernity in this picture is not a homogenized or
totalized whole, but 'a fragmented world of some open but not unlimited possibilities'
(Heller 1999: 65). There is no promise of total freedom, and autonomy in Castoriadis's
sense is not concentrated solely in democracy; it can also be found to a certain extent in
technology. But neither technology or industrialism, nor capitalism, nor democracy, offer
unambiguously progressive forces of development. Heller has continued to believe that
democracy is the key to the emancipatory promises of modernity, but increasingly she
recognizes that perhaps all that is possible is a balancing of the three or four logics of
deve lopment (Heller 1993; Heller and Feher 1988).
In sum, Castoriadis and Heller offer important contributions to social theory by charac
terizing modernity in terms of struggles between different agencies, rather than in terms of
a single logic of transformation. Castoriadis's work thematizes conflict between the
project of autonomy and the project of mastery. Heller's work emphasizes tension between
the logics of industrialism, technology, capitalism, and democracy. Emerging from these
theo ries is a relational view of modernity as a process of social transformation that
unfolds through conflict between contrary forces.
One illuminating connection in which these ideas can be joined together with the work
of Habermas, Touraine, Beck, and Giddens is the revolutions in Eastern Europe of 1989.
This case example is discussed in Box 34.
278
The democratic revolutions that occurred In Eastern Europe in 1989-90 offer an interesting application
of the social theories discussed in this chapter. The revolutions would appear to refute postmodernist
notions of the 'end of modernity'. What came to an end in 1989 was not modernity tout court but
just one kind of modernity, namely a modernity oriented to the project of state socialism. While it is
possible to see the revolutions as demonstrating the end of a certain 'grand narrative' in *Lyotard's
sense, it Is
also possible to seem them as re-establishing modern democratic principles of potitical
legitimacy. Where *Baudrillard (1992b) sees the revolutions as an expression of the
'deconstruction of history', another perspective suggests a reconstruction of modernity. The events
appealed to a new application of classical * Enlightenment ideas about liberty and * civil society
(compare Dahrendorf 1990). The ideals that inspired the revolutions were the modern ideas of
democracy, liberty, and justice, which had been preserved in the civil societ9 movements of the
communist period and which reasserted themselves in 1989 when a general structural crisis occurred
in the Soviet system.
*Castoriadis's approach suggests a view of the 1989 revolutions as an expression of the radical *imagi
nary and a continuation of the mode·rn struggle between democratic *autonomy and state-imposed
sys temic mastery. For *Heller and other East European writers such as Vaclav Havel, they are an instance
of the eventual triumph of organic social agency over systemic institutional control-a vindication of what
Havel called the moral 'power of the powerless· (Havel 1990). *Habermas described them as
'catching-up' revolutions. involving delayed attempts to institutionalize modern liberties (see
Habermas 1991). From Habermas's perspective, the revolutions were the result of social
movements emanating from the
*'lifeworld' and asserting themselves against the 'system'. In 1989, state power was challenged by civil
society and given legitimation by intellectuals. In the language of Alain *Toura1ne's social theory, the
revolutions can be seen 9s a renewal of the capacity of society to create itself, to establish itself
by autonomous popular agency.
One notorious view of these events in the early 1990s was put forward by the American
political commentator Francis Fukuyama, who declared that the revolutions represented the 'end
of history' (Fukuyama 1992). In his thesis, they spelled the end of ideological strife between East
and West and the worldwide triumph of liberal democracy and free-market capitalism. The
illusions and political prejudices of this view have been borne out by the subsequent course of events.
One outcome of the revolutions was a rise in nationalism, xenophobia, right-wing extremism, and anti-
Semitism. This situ ation is far from the end of ideological strife that Fukuyama claimed to predict.
The triple transition-to capitalism, to democracy, and in many cases to national autonomy-has not
been smooth. It has had diverse consequences, ranging from descent into ethnic war in the former
Yugoslavia to the peaceful break-up of the former Czechoslovakia, as well as to German unification
and the recent enlargement of the European Union (see further Otte 1996). At the same time, new
forms of inequality, poverty, and unemployment have arisen as a consequence of the introduction of
free-market capitalism in the for mer Eastern Bloc, while intense ideological battles continue to be
played out elsewhere in the world in the name of religious values and cultural identities, notably in
the Middle East but also in the West.
These developments indicate that the categories and institutions of modernity are still with us,
however much they have been reshaped and reworked. To speak in the language of Ulrich
*Beck, modernity has become more *reflexive. Modernity today is unable to escape the legacy of
history and has constantly had to come to terms with problems created by earlier phases of
modernity. The revolutions in Eastern Europe therefore cannot be reduced to conservative, or
*technocratic or extreme postmodernist arguments about the obsolescence of projects of real social
self-determination. They are pertinent examples of the incompleteness of the proJect of modernity.
MODERNITY AND POSTMODERNiTY· PART i' 279
involve explicit validity claims, the very activity of communication presupposes the
possibility that communication can be 'unconstrained'; that is, that it can arrive at unco
erced consensus, where social actions are initiated not by intimidation or manipulation but
by valid reasons. Habermas stresses the capacity of human communication to foster a
more reasonable society. lt is a theory governed by the belief that through *deliberative
argumen tation and reflection, people can resolve differences and reach agreement.
In his philosophical writings, Habermas proposes a radical consensus theory of truth,
based on the hypothesis of an 'ideal speech situation'. Habermas developed this theory
partly through dialogue with the work of the German linguistic theorist Karl-Otto *Apel,
who introduced the ideas of the American *pragmatist philosophers to German-speaking
audiences in the 1970s. On this theory, truth is not what happens to be agreed upon by a
given bunch of people. lt is what could and would have to be agreed upon by everyone,
were everyone to have a free and equal opportunity to participate in the conversation and
exchange rationally debatable grounds for their views-without exclusion, manipulation,
or coercion. In this way Habermas establishes a normative foundation for critical social
the ory, bringing it out of the impasse of the earlier Frankfurt School's more pessimistic
*ideo logy critique. The critique of ideology in his work now becomes the critique of
'systematically distorted communication'.The concept of *dialogical rationality replaces
Adorno's concep tion of 'negative *dialectics'. The critical enterprise is focused on those
points where power is resisted by the force of communicative reason. So long as people
are able to engage in social action that obeys openly available rules of communication,
there is the possibility that social action can resist unjust uses of power. Habermas is not
saying here that commu nication is always a rational reflective process; but he is saying
that it can be, and often is rational, especially in those critical moments when people
challenge power.
According to Habermas, the history of modernity can be rewritten as the progressive
extension of communicative forms of rationality. Habermas's social theory is an evolu
tionary one, albeit one divested of *teleological assumptions. Social evolution cannot be
explained by recourse to historical or natural laws of any kind. Instead, Habermas's theory
of modernity rests on a conception of societal learning processes (Habermas 1976).
Synthesizing elements of the work of Durkheim, G. H.*Mead, and Talcott *Parsons,
Habermas argues that learning occurs both at the collective level of whole societies and at
the level of individuals. Learning happens simply because not-learning is not possible. In
this approach, which is also influenced by the developmental psychology of Jean *Piaget
and Laurence *Kohlberg, learning is based on the acquisition of communicative com
petences. It involves *cognitive processes that cannot be reduced to rote imitation or
*behaviouristic responses to an external environment. Learning and language use are a
'generative' competence, in the sense in which Noam *Chomsky uses this term. Habermas
argues that the evolution of societies can be theorized in terms of generative trans
formations in cognitive competences and moral consciousness. Modernity emerges when
societies solve problems in post-traditional and post-conventional ways, investing
reflexive universalizing principles in the formulation of social norms, organizational rules,
political practice, and legal systems. The transition to modernity occurs with the institu
tionalization of deliberative processes in the constitution of positive laws, and in the
idea of the autonomy of art, in the primacy of human rights, and in the *secularization of
religion.
MODERNITY AND POSTMODERNITY: PART Ii 281
Like Castoriadis, Habermas, and other writers, the French .ociologist Alain *Touraine argues that a
*post-industrial society based on consumers, service workers, and information brings about new kinds
of social movements, beyond that of the traditional working class (Touraine 1969).
In the 1970s, in opposition to both orthodox Marxism and *structural functionalism, Touraine
(1973) developed a theory of social action around the concept of historical renewal through
social transformation. He wrote that 'society is not just reproduction and adaptation; it is also
creation, self-production' (Touraine 1973: 3). The concept of 'self-production' indicated here is
very different from Niklas *Luhmann's use of the same term (discussed later in this chapter). For
Touraine, self-production refers to the ability of social actors to transform society reflexively by
acting upon it. He wrote that 'Society is not merely a system of norms or a system of domination: it is a
system of social relations, of debates and conflicts, of political initiatives and claims, of ideologies
and alienation' (Touraine 1973: 30). Touraine related this idea to social movements, which are the
agents of historicity.
In hrs more recent book Critique·of Modernity (Touraine 1992), Touraine argues that contemporary
society reflects a field of tensions between two polar tendencies: the tendency of collective •agency,
based on *normative communication, which he calls the tendency of the *'SubJect', and the tendency
of systemic *rationalization, which he calls the tendency of 'Reason' (equivalent to 'instrumental rea
son' in Habermas's lexicon). The challenge of modernity is to unify these tendencies. But the problem
for modernity is that the chances of a principle of unity are slight. According to Touraine, four main
forces have dominated modernity: sexuality, commodity consumption, the business corporation, and
the nation. These correspond to the spheres of personality, culture, economics, and politics. The prob
lem today, however, is that these domains have become so fragmented that there is no longer a princi
ple of unity. For instance, the personal order has become divorced from the collective order, and
production and consumption have lost any ability to bring the two orders together.
Touraine sees some truth in describing the current situation as 'postmodern' insofar as this reminds
us that the twentieth century has been a century not of progress but of crisis and dissolution of any
over arching collective agency. Touraine's thesis is that the only unity that currently exists is that
provided by instrumental rationality. On the one hand, Toura1ne postulates the idea of the 'Subject', or
subjectivat1on the *communicative agency of individuals-as a counterforce to the rule of 'Reason' or
systemic ra tionality. On the other hand, he is in insistent that the Subject cannot by itself unify the
shattered fragments of modernity. He writes th-at 'Society can no longer be defined as a set of
institutions, or as an effect of a sovereign will. It is the creation of neither history nor the Prince. It is
a field of conflicts, negotiations and mediations between rationalization and subjectivation, and they
are the complementary and contradictory faces of modernity' (Touraine 1992: 358).
Touraine rejects both postmodernism and paternalistic *communitarianism as solutions to
these problems (Toura1ne 1994, 1997, 1999). He sees the only solution in forms of democracy
rooted In active otizenship. While his notion of the 'Subject' is somewhat vague, the strength of
his work is his argument that the creative impetus of social action represents a challenge to power
In this respect he demonstrates how economic globalization has not undermined the capacity for
oppositional political action. Even the most marginalized groups in society are capable not only of
resisting domination but also of articulating new conceptions of society with an orientation to equal
ity and solidarity.
MODERNITY AND PART ii 283
opportunities for individuals to maximize their intnests. Rather, it argues for principles of
collective democratic communication capable of determining the very formation of
the interests that come to be claimed as 'private' and thereby shaping these interests in
ways that can express social solidarity and trust. In this sense, discursive democracy
for Habermas can exist in any part of society, not only in the institutionalized spheres
of law and constitutional politics but also in the private sphere and interpersonal
relations.
Habermas also stresses the importance of discursive democracy to the challenges of
globalization, and more especially to European integration (Habermas 2001). Insofar as it
is the site in society where power is contested, it is no longer confined to the state or to
the bourgeois public sphere. The normative claims of democracy are now to be found
everywhere, and have extended beyond the traditional confines of the nation-state (see
Habermas 1996, 1998). It is also in this sense that Habermas speaks of a 'post-national
constellation' in European politics.
Criticisms of Habermas
Habermas's work is the 1970s and 1980s brought critical social theory out of the impasse
of the first generation. It established a new way of theorizing modernity, emancipation,
and social action and provided a normative foundation for critique. But Habermas's
confident shift away from Adorno and Horkheimer's bleak view of instrumental reason
has not been without problems. Many critics have taken issue with Habermas's
unsympathetic attitude to post-structuralism, with his staunchly *universalist mode of
argumentation, with his attempt to generate a grand evolutionary theory of society free
from *metaphysical assump tions, and with his insistence on rational linguistic
communication as a realistic agency of progressive social transformation.
Among some writers, sometimes described as representing a 'third generation' of critical
theory, there is a certain dissatisfaction with Habermas's over-rationalized conception
of the social as grounded in formal structures of language (compare Wellmer 1986).
Habermas's neglect of the dimension of values and cultural experience has led to an
em phasis on new questions in the writings of Axel *Honneth, a student of Habermas.
Central to these concerns is the question of *'recognition' (Honneth 1985, 1990,
1992). For Honneth, it is the 'struggle for recognition' rather than the struggle for
agreement that is the most fundamental fact about social action. With this argument,
Honneth shifted attention toward ethical issues around injured cultural identities,
gender equality, and respect for diversity of value spheres. Honneth's work on
multiculturalism and the 'politics of recognition' here shows affinities with the approaches
of North American theorists such as Nancy *Fraser, Seyla *Benhabib, and Charles
*Taylor.
communication is a condition entirely disconnected from language and social action. For
Luhmann, it is systems that communicate, not social actors. Luhmann replaces the idea of
society with systems of communication.
Luhmann was a contemporary of Habermas who began publishing in the 1960s, devel
oping much of his work through a dialogue with Talcott Parsons's *functionalism, and also
with *cybernetic theory. In his major work Social Systems (1984), Luhmann proposes that
modern society comprises a functionally differentiated system whose subsystems have
become autonomous of each other and of the social system as a whole (see also Luhmann
1970, 1992). This theory has its origins in Parsons's evolutionary functionalism but it
differs from Parsons in several major respects. Luhmann denies the possibility of an overall
systemic unity. He also rejects the idea of modernization as a unilinear evolutionary
process, and he does not view the social in terms of symbolically constructed realities or
'lifeworlds' based on modernizing social integration. Against Habermas, Luhmann argues
that system integration is a more useful concept than social integration, and against both
Habermas and Parsons, he denies the idea that normative values provide the glue that
holds society together. Luhmann shifts the emphasis from integration io *differentiation.
He proposes that every subsystem is self-reproducing, where subsystems are seen as
*'autopoietic', or 'self-creating'. Each subsystem tends to reproduce itself, and it does this
by distinguishing itself from its environment. Systems are ultimately flows of information.
Luhmann describes them as 'operationally closed' in the sense that they do not require
'meaning' in order to function. For this reason 'society' as such does not exist. All that
exists is communication between social systems.
The implications of this are significant for politics, which Luhmann sees as no
longer occupying a functionally central position in society. Luhmann in fact argues that
modern society is centreless, and that there is no one central subsystem, such as the
state or civil society. Not too surprisingly, this led to a dispute in the 1970s with
Habermas, who strongly opposed the suggestion that politics has no central role to play
(Habermas 1976; Habermas and Luhmann 1971). According to Luhmann,
contemporary societies are characterized by complexity as a result of functional
differentiation. The consequence is that political communication has become just one
mode of communication among others. Habermas saw this as a very *technocratic
view of society, a view he also rejected with the simple empirical argument that
politics has always been a prominent motor of historical change. In reply, Luhmann
argued that Hahermas's theory presupposed a simplistic conception of system
integration being confronted by social integration. He insisted that the point of
systems theory was to demonstrate that it is through differentiation, not integration,
that society functions. It is through the creation of differences or functional
distinctions that social changes occur.
The notion of 'distinction', involving systemic societal production of differences, is of
central importance in Luhmann's social theory. The basic codes by which information is
processed are binary ones, creating a distinction between 'inside' and 'outside'.
Luhmann's argument is that distinctions can be made only from within a given system.
There is no absolute independent point from which society can observe or represent itself
(such as God or the State or the Emperor). It is no longer possible to represent society as a
whole. All external positions from which observation might proceed have disappeared
MODERNITY AND POSTMODERNiTV: PART ii 285
today. Instead, Luhmann argues that all observation must take the form of 'self-
observa tions', or, as he also says, 'self-descriptions'. Subsystems must make self-
observations in order for them to distinguish themselves from their environment, i.e.
from other subsys tems. In this respect, the subject as codifier and narrator-in the
sense of old European philosophies of history, in *Hegel and Marx or *Comte-is
replaced by a subject as observer.
Luhmann's idea of an increase in second-order observations can be seen in many areas
of society. For instance, in politics since the nineteenth and twentieth centuries, public
opinion has increasingly functioned like a mirror for different groups in society, making
power contingent. In artistic production, second-order observations are replacing first
order observations insofar as art no longer represents something largely outside itself,
such as the 'natural world': modern art has become predominantly *self-referential. In
science, questions of methodology have become all important, for scientific truth is not a
matter of proclamations but of method. In law, recourse to second-order observations is
evident in the salience of questions of procedure (Luhmann 1990).
Luhmann argues that the future in modernist thought was a means of extending the
present beyond itself. Modernism saw the present as a work of self-projection. Today,
instead, the future is experienced increasingly in the form of risk (Luhmann 1991, 1992).
Risks concern possible but not determined events. Risks are improbabilities resulting
from a decision. It is through risk that we cognitively construct the future, which has no
re demptive solutions to offer us. At most, this suggests a conception of the future as a
strategy for the reduction of complexities and contingencies, but not as a utopian dream.
Luhmann's social theory is close to postmodernism in the central importance it gives to
'difference'. It is, however, important to note that for Luhmann modernity is already char
acterized by difference, by differentiation, and by what he calls 'loss of reference'.
Difference is not simply a condition of postmodernity. Luhmann's systematic and
chal lenging theory of modernity rivals that of Habermas and others. Read in the light of
inter ests in global complexity and indeterminacy, it represents an innovative way of
thinking about contemporary society is able to address issues of *non-linearity in self-
organizing systems. It work suggests a view of society that is no longer to be understood
in the tradi tional terms of nation-state territory or key institutions, or 'collective
values' or 'cultural representations'. Society is not something spatial that is integrated
by particular actors or powers or institutions. It is rather to be conceived of as a system of
differentiated processes of communication.
However, Luhmann's work suffers from various difficulties. Apart from the obscurity of
much of writing style, the main problem is his neglect of social acHon. I Iis theory of com
munication is based on a simplistic notion of his binary codes that leaves little room for
other kinds of communication and interaction that cannot be reduced to this *cybernetic
logic. Luhmann also overstates the capacity of social systems to reproduce themselves,
and pays insufficient attention to issues of crisis, *legitimation, conflicts and opposition.
Politics is very inadequately theorized as 'steering'. Lastly, while Luhmann does empha
size what Parsons called *'interpenetration', this idea still plays a limited role in his theory.
The result is a failure to take into account mixed organizational forms and mixed cultural
forms.
Reflexive modernization
We now turn to a final body of work which explores the ideas of Habermas, Luhmann,
and others in a more empirical vein. This work can be brought together under the theme of
'reflexivity' and 'reflexive modernity'. It is particularly represented by the work of Ulrich
*Beck and Anthony *Giddens.
The idea of *reflexivity is a topical issue in social theory. As mentioned in Chapter 10,
Pierre *Bourdieu defended what he called a *'reflexive sociology' (Bourdieu anti
Wacquant 1992). Reflexivity here means the application of something to itself. In this
case a reflexive sociology is one that applies to itself the critical attitude that it directs to
its research object. Reflexivity suggests self-confrontation. In the methodology of social
science it entails a questioning of the position of the researcher in relation to the research
process. In Luhmann's social theory, reflexivity is the logic of *'self-reference' by which
systems repro duce themselves under conditions of contingency. In the work of Alain
J'ouraine, discussed earlier in Box 35, reflexivity is suggested by the idea of historicity
and by the capacity of so ciety to act upon itself. The notion of reflexivity is also central to
Habermas's conception of a critical *dialogic rationality. In the following discussion, we
look at ideas of 'reflexive modernity' and 'late modernity in the work of Beck and
Giddens.
modernization itself' (13eck 1986: 21). The growing power of technology in modern
society leads to a situation of gigantic risks, and the need to control these risks becomes
more and more important. It is no longer a question of the pursuit of an ideal condition
but rather of the prevention of the worst. The state in this sense ceases to be any kind of
utopian agency oriented to planning and social engineering and instead take on the role of
a pragmatic crisis-managing expedient.
Beck notes that oneof the most distinctive features of risk is its abstract character. Risk
is not immediately observable. Radioactivity, greenhouse gases, microbiological entities,
and pollutants of vanous kinds are not visible in the way that natural hazards such as
hurric anes, floods, or earthquakes are. Most risks are depersonalized; they are detached
from particular social actors, and make the attribution of responsibility difficult.
Moreover, risks are very often global. They are not always nationally specific and cannot
easily be con trolled by national governments. Given these characteristics, managing risk
is not easy. The problem is that risk is primarily a matter of incalculable side effects,
which means that it becomes a condition of perpetual crisis.
Yet Beck also comments that the risk society tends to encourage new forms of politics.
Risk induces reflexivity because there are no certain answers to its problems. Central to
the politics of the risk society is the collapse of the self-legitimation of expertise. In the
risk society everyone is potentially an expert, since expertise can no longer hide
behind the mantle of scientific authority. It is no longer merely a question of the
availability of information but of the definition of risk. It is a question of how we judge
risk, and of where the burden of proof lies, of how to judge compensation, and of whom
to trust. The risk society in this sense is a 'discourse society' (Beck 1986: 128-9). By this
Beck means the pub lic contestation of scientific claims and the clash of lay and expert
voices. Under 'primary modernity', science was an instrument to scientize nature. Under
'second modernity' science has scientized society to the point that science has become the
primary ground on which conflict takes place. Public platforms such as pressure groups
and *NGOs contest the claims of experts, but they also rely upon and make use of science
in order to frame their contestation and do not simply turn their back on science. Reflexive
modernity is thus a condition in which science is now applied to science, by public actors
as well as by experts.
reflexivity and business discourse of 'flexibility' is a thin one. It has been suggested that
Giddens's idea of self-monitoring might better be regarded in terms of what Michel
Foucault described as disciplinary technologies of power over the self.
Conclusion
This chapter has considered the work of some major social theorists writing in the 1980s
and 1990s. All the approaches discussed offer interpretations of modernity from positions
generally hostile to postmodernism in its extreme forms. In addition, with the exception
of Luhmann, all the writers under discussion began their careers by taking part in debates
in
*Western Marxism, while subsequently coming to recognize inadequacies with Marxist
thinking.
Three themes can be highlighted in the theories discussed in this chapter. The first
concerns social movements and resistance to power. According to Heller, Castoriadis, and
Touraine, modernity has been based on the revolutionary dream that society can create
itself without a state. The dream has been shattered, but the impulse still lives on at both
ends of the political spectrum. In Castoriadis's terms, there is a strong emphasis on
modernity as the imagination of alternatives. A second theme is the idea of autonomy,
relating to the capacity of social action to shape society in the image of moral and
political ideals. This is represented in different ways in the social theories of Habermas,
Touraine, and Giddens, as well as Heller and Castoriadis. A third theme concerns
continuity in the project of modernity. The theorists arc agreed that modernity entails an
ongoing proces of renewal and does not simply come to an end. It is in this sense that
modernity involves a condition of constant social transformation. Habermas in particular
speaks of the 'unfin ished project of modernity'.
Drawing on the ideas of these theorists, we can characterize modernity as a condition
of self-confrontation, incompleteness, and renewal in which the past is reshaped by
a globalized present. Modernity expresses self-confidence in the transformative project
of the present as liberation from the past. Modernity involves the belief in the possibility
of a new beginning based on human autonomy. In sum, it refers to a promise that the
world can be continuously reshaped by human agency in diverse social contexts.
In what ways do the theorists discussed in this chapter depart from ideas associated with
postmodern ism?
2 In what ways do theorists discussed in this chapter depart from Marxism?
3 What does it mean for actors in society to be, or to strive to be, collectively autonomous?
4 Is Habermas's theory of communicative rationality sociologically naive?
5 Is Luhmann's systems theory sociologically technocratic?
290 GERARD OELIHHY
6 What does it mean for individuals to be 'reflexive'? What it does it mean for institutions to be
'reflexive'?
7 What features of contemporary life best describe the concept of the 'risk society'7
FURTHER READING
Some good general guides lo themes covered in this chapter are Gerard Delanty's two books
Modernity a11cl f'ost111odemity (Sage, 2000) and Social Tlicory in a Changing World (Polity Press,
1999), Peter Wagner's two books Sociology of Modernity (Routledge, 1994) and Theorising Modernity
(Sage, 2001), Nigel Dodd's Social Theo,)' and Modernity (Polity Press, 1999), and Bryan S. Turner's
edited Theories o(Modernity and Postmodernity (Sage, 1990). An informative text is Jeffrey
Alexander's essay 'Modern, Anti, Post, and Neo: How Intellectuals Have Coded, Narrated, and
Explained the "New World of Our Time"', in his book Fin de Siecle Social Theory (Verso, 1995).
See also Peter Wagner's A History and Theory of the Social Sciences (Sage, 2001). A good anthology
of key readings in the area is Anthony Elliott's edited Blackwell Reader in Contemporary Social Theory
(Blackwell, 1999). An inform ative collection of essays that distinguish an acceptably sociological
conception of postmodernism from more free-wheeling textualist versions is Steven Seidman and Linda
Nicholson's edited Social Postmodemism: Beyond Identity Politics (Cambridge University Press,
1995). One of the best critical assessments of postmodernism is Perry Anderson's The Origins of
Postmodernity (Verso, 1998). Some polemical critiques of postmodernism are Alex Callinicos's
Against Postmodernism (Polity Press, 1989), Christopher Norris's The Truth about Postmodernism
(Blackwell, 1993), Terry Eagleton's The
!llusions of Postmodemis,n (Blackwell, 1996),John O'Neill's Tlte Poverty of Postmodernism (Routledge,
1995), and Timothy Bewes's Cynicism and Postmodemity (Verso, 1997). See also the interesting study
by Robert Pippin, Modernism as a Philosophical problem (Blackwell, 1991).
Some useful introductions to Habermas', work since 1980 are Robert C. Holub's Jurgen Habennas:
Critic i11 the Public Sphere (Routledge, 1991), Martin Matustik's /iirgen Habmnas: A Political-P/Jilosophical
Profile (Rowman & Littlefield, 2001), William Outhwaite's Habmnas: A Critical Introduction (Polity
Press, 1994), and David Rasmussen's Reading Habermas (Blackwell, 1990). Also very informative,
although limited to Habermas's earlier work is Thomas McCarthy's The Critical Theory of Jurgen
Habennas (MIT Press, 1978). Some good studies of Habermas's relationship to the earlier Frankfurt
School are Seyla Benhabib's Critique, Norm and Utopia: A Study of the Foundations of Critical
Theory (Columbia University Press, 1986), Raymond Geuss's The Idea of a Critical Theory (Cambridge
University Press, 1981), and Deborah Cook's Adorno, Habermas and the Search for a Rational
Society (Routledge, 2004). Some good studies of Habermas's work on communication, democracy, law,
and discourse ethics are Stephen K. Whitfs 111e Recent Work of Jurgen Habermas (Cambridge
University Press, 1987), the same author's edited Cambridse Comp,111io,1 to Haber11111s (Cambridge
University Press, 1995), Erik Eriksen's Understanding Ilabermas: Communication Action and
Deliberative Democracy (Continuum, 2004), Rene Schomberg and Kenneth Baynes's edited Discourse
and Democracy:Essays on Habem,as' 'Between Facts and Norms' (State University of New York Press,
2002) and Peter Dews's edited Hl1/Jcrnw1: .4 Critic,1/ N,·,1dcr(Blackwl'll, 1999). A useful collection of
readings from Haber mas is William Outhwaite's edited The Habennas Reader (Polity Press, 1996). For
Habermas's relationship to Foucault, see Michael Kelly's edited C1itiq11emul Power: Ncwsting the Fouc
ll11lt/Haber111asVrliate (MIT Press, 1994) and David Hoy and Thoma, McCartlly's Critirnl
Thcory(Rlackwell, 1992). For normative debates about civil society in the thought of Habermas, Arendt,
Foucault, and Hegel, see Jean Cohen and Andrew i\rato's Civil Society and Political Theory (MIT Press,
1992).
The be t general introduction lo the work of Luhmann in English is William Rasch's Nik/as
Lulzmarm's Modemity: The Paradoxes of Differentiation (Stanford University Press, 2000). Luhmann
himself is rather difficult to read and has not been widely translated in English. His major work is
Social Systems (Stanford University Press, 1995). A more accessible place to begin is his Observations
on Modernity (Stanford University Press, 1998).
MODERNITY AND POSTMODi.'RNITY· PART Ii 291
Anthony Giddens's ideas about reflexivity are laid out in his accessibly written The Consequences
of Modernity (Polity Press, 1990) and Modernity and Self-Identity (Polity Press, 1991). One among
many critical responses to Giddens's writings on the 'Third Way' is Christopher Bryant and
DavidJary's edited The Contemporary Giddens: Social Theory in a Globa/ising Age (Palgrave, 2001).
■ WEBSITES
The term 'globalization' conjures up many images. We think of processes of free trade and
the movement of capital and labour around the globe, or of institutions such as the World
Bank and the International Monetary fund and a host of multinational companies, or of
new technologies such as the Internet, or of the actions of non-governmental organiza
tions (*NGOs) such as Greenpeace and Amnesty International. For some commentators,
the predominant image is one of progressive economic advance. Others will think of street
protest against global injustice. Both sinners and saints, it seems, inhabit the global
domain. The tormer are represented by exploitersof cheap third-world labour and abuse of
GLOBALIZATION 293
the natural environment, the latter by the courage of humanitarian bodies such as the
health professionals of Medecins Sans Frontieres and the like.
What if anything do all these images and conjectures have in common? They seem
to point to such a wide-ranging set of issues that it may be asked whether the word
'globalization' has any consistent meaning. The aims of this chapter are first to ask
what globalization means and to arrive at a working definition. We then move to ask
whether globalization is a multiple set of changes or a purely economic phenomenon, whether
globalization is new, and why globalization matters to social theory. The chapter looks
first at the economic elements of globalization, and their relationship to the idea of flows,
networks,*'disembedding', and the sovereignty of nation-states. Then we look at the more
legal, political, and cultural aspects of globalization. We conclude by setting out some
broader historical contexts for ways of thinking about globalization.
The relationship between globalization and social change raises important questions
about the nature and dynamics of modernity and about long-run trajectories of change
across millennia. Modernity has been seen as taking increasingly decontextualized forms,
as not only restructuring work, culture, space, and time but also creating new forms of
*'transnational' and 'trans-local' connection. for classical social theory in the nineteenth
century, some of the most important social changes were set by the interlocking impact
of the French and Industrial Revolutions. For social theory since the last decade of the
twenti eth century, it is the question of globalization that has dominated attention.
For some, however, globalization is simply a hyped-up way of talking about contemp
orary life. On this view, rather than the discovery of new matters of sociological
importance, all we really have here is a new word for older social trends and issues. Some
writers have taken the view that if globalization simply means cross-border movements of
goods, people, and ideas, it is not new: it has been going on for hundreds, possibly
thousands of years.
From an analytical point of view, there is certainly confusion as to the kind of concept
or theory that globalization amounts to. James Rosenau (1996: 249) poses the following
chal lenging questions. He asks: 'Does globalization refer to a condition, an end-state, or
to a process? Is it mostly a state of mind, or does it consist of objective circumstances?
What are the arrangements from which globalization is a departure?' In short, would we
perhaps be better off without a concept prone to the twin problems of rhetorical overload
and analytical incoherence?
The main difficulty with the term globalization is not that it is meaningless but rather
that it has become an umbrella term for many different social changes. And it is also a
term loaded with a lot of moral and political baggage. This is not something for us to shy
away from, but rather a puzzle we must try to unravel. The position taken in this chapter
is that to abandon the concept would be, on balance, more problematic than retaining it.
What is required is a critical review and refashioning of the terms. This is above all
because debates
294 ROBERT HOLTON
around globalization engage with some very real social changes and theoretical
challenges, some with long-run historical origins, others very recent.
As a first approximation, globalization may be thought of as a range of evolving
processes, relationships, and institutions that are not contained within the borders of nation
states and have significant that transnational elements. While globalization has become
part of the rhetoric of the contemporary liberal economic order, its meaning and useful
ness is far broader. There are many important empirical and theoretical issues that make
little sense without a term of this kind. The term 'international' is not atisfactory because
it retains a notion of social life as conducted between nation-states rather than beyond
them. The term 'transnational' attempts to capture this idea of processes and interactions
inside particular nation-states which affect the way of life of other nation-states and jump
across nation-state boundaries in many diverse, complicated, and largely unregulated,
disorderly ways.
Theorists now debate whether globalization is a new type of social change creating new
identities and new forms of social organization. To the extent that it is a new type of
social change, questions have arisen as to whether globalizing trends represent a
juggernaut of economic power, seemingly beyond human control, or a renewal of market-
and technol ogy-driven changes able to rescue the world from hunger and conflict. The
moral challenge is whether globalization functions only to the advantage of the rich and
powerful, or whether it represents an opportunity for new forms of *cosmopolitan virtue
that somehow transcend the confines and discords of nations and ethnic groups. Political
debates have centred on whether globalization can be managed in a stable manner, and
how far political institutions can he created to establish global demo.:racy.Such debates
are clearly i nterdis ciplinary in scope, implicating a wide range of disciplines.
Contributions to the study of globalization are evident across the span of disciplines from
political science, economics, and geography to law, anthropology, and cultural studies.
We begin by analysing more closely the meaning of the term 'transnational'.
broken apart. (For further discussion of Wallerstein's work, see Chapter 6 of this
book, pp. 149-50).
However, this is not to say that the nation-state focus has been abandoned in any
wholesale fashion. It lives on notably in the various 'realist' schools of international
relations research. *'Realist' writers in international relations studies take the nation-state
and the practice of *Realpolitik as the fundamental basis for world affairs. They point to
the robustness of the nation-state as an institution, claiming that much of what is seen as
'transnational' effectively remains international in scope. Any working definition of
globalization should therefore be carefully designed to encapsulate both the trends that
have been associated with challenges to nation-focused thinking and the counter
responses of realist political science. Why should we think of the world as something
more than a system of nation-states, inhabited by national governments and
nationally situated businesses? The answer will have to do with the significance of certain
key globalizing trends.
The key trends generally associated with globalization are at least one or more of the
following:
• intensified movement of resources, ideas, and peoples across boundaries, and patterns
of social organization and power within which such movements take place;
• greater interdependency between different parts of the globe, including regions, cities,
and localities as much as national societies;
• growing consciousness of the world as a single place, a 'global consciousness'.
Beyond this point, some fundamental choices have to be made in taking this
definition much further. Can we speak of a singular economic phenomenon, or should we
speak of a multidimensional set of processes that may include economic, political, and
cultural elements, all of them moving in different directions, rather than in any one
unitary pattern?
The economic interpretation of globalization is certainly widespread and draws
attention to some fundamental features of our contemporary world. These include the
global distribution of commodities, capital, and labour markets; the power of multina
tional corporations; new communication and information technologies; global consumer
consciousness; and ideologies of free trade and global deregulation. However, the
problem with predominantly economic definitions of globalization is that they can be
overextended. While goods, capital, and technology flow across boundaries, so do
political, cultural, and religious institutions, processes, and forms of thinking. It would not
seem that human rights, popular music, Islam, or Christianity are any less global in their
transnational origins, mobility, and impact than markets or money. Similar global flows
seem to extend across the arbitrary boundary separating the economy from the rest of
society. Accordingly, an increasing trend in recent work has been to define globalization
in broader ways, drawing attention to multiple features, rather than any singular
characteristic (compare Holm and Sorensen 1995; Held 1995; Holton 1998). In addition to
economic globalization, there are elements of a global *polity and a global culture, and
these latter elements do not all necessarily point in the same direction as economic
developments.
296 ROBERT HOLTON
In this sense globalization is a set of processes with 'autonomous logics', rather than a
single master process (Beck 2000b: 11).
Processes of globalization
What, then, are the main processes of globalization, and what are the links between them?
These questions direct us to relationships, institutions, and types of social actors. In the
fol lowing, we look at the role of five factors: markets; time-space compression; networks,
flows, and *'disembedding';*governance and regulation; and the nation-state.
Globalized markets
A first obvious candidate for factors driving globalization is markets. Markets would
appear to be easier to globalize than forms of government or cultural identity. Global
markets for capital, money, labour, goods, and services are fundamental features in all
major theories of globalization. They are characterized by high levels of mobility across
boundaries and are typically evident in significant levels of convergence in commodity
prices, share prices, interest rates, and forms of managerial best practice (compare Sklair
2001; O'Rourke and Williamson 1999). While nation-states find it difficult to regulate the
least mobile factor of production, namely labour, they find it almost impossible to track
the most mobile processes such as electronic transfers of money-let alone impose tax on
such transfers.
However, markets are not entirely unstructured or unregulated. Markets do not
reallocate all resources on a daily basis through the price mechanism (see Williamson
1975). They rely on continuities in management, in levels of accumulated knowledge, on a
predictable and reasonably dependable set of property rights, and on significant levels of
trust between market participants. This is especially true in cross-border activity
conducted within a range of culturally and politically diverse settings, against tight time-
lines and in highly competitive settings. for formal organizations such as multinational
companies, regulat ory bodies and legal systems help to structure markets alongside more
informal interper sonal networks. The human actors involved are not only corporate
executives and their workforces but also market-oriented professionals, public relations
and media personnel, and regulators.
organization of space becomes increasingly transnational. For Saskia Sassen (1994), the
transnational structuring of global capitalism takes place in global cities rather than in
nation-states. Cities such as New York, London, Frankfurt, and Tokyo represent key
centres of economic power and are the location of the core producer services on which
corporate activity depends. Spatial maps of global power have less and less to do with
national bound aries and more to do with relations between global cities.
economies are seen as elevating economic values above all others, leading to high levels
of global inequality and injustice.
anarcho-capitalism. One of the main problems with this is that it ignores the robustness of
nation-state administrations, and specifically their involvement in new regulatory
functions. It is true that some regulatory functions of the nation-state have receded in
prominence, particularly state enterprise and interventionist macro-economic planning.
But many nation-states have taken on new regulatory functions in recent years; for
example, social regulation of personal relations affecting children, women, divorce, and
abortion (compare Mann 1993b: 118). In Europe, the supranational legislative agency of
the EU has adopted a significant number of the regulatory functions previously exercised
by national governments, and it has sought to promote liberalizing policies that enhance
the global competitiveness of European businesses. But in general, EU legislation has
complemented and added to the regulatiory capacities of member states more than it has
taken away from them. In addition, contrary to widespread perception, national welfare
state expenditure is positively correlated with economic openness (Rodrik 1996; Evans
1997; Therborn 1999). That is to say, states with liberal economic policies open to foreign
investment are not, on the whole, states with reduced welfare expenditure for the national
population. However, what does seem clear is that economic globalization requires states
and cultural formations that are conducive to the protection of private property rights. It
requires nation-states to provide physical infrastructure and human capital for market use,
and, at the very least, it encourages a global consumer consciousness (Carnoy 1993; Sklair
2001). Global economic competition can lead state governments to step up their powers of
protection over domestic industry, but it can also encourage them frequently to relax
legislation and legislative powers perceived to limit the competitiveness of national
businesses in the global market place.
The idea of a global consumer consciousness has been theorized by George *Ritzer
under the catchword 'McDonaldization'. Ritzer's thesis is discussed in Box 36.
For some theorists of globalization, the linkage between economy and culture produces what has been
referred to as the 'Coca-Colonization' or 'McDonaldization' of the world. According to George *Ritzer
(1993), the *rationalization of production and service delivery methods harnessed to standardized
global marketing creates globalized consumers. Global corporations, media conglomerates, and
advertising agents organize mass markets around standardized and predictable production formats and
consumption routines. These involve globally recognizable products subsumed within global brands,
and controlled through local franchise agreements that tightly prescribe how products are delivered.
According to this theory, economic globalization creates global cultural convergence around
standardized and privatized consumerism. The public domains of democratic politics and political
participation are seen to decline accordingly (compare Barber 1996).
Whether such arguments are completely convincing has been hotly debated. One problem is the
assumption that consumers are cultural dopes, rather than knowledgeable agents capable of making
choices. One question to be asked is whether producers can simply create the consumers they require,
or whether the many failures in consumer marketing suggest that a conception of relatively less
standardized marketing strategies aimed at consumer niches would represent a more plausible
sociological account. Further aspects of the debate about whether economic globalization causes
cultural 'homogenization' are explored later in this chapter, in Box 37.
300 ROBERT HOLTON
norms. In this connection, many critics of global corporations cite instances of corporate
indifference or violation of human rights and environmental standards. It is hard to
attribute the dynamic behind these developments purely to economic globalization,
either from the positive liberal viewpoint or from the negative Marxist viewpoint.
In the political sphere, decision-making involves both governments and 'governance'.
National governments in Western countries typically retain greater control over some
matters such as taxation or immigration policy than over other matters. In a governmental
sense, aspects of national sovereignty have clearly been pooled upwards, toward regional
or global institutions. In Europe, this is evident at the level of the EU. It is also evident in
matters of trade rules and agreements, as set by the World Trade Organization. On the
other hand, it is less evident in the case of the UN: here even where some sovereignty is
pooled or diluted via global harmonization of rules and standards, nation-state retain
formal juridi cal sovereignty. In this case, transnational arrangements still require the
consent of nation states. It is for this reason that Held here speaks of international rather
than transnational political decision-making. But still, on the whole, having signed upto
bodies that operate in some sense beyond national mechanisms, nation-states have
increasingly become sub ject to processes and procedures administered by transnational
bureaucracies and articul ated by transnational bodies of expertise. By signing up to
transnational systems of rules, they become susceptible to transnational moral pressures
to honour and comply with what has previously been agreed. This is not to deny that such
pressures may be ignored, espec ially by more powerful states, notably by the USA. But
still, the *normative pressure to comply with supranational requirements remains an
effe(·tive factor in contemporary political decision-making.
However, these narratives still have their limitations. Broader global processes need to
be seen at work, and a broader theoretical framework needs to be defined. As Ulrich *Beck
puts it, 'the various autonomous logics of globalization-the logics of ecology, culture,
economics, politics and civil society-exist side by side and cannot be reduced or collapsed
into one another' (Beck 2000a: 11). Another way of making the same general point is to
advert to the globalization of processes such as the search for personal and social security
and the elaboration of a meaningful identity, together with movements for human rights,
greater political and social justice, and greater fairness in the distribution of resources.
In the latter connections, two useful examples can be given as illustrations. The
first concerns active debates in the public sphere about the advantages and
disadvantages of a market-driven global economy. Economic globalization, insofar as
it has exploited low cost labour or generated adverse environmental effects, is indeed
responsible for the processes that its critics.find unacceptable. But the moral criteria that
are applied by critics are not in any direct sense the product of economic globalization.
They draw instead on a range of traditional and modern precepts and attitudes towards
nature, community, democracy, and social justice. Ideas such as living in harmony with
nature or rights to pop ular self-government did not have to wait until the intensified
processes of contemporary economic globalization to emerge, even though the capacity to
organize coalitions of crit ics has depended in large measure on low-cost
communication, information, and trans portation technology.
The second example concerns links between globalization and issues of human security,
including both geopolitical and personal security. These questions have been rather
neglected by sociologists. Thomas *Hobbes's seventeenth-century conception of the
*'state of nature', which saw life as 'nasty, brutish and short', raised in acute form the ques
tion of how to achieve personal and collective security. The answer for Hobbes centred on
the creation of a strong sovereign power. For sociologists, this issue has typically been
pur sued through an analysis of the internal workings of the nation-state and through an
in terest in the economic causes of insecurity. The fragility of social life was only brought
into focus recently with the emergence of a 'sociology of risk' (discussed in Chapter 13 of
this book, pp. 286-9). Meanwhi.le, the study of international security tended to be left to
the dis cipline of international relations.
In this second example of insecurity, one may argue that public perception of global
threats to quality of life have more to tell us about the construction of the UN and its
agencies such as the World Health Organization than merely patterns of corporate
economic power. War may certainly be fought over economic issues, but the fear of war
cannot be reduced to an economic calculus. Personal insecurity in the face of global
environmental risk may come to centre on the actions of corporate or state polluters, but
the search for understanding and effective redress is a far broader matter that many people
see as involving the globalization of moral and political rights and responsibilities. The NGO
slogan 'Think globally, act locally' is symptomatic of the world-view of many critics of
economic g!obalization, implying a com plex relationship between global aspiration and
local competence.
To sum up the answer to our question 'Is legal and political globalization driven by
economic globalization?', we may say the following. Legal and political globalization is
both normatively independent of economic globalization and functionally related to it,
but not functionally reducible to it.
:; l O"f U Z,C
i O ''" 303
over coercive mechanisms such as the use of military power as a mechanism of global
secu rity, as well as the economic coercion entailed by conditionality requirements of the
IMF. These contests indicate that global agendas are not entirely dominated by the
powerful. The influence of the numerous protest events that followed in the wake of the
Seattle meet ing of the WTO in 1999, including the foundation of the World Social
Forum at Porto Alegre in Brazil in 2001, also give ample indication of this.
A second case example worth considering in this connection is the Internet. Here we
have a communications technology that emerged from two rather disparate sources. The
first was the US state, and more especially the US military, which funded research into a
multi-centred communication system able to withstand nuclear attack. The second source
comprised disparate groups of information technologists in California and elsewhere who
wished to explore the possibility of interpersonal communications networks accessible by
individuals-by individuals from below as well as by organizations from above. In the ini
tial stages, the driving forces were bigly variegated and owed comparatively little to
corpo rate economic influence. Although corporate influence rapidly grew to prominence
after 1980, symbolized by Microsoft, the legacy of an accessible tool of communication
has con tinued. Many influential software engineers continue to supply technical expertise
to the public domain, even while corporations seek to defend their intellectual property.
The Internet as an engine and medium of globalized communication has clearly
developed from multiple sources, and continues to reflect multiple user perspectives.
Global cultural life is also an arena in which multiple and often competing or
contradictory trends are in play. It can be argued that the picture is more complex and
paradoxical than simple theories of McDonaldization and cultural imperialism would
suggest (compare Holton 2000). At least three intersecting developments are evident . The
first includes processes of homogenization in which the rationalized standardization of
companies like McDonald's, Nike, and Starbucks does indeed prevail. Here it is certainly
the case that powerful economic interests seek to create and dominate global consumer
markets. But a second trend is resistance to global culture in its standardized consumerist
form. This has been associated with a strong tendency for individuals and groups to
identify with particu lar places and cultural repertoires and with the robustness of national
identities, but not only in a blatantly nationalist form. The third has been the development
of inter-cultural fusions or hybrids in which cultural elements from different sources are
combined, such as in 'world music' and in a host of *syncretic fashion styles.
The complexity of cultural trends requires considerable analytical attention. The
fore most reason for this is that the relationship between global culture and other
national or local cultural forms and institutions is by no means easy to define. While it is
conventional to think in terms of sharp distinctions between global, national, and local
levels of activity, it is not obvious that such 'levels' can be distinguished from one
another in any decisive way. The reality seems to be rather one of *interpenetration
across highly permeable boundaries.
GlOBALilATiON 305
One influential way of proceeding has been through the notion of *'glocalization',
developed by the British sociologist Roland *Robertson (1992, 1995). Robertson orginally
developed the idea of a fusion of the global and the local to understand the *syncretic
character of Japanese religion. A characteristic of Japanese religiosity, according to
Robertson, is the borrowing of elements from different religions, notably Buddhism,
whose influence came to Japan from the Asian mainland, and Shinto, the Japanese state
religion. Japanese people may appeal to both for different purposes, rather than viewing
themselves as either Buddhist or Shinto in affiliation. Robertson's discussion of global
local fusions involves an ambitious theory of social life in terms of mediation between the
universal and the particular. Social life is localized or particularized in time and space but
it is equally implicated in globalized or universalized discourses about the nature of the
cosmos and humanity, embracing fundamental questions of meaning. In this respect,
Robertson's key concepts are ontological, in the sense that they pertain to human social
being, to aspects of the human condition. 'Glocalization' is, so to speak, our human fate.
While possessing certain local roots, different peoples cannot understand their existence
without an engagement with the global, which necessarily leads people to relativize the
perspectives of their received cultural, religious, and historical traditions.
One revealing instance of ambiguities between the global, the national, and the local in
the arena of popular culture is the Eurovision Song Contest. This case is discussed in Box 37.
In the Eurovision Song Contest, contestants represent different countries, each of which organizes a
national contest to determine the European representative. On the night of the Contest, votes for each
song are organized through national systems of voting. One interesting observation is that voters in
particular countries often appear to support contestants from countries that border on their own, or
with which they have historic ties. Here we may ask whether the Contest gives an example of
national resistances to globalization. What would seem to speak against this is that elements of folk
music and national costume have been relatively limited in the show. The overall musical idiom is
the pop song, fusing Afro-American with European elements without any particular national point of
reference. The contestants themselves are also often recent immigrants, again providing a
multicultural rather than national element to the pie;ture.
Hannerz (1992), writing of Sweden's contribution to one of the Contests in the late 1980s, reports
the confusions that have arisen concerning the national integrity of the process. In Sweden's
national contest, organized to determine a 'Swedish' entrant for the wider EurovisIon Contest, 'it
was quite acceptable that the ... first runner-up had been performed by a lady from Finland, and
the second by an Afro-American lady ... Both [migrants] were thought of as representing the new
heterogeneity of Swedish society ... What was controversial was the winning tune, the refrain of
which was "Four Bugs [a brand of chewing gum] and a Coca-Cola" ... Of the two, Coca-Cola was
more controversial ... as a central symbol of "cultural imperialism" ... What drew far less attention
was that the winning tune was a calypso' (Hannerz 1992: 217) The favourite song of the Swedish
contest thus drew all at once on Finnish, American, Afro-American, and West Indian elements.
The challenge here lies in determining not simply whether this is more of a global phenomenon
or more of a national phenomenon. There is the third possibility that it represents an
interpenetration of the global and the national: some kind of *'glocal' fusion of the global and the
local. If so, we may ask: how widespread is this global or 'glocal' *syncretism1 And this question
raises several others. What is
this glocal syncretism driven by? If it is driven primarily by global1zed capitalist entertainment industries,
why does it take the complex cultural forms that It does? If the cultural imperialism argument has less
purchase, may we speak of certain kinds of emergent national, regional, or trans-local identity? This
raises the question of the extent of the independence of global audiences from processes of global
mass media production. Lastly we can also ask how significant such events really are for an under
standing of globalization. Are they trivial events, or are they salient in a more subtle way, perhaps as
banal forms of cultural syncretism, analogous to the taken-for-granted forms of national symbolism
discussed by Michael Billig (1995) in terms of 'banal nationalism'?
Another line of approach to these issues has developed around ideas of *'cosmopolitan
democracy'. These have been formulated by David Held and others in terms of normative
ideals of 'global civil society' or 'cosmopolitics' (Held 1995; Archibugi and Held 1995;
Kaldor 2003). Debates about cosmopolitan democracy invoke universal values of trans
parency, accountability, peace, and justice in world affairs, and try to show how these
values can be reconciled with, and enriched by, the particularistic cultural traditionsof dif
ferent national societies. Many would also see the development of transnational social
movements as emergent indicators of cosmopolitan democracy founded on dialogue
307
between the global, national, and local. The World Social Forum indicates processes of
convergence in global social understanding from very diverse standpoints, issues, and
agendas.
mean that populations will necessarily be reconciled to the world order as it currently
stands-not least in the present condition of profound economic inequalities and
injustices between the rich and the poor, the powerful and the weak.
So far in this chapter we have been concerned with globalization from the standpoint of
very recent socio-economic developments. We end our discussion now by standing back
from the contemporary situation in order to consider some more historical contexts for an
understanding of the term.
Movements of people, goods, and ideas across wide political and cultural borders have
been taking place for centuries, if not millennia. Movements of population in search
of food, land, and freedom or trade between tribes, city-states, and regions go back a long
way in human history. The question we must ask, however, is whether, or how far, such
histor ical movements constitute meaningful instances of the concept of globalization.
The crucial indicators would appear to have to do not only with cross-border
movement but also specifically with closer interdependence between spatially
separate social groups, together with a sense of the world as some kind of single
place. Globalization may not require that individuals feel themselves to be global or
develop global identities and attachments; but it almost certainly means that
individual and group activities must take account of global interdependencies,
whether economic, technological, political, or cultural. The need to take account of
global interdependencies may denote a quality of becoming globalized through
external constraint, by default. It suggests that individuals become enmeshed in
something above their heads or beyond their personal control. This is indeed how many
anti-globalist critics interpret the world. Lack of choice or democratic consultation about
patterns of globalization is certainly the source of much discontent. But there are two
alternative ways in which we can think about how individuals relate to globalizing
processes in a historical context.
The first involves individuals actively participating in cross-border processes and global
culture. They may be merchants or pilgrims, explorers or migrants, multinational
managers or world musicians, colonizers or environmental activists. Activity of this type
involves some kind of enlarged cross-border orientation, whether as a 'citizen of the
world' or as an imperialist, a Muslim or a Jew or a Christian, a free trader or a member of
a world wide diaspora. The second, less overtly global orientation involves all of those
people who make use of material and symbolic resources and repertoires that have an origin
beyond their country of origin, whether technology, foodstuffs, political institutions,
religious practices, or art and literature. Involvement in these social patterns may require
no e,pecially global consciousness; hut such ideas, institutions, and resources may,
nevertheless, have a long pre existing cross-bonier history, whether they are key concepts
in mathematics or forms of eco nomic organization or world religions (compare Curtin
1984).
Some of the most ambitious attempts to produce long-run historical accounts of interac
tions and interdependencies along these lines have been produced by Andre Gunder Frank
and his associates (Frank and Gills 1993). One of Frank's most radical claims is that a
world
GLOBALIZATiOfll 309
system has existed for around 5,000 years, rather than 500 years. This proposition rests on
evidence such as long-distance trade, market exchange, and forms of capital
accumulation. Frank's main aim is to demonstrate the existence of an expansive capitalist
core in world history. This position is significant for two reasons. First, it revises the
familiar thesis that global capitalism originated in the period from the fifteenth century
onward, symbolized hy Christopher Columbus's voyage to the Americas. Second, it
emphasizes the non-Western origins of globalization.
Another significant contribution to historical ways of thinking about globalization is
A.G. Hopkins's edited volume Globalization in World History (Hopkins 2002). This centres
on a fourfold typology of globalization, portrayed in Table 14.2. The typology is not
organized around variations in some single structural principle, such as Marx's 'mode of
production' or Weber's 'form of legitimate domination'. Rather, the typology is based on
changes in institutional patterns of social organization in time and space. The four types
of globalization sketched by Hopkins and his associates are not intended to be a
Procrustean bed on which complex bodies of historical evidence are stretched until they
fit neatly into
Archaic Pre-dates industrialization and nation-state Associated with empires, cities, and
trading diaspora
Present in Asia, Africa, and parts of Actors involved include
kings, warriors, priests, and
Europe traders
Multi-centred s0urces of
Proto Emerges between c. 1600 and 1800, indigenous change, including
with state reconfiguration and improved management of
commercial expansion sea-borne commerce
Actors include explorers, slave
Present in Europe, Asia, and parts of Africa traders, merchants, and
pilgrims
Conclusion
Globalization matters to social theory because it raises many of the core issues in social
enquiry about the nature and direction of social change, mobility and settlement, power
and inequality, conOict and order, solidarity and identity, and complexity in social organ
ization. But globalization also matters because it provides important examples of what
Robert *Merton (1949c) called *'middle-range' theorizing, as against more speculative
forms of *'grand theory'. The will to grand theory reflects several aspirations, from the
search for a unified theory of society to the more activist vocation of prophecy. In the
prophetic mode, analysts have seen globalization both as a harbinger of global riches and
equally as the enemy of social justice, democracy, and community. The emotional
appeal of such views has been eroded in considerable bodies of empirical research by less
grandiose and more complex explanatory approaches. Accounts of globalization are
littered with failed general theories and prophecies, from the assumption of the end of the
welfare state and the nation-state to the idea of cultural homogenization and universal
wealth distribution. In the study of globalization, methodological nationalism has been
challenged hy a new methodological globalism. In its most radical forms, methodological
globalism sees the fluidity of people, images, and resources across space as a new axial
principle (compare Urry 2000). At the same time, however, we should be clear that not
everything is in flux. The robustness of resistances, re idues, and attachments to the ideal
of a stable sense of security built around particular places and contexts constitutes
limits to globalization (compare Scott 1997). The same is true of the many 'glocal'
fusions in which would-be globafom seeks an anchorage in specific fC'gional contexts.
This applies whether we are speaking of the search for new markets around particular
niches, or the search for general
cultural meanings among populations that differ in tradition and identity.
It should be emphasized that the case for regarding globalization as in some sense long-run
does not mean that nothing is new. While flows and interdependencies stretch out over
time and space and must essentially be understood in historical dimensions, the velocity
and intensity of cross-border transactions has increased dramatically in recent years.
This
GLOBAUZATEOI\I 311
■ FURTHER READING
Some excellent general introductions to controversies about globalization are David Held and
Anthony McGrew's two books Globalization/Anti-Globalization (Polity Press, 2002) and Global
Transformations: Politics, Economics and Culture (Polity Press, 1999), as well as the same authors'
use ful collection of edited readings The Global Transformations Reader: An Introduction to the
Globalization Debate (Polity Press, 2000), especially the introductory chapter titled 'The Great
Globalization Debate'. Also good is Leslie Sklair's Globalization: Capitalism and its Alternatives
(Oxford University Press, 3rd edn. 2002). Other useful guides are Jan Aart Scholte's
Globalization: A Critical Introduction (Macmillan, 2000), Malcolm Water's Globalization
(Routledge, 1995), and Robert Holton's Globalization and the Nation State (Macmillan, 1998).
Some influential statements have been Ulrich Beck's What is Globalization? (Polity Press, 2000),
Zygmunt Bauman's Globalization: The Human Consequences (Polity Press, 1998), Martin Albrow's
The Global Age (Polity Press, 1997), Barrie Axford's The Global System (Macmillan, 1995), and
Anthony Giddens's Runaway World: How Globalization is Reshaping our Lives (Routledge, 2000).
Roland Robertson's Globalization: Social Theory and Global Culture (Sage, 1992) was one of the first
books to place globalization on the intellectual map. A major contribution is Manuel Castells's The
Information Age, in a three-volume series The Rise o(the Network Society (Blackwell, 1996), Tile Power
of Identity (Blackwell, 1998), and End of Millennium (Blackwell, 2000). Some path-breaking
empirical
312 ROBERT HOLTON
studies are John Braithwaite and Peter Drahos's Global Business Regulation (Cambridge
University Press, 2000) and Leslie Sklair's The Transnational Capitalist Class (Blackwell, 2001).
See also John Urry's two books Sociology beyond Societies (Routledge, 2000) and Global Complexity
(Polity Press, 2003). The most sceptical view of globalization in relation to the fate of nation-states is
Paul Hirst and Graham Thompson's Globalization in Question (Polity Press, 1996). Some
important studies of global cities, finance and capital flows are Saskia Sassen's three books Cities in a
World Economy (Sage, 2nd edn. 2000), The Global City: New York, London, Tokyo (Princeton
University Press, 2001), and Losing Control? The Decline o(Sovereignty in an Age of Globalisation
(Columbia University Press, 1996).
For cultural aspects of globalization, see Ar jun Appadurai's Modernity at Large: Cultural
Dimensions of Globalization (University of Minnesota Press, 1996). For some examples of thinking
about global ization by geographical theorists, see David Harvey's Spaces of Capital: Toward a Critical
Geography (Routledge, 2001), Edward Soja's Postmodern Geographies (Verso, 1989), Mike Davis's
Ecology of Fear: Los Angeles and the Ima1ination of Disaster (Vintage, 1999), and Nigel Thrift's Spatial
Formations (Sage, 1996).
In the activist mode, an important piece of investigative journalism is Naomi Klein's No Logo
(Flamingo, 2001). Left-leaning texts areJustin Rosenberg's The Follies o{Globalization Theory (Verso,
2001), Alex Callinicos's An Anti-Capitalist Manifesto (Polity Press, 2003), and Michael Hardt and
Antonio Negri's much-discussed Empire (Harvard University Press, 2000). Richard Sennett's The
Corrosion of Character (Norton, 1998) is a very readable study of the 'flexible' entrepreneurial indi
vidual. Another major treatise on this phenomenon in France is Luc Boltanski and Eve Chiapello's
Le Nouvel esprit du capitalisme (Galli ma rd, 2000). On the side of liberal defences of globalization,
two important books are Joseph Stiglitz's Globalization and its Discontents (Penguin, 2002) and
Jagdish Bhagwati's In Defense of Globalization (Oxford University Press, 2004). For conceptions of
'cosmo politan democracy', see David Held's Democracy and the Global Order (Stanford University
Press, 1995), Mary Kaldor's Global Civil Society (Polity Press, 2003), and James Bohman's article 'The
Globalization of the Public Sphere', in Philosophy and Social Criticism, 24/2-3 (1998).
■ WEBSITES
Our time at the start of the new millennium appears to be one of considerable uncertainty.
For many people, the most significant ending of the twentieth century was not the formal
passing of the year 1999 but the fall of the communist regimes of Eastern Europe and the
Soviet Union between 1989 and 1993.These events marked the end of the Cold War and
the end of the bifurcation of the world into the two opposing ideologies of capitalism and
communism. Bleak as it was, the bipolar system that dominated the second half of the
twentieth century created a degree of predictability in international relations, economic
forecasts, and general social expectations that has today mostly disappeared. Today the
world strikes us as a highly volatile place, marked by ever-widening gaps between the
world's richest and poorest nations, by increasing environmental destruction, and by a vast
imbalance of power between political entities of the West such as the USA and the
European Union and the world's diverse other regions, continents, societies, and cultures.
At present, the world offers little evidence of any framework of global civil society
capable of holding the world's most powerful economies and governments to account and
ensur ing a fairer distribution of resources. Certainly no current global legal system
secures all peoples an equal chance to determine their own livelihoods in an autonomous
and simul taneously peaceful way.
If the fall of the Berlin Wall in October 1989 marked the end of the twentieth century, the
symbolic beginning of the twenty-first century for many people was the crashing of four
hijacked aeroplanes by Jslamist terrorists into the World Trade Center in New York and
the Pentagon in Washington on 11 September 2001. This event brought home to many
people the vulnerability, the volatility, and the complacency of our current global life in
the most dramatic and traumatic way. It would appear that intolerant and intolerable acts
such as these are consequences of renewed rises in religious fundamentalism, nationalism,
ethnic hatred, racism, and xenophobia in our world today, as much in opposition to the
West as within the West. Without doubt, they are symptoms of a certain degradation of
global social solidarity, reflecting the absence of any system of shared social, economic,
and political life capable of fostering a mutual concern with the collective welfare of the
species. We should remember that the world that saw 3,000 people die on 11 September
2001 is the same world that sees 2.3 million Africans die each year from HIV, partly as a
result of the shortage of cheaply available drugs.
314 i:\USTIN HARRIN
Since 11 September 2001, world politics appears to have entered a new or 'second'
phase of globalization with an increasingly imperialistic and militaristic face. In a context
of a general shift of the axes of world conflict from the capitalist-communist divide of the
sec ond half of the twentieth century to the oil-rich territories of the Middle East and
the Islamic people who inhabit these lands, the system of Western-led neo-liberal
economic policies that drove the boom of the final years of the last century has become
conscious of a profound crisis in its resources of moral and political legitimacy. At a time
stamped in delibly by the US-led 'war of pre-emption' on Iraq of 2003 and the revelation
of subsequent torturing of Iraqi prisoners of war, and by the seemingly endless failure of
attempts to establish peace and justice for the people of Palestine under Israeli
occupation-to name only two among countless sites of conflagration-the world's dominant
economic system seems compelled to maintain itself by force in the name of a 'war on
terrorism'. If the clos ing years of the twentieth century ushered in what the French writers
Luc Boltanski and Eve Chiapello (2000) call a 'new spirit of capitalism' based on a
new type of flexible individual open to all opportunities for career advantage, the opening
years of the twenty first century appear to be ushering in a new international *state of
nature in which all efforts to develop genuinely impartial legal bodies with universal
transnational jurisdic tion are being systematically undermined by the concerns of the
world's most powerful states for 'national security'.
It is this coexistence of complex and unjust global conditions that makes rigorous social
analysis so important today. When so much of our political life seems to be clouded by
dis tractions from reality, by insuperable quantities of information, by manipulative
publicity campaigns, by 'spin' and 'hype', or by the cult of media celebrity, critical social
analysis has never been more important. At a time when political representation seems
to be increas ingly fashioned in the image of cinema and becomes less and less able to
distinguish between fact and fiction, social theory is a vital tool of response. Sometimes it
is tempting in this climate to throw up our hands in despair at the problems of the
world, or to withdraw into a life of purely private apolitical concerns, or to fixate on
single objects of blame at the expense of complexity and contradiction. This kind of
ieaction is dangerous for several reasons.
Firstly there are facts to be discovered and stated about the causes of our malaise,
through rigorous research. There are illusions, prejudices, and lies to be purged from the
spaces of our public and private lives. But we also have to accept that the answers to our
problems are not always unambiguous or clearly given. When the ancient Greek
philosopher *Plato compared ignorance to the perception of shadows on the walls of a
cave lit by a dim fire, he made an assumption of the ultimate separateness of truth and
enlightenment from the daily contexts of life in which people ordinarily experience the
world. Today this kind of assumption is not possible for us. Today our reality is
intrinsically a reality of shadowy appearances and shifting forms, of mediated images and
messy contradictions. Our reality is not Plato's pure bright light of day outside the cave.
This implies that in banishing false hood and prejudice from politics and society, we
cannot assume our answers to be always the true ones. However intractable or deluded the
world may appear to us, we have to try out our answers in the here and how. We have to
engage with the world as it is and try to transform it from within, through reasoned
deliberation and communication.
NCLUS!'.H' 315
The various schools of social theory discussed in this book offer a few conceptual tools
for dealing with such troublesome realities. They offer techniques of analysis with a
variety of empirical applications in practical contexts. It should b(' stressed that no
particular school has a monopoly on authority. Each should be treated critically, as one
among possible others. This does not mean that all schools and theories can be mixed
together in one great soup. Not all of the theories arc mutually compatible. Tensions and
contradictions remain between some of them. Nor is it the case that if we could mix them
all together, we could cream off the best parts and discard the rest. But many kinds of
productive synthesis and mutual criticism are certainly possible, and it is for this reason
that allthe schools discussed in this book deserve equal consideration. Social theory, as
with all scientific debate, is a pluralistic engagement marked by unity and disunity, at
once by continuity and by discontinuity.
In a most general sense, social theory is a way of thinking about social life that helps us
to address two perennial questions of human existence: Who are we? What should we do?
These questions take on a special importance for us in modern times. To think about who
we are and about what we should do is essentially to ask what it means for us to be
modem, and it is this distinctive question of modernity that lies at the centre of social
theory. The very exist ence of social theory as a scientific project is itself a creation of
modernity. For societies that we today call 'ancient' or 'traditional', social theory is not a
possible structure of thought, at least not in the sense in which we understand the word
'theory' today. Only modernity could have thought of applying a scientific conception to
the making and shaping of its own world. Although ancient societies present us with many
answers to the question of who we are and what we should do, these answers are no
longer our answers, and they are not the answers of social theory. Ancient people thought
about their world and about what they should do in it, but they did not believe their world
to be capable or needful of radical change, to change from its roots. They did not,
fundamentally, believe their world capable of rational transformation through collectively
organized human agency.
To think about who we are and what we should do is to think about our time, about our
place in time and our relationship to time. The thought of the significance of time and of
being-in-time has been a recurrent motif for many of the most influential philosophers of
modernity, from G. W. F. *Hegel to Friedrich *Nietzsche and Martin *I Ieidegger, as well as
for more directly social and political thinkers such as Karl *Lowith (1949), Alexandre
*Kojeve (1933-39), Hans *Blumenberg (1966), Eric *Voegelin (1952), Hannah *Arendt
(1958, 1971), and many others. As these thinkers make clear, ancient people certainly also
thought about their time; but ancient people believed their time to be for the most part
given to them, not made by them. Ancient people believed their time to be given to them
by some being or beings beyond time, by God or by gods or the spirits. In contrast, while
beliefs in God or gods or the spirits still remain very much with us as intellectual and
emotional forces, modern ity contains the idea that we human beings alone are responsible
for making our world and our time. We who live in this world are the agents of our own
destinies. We alone are the agents of history and politics, not gods or spirits. Certainly we
are reminded repeatedly that we are not immortal, and that human beings are only one
species of nature to inhabit this earth. No matter how far we may be capable of extending
our longevity through medicine and natural science, each and every one of us is destined
to die. Death is the insuperable
316 .AUSTIN HARRINGTON
horizon of all our existence. But the distinctive idea of modernity is that human beings are
less and less capable of thinking of death as the gateway to some unchanging realm or to
the start of some new life beyond time-called Heaven or Eternity. In the time of moder
nity, we come to realize more and more that nothing exists beyond death except time. We
realize that nothing exists otherthan being-in-time and non-being-in-time: endless
coming to-be and ceasing-to-be. To be true to our time is to be modern, and to be modern is
to face up to this predicament and seek ways of comprehending it.
Social theory contributes a few ways of addressing this predicament-along with the
ideas of philosophy and the experiences of art and poetry. Social theory gives us reasoned
accounts and diagnoses of attempts by modernity-sometimes beneficial attempts, some
times disastrous attempts-to take possession of time and to compensate for death in our
immediate and only real world: our social world of material inequalities between people,
of violence and injustiGe. When Karl Marx declared that philosophers have only ever
interpreted the world but that the point is to change it, he expressed only a more funda
mental maxim of all modernity and of all modern theorizing. This maxim is that*theoria
'contcmplation', as the ancient Greeks defined it-finds nogenuine truth unless and until
it is mediated with praxis, with practical engagement with the tasks of the here and now:
the tasks of politics, the tasks of using society's shared constituted powers to make its
conditions of life better: freer, fairer, and happier for everyone. It can be said that the
maxim of modernity is that though we remain mortal, we possess the power and the
responsibility to make the best of our existence, by creating a world that offers everyone
an equal chance for a fulfilling social life. Insofar as we are modern and want to be
modern, we want to improve our conditions of shared life, not by ignoring the past or
forgetting the past and not by repeating the past. We cannot have a rational will to want a
future that is always the same as the past. We can only have a rational will to want to
change the world for the better, as best we can.
■ GLOSSARY OF TERMS
The purpose of this glossary is to provide additional explanation for common technical terms occurring usually on more
than one occasion in this book. It is not, however, intended to be a comprehensive dictionary of sociological
terminology. With the exception of a few key terms that have deserved repeated definition in succinct form, the
glossary does not cover terms explained at length m the main chapters of this book under particular section or
subsection titles. It omits explanations for terms which the reader will find adequately described at the relevant page
references listed in the index to this book. It has been designed to fill in some of the gaps between names for major
sociological topics and unfamiliar words defined in any ordinary dictionary of the English language.
absolutism historical term referring to the absolute autopoietic term from the Greek word for 'creation',
power of the sovereign over all subjects, typically under poies1s; used by Nik/as Luhmann with the meaning
the European absolute monarchies of the seventeenth of 'self-generation'.
century; for example under the rule of Louis XIV of
base-superstructure term referring to the simplest
France See further pp. 148-9.
form of the Marxist theory of ideology in which culture
action frame of reference term in the work of Talcott and politics are said to be determined by an underlying
Parsons denoting the conceptual framework to be base of economic forces. The expression occurs in
presupposed in all social enquiry, focusing on the agency Marx's Preface to 'A Contribution to the Critique of
of actors in contexts of structure. See further pp. 93. Political Economy' (1859: 389) but nowhere else in his
writing in any explicit form. The term is usually used to
agency term meaning the ability of individuals to act in
describe the more reductive and deterministic forms of
pursuit of goals, in a context of constraints, determinants,
'vulgar Marxism' prevalent in Soviet doctrine and rejected
and influences on their actions. See further pp. 215-16.
by most of the Western Marxists. See further pp. 155.
anomie term in the work of f:mile Durkheim, meaning a
behaviourism term referring to an approach in
condition of 'normlessness' or moral vacuum, resulting
psychology initiated by J.B. Watson and continued by
from a weakness or absence of rules regulating social
B. F. Skinner, which ignores mental activity and focuses
intercourse; negation of the Greek word for 'law', nomos.
purely on observable behaviour.
See further pp. 54--5.
binary term from the Latin for 'two', binarius;
anthropocentric term meaning any way of thinking that elaborated by Jacques Derrida and used in structuralist
places human images of the world at the centre of the
and post-structuralist theory and feminist theory; refers
universe, naively over-affirming the sovereignty of human
to examples of logical opposites or pairings between
beings as makers and knowers of existence.
two ideas, where one idea is said to be meaningful only
a priori Latin term in philosophy meaning logically true by dependence on the other idea. The two ideas are
and necessary, independent of observation in experience. said to prop each other up, usually with the one
enjoying implicit or explicit dominance over the other;
asceticism term referring to self-denying abstention from e.g. mind/body, rational/irrational, culture/nature,
comforts and pleasures for the sake of a higher goal or
masculine/feminine.
inner truth; used by Max Weber to describe the rise of a
See further pp. 201.
Protestant 'work ethic' in relation to capitalism in early
modern Europe and North America. See further pp. 70. civil society term prevalent in political thought from the
eighteenth century onwards, referring to social relations
autonomy term from the Greek words auto and nomos, that mediate between the private economic interests of
meaning 'self-law', or the ability freely to determine one's
individuals and families on the one hand and the
own actions and to be responsible for oneself; not to be administrative-bureaucratic interests of the state on the
subject to indoctrination or inducement by manipulative other hand. Civil society is the site of the public interest
influences; a term originating in the philosophy of or public sphere, embodied in political institutions and
Immanuel Kant, used particularly by critical theorists associations. Marx saw civil society as little more than a
such as Jurgen Habermas. cover for the interests of the bourgeoisie. Other thinkers,
318
empirical term referring to knowledge based on science and technology; associated with the writings
observation from experience, from data given to the
of Jean-Paul Sartre, Martin Heidegger, and others.
senses.
exploitation term in Marxism referring to the extraction
empiricist term denoting the doctrine that all knowledge
of surplus value from human labour power for the benefit
is based only on observation from experience, from data
of the ruling class, especially for the purpose of profit
given to the senses, denying the validity of other possible
under capitalism; depriving workers of the time, resources,
sources, methods, or forms of knowledge involving the
and freedom to lead fully humane lives. See further
labour of the mind, the imagination, language, and
pp. 46--7.
cultural commun cation.
feudalism term referring to socio-economic relations in
Enlightenment term referring to the eighteenth-century
the Middle Ages in which landowners ('lords') grant
Age of Reason in Western culture (when spelled with a
protection and maintenance to the labourers of the land
capital 'E'); also referring more generically to social
('vassals') 1n return for services in kind, especially service
consciousness guided by rational thought and by critical
in war. In Marxism, feudalism is seen as a mode of
scrutiny of existing ideas and·nstitut1ons, with an
production in which surplus value is extracted from labour
orientation to realizing universally JUSt laws and norms
power in the form of personal ties of obligation to
(when spelled either with a lower-case 'e' or with a
paternalistic authority figures With the rise of capitalism,
capital 'El See further pp. 17, 160-5.
these traditional ties are gradually replaced by the
epistemological, epistemic term from the Greek word anonymity and impersonality of the wage contract. See
for 'knowledge'; refers to the theory of knowledge, or to further pp 147-9
the modes and methods by which knowledge is
obtained. foundational, foundationalist term referring to the
idea of unshakeable grounds for knowledge, founded in
essentialism term referring to questionable notions of self-evident logical truths or in the certainty of sense-data.
basic, fixed, and unchanging identities in particular These grounds are said to remain constant across history
things, ideas, persons, or cultures; for example, the
and across cultures. The idea is criticized in postmodern
notion that women are 'essentially passive', men
and anti-positivist thought, particularly in the work of
'essentially active'.
Richard Rorty.
ethnocentric term referring to habits of thought that
Frankfurt School term referring to the associates of the
misunderstand the distictness,of people who differ in their
lnstitut fur Sozialforschung (Institute for Social Research)
basic cultural values, beliefs, or ideas of the world from
founded at Frankfurt University in 1923 and to its
those people who claim to explain their behaviour.
influence on several German-born Marxist theorists active
ethnography term referring to the practice of researching after the Second World War in Europe and
in detail a whole small-scale society or other social the USA; including Max Horkheimer, Theodor Adorno,
structure or process, using qualitative methods, usually Herbert Marcuse. Leo Lowenthal, Herbert Marcuse,
involving a lengthy period of participant observation; a Jurgen Habermas, and others. See further
standard pp. 160-1.
practice in anthropology but increasingly favoured also in
sociology and even political science. functional equivalent term used by Robert Merton,
suggesting that some social functions may be necessary
ethnomethodology term referring to the work of but need not be met always 1n the same way. For example,
Harold Garfinkel and his associates; stressing microscopic it might be said that sport is a functional equivalent for
participatory study of the ways in which people produce religion.
meaning and social order through ongoing interpretations
of each other's actions. See further pp. 117-19. functionalism term referring mainly to the work of
American sociological theorists active in the middle
Eurocentrism term referring to ways of thinking that decades of the twentieth century, represented by Talcott
unJustifiably extend the validity of European historical and Parsons, Robert Merton, and others; influenced by mile
cultural experiences to all cultures and civilizations of the
Durkheim and by the scientific anthropology of Bronislaw
world. See further pp. 32-3
Malinowski and Alfred Radcliffe-Brown; holding that a
existentialism term denoting a movement in twentieth society is to be studied in terms of interdependent
century European philosophy, stressing the fragility and 'systems' and 'structures' that perform interrelated
finitude of human existence and the responsibility of the 'functions' for the society as a whole: also known as
human person in the face of a soc,al universe that is no 'structural functionalism'. See further pp. 87--8.
longer able to believe in God or to follow conventional
moral norms and that 1s sceptical of the social benefits of
GLOSSARY OF TERMS 321
grand theory term used by critics of Talcott Parsons attitude to life'. A materialist in social theory is someone
to describe his project for 'general unified theory' in who emphasizes explaining social behaviour by
social science. See further pp. 92. reference to basic physical essentials of life (such as
food, shelter, power, or freedom to act on one's needs
guilds term referring to professional associations among and desires, including freedom from suffering, disease,
craftsmen and merchants of the Middle Ages formed for violence, or slavery) in relation to the life chances of a//
mutual aid and protection in specific trades; regarded by people, rich or poor, whether 'money grubbing' or not. In
Emile Durkheim as pre-democratic precursors of the Max Weber's sociology, 'materialist' theories of social
modern trade unions and other 'occupational groups' that life are balanced critically with 'idealist' or 'interpretive'
theories. which emphasize not only
322 HOS'SARY OF HRMS
of as a notional benchmark, in relation to which any subordination of all dimensions of social life to the most
actual phenomenon may either approximate or deviate. efficient achievement of economic profit and
See further pp. 65-6. administrative order; adapted from Max Weber's concept
of 'purposive rat1onal1ty' or 'means nds rationality',
ideology term used either in a strongly value-laden denoting the most efficient use of available means to
sense or in a relatively neutral descriptive sense, or- given ends, without deliberation on the value of the ends
more commonly-in various cnt1cal rnmbinations of
themselves.
these
two senses. In the value-laden sense, ideology means integration term developed by functionalist theorists,
socially generalized false belief, illusion, or 'false indicating that social systems typically maintain an orderly
consciousness', typically serving the interests of a character through coordinating mechanisms, even during
dominant ruling group. In the more neutral sense, times of conflict. For example, fascism provided a means
ideology refers to any system of ideas expressed In of integration for European societies during the 1930s
cultural self-images and shared beliefs of particular depression, albeit a very unstable one. Integration is often
social groups regarded as the functional counterpart to differentiation.
See further pp. 53-4, 97, 102.
GLOSSARY OF TEP.MS 323
intersubjective, intersubjectivity term originating in 'reason' or 'speech'. See further pp. 203---4
Giddens and others, referring to communicative exchange produce what I want (my means). See further pp. 75-6, 93.
between interacting human agents, emphasizing that messianic term used to describe Jewish theological
identities of the self are formed through social interaction themes in the Marxist writing of Walter Benjamin, Ernst
and communication and that reference to the world as an Bloch, and others, referring to the idea that a future
objective reality is achieved only through shared communist society can be affirmed but not 'imagined' or
understandings between actors. 'represented', because it marks an unforeseeable and
Kantianism see Kant (1n Biographies of Theorists) incalculable break with existing historical structures of
thought and behaviour, like the coming of the Messiah to
Keynesian see Keynes (in Biographies ofTheorists) the earthly world.
lack term in the psychoanalysis of Jacques Lacan, meta-narrative term used by Jean-Fran ois Lyotard,
suggesting that culture, morality, and identity represent denoting generalizing accounts of history or science that
forms of compensation for more basic experiences of subsume disparate contexts of experience under a single
privation, denied pleasure, or bodily disorientation in overarching frame of reference. See further pp, 256-8.
sensory life.
metaphysics term in philosophy referring to systematic
lay actor term meaning any ordinary person who is not a conceptions of the fundamental structures of reality,
social scientist; or more precisely, any ordinary person regarded by some twentieth-century philosophers as
except in the case when this person acts as a social responsible for generating confusions in ordinary
scientist. Professor X is a lay actor whenever he or she is language.
out shopping or catching a train, but not when he or she
middle-range theory term coined by Robert Merton
is doing scientific fieldwork.
recommending that theory be grounded in specific empirical
legislative term referring to prescriptive modes of problems for explanation, in preference to 'grand', abstract,
thought preoccupied with universal moral laws, especially or speculative theory. See further pp. 90--2, 102,310.
in the Enlightenment philosophy of Immanuel Kant; used
modernism term denoting cultural, intellectual, and
by commentators on postmodernism, such as Zygmunt
artistic movements that express, interrogate, or celebrate
Bauman; not to be confused with the standard sense of
ideas of modernity; a term with a relatively precise
the lawmaking power of government.
temporal reference, usually thought of as the period
324 GLOSSARY OF TERMS
neo-liberalism term referring to economic policy object relations term in psychology, especially in the
prevalent since the 1980s, involving a return to classical writings of the psychoanalysts Melanie Klein and Donald
eighteenth- and nineteenth-century economic principles Winnicott; refers to the emergence of a sense of self in
of non-interference by governments in the workings of a the child by differentiation from a surrounding world. The
free market; a central term in contemporary debates child experiences a sense of limitation caused by objects
about globalization and the demise of socialism and social which are not part of the child and cannot be changed by
democracy. the child (such as the breast of the mother).
NGOs term used as an abbreviation for 'non objectivist term referring to approaches to social enquiry
governmental organizations'; referring to non-profit that overemphasize the relative importance of structural or
organizations that are neither attached to the state nor systemic constraints on the actions of individuals, and
constituted as private businesses and are established for underestimate the relative importance of individual agency
political or altruistic purposes, typically with charity in relation to structures and systems; usually nvolves an
status; for example, Oxfam, Amnesty International, excessively narrow and strict definition of objectivity,
Greenpeace. sometimes with an appeal to the natural sciences as a
nihilism term deriving from the Latin word for 'nothing', model for social research; typically involves neglect of the
nihil; refers to forms of extreme sceptIcIsm about the expressive, 'subjectively meaningful' character of socio
possibility of cross-cultural agreement over values, cultural life
especially about truth, goodness, justice, and morality;
ontological term deriving from the Greek participle of
often associated with the philosophy of Friedrich Nietzsche
the verb 'to be': refers to enquiry about what exists, or
and postmoderrnsm.
does not exist, in the world; or about what kinds of
nomothetic term from the Greek word for 'law', entities are believed by people to exist; for example,
spirits, ghosts and witches or-alternatively-atoms,
nomos; coined by the Nee-Kantian philosopher Wilhem
Windelband; referring to the study of law-like regularities neurones, H20, electricity, DNA. The term can also be
and generalities rather than historically specific cases used to refer to enquiry about what social life consists of;
and for example,
GLOSSARY OF TERMS 325
of families; or with a broader meaning, referring to more positive science term meaning empirical science,
generalized, indirect, institutional forms of male cultural claiming to be free from metaphysical speculation;
and political hegemony. See further pp 235. 'positive' in the sense of observing what is given or
'posited' in experience, though not necessarily in the
patrimonial term referring to inheritance of positions
sense of 'optimistic' (although this sense is often implied).
of power and especially property by younger men from
older male authority figures, originally by sons from the positivism term coined in the nineteenth century by
father of the family. Auguste Comte, referring to the strongest form of
performative term coined by the philosopher J. L. Austin, empiricism which holds that experimental observation is the
referring to linguistic utterances which create the state of only valid source of knowledge and rejects all other sources
affairs to which they refer in the act being uttered; for of understanding-such as theology, metaphysics, or
example, the utterance of the priest at a wedding, 'I hereby poetry-as incapable of rigorous validation. Positivism found
pronounce thee man and wife'. many adherents in the early twentieth century, including
notably the members of the Vienna Circle, also known as
performativity term referring to the idea that speech the 'logical positivists'. See further pp. 27-8, 203-4.
and language involve not only description of the world but
also action and performance in the world, typically positivity term referring to social experience insofar as it
involving the transmission of relations of power. is felt to be given or 'posited', as it it were a thing of
Alternatively the term may simply mean 'efficiency of nature, impervious to change or negation by criticism.
operation'.
postcolonialism term meaning the study and theory of
phallogocentrism term in feminist theory, coined by cultures, societies. and history 1n the light of Western
Julia Kristeva and Helene C1xous, combining the term colonial conquest. See further pp. 34, 166, 205, 247-9.
'logocentrism' (coined by Jacques Derrida) with the word
post-Fordism term meaning the observation or thesis
'phallus'; used to refer to a masculine privileging of
that modern industrial production has moved away from
326 'iLOSSARY OF TERMS
reflexivity term meaning 'reference to oneself', self-reference term with a technical meaning in the
work of Niklas Luhmann, denoting the manner in which
'application to oneself', or 'reflection on oneself' The
an entity refers to itself in the act of referring to anything
subject of an action is simultaneously the object of the
which is not itself, as having an identity only insofar as it is
action (for example in the French reflexive verb s'habiller,
not something else. Luhmann's use of this term can be
'to get dressed' or 'to dress oneself'). The term implies
compared to structuralist and post-structuralist theories of
self-awareness, self- monitoring, and usually, though not
meaning in terms of relations of difference between
necessarily, self-criticism Reflexivity can pertain to
individual persons or to institutions. See further pp, 221-2. signifiers.
reification term deriving from the Latin word for 'thing', semiotics term deriving from the Greek word semeion,
res; used in Marxism with the meaning 'reduction to a meaning 'sign'; refers to theories of the generation of
meaning in texts and other symbolic objects through
thing', i.e. the reduction of persons, ideas, sensory
differential relationships between signs. See further
qualities, or expressive agencies to commodities or to pure
pp, 198-200,
objects of consumption, administration, or quantitative
categorization sex and gender terms conveying a distinction between
relativism term with a variety of contested definitions. In sex as an anatomical condition and gender as a cultural
the narrowest and least sustainable definition, relativism condition. Sex is said to be given, while gender is said to
is the view that any one person's point of view is as good be non-given, changing, and constructed. The distinction
as another's, or that 'anything goes'. More broadly, it is has been useful to feminist theorists in overturning
the view that truth (or other ultimate values such as essentializing definitions of woman and femininity, but has
been criticized by more recent feminists for overlooking
goodness or beauty) is not universal or absolute in its
the degree to which anatomical categories of sex and the
meaning or content but is best understood as what is
body are also historically changing and discursively
'accepted as true', or as 'what counts as true', for people
in particular cultures, societies, and periods of history. In constructed. See further pp. 236-7, 243-5.
social theory and philosophy, relativism is often used as
signifier and signified terms in semiotics and structural
a term of criticism, emphasizing that while values and
linguistics, where 'signifier' refers to a sign which denotes
beliefs have meaning only in definite social-historical
or connotes some meaning, and where 'signified' refers to
contexts and are
328 GLOSSARY OF TERMS
The following list of biographical entries provides brief reference information for prominent theorists
discussed in this book, as well as for some relevant historical personalities. Entries include references
to a small selection of the major works of named figures.
Becker, Howard (b 1928). US sociologist influenced Bhaskar, Roy (b. 1944). British philosopher of social
by symbolic interact1onism and the Chicago School, sC1ence, influenced by Marxism, originator of 'critical
best known for work on deviance, medicine, and realism·. Author of A RealJSt Theory of Science (1975),
cultural institutions from an ethnographic perspective. The Possibility of Naturalism (1979), and Scientific
Author of Boys m White (1961), Outsiders (1963). and Realism and Human Emanc,pation (1986).
Art Worlds (1982). See further pp. 116. See further pp. 127, 227-9.
Derrida, Jacques (1930--2004). French theorist of Durkheim, tmile (1858-1917). French founder of the
deconstruction, associated with post-structuralism; discipline of sociology and founder of the journal L'Annee
influenced by Nietzsche, Heidegger, Saussure, and structural sociologique; uncle of Marcel Mauss. Author of The
linguistics; leading theorist of t xtual ambiguity, 'differance', Division of Labour (1893), The Rules of Sociological
and 'logocentrism'. Author of Of Grammatology(1967), Method (1895), Suicide (1897), and The Elementary
Writing and Difference (1968), Margins of Philosophy Forms of Religions Life (1912). See further pp. 51-60.
(1972), Speech and Phenomena (1973), and Spectres of
Eisenstadt, Shmuel (b. 1923). Israeli comparative historical
Marx(1992). See further pp. 202-6, 253-4
sociologist of civilizations; influenced in early work by
Descartes, Rene (1596--1650). French seventeenth functionalism; later work advocating a conception of
century rationalist philosopher, regarded as the founder of 'multiple modernities' influenced by Karl Jaspers's thesis
modern philosophy and modern geometry; proponent of of the 'axial age civilizations' Author of The Political
a dualistic theory of mind and body (also known as Systems of Empires (1963); editor of The Origins and
'Cartesian dualism') which has been the object of criticism Diversity of
in twentieth-century social thought. Author tif Discourse the Axial Age Civilisations (1986). See further pp. 136--7.
on Method (1637) and Meditations on First Philosophy
Elias, Norbert (1893-1990). German Jewish sociologist,
(1641). See further pp. 20.
em1gre to Britain and the Netherlands, theorist of conflict,
Dewey, John (1859-1952). American pragmatist socialization, and the 'civilizing process'. Author of The
philosopher of education, democracy, religion, art, and Civilizing Process (1939), The Court Society(1969), and
civic well-being; defined all values with reference to The Germans (1989). See further pp. 141-4, 222.
'experience' conducive to reasonable conduct and
effective practice. Author of Democracy and Education Elster, Jon (b. 1940). Norwegian-born theorist of rational
choice; applied methodological individualist principles to
(1916), Human Nature and Conduct (1922), The Quest
the study of Marx and the philosophy of social science in
for Certainty (1929), and A Common Faith (1934).
general. Author of Ulysses and the Sirens (1979),
Making Sense of Marx (1985), and The Cement of
Society (1989).
Black Skin, White Masks (1952) and Wretched of the Fromm, Erich (1900-80). German social psychologist,
Earth(1961). See further pp. 34,167. emigre to the USA. early brief associate of the Frankfurt
Ferguson, Adam (1723-1815). Scottish Enlightenment School; combined Freudian psychoanalysis with social
historical writer and philosopher, wrote on conflict and critique. Author of The Art of Loving (1956) and To Have
the division of labour in society. Author of An Essay on and To Be (1976). See further pp. 160, 180.
Civil Society (1767). Gadamer, Hans-Georg (1900-2002). German
Feuerbach, Ludwig (1804-72). German nineteenth hermeneutic philosopher, influenced by Martin Heidegger;
century philosopher, follower and critic of Hegel; argued defined hermeneutics as a practice of the interpretation of
that God is the projection of man and an expression of existence, history, and tradition founded in dialogue
human alienation, influencing Karl Marx's materialist between the past and the present; an early influence on
critique of religion and idealist metaphysics. Author of Jurgen Habermas. Author of Truth and Method (1960)
The Essence of Christianity (1841) and Basic Propositions See further pp. 125-7.
of the Philosophy of the Future (1843). Galbraith, John Kenneth (b. 1908). US economist,
Feyerabend, Paul (1924-94). Austrian philosopher of concerned with the fate of the public interest in capitalist
science, emigre to the USA; early advocate of positivism, economies. Author of The Affluent Saeler; (1958) and
later advocate of strong relativism or 'epistemological Economics and the Public Purpose (1973) See further
anarchism'; famous for the provocative slogan that in pp. 140-1.
science 'anything goes'. Author of Against Method
Garfinkel, Harold (b. 1917). US sociologist, founder of
(1975) See further pp. 123.
ethnomethodology, theorist of tacit rules in social
Foucault, Michel (1926-84). French theorist of power, communication and interaction. Author of Studies in
knowledge, science, history, discourse, subjectivity, and Ethnomethodology (1967). See further pp.110, 117-19.
sexuality, influenced by structuralism and Nietzsche.
Geertz, Clifford (b. 1923). US anthropologist, associated
Author of Madness and Civilization (1961), The Order
with a 'cultural turn' in social science modelled on the
of Things (1966), Discipline and Punish (1975), and reading of texts, best known for his concept of 'thick
The History of Sexuality (1976-84) (in 3 vols.). See further description'. Author of The Interpretation of Cultures
pp. 201-12. (1973) and Local Knowledge (1983). See further pp. 122.
336 BIOGRAPHIES OF THEORISTS
The Coming Crisis of Western Sociology (1970) and Harre, Rom (b. 1927) New Zealand-born philosopher of
For Sociology(1973). See further pp. 102. science and social psychologist based in Britain and the
USA; theorist of realism in science, favouring an
Gramsci, Antonio (1891-1937) Italian Marxist theorist,
1nteract1onist approach 1n preference to naturalistic and
co-founder of the Italian Communist Party; imprisoned
by the fascist regime under Mussolini from 1926 until structuralist variants of realism. Author of Social Bemg
his death. Author of Selections from the Prison (1980); co-author with Paul Secord of The Explanation of
Notebooks (1926-37). See further pp. 6-7, 157-9. Social Behaviour (1972). See further pp. 126.
Knowledge and Human Interests (1968), The Theory the slave 1s said to triumph over the master insofar as the
of Communicative Action (1981), and Between Facts master depends on the slave for vital needs, a thesis
notably developed in the writing of the French
and Norms (1992). See further pp. 125-7, 164-5, 279-83.
phenomenological philosopher Alexandre Kojeve.
Halbwachs, Maurice (1877-1945). French sociologist, Author of The Phenomenology of Spirit (1807) and
influenced by Durkheim and the philosopher Henri The Philosophy of Right (1821). See further pp. 6.
Korsch, Karl (1889--1961). German Marxist theorist. such as in the work of Zygmunt Bauman and
influenced by Hegelian dialectical thought Author of others. Author of Totality and lnfin,ty(1961) and
Marxism and Philosophy (1923) and Karl Marx (1938). Otherwise Than Being or Beyond Essence (1974).
See further pp. 157 Levi-Strauss, Claude (b. 1908). French anthropologist,
pioneer of structuralism in anthropology, following
Kracauer, S egfr ed (1889-1956). German cultural theorist.
Ferdinand oe Saussure's structura linguistics Author of
emigre to the USA; theorist of film and photography,
popular culture and the metropolis, influenced by S1mmel The Elementary Structures of Krnsh1p (1949), Tristes
and Marxism; close friend of Walter Benjamin and Tropiques (1955), Structural Anthropology (1958),
Theodor Adorno. Author of The Mass Ornament (1931}. The Savage Mind (1966), and Mythologies (1964--71}.
From Caligari to Hitler: A Psychological History of the See further pp. 200-202.
German Film (1947). and Theory of Film (1960), Lipset, Seymour Martin (b. 1922). US sociologist; studied
democracy and democratization 1n comparative historical
Kristeva, Julia (b. 1941). French-Bulgarian feminist
perspective Author of Political Man (1960) and The First
psychoanalytic theorist and literary critic, influenced by
New Nation (1963) See further pp. 138.
semiotics. Author of Revolution in Poetic Language
(1974) and Tales of Love (1983). See further pp. 189-91. Locke, John (1632- 704). Eng 1sh seventeenth-century
philosopher of Pmpincism; theorist of liberal democracy
Kuhn, Thomas (1922-96) US historian and philosopher
and the origins of private property; supporter of
of science; theorized the history of ,uence in terms of
religious toleration and separation of Church and
discontinuous 'paradigm shifts', casting doubt on linear
state; influential in eighteenth-century France and
progress ,n science; regarded as preparing the ground for
North America. Author of An Essay Concerning
BIOGRAPHIES OF THEORISTS 339
criticized by Hans Blumenberg in relation to the anthropologist based in Britain; pioneer of anthropological
question of the 'legitimacy of the modern age' Author of fieldwork in a functionalist framework; famously studied gift
exchange systems among inhabitants of the Trobriand Islands
From Hegel to Nietzsche
in north-western Melanesia. Author of Argonauts of the
(1941), Meaning in History(1949), and Max Weber and
Karl Marx (repr. 1982). Western Pacific (1922), The Sexual Life of Savages (1932),
and A Soentific Theory of Culture (1944). See further pp. 88.
Luckmann, Thomas (b. 1927). Austrian sociologist,
Mann, Michael (b. 1942) British-born historical
influenced by Alfred Schutz and phenomenological
sociologist; recognized for work on the history of social
philosophy; edited Schutz's later unfinished writings on
power. Author of The Sources of Social Power (1986,
'structures of the lifeworld'. Co-author of The Social
vol. i; 1993, vol. ii). See further pp. 148.
Construction of Reality (1966) with Peter Berger. See
further pp. 121 Mannheim, Karl (1893-1947). Hungarian-born theorist
based in Germany until 1933 before emigrating to Britain;
Luhmann, Niklas (1927-98). German theorist of social
influenced by phenomenology and German historicism;
systems, influenced by Talcott Parsons and cybernetic
founding theorist and methodologist of the sociology of
theory; critic of Habermas. Author of The Differentiation
knowledge and the sociology of culture. Author of
of Society (1970) and Social Systems (1984). See further
Conservatism (1925), Ideology and Utopia (1929), Essays
pp. 283-5.
on the Sociology of Knowledge (1952), and Essays on
Lukacs, Gyorgy (Georg) (1885-1971). Hungarian Marxist the Sociology of Culture (1956). See further pp. 120-1.
theorist influenced by Hegel, German philosophy,
Marcuse, Herbert (1898-1979). German-born Marxist
Weber, and Simmel; became in later work a rather
theorist, emigre to the USA; member of the Frankfurt
dogmatic adherent of Soviet communism. Author of
School; influential in the American 1968 peace
Theory of the Novel (1910), History and Class
movement. Author of Reason and Revolution (1941),
Consciousness (1923), and The Destruction of Reason
Eros and Civilization (1955), and One-Dimensional Man
(1955). See further pp. 156--7.
(1964). See further pp. 166, 180-1.
Luther, Martin (1483-1 546). German sixteenth-century
Marshall, Alfred (1842-1924) English economist;
religious thinker; leader of the Protestant Reformation in synthesized classical political economy with the theory of
northern Germany; believed that salvation was to be
'marginal utility'. Author of The Principles of Economics
sought 'by faith alone', not by tribute to the Church or by
(1890).
outward deeds; translated the Bible into German in
1521-46.
340 BIOGRAPHIES OF THEORISTS
Nietzsche, Friedrich (1844-1900) German nineteenth Popper, Karl (1902 94) Austrian liberal phi'osopher
century philosopher; forerunner of existentialism and of science based in Britain, linked to the Vienna Circle in
philosopher of nihilism; celebrated for his conception of early work, later became a critic of logical positivism,
personality', and for his doctrine of the 'death of God'. acceptance of scientific theories until shown to be false;
also a proponent of the concept of the 'open society'
Author of The Birth of Tragedy(1872), The Gay Science
based on liberal critique of Hegelian-Marxist philosophy
(1882), Thus SpokeZarathustra (1885) and Beyond
of history. Author of logic of Scientific Discovery (1935),
Good and Evil (1886) See further pp 254-5.
The Open SoC/ety and its Enemies (1945), and
Pareto, Vil/redo (1848-1923) lta'ian theorist of power, Conjectures and
elites, and economic advantage, forerunner of rational Refutations (1963).
cho'ce theory; close to the work of Mosca and Michels
Author of The Mind and Society (1916). See further Poulantzas, Nicos (1936-79). Greek-born Marxist theorist
pp. 28-30. based in France, influenced by Louis Althusser; theorist of
the state, social class, and stratification. Author of Political
Parsons, Talcott (1902-79). US theorist; the most Power and Social Classes ( 1968) and Classes in
systematic theorist of functionalism (also known as Contemporary Capitalism (1974).
'structural functionalism'); influenced by
Durkheim, Weber and evolutionary thought, introduced Proudhon, Pierre Joseph (1809-65). Nineteenth-century
European social theory to the USA in the 1930s. Author of French utopian socialist writer, famous for the slogan
The Structure of Social Action (1937), The Social 'property is theft'. Author of What is Property? (1840)
System (1951), TheSystemofModern
Radcliffe-Brown. Arthur (1881-1955) British
Societies (1971), The Evolution of Societies (1977), and
anthropologist, pioneer of functionalism in anthropology
Action Theory and the Human Condition (1978); co
Author of Andaman Islanders (1922) and Structure and
author of Toward a General Theory of Action (1951) with
Function 111 Pnm1tive Society (1952). See further
Edward Shils, and Economy and Society (1956) with Neil
pp. 88.
Smelser. See further pp. 92-9.
Rawls, John (1921-2002). US liberal political philosopher,
Peirce, Charles, S. (1839-1914). American nineteenth
the most influential American political philosopher of
century philosopher, mathematician, and logician; founder
the twentieth century; originator of a Kantian theory of
of pragmatism as a philosophical movement; also
justice evaluating the relative priority of liberty of
propounded a theory of semiotics. Author of Collected
individuals over equality of individuals. Author of
Papers (1n 8 vols.) (1865-1914).
A Theory of Justice (1971), Political liberalism (1993), and
The law of Peoples (1999).
Piaget, Jean (1896-1980). Swiss-French psychologist;
Rex, John (b. 1925). South Afr,can-born sociologist based
studied cognitive development in children, developed a
in Britain, critic of functionalism, proponent of conflict
theory of 'genetic structuralism'; influenced Habermas's
theory. Author of Key Problems of Soc,ological Theory
theory of communicative action Author of The Chtld's
(1961), Race Relations in Soc,ological Theory(1970), and
Conception of Physical Causality (1930), The Moral
Social Conflict (1981). See further pp. 100.
Judgement of the Child (1932), and Genetic
Epistemology (1968). Ricardo, David (1772-1823). English eighteenth- and
nineteenth-century economist; a wealthy stockbroker,
Plato (c. 427-347 BC). Ancient Greek philosopher, disciple
friend of Jeremy Bentham and James Mill (father of John
of the dissident sage Socrates (c. 470-399 sc); the single
Stuart Mill), criticized at length by Marx; analysed
most influential intellectual figure of Western antiquity;
distributions of goods between landowners, workers, and
notable for his conception of truth and Justice as
owners of capital, formulating an 'Iron Law of Wages'
absolute values 1n themselves, knowable only by
which stated that all attempts to improve the real income
trarscendence of everyday subiective opinion. Author of
of workers are futile and that wages necessarily tend
The Republic
toward near-subsistence level. Author of Principles of
(c. 360 ec).
Political Economy and Taxation (1817).
Polanyi, Karl (1886-1964). Austrian-born economic
Rickert, Heinrich (1863-1936). German Neo-Kantian
historian, emigrated to Britain and the USA; analysed the
philosopher; influenced Max Weber's views on the
rise of international capitalism in relation to processes of
342 BIOGRAPHIES OF THEORISTS
Robertson, Roland (b. 1942) British soc1olog1st; regarded Scheler, Max (1874-1928). German theorist, influenced
as one of the first writers to define 'globalization' as a by phenomenology, Nietzsche, and German historicism;
sociological concept; also inventor of the term influenced Karl Mannheim, Alfred Schutz,
·glocalization' Author of Globaltzation, Social Theory and and others in the development of the 'sociology of
Social Culture (1992) and Globalization and Modernity knowledge' as a field of investigation; elaborated a
(2002) See further pp. 304-5. conception of 'philosophical anthropology' emphasizing
the importance of feeling, emotion, desire, will, and
Rorty. Richard (b. 1931). US pragmatist philosopher, critic
compassion in human action and thought. Author of The
of .<\nglo-Amencan analytical philosophy, associated with
Nature of Sympathy(1912), Problems of a Sociology of
postmodernism; sophisticated defender of relativism in
Knowledge (1926), and Man's Place in Nature (1928).
cultural values, sceptical of universal claims to truth and
of indubitable foundations for knowledge; advocate of Schmitt, Carl (1888-1985). German conservative legal
'post-foundat1onalism' Author of Philosophy and the and political theorist. influential in international relat ons
Mirror of Nature (1979) and Contingency, Irony and theory; student of Max Weber; critic of democracy and
Solidarity (1989). bureaucracy, theorist of Realpolitik and of 'friend-enemy
relations'; argued that the essence of political
Rousseau, Jean-Jacques (1712-78). Swiss-French
sovereignty lay in the ability to 'decide in the emergency
Enlightenment philosopher; influential in the French
case' and to prevail over disorder; compromised by
Revolution; champion of republicanism and direct
support for the Nazis. Author of The Concept of the
democracy, believer in the natural goodness of man; critic
Political (1932) and Political Theology (1934).
of social and political corruption. Author of The Social
Contract (1762), tmile (1762), and Confessions (1782). Schumpeter, Joseph (1883-1950). Moravian-born
economist, emigre to the USA; influenced by Weber;
Ryle, Gilbert (1900-76). British analytical philosopher of
critic of both Marxism and classical economics. Author of
language, influenced by Ludwig Wittgenstein; cntimed
Capitahsm, Sooa/ism and Democracy (1942) and History
Descartes's dualism of mind and body as suggesting a
of Economic Analysis (1963). See further pp. 139-40.
notion of 'the ghost in the machine'; distinguished
influentially between practical knowledge ('knowing Schutz, Alfred (1899-1959). Austrian phenomenological
how') and theoretical knowledge ('knowing-that'). Author philosopher, emigre to the USA; influenced by Weber,
of The Concept of Mind (1949) Edmund Husserl, and Henn Bergson, founder of
phenomenological sociology. Author The
Said, Edward (1935-2003). Palestinian-American cultural
Phenomenology of the Social World (1932), Collected
theorist and literary critic, influenced by Marxism,
Papers (1962-66) (in 3 vols.); co-author of Structures of
psychoanalysis, and Michel Foucault, pioneer of
the Lifeworld with Thomas luckmann (1973). See further
postcolonial theory. Author of Beginnings (1975) and
pp. 112-14, 121
Orienta/ism (1978). See further pp. 34.
Searle. John (b. 1932). US philosopher, pioneer of
Saint-Simon, Claude Henn de Rouvroy, Comte de
speech-act theory (with John Austin). Author of
(1760-1825). Nineteenth-century French utopian socialist
Speech Acts (1971) and The Construction of Social
Reality (1995).
BIOGRAPHIES OF THEORiSTS 343
Smith, Dorothy (b. 1926). Canadian feminist theorist, Tocqueville, Alexis de (1805-59). French nineteenth
originator of feminist standpoint epistemology. Author of century liberal political thinker and commentator;
The Everyday World as Problematic: A Feminist Sociology celebrated for his conception of 'voluntary associations' as
(1987) and The Conceptual Practices of Power: A Feminist sources of democratic solidarity. Author of Democracy in
Sociology of Knowledge (1990) America (1835) and The Old Regime and the Revolution
(1856). See further pp. 25-7, 134.
Spencer, Herbert (1820-1903). English Victorian social
philosopher, influenced by Charles Darwin, Auguste Tiinnies, Ferdinand (1855-1936). German founding
Comte, and evolutionary thought. Author of The figure in sociology, a contemporary of Weber and
Principles of Sociology (1882-98) (in 3 vols.). See further Simmel; famously distinguished between a disappearing
pp. 28. condition of Gemeinschaft ('community') and an
emerging condition of Gese/lschaft ('society'). Author of
Spivak, Gayatri Chakravorty (b. 1942). Indian-American Community and Society (1887). See further pp. 30-1,
feminist theorist, influenced by deconstruction; pioneer of 37.
postcolonial criticism; translator of Jacques Derrida's Of
Grammatology(1967). Author of In Other Worlds: Essays Touraine, Alain (b. 1925) French theorist of social action
in Cultural Politics (1988), Outside in the Teaching and collective agency; influential in contemporary social
Machine (1993), and A Critique of Post-Colonial Reason movements research. Author of The Self-Production of
(1999). See further pp. 248. Society (1973), Post-Industrial Society (1974), and Critique
of Modernity (1992). See further pp. 282.
Strauss, Anselm (1916-96). US interactionist theorist,
methodologist of qualitative research and medical Toynbee, Arnold (1889-1975). British historian,
sociologist; developed a method of 'grounded theory'. speculative theorist of the rise and fall of civilizations.
Co-author of The Discovery of Grounded Theory Author of A Study of History (1934-61) (in 10 vols.).
(1967) with Barney Glaser. See further pp. 116.
Vico, Giambattista (1668-1744) Italian Enlightenment
philosopher of history; postulated that civilizations rise and
344 BIOGRAPHIES OF THEORISTS
This bibliography provides details for texts cited in author-date form in the main chapter discussions
of this book. It omits details for texts cited in the Further Reading sections at the end of each chapter.
Texts cited in author-date form are referenced by their first historical dates of publication in the
original languages in which they were written. However, all references to page numbers are to recent
translated and/or reprinted editions in English. Full details of the translated and/or reprinted editions
appear in the listing below. For example, references in Chapter 2 to 'Marx and Engels 1848: SO' refer
to page SO of the 1967 Penguin English edition of The Communist Manifesto, first published in German
in 1848.
- (ed.) (1969), The Positivist Dispute in German - (1998), Neo{unctionalism and After. Oxford:
Sociology, repr. London: Heinemann, 1976 Blackwell.
(originally in German). Althusser, L. (1965), For Marx, repr. London: Allen
-- (1970), Aesthetic Theory, repr. Minneapolis: Lane, 1969 (originally in French).
University of Minnesota Press, 1997 - (1970), Reading Capital, repr. London: Verso,
(originally in German). 1997 (originally in French).
- et al. (1950), The Authoritarian Personality. - (1971), 'Ideology and Ideological State
New York: Harper Row. Apparatuses', repr. in Essays on Ideology.
Ahmed, A. (1992), Postmodernism and Islam: London: Verso, 1984 (originally in French).
Predicament and Promise. London: Routledge. Anderson, B. (1983), Imagined Communities:
Ahmed, S. (1998), Differences that Matter: Feminist Reflections on the Origin and Spread of Nationalism.
Theory and Postmodern ism. cambridge: London: Verso.
Cambridge University Press. Anderson, P. (1974a), Passages from Antiquity to
- (2000), Strange Encounters: Embodied Others in Feudalism. London: Verso.
Post-Colonia/ity. London: Routledge. - (1974b), Lineages of the Absolutist State.
Alexander, J.C. (1982a), Theoretical Logic in London: Verso.
Sociology, i: Positivism, Presuppositions and Current -- (1976), Considerations on Western Marxism.
Controversies. Berkeley: University of California London: New Left Books.
Press.
- (1998), The Origins of Postmodernity.
- (1982b), Theoretical Logic in Sociology, ii: London: Verso.
The Antinomies of Classical Thought: Marx
Archer, M. (1982), 'Morphogenesis versus
and Durkheim. Berkeley: University of
Structuration: On Combining Structure and
California Press.
Action', British foumal of Sociology, 33/4: 456-83.
-- (1983), Theoretica/Logic in Sociology, iii: The
- (1988), Culture and Agency: The Place of
Classical Attempt at Theoretical Synthesis: Max
Weber. Berkeley: University of California Culture in Social Theory. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Press.
- (1995), Realist Social Theory: The Morphogenetic
- (1984), Theoretical Logic in Sociology, iv: The
Modern Reconstruction of Classical Thought: Talcott Approach. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
346 REFERENCES
-- (1997), Postmodernity and its Discontents. -- (1984), Force, Fate and Freedom: On Historical
New York: New York University Press. Sociology. Berkeley: University of California
-- (1998a), Work, Consumerism and the New Press.
Poor. Benjamin,]. (1988), Tize Bonds o(Love. New York:
Buckingham: Open University Press. Pantheon Books.
- (1998b), Globalization: The Human - (1995), Like Subjects, Love Objects. New
Consequences. Cambridge: Polity Haven: Yale University Press.
Press.
- (1998), The Shadow of the Other.
-- (1998c), 'On Glocalization: Or Globalization London: Routledge.
for Some, Localization for Others', Thesis Eleven,
54: 37-49. Benjamin, W. (1925-39), The Arcades Project, repr.
Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press,
- (2000), Liquid Modernity. Cambridge: 2000 (originally in German).
Polity Press.
- (1934), 'The Artist as Producer', repr. in
- (2002), Society under Siege. Cambridge: Collected Writings, vol. ii. Cambridge,
Polity Press. Mass.: Harvard University Press, 1999
Beauvoir, S. de (1949), The Second Sex, repr. (originally in German).
London: Penguin, 1983 (originally in French). - (1936), 'The Work of Art in the Age of
Beck, U. (1986), Risk Society:Towards a New Mechanical Reproduction', in id,
Modernity, repr. London: Sage, 1992 (originally in flluminations, repr. New York: Shoeken, 1969
German). (originally in German).
-- (1997), The Reinvention of Politics: Bentham, J. (1789), Introduction to the Principles of
Rethinking Modernity in the Global Social Morals and Legislation, repr. Oxford: Oxford
Order. Cambridge: Polity Press. University Press, 1996.
-- (1998), Democracy without Enemies. Berger, P., and Luckmann, T. (1966), The Social
Cambridge: Polity Press. Construction of Reality. London: Penguin.
- (2000a), The Brave New World of Work. Bernstein, R.J. (1991), The New Constellation: The
Cambridge: Polity Press. Ethical-Political Horizons of Modernity/
Postmodernity. Cambridge: Polity Press.
- (2000b), What is Globalization?
Cambridge: Polity Press. Best, S., and Kellner, D. (1991), Postmodern Theory:
Critical Interrogations. London: Macmillan.
-- Giddens, A., and Lash, S. (1994), Reflexive
Modernization: Politics, Tradition and Aesthetics in - (2001), The Postmodern Adventure: Science,
the Modern Social Order. Cambridge: Polity Press. Technology, and Cultural Studies at the Third
Millennium. London: Routledge.
Becker, H. (1967), 'Whose side are we on?', Social
Problems, 14: 239-47. Bhaskar, R. (1979), The Possibility of Naturalism.
Brighton: Harvester.
Beechey, V. (1988), 'Rethinking the Definition of
Work', inJ.Jenson, E. Hagen, and C. Reddy Billig, M. (1995), Banal Nationalism. London: Sage.
(eds.), Feminization of the Labour Force: Paradoxes Blackburn, R. (ed.) (1991), After the Fall: The Failure
and Promises. Cambridge: Polity Press. of Communism and the Future of Socialism.
Bell, D. (1962), The End of Ideology: On the London: Verso.
Exhaustion of Political Ideas in the Fifties. New Blau, P. (1964), Exchange and Power in Social Life.
York: Free Press. New York: Wiley.
- (1973), The Coming of Post-industrial Society: Bloch, E. (1952-9), The Principle of Hope, 3 vols.,
A Venture in Social Forecasting. New York: Basic repr. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1986
Books. (originally in German).
- (1980), Sociological Journeys: Essays 1960-1980. Bloor, D. (1976), Knowledge and Social Imagery.
London: Heinemann. London: Routledge.
Bendix, R. (1956), Work and Authority in Industry, Blumenberg, H. (1966), The Legitimacy of the
repr. Berkeley: University of California Press, Modem Age. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1983
1974. (originally in German).
- (1964), Nation-Building and Citizenship: Studies
of our Changing Social Order. New York: Wiley.
348 REFERENCES
-- and Wacquant, L. (1992), An Invitation to -- (1991), The Revenge of History: Marxism and
Reflexive Sociology. Cambridge: Polity the East European Revolutions. Oxford: Polity
Press (originally in French). Press.
- (2001), 'New Liberal Speak: Notes on the Canguilhem, G. (1977), Ideology and Rationality
New Planetary Vulgate', Radical Philosophy, in the History of the Life Sciences, repr.
105: 6-7 (originally in French). Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1988 (originally in
French).
Boyne, R. and Rattansi, A. (eds.) (1990),
Postmodernism and Society. London: Carby, H. (1982), 'White Woman Listen! Black
Macmillan. Feminism and the Boundaries of Sisterhood',
repr. in L. Back andJ. Solomos (eds.),
Braithwaite,]., and Drahos, P. (2000), Global Theories of Race and Racism, London:
Business Regulation. Cambridge: Cambridge Routledge, 2000.
University Press.
Carnoy, M. (1993), 'Multinationals in a Changing
Braudel, F. (1967), Capitalism and Material Life, World Economy', in M. Carnoy et al., The New
1400-1800, repr. London: Weidenfeld & Global Economy in the Information Age. University
Nicolson, 1973 (originally in French). Park, PA.: Pennsylvania University Press.
- and Castells, M. (2001), 'Globalization, the
Knowledge Society and the Network State',
Global Networks, 1/1: 1-18.
REFERENCES 349
- (1967), Studies /11 Ethnomethodology. Row. Gorz, A. (1999), Reclaiming Work: Beyond
Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall. the
Geertz, C. (1973), The Interpretation of Cultures. Wage-Based Society. Cambridge: Polity Press.
New York: Basic Books. Gouldner, A. W. (1965), Enter Plato: Classical Greece
Gellner, E. (1985), Relativism and the Social Sciences. and the Origins o(Social Theory. London:
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Routledge.
Gerhard, U. (2003), • "Illegitimate Daughters": The - (1970), The Coming Crisis of Western Sociology.
Relationship between Feminism and Sociology', London: Heinemann.
in B. Marshall and A. Witz (eds.), Engendering Gramsci, A. (1926-37), Selections from the
the Social: Feminist Encounters with Sociological Prison Notebooks, repr. London: Lawrence
Theory. Buckingham: Open University Press. & Wishart, 1971 (originally in Italian).
Geyer, M. H., and Paulmann,J. (2001), - (1985), 'Cultural Themes: Ideological Material',
'Introduction:The Mechanics of in Selellions from Cultural Writings. repr.
Internationalism', in M. H. Geyer and London: Lawrence & Wishart (originally in
J. Paulmann (eds.), The Mechanics of Italian).
Internationalism:Culture, Society, and Politics
from the 1840's to the First World War. Granovetter, M. (1985), 'Economic Action and
Oxford: Oxford University Press. Social Structure: The Problem of Embeddedness',
American foumal o(Sociology, 91/ 3: 418-501.
Giddens, A. (1976), New Rules of Sociological
Method: A Pmitive Critique of Interpretive Grosz, E. (1990), 'Inscriptions and Body-Maps:
Sociologies. London: Hutchinson. Representations and the Corporeal', repr. in
T Threadgold and A. Cranny-Francis (eds.),
-- (1979), Central Problems in Social Theory:
Feminine/Masculine/Representation.St Leonards:
Action, Structure and Contradiction in Allen & Unwin.
Social Analysis. London: Macmillan.
Habermas,J. (1962), The Structural
- (1981),A Contemporary Critique of Historical
Transformation of the Public Sphere, rcpr.
Materialism. London: Macmillan. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1989 (originally in
- (1982), Profiles and Critiques in Social Theory. German).
London: Macmillan. - (1963), Theory and Practice, repr.
- (1984), The Constitution o(Society: Oullineofthe Cambridge: Polity Press, 1988 (originally in
Theory ofSrructuration. Cambridge: Polity Press. German).
- (1985), The Nation-State and Violence. - (1967), Logic of the Social Sciences, repr.
Cambridge: Polity Press. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press, 1988 (originally in
German).
- (1990), The Consequences of Modernity.
Cambridge: Polity Press. - (1968), Knowledge and Human Interests, repr.
Boston: Beacon Press, 1971 (originally in German).
- (1991), Modernity and Self-Identity: Self
and Society in lhe Late Modern Age. Cambridge: - (1973), Legitimation Crisis, repr.
Polity Press. London: Heinemann, 1976 (originally in
German).
_ (1994), 'Living in a Post-Traditional Society',
in U. Beck, A. Giddens, and S. Lash, Reflexive - ( 1976), Communication and the Evolution of
Modernization: Politics, Tradition and Aesthetic in Society, repr. London: Heinemann, 1979
the Modern Social Order. Cambndge: Polity Press. (originally in German).
- (1998), The Third Way: The Renewal of Social - (1980), 'The Unfinished Project of
l)emoaacy. Cambridge: Polity Press. Modernity', repr. in M. Passerin d'Entreves (ed.),
Habermas and the Unfinished Projeeto(Modemity.
Glaser, B., and Strauss, A. (1967), The Discovery of
Cambridge: Polity Press.
Grounded Theory. New York: de Gruyter.
- (1981a),The Theory o(Communicative Action,
Goffman, E. (1956), The Presentation ofSelfin Everyday
i: Reason and the Rationalization of Society,
Life, repr. London: Penguin, 1971.
repr. Cambridge: Polity Press, 1984 (originally in
German).
- (1981 b), The Theory of Communicative Action,
ii: Lifeworld and System, repr. Cambridge: Polity
Press, 1987 (originally in German).
REFERENCES 353
Hamilton, R., and Barrett M. (1986), The Politics of Hayek, F. A. (1944), The Road to Serfdom, repr.
Diversity: Feminism, Marxism and Nationalism. London: Routledge, 1976.
London: Verso. Hebdige, D. (1979), Subculture: The MeaningofStyle.
Hannerz, U. (1992), Cultural Complexity: Studies London: Methuen.
in the Social Organization of Meaning. New York: -- (1989), 'New Times: After the Masses', in
Columbia University Press. S. Hall and M.Jacques, (eds.), New Times: The
Haraway, D. (1991a), '"Gender" for a Marxist Changing Face of Politics in the 1990s. London:
Dictionary: The Sexual Politics of a Word', in Lawrence & Wishart.
id., Simians, Cyborgs and Women:
The Reinvention of Nature. London:
Free Association Books.
354 REFERENCES
Leu pin, A. (1991), Lacan and the Human Sciences. - (1992), Observations on Modernity, repr.
Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press. Stanford: Stanford University Press, 1998
(originally in German).
Levi-Strauss, C. (1949), The Elementary Structures of
Kinship, repr. Boston: Beacon Press, 1969 Lukacs, G. (1910), Soul and Form, repr. London:
(originally in French). Merlin Press, 1974 (originally in Hungarian).
- (1950), Introduction to the Work of Marcel - (1915), The Theory of the Novel, repr.
Mauss, repr. London: Routledge, 1987 (originally London: Merlin Pres , 1971 (originally in
in French). German).
-- (1955), Tristes Tropiques, repr. London: - (1923), History and Class Consciousness:Studies
Jonathan Cape, 1973 (originally in French). in Marxist Dialectics, repr. London: Merlin Press,
1971 (originally in German).
- (1958), Structural Anthropology, repr. New York:
Basic Books, 1963 (originally in French). Lukes, S. (1985), Marxism and Morality. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
- (1964), The Raw and the Cooked: Introduction to
a Science of Mythology, repr. London:Jonathan Lury, C. (1996), Consumer Culture.
Cape, 1970 (originally in French). Cambridge: Polity Press.
- (1966), The Savage Mind. Chicago: - (2002), 'From Diversity to Heterogeneity:
Chicago University Press (originally in A Feminist Analysis of the Making of
French). Kinds', Economy and Society, 31/4: 588-
605.
Upset, S. M. (1960), Political Man: The Social Bases
of Politics, repr. Baltimore:Johns Hopldns Lyotard,J.-F. (1974), Libidinal Economy, repr.
University Press, 1981. Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1993
(originally in French).
- (1963), The First New Nation: The United
States in Comparative and Historical Perspective, - (1979), The Postmodern Condition: A Report
repr. on Knowledge, repr. Manchester: Manchester
London: Heinemann, 1964. University Press, 1986 (originally in French).
-- (1996), American Exceptionalism:A -- (1982), 'An Answer to the Question: What
Double Edged Sword. New York: Norton. is Postmodemism?', in id., The Postmodern
Condition: A Report on Knowledge, repr.
Lockwood, D. (1956), 'Some Remarks on "The Social
Manchester: Manchester University Press, 1986
System", British Journal of Sociology, 7: 134-46.
(originally in French).
- (1964), 'System Integration and Social
- (1986), The Postmodern Explained:
Integration', in G. Zollschan and W. Hirsch
Correspondence, 1982-1985, repr. Minneapolis:
(eds.), Explorations in Social Change. London:
University of Minnesota Press, 1993 (originally
Routledge.
in French).
- (1992), Solidarity and Schism:The Problem
- (1993), Political Writings. Minneapolis:
of Disorder in Marxist and Durkheimian
University of Minnesota Press.
Sociology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
REFERENCES 357
Mills, C. W. (1956), The Power Elite. Oxford: Oxford Oakley, A. (1974a), The Sociology of Housework.
University Press. London: Martin Robertson.
- (1959), The Sociological Imagination. Oxford: -- (1974b), Housewife. London: Allen Lane.
Oxford University Press. Offe, C. (1985), Disorganized Capitalism:
Mills, S. (1998), 'Post-colonial Feminist Theory', Contemporary Transformations of Work and
in S.Jackson andJ.Jones (eds.), Contemporary Politics. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press (originally
Feminist Theories. Edinburgh: Edinburgh in German).
University Press.
- (1996), Varieties a/Transition: The East
Mitchell,]. (1974), Psychoanalysis and Feminism. European and East German Experience.
London: Allen Unwin. Cambridge, Mass.: MIT Press (originally in
German).
Mohanty, C. T. (1988), 'Under Western Eyes:
Feminist Scholarship and Colonial Discourses', Ohmac, K. (1990), The Rorderless World. London:
FeministReview, 30: 61-89. Collins.
- (2002) ' "Under Western Eyes" - (1996), The End of the Nation State: The Rise
Revisited: Feminist Solidarity through of Regional Economies. London: HarperCollins.
Anticapitalist Struggles', Signs, 28/21: 499-
Outhwaite, W. (1987), New Philosophies a/Social
535.
Science: Realism, Hermeneutics and Critical Theory.
Moore, B. (1966), The Social Origins of Dictatorship London: Macmillan.
and Democracy: Lord and Peasant in the Making of
the Modem World, repr. London: Penguin, 1969. Pareto, V. (1916), The Mind and Society: A Treatise
on General Sociology, repr. New York: Dover,
- {1978), In;ustice: The Social Bases of 1963 (originally in Italian).
Obedience and Revolt. London:
Macmillan. Parsons, T. (1937), The Structure of Social Action:
A St11dy in Social Theory with Special Reference to
Mosca, G.(1896), The Ruling Class, repr. New a Group u(Recent European Writers. New York:
York: McGraw-Hill, 1939 (originally in Italian). McGraw-Hill.
Mouzelis, N. (1995), Sociological Theory: What Went
-- (1942a), 'Democracy and the Social Structure
Wrong? Diagnosis and Remedies. London: in Pre-Nazi Germany', Journal of Legal and
Routledge.
Political Sociology, 1:96-114.
Mulvey, L. (1989), Visual and Other Pleasures.
- (1942b), 'Some Sociological Aspects of the
London: Macmillan.
Fascist Movements', Social Forces, 21: 138-47.
Munch, R. (1987), Theory of Action:Toward a New
-- (1949a), 'The Professions and Social Structure',
Synthesis Going beyond Parsons. London: Routledge.
repr. in id., Essays in Sociological Theory: Pure and
Myrdal, A., and Klein, V. (1956), Women's Two Applied. New York: Free Press 1954.
Roles: Home and Work. London: Routledge.
,; t f-f 1H •,· 359
- (1949b), 'Age and Sex in the Social Structure Poster, M. (1975), Existential Marxism in Postwar
of the United States', repr. in id., Essays in France: From Sartre to Althusser. Princeton:
Sociological Theory: Pure and Applied. New York: Princeton University Press.
Free Press, 1954.
- (ed.) (1988), Jean Baudrillard: Selected Writings.
- (1949c), 'The Kinship System of the Stanford: Stanford University Press.
Contemporary United States', repr. in. id., Essays
- (1990), The Mode of Information:
in Sociological Theory: Pure and Applied. New
York: Free Press, 1954. Poststructuralism and Social Context. Cambridge:
Polity Press.
- (1949d), 'Social Classes and Class Conflict in
the Light of Recent Sociological Theory', repr. in. Pringle, R. (1988), Secretaries Talk: Sexuality, Power
id., Essays in Soriologica/ Theory: Pure and Applied. and Work. London: Verso.
New York: Free Press, 1954. Putnam, R. D. (2000), Bowling Alone: The Collapse
- (1951), The Social System. New York: Free and Revival of American Community. New York:
Press. Simon & Schuster.
-- (1956), 'The American Family', in id., Radcliffe-Brown, A. R. (1935), 'On the Concept of
R. F. Bales, et al. (eds.), Family, Socialization and Function in Social Science', American
Interaction Process. New York: Free Press. Anthropologist, 37: 39S-6.
-- (1964), 'Social Structure and the Development - (19S2), Structure and Function in Primitive
of Personality: Freud's Contribution to the Society: Essays and Addresses. London: Cohen &
Integration of Psychology and Sociology', in id., West.
Social Structure and Personality. New York: Free Press. Ragland-Sullivan, E., and Brivic, S. (eds.) (1991),
-- (1966), Societies: Evolutionary and Comparative Joyce between Genders: Lacanian Views. Tulsa,
Perspectives. Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall. Okla.: University of Tulsa Press.
- (1967), 'On the Concept of Political Power', Reekie, G. (1993), Temptations:Sex, Selling and the
in id., Sociological Theory and Modern Department Stare.St Leonards: Allen Unwin.
Society. New York: Free Press.
Rex,J. (1961), Key Problems of Sociological Theory.
- (1971a), The System of Modern Societies. London: Routledge.
Englewood Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Rich, A. (1983), 'Compulsory Heterosexuality and
-- (1971 b), 'Commentary', in H. Turk and Lesbian Existence', in A. Snitow, C. Stansell,
R. L. Simpson (eds.), Institutions and Exchange: and
The Sociologies of Talcott Parsons and George S. Thompson (eds.), Powers of Desire: The Politics
Caspar Homans. New York: Bobbs-Merrill. of Sexuality. New York: Monthly Review Press.
- (1977a), Soda/ Systems and the Evolution of
Ricreur, P. (1965), Freud and Philosophy, repr.
Action Theory. New York: Free Press.
New Haven: Yale University Press, 1970 (originally
- (1977b), 'Equality and Inequality in Modern in French).
Society, or Social Stratification Revisited', in
- (1969), The Conflict of Interpretations,
id., Social Systems and the Evolution of
repr. Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University
Action Theory. New York: Free Press.
Press, 1974 (originally in French).
Pateman, C. (1988), The Sexual
Contract. -- (1983-5) Time and Narrative, 3 vols.,
Cambridge: Polity Press. repr. Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
1984-8 (originally in French).
Polanyi, K. (1944), The Great Transformation, repr.
Boston: Beacon Press, 1957. Riesman, D. (1950), The Lonely Crowd. New Haven:
Yale University Press.
Pollert, A. (1981), Girls, Wives, Factory Lives.
London: Macmillan. Ritzer, G. (1993), The McDonaldization of Society:
Pollock, G. (1988), Vision and Difference: Femininity, An Investigation into the Changing Character of
Feminism and the Histories of Art. London: Contemporary Social Life. Newbury Park, Cal.:
Pine Forge Press.
Routledge.
Popper, K. (1935), The Logic of Scientific Discovery, Robertson, R. (1992), Globalization:Social Theory
repr. New York: Basic Books, 1959 (originally in and Global Culture. London: Sage.
German). - (1995), 'Glocalization, Time-Space and
Portes, A. (1998), 'Social Capital: Its Origins and Homogeneity-Homogeneity', in M.
Applications in Modern Sociology', Annual Featherstone, S. Lash, and R. Robertson (eds.),
ReviewofSociology, 24: 1-24. Global Modernities. London: Sage.
360 REFERENCES
-- (1996), 'Postmodern Social Theory', in Sydie, R. A. (1987), Natural Women, Cultured Men: A
B. S. Turner (ed.), The Blackwell Companion to Feminist Perspective on Sociological Theory. Milton
Keynes: Open University Press.
Social Theory. Oxford: Blackwell.
Taylor, C. (1989), Sources of the Self Cambridge:
-- (2001), 'Sociology, Morality and Ethics: On
Cambridge University Press.
Being with Others', in G. Ritzer and B. Smart
(eds.), Handbook of Social Theory. London: -- (1993), 'To Follow a Rule', in C. Calhoun,
Sage. E. LiPuma, and M. Postone (eds.), Bourdieu:
Critical Perspectives. Cambridge: Polity Press.
- (2003), Economy, Culture and Society: A
Sociological Critique ofNeo-liberalism. Therborn, G. (1976), Science, Class arid Society: Ori
Buckingham: Open University Press. the Formation of Sociology and Historical
Materialism. London: New Left Books.
Smelser, N. (1959), Social Change in the Industrial
Revolution: An Application of Theory to the - (1995), 'Routes to/through Modernity', in
Lancashire Cotton Industry, 1770-1840. London: M. Featherstone, 5. Lash, and R. Robertson (eds.),
Routledge. Global Modernities. London: Sage.
Smith, A. (1776), The Wealth of Nations, repr. -- (1999), 'Introduction:The Atlantic
London: Penguin, 1970. Diagonal in the Labyrinths of Modernities and
Globalizations', in G. Therborn and
Smith, A. D. (1983), 'Nationalism and Social L.-L. Wallenius (eds.), Globalizations and
Theory', British Journal of Sociology, 34: 19-38. Modernities: Experiences and Perspectives of Europe
Smith, D. E. (1987), The Everyday World as arid Latin America. Stockholm: Swedish Council
Problematic: A Feminist Sociology. Milton Keynes: for Planning and Co-ordination of Research.
Open University Press. Thomas, W. I., and Thomas, D.S. (1928), The Child
Smith-Rosenberg, C. (1975), 'The Female World in America: Behavior Problems and Programs. New
of Love and Ritual: Relations between Women York: Alfred A. Knopf.
in Nineteenth-Century America', Signs, 9: 1-29. Thompson, E. P. (1978), The Poverty of Theory, repr.
Spencer, H. (1882-98), The Principles of Sociology, 3 London: Merlin Press, 1995.
vols., repr. London: Macmillan, 1969. Thompson,]. B. (1981), Critical Hermeneutics: A Study
Spivak, G. (1988a), In Other Worlds: Essays in in the Thought of Paul Rica:ur and Jurgen Habermas.
Cultural Politics. London: Routledge. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
362 REFERENCES
Berger, P.
Marshall, T.H. 138-9 Weber and Simmel 82-4
biography 332
relation to nineteenth-century feminist readings 235-8
sociologist 121
liberalism 26 key movements of eighteenth
Bhaskar, R.
Schumpeter,J. 139-40 and nineteenth centuries
biography 332
socio-economic modernity community and society 30-1
hermeneutics 127
23-4 liberalism 25-7
realism 227-9
Tilly, C. 145-6 political economy 24-5, 43-7
Binary
Weber, M. 67-9 positivism 27-8
glossary 317
Castells, M. socialism 24
Levi-Strauss, C. 201
biography 333 theories of elites 28-30
Bloch,E.
globalization theorist 296-7 utilitarianism 24-5
biography 332
Castoriadis, C. Cohen,G.H.
Marxist theorist 158, 167
biography 333 biography 333
Bloor, D. 124
social agency 275-6 structural and analytical
Blumer,H.
Chicago School Marxism 186
biography 333
Blumer, H. 110, 115-16 Coleman,J.
interactionism 110
Garfinkel, H. 117-19 biography 333
symbolic interactionism 115-16
Goffman, E. 116-17 rational actor approach 104-5
Body
interactionism 110 Colonialism
'absent presence' 236-7
Meade, G.H. 110, 114-15 see also Imperialism
'habitus' 222-4
symbolic interaction ism 115-16 deconstruction 205
Bourdieu, P.
Chodorow, N. Fanon, F. 34
biography 333
biography 333 feminist social theory 247-9
Giddens compared 217
feminist psychoanalytic theorist Said, E. 34
problems of individualism
186-8 Commodity fetishism
227-9
Cicourel, A. 344 glossary 318
reflexive sociology
Citizenship arxist term 46-7
cultural capital 224-7
Bendix, R. 142 Common sense
'habitus' 222-4
globalization 300-1 reorientation of sociology of
overview 221-2
Marshall, T.H. 138-9 knowledge 121
Bureaucracy 74
Civil society role in social theory 6-7
Butler,J.
Durkheim, E. 53-4 Communication
biography 333
Gramsci, A. 157-59 see also Language
feminist theorist 243-5
Marx, K. 48-9 communicative rationality
Civilizing process 279-80
Bauman, Z. 36 glossary 318
C
Elias, N. 32, 141-4 Habermas,J. 279-80
Calvin,].
Freud, S. 176-8 internet 304
biography 333
glossary 318 Luhmann, N. 283-5
Protestant ethic 68-9
historical social theory 141-4 mass media 264-5
Capitalism
Class Communism
Anderson, P. 147-9
cultural studies 168-72 see also Marxism; Western
Castoriadis, C. 275-6
Dahrendorf, R. 100 Marxism
critique by Marx
Elias, N. 141 fall of Soviet communism 171-2
expansion and self
feminist readings 241, 246-7 The Communist Manifesto 41, 48
destruction 47-8
glossary 318 Community and society 30-1
feudalism 44-5
Gramsci, A. 157 Comparative historical
labour theory of value 46-7
Hayek, F. 140 sociology. see Historical
overview 43-4
Marcuse, H. 165-66 social theory
use and exchange values
distinguished 45-6 Marshall, T.H. 138-9 Comte,A.
globalization 300 Marxism 44-5, 165-68 biography 333
Hayek, F. 140 Wallerstein, I. 149 conclusions 37
Weber,M 72 foundations of positivism 27-8
Heller, A. 278
Classical theory founder of term 'sociology' 2
Jameson, F. 265-6
conclusions idea of unified science 4
Lyotard,J-F. 261-2
Marx and Durkheim 59-60 influence on Durkheim 52
HJDH 367
interpretivism distinguished
Bloch, E. 158 Descartes, R.
112
Gramsci, A. 157-9 biography 334
theory of social evolution 27-
8 Lukacs, G. 156-7 cultural modernity 20
Conflict studies in Britain and Determinism
Eisenstadt, S. 137 USA 168-72 glossary 319
Heller, A. 276-8 Western modernity 20-1 problems with structure and
Simmel, G. 79 'Culture industry' agency 227-9
Conflict theorists Adorno and Horkheimer 160-1 globalization 300
glossary 318 Dialectic
Dahrendorf, R. 100
dualist approach 105 Cybernetics Adorno and Horkheimer 162-4
Lockwood, D. 102 glossary 318 glossary 319
Mills, C.W. 100 self-regulating systems 284 Marx 42
objections to Differentiation
functionalism 100-1 Durkheim, E. 53-4
re-evaluation 101-2 D globalization 307-8
Rex,J. 100 Dahrendorf, R. glossary 319
Constructivism biography 334 Luhmann, N. 283-5
conflict theorist 100 Parsons, T 97-9
deconstruction 203-6
social constructionism 123-5 Darwin,C. Smelser, N. 136
social studies of science 123-5 biography 334 structural differentiation
cultural modernity 21, 28 Eisenstadt, S. 137
Consumer society 263-5
de Beauvoir, S. Parsons, T 97-9
Contingency 266-9
Control. see Social control biography 332 Smelser, N. 136
Cooley, C.H. sex-gender distinction 243 Dilthey, W.
biography 333 de Saussure, F. biography 334
Chicago School 115 biography 342 interpretive social theory 112
Critical theory structural linguistics 197-200 Discursive practices
contemporary strands 164-5 de Tocqueville, A. Butler,J. 243-5
glossary 318 foundations of liberalism 25- 7 democracy 281-3
sociology 134 dispositive approach,
Habermas,J. 283
Debord, G. 209-12
hermeneutics 127
Horkheimer, M. 160-1 biography 334 epistemes 207-8
consumerism and Foucault, M. 207-12
Western Marxism
existentialism 166-7 anti-capitalism 167 glossary 319
Frankfurt School 160-5 Deconstruction Habermas,J. 281-3
Marcuse, H. 165-66
Derrida, J. 204-6 'Disembedding'
structuralism 167-8 glossary 319 glossary 319
logocentrism 203-4 Polanyi, K., 297-8
Culture
meaning 204-6 'Disenchantment with the
Baudrillard, J. 263-4
Deleuze,G. world' 76, 83
Bourdieu, P. 224-7
biography 334 Uivision of labour
Frankfurt School
technologytheorist 191-3 Durkheim, E. 53-4
Adorno, T. 162-4
Democracy glossary 319
Benjamin, W. 162
cosmopolitanism 297 Marxism 45-7
'culture industry' 160-1
Habermas,J. 281-3 Domination
Habermas,J. 164-5
Hayek, F. 140 feminist social theory 235,
Horkheimer, M. 162-4
Upset, S. 138 246-7
Freud, S. 178
political modernity 22 Gramsci, A. 157-9
functionalism 95-7
Schumpeter,J. 139-40 Weber, M. 72-5
globalization 304-5
Derrida,J. Douglas,M.
imperialism 306
biography 334 biography 334
Jameson, F. 266
deconstruction 204-6 anthropological approaches to
mass media 264-5
introduction of influential knowledge 122
overlap with social
concepts 202-3 Dualism
science 11
logocentrism 203-4 glossary 319
Simmel, G. 81-2
postmodernism 253-4 feminist readings 235
Western Marxism
368 INDEX
Durkheim, E.
Education Evans-Pritchard, E.E.
anomie 54-5
Bourdieu, P. 226 biography 334
approach to knowledge 122
Lipset,S. 138 anthropologist 126
biography 334
secularization 57-8 Evolution
conclusions 59-60
Eisenstadt, S. Darwin, C. 21, 28
difference of psychology
biography 334 social evolution
and social theory 10
comparative historical Comte,A. 27-8
feminist readings 236
sociologist 136-7 Durkheim, E. 10
globalization 294
Elias, N. religion 11-12
historical understanding 134
biography 334 Spencer, H. 28, 37, 53
ideas from Spencer 28
conflict and sociology 141-4, 222 Exchange value 45-6
interpretivism distinguished 111
Elites Existentialism
methodology 51-3
key movement of nineteenth glossary 320
moral individualism 56-7
century 28-30 Sartre,J-P. 166-7
origins of functionalism 88
Lipset,S. 138 Exploitation
reaction to Marxism 101
Mills,C.W. 100 extraction of value 46-7
religion 58-9
Emancipation glossary 320
secular education 57-8
critical theory 160-4
sexuality 245
glossary 319
solidarity and differentiation
Habermas,J. 164-5
53-4
Marx 48-9 Family
suicide 52
Empiricism feminist perspectives 235
Weber's approach to religion
glossary 320 nuclear families 99
distinguished 71
observational doctrine 112 socioeconomic modernity 19
Enlightenment Fanon,F.
critical theory biography 335
E
Adorn, T. 162-4 racism and imperialism 34,
Economic theory
Bloch, E. 158, 167 167
see also Globalization;
Industrialization; Habermas,J. 164-5 Fashion 78
Horkheimer, M. 160-1 Feminist social theory
Urbanization
agriculture eighteenth-century Europe 17 classical influences
feminist values 234, 250 contemporary theories 236-7
agrarian power 145
Foucault, M. 253 Durkheim, E. 236
community and society 30-1
community and society 30-1 glossary 320 Marxism 238-9
determinism Kant,!. 22 scope 234-5
problems in structure and Epistemes Simmel, G. 236
agency 227-9 glossary 320 socialization 236-7
globalization 300 knowledge 207-8 Weber, M. 235
Hirschmann, A. 26 Equality 28-30 conclusions 249-50
Marx critique of capitalism Ethics. see Morality criticisms of functionalism 103,
expansion and self Ethnocentrism 107
destruction 47-8 glossary 320 gender exclusion 246-7
feudalism 44-5 habits of thought 33 modernity 239-43
labour theory of value 46-7 Ethnomethodology postcolonial theory 247-9
overview 43-4 Garfinkel, H. 117-19 psychoanalysis
use and exchange values glossary 320 Benjamin,]. 188-9
distinguished 45-6 Eurocentrism Chodorow, N. 186-8
modernity 23-4 cultural thinking 32-3 importance 185-6
Polanyi, K. 26 glossary 320 Kristeva,J. 189-91
political economy 24-5, 43-7 Europe scope 233-4
Ricardo, D. 42 historical social theory sex-gender distinction 243-5
solidarity and differentiation Anderson, P. 147-9 sexual orientation 245-6
53-4 Mann,M. 148 Feudalism
Smith, A 24-5, 42, 134 nation-states weakened by Anderson, P. 147-9
Weber, M. 70-1 globalization 299 glossary 320
world systems theory 149-50 Marx critique of capitalism 44-5
INDEX 369
Feuerbach, L.
Functionalism exclusionary effects 246-7
biography 335
Alexander,). 106-7 feminist social theory
philosopher 42-3
conclusions 107-8 modernity 239-43
Feyerabend, P.
Eisenstadt, S. 137 sex-genderdistinction 243-5
biography 334
globalization 307-8 glossary 321
rise of social
glossary 320 Kristeva,J. 189-91
constructionism 123
influence on historical social sexual orientation 245-6
Forms. see under Sociology
theorists 135-6 Giddens,A.
Foucault, M.
influence on structuration agency 217-20
biography 335
theory 218 biography 336
'archaeological' approach
Merton, R. 90-2 Bourdieu compared 217
207-8
nuclear families 99 problems with determinism and
discipline 210
objections and alternatives individualism 227-9
discursive practices 201-12
conflicttheory 100-1 reflexivity and
'genealogical' approach 209-12
:'v!arxism 101-3 individualization 287-9
importance 206-7
neo-functionalism 105-7 structuration theory 217-20
knowledge 207-8
rational actor approaches structure 217
postmodern theorist 253-4
104-5 'Third Way' politics 217
power 210-11
origins in anthropology 88-90 time-space 'distanciation'
rise of constructivism 124
overview 87-8 296-7
Frankfurt School
Parsons, T view of functionalism 106
Adorno, T. 162-4
social integration 95-7 Globalization
Benjamin, W. 162
structural differentiation conclusions 310-11
'culture industrialization' 160-1
97-9 culture 304-5
glossary 320
systems of action 93-5 differentiation 307-8
Habermas,J. 164-5
unified general theory 92 'disembedding' 297-8
Horkheimer, M. 162-4
'voluntaristic theory of economic determinism 300
overview 160- I action' economic theory 301-2
psychoanalytic social theory 93 free markets 296
180-1 psychoanalytic social theory governance 298
Weber's influence 75 180-1 historical perspective 308-10
Fraser, N. Fundamentalism integration 307
biography 335 postmodern discontents 269 international law 300-1
Habermas and the public sphere renewed support 313 Marx critique of capitalism
242
47-8
Free markets
meaning and scope 292-4
globalization 296 G lime-space compression 296-7
Hayek, F. 140-1 Gadamer, H-G. transnationalism 294-6
Freud,S. biography 335 universalism and particularism
analysis of identity and self 176 hermeneutics 125-7 305-7
biography 335 Galbraith,J.K. weakened nation-states 298-9
civilization 176-8 biography 335 world systems theory 149-50
importance 175-6 free markets 140-1 'Glocalization'
links with Weber and Simmel Garfinkel, H. glossary 321
82-4 biography 335 Robertson, R. 304-5
Oedipus complex 176-8 ethnomethodology 117-19 Goffman, E.
problems of generalization 179 interactionism 110 biography 336
repression 176-8 Geertz, C. interactionism 110
Friedan, B. anthropologicalapproaches to 'presentation of self' 116-17
biography 335 knowledge 122 Gouldner, A.
criticisms of Parsons 103 biography 335 biography 336
gender and exclusion 247 Gemeinschaft and Gesellschaft Marxist objections 102
Fromm,E. 30-1 Governance
biography 334 Gender glossary 321
Frankfurt School 160 see also Sexuality social regulation,
psychoanalysis 180 Benjamin,). 188-9 298
Chodorow, N. 186-8
370 INDEX
Language (cont.)
Luther,M. distinguished 45-6
Lacan,J 183
biography 339 critique of idealism 41-3
Levi-Strauss, C. 201
Protestant ethic 68 critique of political liberalism
structuralism 197-200
Lyotard,J-F. emancipation 48-9
Winch, P. 125-7
biography 339 property and revolution
Wittgenstein, L. 125
capitalism 261-2 49-50
Lash, S. 260-2
general themes 256-8 Durkheim distinguished 56-8
Latour, B.
knowledge feminist readings 238-9
biography 338
scientific 260-1 globalization 294
rise of social constructionism
status 260 historical understanding 134
124
Marxism 167 influence on sociology of
Law
postmodernism 253-4 knowledge 120
globalization 300-2
psychoanalytic social theory interpretivism distinguished
Habermas,J. 281-3
192-3 111
political modernity 22
rise of constructivism 124-5 labourtheoryofvalue 46-7
Weber, M. 72-5
objections to functionalism
Legitimacy
101-3
glossary 323
M overlap of history and social
Lyotard,J-F. 260-2
Machiavelli, N. theory 11
Weber, M. 72-5
biography 339 psychoanalytic social theory
Levi-Strauss, C.
political philosopher, 180-1
biography 338
McClintock, A. 248-9 theory of social elites
influence of Durkheim 59
McDonaldization 299 29 Mass media 264-5
structuralism 200-2
Malinowski, B. Materialism 42
Liberalism
biography 339 Mead,G.H.
critique by Marx
functionalism in biography 340
emancipation 48-9
anthropology 88 American pragmatism 114-15
property and revolution
Mann,M. interactionism 110
49-50
biography 339 Media 264-5
neo-liberalism 150, 217, 262,
anthropologist 148 Merleau-Ponty, M.
288
Mannheim, K. biography 340
nineteenth-century movement
biography 339 critique of ideology 156
25-7
sociologyofknowledge 120-1 Merton, R.
Lifeworld
Marcuse,H. biography 340
glossary 323
Habermas,J. 281 biography 339 differentiation 307
Husserl, E. 113 Marxist theorist 166, 180-1 'middle-range' theories 90-2
Upset, S. Markets 102,310
biography 338 globalization 296 Methodology
sociologist 138 Hayek, F. 140-1 Durkheim, E. 51-3
Lockwood, D. Marshall, T.H. ethnomethodology 117-19
biography 339 biography 340 research 4-5
social and system integration social policy 138-9 Weber, M. 64-6
102 Marxism Michels,R.
Logocentrism see also Western Marxism biography 340
glossary 323 'alienation' 47 elites 28-30
Husserl, E. 203-4 biography 340 'Middle-range' theories
Luckmann, T. Castoriadis, C. 275-6 glossary 323
biography 339 comparisons with Freud 176 Merton, R. 90-2, 102, 310
sociologist 121 conclusions 59-60 Mitchell,J.
Luhmann,N. conflict theory 100 psychoanalysis and feminism
biography 339 critique of capitalism 185
social systems 283-5 expansion and self Mill,J.S.
Lukacs,G. destruction 47-8 biography 340
biography 339 feudalism 44-5 foundations of liberalism,
Marxist theorist 156-7 overview 43-4 25-7
use and exchange values rejection by Durkheim 53
INDEX 373
Mills,C.W.
Durkheim, E. 58-9 Freud, S. 176-8
biography 340
Marxism 171-2 Guattari, F. 192
conflict theorist 100
Mosca, G. Levi-Strauss, C. 202
Mitchell,].
biography 340 postmodernism 192
biography 340
elites 28-30 Orientalism
socialist feminist 185
Multiple modernities 33 glossary 325
Modernism
Said, E. 34
culture 17-20, 253-9, 274-5
glossary 323
N
Modernity p
Nation-states
see also Post modernism
historical social theory Paradigms
agrarian power 145
Bendix, R. 142 glossary 325
community and society 30-1
Moore, B. 145 scientific assumptions 123
conclusions 36-7, 289
Skocpol, T. 146-7 Pareto, V.
cultural modernity 20-1, 28
Tilly, C. 145-6 biography 341
'disenchantment with the
Marx critique of political elites 28-30
world' 76, 83
liberalism 42 Parsons, T
Enlightenment
Middle East 269 biography 341
eighteenth-century Europe
political modernity 21-2 differentiation 307
17
secular education 57-8 feminist criticisms 103
feminist values 234, 250
weakened by globalization Giddens compared 218
Foucault, M. 253
298-9 ideas from Spencer 28
Kant, I. 22
Negri,A. influence on historical social
Eurocentrism 32-3
biography 340 theorists 135-6
feminist social theory 239-43
Marxist theorist 167 Merton compared 90-2
Foucault, M. 208
Neo-functionalism 105-7 modernity and traditionalism
Habermas,J.
Neo-Kantism distinguished 18-19
communicative action
glossary 324 reformulation of ideas by
279-80
Rickert and Windleband 112 Garfinkel 117-18
critical theory 283 relation to Luhmann 284
Neo-liberalism
Heller, A. 278
economic policy 150,217,262, social integration 95-7
Luhmann, N. 283-5 stratification 18-19
288
meaning 17 structural differentiation 97-9
glossary 324
metropolis 82 systems of action 93-5
Networks 297-8
modernism 17-20, 253-9, unified general theory 92
Nietzsche, F.
274-5 'voluntaristic theory of action'
biography 341
multiple modernities 33 93
links with Weber and Simmel
origins 17-18 Particularism
82-4
political modernity 21-2 cultural beliefs 305-7
origins of postmodernism
rationalization 75-6 glossary 325
254-5
Simmel, G. 80-2 Parties 72
Norms
socio-economic modernity Patriarchy
Durkheim, E. 54-5
23-4 feminist readings 235
glossary 324
Touraine, A. 282 glossary 325
normative attitudes 7-9, 324
traditionalism distinguished Phallogocentrism
Parsons, T. 95-7
18-20 feminist readings 249
Western science 20-1 glossary 325
Money Phenomenology
0
gender 242 glossary 325
Objectivity
globalization 292 Husserl, E. 3 112-14
glossary 324
Marxism 46-7 Philosophy
approach to social enquiry 7-
Simmel, G.,80-1 American pragmatism 114-15
9 'Occidental rationalism' 75-6
wealth creation 263 empiricism 112
Oedipus complex
Moore, B. 340 existentialism 166-7
Benjamin,]. 188-9
Morality Greeks 10
Chodorow, N. 186-8
Bauman, Z. 266-9 idealism 65-6, 93
Deleuze, G. 191-2
374 INDEX
Philosophy (cont.)
Post-industrial society Practice
influence on Marx 42-3
Bell, D. 257-8 'praxis' 159
interpretivism distinguished
glossary 326 relation to theory 6-7, 315
112
Postmodernism Pragmatism
language 125
1980's 256-8 content and validity of
logocentrism 203-4
ambiguity of terms 258- concepts 114-15
metaphysics 202-6
9 Baudrillard,J. 253, 263- glossary 326
Nietzsche, N. 82-4, 254
5 Praxis philosophy 159
positivism 27-8
Bauman, Z. 266-9 'Presentation of self' 116-17
relation to social science 11
Castoriadis, C. 275-6 Private property 49-50
sociology of knowledge 119
conclusions 270,289 Protestant ethic
theory and practice 11-12,
evaluation and points of consumerism 266-9
314-5
criticism 274-5 Weber, M. 67-9
Polanyi, K.
glossary 326 Psychoanalytic social theory
biography 341
Habcrmas, J. conclusions 193-4
economic historian 26
communicative action Deleuze, G. 191-3
Political theory
279-80 feminist readings
agrarian power 145
defence of enlightenment Benjamin,]. 188-9
Arendt, H. 3, 9-10, 36
project 259,283 Chodorow, N. 186-8
Aristotle 10
Jameson, F. 265-6 importance 185-6
critique by Marx 48-50
Luhmann, N. 283-5 Kristeva,J. 189-91
globalization 300-1
Lyotard,J-F. Freud, S.
Habermas,). 281-3
capitalism 261-2 analysis of identity and self 176
liberalism 25-7
general themes 256-8 civilization 176-8
Upset, S. 138
knowledge 260 problems of generalization 179
Mill,J. 25-7
science 260-1 importance 175-6
modernity 21-2
origins 254-5 Lacan,J.
political sociology
poststructuralism compared problems with his approach
Elias, N. 141-4
254 183
Lipset,S. 138
psychoanalytic social theory structuralism 181-3
Tocqueville, de 134
191-3 Marxism and functionalism
Rawls,J. 281
scope 252-3 180-1
relation to social
theorists identified 253 Zizek, s. 184-5
science, 9-10
Poststructuralism Psychology
Weber,M.
conclusions 212-13 Durkheim's rejection 51
dominant social groups 72
Derrida,]. relation to social theory 10
domination and legitimacy
deconstruction 204-6 Public sphere
72-5
introduction of influential Fraser, N. 242
leadership 75-6
concepts 202-3 glossary 326
overview 71
logocentrism 203-4 Habermas,J. 164-5, 281-3
leadership 75-6
glossary 326
Popper, K.
postmodernism compared,
biography 341
254 Q
science philosopher 123
relation to structuralism 200-2, Queer theory
Positivism
212-13 glossary 326
Comte,A. 27-8
scope and meaning 196-7 sexuality 245-6, 326
empiricism 112
Power
glossary 325
Elias, N. 141-4
logical positivism 203-4 R
Foucault, M. 210-11
positive science 112, 325 Radcliffe-Brown, A.
functionalism 95-7
Postcolonialism biography 341
Mann,M. 148
deconstruction 205 functionalism in anthropology
Mills,C.W. 100
Fanon, F. 34, 166 88
Parsons, T. 95-7
feminist social theory 247-9 Rational choice theory
Weber,M.
glossary 325 actors and choice 104-5
domination and legitimacy
Said, E. 34 glossary 326
72-5
socia I groups 72
fNDEX 375
Rationalism
world religions and socio biography 342
actors and choice 104-5
economic change 70-1 speech-act theory 125
glossary 326
Representation Science
'occidental rationalism' 75-6
collective representations 59 Lyotard,J-F. 260
role in Western modernity 33-6
representative government 22 relationship to social theory
Weber, M. 75-6
Repression 3-4
Rationalization
Chodorow, N. 186-8 rise of constructivism 123-5
glossary 326
Freud, S. 176-8 Western modernity 20-1
postmodernism 254-5
Research Secularization
Weber, M. 75-6
methodology 4-5 education 57-8
Rawls,].
objectivity 8 glossary 327
biography 341
Revolution Protestant ethic and capitalism
political philosopher 281
1989 278 266-9
Realism
fall of Soviet communism, 171- Weber,M. 75
Archer, M. 227-9
2 historical social theory 146-7 Western modernity 21
Baudrillard's denial of the real
Marx, K. 49-50 Self
264-5
postmodemism 278 deconstruction 205
Bhaskar, R. 227 -9
Rex,J. Elias, N. 141-4
international relations 227-8,
biography 341 'presentation of self' 116-17
295
conflict theory 100 psychoanalytic social theory
glossary 326
Ricardo,D. 176-8
hermeneutics 127
biography 341 Semiotics
Reason
economist 42 glossary 327
challenges to Western Kristeva,J. 189-91
Riesman,D.
modernity 33-6
biography 342 meaning and scope 198-200
communicative rationality
sociologist 119 Sex-gender distinction
279-81
Risk societies feminist readings 243-5
ethnomethodology 117-19
Beck, U. 286-7 glossary 327
instrumental rationality 166
Luhmann, N. 285 Sexuality
political modernity 22 see also Gender
Ritzer, G.
Weber, M. 7S-6
biography 342 feminist social theory 236-7
Reflexivity
McDonaldization 299 Foucault, M. 211-12
Beck, U. 286-7
Robertson, R. glossary 327
Bourdieu, P. 221-7
biography 342 Oedipus complex
Giddens,A. 287-9 Freud, S. 176-8
globalization 304-5
glossary 327 Levi-Strauss, C. 202
Rule of law 281-3
'habitus' 222-4 postmodernism 192
meaning and scope 286 qucertheory, 245-6,326
overview 221-2
Regulation 298, 303-4
s repression
Said,E. Chodorow, N. 186-8
Relativism
biography 342 Freud, S. 176-8
glossary 327
cultural theorist 34 Simmel,G.
sociologyofknowledge 120
Sartre,J-P. ambivalence 79-80
Religion
biography 342 biography 343
cultural modernity 20-1
existentialism 166-7 feminist readings 236
Durkheim, E. 58-9
Saussure, de, F. interaction and exchange 77
fundamentalism 269 interpretivism distinguished
biography 342
Marx, K. 42
structural linguistics 197-200 111
relation of theology to social
Schumpeter, J. metropolis 82
theory 11-12 modernity 80-2
biography 342
secularisation 21, 57-8,
economist 139-40 money 76,80-1
75 origins of postmodern ism 255
Schutz,A.
totemism 58, 200 sociability 78-9
biography 342
Weber,M. Simulacra
impact 121
Protestant ethic and Baudrillard,J. 264-5
interpretivism 112-14
capitalism 67-9 Jameson, F. 266
Searle,}.
376 INDEX
Skocpol, T.
glossary 328 elites
biography 343
Parsons, T 97 key movement of
revolutions 146-7
Sovereignty nineteenth century 28-30
Smelser,N.
globalization 300-1 Upset, S. 138
biography 343
Hobbes, T. 94 Mills, C.W. 100
functionalist 135-6
nation states 22 gender 246-7
Smith,A.
Speech-act theory status
biography 343
glossary 328 Bourdieu, T. 222-4
historical thinker 134
hermeneutics 125 groups 72 328
influence on Marx 42
Spencer,H. Parsons, T. 72
political economy 24-5
biography 343 Weber, M. 72
Sociability 78-9
conclusions 37 Strauss, A.
Social control
development of positivism 28 biography 343
Foucault, M. 210
rejection by Durkheim 53 Chicago School 116
Parsons, T. 95- 7
Spivak,G. Structuralism
Social constructionism
biography 343 see also Poststructuralism
deconstruction 203-6
gender and postcolonial theory Althusser, L. 167-8, 184-5
glossary 328
248 Foucault, M.
social studies of science 123-5
State 'archaeological' approach
Social order 93-5
see also Nation-states 207-8
Social theory
Comte,A. 27-8 'genealogical' approach
interpretation of facts 7-
Durkheim, E. 55 209-12
9 meaning 1-3
Marx critique of political importance 206-7
methodology of research 4-5
liberalism 48-50 glossary 328
overlapping domains
Middle East 269 Lacan,J.
humanities 11-12
political modernity 22 problems with his approach
political theory 9-10
Soviet communism 171 183
psychology 10
Weber, M. 72-5 psychoanalysis 181-3
relationship to science 3-4
role of common sense 6-7 Status Levi-Strauss, C. 200-2
Socialism Bourdieu, T. 222-4 meaning and scope 196-7
glossary 328 Saussure, F. de 197-200
see also Marxism
fall of Soviet communism 171-2 groups 72, 328 semiotics 198
Parsons, T. 72 Western Marxism 167-8
Hayek, F. 140
Weber,M. 72 Structuration theory
Schumpeter,J. 139-40
'Third Way' politics 217 Strangers Giddens,A. 217-20
Simmel, G. 78 glossary 328
Western Marxism
Bloch, E. 158 Weber,M. 71 Structure
Korsch, K. 157 Stratification Archer, M. 227-9
Lukacs, G. 156 class Bhaskar, R. 227-9
Sociology cultural studies 168-72 Bourdieu, P.
Comte,A. 2 Dahrendorf, R. 100 Giddens compared 217
knowledge Elias, N. 141 reflexive sociology,
Mannheim, K. 120-1 feminist readings 241, 246-7 221-7
overview 119 glossary 318 conclusions 212-13, 230-1
reorientation towards Gramsci, A. 159 dual reality with agency,
common sense 121 Hayek, F. 140 216-17
Simmel's theory of forms Marcuse, H. 166 Giddens, A. 217-20
interaction and exchange 77 Marshall, T.H. 138-9 glossary 328
overview 76-7 Marxism 44-5, 166-7 meaning and scope 215-16
sociability 78-9 Wallerstein, I. 149 Parsons, T. 96
'social theory' and Weber,M 72 problems with determinism
'sociological theory', xx cultural capital 224-7 and individualism,
Solidarity education 228-30
Durkheim's theory 53-4 Bourdieu, P. 226 Symbolic interactionism,
functionalism 89 Upset, S. 138 115-16
secularization 57-8 see also lnteractionism
INDEX 377
Systems
Transnationalism globalization 294
Giddens, A. 218-20
glossary 330 'habitus' 222
Habermas,J. 281
well-regulated relationships influence as reaction
Parsons, T. 93-5
294-6 to Marxism 101
Lockwood, D. 102
Trust 56-7 influence on conflict theory
Luhmann, N. 283-5
100
Systems theory
historical understanding 134
glossary 328
u ideal types 65-6
Luhmann, N. 283-5
Understanding importance to social theory 67-8
interpretivism 111-12, 128 interpretivism distinguished
Weber,M. 65 111-12
T
Universalism links with Nietzsche and Freud
Taylor,C.
Enlightenment claims 305-7 82-4
biography 343
glossary 330 modernity and traditionalism
rational actor approach 105
Urbanization distinguished 19
Technology
Chicago School 112 origins ofpostmodernism 255
Heller, A. 278
Simmel, G. 82 overview 64-5
information society 262
socio-economic modernity political theory
internet 304
23-4 dominant social groups 72
technocracy 35
time-space compression 296-7 domination and legitimacy
time-space compression
Utilitarianism 72-5
296-7
glossary 330 overview 71
Terrorism 73,269,314
nineteenth-century movement rationalization 75-6
Theology 11-12 24-5 religion
Theory rejection by Durkheim 52-3 Protestant ethic and
conclusions 315
capitalism 67-9
meaning 1-3
world religions and
relation to practice 6-7
V socio-economic
'Third Way' politics 217
Values change 70-1
Thomas, W.I. interpretation of facts 7-9 Simmel distinguished 79
biography 343 Marx critique of capitalism status of the West 32-3
Chicago School 115 labour theory of value 46-7 support from Winch 125-6
Thompson, E.P. use and exchange values values 65-6
biography 343 verstehen 65
distinguished 45-6
cultural studies in Britain and use value 45-6 Western Marxism
USA 168-9 Althusser, L., 167-8, 184-5
Weber, M. 65-6
Tilly, C. 'Verstehen' Bloch, E. 158
biography 343 collapse of Soviet communism
glossary 330
nation-states 145-6 171
interpretivism 111-12
Tocqueville, de, A. Weber,M. 65 conclusions 172
foundations of liberalism 25-7 critical theory
Vico,G.
sociology 134 biography 343 existentialism 166-7
Tonnies, F. Enlightenment philosopher 6 Frankfurt School 160-5
biography 343 Marcuse, H. 166
community and society 30-1, structuralism 167-8
37
w in France 166-7
Totalitarianism 36 Wallerstein, I. glossary 330
Totcmism biography 344 Gramsci, A. 158-60
Durkheim, E. 58 globalization 294 influence on cultural studies
glossary 329 world systems theory 149-50 in Britain and USA
Levi-Strauss, C. 200 Weber,M. 168-72
Touraine, A. biography 344 in Italy 166-7
biography 343 bureaucracy 74 Korsch, K. 157
social action and collective capitalism 67-9 Lukacs, G. 156-7
agency 282 differentiation 307 overview 154-5
Traditionalism 18-20 feminist critics 235 scope and meaning 155
378 INDEX
Williams, R.
distinguished, 125-7
biography 344 z
Wittgenstein, I.
cultural studies in Britain and Zizek,S.
biography 344
USA 168-9
language and hermeneutics 125 biography 344
Winch,P.
World systems theory psychoanalytic social theory
biography 344 184-5
glossary 330
social and natural sciences relation to Lacan 182
Wallerstein, I. 149-50
OXFORD
UNIVERSITY PRESS
www.oup.com
rrr
9 78 01 99
Tn 25 5702