Kierkegaard, Post-Modernism, and The Church of The Post-Modern Epoch by Logun Moe
Kierkegaard, Post-Modernism, and The Church of The Post-Modern Epoch by Logun Moe
Kierkegaard, Post-Modernism, and The Church of The Post-Modern Epoch by Logun Moe
by
Logun Moe
May 3, 2022
0
Introduction
Soren Kierkegaard was a 19th century religious thinker who has had a deep influence on
post-modern thought. He is widely considered one of the first existentialists, and even praised as
the father of existentialism by many, and has been given a seat at the table of contemporary
philosophers, political theorists, and religious thinkers alike. Kierkegaard’s religious and
philosophical thought has deeply seeded itself in the post-modern world through his brilliant and
inquisitive writings that questioned power structures, objectivity, the self, and even the very
conclusions he, himself, propounded. This essay will make the obvious claim that Kierkegaard
has influenced postmodernity, and will attempt to prove this by showing just some of the many
ways in which he has become a voice for post-modern thought. Further, given the ecclesiological
and historiological purposes of this essay, it will also be shown that Kierkegaard acts as a sort of
‘post-modern-prophet’ showing the contemporary church it’s need for a dedicated pursuit of
truth in the midst of a church culture that all too often rests in the status quo of regurgitated
thought, which are predominately used by scholars in post-modern scholarship, and which
subsequently fit well within the generally accepted subset of postmodern categories. These
elements are Kierkegaard’s use of subjectivity, his deconstructionism, and his anti-
institutionalism. Kierkegaard’s use and understanding of these methods will be explored, as well
Kierkegaard’s influence on post-modernity will further be shown by starting out with a portrayal
of the life and time of Kierkegaard in such a way, so as to draw, the obvious connection between
1
his works and culture, and his influence on the post-modern epoch, while also giving a brief and
genuine look Kierkegaard as a man (this exploration of the life, time, and works of Kierkegaard
will also serve to show, however subtly, that the aforementioned tenets of post-modernism were
at play in his life). It is in a similar fashion that this essay will end, tying together all the
and the need for Kierkegaardian voices in the contemporary church today in order to spur on a
genuine faith in the elect of Christ as they — as Kierkegaard would say — “become Christian.”
Soren Kierkegaard was born 5 May 1813 in Copenhagen, Denmark, and died 11
November 1855, in the same city of his birth.1 In birth, death, and life Kierkegaard remained
close to home. It seems that he reserved his adventures for the inward exploration of faith and
intellect, rather than of the world and it’s pursuits. He opted, instead, to live a rather domestic
life, travelling less than six times, and going only to Sweden and Germany – quite likely for
some type of intellectual affair.2 Kierkegaard spent much of his time (when not involved in
intellectual endeavors or writing) walking through the streets of Copenhagen, or taking leisurely
carriage rides through the nearby country-side. In fact Kierkegaard’s wanderings through the
streets of Copenhagen, has to some, been interpretated as a selfish necessity, since the extreme
intellectual needed a variety of other minds to interact with in order to produce his many works
which touch on the human experience. But Kierkegaard clearly had a motive for expressing a
common nature with the fellow man. As an upperclassman and Christian, Kierkegaard seems to
1
Lissa McCullough, “Kierkegaard, Søren,” The Routledge Encyclopedia of Postmodernism, ed. Victor E.
Taylor and Charles E. Winquist (London: Routledge, 2001), 1
2
McDonald, William, "Søren Kierkegaard", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter 2017
Edition), Edward N. Zalta (ed.), URL = <https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2017/entries/kierkegaard/>., 1
2
have felt a desire to connect with humanity from all walks of life, as an outward expression of
Kierkegaard’s quiet life was, however, not due to only a quiet humility, or desire for
peace, or religion, necessarily, but also, it seems to come from a deep inwardness that pervaded
his life from an early age until his death.3 This inwardness required his earnest attention and
meditation. It seems have deeply guided him and infected his writings and life. Eventually this
inwardness would become one of the guide-posts for post-modern Kierkegaardian scholars.
It was this type of inwardness that lead to Kierkegaard’s fame, as he fiercely rebuked,
and stood against, those systems of social and philosophical orders that, in Kierkegaard’s mind,
left the human as a simple observer or “third-person,” rather than an engaged member of society
and faith.4 Kierkegaard felt that the Danish Lutheran State Church had failed miserably and had
made faith too easy, and therefore not genuine, and even, according to McCullough, “neo-
pagan.”5 To Kierkegaard, this was a result, not only of the state church, but of the rise of
As these ideals pervaded Denmark and the Church, Kierkegaard was hit close to home, as
even his own father and brother became members of this dogmatized and rationalized Church,
with his brother becoming a Bishop later in life, and his father often rubbing shoulders with the
religious elite, as a well-off nobleman, and intellectual.7 Kierkegaard’s familial ties to the upper
echelons of the State Church likely kept him from rebellious public discourse towards the
3
McDonald, 2017
4
McCullough, 2001, 7.
5
McCullough, 2001, 7.
6
This statement comes from multiple sources and pervades almost any work on Kierkegaard that I’ve
found. But see McCullough, 2001, 2 for a bulk of this information.
7
McDonald, 2017.
3
Church, but upon his fathers death, Kierkegaard began speaking out against the hypocrisy of the
Following his father’s death, Kierkegaard almost immediately (within days) broke his
engagement to hi betrothed, Regine Olsen, writing later in his Journal that he was made free by
this break to pursue his academics, and religious calling.9 However, it has been duly noted that
miss Olsen remained his muse throughout his life, and that he considered his giving her up a
sacrifice for religious duty.10 The connection between the loss of his father and the giving up of
his betrothed, must have some psychological cause, but it seems that Kierkegaard viewed it is as
It was following these losses that he began to get embroiled in arguments, as with his
rival Martensen, who, as a teacher of Kierkegaard knew he was working on collection regarding
Faust, and so published his own work on Faust before Kierkegaard, causing Kieekegaard to
abandon the work, at least for a time.11 Martensen would later become bishop.12 Beginning in
1846, Kierkegaard would become involved in a lengthier battle with another academic rival and
former teacher, Moler, over petty writings towards Kierkegaard in a satirical Magazine, The
Corsair.13 Nonetheless this battle was one Kierkegaard claimed to undertake as a spiritual one,
since he felt Moler’s public and private immorality justified it.14 These intellectual battles show
Kierkegaard’s growing reluctance to overlook the status quo, and his deepening desire to speak
against the hypocrisy and detachment from true faith that he saw appearing socio-ecclesiastical
4
While Kierkegaard’s religo-socio-political life was affected his family’s natural
intermingling with it, he nonetheless seemed to have had a happy relationship with them all.
According to Kierkegaards niece, his parents’ rearing was stern, and serious, yet afforded them
much time for youthfulness, and allowed Soren’s wit and satire to become a dominant trait
within him which was free to roam in the Kierkegaard household.15 Kierkegaard’s wit and
intellect is often credited as coming from his father, who shared a great love for philosophy and
education, and no doubt had a great influence on the intellectual that Soren turned out to
become.16
Kierkegaard’s father was a rationalist who raised the family in a mixture of Lutheran
State Church doctrinal adherence and heartfelt Moravian pietism.17 This religious upbringing
very likely had an influence on Kierkegaard’s writing which largely pertained to finding true,
and felt Christian practice, within a doctrinally dominant church-society. Soren seemed to have
had great relationship with his father, writing in his Journals concerning him, upon his death, “I
so deeply desired that he would have lived a few more years… he was a faithful friend.”18 Of his
mother, however, Kierkegaard wrote nothing. Not a word anywhere, even upon her death.
However, as McDonald points out, Kierkegaard may have had only the deepest love for his
mother, and his lack of speech of her may have been the greatest display of affection and honour,
since he says in his Concluding Unscientific Postscript, “an omnipresent being, makes himself
known by his invisibiblity.”19 And so, while he used his own form of literary communication, it
seems that Kierkegaard’s absence of writing of his mother is the very thing that spoke of it. This
15
Wikipedia, 2022.
16
McDonald, 2017
17
Roberts, Kyle. Emerging Prophet: Kierkegaard and the Postmodern People of God (p. 7). Cascade Books,
an Imprint of Wipf and Stock Publishers. Kindle Edition, 7.
18
Wikipedia, 2022.
19
McDonald, 2017.
5
is also the possible cause of his brother saying that Kierkegaard’s love for his mother would be
made known by volumes of which he wrote of her.20 This is the type of literary wit, that
Kierkegaard is said to have had by many scholars, especially post-modern ones, making him a
sophisticated literary pedant of almost all disciplines. Nevertheless he remains most noted as a
Kierkegaards works can be mostly broken down into 2 categories: his Pseudonymous
writings, and his Upbuilding Discourses.22 Kierkegaard’s Pseudonymous writings are those
which are written by him, but published under pseudonyms. They tend to deal with more abstract
topics and do not necessarily represent his own views, but might be considered a sort of
Kierkegaard is most famous for denying), that had he presented his own ideas as a thought
experiment rather than truth, Hegel would have been the greatest philosopher to every live,
however in presenting his ideas as truth, Kierkegaard felt Hegel instead was among the worst.24
Nonetheless it seems wrong to conclude that Kierkegaard did not believe the conclusions of his
pseudonymous writings. Rather his pseudonymous writings served a purpose other than
expounding the truth as he saw it. Kierkegaard’s main goal in writing anything is widely
20
McDonald, 2017. My research on this specific point is not deep, but this sounds like it could be hearsay.
Other sources have shown that some of McDonald’s work in this source may have relied on other elements of
disputed histories.
21
Evans, 2009, 1
22
Evans, 2009, 2
23
Evans, 2009, 2
24
6
understood as pushing the reader towards their own existential “becoming” as humans and as
subtlety prompt the reader into becoming on their own accord, rather than being told what to be
and who to be it by yet another religious authority. While Kierkegaard took authorial ownership
of his pseudonymous writers as the editor of their works, he nonetheless recommended that these
works be read as if written by their pseudonymous authors, and not him in order to properly
understand them.26
writings. Of these he wrote over 25 Discourses over a ten year period, ending in 1841, at age
38.27 These writings tend to focus on religious matters (though not strictly, and not as though the
pseudonymous writing don’t focus on religion), and tend to be written under his own name.28
These discourses are the writings of Kierkegaard which he himself claimed to be his own point
of view (as opposed to the pseudonymous thought experiments).29 Further as Pattison puts
succinctly, “The discourses are not thought experiments, but offer real input into real
problems.”30 Thus, while the Discourses and Pseudonymous Writings are separated by all the
aforementioned, the main difference between them is that the Discourses are direct and concrete
and the Pseudonymous Writings are indirect and abstract—The recognition of this difference
puts a kink in the arguments for some extreme postmodern usages of Kierkegaard as it shows
him as entering into the world of concrete, even modern thought, and to some, puts him into the
25
Roberts, 1.
26
Roberts, 9.
27
Pattison, George, Soren Kirkegaard, Spiritual Writings, A New Translation and Selection by George
Pattison (New York: HarperCollins Publishers, 2010), xvii
28
Evans, 2009, 2.
29
Pattison, 2010, xii.
30
Pattison, 2010, xiii
7
very system he was against.31 But despite this Kierkegaard maintains much of his anti-
become, rather than be made by the world.32 This keeps in line with his broadly accepted
subjective existentialism, as well as his theory of the individuals’ movement from religiousness
Within these works, both the Pseudonymous and the Discourses, are found themes which
have influenced the postmodern epoch, namely (for the purposes of this essay), subjectivity,
deconstructionism, and anti-institutionalism. These themes have been very briefly mentioned in
the introduction to Kierkegaards Life, Time, and Works, but now some these tenets will be
more precise word than it’s common usage implies. For the common post-modernist, or anti-
postmodernist for that matter, subjectivity implies a sort of relative truthfulness wherein the
subject decides truth. However, for Kierkegaard subjectivity is, in fact, the only way to
experience truth.34 This comes from the development of religious experience that Kierkegaard
saw in Denmark (which has been introduced to this essay previously), which allowed the one
experiencing it to become an onlooker, where the question of ones faith was not in regard to the
31
While this is true, the purposes of this essay are not to declare Kierkegaard a postmodernist. He clearly
was not for many reasons. However it is to show that Kierkegaard has been shown to be (often accurately) an
influence on postmodernity and that his work offers good insight for the Christian of the post modern epoch.
32
Pattison, 2010, xiii.
33
Shrag, Calvin, O. “The Kierkegaard Effect in Shaping the Contours of Modernity.” In Kierkegaard in
Post/modernity, Edited by Martin J. Matsustik and Merold Westphal, Germany: Indiana University Press, 1995, 9.
34
Jegstrup, Elsebet. “A Questioning of Justice: Kierkegaard, the Postmodern Critique and Political Theory.”
Political Theory 23, no. 3 (1995): 425–51. http://www.jstor.org/stable/191752, 3.
8
individuals actual experience of the object of their faith and their relationship together, but rather
it became about simply confessing a doctrine given to the masses from the authorities.
This, to Kierkegaard, was the result of Hegelian objectivity. For Kierkegaard, if one did
not experience a subjective faith, there was none to be had. This, in part, is because the
relationship of the subject to the object of faith is dependent on the objects ability to work in the
development of Life’s Stages between the aesthete, to the ethical, to the religious. 36 Thus, for
misconception of subjectivity), as it, in fact leads the subject to the Absolute truth, namely God.
However, as it has been previously mentioned, Kierkegaard seems to leave room for the
religiousness of a person to be developed without the exact reference to “God” so as to allow for
the subjects own “becoming.” This again is important as the context of Kierkegaard’s writing
was in and against the modern scientific movement, and its chokehold on genuine faith.
Kierkegaardian concept which Sarte spent much time deliberating upon and, ultimately, making
his own.37 Within this understanding, the ‘singular’, or the subject, becomes engaged the
universal—and even becomes it—only through subjective experience.38 For Kierkegaard the
universal has been said to be God, but his language is unclear, and makes it appear that the
universal is, vaguely, something greater than the self. This is seen in Fear and Trembling where
in one instance he says “the ethical is the universal,” and later “the…individual[s].. task…is to
35
Schrag, 1995, 7.
36
Schrag, 1995, 6.
37
McBride, Willian, L. “Sartes Debt to Kierkegaard: A Partial Reckoning.” In Kierkegaard in Post/modernity,
Edited by Martin J. Matsustik and Merold Westphal, Germany: Indiana University Press, 1995, 18.
38
Kierkegaard, Soren. “Fear and Trembling.” In A Kierkegaard Anthology, edited by Robert Bretall.
Princeton University Press, NJ. 1973, 129.
9
become the universal.” What is also possible is that the universal is the “whole” or the “other[s].”
And so for Kierkegaard, the way to experience the whole (universal), is to first experience the
subject (singular). Thus in short, subjectivity is the first necessity in becoming, or existing, or
engaging in truth.
Anti-institutionalism, for Kierkegaard, had much to do with the Danish Lutheran Church,
and Hegelianism. These were his enemies, in many ways, upon whom he released his quiver of
fiery words. They created the very systems that Kierkegaard felt were contrived and leading
people away from truth by their obnoxious demands. From the faults of these two systems grew
Kierkegaard’s anti-institutionalism which spread to almost any and every system, even reality
itself.39
may also be true that his own wild spirit had some to do with it. Kierkegaard’s upbringing may
have been harsh or stern, according to Gonzalez, and this may have lead to nurtured anti-
authoritarianism in him.40 While Kierkegaard was oft well-behaved as a boy he was also known
to get into altercations at school, and disregard his teachers.41 Thus, as it is with all of us, his anti-
institutionalism may have been due to more than an intellectual or spiritual yearning for truth,
but also to do with an emotional, or more carnal reaction to, life around him. Regardless,
Populus to be truly Christian, due to the systems that were put in place by those with power and
authority.
39
González, Justo L.. The Story of Christianity: The early church to the reformation. Volume 1. United
States: HarperCollins, 2010, 291.
40
Gonzalez, 2010, 289
41
Wikipedia, 2022.
10
As we see in Elsebet Jegstrup’s A Questioning of Justice, Kierkegaards anti-
institutionalism was something that went beyond a hatred of the systems, and into an outright
disbelief in them. This is seen in Kierkegaard dismissal of “constructed justice” for a type of
justice that is “beyond.” Kierkegaard felt that all justice systems, that were constructed by man,
would be misconstrued, and thus would not be justice at all.42 Nonetheless this need for justice
shows the probable existence of Justice, and thus if the justice is not available to us on earth, it
points to an external justice, expressed, attained, and fulfilled through love.43 This external
justice of love, clearly points to God, and further fulfills the law in distinctly Christian way. Thus
for Kierkegaard, even though he may have had an innate anti-authoritarianism, his anti-
institutionalism, was not a selfish denial of the systems or people he disliked. Rather it was yet
another way of eliminating the delusions of objectivity from oneself, and instead allowing for the
individual to subjectively engage with the Absolute, and enter the journey of becoming through
It. Further his anti-institutionalism showed the utter inability of the system (and of human reason,
Kierekgaards Deconstructionism
In many ways Kierkegaard’s deconstructionism gets to the heart of him, and to the heart
of post-modernity’s love and use for him. As mentioned above Kierkegaard had grown to believe
that systems were no good, and that if reality itself became a system or was at least viewed as a
system, there would be no real truth that was experientable, as it would dwell within the confines
of seeking an objective truth to understand, rather than to experience and live in its reality. It is to
this extent, then, that Kierkegaard is a deconstructionist. Where a system exists, Kierkegaard
42
Jegstrup, 1995, 432.
43
Jegstrup, 1995, 432.
11
would deconstruct it.44 At least this is the hope of the post-modernist who longs to see an end to
Kierkegaard’s deconstructionism is not limited to others and their systems, but are also
applied to himself. As Pattison points out, Kierkegaard’s pseudonymous writings have critiqued
his Discourses, or at least posed questions to them, and vise versa.45 Thus it seems that for
Kierkegaard to deconstruct is to let go of the self, and especially of the self that may be
contrived, and as has been shown elsewhere in this essay, to allow the Absolute (God) to
This must be why the lack of systems is so important for Kierkegaard. If the system is the
thing upon which the human is relying on to become what God intends to make it, then the
system must be perfectly correct, since the system is the thing producing the becoming of the
individual. However, as Kierkegaard knew, and expounded upon as his “sine qua non,” the
human being is inherently sinful, and thus the system it contrives cannot be perfect, nor very
good at all.46 Thus the true constructing (by God) of the individual from the aesthete to the
ethical to the truly religious, not only involves, but requires simultaneous deconstructing.
It's easy to see how the post-modern extremist might enjoy Kierkegaard’s ferocious
deconstruction cares far more of self-deconstruction to the glory and power of God, than to the
disestablishment of the structures that be, and those postmodernists who adhere to
44
This may be a stretch. I have limited experience with Kierkegaard and need to rely only on what my
research has given me as well as the implications of that research, this statement would be an implication thereof.
45
Pattison, 2010, xv.
46
McCullough, 2001, 3.
12
Kierkegaardian philosophy must undergo their own deconstruction of post-modernism, for the
postmodern scholarship on him, and by the appropriation of him in such scholarship for the
benefit of the (post-modern) authors purposes. It is also very easy to see why this is so, for, as
shown above Kierkegaard is very clearly in line with at least several post-modern ideals, and one
does not need to twist his words to make him appear so. Kierkegaard, through his subjectivity,
anti-institutionalism, and deconstructionism, shared much in common with those who identify
to intellectualism spawns from a deeply biblical and Christian place. He was not anti-modern in
the same sense as a post-modernist today. But, the fact is that neither do most postmodernists
today, fit into the stereotypical extremes of post-modernism . This is because post modernism is
not a black or white issue, but rather it is most epitomized as a reaction to modernism. 47
With the definition of Postmodernism being best put forth as a reaction to modernism, it
becomes clear that the divergence from a specific “system” of thought which would define post-
modernism is likely, and therefore the diversity of thought within this post-modern epoch is
wide. This sea of thought becomes even larger when Christian believers identify within post
modernism, given the paradoxical theology of the bible (namely the tension between the
existence of absolute truth and the humans seeming inability to fully grasp such absolute
47
Thompson, Glendon, “Postmodern Theology.” April 8, 2020.
https://www.thegospelcoalition.org/essay/postmodern-theology/
13
knowledge, or as some call it falsely call it, “relativism”). Even more is the sea broadened when
considering the contemporary global and pluralistic world. Thus post-modernism does need to be
defined in radical such terms as Nietzche would describe wherein there are no facts, no god, only
nihilism, nor does this narrative need to be echoed by conservative reactionaries to post-
modernism.48
wherein all who are seeking a personal truth, that goes beyond “truths” and enters into a great
beyond, wherein one is relinquished form the truth of the System, and freed from the shackles of
the world, and found in the hands of an undeniable Absolute, which does not deny the heart of
the post-modern quest for Truth (whether this object of the quest is known, or unknown to the
seeker) beyond systemic “truths.” Indeed the Kierkegaardian concepts which influence post-
modernism flip post-modernism on it’s head, deconstructing it, re-subjecting it to the subject
looking upon it, and tearing down the systems which have been built around that which aimed to
be against the system. When Kierkegaard is used as lens for post-modernism, he allows post-
Furthermore Kierkegaard invites the church of the post-modern epoch to do the same. He
invites the church to tear down its wall from both sides: those who find themselves as anti-
modernist, and those who are anti-postmodernist; those are who extreme and those who are not.
Ultimately Kierkegaard invites the post-modern epoch into a new post-modernism, into and era
Kierkegaard calls the contemporary church to becomes subject of experience, rather than
48
Thompson, 2020.
14
onlookers upon facts and theories. He calls us to take a leap into the unknown, to relinquish our
systems, and join together from all sides into a free becoming.
When considering Soren Kirkegaard’s life, time, and works it is clear that there is much
in common between the post-modernist and the late Kierkegaard, and indeed he has been
is both too radical, and to near to modernism, for the average post-modernist, as he calls the
comprehension. And while this Kierkegaardian “post-modernism” does not fit perfectly into the
contemporary post-modern society, it may be far truer to post-modernism than the current
increasingly pluralistic post-modern epoch, welcoming them, and calling them to subjective
deconstruction which might lead them to and impossible faith given by Christ. And it is this
same approach that the church of the post-modern epoch ought to learn from. It is no longer a
time wherein the church can, as in Kierkegaard’s day, allow for membership in the system of
church to account for the true experience of faith with the living God. Nor, can it put up boarders
between those true seekers who, while outside the doors of the Church, are not outside the call of
God. The church ought to take notes of Kierkegaard and bring itself under a radical subjectivity,
questioning it’s own being in Christ, rather than the being of others in Christ, and instead
welcome the outsiders and objective onlookers, into as subjective experience with the living
God, as we all, together, become Christian, without the helps of systems, but only by the mercy
of God.
Conclusion
15
This essay has surveyed the life, time and works of Kierkegaard, and has further done so
the influence on, and relevance to, post-modernism that he has had. In so doing Kierkegaard has
been shown to be a fierce intellectual with an innate desire to experience truth, and specifically
spiritual truth over and above gazing upon objective facts from afar. Kierkegaard fought against
the establishment of what he understood to be a false Church (Danish Lutheran Church) and
philosophy (scientism), and implemented his unwavering subjectivity instead, as the answer to
true faith in a world where faith was being lost. The lost world of Kierkegaard’s day is not unlike
the lost world of today. The advantage of today is that much of the ideas Kierkegaard put forth in
a war on the Church and on Modernism have been accepted, and therefore the Church today
ought to learn from Kierkegaard and reach our world through a radical Kierkegaardian
References
McCullough, Lissa, “Kierkegaard, Søren,” The Routledge Encyclopedia of Postmodernism, ed.
Victor E. Taylor and Charles E. Winquist. London: Routledge, 2001.
McDonald, William, "Søren Kierkegaard", The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Winter
2017 Edition), Edward N. Zalta
(ed.),<https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/win2017/entries/kierkegaard/>.
Roberts, Kyle. Emerging Prophet: Kierkegaard and the Postmodern People of God. Cascade
Books, an Imprint of Wipf and Stock Publishers. Kindle Edition.
16
Pattison, George, Soren Kirkegaard, Spiritual Writings, A New Translation and Selection by
George Pattison. New York: HarperCollins Publishers, 2010
Shrag, Calvin, O. “The Kierkegaard Effect in Shaping the Contours of Modernity.” In
Kierkegaard in Post/modernity, Edited by Martin J. Matsustik and Merold
Westphal, Germany: Indiana University Press, 1995.
González, Justo L.. The Story of Christianity: The early church to the reformation. Volume
1. United States: HarperCollins, 2010.
Thompson, Glendon, “Postmodern Theology.” April 8, 2020.
https://www.thegospelcoalition.org/essay/postmodern-theology/
Jegstrup, Elsebet. “A Questioning of Justice: Kierkegaard, the Postmodern Critique and Political
Theory.” Political Theory 23, no. 3 (1995): 425–51. http://www.jstor.org/stable/191752.
McBride, Willian, L. “Sartes Debt to Kierkegaard: A Partial Reckoning.” In Kierkegaard in
Post/modernity, Edited by Martin J. Matsustik and Merold Westphal, Germany: Indiana
University Press, 1995
Kierkegaard, Soren. “Fear and Trembling.” In A Kierkegaard Anthology, edited by Robert
Bretall. Princeton University Press, NJ. 1973
17