Does God Roll Dice? Neutrality and Determinism in Evolutionary Ecology

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 16

Biology & Philosophy (2019) 34:3

https://doi.org/10.1007/s10539-018-9657-8

AREA REVIEW

Does God roll dice? Neutrality and determinism


in evolutionary ecology

Som B. Ale1 · Abdel Halloway1 · William A. Mitchell2 · Christopher J. Whelan1,3

Received: 17 October 2017 / Accepted: 20 November 2018 / Published online: 5 December 2018
© Springer Nature B.V. 2018

Abstract
A tension between perspectives that emphasize deterministic versus stochastic pro-
cesses has sparked controversy in ecology since pre-Darwinian times. The most
recent manifestation of the contrasting perspectives arose with Hubbell’s proposed
“neutral theory”, which hypothesizes a paramount role for stochasticity in ecologi-
cal community composition. Here we shall refer to the deterministic and the sto-
chastic perspectives as the niche-based and neutral-based research programs, respec-
tively. Our goal is to represent these perspectives in the context of Lakatos’ notion
of a scientific research program. We argue that the niche-based program exhibits
all the characteristics of a robust, progressive research program, including the abil-
ity to deal with disconfirming data by generating new testable predictions within
the program. In contrast, the neutral-based program succeeds as a mathematical tool
to capture, as epiphenomena, broad-scale patterns of ecological communities but
appears to handle disconfirming data by incorporating hypotheses and assumptions
from outside the program, specifically, from the niche-based program. We conclude
that the neutral research program fits the Lakatosian characterization of a degenerate
research program.

Keywords Determinism · Neutral theory · Niche theory · Scientific research


program · Stochasticity

* Som B. Ale
[email protected]
1
Department of Biological Sciences M/C 066, University of Illinois at Chicago, 845 W. Taylor
Street, Chicago, IL 60607, USA
2
Department of Biology, Indiana State University, Science Building Room 283A, Terre Haute,
IN 47809, USA
3
Moffitt Cancer Center, 12902 USF Magnolia Drive, Tampa, FL 33612, USA

13
Vol.:(0123456789)
3 Page 2 of 16 S. B. Ale et al.

Introduction

Any well-trained naturalist can identify both similarities and differences among
species, regardless of relational distance. Through much of the development of
ecology, from its beginnings in natural philosophy and descriptive natural his-
tory, those characteristics were used to help explain patterns of distribution and
abundance of species. Ernst Haeckel (quoted in Mayr 1977) defined ecology as
the study of the complex interactions among species and their environment that
determine relative abundance and distribution. Darwin (1859) referred to those
interactions as the “struggle for existence.” This perspective led to first Grinnell’s
(1917) and then Elton’s (1927) concepts of the niche, both fully integrated in
Hutchinson’s (1957) hypervolume.
Despite the order perceived by naturalists from von Humboldt (1849) to
modern times (e.g., Diamond 1975), some questioned whether these ecological
communities (or assemblages) were in fact distinguishable from communities
assembled randomly (e.g., Simberloff 1978; Connor and Simberloff 1979). The
tension between perspectives that emphasize deterministic versus stochastic pro-
cesses has sparked controversy since pre-Darwinian times (see White 1789). The
most recent manifestation of the contrasting perspectives arose with Hubbell’s
proposed “neutral theory” (Bell 2000; Caswell 1976; Hubbell and Foster 1986;
Hubbell 2001). Here we shall refer to these perspectives as the niche-based and
neutral-based research programs. Our goal is to represent these perspectives in
the context of Lakatos’ notion of a scientific research program (Lakatos 1978).
The idea that natural communities assemble via deterministic processes
appeared in the early twentieth century with the super-organism framework of
Clements (1916). His work represented an early attempt to use species differences
to predict community-level phenomena. Clements’ view of communities is often
contrasted with that of Gleason’s (1926) individualistic concept of communities
which posits a role for some random processes in the assemblage of community
structure. But even Gleason recognized that communities were not purely random
assemblages of species (Nicolson et al. 2002). In Gleason’s scheme, chance plays
a role in dispersal and establishment of a species within an area, but success and
coexistence of species in that area are governed by adaptive traits like physiol-
ogy, resource exploitation, morphology, and behavior (Brown 1995). Later in the
twentieth century, ecologists employed Hutchinson’s niche hypervolume concept
to seek a mechanistic understanding of community structure (Hutchinson 1957;
MacArthur and Levins 1967; MacArthur 1972). More recently, the niche con-
cept has included additional mechanistic processes such as resource-consumer
dynamics (Chase and Leibold 2003; Holt 2009). Then, during the last decade of
the twentieth century, a new type of theory was proposed that sharply challenged
the underlying assumptions of the niche theory. This “neutral” theory (Hubbell
2001; Bell 2001) assumes that patterns of community process and structure can
be most parsimoniously understood without reference to niches or differences
between species that manifest in their demographic rates. Neutral theory seemed
to score some early successes (Hubbell 1997; Bell 2000) but subsequent reviews

13
Does God roll dice? Neutrality and determinism in evolutionary… Page 3 of 16 3

highlighted some shortcomings (McGill et al. 2006). As all theories do, the neu-
tral theory has seen modifications and enhancement since its inception (Rosindell
et al. 2011). And recently, some workers have suggested that the two theories
each have their strengths and should be integrated (Wennekes et al. 2012; Mat-
thews and Whittaker 2014; Janzen et al. 2015).
Here we examine the niche-based and the neutral-based approaches through the
lens of scientific research programs (Lakatos 1978; Mitchell and Valone 1990).
We argue that the niche-based program exhibits all the characteristics of a robust,
progressive research program, including the ability to deal with disconfirming data
by generating new testable predictions within the program. In contrast, the neu-
tral-based program succeeds as a mathematical tool to capture, as epiphenomena,
broad-scale patterns of ecological communities but appears to handle disconfirming
data by incorporating hypotheses and assumptions from outside the program (see
Glossary).

Niche versus neutral theory

Evolutionary ecologists working within the framework of the niche-based program


typically hold the bedrock principle that natural selection optimizes fitness (e.g.,
Hutchinson 1957; Williams 1966; Maynard Smith 1982; Vincent and Brown 2005;
Brown 2016). The species’ niche is defined by a combination of its environment and
adaptive traits which allow individuals to gather resources, evade enemies and per-
form other functions that influence their relative birth and death rates, which then go
onto influence species distributions, abundances, coexistence, and thus community
composition.
To illustrate, consider the example of habitat selection by animals. Individual ani-
mals, subject to constraints on information, together with physiological, morpho-
logical and behavioral characteristics, select habitat that maximizes their expected
offspring production. This, however, produces a paradox: If all individuals in a
population choose to live in the same (preferred) habitat, that habitat will become
crowded, thereby reducing average fitness. As a habitat becomes crowded, the best
response of an additional individual is to select instead the next best habitat, until
the expected pay-off in all available habitats is equal (Fretwell and Lucas 1969;
Morris 1988). The dispersion of individuals among habitats within a heterogeneous
landscape in this scenario will achieve temporary ecological stability when no indi-
vidual can gain by dispersing elsewhere. The distribution at this time is at a dynamic
equilibrium known as the ideal free distribution (Krivan et al. 2008). Competition
for ever-diminishing resources thus influences habitat preference.
When two species choose habitats, differences in their abilities to acquire
resources in the different habitats can lead to species-specific density-dependent
optimal habitat choice (Rosenzweig 1981). This occurs when trade-offs in resource
exploitation strategies allow different species to possess a fitness advantage in dif-
ferent habitats. In this case, diversity is maintained by the separation of species into
different ecological niches that result from different adaptations to environmental
heterogeneity. A community is then a composition of species whose competitive

13
3 Page 4 of 16 S. B. Ale et al.

interaction strengths are determined by their eco-evolutionary trade-offs over one


or more axes of environmental heterogeneity (Kotler and Brown 1988; Chase and
Leibold 2003).
Critics of the niche-based program argue that niches are unnecessary to explain
community patterns and processes. Instead, they propose that many characteristics
of natural communities can be explained parsimoniously with stochastic or neutral
models that invoke no niche differences among species (e.g., Connor and Simberloff
1979; Storch and Frynta 1999; Hubbell 2001; Bell 2001; Jonzén et al. 2004; Alonso
et al. 2006; Rosindell et al. 2011, 2012). These neutral models assume that individu-
als within a trophic level are functionally equivalent in birth, death, dispersal, and
speciation (Hubbell 2001). In this paradigm, the success or failure of any individ-
ual is determined simply by random “ecological drift”—random variation in births,
deaths, or dispersal. Consequently, random variation is what creates differences and
structure within a community or ecosystem. Apparent habitat partitioning among
species is simply the random assortment of individuals among habitats.
Randomness is used by scientists to handle two parts of their systems: the
unknown and the irrelevant. The unknown flows from the fact that scientists lack
perfect information about their systems; they characterize their uncertainty by using
confidence intervals, maximum likelihood estimations, and Bayesian probabilities.
The irrelevant part arises because scientists typically expect that some variables will
have little effect on their questions of interest. Inclusion of such irrelevant variables
renders the theory less tractable without increasing its empirical content or success.
As von Neumann (1947) once said, “[the] truth…is much too complicated to allow
anything but approximations”. Therefore, any model will necessarily be a simplifica-
tion of reality. Often these features incidental to the model’s message are expressed
as random variation. In the next two sections, we explore these uses of randomness
in the context of niche and neutral theory.

Randomness as the unknown in niche and neutral explanations

Niche theory, which can be traced to Darwin (1859), was developed into its modern
form through the works of Hutchinson (1957), MacArthur and Levins (1967), Mac-
Arthur (1972), and Chase and Leibold (2003). Evolutionary ecologists have recently
enhanced the mechanistic underpinnings and predictive power of niche theory by
incorporating resource-consumer models (Chase and Leibold 2003; Holt 2009).
The Hutchinson-MacArthur school (Hutchinson 1957; MacArthur 1972; Vincent
and Brown 2005; Slack 2010) works with the assumption that, even with tremen-
dous complexity and a myriad of ecological interactions, natural communities are
dynamic systems organized by regular and deterministic forces resulting species’
differences (e.g., Mitchell and Valone 1990; Brown 2001). Fundamental to these
models is the notion that ecological systems are regulated by dynamic attractors
in the space of species densities. Such attractors could be points, orbits, or more
complicated structures. Because of these attractors, communities respond to distur-
bance in predictable ways, either converging on their previous attractor or a new
one, depending on the perturbation (Pimm 1991). So, while species densities may

13
Does God roll dice? Neutrality and determinism in evolutionary… Page 5 of 16 3

fluctuate in response to disturbances, they are in principle predictable—they do not


wander in a random walk of densities. Or, to paraphrase Einstein, God does not roll
dice.
Consider the initial position of an entity, a population for instance, in a dynamic
system with a set of forces. In deterministic models, the subsequent position of the
entity is specific and predictable. Modelers include in their model systems only a
subset of the processes that occur in nature, with stochastic elements standing in
for the residual variation (Clark 2009). They focus on the subsets because there are
other unknown forces that cannot be measured with current tools, technology and
budgets. But the unknown forces, in principle, could be measured, and at least some
will be included in future models as the means become practical. The expanded
model increases the apparent determinism and predictability of the system by pro-
viding more explanation for what had previously been unknown.
Clark (2009) suggests a heuristic model of this process:
Response = f (covariates, parameters) + error (1)
The first term is deterministic and explains how processes contribute to the
response. The second term is not explanatory and takes up uncertainty by repre-
senting variation that one cannot account for in the first term. This is the stochastic
element.
Progress in science, according to Clark (2009), occurs when variation moves
from the second term (unknown) to the first term (known). With movement of vari-
ation in this direction, processes or phenomena shift from being attributed to sto-
chastic variation to deterministic causation. The neutral models, Clark (2009) states
further, emphasize movement in the opposite direction. Hence neutral models, at
their essence, hold that phenomena attributed to the second, stochasticity term bet-
ter represent explanations for species co-occurrence than do known, observable pro-
cesses whose cause and effect relationships are well understood. Advocates of neu-
tral models derogate observable differences in species characteristics as paramount
mechanisms for coexistence.

Randomness as the incidental in niche and neutral explanations

Physicists in the nineteenth century knew well that it is impossible in practice to


know the positions of all the molecules in a volume of a gas. This spurred them to
develop the methods of statistical physics, which led to an understanding of many
properties of systems, such as gases, that are composed of a large number of mol-
ecules. However, Laplace’s (1902) probability theory does not say anything about
achieving a perfect knowledge and a universal predictability, rather how to proceed
in the absence of such a complete knowledge.
Consider a compact sphere dropped in a vacuum. Its motions will obey Newton’s
second law (F = ma). Drop a banknote from a distance in the real world. It will flut-
ter and at the end come to rest far from where it was dropped. Does this falsify the
second law? No. The banknote’s deviation from a free-fall trajectory is explained
by other forces (including wind and air resistance) not explained in Newton’s fun-
damental laws of motion (Hoeferyz 2003, p. 1406). Analogous situations arise in

13
3 Page 6 of 16 S. B. Ale et al.

population ecology. That a population’s growth does not follow a perfectly sigmoi-
dal curve does not imply that the logistic or Lotka–Volterra equations are not predic-
tive, nor that niche theory concept is flawed.
Deterministic population models may tell us nothing about why a particular
population does not exhibit perfect sigmoid growth—there may be a host of factors
affecting population growth. The deterministic models of population growth do tell
us that population growth is a function of each species’ own population size and that
of the other species with which it interacts. The sigmoid growth model does not say
anything about when and how a population may be doomed when struck by a cata-
strophic hurricane. These factors are incidental to the message of sigmoid models of
population growth. The last decade witnessed many analyses of population regula-
tion (e.g., Ziebarth et al. 2010; Knape and de Valpine 2012; Kalyuzhny et al. 2014),
demonstrating that regulation may be weak, because of noise in ecological systems.
This should not prompt ecologists to seek shelter under stochasticity, but realize our
knowledge of the system was genuinely imperfect, and constantly gear our efforts to
knowing more about the system.

Lakatosian research program

We suggest that the niche-based and neutral schools correspond to two different
types of scientific research programs (sensu Lakatos 1978). According to Lakatos,
a scientific research program comprises two kinds of assumptions (or hypotheses):
hard core and auxiliary. Hard core assumptions are not directly testable in isolation,
but must be conjoined with the auxiliary hypotheses to construct models to explain
observations and generate predictions. An example of a hard core would be New-
ton’s laws of attraction which must be combined with auxiliary assumptions regard-
ing the masses and distances between planets (among other things), to produce a
model capable of predicting planetary motion. Auxiliary assumptions may be spe-
cific to a system, such as the number and masses of planets. They may also include
simplifying assumptions of nature known to be false, but which allow scientist to do
the math required to make predictions.
In the early stages of Newton’s program, he made the auxiliary assumptions
that the solar system consisted of the sun and a single planet, and that the planet
was a point mass with no volume. Even with these simplifications, Newton made
new and successful predictions about planetary motion. There were of course some
data inconsistent with this simple model. But Newton already knew that would be
the case; indeed, he could even anticipate what new auxiliary assumptions would
be needed to explain the anomalies. The models incorporating the new auxiliary
hypotheses explained not only previous anomalies but also made new, testable pre-
dictions. The positive heuristic of a research program directs the scientist to alter
only the auxiliary hypotheses while leaving the hard core untouched. In this man-
ner, the hard core itself can be evaluated even as simplifying assumptions and failed
auxiliary hypotheses are replaced. According to Lakatos, a progressive research
program is not one that never fails an empirical test, but rather one that, in such
cases, replaces auxiliary hypotheses to produce a new model that can explain the

13
Does God roll dice? Neutrality and determinism in evolutionary… Page 7 of 16 3

previously disconfirming observation and make new testable predictions. If some


of these predictions are successful, then the program is said to be empirically pro-
gressive. A degenerating program, on the other hand, is one in which new auxiliary
hypotheses are produced primarily to explain previous anomalies and data, but these
new hypotheses either do not generate new predictions, or the predictions they make
are not successful Lakatos proposed that scientific progress occurs when different
research programs show different rates of success at anticipating anomalies, modify-
ing auxiliary assumptions to generate new successful predictions.
In our view, the niche-based research program includes several hard core assump-
tions: (1) fitness is density-dependent, (2) organisms experience fitness trade-offs
along one or more axes of environmental heterogeneity, such that traits improving
fitness in one environment decrease fitness in a different environment, and (3) organ-
isms respond adaptively to the densities and traits of conspecifics and hetero-spe-
cifics. These hard core assumptions must be conjoined with auxiliary hypotheses
to make testable predictions. Examples of such auxiliary hypotheses might include
the nature of a trade-off between speed and efficiency of foraging among competing
species (Kotler and Brown 1988; Wilson et al. 1999), the adaptive responses by a
prey species to predation-risk (e.g., Brown 1999), or the information regarding het-
ero-specific densities available to individuals selecting habitats (Rosenzweig 1981;
Morris 1988). Some predictions may succeed, while others may fail. But the fail-
ures can be handled using the positive heuristic of modifying auxiliary hypotheses
to explain anomalies and generate novel predictions (Lakatos 1978); perhaps we had
assumed that prey have fixed, unchanging information about the predation-risk in
a habitat. We can replace that assumption with one that allows prey to update their
information about predation-risk (Welton et al. 2003; Martín and Lopez 2005). The
new model explains the previous anomaly and makes new predictions which we can
then test with a new experiment. Thus, we use the data to iterate through a sequence
of increasingly better, more predictive models in a manner consistent with a progres-
sive research program. Indeed, this is how we see in models variation shifting from
the stochastic element to the deterministic element (Clark 2009, 2012).
If we try to frame the neutral approach as a Lakatosian research program, we
encounter a problem with how proponents treat its apparent hard core. This hard
core would seem to be: (1) fitness is density-dependent, and (2) “all individu-
als within a particular trophic level have the same chances of reproduction and
death regardless of their species identity” (Rosindell et al. 2011). The auxiliary
assumptions of the program would include the demographic parameters for birth,
death and dispersal, common to all species within a trophic level. A major dis-
tinction between the neutral and niche program is that, because the neutral hard
core assumes that species are functionally similar, the neutral program has no
role for environmental heterogeneity. We allow that neutral theory can produce
models—including some of great complexity—that are consistent with previous
observations (e.g., some species-area distributions). While that would seem to be
a success, the same could be said of the Ptolemaic model of planetary motion
which could be made to account for almost any planetary or heavenly body
motion with the addition of more epicycles. What the Ptolemaic program lacked,
but the Copernican (and later, Newtonian) program possessed, was the positive

13
3 Page 8 of 16 S. B. Ale et al.

heuristic that allowed it to predict new data that were corroborated by observa-
tions. Lakatos and Zahar (1978) state the problem with the Ptolemaic program
thusly, “Each move in the geocentric programme had dealt with certain anomalies
but had done so in an ad hoc way. No novel predictions were produced, anomalies
still abounded and certainly each move had deviated from the original Platonic
heuristic.” We believe that the neutral program in community ecology suffers
similar shortcomings; there does not appear to be a positive heuristic that antic-
ipates anomalies, or permits observed anomalies to motivate new models with
new testable predictions that are then corroborated. In effect, the neutral research
program does not appear progressive but degenerating.
A critical feature of a progressive Lakatosian research program is that it can han-
dle empirical anomalies by revising auxiliary assumptions while retaining its hard
core. But the neutral program’s hard core tends to be revised in response to empiri-
cal anomalies. For example, the hard core assumption that species are functionally
similar is replaced by adding guild structure to a community to improve the fit of the
model to tree data from Barro Colorado Island (e.g., Janzen et al. 2015). While this
may be characterized as “integrating” neutral and niche theory, the improved model
invokes the hard core of the niche program, but not that of the neutral program. So,
while it may be the case that some patterns can be predicted by both niche and neu-
tral models (Rosindell et al. 2012), failed predictions lead to revision of the niche
program’s auxiliary assumptions, but the neutral program’s hard core.
The distinction between the neutral and niche research program is not whether
you favor simple or complex models, but rather the role that simplicity plays. In a
Lakatosian research program, simplicity can be found in the auxiliary assumptions,
especially early in the development of a program. Simple auxiliary assumptions
are important for making predictions, and when those fail you replace a simplify-
ing assumption with another, more complex hypothesis. Each new addition adds
empirical content because it makes new predictions. Lakatos (1978) describes how
Newton begins with the simplest of systems, a single point-like planet revolving
around a fixed point-like sun. He applied his hard core assumptions to this system
to generate predictions. And then he successively added more reality by allowing
heavenly bodies mass, spin and shape. Eventually he included interplanetary forces.
But even as he increased the complexity of the systems he retained the same immu-
table hard core. Each new addition to the auxiliary assumptions added complex-
ity and improved the empirical content without changing that hard core. Contrast
this with the neutral program where it is the hard core itself whose simplicity is
replaced with other hypotheses of more empirical content capable of generating
novel predictions.
Proponents of neutral theory, in defense of their assumption of demographic neu-
trality, cite the example of an ideal gas where the assumptions are that the molecules
behave as point-like particles that do not interact and that exchange energy only with
the walls of the container in which they are kept at a given temperature. But in con-
trast to inanimate matter, in ecosystems, we deal with entities that mutate, evolve,
and change, and fine-tune their interactions with partners. Thus the problem at the
core of the statistical physics of ecological systems is to identify the key elements
one needs to incorporate in models to reproduce the known emergent patterns and

13
Does God roll dice? Neutrality and determinism in evolutionary… Page 9 of 16 3

eventually discover new ones (Azaele et al. 2016). Moreover, the ultimate goal is to
discover, and critically test, causal mechanisms producing emergent patterns (Bunin
2017).
Neutral program proponents claim that some of the program’s auxiliary assump-
tions can be relaxed, including speciation (Etienne et al. 2007), spatial structure
(Rosindell and Cornell 2007, 2009) and the zero-sum rule (Etienne et al. 2007; Hae-
geman and Etienne 2008), and that this often does not affect the theory’s predictions
or produces predictions that match observations better (see Wennekes et al. 2012).
Some of these auxiliary assumptions, such as an unrealistic panmictic source pool,
however, are difficult to defend. Neutral theory cannot, because of the symmetry
assumption of its hard core, predict which species will be rare or common (Wootton
2005; Leigh 2007). Because the hard core is essentially devoid of empirical content,
we can never be sure to what new topics it can be applied—we know neither the
domain of the theory nor when its assumptions are more likely to apply. It is not
progressive.
One of the main advantages of the niche relative to neutral approach is the abil-
ity to generate additional mechanistic hypotheses when the established mechanis-
tic models fail to predict observed patterns. Rosindell et al. (2012) argue that many
mechanistic extensions of the neutral model can also test additional hypotheses (see
also Jabot and Chave 2011; Janzen et al. 2015). These studies, however, use the neu-
tral model as a null hypothesis and then build onto it to further describe anomalies
in the data not described by the neutral model. Is this use of the neutral model char-
acteristic of a robust, progressive research program? No. A null model, as Gotelli
and McGill (2006) posit, is a tool to test the existence of some process. It does this
by predicting how data would look in the absence of the process. A null model does
not include novel processes that generate novel predictions. So, while null models
can play a critical role in the heuristic of a research programs, they would not seem
to constitute part of the hard core.

Neutral theory as a null hypothesis

Some neutral theory proponents treat the neutral model both as a statistical null
model and process-based model (see Gotelli and McGill 2006; Munoz and Huneman
2016). Statistical (traditional) null models are based on randomization of empirical
data (stochasticity applied to existing data), while dynamical process-based mod-
els incorporate a stochastic process into a biological model (stochasticity applied to
a process-based model; see Gotelli and McGill 2006). This duality, as Gotelli and
McGill (2006) point out, should be explicitly expressed to avoid confusion. If the
neutral model is used as a null hypothesis (e.g., Bell 2001), its alternative hypothesis
needs to be made explicit. If it is considered as a process-based model, which seems
to be the case (see Hubbell 2001; Wennekes et al. 2012), then it should be com-
pared to the predictions of a (simpler) null model, such as the log-normal (weaker,
less explicit test). Those advocating the neutral model as a process-based predictive
model (see for instance, Munoz and Huneman 2016) rather than as a null model can-
not take refuge in null models and use weaker tests (Harte 2003; Gotelli and McGill

13
3 Page 10 of 16 S. B. Ale et al.

2006). For traditional null models of community assembly, the alternative hypoth-
esis is that species interactions are important, whereas, for neutral models, the alter-
native hypothesis encompasses species interactions and species differences (Gotelli
and McGill 2006), as well as an axis of environmental heterogeneity on which spe-
cies differences manifest fitness differences.
Some studies show that models with stochasticity can make novel, testable pre-
dictions, but they are mixed neutral-niche models (see Kalyuzhny et al. 2015). For
example, Kadmon and Allouche’s (2007) model predicts that an increased habitat
heterogeneity leads to more stochastic extinctions and possibly lower richness, a
prediction that was later corroborated (Allouche et al. 2012). Other neutral models
were used to predict extinction debts (Halley and Iwasa 2011) and time to origina-
tions of clades (Maruvka et al. 2013). In this last case, using neutral models as a null
model, the motivation of Maruvka et al. (2013) was to deviate from simpler stochas-
tic models for the sake of prediction.

Discussion and conclusion

We ought then to regard the present state of the universe as the effect of its anterior
state and the cause of the one which is to follow—Pierre-Simon Laplace.
Prediction is difficult, especially the future—Niels Bohr.
Several attempts to integrate niche-based and neutral-based programs have been
proposed (Vellend 2010; Fisher and Mehta 2014; O’Dwyer and Chisholm 2014).
But we see two fundamental problems with integrating the niche-based and neutral-
based research programs. First, the neutral program is, as we argue above, a degen-
erate scientific research program. While it does succeed at capturing static, aggre-
gate, emergent patterns like species abundance distributions, it does not appear to
succeed at generating novel predictions when the hard core is combined new auxil-
iary hypotheses from that program. A second problem is that attempts to merge the
two conceptual frameworks do so by replacing the neutral hard core with the niche
hard core (environmental heterogeneity and functional non-equivalence), and then
introducing some stochasticity. Of course, this means the theory is no longer neutral
(Gewin 2006) in the sense originally advocated by Hubbell and other proponents
(see also Munoz and Huneman 2016).
Niche-based, deterministic frameworks and neutral-based, stochastic frameworks
have been viewed as lying on opposite sides of a continuum (Gravel et al. 2006).
We view this continuum, however, to be misleading. Species differ in vital rates,
physiologies, morphologies, and many other ways that render the ecological equiva-
lence assumption of neutral theory wrong. Likewise, the world does not seem to be
wholly deterministic—we know that demographic and environmental stochasticity
is real and may, at some times and some places, trump deterministic causal path-
ways. Hence, we advocate not so much an integration of the two approaches, but a
resolution.
To some extent, the argument over niche versus neutral research programs,
and attempts to integrate, synthesize or resolve them, is an exercise in re-invent-
ing the wheel. May (1972) demonstrated that increased community complexity

13
Does God roll dice? Neutrality and determinism in evolutionary… Page 11 of 16 3

(increased species richness), contrary to the prevailing views at the time (MacAr-
thur 1955), decreased stability. Subsequent analyses (Yodzis 1981; Pimm 1984)
showed this surprising result arose from the random assembly of the species com-
prising May’s (1972) community matrices. Communities based on actual food
webs (Yodzis 1981; James et al. 2015; Jacquet et al. 2016) or with non-random
interaction coefficients (Pimm 1984; Allesina and Tang 2012) were much more
likely to exhibit stability and achieve an equilibrium. These latter analyses built
upon and strengthen the earlier analysis: while random communities are more
likely to be unstable as species are added, some non-random communities, spe-
cifically those that resemble communities we observe in nature, have properties
that engender stability even at high species richness.
These developments, perhaps delayed or waylaid in recent years by the excur-
sion into neutral theory, illustrate how niche theory exemplifies a progressive
research program as envisioned by Lakatos. When May (1972, 1974) looked at
the question of diversity and stability, he used randomness due to mathematical
and computational constraints along with ecologists’ general lack of knowledge
about real world community structure, the incidental and unknown. To May, real
ecological communities were never random; randomness was only an auxiliary,
never a core assumption (e.g., May 1999). In comparison, attempts to rescue neu-
tral theory proceed by relaxing assumptions of ecological equivalence, in essence,
adding niche differences and associated trade-offs. Recently Munoz and Huneman
(2016) interpret ecological equivalence in light of strong and weak versions, the
former being a mechanistic view of neutral theory at the individual level while
the latter was shown to involve both equalizing (no competition) and stabilizing
(competition) factors, adopting Chesson’s (2000) framework. Referring to these
chimeras as “neutral” theories seem misguided at best, equivocal (Munoz and
Huneman 2016, p. 330), and ultimately futile. A “neutral” research program that
builds in niche differences has sacrificed its hard core and is no longer neutral.
Hubbell (in Gewin 2006), referring to neutral theory, stated: “Other theories don’t
suffer the ignominy of having a self-destruct button.” We would say instead that
neutral theory seems, like a cat, to have nine (or more) lives. Inclusion of niche
differences in “neutral” models reflects, as we argue above, the empirical success
of niche-based approaches.
Where does this leave neutral theory? We find no fault with the mathematical
principles used by neutral theorists. Averaging and aggregating is a valid tech-
nique used by scientific disciplines to understand and analyze the natural world.
Developing a model of reality necessarily involves a simplification of reality, with
the best models having the simplification tailored to the scale of the phenomenon
to be understood (Levin 1992). Unfortunately, this is simply model building 101.
Instead, we argue that the resurgence of niche theory (e.g., Levine and HilleRis-
Lambers 2009; HilleRisLambers et al. 2012; Letten et al. 2016) and proposals to
synthesize niche theory with Chesson’s (2000) coexistence theory (Letten et al.
2016) represent the best way forward. This synthesis is fully consistent with the
conception of a progressive research program (Lakatos 1978). Bertrand Russell
(1997) said it most aptly: that scientists “… should seek causal laws is as obvious
as the maxim that mushroom-gatherers should seek mushrooms.”

13
3 Page 12 of 16 S. B. Ale et al.

Acknowledgements Thanks are due to D. W. Morris for intellectual discussions when Som B. Ale was
at Lakehead University with support from Canada’s International Polar Year program “Arctic Wildlife
Observatories Linking Vulnerable EcoSystems” and Canada’ Natural Sciences and Engineering Research
Council. The authors also thank Burt Kotler, an anonymous reviewer, and Linus Svensson for crisp com-
ments on a previous draft of the manuscript. Abdel Halloway wishes to thank the National Science Foun-
dation (NSF) Graduate Research Fellowship (DGE-0907994 and DGE-1444315) for support. Any opin-
ion, findings, and conclusions or recommendations expressed in this material are those of the authors(s).

Glossary

Dispersal limitation Limitation of distribution or abundance in


the vicinity of its parents because of either
constraints on dispersal or inadequate pro-
duction of dispersing individuals.
Ecological drift Under ecological drift (Hubbell 2001) all
individuals in the community, regardless
of species, have equal probabilities of giv-
ing birth, dying, immigrating to another
location, and (in one version of the model)
acquiring a mutation that will eventually
result in speciation. This does not mean
that all species have an equal chance.
Abundant species have a greater likeli-
hood of being drawn, but only by virtue
of their abundance. Individuals are equal,
but species, as collective entities, are not
(Norris 2003)
Ecological equivalence  when differences among individuals
belonging to different species do not trans-
late into differences in their probabilities
of beingand persisting, in the present and
future community
Neutrality equivalence, and symmetry That different individuals from different
species belonging to the same function-
ally uniform ecological community have
similar birth, death and dispersal rates
(Hubbell 2001; Etienne and Olff 2005).
The neutrality hypothesis is that differ-
ences in species traits do not either affect
the chances of that species being present
or absent in a community, or influence
changes in their relative abundances
Niche theory Species can stably coexist in an ecologi-
cal community if their characteristics (or
traits) allow them to specialize on one
particular set of resources or environment

13
Does God roll dice? Neutrality and determinism in evolutionary… Page 13 of 16 3

conditions (niches) in which they are


superior to their competitors (Grinnell
1917; Hutchinson 1957; Chase and Lei-
bold 2003)
Relative species abundance The probability that a species has n indi-
viduals in a given region. When multi-
plied by the total number of species in the
region this gives the number of species
with n individuals. This is known as the
species-abundance distribution

References
Allesina S, Tang S (2012) Stability criteria for complex ecosystems. Nature 483:205–208
Allouche O, Kalyuzhny M, Moreno-Rueda G, Pizarro M, Kadmon R (2012) Area–heterogeneity trade-off
and the diversity of ecological communities. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 109:17495–17500
Alonso D, Etienne RS, McKane AJ (2006) The merits of neutral theory. TREE 21:451–457
Azaele S, Suweis S, Grilli J, Volkov I, Banavar JR, Maritan A (2016) Statistical mechanics of ecologi-
cal systems: neutral theory and beyond. Rev Mod Phys 88:035003. https​://doi.org/10.1103/RevMo​
dPhys​.88.03500​3
Bell G (2000) The distribution of abundance in neutral communities. Am Nat 155:606–617
Bell G (2001) Neutral macroecology. Science 293:2413–2418
Brown JH (1995) Macroecology. University of Chicago Press, Chicago
Brown JS (1999) Vigilance, patch use and habitat selection: foraging under predation-risk. Evol Ecol Res
1:49–71
Brown JS (2001) Ngongas and ecology: on having a worldview. Oikos 94:6–16
Brown JS (2016) Why Darwin would have loved evolutionary game theory. Proc R Soc Lond B Biol Sci
283:20160847. https​://doi.org/10.1098/rspb.2016.0847
Bunin G (2017) Ecological communities with Lotka–Volterra dynamics. Phys Rev E 95:042414. https​://
doi.org/10.1103/PhysR​evE.95.04241​4
Caswell H (1976) Community structure: a neutral model analysis. Ecol Monogr 46:327–354
Chase JM, Leibold MA (2003) Ecological niches: linking classical and contemporary approaches. Uni-
versity of Chicago Press, Chicago
Chesson P (2000) Mechanisms of maintenance of species diversity. Annu Rev Ecol Evol Syst 31:343–366
Clark JS (2009) Beyond neutral science. TREE 24:8–15
Clark JS (2012) The coherence problem with the Unified Neutral theory of biodiversity. TREE
27:198–202
Clements FE (1916) Plant succession: an analysis of the development of vegetation. Carnegie Institute of
Washington Publication, Washington
Connor EF, Simberloff DS (1979) The assembly of species communities: chance or competition? Ecol-
ogy 60:1132–1140
Darwin C (1859) On the origin of species by means of natural selection, or the preservation of favoured
races in the struggle for life. J. Murray, London
Diamond JM (1975) Assembly of species communities. In: Cody ML, Diamond JM (eds) Ecology and
evolution of communities. Cambridge, Belknap, pp 342–444
Elton CS (1927) Animal ecology. Sidgwick and Jackson, London
Etienne RS, Olff H (2005) Bayesian analysis of species abundance data: assessing the relative importance
of dispersal and niche-partitioning for the maintenance of biodiversity. Ecol Lett 8:493–504
Etienne RS, Apol MEF, Olff H, Weissing FJ (2007) Modes of speciation and the neutral theory of biodi-
versity. Oikos 116:241–258
Fisher CK, Mehta P (2014) The transition between the niche and neutral regimes in ecology. Proc Natl
Acad Sci USA 111:13111–13116

13
3 Page 14 of 16 S. B. Ale et al.

Fretwell SD, Lucas HL Jr (1969) On territorial behavior and other factors influencing habitat distribution
in birds. Acta Biotheor 14:16–36
Gewin V (2006) Beyond neutrality—ecology finds its niche. PLoS Biol 4:e278
Gleason HA (1926) The individualistic concept of the plant association. Bull Torrey Bot Club 53:7–26
Gotelli NJ, McGill BJ (2006) Null versus neutral models: what’s the difference? Ecography 29:793–800
Gravel D, Canham CD, Beaudet M, Messier C (2006) Reconciling niche and neutrality: the continuum
hypothesis. Ecol Lett 9:399–409
Grinnell J (1917) Field tests of theories concerning distributional control. Am Nat 51:115–128
Haegeman B, Etienne RS (2008) Relaxing the zero-sum assumption in neutral biodiversity theory. J
Theor Biol 252:288–294
Halley JM, Iwasa Y (2011) Neutral theory as a predictor of avifaunal extinctions after habitat loss. Proc
Natl Acad Sci USA 108:2316–2321
Harte J (2003) Tail of death and resurrection. Nature 424:1006–1007
HilleRisLambers J, Adler PB, Harpole WS, Levine JM, Mayfield MM (2012) Rethinking community
assembly through the lens of coexistence theory. Annu Rev Ecol Evol Syst 43:227–248
Hoeferyz C (2003) For fundamentalism. Philos Sci 70:1401–1412
Holt RD (2009) Bringing the Hutchinsonian niche into the 21st century: ecological and evolutionary per-
spectives. Proc Natl Acad Sci USA 106(Suppl. 2):19659–19665
Hubbell SP (1997) A unified theory of biogeography and relative species abundance and its application to
tropical rain forests and coral reefs. Coral Reefs 16(Suppl.):S9–S21
Hubbell SP (2001) The unified neutral theory of biodiversity and biogeography monographs in popula-
tion biology. Princeton University Press, Princeton
Hubbell SP, Foster RB (1986) Biology, chance and history and the structure of tropical rain forest tree
communities. In: Diamond JM, Case TJ (eds) Community ecology. Harper and Row, New York, pp
314–329
Hutchinson GE (1957) Concluding remarks, cold spring harbor symposium. Quant Biol 22:415–427
Jabot F, Chave J (2011) Analyzing tropical forest tree species abundance distributions using a non-neutral
model and through approximate Bayesian inference. Am Nat 178:E37–E47
Jacquet C, Moritz C, Morissette L, Legagneux P, Massol F, Archambault P, Gravel D (2016) No com-
plexity-stability relationship in empirical ecosystems. Nat Commun 7:12573
James A, Plank MJ, Rossberg AG, Beecham J, Emmerson M, Pitchford JW (2015) Constructing random
matrices to represent real ecosystems. Am Nat 185:680–692
Janzen T, Haegeman B, Etienne RS (2015) A sampling formula for ecological communities with multiple
dispersal syndromes. J Theor Biol 374:94–106
Jonzén N, Wilcox C, Possingham HP (2004) Habitat selection and population regulation in temporally
fluctuating environments. Am Nat 164:103–114
Letten AD, Ke PJ, Fukami T (2017) Linking modern coexistence theory and contemporary niche theory.
Ecol Monogr 87:161–177
Kadmon R, Allouche O (2007) Integrating the effects of area, isolation, and habitat heterogeneity on spe-
cies diversity: a unification of island biogeography and niche theory. Am Nat 170:443–454
Kalyuzhny M, Seri E, Chocron R, Flather CH, Kadmon R, Shnerb NM (2014) Niche versus neutrality: a
dynamical analysis. Am Nat 184:439–446
Kalyuzhny M, Kadmon R, Shnerb NM (2015) A neutral theory with environmental stochasticity explains
static and dynamic properties of ecological communities. Ecol Lett 18:572–580
Knape J, de Valpine P (2012) Are patterns of density dependence in the global population dynamics data-
base driven by uncertainty about population abundance? Ecol Lett 15:17–23
Kotler BP, Brown JS (1988) Environmental heterogeneity and the coexistence of desert rodents. Annu
Rev Ecol Evol Syst 19:281–307
Krivan V, Cressman R, Schneider C (2008) The ideal free distribution: a review and synthesis of the
game theoretic perspective. Theor Popul Biol 73:403–425
Lakatos I (1978) Falsification and the methodology of scientific research programmes. In: Lakatos I (ed)
The methodology of scientific research programmes. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge, pp
8–101
Lakatos I, Zahar E (1978) Why did Copernicus’s research programme supersede Ptolemy’s? In: Lakatos I
(ed) The methodology of scientific research programmes. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge,
pp 8–101
Laplace PS (1902) A philosophical essay on probabilities, 6th edn. Dover Publications, New York
Leigh EG Jr (2007) The neutral theory: a historical perspective. J Evol Biol 20:2075–2091

13
Does God roll dice? Neutrality and determinism in evolutionary… Page 15 of 16 3

Levin SA (1992) The problem of pattern and scale in ecology: the Robert H. MacArthur Award Lecture.
Ecology 73:1943–1967
Levine JM, HilleRisLambers J (2009) The importance of niches for the maintenance of species diversity.
Nature 461:254–258
MacArthur R (1955) Fluctuations of animal populations and a measure of community stability. Ecology
36:533–536
MacArthur RH (1972) Geographical ecology. Princeton University Press, Princeton
MacArthur R, Levins R (1967) The limiting similarity, convergence, and divergence of coexisting spe-
cies. Am Nat 101:377–385
Martín J, Lopez P (2005) Wall lizards modulate refuge use through continuous assessment of predation
risk level. Ethology 111:207–219
Maruvka YE, Shnerb NM, Kessler DA, Ricklefs RE (2013) Model for macroevolutionary dynamics. Proc
Natl Acad Sci USA 110:E2460–E2469
Matthews TJ, Whittaker RJ (2014) Neutral theory and the species abundance distribution: recent develop-
ments and prospects for unifying niche and neutral perspectives. Ecol Evol 4:2263–2277
May RM (1972) Will a large complex system be stable? Nature 238:413–414
May RM (1974) Stability and complexity in model ecosystems. Princeton University Press, New Jersey
May R (1999) Unanswered questions in ecology. Philos Trans R Soc Lond B Biol Sci 354:1951–1959
Maynard Smith J (1982) Evolution and the theory of games. Cambridge University Press, Cambridge
Mayr E (1977) Darwin and natural selection: how Darwin may have discovered his highly unconventional
theory. Am Sci 65:321–328
McGill BJ, Maurer BA, Weiser MD (2006) Empirical evaluation of neutral theory. Ecology 87:1411–1423
Mitchell WA, Valone TJ (1990) The optimization research program: studying adaptations by their func-
tion. Q Rev Biol 65:43–52
Morris DW (1988) Habitat-dependent population regulation and community structure. Ecol Evol
2:253–269
Munoz F, Huneman P (2016) From the neutral theory to a comprehensive and multiscale theory of eco-
logical equivalence. Q Rev Biol 91:321–342
Nicolson M, McIntosh RP, Nicholson M (2002) H.A. Gleason and the individualistic hypothesis revis-
ited. Bull Ecol Soc Am 83:133–142
Norris S (2003) Neutral theory: a new, unified model for ecology. BioScience 53:124–129
O’Dwyer JP, Chisholm R (2014) A mean field model for competition: from neutral ecology to the Red
Queen. Ecol Lett 17:961–969
Pimm SL (1984) The complexity and stability of ecosystems. Nature 307:321–326
Pimm SL (1991) The balance of nature? Ecological issues in the conservation of species and communi-
ties. University of Chicago Press, Chicago
Rosenzweig ML (1981) A theory of habitat selection. Ecology 62:327–335
Rosindell J, Cornell SJ (2007) Species-area relationships from a spatially explicit neutral model in an
infinite landscape. Ecol Lett 10:586–595
Rosindell J, Cornell SJ (2009) Species-area curves, neutral models, and long-distance dispersal. Ecology
90:1743–1750
Rosindell J, Hubbell SP, Etienne RS (2011) The unified neutral theory of biodiversity and biogeography
at age ten. TREE 26:340–348
Rosindell J, Hubbell SP, He F, Harmon LJ, Etienne RS (2012) The case for ecological neutral theory.
TREE 27:203–208
Russell B (1997) Religion and science, 2nd edn. Oxford University Press, New York
Simberloff D (1978) Using island biogeographic distributions to determine if colonization is stochastic.
Am Nat 112:713–726
Slack NG (2010) G. Evelyn Hutchinson and the invention of modern ecology. Yale University Press, New
Haven
Storch D, Frynta D (1999) Evolution of habitat selection: stochastic acquisition of cognitive clues? Ecol
Evol 13:591–600
Vellend M (2010) Conceptual synthesis in community ecology. Q Rev Biol 85:183–206
Vincent TL, Brown JS (2005) Evolutionary game theory, natural selection, and Darwinian dynamics.
Cambridge University Press, New York
von Humboldt A (1849) Aspects of nature: in different lands and different climates, with scientific eluci-
dations (trans: E. J. Sabine.). Longman, Brown, Green, and Longmans and J. Murray, London

13
3 Page 16 of 16 S. B. Ale et al.

von Neumann J (1947) The works of the mind. In: Heywood RB (ed) The mathematician, vol 1. Univer-
sity of Chicago Press, Chicago, pp 1–9
Welton NJ, McNamara JM, Houston AI (2003) Assessing predation risk: optimal behaviour and rules of
thumb. Theor Popul Biol 64:417–430
Wennekes PL, Rosindell J, Etienne RS (2012) The neutral—niche debate: a philosophical perspective.
Acta Biotheor 60:257–271
White GF (1789) The natural history of Selborne. Penguin, London
Williams GC (1966) Adaptation and natural selection. Princeton University Press, Princeton
Wilson WG, Osenberg CW, Schmitt RJ, Nisbet RM (1999) Complementary foraging behaviors allow
coexistence of two consumers. Ecology 80:2358–2372
Wootton JT (2005) Field parameterization and experimental test of the neutral theory of biodiversity.
Nature 433:309–312
Yodzis P (1981) The stability of real ecosystems. Nature 289:674–676
Ziebarth NL, Abbott KC, Ives AR (2010) Weak population regulation in ecological time series. Ecol Lett
13:21–31

13

You might also like