TURNER, Mike. Constructions and Creativity (2020)

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 18

Cognitive Semiotics 2020; 20202019

Mark Turner*
Constructions and creativity
https://doi.org/10.1515/cogsem-2020-2019

Abstract: The first principle of cognitive linguistics is to look for the origins of
linguistic powers in robust mental operations not specific to language. For millennia,
language science has assumed that human beings possess mental operations for
unifying, combining, and merging patterns to create expressions, and that,
conversely, they can analyze expressions they encounter to recognize patterns that
were combined to produce them. The third section of this article reviews some of the
literature concerned with these powers to combine patterns into expressions and to
analyze expressions into patterns that were blended to create them. Any assumption
about such a linguistic power takes out a loan on theory that must be cashed out with
a non-language-specific explanation if the theory is to count as cognitive. One can
stipulate to the existence of some unexplained power that is needed for linguistic
performance, but that stipulation is insubstantial until it is grounded in a demon-
strated non-language-specific operation. An assumption or stipulation about a lin-
guistic power is cashed out when we locate and model the non-language-specific
cognitive operations that make that linguistic power possible. The first section of this
article presents the proposition that the non-language-specific mental operation that
accounts for these linguistic powers is blending, otherwise known as conceptual
integration. The second section provides a topical review of blending in specific
communicative form-meaning pairs and their combination. Blending is the foun-
dation of creativity in communication, or, more specifically, in the creation and
combining of form-meaning pairs, also called “constructions.”

Keywords: construction grammar, creativity, conceptual integration, blending

1 Blending
Research on blending per se and by that name began in 1992. The first presentation
occurred in 1993 and the first technical report appeared in 1994 (Fauconnier and

*Corresponding author: Mark Turner, Case Western Reserve University, Cleveland, USA,
E-mail: [email protected]
2 M. Turner

Turner 1994). A quarter-century after that first technical report, several million
words at least have been published on blending, in nearly every field that studies
human affairs: art, music, religion, law, decision-making, mathematical insight,
scientific discovery, AI, dance, fashion, advanced tool use, advanced social
cognition, creativity in all fields, and so on. Blending has been the core subject of
several major longitudinal scientific grants in various fields in North America,
South America, Europe, and Asia. Most publications on blending do not treat
language at all. An attempt has been made to list major publications at http://
blending.stanford.edu, but the field is too large to survey. For an overview, see
especially Fauconnier and Turner (2002) and, secondarily, in chronological order,
Turner (1996), Fauconnier (1997), Turner (2001), Fauconnier and Turner (2008),
and Turner (2008, 2011, 2014).
Principal findings of blending theory include the following:
1. While rudimentary blending seems to be available to several species, cogni-
tively modern human beings are a step up the cline. Human command of
advanced blending is indispensable to human creativity. The small extra step
up the cline makes a vast difference in ability and products.
2. For cognitively modern human beings, blending is not at all costly. On the
contrary, it is a constant and almost entirely invisible operation. The cogni-
tively modern human mind is built to attempt to blend when possible. Blending
is opportunistic. Nearly all blending attempts fail almost immediately by failing
to meet the constitutive requirements of building a blending network. The
relatively small number of attempts that survive rarely attach to a purpose or
survive optimality constraints on blending. Few of those actually penetrate to
action (such as expression). Few of those ever enter into consciousness. Very
few of those achieve uptake by the community. Very few of those become
entrenched for a community or a culture.
3. Blending is not a mental pattern with a fixed template or sequence. It is instead
a principled mental operation that can run across any cognitive network that a
human being is activating. Very many different kinds of blending products
have been studied. There are some standard generic patterns of blending that
arise repeatedly, but they are only standouts in the general landscape.
4. Blending work can be done anywhere in the blending network at any instant in
the construction of the network, including in developing various spaces and
developing vital conceptual relations between them.
5. Blending networks recruit from stable structures and can themselves become
stable, widely-shared, and entrenched.
6. Blending networks create emergent structure not only in the blended space but
throughout the network.
Constructions and creativity 3

7. Blending plays a crucial role in everything we tend to view as distinctly human,


and no analysis of higher capacities will be adequate if it leaves blending out of
account. A theory of art, mathematics, science, religion, spirituality, learning,
phylogenetic, human neurobiology, cultural evolution, etc. that leaves
blending out of account is fundamentally flawed. But in the great scheme of
things, the role of blending is still very small. Socially and consciously, we are
often aware of blending phenomena, which we use for social distinctions,
technological advances, aesthetic experience, spirituality, and so on. Accord-
ingly, we notice blending in some cases. But billions of years preceded the
relatively recent evolution of advanced blending; elaborate social and de-
mographic work is needed to exploit the capacity fully. It is easy to make the
mistake of discounting the vast run-up to advanced blending by falling for the
“Last is Everything” fallacy. Advanced blending seems to be evolutionarily
recent, but it is very small relative to what it built upon.
8. Although advanced blending comes last in this evolution of mental operations,
it is not a linear addition but on the contrary changes the way we deploy all
those other mental operations.
9. In the great scheme of things, blending is just one of very many important
mental operations. Blending research is not a reductionist program. There is no
attempt to argue that everything is a variety of blending, or that a particular
mental or social achievement is explained by blending tout court.

Examples used to give an elementary taste of blending need to be recognizable as


blends, if the examples are to be pedagogically effective. Consequently, these ex-
amples are typically pyrotechnic. Such pyrotechnic examples are useful, but insid-
ious, because their visible flashiness misleads students into assuming that blending is
a special, pyrotechnic, unusual, and visible operation instead of what it is: the basic
harmony of the way we think. Blending is almost entirely invisible at first glance.
A chestnut example where the blending is visible is “the riddle of the Buddhist
Monk.” A Buddhist monk in the pre-dawn light, standing for a while at the foot of a
mountain path that leads to the summit, decides to climb the path. He begins at
dawn walking up the mountain, reaches the top at sunset, meditates at the top
overnight until, at dawn, he begins to walk back to the foot of the mountain, which
he reaches at sunset. Make no assumptions about his starting or stopping or about
his pace during the trips. Riddle: is there a place on the path which the monk
occupies at the same hour of the day on the two separate journeys?”
Many people, including trained mathematicians, fail to see the answer quickly
or at all. But separate the action into two mental spaces, one with the monk
ascending and one with the monk descending, both from dawn to dusk, and then
blend them. Think of two videos being superimposed. In the blend, there are two
4 M. Turner

monks, one at the foot of the path and one at the top, and they begin traversing the
path at dawn and finish traversing the path at sunset. We complete the blend with
the knowledge that two people who traverse a path in the same time interval in
opposite directions must, so long as they stay on the path, meet. Given the way the
blend is assembled, the place the monk occupies at the same hour of the day on the
two separate journeys is the spot where “the monk” “meets” “himself” in the
blend. There is selective projection to the blend (calendrical dates are not projected
to the blend, nor is the intentional state of someone who actually encounters
himself, etc.) and there is emergent structure in the blend (two monks, a meeting).
The two paths are fused, as are the two dawns and the two dusks. There are many
complexities to how the blend is assembled. Some of them are reviewed in Turner
(2012), which includes three mathematical proofs, all of them launched by
blending of standard types deployed in mathematics, as reviewed in Alexander
(2011) and Lakoff and Núñez (2000).
A blend is a “mental space” in a conceptual network of potentially many such
mental spaces, in a potentially highly dynamic network, and helps to manage that
conceptual network, including its construction and dynamism. A slightly less
pyrotechnic chestnut example of blending is the “miserable Bay Area stock-
broker.” Consider Bill and Peter, brothers-in-law, each happy. Bill is a mathe-
matically-talented professor in the Eastern time zone who likes both investing and
San Francisco. Peter is a stockbroker in San Francisco. Bill, in the East, wonders,
analogically, should he move to San Francisco and be a stockbroker and get a huge
raise? No: Bill is a night owl but Peter must arise at 5:30 AM Pacific Time to pull
himself together for an hour to then deal with the stock market's opening at
9:30 AM Eastern Time. Peter likes the morning but Bill hates it. Mentally, Bill has
created a new, blended person—Bill-as-Peter, who is miserable. Everyone is happy
in the inputs but the central structure of the conceptual network is the miserable
stockbroker in the blend. That misery is emergent structure. The selectivity of the
projection is crucial. The stockbroker in the blend is not married to his own sister,
even though the person in the blend is a stockbroker married to the woman who is
in fact the sister of the stockbroker in the inputs.
A shockingly creative example which at first almost nobody takes as involving
blending is the chestnut case of the cyclic day (Turner 2014). In our experience, there
is actually just one day and then another day and then another day and then another
day, in a sequence that stretches out indefinitely, forward and backward. The days in
that sequence are all quite different. They do not repeat. If we woke up today and it
was exactly the same as yesterday because it was in fact the same day in every detail,
we would be sure we had lost our minds. And then it would not even be the same
day, because yesterday we did not think we had lost our minds. Day after day after
day, indefinitely, with all those differences between days, is too much to
Constructions and creativity 5

comprehend, too much to fit inside working memory, too much to carry around and
manage. It is not mentally portable. So, we blend these different days into a
conception of a cyclic day. We do this by using a very common general blending
template. There are analogies and disanalogies across the different days in our
experience. The analogies are packed into one thing in the blend: the day. The
disanalogies are packed into change for that thing: The day is cyclic; it starts over
every dawn and repeats. No one of the individual input days to the cyclic day blend is
cyclic; no one of those individual input days repeats or starts over. But because of
blending, all the days that have ever happened or will happen can be packed into a
single idea, a tight, tractable, manageable, human-scale idea — the cyclic day, which
repeats. Thinking of the cyclic day, we can say, “dawn is coming around again,” “it's
time for my morning coffee,” or “this park closes at dusk.” We know how these words
and concepts apply to the compact blend, and we can unpack from that blend to any
parts of the mental web that interest us, to any day at any time, and even to a
tractable stretch of days. The cyclic day is a compact touchstone, a congenial blend
for thinking about the vast sequence of days. This vast sequence of days is of course
itself too big for working memory. The compact blend — the single cyclic day, a new
idea — makes it possible for us to work with concepts of time that stretch far beyond
what we would otherwise be able to manage.
The riddle of the Buddhist Monk is not solved by abstracting what is common to
the ascent and the descent. The miserable stockbroker is not imagined by abstracting
what is common to the two brothers-in-law. The cyclic day is not conceived by
abstracting what is common to every day (none of which repeats). Other chestnut
examples from Fauconnier and Turner (2002) and the other introductory texts cited
above demonstrate a vast range of blending in which the constructed meaning is not
an abstraction over inputs but goes far beyond it (see, e. g., the chestnut analysis of
“dinosaurs turned into birds”). Blending is very complicated.

2 Blending at work in specific communicative


patterns
To know a language is to know a relational network of form-meaning pairs and
how they blend to produce expressions. Form-meaning pairs are often referred to
as “constructions.” Speakers mentally combine various form-meaning pairs to
construct completely specified communicative performances and enact them.
Such a performance is commonly referred to as a “construct.”
Language science needs a theory of creativity to account for:
6 M. Turner

1. Relatively quick (fewer than thousands of years, which of course includes


anything down to milliseconds), non-species-wide creation of a form-meaning
pair, at any point in human descent;
2. The blending of form-meaning pairs to create expressions, or more generally,
communicative performances (“constructs”);
3. The creation of novel form-meaning pairs, using established ones as inputs,
whether or not these new form-meaning pairs become entrenched to some
degree;
4. The phylogenetic origin of language;
5. The ontogenetic acquisition of language.

The remainder of this section gives some examples of constructions that have
received blending analyses.

2.1 Conditionals

Linguistic expressions for building “possibility” mental spaces (Fauconnier 1985)


— e. g., “if I were a stockbroker, like my brother-in-law” — are routinely used to
prompt for blending networks, as analyzed at length in Fauconnier and Turner
(2002) and Dancygier and Sweetser (2005, 2012). If-then conditional constructions
are one of the most obvious aspects of grammar used to prompt for blending, but
there are many others, e. g., “I could be a stockbroker.”

2.2 Change predicates

We saw in the example of the cyclic day the use of a generic template according to
which vital relations of analogy and disanalogy across mental spaces in a mental
web are compressed in the blend to provide a human-scale concept. The analogical
connections between input spaces are compressed to an identity or unity in the
blend, and the disanalogical connections are compressed to change for that
element in the blend. Naturally, grammar for expressing change becomes avail-
able to the blend. We say that “evolutionarily, dinosaurs turned into birds” and
expect the hearer not to think we mean that some dinosaurs actually turned into
birds; rather, we expect the hearer to understand that the change for “dinosaurs”
in the blend unpacks to vital relations of analogy and disanalogy across the very
many inputs. In the blend, there is an identity, a group identity, consisting of
dinosaurs, and this identity “changes” into a different group identity, birds (Fau-
connier and Turner 2002). Such change predicates have been widely analyzed in
the literature (Tobin 2010).
Constructions and creativity 7

2.3 The ground and blended grounds

Deictics and, more broadly, indexicals — such as I, you, here, and now — are form-
meaning pairs tied to elements in the conceptual frame of the ground (Langacker
1985: 113, 1986). Their utility depends on our ability to do what Fauconnier and
Turner (2002) refer to as “simplex blending.” A simplex blend is one in which one
input mental space is an established conceptual frame and the other input spaces
contain elements of just the sort to which the conceptual frame is expected to
apply. For example, if one mental space has the kinship frame father-child and
another mental space has two people, Paul and Mary, then the blended space can
blend Paul with father and Mary with child and we can prompt for this blend by
saying “Paul is Mary's father.”

2.4 Viewpoint

Viewpoint arises inevitably from embodiment: participants in any scene of


communicative joint attention are embodied and blending projects selectively
from viewpoints in the input mental spaces to the blend (Sweetser 2012).
Recanati (1995) analyzes the way in which what he calls “the epistolary
present” expresses a blended temporal viewpoint belonging to the blended joint
attention that arises for personal correspondence. In the blend, writer and reader
are present in the moment and jointly attending, although they know that outside
the blend in the mental web organized by the blend they are in different times and
conditions. Turner (1996) analyzes other temporal viewpoint blends, as when the
wife, headed to the shower, says to her husband (who has asked how a certain
task will be accomplished), “my husband took care of that while I was in the
shower.”
Nikiforidou (2010, 2012) analyzes the role of blending in a construction she
calls “Past tense + proximal deictic,” with emphasis on the cases where the
proximal deictic is now. The preferred patterns are “was/were + now,” as in “it was
now possible … ” and, for a non-copula verb, “now + past tense,” as in “he now
saw that … ” Nikiforidou provides “a detailed blueprint of the blending mappings
cued by the [past + proximal deictic] pattern” (2012: 177).

2.5 Polysemy

The mechanisms reviewed in the previous sections receive a generalized analysis


in Fauconnier and Turner (2002) to explain polysemy as a consequence of
8 M. Turner

blending. Some of the products of such blending strike hearers as “metaphoric” for
reasons analyzed in Turner (1996).

2.6 X is the Y of Z

All constructions prompt for blending, but certain constructions are specialized to
serve as prompts for blending over all conceptual domains. Consider Turner's
(1987) analysis in Death is the Mother of Beauty of conceptual connections and their
integration. Its data consisted of uses of kinship terms, such as “mother.” The
sentential construction involved in “death is the mother of beauty” is the “X is the Y
of Z” construction. This XYZ construction has routine everyday use, as in “Paul is
the father of Sally.” It has been analyzed by Turner (1991, 1996) and Fauconnier
and Turner (2002). These analyses include models of other grammatical con-
structions tightly related to the XYZ construction.

2.7 Single words and morphemes

There are many linguistic prompts for blending that are narrower in application.
Safe, for example, said of some situation, prompts us to blend that situation with
the frame of harm, understand that the blend is counterfactual with respect to the
original situation, and now blend the original situation and the counterfactual
blend so that the counterfactual relation between them is compressed to absence of
harm as emergent structure in the blend, understood as a property, safe, that can
be signaled by an adjective. Other single words prompting for particular blending
templates include danger, lucky, accident, mistake, gap, dent, missing, detour, and
many others. A single sentence can contain many such words, calling for many
such compressions, as in the National Public Radio warning a few days before
Halloween, October 2000, “a Halloween costume that limits sight or movement is
an accident lurking in disguise.” Turner (2008) analyzes the range of blending
compressions involved in the morphemes over and under. Nili Mandelblit analyzes
the use of morphological inflection of a main verb to prompt for blends of the frame
of an action with the frame of causation (reviewed in Fauconnier and Turner 2002).

2.8 Adjective + noun

Consider adjectives, such as those in guilty pleasures, likely candidate, and red ball.
Notice that “likely candidate” (Eve Sweetser's example) is usually used to refer to
Constructions and creativity 9

someone who is not (yet) a candidate. In that case, we are not composing the
meaning of candidate and the meaning of likely. On the contrary, we are taking
candidate from one mental space and likely from a mental space that includes a
particular kind of frame. “Likely candidate” can be taken as prompting us to
construct a blended frame in which there is someone who is likely to become a
candidate. In “allow yourself this guilty pleasure” and “chocolate is a guilty plea-
sure,” it is not the pleasure itself that is guilty. Rather, it is the person who has the
pleasure who feels guilty. In this case, there is a cause-effect vital relation between
the input spaces — having the pleasure in one space causes the guilt in the other.
But now, that outer-space cause-effect relationship is compressed in the blend into
a feature of the pleasure. There are many similar examples, such as grateful
memories. The memories are not grateful. The person who has the memories is
grateful for the events to which the memories refer. But now that intentional
relationship between the person and the person's memories and the events to
which they refer is compressed into a feature of the memories in the blend.

2.9 Basic clauses

Fauconnier and Turner (1994) build on Goldberg (1995) to analyze the ways in
which basic clausal constructions like caused-motion, resultative, and ditransitive
prompt for blending basic and familiar human-scale frames with sometimes large
mental webs in order to produce compressed blends that can be expressed with the
clausal form projected to the blend. The result is expressions that use verbs suited
to other mental spaces in the web but not necessarily to caused-motion, resulta-
tive, or ditransitive frames. Parade examples of the caused-motion construction
include “he sneezed the napkin off the table” and “she drank him under the table.”
Others are “the officer waved the tanks into the compound,” “Junior sped the car
around the Christmas tree” (where the verb comes from the manner of the caused
motion), “I read him to sleep,” “I muscled the box into place,” and “Hunk choked
the life out of him.” The case is similar for the resultative construction, the cit-
ransitive construction, and other clausal constructions.

2.10 Blended syntax

Blends frequently have new emergent structure, but because linguistic construc-
tions attached to the input spaces in the mental web can be projected down to be
used of the blend to express that emergent structure, it is rare that new linguistic
constructions are needed in order to express meaning, and a good thing, too. But
blending also provides a mechanism for creating emergent structure for the form
part of a form-meaning pair.
10 M. Turner

Fillmore and Atkins (1992) presented the classic analysis of the verb risk, its
syntax, and its meaning. In effect, Fillmore and Atkins analyze the lexical meaning
of risk as a set of frame blends, as reviewed in Turner (2015).
Fauconnier and Turner (2002) analyze nominal compounding as blended
syntax, in which one noun is taken from each of two blended spaces, and the blend
is expressed by a syntactic structure noun + noun, which still counts as a noun
phrase and so can combine in the usual ways with constructions that call for a
noun phrase. Fauconnier and Turner (1994, 2002) also provide an elaborate
analysis of French double-verb causatives as an example of emergent syntax under
blending.

3 Related work on blending in communication


Graph theory provides mathematical tools for crafting formal representations of
patterns of various types, determining relationships (such as subsumption) between
those formalizations, and unifying those formalizations. Graph theory is the foun-
dation of formal approaches in unification grammars (Shieber 1995) such as Func-
tional Unification Grammar, Definite-Clause Grammars, Lexical-Function Grammar,
Generalized Phrase Structure Grammar, and Head-Driven Phrase Structure
Grammar. Unification grammars typically represent a construction as an attribute-
value matrix (AVM), and in fact an AVM is simply an object in graph theory.
Many readers will be familiar with the extraordinarily influential work on
AVMs in the never published but legendary Construction Grammar Coursebook by
Charles Fillmore and Paul Kay, such as the AVM for the lexical construction shoe,

a very simplified AVM for the subject-predicate construction,


Constructions and creativity 11

and the “unified” AVM representing the construct that is the sentence “trout relish
worms.”

In graph theory, an AVM is an instance of a Directed Acyclic Graph (DAG) (Harary


1969). DAGs can be unified in graph theory through certain established algorithms.
A unification of two DAGs is the most general graph that includes all the infor-
mation in all of the inputs, if it exists.
The operation postulated as Merge in the Minimalist Program (Chomsky 1999)
is to a great extent a notational variant of DAG unification in graph theory. (Of
course, AVM unification in unification grammars operates over various assumed
types of structure — syntactic, semantic, pragmatic, phonological, etc. — while
Merge in the Minimalist Program is restricted to syntactic objects.) Both DAG
unification and Merge embrace recursion.
DAG unification and Merge are interesting theoretically, but the major ques-
tion from blending theory is: what is the cognitive basis for stipulating that DAG
unification or Merge are human capacities? Certainly, human beings can do such
things, but stipulating that they can do so takes out a loan of theory that needs,
from a cognitive perspective, to be cashed out: what is the non-linguistic mental
operation that makes these linguistic powers possible? The assertion of the present
article is that the indispensable mental operation is blending.
To be sure, even if we are concerned only with language behavior rather than
cognition generally, blending theory has an objection to such DAG unification
approaches. They are indeed handy if the goal is to craft algorithmic processes for
natural language processing: the mathematical theory and computational prac-
tices are strong and productive. But DAG unification models are bad as linguistic
theory, because they do not have room for selective projection and emergent
structure, argued to be indispensable in the blending analyses of linguistic phe-
nomena, some of which are mentioned in the preceding section of this article. Most
important, DAG unification and Merge do not account for the creativity we see in
the origin of form-meaning pairs, the ontogenetic acquisition and development of
form-meaning pairs, the phylogenetic development of form-meaning pairs, and
the creation of new form-meaning pairs. A theory that does not account for such
12 M. Turner

creativity is not a theory of human language, although it might, and manifestly


often does, provide structure for the development of efficient and useful natural
language processing tools.
The justification for stipulating the existence of a process in a scientific model
is usually that such a scientific generalization allows us to “explain” a great deal in
a compendious fashion, one that is not deeply disconfirmed by vast stretches of
available evidence. The successful generalization is one that applies aptly to
ranges of data that were not in the original data the contemplation of which led to
the original hypothesis of the scientific generalization. This is the justification
upon which the assertion of operations like DAG unification rests. Blending theory
also asserts this justification, and additionally argues that it does a better job of
accounting for the evidence, such as the evidence for various kinds of invention,
innovation, and creativity. But there is a second justification, the principal
emphasis of this article, that blending asserts: it does not stipulate the existence of
language-specific mental operations, leaving it to cognitive scientists and psy-
chologists and neuroscientists to go and locate them. On the contrary, the exis-
tence of blending and of its mechanisms is asserted on the basis of broad analysis
of evidence from non-linguistic thought and action. Blending theory does not need
to stipulate to the existence of a linguistic operation with certain powers in order to
account for language; on the contrary, it adduces one that has already been
analyzed outside of language science.
Within cognitive and functional approaches to language, there are repeated
presentations of processes of language that look much like blending. The most
prominent and thorough of these theories is Cognitive Grammar (Langacker 2006).
Langacker writes, for example, that “one constructional schema can be incorpo-
rated as a component of another” (ibid.: 46). These many analyses include con-
siderations of coercion when two units combine (Taylor 2002: 287), partial
sanctioning of a unit, and extension and innovation during the combination of
units (Langacker 2008: 215–255). The thorough attention to varieties of unification
and combining is present in Cognitive Grammar from its earliest days. For
example, in his landmark 1986 introduction to the field in Cognitive Science (1986),
Langacker writes,

When a head combines with a modifier, for example, it is the profile of the head that prevails
at the composite-structure level. (Ibid.: 13)

Each sense of ring […] combines with the phonological unit [ring] to constitute a symbolic
unit. (Ibid.: 18)

An auxiliary verb, either have or be, combines with the atemporal predication and contributes
the requisite sequential scanning. (Ibid.: 27)
Constructions and creativity 13

A modifier is a conceptually dependent predication that combines with a head, whereas a


complement is a conceptually autonomous predication that combines with a head. (Ibid.: 34)

[Of the sentences “liver likes Alice” and “Alice likes liver”] It should be apparent, however,
that the same composite structure will result if the constituents combine in the opposite
order, with Alice elaborating the schematic trajector of likes, and then liver the schematic
landmark of Alice likes. This alternative constituency is available for exploitation, with no
effect on grammatical relations, whenever special factors motivate departure from the
default-case arrangement. (Ibid.: 35)

It may be that Langacker and other cognitive and functional linguists would agree
(no doubt with illumination or objection, and only to a certain extent) that such
analyses presuppose general cognitive mechanisms not specific to language and
that indeed the chief one they presuppose is blending.
In response to this section, Langacker writes (p.c., and published here with his
permission):

I fully agree that CG “analyses presuppose general cognitive mechanisms not specific to
language and that indeed the chief one they presuppose is blending.” I have long taken it for
granted that conceptual and grammatical structures can be characterized in terms of map-
pings between mental spaces, and in particular, that ‘composition’ amounts to (bipolar)
blending. This conforms to my traditional description that component structures are ‘inte-
grated’ to form the composite whole. Perhaps because it is so evident, I have not made the
connection to conceptual integration theory as explicit as I perhaps should have done. Here is
one succinct statement: “In composition, component structures undergo conceptual inte-
gration to form a composite structure that is more than just the sum of its parts” (Langacker
2017, 118). Slightly more elaborate indications of the affinity are found in Langacker (2009: 47)
and (Langacker 2015: 135–136).

4 Multimodal communicative blending


To know a language is to know a relational network of form-meaning pairs and
how they blend to produce expressions. More generally, to know a communicative
system is to know a relational network of form-meaning pairs and how they blend
to produce (actually performable) constructs. Part of the reason that we can un-
derstand text is that we can simulate mentally, in the backstage of cognition, a
whole human performance whose language we would write down as that text. This
is easy to demonstrate: if we hand anyone a text to read aloud, for example, they
will do so with a great range of auditory and bodily performance that is nowhere
“encoded” in the text but that seems to them obviously to be part of its actual
performance. It is an oversight to claim that these aspects of performance are
irrelevant to the text on the ground that we do not have to perceive them to
14 M. Turner

understand the text. What we do not perceive we may well imagine. All under-
standing happens in the hearers, not in the texts.
There are many forms — auditory, visual, and textual — that we take to have a
special relationship to a language, traditionally considered. But blending of forms
that have communicative function is quite general; this blending for communication
includes co-speech gesture broadly considered; the use of material affordances in
the environment as props broadly considered; and a great range of auditory, visual,
and motor performances, including pauses, laughter, clicks, taps, shoves, pokes,
winks, nods, singing, whistling, cartoons, movies, music, television news, and on
and on. Theoretically, we draw distinctions between performances in this ocean of
performance and are unlikely to agree to homogenize all such form-meaning pairs
and their blends to the same communicative status. But the general theory of form-
meaning pairs and their blends applies to all such performances (Turner 2018).
Consider a chestnut example (used inter alia in Turner 2018) of creative
blending in language: someone sees a termite doing something to wood. The
meaning attached to the form “food” certainly does not include wood, but people
can make a blend of a person eating food and what the termite is doing to the wood.
This blend is not an algorithmic unification of these two quite different input
spaces, but instead a new mental space constructed through selective projection
from these inputs and conceptual elaboration to produce emergent structure in the
blend. Crucially, forms that apply to any of the input spaces (and there can be
many) can be projected to the blend to pick out corresponding meaning there,
despite its not conforming to the meaning in the input from which it was projected.
The wood can now be referred to as “food.”
In the same way, the young child who sees a lion at the zoo for the first time can
point and say “kitty” to the delight of charmed adults. As analyzed in Fauconnier
and Turner (2002), projection and blending of forms to refer to meaning developed
in new situations solves the problem of equipotentiality.
Nesset et al. (2013: 229) explores linguistic creativity under blending by
looking at a corpus of TV news clips in Russian and in English and investigating the
use of the five Russian deictic words that correspond to the English meanings ‘here’
and ‘now:’ zdes', tut, sejčas, teper' and vot. These are forms with routine if quite
complicated use in actual scenes of face-to-face classic joint attention (Turner
2017). They acquire slightly different sets of distributions for TV news. The English
and Russian words acquire in the usage domain of TV network news distinct radial
category profiles, in the sense that they display different centers of gravity in the
semantic network. The authors propose the “Minimal Adaptation Hypothesis,”
according to which “language makes adaptations that are as small as possible
when applied to a new setting, such as the one created by TV” (Nesset et al. 2013:
229). This is unrecognized but impressive creativity.
Constructions and creativity 15

This creativity is open-ended. In the case of web tutorials, the tutor can say “If
you have any questions about getting the data from your old hard drive to your
new hard drive, we made a video for you that covers the process, and we will link
to it, right there” and points to and looks at the word “HERE” which appears
suddenly in the blended ground when she points and says “there.” The printed
word “HERE” is a form, and we know that its deployment in the blend carries the
new, creative meaning that clicking on the visible spot directs a web browser to
the linked URL.
Accordingly, the form “HERE” acquires a new meaning for the blend that it
does not otherwise have. Turner (2017) discusses such creativity through blending
for a range of linguistic forms, from lexical to clausal.
The need for cognitive (as opposed to merely linguistic) models of communi-
cation is suggested by a range of recent publications, such as the articles in the
2017 special issue of Linguistic Vanguard: Towards a Multimodal Construction
Grammar (Zima and Bergs 2017). The author views proposals in that volume as
potentially inspiring for the development of blending theory and takes as a starting
point for further research that those approaches are compatible with the blending
approach but less specific as models and less general in range of application.
Additionally, the author takes the view, based on many extended conversations
consistently over a period of more than 40 years with Charles Filmore, that a
blending approach is compatible with most of his view of Construction Grammar,
although explicitly and sometimes (notably in conferences and workshops at
Berkeley) publicly contrary to the unification approach maintained by his
collaborator Paul Kay, specifically on blending's fundamental assertion of the
pervasive role of both selective projection from inputs and emergent structure in the
blend. The blending approach has been discussed publicly and privately with
Adele Goldberg when she was on the faculty at UC San Diego in 1992–1993 and
many times since. Her exemplary career in Construction Grammar has deservedly
inspired a strong international following, and it would be good for linguistics to
arrange for a consideration of whether there are any incompatibilities between her
tradition and the blending analyses.

5 Conclusion
In 1996, in a chapter titled “Language” in The Literary Mind: The Origins of Thought
and Language, I argued that “Cognitive mechanisms whose existence we must
grant independent of any analysis of grammar can account for the origin of
grammar” (Turner 1996: 141). That argument showcased blending in the creation of
constructions and the combining of constructions and in human linguistic
16 M. Turner

innovation. The present article maintains that claim, more than 20 years later, but
this time cites some of the work on blending in language and communication done
recently. This article does not claim that any specific analysis of a specific linguistic
phenomenon in the literature should be discarded or displaced by a blending
approach, or that processes that look much like blending have not been discussed
widely by language scientists during the last three thousand years. On the con-
trary, those many stipulations of linguistic processes need, in order to count as
cognitive linguistics, a grounding in mental operations whose existence and power
we must grant independent of any analysis of grammar. My claim is that the
obvious candidate for this cognitive anchoring is blending. To be sure, in the
conversation between theory of blending and theory of linguistic phenomena,
there will be many detailed moments of analytic contest. Contest is indispensable
to the progress of science. Properly conducted, it will strengthen and improve both
blending theory and cognitive linguistics.

References
Alexander, James C. 2011. Blending in mathematics. Semiotica 187. 1–48.
Chomsky, Noam. 1999. Derivation by Phase. Cambridge: MIT Press.
Dancygier, Barbara & Eve, Sweetser. 2005. Mental spaces in grammar: conditional constructions.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Dancygier, Barbara & Eve, Sweetser (eds.). 2012. Viewpoint in language: A multimodal
perspective. Cambridge UK: Cambridge University Press.
Fauconnier, Gilles. 1985. Mental Spaces: Aspects of Meaning Construction in Natural Language.
Cambridge: MIT Press.
Fauconnier, Gilles. 1997. Mappings in Thought and Language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Fauconnier, Gilles & Mark B. Turner. 1994. Conceptual Projection and Middle Spaces. San Diego:
UCSD Department of Cognitive Science Technical Report 9401.
Fauconnier, Gilles & Mark B. Turner. 2002. The Way We Think: Conceptual Blending and the Mind's
Hidden Complexities. New York: Basic Books.
Fauconnier, Gilles & Mark B. Turner. 2008. Rethinking metaphor. In Raymond W. Gibbs (ed.),
Cambridge Handbook of Metaphor and Thought, 53–66. New York: Cambridge University
Press.
Goldberg, Adele. E. 1995. Constructions: A construction grammar approach to argument structure
constructions. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Harary, Frank. 1969. Graph Theory. Boulder: Westview Press.
Lakoff, George & Rafael Núñez. 2000. Where Mathematics Comes from: How the Embodied Mind
Brings Mathematics into Being. New York: Basic Books.
Langacker, Ronald W. 1985. Observations and speculations on subjectivity. In John Haiman (ed.),
Iconicity in syntax, 109–150. Amsterdam and Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
Langacker, Ronald W. 1986. An introduction to cognitive grammar. Cognitive Science 10. 1–40.
Langacker, Ronald W. 2006. Cognitive grammar. In Dirk Geeraerts (ed.), Cognitive Linguistics:
Basic Readings, 29–67. Berlin: Mouton de Gruyter.
Constructions and creativity 17

Langacker, Ronald W. 2008. Cognitive Grammar: A Basic Introduction. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Langacker, Ronald W. Metonymic grammar. In Klaus-Uwe Panther, Linda L. Thornburg & Antonio
Barcelona (eds.), Metonymy and Metaphor in Grammar, 45–71. Amsterdam and
Philadelphia: John Benjamins.
Langacker, Ronald W. 2015. Construal. In Ewa Dąbrowska & Dagmar Divjak (eds.), Handbook of
Cognitive Linguistics, 120–143. Berlin and Boston: De Gruyter Mouton.
Langacker, Ronald W. 2017. Ten Lectures on the Elaboration of Cognitive Grammar. Distinguished
Lectures in Cognitive Linguistics. Leiden and Boston: Brill.
Nikiforidou, Kiki. 2010. Viewpoint and Construction Grammar: The case of past + now. Language
and Literature 19(2). 265–284.
Nikiforidou, Kiki. 2012. The constructional underpinnings of viewpoint blends: The past + now in
language and literature. In Barbara Dancygier & Ewe Sweetser (eds.), Viewpoint in Language:
A Multimodal Perspective, 177–197. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Nesset, Tore, A. Endresen, L. Janda, A. Makarova, F. Steen & M. Turner. 2013. How here and now in
Russian and English establish joint attention in TV news broadcasts. Russian Linguistics 37.
229–251.
Recanati, F. 1995. Le present epistolaire: Une perspective cognitive. L’Information grammaticale
66. 38–44.
Shieber, Stuart M. 1995. An Introduction to Unification-based Approaches to Grammar.
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Sweetser, Eve. 2012. Introduction: Viewpoint and perspective in language and gesture, from the
Ground down. In Dancygier and Sweetser 2012. 25–46.
Taylor, John R. 2002. Cognitive grammar. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Tobin, Vera. 2010. Grammatical and rhetorical consequences of entrenchment in conceptual
blending: Compressions involving change. In Fey Parrill, Vera Tobin & Mark B. Turner (eds.),
Meaning, Form, and Body. Stanford: Center for the Study of Language and Information.
Turner, Mark. 1987. Death is the mother of beauty: Mind, metaphor. Criticism: University of
Chicago Press.
Turner, Mark. 1991. Reading minds: The study of English in the age of cognitive science. Princeton
University Press.
Turner, Mark B. 1996. The lIterary Mind: the Origins of Thought and Language. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Turner, Mark B. 2001. Cognitive Dimensions of Social Science: the Way We Think About politics,
Economics, Law, and Society. New York: Oxford University Press.
Turner, Mark B. 2008. The mind is an autocatalytic vortex. In Jürgen Schlaege (ed.), REAL:
Yearbook of Research in English and American Literature, vol. 24: The Literary Mind, 13–43.
Tübingen: Gunter Narr Verlag.
Turner, Mark B. 2011. Ten Lectures on Mind and Language. Eminent Linguists Lecture Series.
Beijing: FLTR Press.
Turner, Mark B. 2012. Mental packing and unpacking in mathematics. In Mariana Bockarova,
Marcel Danesi & Rafael Núñez (eds.), Semiotic and Cognitive Science Articles on the Nature of
Mathematics, 248–267. Munich: Lincom Europa.
Turner, Mark B. 2014. The Origin of Ideas: Blending, Creativity, and the Human Spark. New York:
Oxford University Press.
Turner, Mark B. 2015. Blending in language and communication. In Ewa Dąbrowska & Dagmar
Divjak (eds.), Handbook of Cognitive Linguistics, 211–232. Berlin: De Gruyter Mouton.
18 M. Turner

Turner, Mark B. 2017. Multimodal form-meaning pairs for blended classic joint attention.
Linguistics Vanguard 3(1). https://doi.org/10.1515/lingvan-2016-0043.
Turner, Mark B. 2018. The role of creativity in multimodal Construction Grammar. Zeitschrift für
Anglistik und Amerikanistik 66(3). 357–370.
Zima, Elisabeth & Alexander Bergs (eds.), 2017. Linguistics Vanguard 3(1). Special Issue: Towards
a Multimodal Construction Grammar.

Bionote
Mark Turner
Case Western Reserve University, Cleveland, USA

Mark Turner is Institute Professor and Professor of Cognitive Science at Case Western Reserve
University and Doctor Honoris Causa in Linguistics from the Université de Haute-Alsace. His books
include The Origin of Ideas: Blending, Creativity, and the Human Spark and The Literary Mind: The
Origins of Thought and Language, from Oxford University Press. He directs the Cognitive Science
Network and co-directs Red Hen Lab, dedicated to big data science of multimodal communication.

Special Issue: Construction Grammar and Creativity edited by Thomas Hoffmann

You might also like