Matthewson (2016) Modality
Matthewson (2016) Modality
Matthewson (2016) Modality
Modality
Lisa Matthewson
18.1 Introduction
There are an infinite number of ways the world could have been. For exam-
ple, my first name happens to be Lisa, but my parents could have named me
Super Princess Lisa Superhero Easter Bunny.1 Another way to say this is there
are some possible worlds (Lewis, 1973) where my name is Super Princess
Lisa Superhero Easter Bunny. Natural language allows us to say all kinds of
things about these possible worlds – such as My parents should have named me
Super Princess Lisa Superhero Easter Bunny, or If my parents had named me Super
Princess Lisa Superhero Easter Bunny, I would have been angry at them. The ability
to talk about possible worlds is known as modal displacement (von Fintel
and Gillies, 2011, who follow Hockett’s (1960) discussion of temporal and
spatial displacement).
Modal displacement is, as far as we know, unique to human language,
universal to all languages, and acquired early. English-acquiring two-year-
olds freely talk about what is permitted, obligated, or compatible with some-
one’s abilities; they say things like you can’t get it till it’s Mother’s Day,2 he just
can borrow him,3 or you have to be quiet so she can sleep,4 and we expect that
1
Thanks to Madeleine Davis (p.c.) for the name idea.
2
www.youtube.com/watch?v=YQ9vv4CPzcY&feature=related.
3 4
www.youtube.com/watch?v=NDLK6dopfuc. www.youtube.com/watch?v=4Y5nbStIjeI.
526 L I S A M AT T H E W S O N
5
Abbreviations in this chapter not covered by the Leipzig Glossing Rules: ii : series ii pronoun, circ :
circumstantial, cn : common noun connective, cust : customary aspect, deic : deictic, deon : deontic, dir :
directive transitivizer, emph : emphatic, epis : epistemic modal, exis : assertion of existence, infer : inferential
evidential, lex : lexical particle, mid : middle, mod : modal, necess : necessity modal, nonaff : non-affirmative,
pn : proper name, possib : possibility modal, prosp : prospective aspect, sens.non.vis : sensory non-visual
evidential, s.pl : plural subject, stat : stative, vai : intransitive animate verb, val : valency adjuster, vti :
transitive inanimate verb.
Modality 527
(3) Context: The Youth Orchestra is holding auditions. At one point the
conductor says:
Madeleine can put her violin away now.
(4) Context: Madeleine is three and has recently started violin lessons. At first, she
wasn’t able to put her violin away in its case because she wasn’t strong enough
to loosen the bow. But she has grown stronger.
Madeleine can put her violin away now.
(7) a. Madeleine can put her violin away now (but she can also keep
playing if she wants).
b. Madeleine must/has to put her violin away now (#but she can also
keep playing if she wants).
We have seen so far that the truth values of modal assertions depend on the
world in which they are uttered, because the set of worlds quantified over
is narrowed down by a set of propositions which are true in the evaluation
world. In a similar fashion, their truth values depend on the time at which
they are uttered. Suppose, for example, that the conductor’s actual-world
rules require that each auditioner play at least one piece and two scales. At
time t, Madeleine has played one piece and no scales, and five minutes later
at t , she has played two scales as well. Sentence (3) would be false at t, and
true at t , because at t Madeleine’s putting her violin away is not compatible
with the conductor’s actual rules, but at t , it is. Moreover, the propositions
6
Except when it appears under negation; see Palmer (2001, p. 103) and McCormack and Smith (2002,
p. 135), among others.
7
This is a simplification; see Section 18.2.1.
Modality 529
we use to narrow the worlds quantified over can change over time: the con-
ductor could change her rules from one minute to the next, or a person’s
abilities could change.
Just like modal flavour and modal force, modal–temporal interactions can
be lexically restricted. More often, however, they are influenced by tense or
aspect functional heads; this is especially easy to see in languages where
modals overtly inflect for these categories. The Dutch data in (8) show that
past marking on the modal auxiliary causes the modal to be evaluated at
some past time.
(8) a. we moeten winnen
we must.prs.1pl win.inf
‘We have to win.’
(In all worlds compatible with our obligations or goals at the
utterance time, we win.)
b. we moesten winnen
we must.pst.1pl win.inf
‘We had to win.’
(In all worlds compatible with our obligations or goals at some past
time, we win.)
c. we kunnen winnen
we can.prs.1pl win.inf
‘We are able to win.’
(In some world compatible with our abilities at the utterance time,
we win.)
d. we konden winnen
we can.pst.1pl win.inf
‘We were able to win.’
(In some world compatible with our abilities at some past time, we
win.)
(Hotze Rullmann, p.c.)
Our discussion so far has been completely informal and has also been sim-
plified. The first way in which it has been simplified is that we have bluntly
talked about modal flavour. However, one of Kratzer’s important proposals
is that modal flavour comprises two separate parameters – called ‘conversa-
tional backgrounds’ – a modal base and at least one ordering source. In Sec-
tion 18.2.1 we briefly review the motivation for this double relativity of
modals, and in Section 18.2.2 we discuss where the conversational back-
grounds come from. Section 18.2.3 presents some cross-linguistic data, and
Section 18.2.4 discusses ongoing debate about the status of the epistemic–
circumstantial division in conversational backgrounds.
530 L I S A M AT T H E W S O N
(10) Context: The conductor’s rules state that auditioners play at least one piece
and two scales, they play no more than five scales, and they play everything
from memory. When Jane auditions, she uses sheet music rather than playing
from memory. Now it’s Madeleine’s turn and she has played one piece and two
scales.
a. Madeleine must stop playing now.
b. Madeleine can stop playing now.
We want to predict that (10a) is false and (10b) is true. The simple system so
far predicts the reverse. The problem is that the conversational background
lumps together propositions describing the rules with propositions describ-
ing Jane’s actions, and the resulting set of propositions is inconsistent (there
are no worlds in which all the rules are obeyed and in which Jane disobeyed
the rules). Since there are no worlds to quantify over, the universal quantifi-
cation in (10a) is trivially true, and the existential quantification in (10b) is
false.
A second problem with the simple system is that it has no way to deal
with graded modality, as in (11).
8
I assume a basic familiarity with semantic formalism, approximately to the level of Heim and Kratzer (1998).
9
Propositions are sets of worlds (the worlds in which the proposition is true), so a set of propositions is a set
of sets of worlds. The intersection of those sets of worlds gives the set of worlds in which all the
propositions are true.
Modality 531
The solution to all these problems is that modals are interpreted relative
to two conversational backgrounds: a modal base and at least one ordering
source. The modal base assigns to each world a set of propositions which are
true in that world, and the ordering source assigns to each world a (possibly
inconsistent) set of propositions representing, for example, norms, ideals,
laws, desires. The set of worlds in which all the modal base propositions are
true is then ordered according to how many of the ordering source propo-
sitions are true in each world, and the modal quantifies over only the most
ideal worlds as identified by the ordering source.
The ordering determined by a set of propositions A is defined in (13): w is
at least as close as z to the ideal determined by A if and only if all proposi-
tions in A that are true in z are also true in w.
If we assume for the purposes of simplicity that there is always a world (or
set of worlds) which comes closer to the ideal than any other worlds (i.e., we
adopt the Limit Assumption), we can define an operator which selects the
‘best’ worlds, and then have the modals quantify only over these. Examples
(14) and (15) draw on von Fintel and Gillies (2011, p. 61) and Portner (2009,
p. 67); f is the modal base and h is the ordering source. (See Lewis, 1973 and
Stalnaker, 1984 on the Limit Assumption, and for modal definitions which
do not adopt it, see Kratzer, 1981, p. 48 and Kratzer, 1991b, p. 644.)
10
Von Fintel and Gillies (2010) argue that (12a) does entail (12b); see Section 18.3.1 below.
532 L I S A M AT T H E W S O N
Here is an example of how the modal base and the ordering source interact
to give the right results.
(16) Context: As in (10), except that Madeleine has played one piece and five scales.
Madeleine must stop playing now.
Example (16) asserts that in all worlds which are compatible with the facts
about the audition and which are best according to the conductor’s actual-
world rules, Madeleine stops playing. This is the right result. The set of
worlds compatible with the facts includes only worlds where one of the con-
ductor’s rules has already been broken. But that’s okay – we just find the
best we can. Out of the worlds where Jane has already broken the rules, the
best ones are those where Madeleine obeys the rules. And in all of those, she
stops playing now.
As hinted already, all modal bases are realistic: they assign to any world
a set of propositions which are true in that world. In other words, for
any world w and modal base f, w is a member of ∩ f(w) (see, e.g., Kratzer,
2012, p. 55). It is often assumed that there are two types of realistic conver-
sational background: epistemic, and circumstantial/root. The former pro-
duces sets of propositions representing the available evidence; the latter
produces sets of propositions representing relevant facts about the circum-
stances. (In Section 18.2.4, I discuss this dichotomy further, and the difficul-
ties with formally distinguishing the two types.) If a conversational back-
ground is non-realistic, it must be an ordering source.11 Common examples
of flavours of ordering source are deontic (dealing with rules), bouletic (deal-
ing with desires), teleological (dealing with goals), and stereotypical (dealing
with normalcy). The first three of these operate on circumstantial modal
bases; Portner (2009) groups them under the term priority modals. See Palmer
(2001) on the different categories of modal flavour which are made use of
cross-linguistically.
(17) a. According to the audition rules, Madeleine can put her violin
away now.
b. Physically, Madeleine can put her violin away now.
c. Given the information in the report, Gerry might be the
murderer.
11
This is because a non-realistic conversational background may contain an inconsistent set of propositions,
and using this as a modal base would lead to the triviality problems discussed above.
Modality 533
12
Even in the presence of an overt adverbial phrase, the conversational background can be given by the
context, as pointed out by Nauze (2008, p. 157). The modal in (i) has an epistemic interpretation, in spite
of the deontic adverbial.
Context: We are discussing the upcoming trial of the suspected criminal, Jockl. The trial has not yet
beg[u]n and we wonder what the outcome will be.
(i) In view of what the law provides, Jockl may be executed.
(Nauze, 2008, p. 157)
13
Nauze (2008, p. 153), for example, argues for a polysemy account.
14
An argument which is sometimes advanced against an ambiguity analysis is that there are as many
different particular conversational backgrounds as there are contexts and that this multiplicity of meanings
534 L I S A M AT T H E W S O N
would be impossible to deal with lexically (see, e.g., Hacquard, 2011, p. 11). However, this argument is
weakened by the fact that modals in many languages do lexically encode overarching modal flavours like
‘deontic’ or ‘epistemic’. An ambiguity account combined with contextual dependence is therefore tenable,
and would be parallel to Partee’s (1988a) analysis of the quantifiers many and few. Partee claims that
many and few are each ambiguous between cardinal and proportional readings, but the specific
cardinalities or proportions they require are dependent on context.
15
Or by the holder of the attitude event, in the case of a modal embedded under an attitude verb.
Modality 535
a This element has various pronunciations, partly dependent on dialect: either ima, imaa,
or ima’.
second-position clitics ima(’a) and gat, the latter strictly by the clause-initial
verbs or predicative particles da’akhlxw, anook, and sgi. Examples are given
in (18)–(19). The reportative gat in (18b) is not necessarily translated into
English using a modal; however, Peterson (2010) argues that it has epistemic
modal semantics. A more revealing translation of (18b) would be ‘Given
what I heard, the berries might/must be ripe.’
(18) a. Context: There was a bad can of fish; everyone at the dinner got sick.
yugw=ima’=hl nee=dii am=hl hon=hl gup-diit
ipfv=epis=cn neg=cntr good=cn fish=cn eat-3pl.ii
‘The fish they ate must’ve been bad.’
(Matthewson, 2013a, p. 360, adapted from Peterson, 2010, p. 162)
b. Context: Your brother told you the berries are ripe now. Later, you tell me
the berries are ripe, based on what your brother told you.
hlaa mukw-t=gat=hl maa’y
incept ripe-3sg.ii=report=cn berries
‘The berries are ripe (I heard).’
(Matthewson, 2013a, p. 362)
(20) Context: You’re up in the Suskwa and notice a burnt patch of forest. You know
that huckleberries typically take seed in burnt alpine areas.
a. da’akhlxw=hl dim limxs=hl maa’y go’osun
circ=cn prosp grow.pl=cn berries loc.here
‘Berries might/can/are able to grow here.’
b. #limxs=ima=hl maa’y go’osun
grow.pl=epis=cn berries loc.here
‘Berries might be growing here.’
(Peterson, 2010, p. 158)
(21) a. aus dieser Kanne Milch kann die Kathl ein Pfund
from this can of milk can the Kathl one pound of
Quark machen
cottage cheese make
‘Kathl can make a pound of Quark out of this can of milk.’
b. es kann sein, dass die Kathl aus dieser Kanne Milch ein Pfund
it may be that the Kathl from this can of milk one pound
Quark macht
cottage cheese makes
‘Kathl might make a pound of Quark out of this can of milk.’
538 L I S A M AT T H E W S O N
The theoretical problem is that both types of modal base depend on facts
about the world of evaluation, and as such, there is no formal way to dis-
tinguish the two. As Nauze (2008, p. 155) points out, in many contexts the
very same set of propositions can serve as either an epistemic modal base or
a circumstantial one. Kratzer (2012, p. 24) concurs and writes that ‘[i]t now
seems to me a hopeless enterprise to try to characterize formal objects like
conversational backgrounds as “circumstantial” versus “epistemic”’.
To see the problem, imagine that the relevant circumstances for a partic-
ular modal assertion are identical to the relevant evidence we have (that is,
we know everything that is relevant). In this case, a circumstantial and an
epistemic modal base will contain the exact same set of propositions. Nauze
gives the example in (22), which involves similar modal flavours to (21) but
has a context in which the two modal bases (which we want to classify as
circumstantial and epistemic respectively) contain identical propositions.18
(22) Context: It is 2.50 pm on Saturday and we all know that France is playing
England at 3.00 pm in the Six Nations rugby tournament. Furthermore we
know that Fabrice is home (and has a television receiving the game).
a. Fabrice can watch the game.
b. Fabrice might watch the game.
(Nauze, 2008, pp. 154–155)
(23) Given the rumour, Roger must have been elected chief (#but he
actually wasn’t).
18
The problem cannot be solved by using different types of ordering sources. Nauze (2008, p. 155) also
shows that deontic and stereotypical ordering sources can contain identical sets of propositions in the
same context.
19
Another facet of the new approach is the idea that a modal’s domain is projected from an anchor. Anchors
may be individuals, events, situations, or bodies of evidence. Implicit domain-fixing functions map the
anchors to ordered sets of modal alternatives. Here I set the details of anchors aside, concentrating on the
issue of the epistemic–circumstantial divide.
20
On counterparts, see Lewis (1986).
Modality 539
The content mode, on the other hand, provides functions which return
sets of worlds compatible with the propositional content of some actual-world
source of information. This is illustrated in (24). Here, the claim is that in
all worlds in which the content of the rumour is true, Roger was elected chief.
This allows the speaker to believe that the rumour was a lie.
(24) According to the rumour, Roger must have been elected chief
(but he actually wasn’t).
Notice that must behaves differently in (23) and (24), even though both
these uses would traditionally be classified as epistemic. The new classifi-
cation therefore splits the old class of epistemic modals. Content-mode epis-
temics are not based on the speaker’s knowledge, or necessarily on anyone’s
knowledge – the content of rumours and other similar sources of informa-
tion can be false.21
The traditional class of circumstantial modals, on the other hand, all use
the factual mode, as they all rely on some actual-world facts and quantify
over worlds in which counterparts of those facts hold. The relation between
the old and new classifications is schematized in Table 18.2.
The split between factual- and content-mode epistemics is lexicalized in
many languages. For example, the St’át’imcets reportative modal ku7 is fac-
tual, as shown by the fact that the St’át’imcets sentence on which (23)–(24)
are based does not allow the speaker to totally disbelieve the rumour (see
Matthewson et al., 2007). In contrast, the German reportative modal sollen is
a content-based modal and does allow the speaker to disbelieve the rumour
(Kratzer, 2012, p. 35).22 Other elements traditionally analysed as evidentials
also lexically encode the difference between factual- and content-mode con-
versational backgrounds. This is shown in (25)–(28) for St’át’imcets. The fac-
tual modal k’a requires the speaker to have indirect inferential evidence
for the prejacent, while the content modal lákw7a requires the speaker to
have sensory, non-visual evidence for the prejacent. Only lákw7a allows the
speaker to believe that the prejacent is false (Matthewson, 2011, 2012a).
21
Kratzer (2012) calls the two types of epistemic modals evidential vs. informational. This is a different use of
the term evidential from its traditional use, which picks out elements which encode information source
(Aikhenvald, 2004).
22
The Quechua and Cheyenne reportatives also allow the speaker to disbelieve the report (Faller, 2002;
Murray, 2009). Faller (2002) and Murray (2009) do not analyse their respective reportatives as having
modal semantics, but Faller (2011) analyses the Quechua one as a content-mode (‘informational’) modal,
similar to German sollen.
540 L I S A M AT T H E W S O N
23
Thanks to an anonymous reviewer for raising this issue. McCready uses the example of a bloody knife
hidden in a cupboard: the knife itself is just a knife, but the proposition that the knife is there is what serves
as evidence.
Modality 541
may have modals which are lexicalized to cover all kinds of factual inter-
pretations, including traditional circumstantial interpretations as well as
factual–evidential ones. Whether this prediction is upheld is a topic for
future research.
Before leaving the issue of modal flavour, I will mention one more issue of
ongoing debate in the area of epistemic modality. Suppose we could agree
that epistemic modals depend on stores of information which constitute
indirect evidence for actual-world events. There is then still debate about
whether epistemic modals necessarily rely on an agent who is the holder
of that store of information. If an agent is involved, how is that relativism
to an agent capturable? The literature on this topic is large and interesting,
and consensus has not yet been reached (for relevant discussion, see Garrett,
2001; Hacquard, 2006, 2010; von Fintel and Gillies, 2007, 2008, 2011; Yalcin,
2007; Stephenson, 2008; Waldie, 2012, among others).
Kratzer (1981, 1991b) argues that the ordering source provides a way to
account for graded modal force. Kratzer defines various graded modal
notions such as ‘slight possibility’, ‘good possibility’, and ‘better possibility’;
examples are given in (30)–(31) (see discussion in Portner, 2009, pp. 69–71).
(33) a. After using the bathroom, everybody ought to wash their hands;
employees have to.
(von Fintel and Gillies, 2008, p. 116)
b. After using the bathroom, everybody should wash their hands;
employees must.
24
For a third set of approaches which rely on pragmatic differences between strong and weak necessity
modals (e.g., a presupposition on must that is missing on should, or evidential differences between the
two), see Ninan (2005), Copley (2006), Swanson (2008).
544 L I S A M AT T H E W S O N
Sloman (1970), von Fintel and Gillies (2008) argue that ought universally
quantifies over a domain which is narrowed down by an additional restric-
tion, over and above the restrictions on the domain of must. In (34a), for
example, the claim is that in all the worlds where the relevant facts are the
same as in the actual world and in which you meet your goal of getting to
Ashfield, you take Route 2. There are no other options for meeting your goal.
In (34b), the claim is weaker: in all worlds in which you satisfy a secondary
goal (such as avoiding heavy traffic) you take Route 2.
Von Fintel and Iatridou argue that the secondary goal is due to a second
ordering source, whose presence can be signalled by counterfactual mor-
phology in a range of languages. This approach uses only tools provided by
a standard analysis of modals, but/and it raises interesting questions about
ordering sources. One issue discussed by Rubinstein (2012) is how we tell
which ordering source is which – which is the ‘primary’ and which the ‘sec-
ondary’? Rubinstein proposes that weak necessity modals rely on ordering
sources which involve a departure from the collective commitments of par-
ticipants in the discourse. For example, suppose there are four ways to get
to Amherst from Cambridge. A speaker who utters (35) conveys that while
taking Route 9 is not a necessity given the collectively agreed-upon goal of
getting to Amherst, it is a necessity given some assumption that the speaker
presupposes is not collectively shared with the hearer (such as seeing nice
scenery, or stopping for lunch at a particular place on the way).
According to von Fintel and Gillies, epistemic must does not signal weaken-
ing with respect to the assertion of the plain prejacent. Instead, it signals
Modality 545
indirect evidentiality (as discussed in the previous section), and this leads to
a perceived weakening. One thing to note about this idea is that the evi-
dentiality claim is independent of the no-ordering-source claim. It could
conceivably be correct that must requires indirect evidence, but false that
it makes no use of an ordering source.
A final strand of current research in the area of modal force is modals
without duals. These are modals which do not come in necessity–possibility
pairs, but can be used in contexts supporting either necessity or possibility
claims. These have been most extensively discussed for languages other than
English (Rullmann et al., 2008; Davis et al., 2009; Peterson, 2010; Deal, 2011).
In the next subsection, I discuss two examples of such languages, Gitksan
and Nez Perce.
(37) Context: You’re wondering where your friend is. You notice his rod and tackle
box are not in their usual place.
yugw=ima=hl dim ixw-t
ipfv=epis=cn prosp fish.with.line-3
‘He might be going fishing.’ / ‘He must be going fishing.’ / ‘He’s
probably going fishing.’ / ‘He’s likely going fishing.’ / ‘He could be
going fishing.’ / ‘Maybe/perhaps he’s going fishing.’
(Peterson, 2010, p. 161)
Note that in the example above the spelling of ixw has been corrected
(cf. Rigsby, 1986, p. 170).
The claim that ima(’a) is not semantically a necessity modal is supported
by data such as in (38). In this discourse context, must would be infelicitous
in English.
(38) Context: You thought your friend was fishing. But you see his rod and tackle
box are still at his house. You really don’t know if he’s fishing or not.
yugw=imaa=hl da’awhl ixw-t oo ligi nee=yimaa=dii ixw-t
ipfv=epis=cn then fish-311 or indef neg=epis=cntr fish-311
‘Maybe he’s fishing, maybe he’s not fishing.’
(Matthewson, 2013a, p. 361)
546 L I S A M AT T H E W S O N
(39) Context: I am watching people clean out a cooler and throw away various
things.
hi-wqíi-cix-∅ ’iléx̂ni hipt ke yox̂ hi-pá-ap-o’qa
3subj-throw.away-ipfv.pl-pres a.lot food rel dem 3sbj-S.pl-eat-mod
(i) ‘They are throwing away a lot of food that they could eat.’
(ii) ‘They are throwing away a lot of food that they should eat.’
(Deal, 2011, p. 574)
Although the English translation in (40-i) entails (the first part of) (40-ii),
the Nez Perce sentence is not a viable way to express the specific negated-
necessity meaning of (40-ii). That is, the Nez Perce sentence cannot be under-
stood as conveying that they are throwing away all the food they should eat,
but keeping some food they could eat (the junk food).
Deal analyses o’qa as a possibility modal, which is acceptable in non-
downward-entailing necessity contexts because there is no contrasting
necessity modal to induce a scalar implicature. In other words, Nez Perce’s
circumstantial modal system parallels what English’s nominal quantifier
system would look like if it possessed the existential quantifier some, but no
universal quantifier like all or every. In such a version of English, (41a) would
fail to implicate that not all the guests brought presents and therefore
would be acceptable in a context where all of the guests brought presents.
Modality 547
This is parallel to the felicitous use of o’qa in the necessity context in (39-ii).
The downward-entailing (41b) would (just like in real-life English) be unable
to express the negated-universal meaning: (41b) would be unable to express
the claim that it is false that all of the guests brought presents (but true
that some of them did). This parallels the infelicity of o’qa in the downward-
entailing necessity context in (40-ii).
(42) Context (possibility): You know that Mary loves to go running and often goes
on runs randomly. She could also be at the store or at school. I ask you, where
is Mary?
a. Mary mat ac-qíc-əlx
Mary mod cust-run-lex
‘Mary might be running.’
b. Mary cmay ac-qíc-əlx
Mary mod cust-run-lex
‘Mary might be running.’
(Menzies, 2013, p. 2)
25
One of Kratzer’s motivations for a degree-modal analysis is that Rullmann et al. (2008), Peterson (2010),
and Deal (2011) fail to explain the absence of duals in the respective languages (Kratzer, 2013, pp.
184–185). While a degree-modal analysis may turn out to be preferable, I am not sure that the absence of
duals is something which necessarily requires explanation. Some modals have duals, some do not. Attitude
verbs do not seem to have duals, for example.
548 L I S A M AT T H E W S O N
(43) Context (necessity): Mary runs every day to train for a marathon. She usually
runs at 6 pm on Tuesdays. Today is Tuesday and it’s 6 pm. I ask you, where is
Mary?
a. Mary mat ac-qíc-əlx
Mary mod cust-run-lex
‘Mary must be running.’
b. #Mary cmay ac-qíc-əlx
Mary mod cust-run-lex
‘Mary might be running.’
(Menzies, 2013, p. 2)
We thus see that within a single language’s epistemic system, one modal
behaves as if it lacked a dual, while one behaves like a strict possibility
modal. This raises interesting questions for the idea that possibility modals
in languages like English are weak because of scalar implicatures induced
by the contrasting necessity modal. See Section 18.5 for discussion of an
emerging formal typology of modal force.
26
More generally (to take into account tenseless languages), what is crucial is that the modal is provided with
a reference time in whatever way the language independently provides reference times to non-modal
clauses.
27
Some analyses, including that of Condoravdi (2002), do not include a prospective viewpoint aspect but
instead place an inherent future semantics in the modal itself. I am using prospective here by analogy to
languages which overtly mark future temporal orientation with prospective aspect markers, such as Gitksan
(see Section 18.4.3). Kratzer (2011b) argues that English possesses a null prospective aspect marker which
co-occurs with modals, and its absence can lead to actuality entailments. (For other work on the important
topic of actuality entailments, which unfortunately I do not have space to go into here, see Bhatt, 1999;
Hacquard, 2006, 2009; Mari and Martin, 2007, among others.)
550 L I S A M AT T H E W S O N
The schemas in (51) show how the various temporal operators apply. In each
case the tense provides the temporal perspective (TP), and aspect restricts the
temporal orientation (TO). Note that prospective aspect merely induces non-
pastness; depending on the Aktionsart of the predicate and the perfective/
imperfective distinction, prospective can derive either strict future orienta-
tion (with an eventive perfective verb) or ambiguously present/future orien-
tation (with a stative predicate and/or an imperfective).
The schemas so far all have present tense, therefore present temporal
perspective. As is well known, English modal auxiliaries do not synchron-
ically inflect for tense, but in languages in which they do (such as Dutch
or German), past tense morphology on the modal gives past temporal per-
spective. This also happens with English semi-modals such as have/had to or
is/was able to. Otherwise, past TP in English is marked by the perfect aux-
iliary have. In (51c)–(51d), have introduces a low-scoping perfect aspect and
gives past TO, but have can also induce past TP when it combines with
a modal which contains historical past tense morphology (such as might
or could). These two different roles for have underlie the famous ambigu-
ity of might have-constructions, pointed out by many including Condoravdi
(2002), Huddleston and Pullum (2002), Ippolito (2003), and illustrated in
(52)–(53).28
28
The details of how have manages compositionally to contribute past TP have been debated in the literature
and go beyond what we can discuss here (see Condoravdi, 2002; Ippolito, 2003; Arregui, 2005; Hacquard,
2006; Laca, 2008; Rullmann and Matthewson, 2012, for discussion).
Modality 551
The readings in (52) and (53) differ not only in temporal properties but
in conversational background: (52) is epistemic, while (53) is circumstantial
(more specifically, metaphysical, according to Condoravdi, 2002, although
see Abusch, 2012, for a dissenting view).29 How the unattested combina-
tions of temporal perspective, temporal orientation, and conversational
background are ruled out is a question that immediately arises. One sub-
part of the puzzle is the restriction of the circumstantial reading in (53)
to future orientation. If (53) does involve metaphysical modality, its future
orientation follows from Condoravdi’s (2002) Diversity Condition, or from
Werner’s (2003) Disparity Principle. These are general principles which rely
on the fact that metaphysical modals quantify over worlds which only vary
for times following the temporal perspective.
A second sub-part of the puzzle posed by (52)–(53) is the restriction of
the epistemic interpretation to a present temporal perspective. This can be
derived within Condoravdi’s system via a stipulation that epistemic modals
cannot scope under either past tense or the perfect auxiliary. This issue has
been the subject of much debate, and I discuss it in slightly more detail in
the next subsection.
Many researchers have denied that epistemic modals can have past temporal
perspectives, at least in English. Hacquard (2011, p. 1495), for example, states
29
A metaphysical modal base is a circumstantial modal base which provides a set of worlds which are all
identical to the actual world up to and including the time at which the modal base is calculated
(Thomason, 2002).
552 L I S A M AT T H E W S O N
that ‘epistemic modals are evaluated at the speech time’ (see also Groe-
nendijk and Stokhof, 1975; Cinque, 1999; Condoravdi, 2002; Stowell, 2004;
Hacquard, 2006; Borgonovo and Cummins, 2007; Demirdache and Uribe-
Etxebarria, 2008; Laca, 2008). A common belief is that the semantic restric-
tion on the temporal properties of epistemic modals derives from a syntac-
tic restriction, namely that epistemic modals scope over tense, while non-
epistemic modals scope under it. Hacquard (2011) (among others) adopts
Cinque’s (1999) hierarchy of functional heads, relevant portions of which
are given in (55):30
(55) Modepis > Tense > Aspect > Modvolitional > Moddeontic necessity
> Modability/deontic possibility
(Hacquard, 2011, p. 1496)
The view that epistemic modals always scope over tense has not gone unchal-
lenged. Epistemic modals have been shown to allow past temporal perspec-
tives in a number of languages; see Eide (2003, 2005) for Norwegian, Kratzer
(2009) for English and German, and Homer (2013), Mari (2010), and Mar-
tin (2011) for French. Within English and to a certain extent for other lan-
guages, the issue is still controversial. Von Fintel and Gillies (2008) argue
that (54c) does have a past-TP epistemic reading; the reading is facilitated
by a discourse context as in (56). Von Fintel and Gillies (2008, p. 87) state
that here ‘It is possible for [the speaker] to have said something true, even
though at the time of utterance she knows . . . there is no ice cream in the
freezer.’
(56) Context: Sophie is looking for some ice cream and checks the freezer. There is
none in there. Asked why she opened the freezer, she replies:
There might have been ice-cream in the freezer.
(von Fintel and Gillies, 2008, p. 87)
The debate about past epistemics goes beyond simple empirical disagree-
ment: among those who acknowledge that epistemic modals can have a
past temporal perspective, some deny that it reflects the ability of the epis-
temic modal to scope under a clause-mate past tense. It has, for example,
been proposed that the relevant readings involve an elided embedding atti-
tude verb or because-clause (Hacquard, 2006, 2011), or that they are felic-
itous due to contexts of (free) indirect discourse (Fagan, 2001; Boogaart,
2007; Hacquard, 2006, 2011). For arguments against some of these escape
hatches, see Homer (2013), Rullmann and Matthewson (2012), and see
Portner (2009, pp. 222–236) for summary and discussion.31
30
As discussed in Section 18.2.2 above, Hacquard does not derive the effects of syntactic position on
interpretation simply from a cartographic syntax. Her proposal is that the different interpretations arise
because modals interact locally with different elements which partially determine the modal’s
interpretation.
31
Portner (2009, p. 227) himself states that a past temporal perspective is rare but not impossible for
epistemic modals, and that the past readings may be limited to stative sentences. See also Iatridou (1990)
for relevant discussion, including the claim that some but not all of what we currently classify as epistemics
can scope under tense.
Modality 553
32
www.totemfieldstoryboards.org/stories/feeding_fluffy/.
554 L I S A M AT T H E W S O N
Further evidence for past-TP epistemic modals is given in (60)–(62) from Gitk-
san; these data also support the second proposal of this section, namely
that viewpoint aspects control temporal orientation. Observe that (60)–(62)
are a minimal triplet containing the epistemic modal ima(’a), a uniformly
past temporal perspective (ensured by the context), and all three possible
temporal orientations, past, present, and future respectively. While in (60)
there is no overt marking of past orientation, in (62) the future orientation
is achieved by means of the overt prospective aspect marker dim.
(60) Context: When you looked out your window earlier today, the ground was wet,
so it looked like it might have rained. But you found out later that the
sprinklers had been watering the ground.
yugw=imaa=hl wis da’awhl
ipfv=epis=cn rain then
‘It might have rained.’ [based on my evidence earlier]
(Matthewson, 2013a, p. 366)
(61) Context: When you looked out your window earlier today, water was falling, so
it looked like it was raining. But you found out later it was the gutters leaking.
yugw=imaa=hl wis da’awhl
ipfv=epis=cn rain then
‘It might have been raining earlier.’
(Matthewson, 2013a, p. 363)
(62) Context: This morning you looked out your window and judging by the clouds,
it looked like it might have been going to rain, so you took your raincoat. Later
you’re explaining to me why you did that.
yugw=imaa=hl dim wis
ipfv=epis=cn prosp rain
‘It might have been going to rain.’
(Matthewson, 2013a, p. 366)
Second, English and Gitksan are mirror images, since past orientation is
obligatorily marked in English (via have), but future orientation is obligato-
rily marked in Gitksan (via dim). And third, English and Gitksan can be anal-
ysed as abstractly parallel, if we are willing to postulate a null prospective
aspect in English and a null perfect in Gitksan (cf. Van de Vate, 2011).
In this section I have sketched a Condoravdi-inspired approach to modal–
temporal interactions, which makes the universal hypotheses that temporal
perspective is given by tense (or the language-internal functional equivalent)
and temporal orientation is restricted by aspect. Obviously, languages vary
independently in their temporal systems. An overarching goal is therefore
to establish the extent to which variation in modal–temporal interactions
reduces to those independent temporal differences. For example, we have
already seen that languages without overt past–present distinctions allow
past temporal perspectives without any overt marking. This is predicted by
the system presented. Whether other predictions are upheld is a matter for
future research.
In this chapter we have discussed the basics in three major areas in modal-
ity research: modal flavour, modal force, and modal-temporal interactions.
Many empirical and analytical questions remain about all of these areas, as
well as about the interactions between them. Assuming that our ultimate
goal is a theory of universals and variation in human language, one impor-
tant task for the field is to gather information about modality in unfamiliar
and understudied languages. Formal research on such languages will allow
us to develop a formal typology of modality, which in turn will facilitate
greater theoretical understanding.
There is, of course, already a rich tradition of modality research in the
typological literature (see Bybee et al., 1994; de Haan, 1997; van der Auw-
era and Plungian, 1998; Palmer, 2001; Hengeveld, 2004; van der Auwera
and Ammann, 2011, among others). These works provide extensive infor-
mation about how modal notions are expressed across languages (e.g., as
verbs, affixes), what types of categories are encoded, and the grammatical-
ization paths of modal elements. Added to this is a recent growth of formal
research on modality, which is able (through hypothesis-driven investiga-
tion and the collection of negative evidence) to isolate precisely and accu-
rately the semantics of modal elements in a range of languages.33,34
33
For critiques of a non-hypothesis-driven typological approach to modality, see Matthewson (2013b) and
Davis et al. (2014). Along similar lines, Nauze (2008, p. 19) points out that a good typology of modality
must rely not only on general descriptive sources such as grammars but on ‘semantically motivated
descriptions’ of modal systems.
34
For a recent example of formal cross-linguistic research on modality, see Arregui et al. (2014), who provide
a modal analysis of imperfective aspects in several different languages.
556 L I S A M AT T H E W S O N
35
Abraham (1998, p. 233) argues more radically for modals of all forces that ‘reference to the future under
no circumstances gives an epistemic reading’.
Modality 557
(65) Context: Tom wasn’t fishing yesterday, and you were wondering about his
health. But today you see him fishing.
Hī ika a Tom he aho nei . . . liga malolo a ia
catch.fish fish abs Tom on day this epis strong abs 3sg
‘Tom is fishing today . . . he’s probably well.’
(Matthewson et al., 2012, p. 228)
Example (67) shows the possibility modal maeke in one of its most frequent
uses, an ability reading, and Example (68) shows the necessity modal lata
with an obligation interpretation.
Modal elements can only have more than one meaning along a unique
axis of the semantic space: they either vary on the horizontal axis and
thus are polyfunctional in the original sense of expressing different types
of modality or they vary on the vertical axis and can express possibility
and necessity, but they cannot vary on both axes. (Nauze, 2008, p. 222)
Table 18.4 Hypothetical modal system of the root domain: predicted to exist under
Nauze’s (2008) typology (Vander Klok, 2013, p. 18)
Modal flavour
Root domain
Deontic Pure circumstantial Teleological
Modal Necessity x y y
force Possibility x w z
36
References for any one of these topics would be too numerous to cite.
Modality 559
(69) Context: Sophie is looking for some ice cream and checks the freezer. There is
none in there. Asked why she opened the freezer, she replies:
There might have been ice cream in the freezer.
#Maybe there was ice cream in the freezer.
(adapted from von Fintel and Gillies, 2008, p. 87)
Acknowledgements
I am very grateful to Maria Aloni, Henry Davis, and an anonymous reviewer
for helpful feedback on an earlier version of this paper. Many thanks to
St’át’imcets consultants Carl Alexander, Laura Thevarge, the late Gertrude
Ned, the late Beverley Frank, and the late Rose Agnes Whitley, to Gitksan
consultants Vincent Gogag and Barbara Sennott, and to Niuean consultant
co-author Lynsey Talagi. This research was supported in part by SSHRC grant
#410-2011-0431.