Kennedy Thewellofbeing
Kennedy Thewellofbeing
Kennedy Thewellofbeing
net/publication/327680412
CITATIONS READS
12 260
1 author:
David Kennedy
Montclair State University
32 PUBLICATIONS 156 CITATIONS
SEE PROFILE
All content following this page was uploaded by David Kennedy on 05 October 2021.
The
Well
of
Being
Childhood,
Subjectivity,
and Education
David Kennedy
Published by
State University of New York Press, Albany
HQ767.9.K453 2006
305.23—dc22
2005025462
10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1
Kennedy00FM 1/11/06 10:34 AM Page v
Contents
Preface ix
1. Questioning Childhood 1
Whose Child? 1
Which Adult? 5
The Western Construction of Childhood 8
Theorizing Childhood 13
Adult-Child Dialogue 14
The Child Before Us: Education, Parenting, and the
Evolution of Subjectivity 21
vii
Kennedy00FM 1/11/06 10:34 AM Page viii
Notes 187
Bibliography 211
Index 229
Kennedy00FM 1/11/06 10:34 AM Page ix
Preface
ix
Kennedy00FM 1/11/06 10:34 AM Page x
Preface xi
water, fire, the tree without putting a love into them, a friendship which
goes back to our childhood. We love them with childhood. When we
love all these beauties of the world . . . we love them in a new found
childhood, in a childhood reanimated with that childhood which is
latent in each of us.”2
Bachelard confirms for us that the childhood of the adult is an
invention of sorts, but also the impossible memory of a perceptual con-
dition, of a form of subject-world relation that we can observe in the
actual children with whom we are in relation but never experience
again, except perhaps in flashes. The adult-child relationship, even in
such a socially and psychologically degraded atmosphere as the one so
often produced by universal compulsory schooling, will always carry
this complex relation between what we were and what they are, what
they might become and what we might have become, what they are and
what we might become, and what they might become and what the
world might become as a result. This book is about the possibilities that
inhabit the interstices of these relations and, finally, about the sort of
school that would be capable of mining their depths.
Kennedy01 1/11/06 10:35 AM Page 1
Questioning Childhood
Whose Child?
It is now about one hundred years since the child became an official
object of Western science. Child study was institutionalized in the uni-
versities, the media, and the government extension offices at the
moment that the Darwinian explanatory paradigm was sweeping West-
ern self-understanding, and the notion of Progress had not yet been
fatally complicated by the Great War. Its birth coincides with the birth
of the disciplines that have regulated its discursive space ever since—
psychology, sociology, and pedagogy.
Child study is traditionally thought of as the domain of these three
forms of discourse. The questions these discourses ask of the child are
determined by their historical self-understanding as aspirants to “hard
science,” i.e., a science that can make the same universally verifiable
knowledge claims as physics or biology say they can about the world
and how it works. In order to bend the object of understanding to the
method of understanding, the human sciences fall into the unavoidable
trap of objectifying children in the same way that hard science must
objectify its objects in order to know them. The object of the discipline
is born with the discipline—in this case, the child as a natural kind, and
the study of the child as an extension of the science of biology. The
1
Kennedy01 1/11/06 10:35 AM Page 2
questions that get asked of children and of childhood are the same ques-
tions that get asked of any organism in its environment. And further,
these questions get asked as if by one species—the adult—of another—
the child.
This inquiry is not so much directly about the negative conse-
quences of this view of the child and of childhood, of which there are
several,2 as about the questions of and to children and childhood that it
leaves out. Those of us in search of a thicker, more dynamic view of the
phenomenon of human childhood are regularly disappointed by the
absence of any questions that cannot be answered in terms of the nar-
rowed framework of the search for statistical norms, arrived at through
standardized forms of research, leaving us with a child who has been—
at the very moment we thought we had accessed the “thing itself”—
neutralized by the techniques used to study him or her.
The problem is not just epistemological—not just about what
adults can know about children and how—but political. Modern sci-
ence is as hegemonic a knowledge framework as was the theocentric.
Like the theocentric, it presumes to be an epistemological bottom line;
in the end, all other knowledge claims must meet its criteria for legiti-
macy. When a big knowledge framework assumes that kind of self-
importance, its fundamental beliefs become elements of perception
itself, and are put beyond question. So enframed, we no longer feel the
need for identification of and ongoing inquiry into the founding philo-
sophical assumptions that undergird our knowledge claims—we no
longer understand ourselves as interpreters, but as direct knowers.
In the case of child study, the interpretations that provide research
frameworks for the “child” of normal science are, on the surface
anyway, the result of the philosophical constructions of childhood of
one or another massively seminal thinker—a Darwin, a Freud, or a
Piaget. These thinkers—who are sometimes but not always more aware
of their philosophical assumptions than their followers—provide
normal science with the big picture for its local research agendas, which
take decades to play out, hedged about as they are with self-contained,
internally developed methodologies. Typically enough, all three of the
giants mentioned above considered themselves scientists rather than
philosophers, but the further we are from them in time, the more we see
them to have been speaking in the context of ontological, epistemologi-
cal, and anthropological assumptions that they never felt obliged to
fully articulate or clarify. To put it bluntly, the “child” of the modern
scientists is a culturally and historically mediated, philosophical con-
struct disguised as the hard object of experimental science.
Kennedy01 1/11/06 10:35 AM Page 3
Questioning Childhood 3
Questioning Childhood 5
Which Adult?
Questioning Childhood 7
life without differance.”17 But like those other liminal figures, she also
represents an opening for psychological development. She is the other
who finally cannot be gotten around: her radical alterity demands
either violence or dialogue in response. We do not have to look far for
the former; the latter, I will argue, offers an enormous promise for the
possibilities of personal, social and cultural evolution.
Questioning Childhood 9
Plato also often associates children with slaves, women, and animals,
and both he and Aristotle group children with the “the sick, the drunk,
the insane, and the wicked.”19
But even here—in the invocation of the human limit condition of
animals, the mad, the intoxicated—the positive side of the ambivalence
glimmers, for a perennial tradition identifies the drunk and the insane
with the “wisdom of the gods.” “Drunkards and children tell the
truth,” quotes the (drunken) Alcibiades proverbially in the Symposium
(then slyly blurts out—”drunkards anyway”).20 Children were indeed
associated in Greek mythic lore with nature and the gods, and played
parts in festivals and ceremonies to which this association gave them a
natural right. Like the gods themselves, children were marginal to the
adult world of the polis, and so could act as intercessors with beings
from other worlds. In Athens, a child was chosen each year to act as
intermediary between the initiates and the divine presence in the Mys-
teries of Eleusis.21 The otherness of nature and the otherness of the
divine meet in the child archetype in art, myth, and ceremony—not just
in the ancient world, but in the medieval, modern, and postmodern,
under various tropes.
The ambivalent and even polarized iconic location of “child” both
evokes and locates the fault line running through the history of Western
subjectivity—between body and mind, flesh and spirit, instinctual
expression and repression, license and control, unconscious and con-
scious, profane and sacred. To the extent that children act as screens
for adults’ projections of the first term of each of these contrastive
pairs—body, flesh, instinct, license, the unconscious, the profane—they
represent the dangerous otherness of the left hand, or “sinister” in the
Western discourses of self—the shadow, the unconscious, desire—with
which our rationalist tradition heroically struggles, wielding the
weapons of what Michel Foucault called “technologies of the self.” As
representations of desire, their status—like the status of women, the
terminally nonrational (the mad), and the “primitive”—in Western
patriarchal culture is both marginal and prophetic. Traditionally, these
groups evoke both destructive chaos and the transformative potential
of desire. The child’s location in this paradox of subjectivity will play
Kennedy01 1/11/06 10:35 AM Page 10
Questioning Childhood 11
Questioning Childhood 13
Theorizing Childhood
Adult-Child Dialogue
Questioning Childhood 15
Questioning Childhood 17
we shall see is thought to have been the case in Europe until the early
modern period—there was hardly a leap to be made. The factors con-
tributing to the opening of this distance in the West—along with the
implications for cultural development that this distance represents—will
be taken up further along.
The “dialectical difficulty” that Schutz mentions is in fact the very
difficulty that hermeneutics, or interpretation theory—which is a theory
of dialogue—works to overcome. Hermeneutics was originally about
reading texts, but it emerged from a situation analogous to the adult-
child relation: people were seeking to understand texts written during
one historical epoch that had become distant and even strange to
another. In other words, the hermeneutical situation begins when we
(adults) confront a text (child) from which we have become distant,
thus creating a relation in which we encounter both familiarity and
strangeness, and a certain level of alienation and misunderstanding.40 If
this were not the case, the whole interpretive process would not even be
called for. “The aim of all hermeneutics,” according to Paul Ricoeur, “is
to struggle against cultural distance and historical alienation. Interpreta-
tion brings together, equalizes, renders contemporary and similar.”41
Like the Schutzian leap, interpretation has, as Hans-Georg Gadamer
says, “to cross the abyss of historical consciousness.”42 As there is an
abyss between us and our historical past, so there is a potential abyss
between each individual and her childhood.
Forgetfulness is the pervasive context of our experience of finitude,
and it is forgetfulness that works to create the distance between adult
and child. Hermeneutics operates in a space of difference between, not
only reader and text, but subject and object. It is dialogical in that the
reader/subject places himself within that space of difference, in what
Martin Buber called “actuality,” that is “participation in a being that is
neither merely a part of him nor merely outside of him,”43 and takes it
as his task to interrogate this “between.” The hermeneutical relation-
ship is particularly apposite to the adult-child relation because it denies
in its very structure the possibility of the situation of objectivity that is
exemplified by modernist theory. It represents a move beyond the West-
ern objectivity-myth, in that, for interpretation-theory a science free
from prejudice is impossible. There is always a set of preunderstand-
ings—a historical-cultural horizon—from which we view the text-other.
This is not only a historical-cultural horizon, but an ontological situa-
tion, which Ricoeur describes as “belonging.” The “allegedly
autonomous subject and the allegedly adverse object,” he insists, are
actually two terms of a “prior relation of inclusion” that encompasses
Kennedy01 1/11/06 10:35 AM Page 18
them both.44 It is through the subject coming into dialogue with the
object rather than isolating it in theoretical constructs that understanding
emerges. As such, hermeneutics is theory as affinity and participation,
rather than as distance and domination. It resists the idea that through
subjecting nature—in this case in the form of the child—to mathemati-
cal/statistical construction nature can be known except partially.
It is central to the dialogical relation that the knower is changed by
the known in the act of knowing. Through opening oneself to the object
and its different meanings, one comes, not only to a new understanding
of the object, but to a new self-understanding. There is no overview that
would enable us to grasp in a single glance the whole of the object, or
even its complete context, but only the horizon of the play of our rela-
tion, and the discipline of the dialogue. “To understand,” says Ricoeur,
“is not to project oneself into the text [read “child”] but to expose one-
self to it; it is to receive a self enlarged by the appropriation of the pro-
posed worlds which interpretation unfolds”:
Questioning Childhood 19
Questioning Childhood 21
Questioning Childhood 23
major change mentioned above (p. 14) for the deconstruction of the ide-
ology of adulthood and the decolonization of education. For it is how
adults understand themselves and the structure, limits and possibilities
of their own subjectivity that determines how they understand children
and childhood.
Postmodern adult subjectivity is laboring under a number of influ-
ences that act to deconstruct the ideology of adulthood. The original
template for the Western notion of the adult subject, stated clearly by
Plato in his utopian treatise Republic, not only excludes childhood
altogether—which Plato seems to have implicitly understood as a kind
of deformity of self—but is founded upon relations of internal hierar-
chy and domination. His seminal characterization described the self as
composed of three elements or dimensions—appetite, volition or will,
and reason—which in order to function optimally, require the domina-
tion of the first two elements by the last and smallest. Appetite must
come under the rulership of will, and will of reason, or the conse-
quence is personal and social chaos.62 Plato’s conception is a static,
hierarchical one—at least from our position in the history of subjectiv-
ity—which defines optimal adulthood (i.e., the successful self) as a
nested structure of domination, directly analogous to the traditional
Indo-European tripartite class structure of royalty, military, and peas-
ant.63 This model of self traveled into the modern West through Stoic
and Christian traditions, and was rendered into a radical dualistic
ontology in early modernism in Descartes’ res cogitans and res extensa.
Not only is it a coercive notion of self-formation, but from Plato until
now it forces children—whom it characterizes as naturally dominated
by appetite and self-will—in the position of chaotic, even monstrous
beings, in need of specific discipline to bring the dimensions of the self
into successful balance.
Perhaps the most influential Western model of subjectivity after
Plato’s—Freud’s—deconstructs this hierarchy, and places the elements
of the self not just in a more complex, but in a dialogical and even
dialectical, relationship.64 There is still an internal politics of self in
Freud, but it is a politics in which ambiguity and mutual influence and
even interpenetration of contradictory elements predominate. Relation-
ships of hierarchy are reinterpreted as relations of repression, displace-
ment and sublimation—none of which presuppose conscious mastery of
one element by another, but rather fluid negotiations—and the possibil-
ity is at least acknowledged65 of cultural influences that can minimize
repression. Most importantly for child rearing and education, Freud’s
model leads to the redefinition of the human life cycle as multi- rather
than unilinear: all the phases of the cycle are represented in each one,
Kennedy01 1/11/06 10:35 AM Page 24
Questioning Childhood 25
the status of full-fledged interlocutors with adults, that space will bloom
in ways that have been characteristically suppressed until now, and the
human experience will, however slowly, change to allow—as the
Romantic poet and philosopher Samuel Taylor Coleridge put it at the
moment of the discovery of childhood in the modern West—each of us
to “carry the feelings of childhood into the powers of manhood.”67
Kennedy01 1/11/06 10:35 AM Page 26
Kennedy02 1/11/06 10:36 AM Page 27
27
Kennedy02 1/11/06 10:36 AM Page 28
I was asking myself these questions, weeping all the while with
the most bitter sorrow in my heart, when all at once I heard the
sing-song voice of a child in a nearby house. Whether it was the
voice of a boy or a girl I cannot say, but again and again it
repeated the refrain ‘Take it and read, take it and read.’ At this
I looked up, thinking hard whether there was any kind of game
in which children used to chant words like these, but I could
not remember ever hearing them before. I stemmed my flood of
tears and stood up, telling myself that this could only be a
divine command to open my book of Scripture and read the
first passage on which my eyes should fall.6
body of Eros, or Love, who in ancient myth unites heaven and earth.
Their trademark is an innocent sensuality that was later reappropriated
in the putti, or “cupids” of Renaissance art, where they find their way
into both pagan and Christian themes. There they accompany both
Aphrodite in her amours, and the Holy Child and his mother—and even
God the Father, or the adult Jesus as he comes from heaven to carry off
a dying or enraptured saint. Often they appear in legion, filling the sky.
In their representation in pagan themes, these naked, playful super-tod-
dlers are often depicted in contact with the elemental forces of nature—
wrestling playfully with a swan, riding a dolphin, or even riding rams,
panthers, lions, officiating serenely over preliminaries to the act of love
or accompanying the dead to the underworld. Some are winged. Josef
Kunstmann connects them with “daemons,” or intermediaries between
heaven and earth, creatures who connect the above and the below, the
holy and the profane. The naked toddler, in his uninhibited play,
releases and secures the connection between the sensual and the sacred.
Like their original prototype Eros, who was first represented as an ado-
lescent, the eroti, according to Kunstmann, “combine the most unlikely
contrasts and hold together body and soul, heaven, earth, and the
underworld.”11
The Orphic sect worshipped Eros as the creator of the world. For
Plato he represented the desire to create in beauty—he who evokes in
the soul the memory of the primal Ideas. But there is also, from the
beginning, a curious ambivalence about this naked youth. The mythic
tradition identified both a lofty (Uranios) and a base (Pandemos) Eros,
matching the dual aspects of his mother Aphrodite. Boethius (480–524)
said of the god whom Homer ignored, he is “the most beautiful of the
immortal gods, who loosens the limbs and restrains the temper of all
men and gods, but who also overthrows wise counsel.”12 The eroti rep-
resent both the fleshly nature of the spiritual and the spiritual nature of
the fleshly—opposites that, when not promoting ecstatic unity, tempt
excess and bad judgment.
But in fact they were appropriated by Christian art—if not with the
gusto of their pagan counterparts—quite early. They are found on early
Christian graves and sarcophagi playing with hoops and balls (symbols
of the soul), or placing wreaths on the heads of husband and wife. They
are identified with the guardian spirits of early Christianity, but retain
their erotic function as the element that knits things up in love and
makes them flow, while their demonic element—the possibility for
“pandemonium”—is muted or elided. They appear to have no symbolic
connection with the child Jesus—who first appears in late Hellenistic
times as well—but in this case with his mother, nursing, in a second-
Kennedy02 1/11/06 10:36 AM Page 33
lation of childhood and its importance in the life cycle, which will be
taken up below.
When the naked child is not in amorous interaction with the
mother, but held among other adults—particularly in depictions of the
Adoration of the Magi, and the paintings of the Madonna and Child
with the saints, another symbolic aspect emerges. Nothing could better
communicate the stunning glory of the flesh revealed in its restoration
than setting it off against a surrounding group of fully clothed, intensely
concentrating adults. All the bodies of the adults, in various stages of
age and experience, are hidden, but stand in astonishment and grave
wonder before the insouciant, gleaming nakedness of Desire. If, for pur-
poses of analysis, we bracket out the narrative of this child as God-King
of the universe—or even keep the narrative but assign to it a psycholog-
ical and archetypal rather than a purely historical or theological empha-
sis—the extent to which the divine child is the “inner child” of all the
observing adults becomes more insistent. On the psychological level,
these scenes are object lessons in the developmental command of the
Western wisdom tradition that calls on each adult to be “born again,”
and “become like a little child.”
Finally, the divine child of the Renaissance reemerges, as we have
already seen, in the eroti of the earlier Hellenistic period, now become
cupid-angels, who reassert their function as mediators between flesh
and spirit, earth and sky. We find them particularly in paintings where
heaven opens up, and they are seated, hovering, or flying just on the
boundary between earth and heaven. In his analysis of Raphael’s widely
reproduced Sistine Madonna (1514, Royal Picture Gallery, Dresden),
Kunstmann compares the two eroti posted on the picture plane to “sen-
tries” at the transition point between the real and the visionary worlds,
mediators between time and eternity, inner and outer space.32 They are
expressions of the elemental sympathy by which the whole cosmos is
held together in the divine love, the “impossible” union between eros
and agape. Nor have they lost the ambivalence that they had in Hel-
lenism, for they are also present wherever erotic pandemonium suggests
itself—as in the effulgent Venuses of Titian, or the woodland revels of
Silenus and his entourage.
The direction of the representation of the divine child from the
Gothic onward was one of ever increasing realism and naturalism.
Although “real” children were depicted relatively infrequently and usu-
ally as marginal figures in Renaissance art, the trend toward realism
was part of an emergent secularism in a West “coming of age” in early
modernism, which understood itself as no longer preoccupied with mere
Kennedy02 1/11/06 10:36 AM Page 40
“myths.” Yet at its point of balance in the High Renaissance, the new
realism was used in the service of the mythic—to justify the faith in the
divinity of Christ, and to summarize the archetype of the divine child
with a new, not just theological, but psychological immediacy. In its
struggle to integrate pagan and Christian spirituality, Renaissance art
found that the more realistic the body and behavior of the divine child,
the more the mystery of the “humanation of the divine” is revealed, and
the better incarnational Christian theory makes its point. The more the
child acts and looks like a child, the more astonishing and significant
his divinity appears, and the more we recognize in his own psychologi-
cal unity the goal—set before us rather than in our past—of our own
development as adults. The “little child” that the paintings instruct us
wordlessly to become is here represented, not as a limitation or even a
return, but as a further synthesis, beyond the necessary fall into the divi-
sion of adulthood. The child announces the unification of the oppo-
sites—flesh and spirit, mind and heart—which is the goal of human
development. And it is of particular dialectical significance that it was
here, at the onset of an epoch in which “adult” became a cultural, psy-
chological, and epistemological ideal, that the child archetype took on
this personal, psychological interest for adult development, and that
God—the primary image of wholeness—was stated not as an adult but
as a naked, playing infant.
In keeping with the growth of a naturalistic ideal in modernism,
the mythic elements of the child archetype experienced a subtle but
increasing obscuration as the art of the Renaissance reached its apogee
and was transformed along with the world it was representing. This
was already reflected in the legendary psychological accuracy of
Leonardo’s (1452–1519) work, whereby even the figures of the holy
family, while presented in a fully traditional manner, show with an
almost uncanny immediacy their individual, idiosyncratic personalities,
which tend to deemphasize the mythic and archetypal elements. In
Michaelangelo (1475–1564), the brooding interiority of the human
began to make earlier painters like Raphael (1483–1520) look psycho-
logically naive.
This more radical naturalism of the High Renaissance increased
steadily through Mannerism and the Baroque. In the sixteenth and sev-
enteenth centuries, painters like Carravaggio (1573–1610), Parmigian-
ino (1503–1540), and Rubens (1577–1640) created transitional forms
between the iconography of the humanation of the divine and a natura-
listic iconography from which the divine seems to have withdrawn. In
Parmigianino’s Madonna with the Long Neck (c. 1540, Florence, Uffizi
Kennedy02 1/11/06 10:36 AM Page 41
Gallery) the flesh of the divine pair itself is numinous, rather than evok-
ing or expressing the noumenon. Ostensibly, it assumes the icono-
graphic tradition of Renaissance incarnational theology, but there is a
not-so-subtle change toward the glory of the carnal in and for itself,
rather than the glory of redeemed or redeeming carnality. A spiritualiza-
tion of pure immanence begins to replace the naturalization of the spiri-
tual that incarnation implies. Rather than the divine taking on body, the
body in itself comes to be seen as divine—or, if not as divine, as com-
plete in its immanence, represented in its erotic beauty, through which it
comes to reference only itself, rather than to point beyond itself. When
the sensuality of the eros-agape union is portrayed in this increasingly
naturalistic style, it becomes—for example in the Madonna with the
Long Neck—sexually provocative. Heaven has drawn away from the
divine pair, leaving them as direct, unequivocal objects of desire.
In sixteenth- and seventeenth-century European art, the infant
Christ-Eros, although he by no means disappeared, began to lose his
symbolic power, and to become—as for example in Jose Ribera’s The
Holy Family with Saint Catherine (1648, Metropolitan Museum, New
York)—merely the youngest member of a rather mundane-looking holy
family, now portrayed as a unit, in idealization of Europe’s emerging
middle class nuclear family. In Northern Europe, children began to
appear in family portraits, which, for the Protestant bourgeoisie became
a new sort of icon. The golden age of seventeenth-century Dutch art
reveals the modern, newly “invented” child of the middle classes, typi-
cally portrayed with her mother, as in Hooch’s (1629–1684) portraits of
domestic life, or dressed up for a family portrait. These portraits, which
at first glance seem to portray children as “little adults”—an impression
created by the fact that they wear the same clothes as adults—when
given close attention, show a sensitivity to the nature of children—their
gaze, their posture—which is in continuity with Renaissance naturalism,
but which has escaped the melodramatic sensuality of mannerism. The
archetype of the divine child is muted, if only in the fact that the child is
portrayed as a part of a larger group, or when with her mother, in a
mundane activity setting. When the divine child motif does appear, par-
ticularly among the French and English aristocracy, it is either as an
occasion for a refined prurience or as a legitimation of royal power; it
has become an iconographic marker in the politics of class.
The rise and ascendency of the bourgeoisie made of the painter a
social observer rather than a theologian. The Dutch child dressed in his
father’s clothes is no less a child, but his new, more prominent but also
more strictly controlled role in the adult world is what the paintings
Kennedy02 1/11/06 10:36 AM Page 42
behind her (and the absent presences at whom she is looking) suggest
they are introjected images, and her retinue, so both slavishly and
indifferently attentive (including a faithful animal) can, by a slight dis-
placement of the imagination, be seen both as the real people they are,
and as creatures of her imagination, dream-figures in the tortuous nar-
rative landscape of childhood.
Las Meninas can also be understood as a first statement of a
modern twist on the divine child—the “enigmatic child,” the child who
has become a mystery to the adult, who is too removed from childhood
to experience it as anything but an ambiguous message from another
world.33 The Infanta’s watchful, removed facial expression, her stiff,
adult dress, her gaze fixed on an absent presence, her encirclement by a
troupe of retainers who, given her overwhelming centrality, appear
almost as other aspects of herself, reflect that different sort of wonder
that, from the mid-nineteenth century on, surround fictional and poetic
representations of children. This too is a divine child—an enigmatic
symbol of intimate otherness—but it is a symbol of alienation, akin to
madness and animality, both of which are also “divine,” rather than
unity. It reflects a new distance between adulthood and childhood,
rather than a recognition of the psychological centrality of childhood
throughout the life cycle. Thus, the ever-emerging iconography of mod-
ernism finally closed around the mythological theme of the divine child,
and expressed it negatively, rather than positively.
The periodic neoclassicisms of the modern world, when they do
invoke the ancient themes, do so with either a sentimentality or a self-
conscious eroticism that is a mockery of the power of Renaissance sym-
bolism. The “cute” erotic child of the world of advertising34 may be
said to be yet another image of this child, in which the spiritual evoca-
tion of divine carnality, or “innocent flesh” has become all flesh, and
the Eden to which she points an Eden of soaps, diapers, and baby
foods. But the divine child also appears periodically in spontaneous
images, for example in William Zorach’s Affection which evokes the
Hellenistic putti riding dolphins, or wrestling with geese. And Phillip
Evergood’s Lilly and the Sparrows (1939, Whitney Museum, New
York) portrays the edenic unity in a tenement window. There is no
longer a tradition like the Christ Child to carry the archetype, but it
emerges spontaneously in images that are, as they were in the High
Renaissance, also the most phenemonologically accurate, in that they
tend to express characteristics of the young child’s lived experience
which we recognize from our observations and interactions with chil-
dren themselves.
Kennedy02 1/11/06 10:36 AM Page 44
province; each, rather, is reflected in the other, and only in this recipro-
cal relation does each disclose its own meaning.”45
What in fact Traherne is projecting in his work is an image of the
lived experience of early childhood as a form of knowledge that could
be called “sacramental,” in that it operates in a participatory mode, and
grasps its object through a unifying act of the imagination, rather than
through the division implicit in analytic knowledge. It is this form of
knowledge that Romanticism, in reaction to the objectifying epistemol-
ogy of modern science, undertook to explore more than a century after
Traherne, and which reemerged in psychoanalytic theory yet another
century later in Winnicott’s notion of “transitional space.” Traherne’s is
a preliminary statement of Romantic epistemological themes, and a
bridge between their religious and psychological expressions. And the
uses he makes of infant awareness—to see it as both a founding, origi-
nal state and as a goal of adult development, is a first psychological
interpretation of Jesus’ command to “become as a little child.”
Traherne also stated other major themes that later preoccupied cer-
tain Romantics.46 One was the loss of continuity between childhood
and adulthood, and the sense that they represented two separate mani-
festations of the self. The adult not only must attempt to explain the
relationship between that self and this one, but to explain how they
could be so different. For the modern adult, childhood is a lost world;
for the poets of childhood of the seventeenth century, a lost paradise. To
regain it was not a matter, as it may have been with Crashaw or
Vaughan, of a regression, but of a dialectical reappropriation, involving
the journey out of what Traherne called Innocence, through the stages
of Sin and Grace, and on to Glory, which recovered the original open-
ness to the world that was given in childhood. So Traherne could say, “I
perceived that we were to live the life of God when we lived the true life
of nature according to knowledge: and that by blindness and corruption
we had strayed from it.”47
The way was prepared for the Romantic theme of finding the lost
connection by the decline, at the end of the eighteenth century, of the
literary genre called Pastoral and the rise during that same period of the
childhood autobiography, or Childhood.48 Both genres deal with an
original innocence, destroyed by a fall. In the earlier Pastoral, a primary
world in which nature and society are in perfect harmony—Arcady—is
interrupted. In the Childhood, the arcadian world has long since
receded beyond the view of social possibility and all that remains of it is
one’s childhood. The process of memory and the project of reappropria-
tion occurs, not—as in the Pastoral—in the mythic history of the race,
but in the history of the individual, and it happens in real time and
Kennedy02 1/11/06 10:36 AM Page 49
already present in Traherne, for whom the Infant is, if not the higher,
truer self, then the originary, prophetic manifestation of that true self,
to be recovered through adult spiritual discipline. As the poet Georges
Bernanos said, “The deadest of the dead is the little boy I used to be.
And yet, when the time comes, it is he who will resume his place at the
head of my life.”52
The religious crisis that was symptomatic of the Western middle
classes in the ages both of Enlightenment and Romance, made of child-
hood the Eden from which the adolescent, experiencing the loss of faith
in Church and creed, was expelled. It is significant that childhood came
to represent religious experience, because such experience, given the
young child’s place before religious discourse, is necessarily not one that
can be described in terms of confessional doctrine. So, as in Traherne’s
account, the spiritual experience lost in leaving early childhood is the
existential experience of the numinosity of the natural world—the
“glory” of wildflowers and grains of sand. It is a condition of percep-
tion rather than an exercise of the will, as Christianity more typically
was for the adult. Traherne says:
feeling eye itself, “wedded to this goodly universe in love and holy pas-
sion,” experiences the joy of unconditioned existence, and thereby finds
the world transformed.65
The reanimation of the perceptual universe characteristic of
Wordsworth’s vision is a reappropriation of the panvital cosmos of the
premoderns, based on a psychological rather than a theological ration-
ale, although it certainly could have theological implications. Perception
transformed in joy now “reads” the book of nature—the ancient Chris-
tian liber naturae—and finds “all things there look[ed] immortality,
revolving life, and greatness still revolving, infinite.” This renewal of
mind in nature through the imagination results, in turn, in a society of
persons that “is here a true Community, a genuine frame of many into
one incorporate. . . . One household, under God, for high and low.”66
Like many of his generation, Wordsworth was in his youth a pas-
sionate supporter of the ideals and goals of the French Revolution. His
desire for social transformation was not secondary to his thought, but
was deeply influenced by the failure of that most crucial of social exper-
iments. Having experienced the end of Enlightenment in the Terror, he
rejected the possibility of a planned utopia based on social engineering,
and henceforth assumed that the inner transformation of the individual
can be the only basis for a society redeemed from endemic structural
evil—which is nothing more (or less) than the principle of radical sepa-
ration. Romanticism is the Revolution internalized, a transformation of
consciousness in each adult, prefigured for each adult in his own child-
hood, which points to the infinite task of the formation of a human
society in which, as in early childhood, the distinction between public
and private self is abolished, we “live and feel in the present,” and live a
“unitary, undivided existence.” The polarities that make for the “divid-
edness, alienation, and inner deadness of modernity”—polarities
between spirit and matter, mind and nature, desire and contingency—
are overcome, leading, in Schiller’s words, to “a conflict fully reconciled
not only in the individual, but in society, . . . a free uniting of inclination
with the law, of a nature illuminated by the highest moral dignity,
briefly, none other than the ideal of beauty applied to actual life.”67
The developmental goal of the Romantic adult is also profoundly
informed by childhood through its relationship to play, which is the
modus operandi of children. For Schiller, the human ontolological voca-
tion is to build—in a dialectical overcoming of the polarization of spirit
and matter, of reason and the sensuous—a “third joyous kingdom of
play and of semblance, in which man is released from all that might be
called constraint, whether physical or moral.” The “aesthetic state” is
the form of consciousness of a “‘new age’ in which mankind will achieve
Kennedy02 1/11/06 10:36 AM Page 55
mind and nature that was Wordsworth’s ideal, and which made of the
young child, for him, a symbol of greatest significance for an inquiry
into subjectivity, and thereby the basis of a philosophy of human
nature.75 Once it is understood, as Eugen Fink put it, that “Being in its
totality functions like play,”76 then play becomes an ontological frame-
work for our understanding of the subject-world relation, and an indi-
vidual and cultural ideal.
The Romantic uses of childhood involved not only its emblematic char-
acter as prophetic of a psychological and sociocultural goal, but, more
practically, the actual historical work of the creation of that goal—the
“third joyous kingdom” or “third way of living”—and the social con-
struction of a style of human subjectivity which makes it possible. The
history of the Romantic period in Europe and even the U.S. is filled
with extraordinary social experiments—experiments that extend to the
level of the reconstruction, not just of economy, but of family and sexu-
ality. The communist impulse and aspiration was in no way created by
Marx, but he provided it with a grand theory of history. The two social-
ist visionaries St. Simon and Fourier were spiritually affiliated with
Wordsworth and Schiller to the extent that they understood the funda-
mental reconstruction of social forms as in mutual causal relationship
with the reconstruction of subjectivity.
The efficient cause of Romantic social and political theory was the
social nemesis of rapid industrialization, the accumulation of capital in
the hands of the few, and aggressive centralized state control of popula-
tions. Universal compulsory education, which emerged during the early
nineteenth century, was fueled, not by a concern for a marriage of mind
and nature, but by the ambition of the increasingly hegemonic and reac-
tionary nation-state and its dominant elites to shape the world to their
political, social and economic interests. The reproductive goals of state
and economy and the technological ambitions of the Industrial Revolu-
tion made early and increasingly binding alliance: the “factory model”
of schooling is virtually synonymous with universal education in the
West. Seen dialectically, this harnessing of education to individual and
social repression and economic exploitation may have been necessary in
order to create a society with enough economic surplus to allow for the
leisure necessary for the universal emergence of the “third way.” If this
is the case, the West is now in a prolonged and difficult transition, for
the circular problem that plagues this hope is that the economic justice
Kennedy02 1/11/06 10:36 AM Page 57
adults who worked there thought that children could or should be thus
sacrificed—that they were expendable, or that they had nothing more to
offer than to be shaped by such a system. Such adults either don’t rec-
ognize the primordial child—themselves or the child before them—or
consider the “third way of living” to be a narcissistic, decadent ideal,
impractical, hubristic (“spoiled”), dangerous, and better expunged
through mechanical habituation. This returns us to the questions posed
in the first chapter concerning the characteristics, causes, and implica-
tions of the ideology of adulthood, or “adultism,” which lies at the
heart of the stubborn and pervasive mediocrity of the theory and prac-
tices of traditional schooling.
To get a sense of the range and depth of this particular and near
universal—however sentimentalized—form of the adult-child relation, it
is necessary to at least look into the history of adulthood, particularly in
the area of adult self-understanding. If “adult-child” is an inseparable,
contrastive pair, then any adult construction of subjectivity will imply a
construction of the child subject—both within me (“inner child”) and
outside of me (the child before me). If the child is colonized in the
modern Western structures of schooling, she is colonized within the
subjective structure of the adults who are her caretakers. And if the
adult-child relation is changing, then a different adult-child balance or
economy is being created within modal adult subjectivity, and adult
subjectivity is changing. The next chapter is dedicated to exploring fur-
ther both that chiasmic structure adult-child, and its implications for
individual, cultural, and social transformation.
Kennedy03 1/11/06 10:37 AM Page 63
It has already been suggested that early modernism was the historical
moment at which there began an increasing social separation between
adult and child through age-graded institutions, economic and domestic
isolation, and, over centuries, psychological theories of childhood that
acted to objectify children as a separate class. One could go further and
claim that, just as Philippe Aries, in his seminal study of the history of
childhood2 made the phrase “invention of childhood” famous, so this
moment in Western history was also the moment of the invention of
adulthood, or at least the form of adulthood of our age.
The history of adulthood in the West—in the privileged, patriar-
chal West anyway, which is mostly what we have a record of—is char-
acterized by an attitude toward childhood and children that I have
called “adultism.” Like racism, ethnocentrism, and sexism, adultism is
based on what appear to be empirical differences—in anatomy, neural
development, ego-structure, psychoculture, size, and physical strength.
These “real” differences very often lead to “subspeciation,” or the ten-
dency to regard and to treat certain human others implicitly as if they
were members of a separate species. As a psychological phenomenon,
63
Kennedy03 1/11/06 10:37 AM Page 64
words, the three “elements into tune with one another by adjusting the
tension of each to the right pitch,” which he most often expresses as a
situation of internal hierarchy. The child of Western patriarchal ration-
alism represents the ambiguity and ambivalence of what is given as the
human at the beginning of the life cycle, and the possibility of the con-
struction of an ideal self in which “each part of his nature is exercising
its proper function, of ruling or of being ruled.”10 The disciplinary con-
struction of the Platonic self is carried on into adult life in the history of
Western subjectivity in what Foucault has called “the technologies of
the [male adult] self.”11 Unity of self is accomplished only through the
eternal vigilance of reason over appetite and will, a product of constant
self-examination and readjustment through self-discipline. This system
of internal relations of domination was replicated macrocosmically, not
just in the utopia of Plato’s Republic, but in the very real Indo-Euro-
pean social political class system as a whole, where kings (reason) con-
trolled warriors (emotions, spirited will), who in turn ruled over the
agricultural classes (appetite).12 Once this domination model is internal-
ized as an ideal of intrasubjective power relations—an internalization
that has its first statement in the Republic—a technology becomes nec-
essary in order to accomplish adulthood. This technology is education,
which Aristotle defines as being “brought up in a particular way from
our very youth, as Plato says, so as both to delight in and to be pained
by the things that we ought; for this is the right education.”13 Education
as habituation by adults then presents itself as a ritual of force and
inscription, and an absolute cultural necessity.
Those who speak of the “invention” of childhood in the Renais-
sance and early modern period might more safely use the term “reinven-
tion,” for children have always been as much imagined as experienced
by adults. And the post-medieval reinvention of childhood is necessarily
an aspect of the reinvention of adulthood, in this case with similarities
to the adult of Greco-Roman antiquity, albeit in a dramatically different
cultural context, and with a different form of adult self-explanation.
The attitudes and behaviors Foucault describes as the “cultivation of
the self,” common among Stoics and Epicureans in the first two cen-
turies CE, have much in common with the psychosocial set of emergent
middle-class values of adulthood in early modern Europe. In both cases
there is a new emphasis on the individual as a discrete and separated
subjectivity, on impulse control, on self-examination, or—as befits the
new, print-based information environment of modernity—“reading”
oneself.
Foucault described the first two centuries CE in the Hellenistic
world as “the summit of a curve: a kind of golden age in the cultivation
Kennedy03 1/11/06 10:37 AM Page 67
dialogue with their own children is the extent to which their own par-
ents and teachers were in dialogue with them when they were children.
The present Western historical moment contains—like any histori-
cal moment—a number of contradictions: an educational system that
still largely colonizes childhood; a growing culture of adults who believe
in and practice dialogue with their children and expect the educational
system to do so as well; either increasing incidences of or increasing dis-
closure of incidences of sexual abuse of children; the cultural phenome-
non of the “disappearance of childhood”—that is, the putative breaking
down of “the dividing line” between adulthood and childhood—and an
emergent reformulation of adult subjectivity, goaded forward by a
myriad of influences, the most obvious of which is a new individual and
cultural intervisibility made possible by an increasingly global, intercon-
nected electronic information environment. In the search for a narrative
capable of recognizing and including all of these phenomena, I want
first to circle back yet again, in a closer approach, to the historical
accounts we do have of the adult-child relation in the West, and search
for their logic in a narrative that combines the accounts we have both of
the history of childhood and of adulthood. I want to try to show what I
have already suggested—a dialectical movement leading to the present
situation, which assumes the necessity of each previous moment to the
one succeeding it.
This dialectical narrative is symmetrical with the hermeneutical
theory presented in Chapter 1, which is a narrative about the conditions
and possibilities of dialogue per se. I want to consider adult-child dia-
logue both as a possibility within each cultural epoch of history, and as
the metadialogue represented by the interrelations between succeeding
cultural epochs—their themes, their emphases, and the dialectical logic
of their transformations. What motivates this consideration is the
search for an understanding that can guide a normative inquiry into the
praxis, not just of child rearing and education, but of the cultural and
social and political transformation that optimal child rearing and edu-
cation always promise.
like the “problem of other minds.” Like the cosmos of the young child,
the oral/aural cosmos was “egocentric” in the sense that, as the histo-
rian of culture Walter Ong has pointed out, a speaking and hearing
world “situates man in the middle of actuality and in simultaneity,” and
does not even entertain the notion of a knowledge that is separated
from the deepest sort of personal commitment. In this psychoworld,
knowledge is communication, an active principle within things—com-
municating from their life rather than from an understanding of cover-
ing laws, or principles outside of the things they regulate or describe.
This world is whole and self-communicating and for this kind of under-
standing, being is event—hence personal and interactive—rather than
something neutral, impersonal, or simply “there.”38
The invention of moveable print came in 1450, fifty years before
Erasmus’ etiquette manual—the text upon which Elias bases his analysis
of the transformation of adult subjectivity—became the first best seller
(after the Bible), in an information environment that had been trans-
formed, relatively speaking, as rapidly as the computer transformed the
late twentieth century’s. The argument for the critical effect of informa-
tion environment on the construction of modal personality is based on
the assumption that, as Ong puts it, “intelligence is relentlessly reflex-
ive, so that even the external tools that it uses to implement its work-
ings become ‘internalized’, that is, part of its own reflexive process.”39
With the rapid growth of the printing press, the external tool of not just
the written, but the mechanically printed (i.e., standardized, universally
distributed) word was fully internalized by Western culture. This inter-
nalization led, according to Ong, to a widespread reorganization of the
“sensorium,”40 whereby the primacy of the oral/aural sense axis was
replaced by that of the visual, with a corresponding shift in the value
and even function of the senses in knowledge-construction.
What Ong has referred to as the “psychodynamics of orality”—the
psychological characteristics or style of subjectivity of oral as opposed
to literate cultures—bear an interesting resemblance to the psychody-
namics of young children. Primary oral culture’s emphasis on the magi-
cal, illocutionary aspects of language, its emphasis on communication,
on formulaic expression, its tendency to “totalize,” its closeness to the
human lifeworld, its empathetic and participatory mode of apprehend-
ing the world, its concrete, contextual, complexive forms of categoriza-
tion, the mythic and agonistic qualities of its characteristic narrative, its
“conservative holism” toward persons and situations, its form of tem-
poralization41—all of these modes are familiar to students of the young
child. By contrast, the psychodynamics of literacy that swept sixteenth-
century Europe evoke the modal subjectivity of the modern, egosyn-
Kennedy03 1/11/06 10:37 AM Page 81
And now another story, an even grander narrative, which claims that
the adult-child relation has in fact been evolving over Western cultural
Kennedy03 1/11/06 10:37 AM Page 86
time, and that each stage in this evolution represents a closer approach
between the two. The direction of this evolution has—seen from the
psychohistorical perspective just presented—been toward separation.
Seen from a dialectical perspective, this separation is understood as a
moment implicitly oriented toward overcoming separation in a more
highly developed unity, or unity-in-difference. This is the story of adult-
hood separating from, then journeying toward a reencounter with child-
hood on another level. It is based on an understanding of both
collective and individual development as beginning in undifferentiated
fusion, followed by splitting and separation of elements, and leading
through periods of growth and crisis to a reintegration of those ele-
ments as a differentiated, articulated unity. In psychoanalytic parlance,
they are reconstellated under what Jung called a “transcendent func-
tion,” a dialectical third that “resolves the tension—of energy and con-
tent—existing between the ego stability of consciousness and the
contrary tendency of the unconscious to overwhelm it.”54 The story
leads to the hypothesis—to be taken up in the next chapter—that the
West is currently a century or two into a historical moment in which
adultism is being overcome in those same middle classes in which it
arose, and that there is emerging, not only a new form of adult-child
relation, but a new form of adult subjectivity that results from this rela-
tion, since it is based on the adult’s relationship with his own child-
hood, which is to say a new relationship between the elements of his or
her own subjective structure.
In antiquity, as this story—developed by psychohistorian Lloyd
deMause55—goes, adults were fused with their children to such an
extent that they not only projected their shadow contents onto them,
but acted upon those projections, and commonly battered and even
murdered them as a result. According to deMause, infanticide was
common in the ancient world, and what we would call child abuse—
both physical and sexual—was a norm. The child was the “toilet lap”
for the unresolved sexual and aggressive contents of adults. Children
who expressed instinctual needs or aggression evoked those same
poorly contained contents in adults, leading to murderous reaction,
or—what is virtually the same thing—to considering them as scarcely
human, accepted into life at the discretion of the head of the family
(pater potestias). This was the “Infanticidal Mode” of the adult-child
relation, which prevailed well into the first millenium.
The second mode, Abandonment, represented a partial withdrawal
or containment of the projective reaction of adults to children. Now,
especially under the influence of Christianity, infanticide was no longer
Kennedy03 1/11/06 10:37 AM Page 87
the shadow projection in the needy child, but it doesn’t trigger extreme
violence or abandonment; in fact Christian and in particular Calvinist
anthropology could even be seen as a first stage in owning the shadow.
Being able to recognize it in himself, and even attribute it to human
nature in general, is a step beyond projecting it onto the other in the
form of child, slave, woman, “native” or “barbarian.” It is separated
and well-enough contained within the adult that he begins to attribute
it, not just to infantile, but to human nature in general.
With the Intrusive Mode, which was more or less coterminous with
Renaissance, Reformation, and the gradual emergence of capitalism and
the middle classes—that is, the rise of the modern reality principle—we
rejoin the narrative of the invention of adulthood. Here the adult has
separated himself from the child to the extent that he sees the possibility
of a methodical process of eradication of the child “nature” (thereby
securing again and vindicating the eradication of his own “fallen
nature”) through technologies of child rearing and education. The
shadow contents are still split off within the adult and projected onto
the paradigmatic other—the child, that “stranger who while being
Other is me”—but the instinctual danger that the child represents is rec-
ognized as within all of us. The responsible parent must “reach inside
the child and rearrange her very insides.”57 Now mental punishment is
preferred over physical punishment, although the latter is sometimes
necessary. Thus at the height of Reformational notions of innate sinful-
ness, Protestant religious and psychological individualism opens the
door to the possibility of overcoming this sinfulness through technolo-
gies of the self; and the primary technology of the self, applied to the
other, is education, training, and methodical, systematic planned action
upon the infant body—in short, “discipline.” As a German child-rearing
manual of 1748 assures us, “If willfulness and wickedness are not
driven out, it is impossible to give a child a good education. The
moment these flaws appear in a child, it is high time to resist this evil so
that it does not become ingrained through habit and the children do not
become thoroughly depraved.” And the author adds a rationale that
evokes in a few sentences the level of splitting, fragmentation, and
denial of the unconscious required by the new instinctual economy:
One of the advantages of these early years is that then force and
compulsion can be used. Over the years, children forget every-
thing that ever happened to them in early childhood. If their
wills can be broken at this time, they will never remember after-
wards that they had a will, and for this very reason the severity
that is required will not have any serious consequences.58
Kennedy03 1/11/06 10:37 AM Page 89
from the outside world and expelling bad parts from the inner
world. There is a continual unconscious wandering of other
personalities into ourselves. . . . Every person, then, is many
persons . . . We are members of one another.69
childhood, for he undergoes dialogue, not just with his own interior
childhood, but with the persons of many actual children, and the cul-
ture of childhood in its current historical form. In this new formulation,
school remains what it has always been—a place where the child is
introduced to the discourses and the forms of knowledge of adult cul-
ture, and to the culture of childhood of her own time. But when the
adult enters this experience as a subject-in-process, as a “decentered”
ego for whom the child is an interlocutor rather than an object of
manipulation, the school is understood as the communicative space in
which children and adults are in a process of mutual transformation.
School is the cultural “between” of the dialogical relation, the space of
difference, which is the space neither of the subject nor the object, the
adult or the child, but where their forms of life meet and converse. It is
analogous to the theater, or the artist’s studio. It is a space of play and
creativity, where new cultural forms, new forms of subject-object rela-
tion, and new forms of negotiation between primary and secondary
process are tried out. It is the space where life and art meet in the inter-
ests of individual, cultural, and social transformation.
The adult involved in the life-cycle moment that Erik Erikson
called the “generative”—the moment of turning and caring for the
next generation73—is also the moment that Jung identifies as the onset
of individuation—the process of the decentering of the ego in the inter-
ests of further self-integration. This, in turn, is identified with Levinas’
“rupture of the egoist-I and its reconditioning in the face of the other,”
or the moment of the emergence of a new form of alterity, or being-in-
relation-to-the-other. As the monotheistic, hierarchical self is decon-
structed, the self understood as in a continual process of reconstruction
becomes possible. The subject-in-process is a form of selfhood whose
boundaries—both internal and external—have become problematized.
It is the end of what Elias called the “discrete self,” or homo clausus
(closed man), the epistemological subject of classical philosophy, the
self who might as well have come into the world as an adult, whose
“core, his being, his true self appears . . . as something divided within
him by an invisible wall from everything outside, including every other
human being.”74 Homo Clausus is the adult self of the Intrusive adult-
child relation, in whom childhood is dramatically split off, invested
with ambivalent projections and identifications, and projected onto the
real child.
The Intrusive form of adult subjectivity showed the first signs of its
eventual transformation in the first half of the nineteenth century under
the influence what deMause has called the Socializing Mode. Here the
parent still understands the child as an instinctually ambivalent crea-
Kennedy03 1/11/06 10:37 AM Page 97
ture, but the element of danger has been reduced to the extent that the
adult now identifies with that instinctual ambivalence, and is no longer
blindsided by it in her own psychic economy. For the authors of the
early-nineteenth-century form of autobiography called the Childhood,
the child was denizen of a lost paradise of self-world unity, or the myth
of the wild man projected backwards and placed in his original Eden.
For the theologically liberal middle classes, this wildness was reappro-
priated and redeemed as a form of energy that did not need to be
forcibly excised or repressed or suppressed in children. Certain cultur-
ally influential adults no longer felt the need to “reach into the very
insides” of the child through discipline, but rather to create forms and
styles of parenting and education that provided structures that shaped
the “wildness” into socially acceptable forms. This is first fruits of
Romanticism’s affirmation of the unconscious and the irrational, con-
temporary with the new culture wars then raging in Christian circles
over the doctrine of original sin.
At this moment in the adult-child relation, a new metaphor of
childhood began to emerge in adult discourse—the child as plant, and
education as gardening. The organic metaphor replaced earlier Ambiva-
lent and Intrusive metaphors of malleable wax and tabula rasa. The
gardener need only provide enough light, enough water, perhaps
(depending on the child) some weeding, and a nutrient-rich soil for the
emergence of a psychologically healthy adult. The child still represented
nature, and nature still needed to be tamed—but not forcibly subdued.
The plant is nature understood as endowed with an internal develop-
mental plan, which, given the right conditions, will unfold of itself. A
continuity had been established between the child and the adult.
Wordsworth’s phrase “the child is father to the man,” which seems so
obvious today as to appear tautological, was in the nineteenth century,
a dawning realization. The Intrusive Mode, which constructed adult-
hood as completely separate from adulthood—and consciousness, rep-
resented by ego, as completely separate from the unconscious— had
reached its term, and the moment of the possibility of dialogue had
arrived. At this furthest moment of hermeneutical distantiation, the
adult turned and began to face the child.
Dialogue becomes possible at the dialectical moment of separation
because it is only at this moment that there is the possibility of a critical
stance toward our own projections. The projective reaction is now even
further controlled, for the adult recognizes his own nature in the
instinctual expression of the child—a nature that, in the Socializing
Mode, still needs to be shaped, but not forcibly reconstructed. The
advent of the Socializing Mode was in fact the historical moment in
Kennedy03 1/11/06 10:37 AM Page 98
Boundary Work
Homo clausus fell slowly apart over the course of the twentieth century.
The urges and tendencies that led to his deconstruction came from
many quarters. The rise and ascendancy of evolutionary theory refor-
mulated Western notions of personal/cultural development and change.
The Freudian revolution coincided with the rise of multiple visions of
selfhood through the findings of cultural anthropology, which in turn
emerged from the ever-increasing intervisibility of cultures that followed
the explosion of travel and communications technologies. That explo-
sion has now resulted in a transformed information environment. The
silent, logical cosmos of print—the cosmos of the discrete self—is rap-
idly giving way to the new electronic, digitized cosmos of binary code.
The new information world is as dramatically new as was the
world of the book for the fifteenth and sixteenth centuries. It is different
because it is a more plural world—where digital and analogical (of both
voice and picture and printed word) modes meet and mix, but above all
where space and time are overcome in the simulacrum, the representa-
tion, or the “virtual.” Now the cultural experience of subjectivity and
intersubjectivity is both immediate and removed: self is here and there,
other is there and here. One is everywhere and nowhere.
105
Kennedy04 1/11/06 10:37 AM Page 106
the space, but are only continually passing through it. In a society that
is moving over the boundaries of the classical “modern,” the elements
of the collective are so inextricably interdependent that one saboteur
could bring down the whole system, yet each individual unit of the
system lives as if it were a completely independent individual.
Whether this is a real or only apparent paradox, the contradiction
between the individual and the collective of modernism is now reaching
a dialectical moment of crisis, which is both triggered and expressed
through the technological development of the new kind of time-space of
media, and the new information environment that results from this
development. Now, wherever there is a camera or a modem connected
to the vast planetary network of fiber-optic cable, a rapidly increasing
number of subjects can be “there” through the simulacrum of sound
and image. This new collective dimension is constructed on the basis of
the subject’s lived space and time, but is in fact a transcendent space-
time continuum. As a space, it represents omni-presence, the possibility
of being everywhere at once, which also means being nowhere in partic-
ular; temporally, it abolishes the past, and makes every representation a
now, which also implies never. As such, it produces, as Gianni Vattimo
has suggested, “a generalized cultural contamination in a world which
no longer offers a sharp split between subject and object, sameness and
otherness, or fiction and truth.”3 The relationship between individual
and collective constructed by the new information environment con-
founds subjectivity itself. One can only appear in an Internet chat room,
for example, through connecting with the collective virtual field; but
one’s appearance, unlike an appearance in the space of preliterate oral-
ity, is not an appearance at all. The I that appears is by definition a rep-
resentation, and as such a “play self”—a self of infinite possibilities,
none of them realizable except virtually, in the realm of “as if.” Tech-
nology has developed a new way for persons to be present to each other
in space and time.
From one point of view, the virtual social space of the chat room is
one in which I can undertake the chief project of the subject-in-process,
which is to resolve, through the play of my relations with the world and
the other, the internal contradictions of my own subjectivity, as part of a
process of continual reconstruction. Like the subjective play space of
the young child, it is transitional, in the sense that it offers a reconfigu-
ration of the subjective and objective poles of experience—a bridge
between primary and secondary process, desire and reality. And it is
itself an organon, a subject. It replaces the previous subjective organons
of the family, the tribe, and the nation. As the former organons bound
subjects together in a larger subjectivity, the larger subject in this case is
Kennedy04 1/11/06 10:37 AM Page 109
new sort of adult subjectivity, and if a new sort of adult subjectivity can
only be produced by empathic parenting, then where does or can
change enter the system?
Another major dimension of the cultural construction of subjectiv-
ity, also related to field theory, has to do with the unicity or plurality of
the components of human selfhood, and by implication the extent to
which the self is or is not understood as constituted by otherness. In a
field theory of selfhood, the subject includes its alters, or the other
selves—both internal and external—with which it is in relation, whether
at the moment or as a result of past relations, as well as the collective
subject, whether that be defined in terms of family, clan, tribe, nation,
species, genus, or cosmos. Historically, even discrete theories of the self
include internal plurality, whereas a field theory assumes plurality both
within and across subjective boundaries. Plato’s basic Indoeuropean for-
mulation included, as we have seen, three components—reason
(logikos), the passionate or the “spirited element” (thumos), and
instinctual desire (epithumia)—and the successful self-structure was
understood as a necessarily imposed hierarchical unity among the three.
Aristotle’s permutation of Plato’s theory of self is an organic, biologistic
one, but retains its hierarchical structure. Both are subjective structures
that are held in place by reason, or, as Aristotle defined it, the “execu-
tive” function. Neither are dialectical models—that is, neither assume a
transformative or reconstructive interplay between the plural elements
of the self, but rather are based on an integrative model of a coming
into a unitary or harmonic situation of internal “right relation.”
Plato’s theory of self does take intersubjectivity into account in an
interesting way. As given to us in the Republic, the internal elements of
the self are, as we have seen, writ large in the “natural” elements of
social and political configuration. The appetitive or instinct-determined
element is represented by the lower classes of agriculturalists and crafts-
men and tradesmen—the producers (the “iron”). The level of passion or
spirited will is represented by a warrior class (“silver”), and reason by
an intellectual ruling class (“gold”). Here internal relations reflect and
are reflected by external ones, and vice versa, but the task of subjectiv-
ity is not so much to develop or transform or to create itself as it is to
find its place in the larger cosmic order of intrinsic human character
and function. This, for Plato, represents dikaiosune—“justice,” “moral-
ity,” or “well-being,” life lived in right relation with one’s own nature.
It assumes, as already pointed out, relations of hierarchical domination,
not just within the polis, but within the individual. The states and activ-
ities that tend to push or displace subjectivity toward change, transfor-
mation, and development—childhood, myth, and experimental art—are
Kennedy04 1/11/06 10:37 AM Page 111
dangerous for this form of subjectivity, for they trigger inquiry and
dialectical change, which almost by definition represents error, danger,
and social disintegration.
Plato’s is a field-self to the extent that each internal dimension is
represented externally, and vice versa. Although I may be a genetically
determined member of the class of “iron,” there is a “gold” dimension
within me, and I leave that dimension to be expressed externally
through those who are genetically “gold.” If I am gold, then the iron
part of myself is an alter, and so on. Whichever class I am a member of,
I live in a social world in which members of the two other classes
express genetically two elements of myself which I don’t. In this part-
whole relation, I see the disciplinary structure that is the normative
ideal of my own subjectivity displayed and worked out in the larger
social, political, and economic fabric. This suggests—albeit in a mythic
formulation—a complicated situation of alterity, but a clearly demar-
cated and ritualized one.
Aristotle’s implicit theory of subjectivity is based, not on a set of
correspondences between the micro and the macro, the individual and
society, but on an organismic, biological metaphor. Lower and higher
forms are here represented as a developmental chain of being reaching
from the vegetative soul to the animal soul to the human, all drawn
toward an omega point by the unmoved mover, the teleological both
origin and endpoint of an ultimately concentric cosmos. As Plato’s
philosopher king has the lower functions of spirited will and appetite
within, so Aristotle’s man has the vegetative and the animal souls within
him, and in a similar hierarchical relation. But Aristotle’s formulation
implies change and development, if only implicitly: the movement from
vegetative to animal to human implies both an evolutionary and a
developmental path. And the three categories are in a nesting hierar-
chy—each controls the one below it, not through demanding obedience,
but through sublating it.6
Plato’s and Aristotle’s are founding theoretical models of self in the
Western tradition—first and enduring formulations. They were carried
forward in a practical, applied way by the Stoic/Epicurean tradition,
associated with the rise of pan-Hellenism through the vehicle of
empire—both Alexandrian and Roman—where they were cashed in in
the form of techniques and attitudes designated as “care of the self.”
Care of the self implies what Foucault called “technologies of the self.”
This second term is a semantic intensification of the first that captures
this crucial moment in the evolution of the Western subject in which the
Platonic/Aristotelian self turned on itself with tools—the private diary,
the daily meditation during which one accounts for one’s thoughts and
Kennedy04 1/11/06 10:37 AM Page 112
alistic upsurge and the social and political process that would have
detached individuals from their traditional affiliations” during the
period of late Roman Empire9 is a historical pattern that we also find
associated with the rise of middle-class individualism in the European
early-modern period, and which in late-modern Western culture reaches
crisis proportions, in paradoxical, inverse relationship with economic,
technological, and infrastructural field-dependence.
In Stoicism and then Christianity, the modern Western discrete
individual was, if not born, at least announced. From our perspective, it
was a male patriarchal/adultist and colonialist individual. It colonized
within as it colonized without. Those rejected and manipulated ele-
ments of selfhood that were projected onto the slave, the woman, and
the child were—as is evidenced by the very fact of their projection—ele-
ments that represented danger to the ruling element of reason, and
therefore led to the attempt to dominate those elements, both within the
self and outside it. The Stoic subject, like the modern, was in a relation-
ship of what twentieth-century psychoanalysts, following Freud’s refor-
mulation of subjectivity, would later call “splitting” with desire, or the
“passions”—“the irrational power within us which refuses to obey
reason.”10
It would take a further deconstruction of subjectivity, arrived at
dialectically through a developmental process of distanceiation and sub-
sequent dialogue, before the projections were in a position to be with-
drawn—or, more accurately, to enter awareness as internal elements of
the psyche rather than as unambiguous and socially enforced “facts”
about the alien or different other. In fact in the traditional Western his-
torical narrative, the emergent discrete individual of late antiquity dis-
appeared along with the Roman Empire, and, as part of empire’s
dissolution, retreated into Christian monasticism, where it percolated in
ritualized isolation as the “dark ages” swept Europe. In the psychologi-
cal hothouse of the monastery, care of the self became an obsessive self-
scrutiny, in which Platonic reason was associated with the gaze of God,
or the absolute. The monastery was the moment of the new, private
self’s retreat from the world altogether, polarizing the promiscuous
sociability and characteristic field-dependent subjectivity of emerging
“barbarian” medieval Europe.
In Freudian terms, both Stoic and modern middle-class subjectivity
put ego in a new relationship with the other elements of the psyche. The
Stoic subject discovered the superego, the watcher within, who became
both the analyst and the judge of the new, problematized self. Subjectiv-
ity becomes a puzzle, an unfamiliar and sometimes treacherous territory
characterized by blind spots and obscurities, and subject to paradoxical
Kennedy04 1/11/06 10:37 AM Page 114
The ontological basis for the move from discrete subject to intersubject
had already been initiated in the paradigm change introduced by Dar-
winian evolutionary thought, which implicitly redefined organism and
environment—or self and world—as a unity, and their relationship as
interactive, mutually determinative, and in constant equilibrative trans-
formation. With the emergence of gestalt psychology, field and systems
theory—already more fully developed in physics—entered the realm of
the human subject, and initiated a new subject-world, self-other bound-
ary condition, which in turn has gradually redefined our notions of sub-
jectivity and intersubjectivity. Gestalt theory implicitly understands the
self as a form better defined as an organism than, as was implicit in the
ancient Platonic tripartite model, a discrete unit, or in Descartes, a spir-
itual entity. Self-as-organism has different kinds of boundaries than self-
as-unit. First, it is permeable, in interactive exchange with what it
shares boundaries with. It moves and reshapes as the boundaries of the
other do. It takes its definition from the other as well as giving the other
its definition. Its boundaries are irregular and continually shifting, and
those shifts are determined by the need for survival and mastery, or
equilibration of structures, or “integrity”—if by that term is understood
a state in which internal/subjective and external/intersubjective subsys-
tems are in a state of integration—which in turn means that they have a
dynamic functional balance, and are not in so much disjunction that
they threaten both the organism and the environment, or self and other.
From a field- and systems-theory perspective, the self is in contin-
ual negotiation with the other and the situation in which it finds itself
with the other, working to define itself as a diverse unity. It is both an
individual and part of a whole structure that is more than the sum of its
parts—a borderline phenomenon, which takes its identity from the
selves with which it shares boundaries as much as from some individual
teleological principle within itself. The subject-in-process is defined as
much by this border or boundary-work—the history and process of its
relations with its margins and interfaces—as by an idea of an internal
structure, or core. In its developmental vicissitudes, the subject’s bound-
aries are explored, probed, pushed against, raised, taken down,
adjusted, and so on, in a continual process of transformation.
Kennedy04 1/11/06 10:37 AM Page 121
who are also selfobjects: this is what the play of art, ritual, eroticism,
and philosophical inquiry are about. Psychoanalysis—at least following
Erikson’s and Jung’s widening of Freud’s horizon—assumes develop-
ment across the life course, and thus is often referred to as a new
religion for good reasons: it sets up the temenos—the “sacred enclo-
sure”—of the consultation room as a transitional space where subjectiv-
ity communes and interacts with its transcendent elements—meaning
those elements both within the subject herself and in the person of the
other—which are “alters” or self-parts within the whole system of the
intersubject. This is especially true of group therapy—and, by exten-
sion, the intensive group experience called “school”—where the sys-
temic aspects of intersubjective experience are triggered and magnified
through encounter in the transitional space with multiple others. The
psychotherapeutic movement may be understood as another dialectical
moment in the history of the care of the self, but it is a moment con-
structed on a different model of the self. It follows the moment of the
radical privatization of subjectivity in homo clausus, and accompanies
the emergence of a dialectical third term, which sublates both homo
clausus and the form of subjectivity that preceded it, the medieval col-
lective or fused self.
This third term, the intersubject, can also be identified with a mil-
lennial ideal that has shaped Western cultural aspirations at least since
the appearance of the Christ figure. In his late work Aion: Researches
into the Phenomenology of the Self, Jung finished his lifelong inquiry
into the symbological history of Western subjectivity with the sugges-
tion that Christ represents the implicit psychological goal of the individ-
uation process, a subjective state he called the Self. As we have seen, the
Self is for Jung a structure in which conscious and unconscious contents
have undergone a reconfiguration such that they are no longer in rela-
tions of antagonism or ambivalence, or mediated by repression, defense,
censorship, and consequent neurosis, but are integrated in a psychologi-
cal structure that allows their optimal interplay and intervisibility. This
ideal integration is an emergent system-balance achieved apart from
relations of hierarchy or domination of one part of the psyche by
another, which by analogical implication suggests the end of relations of
hierarchy and domination between subjects. This theme is found in
multiple images offered by Western post-Christian visionaries—whether
in Blake’s Marriage of Heaven and Hell, which announces (following
the eighteenth-century Swedish mystic Emmanuel Swedenborg) a new
psychological age, or the notion among Romantic poets and philoso-
phers of the unification of mind and nature; or Whitman’s new Ameri-
Kennedy04 1/11/06 10:37 AM Page 123
If this is the case, then the present moment offers an apparent para-
dox. On the one hand, normative or “politically correct” parental atti-
tudes toward children are characterized by the Empathic Mode. Broad
public sentiment is shocked and outraged by cases of infanticide, and
numerous agencies, both public and private, are dedicated to saving
children from all forms of abuse. Among the Western middle classes,
spanking children is now understood as physical abuse. Liberal
“experts” also commonly promulgate parenting protocols and method-
ologies in the popular press based on the empathic assumptions that
children are to be listened to and their felt needs taken seriously. Dissat-
isfaction with the intrusive and/or socializing character and practices of
the state-controlled public schools has reached—in the United States
anyway—the status of a permanent public disposition. The pronounce-
ments on childhood with which Rousseau astonished the world in
1763—“Childhood has its place in the scheme of human life. We must
view the man as a man, and the child as a child . . . Nature wants chil-
dren to be children before they are men. . . . Childhood has ways of
seeing, thinking and feeling particular to itself: nothing can be more
foolish than to seek to substitute our ways for them”34—have become
common coin. If one surveyed only the popular advice literature and
ignored the actual experience of children in Western cultures, one
would assume that children had never been more valued by adults, or
better cared for. And in one sense this is a valid assumption.
On the other hand, children are increasingly abandoned to the
institutions of the state—if “state” is understood in the broader sense to
include the corporate, media, and civic/legal worlds—schools, day-care
centers, afterschool programs, and organized programs that act to ghet-
toize children within an architectural environment relentlessly designed
in the image of low-level corporate office buildings—stripped-down
boxes filled with ugly furniture, set in increasingly dehumanized urban
and suburban landscapes bereft of the sorts of play zones and spaces
traditionally associated with childhood. Children are also abandoned to
the “main square” of the new information environment, the virtual
space and time of the media, which both constructs and manipulates
them as market-subjects, and exposes them regularly to multiple images
of the two aspects of adult life the exclusion of which the traditional
notion of childhood depends on—sexuality and violence. The decline of
the traditional nuclear family has placed many children in a sort of
demilitarized zone of familial relationships. Teachers in early-childhood
settings testify to the increasing levels of knowledge of sexual informa-
tion and corresponding vocabulary among young children, and homi-
Kennedy04 1/11/06 10:37 AM Page 135
The child, along with the “noble savage” of modern Western colonial-
ism, was the first to emerge to conquer—in classic theory-of-empire
fashion—from within, and to initiate the culture of postcolonialism.
Along with the “aboriginal” or “native,” the domesticated woman, the
“lower classes,” the madman, and more recently the “queer,” the child
represents the difference overlooked and projected by homo clausus.
The child and the woman are the most dangerously seductive of all, for
they are an enemy not at but within the gates—the wild man in the
bosom of the “civilized” family, repression’s “savage” displacement.
Along with the other “othered” ones, children carry what feminist
philosopher Sandra Harding has called an “epistemic privilege.” These
“others” represent alternative standpoints, or ways of seeing the world
based on a difference in material, class, physical, sexual—or, in the case
of the mad and young children—cognitive and even perceptual reality
from the dominant culture and its ways of knowing the world. Harding
refers to as them “valuable ‘strangers’ to the social order,” or “outsiders
within.”52 They are those marginalized by Eurocentric, patriarchal per-
sonal, interpersonal and social constructs. As we have seen, they are
typically screens for both the dark and the light projections of the dom-
inant class—both the shadow and the ideal of freedom from repression.
They are those “bondsmen” in Hegel’s master-slave relationship whose
identity is canceled, or put under erasure by the “desire” of the lord or
master, who, ironically, only knows himself through his mastery of
them—that is, through their negation—and therefore is dependent upon
them for his sense of self. As Hegel says of the desire of the lord, “First,
it has lost its own self, since it finds itself as an other being; secondly, it
has thereby sublated that other, for it does not regard the other as essen-
tially real, but sees its own self in the other.”53 As the conqueror proj-
ects his own split-off, unconscious contents onto the conquered and
distances her as the profane, the untouchable, the quintessential other,
so by a dialectical process, the split-off content appears in the other—in
the flesh—and becomes not just an adversary but a part of one’s own
subjective field, a “selfobject,” and as such, a potential interlocutor. The
slave shares in the master’s power because the master defines himself in
opposition to the slave, and therefore needs the slave as a dimension of
his own subjectivity.
Kennedy04 1/11/06 10:37 AM Page 143
1. Man has no body distinct from his Soul; for that call’d
Body is a portion of Soul discerned by the five Senses, the
chief inlets of Soul in this age.
2. Energy is the only life, and is from the Body; and Reason is
the bound or outward circumference of Energy.
3. Energy is Eternal Delight.65
could result in “the transformation of work into play.”68 The most logi-
cal cultural site for the institutionalization of this transformation—
which hinges on adults entering into dialogue both with their own
construction of childhood and with real children—is the school. And it
is the school to which, finally, we turn.
Kennedy04 1/11/06 10:37 AM Page 150
Kennedy05 1/11/06 10:38 AM Page 151
Reimagining School
151
Kennedy05 1/11/06 10:38 AM Page 152
The argument of this book has been that, although there are many vari-
ables that contribute to the evolution of subjectivity, the final determi-
native causal factor is the kind and quality of the adult-child
relationship itself—if only because it is through child rearing that any
cultural trait is reproduced. When the latter comes to be understood as
a relationship of dialogue, it is intimately associated with internal dia-
logue in the adult—the dialogue between the adult and his own “child”;
and according to the hermeneutic principal of subjectivity, internal dia-
logue is the dialectical engine of subjective transformation. That is, the
qualitative shifts in the adult-child relation over historical time have
directly to do with the shifts in the psychic economy of the adult that
result from internal dialogue. These shifts center in the organization and
reorganization of the relations between habit and impulse, conscious
and unconscious, superego (or “conscience”) and ego, and in a tempo-
ral dimension, of the relations between present, past, and future
(whether, for example, the adult considers himself capable of “starting
again,” “like a child”). To the extent to which they hinge on the ability
of the various dimensions of selfhood, some of which are in contradic-
tion, to listen to each other and to be moved by each other’s “reasons,”
they can be understood as relations of power. On its most fundamental
level, dialogue is about power, for it is based on the premise, as Martin
Buber put it, that “Each must expose himself wholly, in a real way, in
his humanly unavoidable partiality, and thereby experience himself in a
real way as limited by the other, so that the two suffer together the des-
tiny of our conditioned nature and meet one another in it.”21 This state-
ment can be applied to both external and internal dialogue.
When it moves across the shifting boundaries of the subject, inter-
nal dialogue forms the basis for dialogue with the other, who on the
Kennedy05 1/11/06 10:38 AM Page 159
What “it” says is connected for Buber with the “sign.” “Signs,” he
says, “happen to us without respite, living means being addressed, we
would need only to present ourselves and to perceive.”31 Although
Kennedy05 1/11/06 10:38 AM Page 162
Buber insists that the signs that “happen to us” cannot be predicted or
categorized, we may say that the adult in dialogue with childhood and
the child is in the realm of a specific order of signification, and that the
sign of childhood is received across that “abyss of historical conscious-
ness” between the adult and her childhood mentioned in Chapter 1
which characterizes the hermeneutical situation. The “it” that speaks to
the adult is the child’s form of life in its structure as a different relation-
ship between habit and impulse, reason and desire—a different tension
of consciousness. But this is not a sign unless it arrives uncategorized,
not—as in the monological, “educative” relationship, as something
“understood in advance”—but as a sign that triggers the appropriation
of a new or rediscovered form of knowledge in the adult. Therefore it
should not and in fact cannot be named or predicted, and in the end
must be understood as the sign of the difference, or alterity that makes
for genuine dialogue. It is the recognition of difference between adults
and children that leads adults to recognize and listen to the individual
voices of children, rather than to presume “to express the other’s claim
and even to understand the other better than the other understands
himself,” and thereby “seek to calculate how the other person will
behave.” It is the possibility of this recognition that gives the phenome-
non of school its importance, and makes of it a key intercultural space
of meeting and coconstruction.
Adults and children are faced with at least four kinds of concrete
difference. Physical and physiological difference—in size and weight,
patterns of activity level, hormonal and neuronal differences—either
result in or are translated into social difference, above all differences in
power, wealth, status, and degrees of independence. The existential dif-
ference between adults and children—the kind and quality of their lived
experience—is an expression both of physical and physiological differ-
ences and of social difference. It is different, for example, to negotiate
the world from a height of three or four feet, as opposed to five and a
half or six, and neuronal differences translate into differences in percep-
tion itself. Finally, different degrees of inductive experience make for a
different practical logic—the child’s cognitive maps and categorical
structures are typically not as complex as the adult’s, simply because she
has not been around as long. This is not to deny that children of five
may have developed a more sophisticated and functional structure of
judgment in their given life-context than some full-grown adults—espe-
cially in schools, which are designed at least partially with children in
mind. In fact one of the major characteristics of adultism is the ignorant
attribution of ignorance to children.
Kennedy05 1/11/06 10:38 AM Page 163
individuality again within a dual system of self and other: the intersub-
ject “can accomplish the act of relation in the acknowledgement of the
fundamental actuality of distance.”34 Broadly speaking, the premodern,
collective self is in a situation of psychological fusion with the other,
and the modern, discrete self is in a situation of isolation and objectifi-
cation. The intersubject is in a situation of dialogue, which sublates
both terms of the binary construct in a third structure that mediates dis-
tance and relation.
Dialogue assumes the rupture of the egoist-I and the reconstellation
of the ego-Self axis, which precipitates an internal reconstruction
whereby the self recognizes its own multiplicity, the otherness within
itself, and simultaneously that the other—who is also multiple—is a
part of its intersubjective field through projection and introjection. Dia-
logue both causes and is caused by reconstruction across the boundaries
of the self, but it emerges not as an experience of fusion or collective
identification, but as the recognition of the very otherness of the
other—the recognition that the other “is absolutely not myself” and
that the other is “the very one she is.” Dialogue implies accepting
another human being in his or her particularity as “the single one,” the
“Thou.”35 It requires the withdrawal of the projection of the egoist-I,
which, paradoxically, reveals, not just the individual who is absolutely
not myself, but the intersubjective structure of subjectivity that contains
us. I and the other are both more individualized through withdrawal of
the projection, and more recognizable as field beings, in that the struc-
ture of intersubjectivity is clarified when its contents (projections and
introjections) are distinguished from its formal structure—the structure
that carries and organizes those contents.36
The “between” of dialogue is both the between within the sub-
ject—the difference that the subject finds within herself—and the
between between subjects—the space of interlocution where self-other
boundaries become mutually transgressive and thereby negotiable
between persons. These two forms of alterity are in dialectical relation.
Together, they establish transitional or “potential” space—the space
outside the individual, but is not the external world, the space of cre-
ativity and transformative process. It is, as we have seen, the dialectical
“third way of living,” which mediates the inner reality of the individual
and the shared reality of the world that is external to individuals. The
transitional is a space of the deconstruction and reconstruction of inter-
human relations of all kinds, including relations of power—which
implies the dialectical overcoming of Hegel’s paradigmatic master-slave
relationship in the direction of equality—and relations involving the
reconstruction of mutual values and accepted social and political prac-
Kennedy05 1/11/06 10:38 AM Page 165
tices. It is the space of the more fluid relation between impulse and
habit that is childhood, and is marked above all by the sign of play,
which, as Winnicott has shown, corresponds in the world of adults to
the space of what he broadly calls “culture”: art, philosophy, religion,
intense relational experience, dreaming, envisioning.37
The transitional “between” is the site where the ego understood as
the bearer of the “same,” the “thematizing gaze,” the epistemological
subject who “never encounters anything truly other in the world”
because it assimilates the other to its own structures of judgment—
which, as we have seen, Levinas associates with Western reason—under-
goes reconstruction, creating at least the possibility of “the liberation of
the ego with regard to the self.”38 Philosopher Hugh Silverman calls it
“the space of difference which is neither that of the subject nor that of
the object”—a space of inquiry, in that inquiry involves “the appropria-
tion of a space which is neither that of the interpreter nor of the inter-
preted, but one which uncovers what most needs to be said with respect
to that which is interpreted”39—in which one is, in Buber’s terms,
“addressed” by the “sign.” The interlocutors enter dialogue as a space
in which the assumptions of both are put under interrogation, and in
which therefore the outcome is uncertain and emergent. Nor is there
any necessary expectation that difference will be overcome. If it is over-
come it will be through a higher resolution, a sublation, which will in
turn carry its own difference within it.
any given project, and to the extent to which the theme or topic of the
project is the outcome of a negotiation between the teacher—whose
interest is in communicating and transmitting the content and processes
of the disciplines—and the student’s interest.55 A project may be an
individual or a collaborative inquiry, and a certain proportion of each
day is devoted to it. It often calls for “field trips,” and requires suffi-
cient shop, studio, laboratory, and library spaces for its implementation.
As recently implemented in the schools of Reggio Emilia, projects fall
naturally into three categories: those that arise directly from the interest
of a child or children, those that reflect mutual interests of teachers and
children, and those chosen by teachers with certain cognitive or social
concepts in mind.57
The effect of such an emergent curriculum is to diversify grouping
practices, and thereby pedagogical strategies as well. At any given point
during the school day, groups ranging in size from one to twenty per-
sons may be found assembled, not to speak of whole-school assemblies
devoted to various purposes. Each of these groupings will have an
appropriate space in which to meet—a space that optimally both con-
tains, encourages, and contributes to the structure of the particular
activity in which the individual or group is engaged. Teachers will be
engaged in a corresponding variety of pedagogical activities—from lec-
ture or drill to small or large group facilitation to individual, small or
large group guided skills instruction. Some students will be engaged in
project work, alone or in small groups, some assembled in groups of
varying sizes for tutoring or skill instruction in subjects such as mathe-
matics or foreign languages; some will be writing or engaged in cooper-
ative editing or writing, some will be working on a dramatic
production, or practicing or performing music; some will be crafting an
object in shop or studio, some engaged in group critique of a work of
art, some engaged in observation of cellular structures in a laboratory,
and some engaged in communal literary or historical and philosophical
investigation, which includes dialogical inquiry.
If there is a set of content-expectations that form the conceptual
spine and the scope and sequence for curriculum, they are understood
as one dimension of the structure in which students and teachers enter
into dialogue in order to produce an emergent curriculum. If adults
decide, for example, that certain literacy, numeracy, musical, artistic,
computer, kinaesthetic, or other knowledge and skills are critical to the
school’s notion of a “good education,” then the principle of dialogue
requires that they find a way to bring that knowledge and those skills
forth in the context of the interest of the students. “Interest” of the stu-
dents does not necessarily imply their pleasure interests—there is no
Kennedy05 1/11/06 10:38 AM Page 177
always asked, but does so as if for the very first time. The experience of
communal dialogue about our most fundamental assumptions brings us
face to face with the original condition of philosophy—philosophy not
as didactics, and not just as conversation, but as an emergent, multivo-
cal, and interactive oral inquiry into questions that require an answer
before any further questions can be answered, yet which are in them-
selves unanswerable.62
So reconstructed, philosophy takes its place again, as in the
medieval synthesis, as the “queen of the sciences,” but in this case as an
oral event-structure like the Socratic, implicitly dedicated to the contin-
ual reconstruction of the answers to the same questions humans have
always asked, and always implicitly oriented to the underlying question,
“How are we to live?” In the school of the third way, this activity is
where the whole conceptual structure of the curriculum enters transi-
tional space. It is the space between the conceptual structures of the dis-
ciplines and the conceptual structures of each child and of the
community, and as such a space of interrogation and dialogue. Recall-
ing Winnicott’s characterization of transitional space as “outside the
individual, but . . . not the external world,” a space into which “the
child gathers objects or phenomena from external reality and uses these
in the service of . . . inner or personal reality,”63 philosophy as commu-
nal dialogical inquiry is the space where our assumptions, our funda-
mental beliefs enter into question for purposes of reconstruction. And
those beliefs are as much about ethical and moral questions as they are
about metaphysical or epistemological ones.
In a school of the third way, the dimension of collaborative philo-
sophical inquiry will be present throughout the emergent curriculum as
a form of problematization of belief—a first inquiry into the epistemol-
ogy, and by implication the methodology, of any discipline that is a part
of that curriculum. For example, a project that undertakes to examine
the architectural, economic, social, and cultural changes in a given
urban neighborhood in the last 100 years will naturally involve the
introduction of historical research, which in turn will call for an inquiry
into principles of historiography, which in turn will involve an inquiry
into the fundamental concepts that are at issue in the philosophy of his-
tory—what constitutes a historical “fact,” the question of historical
goal, direction, or pattern and the idea of “progress,” the question of
the narrative element in history (whether it can ever be anything but a
“story”), and, correspondingly, questions of interpretation: can history
ever in its very nature, be “objective”? Is all history revisionary? And
moving into ethical questions—can history be responsible or irresponsi-
ble, and if so, how does one do responsible history?
Kennedy05 1/11/06 10:38 AM Page 181
and those changes are passed to the next generation through the narrow
funnel of child rearing and education. The notion of finding a way to
predict how the changes happen implies that one could find a way to
direct and control them, which is exactly the dialectic of welfare work,
where one is concerned to understand others better than they under-
stand themselves. This is the attitude of adultism, which attempts, espe-
cially through schooling, to reconstitute the reality of the child as an
adult, rather than providing a space for a transition between childhood
and adulthood that allows for the dialectical preservation and presence
of childhood in adulthood, which in turn is the basis for the reconstruc-
tion of subjectivity.
Not only are causal factors both reciprocal and overdetermined,
but experience would seem to indicate that in the history of cultures
and societies the “highest” and “lowest” forms of subjectivity and
forms of relation are always present, and their interaction ambiguous
and even ironic. There will always be brutalization and dehumanization
and there will always be compassion and altruism; always the highest
form of idealism in action and the most egregious cynicism, venality,
and impoverished imagination; always surprising breakthroughs of the
good and dramatic failure and misunderstanding of the most noble
intentions. There will always be filial kindness and basic human solidar-
ity in the search for peace and justice, and there will always be perver-
sity, violence, and blind selfishness, both individual and social. To
attempt to construct a system, whether of child rearing or education,
which overcame this fundamental human condition would not only be
totalitarian, but its success would create an entropic social condition
from which the conditions for growth were removed.
Empathic parents will always in some cases inadvertently, and
against their own deepest wishes, raise children who become nonem-
pathic adults, and vice versa. To recognize multiplicity and contradiction
internally—in the self—is to recognize it in the larger system of subjectiv-
ity that is the collective, and on this account, Socrates was right when he
said that virtue cannot be taught.64 But multiplicity and contradiction
are the very conditions of change, and thus, logically, the kind and qual-
ity of multiplicity and contradiction themselves will change. The intellec-
tual, moral, and aesthetic mediocrity of the post-Intrusive school is a
result of institutional resistance to that change. Institutions and individu-
als resist change because present change—the situation visible to us at
any given moment—carries contradictions and multiple possibilities that
hint at alternate futures, not all of them positive. Negative and positive
elements and their conflict within a system are necessary to system trans-
formation, and in matters related to the historical construction of subjec-
Kennedy05 1/11/06 10:38 AM Page 185
tivity, change will always hint both at the dark and light, deadly chaos
and a transformed order, thanatos and eros.
The intersubject represents both the death of the subject—not just
its dissolution in the discourses that constitute it but the erosion of the
boundaries that, for champions of Western individualism, constitute its
only ethical possibility—and the possibility of its positive transforma-
tion. On the dark side of the dialectic of change, “mass man” was
already registered from the middle of the nineteenth century on by
observers like Kierkegaard, Nietzsche, and Ortega y Gasset, and the rise
of the discourses both of sociology and of a psychology of the uncon-
scious at the end of that century initiated the deconstruction of the
finite, punctual self. It could easily be argued that the modal subjectivity
produced by the new information environment and the triumph of
global ideological and economic systems represents a profound loss of
dimensionality in the self, and the erosion of those necessary tensions
without which the modal personality of our time becomes increasingly
shallow, shortsighted, and even mildly sociopathic—a subject in whom
the relationship between reason and desire called sublimation, which
for Freud was what held civilization together, has disappeared, and
nothing has replaced it. This is Marcuse’s “one dimensional man” in
whom the possibilities of the intersubject have fallen victim to “the
social controls of technological reality, which extend liberty while inten-
sifying domination.”65 In this form of subjectivity, the liberation of
desire from reason is a complete chimera, presented for the benefit of
the market as a series of television commercials, and actually signals the
loss of autonomy, critical consciousness, social responsibility and any
sense of history. One-dimensional man represents the onset of the pro-
liferation of a new form of the totalitarian personality, the one best
adapted to the various forms of economic imperialism that represent the
dark side of global capitalism.
The light side of the dialectic is the promise of the reconstruction of
the relationship between reason and desire in a form of subjectivity
across boundaries with the other and with the “others” within oneself.
The intersubject understands her identity as a field-being, not as the
sign of ego dissolution or inflation, psychological chaos, magical think-
ing, herd politics, and ethical relativism, but as the trigger for a form of
individuality made more poignant both by its recognition of its other-
ness within, and of its systemic connection and fundamental identifica-
tion with others. In this case, the deconstruction of the boundaries of
the punctual self lead to further self-actualization and greater social
compassion, further capacity for solidarity in the human cry for justice
and life-affirmation. The promise here is in a reconstruction that leads
Kennedy05 1/11/06 10:38 AM Page 186
Notes
187
Kennedy06Notes 1/11/06 10:39 AM Page 188
1. Eugene Ionesco, quoted in Coe, When the Grass Was Taller, 63.
2. G.C. Jung, and C. Kerenyi, Essays on a Science of Mythology: The
Myth of the Divine Child and the Mysteries of Eleusis (Princeton,
NJ: Bollingen, 1963), 35.
3. “Then some children were brought to Him so that He might lay
His hands on them and pray; and the disciples rebuked them. But
Jesus said, ‘Permit the children, and do not hinder them from
coming to Me; for the kingdom of heaven belongs to such as
these.’” Matthew 19: 13, 14. New American Standard Version.
4. 1 Corinthians 1:18–2:16.
5. For an account of this countertradition, see David Kennedy, “Child
and Fool in the Western Wisdom Tradition.” And see, for example,
Pierre Erny, Childhood and Cosmos: The Social Psychology of the
Black African Child (Washington, DC: Black Orpheus Press, 1973),
and “Taliesin,”in Barbara Leonie Picard, Hero-Tales from the
British Isles (New York: Criterion Books, 1966).
Kennedy06Notes 1/11/06 10:39 AM Page 193
84. Erikson presents us with a working version of this model in his epi-
genetic model of the life cycle. See his Childhood and Society.
85. Thus the poet Rilke: “. . .the child may become older and more
sensible in the everyday sense of the word, in which case he
becomes a budding citizen who will join the order of his historical
epoch and be ordained as a member. Or, again, he may ripen qui-
etly and simply from the depths of his being, nourished by his own
existence as a child, in which case he will belong to the spirit of all
epochs—he will be an artist.” Quoted in George Boas, The Cult of
Childhood (London: The Wartburg Institute, 1966), 112.
86. Quoted in Coe, When the Grass Was Taller, 41.
87. Quoted in Abrams, Natural Supernaturalism, 380.
88. Norman O. Brown, Life Against Death: The Psychoanalytic Mean-
ing of History (Middletown, CT: Wesleyan University Press, 1959),
31–34, passim.
89. Winnicott, Playing and Reality, 41.
90. Brown, Life Against Death, 30.
91. A clear example of this influence can be found in the institution of
art, which was dramatically influenced by children’s art over the
course of the twentieth century. See Jonathon Fineberg, The Inno-
cent Eye: Children’s Art and the Modern Artist (Princeton: Prince-
ton University Press, 1997).
1. John Dewey, The School and Society, in M.S. Dworkin, ed., Dewey
on Education: Selections (New York: Teachers College Press,
1959), 49.
2. John Dewey, Human Nature and Conduct, 179.
3. Ibid., 89.
4. Ibid., 16.
5. Ibid., 67, 71, 70.
6. Ibid., 97.
7. Ibid., 96.
8. Ibid., 79.
Kennedy06Notes 1/11/06 10:39 AM Page 207
9. Ibid., 97.
10. Ibid., 70, 89.
11. Erikson, Childhood and Society, 259.
12. Dominick Cavallo, “The Politics of Latency: Kindergarten Peda-
gogy, 1860–1930,” 159.
13. Barbara Finkelstein, “Schooling and the Discovery of Latency in
Nineteenth-Century America,” The Journal of Psychohistory 13,1
(Summer 1985), 3. See also her “Casting Networks of Good Influ-
ence: The Reconstruction of Childhood in the United States,
1790–1870.”
14. Erikson, Childhood and Society, 260.
15. Loris Malaguzzi, “History, Ideas, and Basic Philosophy,” in Car-
olyn Edwards, Leila Gandini, and George Forman, eds. The Hun-
dred Languages of Children (Norwood, NJ: Ablex, 1993), 64.
16. Carolyn Edwards, “Partner, Nurturer, and Guide: The Roles of the
Reggio Teacher in Action.” In Ibid., 152.
17. Dewey, The School and Society, 52. Dewey adds, “In this case, the
child becomes the sun about which the appliances of education
revolve; he is the center about which they are organized.”
18. Ibid., 49.
19. Dewey, Human Nature and Conduct, 67.
20. Ibid., 69, 70, 75.
21. Martin Buber, Between Man and Man (New York: Macmillan,
1965), 6.
22. Martin Buber, “Dialogue,” in Between Man and Man, 8.
23. Ibid.
24. Buber, I and Thou.
25. Buber, Between Man and Man, 20.
26. Gadamer, Truth and Method, 322, 323.
27. Buber, Between Man and Man, 9.
28. Ibid.
29. For a discussion the original Greek idea of theoria, see Gadamer,
Truth and Method, 111.
30. Buber, Between Man and Man, 9.
31. Ibid., 10.
Kennedy06Notes 1/11/06 10:39 AM Page 208
Bibliography
211
Kennedy07Bib 1/11/06 10:40 AM Page 212
Elias, Norbert. The Civilizing Process and State Formation and Civiliza-
tion. Trans. Edmund Jephcott. Oxford: Blackwell, 1994 [1939].
Elias, Norbert. “The Civilizing of Parents.” In The Norbert Elias
Reader, ed. Johan Goudsblom and Stephen Mennell. Oxford:
Blackwell, 1998.
Eluard, Paul. Oevres Complete. Paris: Bibliotheque de la Pleiade, Galli-
mard, 1968.
Emerson, Ralph Waldo. “Nature.” In Selected Essays, Lectures, and
Poems, ed. R.E. Spiller. New York: Washington Square Press,
1965.
Erasmus. On Education for Children. In The Erasmus Reader, ed. E.
Rummel. Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1990.
Erikson, Erik H. Childhood and Society. Second ed. New York: Norton,
1963.
Erikson, Erik. H. Insight and Responsibility. New York: Norton, 1964.
Erny, Pierre. Childhood and Cosmos: The Social Psychology of the
Black African Child. Washington, DC: Black Orpheus Press,
1973.
Featherstone, Joseph. “Rousseau and Modernity.” Daedalus 107
(Summer 1978): 167–192.
Fineberg, Jonathon. The Innocent Eye: Children’s Art and the Modern
Artist. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1997.
Fink, Eugen. “The Ontology of Play.” Philosophy Today 4 (Summer
1960): 95–109.
Finkelstein, Barbara. “Pedagogy as Intrusion: Teaching Values in Popu-
lar Primary Schools in 19th Century America.” Journal of Psy-
chohistory 2, 3 (Winter 1975).
Finkelstein, Barbara. “In Fear of Childhood: Relationships Between
Parents and Teachers in Popular Primary Schools in the 19th
Century.” Journal of Psychohistory 3, 3 (Winter 1976).
Finkelstein, Barbara. “Casting Networks of Good Influence: The
Reconstruction of Childhood in the United States, 1790–1870.”
In American Childhood: A Research Guide and Historical Hand-
book, eds. J.M. Hawes and N.R. Hiner. Westport, CT: Green-
wood Press, 1985.
Finkelstein, Barbara. “Schooling and the Discover of Latency in Nine-
teenth-Century America,” The Journal of Psychohistory 13, 1
(Summer 1985), 3.
Kennedy07Bib 1/11/06 10:40 AM Page 216