Textbook Internet Society and Culture Communicative Practices Before and After The Internet 1St Edition Tim Jordan Ebook All Chapter PDF

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 54

Internet Society and Culture

Communicative Practices Before and


After the Internet 1st Edition Tim
Jordan
Visit to download the full and correct content document:
https://textbookfull.com/product/internet-society-and-culture-communicative-practices-
before-and-after-the-internet-1st-edition-tim-jordan/
More products digital (pdf, epub, mobi) instant
download maybe you interests ...

Before and After Photography Histories and Contexts 1st


Edition Jordan Bear

https://textbookfull.com/product/before-and-after-photography-
histories-and-contexts-1st-edition-jordan-bear/

Social Theory After The Internet Media Technology And


Globalization Ralph Schroeder

https://textbookfull.com/product/social-theory-after-the-
internet-media-technology-and-globalization-ralph-schroeder/

Internet Memes and Society Social Cultural and


Political Contexts Anastasia Bertazzoli

https://textbookfull.com/product/internet-memes-and-society-
social-cultural-and-political-contexts-anastasia-bertazzoli/

Language And Online Identities The Undercover Policing


Of Internet Sexual Crime Tim Grant Nicci Macleod

https://textbookfull.com/product/language-and-online-identities-
the-undercover-policing-of-internet-sexual-crime-tim-grant-nicci-
macleod/
Digitized Lives Culture Power and Social Change in the
Internet Era T. V. Reed

https://textbookfull.com/product/digitized-lives-culture-power-
and-social-change-in-the-internet-era-t-v-reed/

The Internet of Toys: Practices, Affordances and the


Political Economy of Children’s Smart Play Giovanna
Mascheroni

https://textbookfull.com/product/the-internet-of-toys-practices-
affordances-and-the-political-economy-of-childrens-smart-play-
giovanna-mascheroni/

Pierre Musso and the Network Society From Saint


Simonianism to the Internet 1st Edition José Luís
Garcia (Eds.)

https://textbookfull.com/product/pierre-musso-and-the-network-
society-from-saint-simonianism-to-the-internet-1st-edition-jose-
luis-garcia-eds/

The Internet Myth From The Internet Imaginary To


Network Ideologies Paolo Bory

https://textbookfull.com/product/the-internet-myth-from-the-
internet-imaginary-to-network-ideologies-paolo-bory/

The Internet in China: From Infrastructure to a Nascent


Civil Society 1st Edition Gianluigi Negro (Auth.)

https://textbookfull.com/product/the-internet-in-china-from-
infrastructure-to-a-nascent-civil-society-1st-edition-gianluigi-
negro-auth/
Internet, Society and Culture
Internet, Society and Culture
Communicative Practices Before and After the Internet
Tim Jordan
Contents
Acknowledgements
1 Before and After the Internet
2 Communicative Practices
3 Letters: Pre-Internet Communicative Practices
4 Virtual Worlds: Internet Communicative Practices
5 Internet, Society and Culture: Anxiety and Style
6 Signature: Flow and Object
Bibliography
Index
Copyright
Acknowledgements
I’d like to thank the following for making whatever their intended or unintended contribution was. Of course, the book (including all its
faults) is my responsibility.
Katie Gallof has been a very helpful and interested editor. Two anonymous referees helped ensure I made clear the methodological
choices underpinning this project.
Open University colleagues helped by listening as I started to sort out these ideas as the project began. In particular Richard Collins,
who showed me Esther Milne’s book Letters, Postcards, Emails (which nearly stopped me in my tracks when I thought it was the
project I was embarking on), and Steve Pile who both helped intellectually and also in other important ways when my personal life was
difficult. Jenny Robinson offered a place to stay when I was in-between houses which was both generous and deeply needed. Much of
the writing up was done while on a sabbatical from the Open University which helped significantly to recover from being Head of
Department. The Sociology Department at the Open University also supported this research with a small grant that enabled a pilot
project into the research on letters.
Many thanks to Donna Haraway and the History of Consciousness Department at University of California at Santa Cruz who offered
a very congenial and challenging home, and I apologize to them for not giving enough back. Between the trees of UCSC’s campus and
trips to watch Steamer Land and Mavericks, this was an environment that helped me to think-with.
The British Academy supported this research with a small grant without which the archival analysis of letters in Australia would not
have been possible. The librarians in the State Library of Victoria were magnificent. The Mitchell Library in Sydney was also helpful.
My friends and family in Australia offered a counterpoint to the long days immersed in the nineteenth century with twenty-first-century
wine, food and company.
The research group Cultural Production in the Digital Age run by Tarleton Gillespie and Hector Postigo provided an important
intellectual environment and the chance to talk through ideas with other better informed colleagues.
New colleagues at King’s College London in Culture, Media and Creative Industries and in Digital Humanities have provided a
stimulating environment. Students on the Masters in Digital Culture and Society at King’s College London have also provided many
digital natives who’ve corrected and expanded my knowledge.
My friends Nick, Rahman, Liam, Rodolphe and latecomer Joth have proven how virtual friends can become some of the best of
friends. And to my guild AS which provides much amusement even when Anders tricked me into becoming guild leader again.
Finally, this goes to Matilda and Joanna with love.
1
Before and After the Internet
Introduction
The nature of culture and society changed at the end of the twentieth century, as novel forms of communication dependent on internet
technologies came into widespread use. With the internet came not just email, electronic discussion boards, social networking, the world
wide web and online gaming but across these, and other similar socio-technical artefacts, also came different identities, bodies and types
of messages that changed the nature of communication and culture. The following arguments explore interrelations between the rise of
the internet and different identities, bodies and messages in communication and examine their effects on twenty-first-century cultures
and societies. The focus is on the practices that make the sending and receiving of messages possible and how these practices have
changed. This will be done by comparing a case study of pre-internet communication using early nineteenth-century letters with a case
study of deeply immersive internet communication using online virtual world gaming. This will lead to consideration of the meaning of
changes in communication brought by internet technologies for wider cultural and social change, particularly in the normalization of
communicative anxiety.
Such a project explores the nature of communication after the rise to mass use of internet technologies. In this sense, being ‘after the
internet’ is not the same as being without the internet but instead refers to how communication operates once internet technologies are
integrated into it. The first step of this project is to consider the claim that there has been social and cultural change related to internet
technologies, and, to do this, it is useful to look at a puzzle about metaphors and analogies between the non-virtual world and virtual
phenomena. Such metaphors are nearly always based on a familiar phenomenon from the non-virtual world (e.g. letters) that is then
applied to an aspect of the virtual world (e.g. email) to explain or introduce the latter. The puzzle is that such metaphors often appear
obviously and intuitively clear, allowing what seemed novel and puzzling to be understood as familiar and obvious, yet after some
consideration such metaphors usually turn out to be significantly misleading. What at first seems to be an insight turns into a failed
interpretation, and in doing so offers an indication of cultural and social changes that have come with mass use of the internet. To see
this, we can look at two examples of the difficulty of comparing what seem, at first glance, to be the same acts conducted in the online
and offline worlds; burglary and street protest.

Metaphors and their failures: the metaphor of burglary


Hacking, or to some cracking, refers to the act of breaking into someone else’s computer remotely. 1 As has often been said in computer
security circles, the only way to be certain someone cannot access your computer illicitly is to lock it in a secure room that has no access
to the internet and then allow no one else access to the room. Once a computer is connected in some way that allows other computers
to access it then the chance that someone can break into that computer is always there, whether it is secured by password or firewall or
these and all manner of other computer locks.
The history of cracking offers many varied and increasingly complex ways of breaking into a computer (Goldstein, 2008). These range
from the cracker who gained access to the Duke of Edinburgh’s email account by guessing that the password would be 1234, to the
production of a program that automated breaking into accounts on Microsoft networks, to the ‘playful’ types who break into websites
and rename them (the Central Intelligence Agency renamed to the Central Stupidity Agency, for example) (Taylor, 1999, p. 72; Jordan
and Taylor, 2004, pp. 111–14). From the beginning of cracking, it seemed that an obvious metaphor for it was burglary. The success and
failure of this metaphor can be examined drawing on a formative time in the history of hacking and the internet; the 1990s period of
cracking, which is now sometimes called its ‘golden age,’ before the more criminal and geopolitical phase of the early twenty-first
century (Sterling, 1994; Menn, 2010; Poulsen, 2011).
Burglary makes sense as a metaphor for cracking because it captures its key characteristics. There is the sense of the illicit and the
need to break something to pass a boundary, and it further captures the sense of an invasion of space by someone not meant to be there
who is gaining some advantage. Most important of all, burglary is well known and easily understood and can thus make the strange into
something commonplace. The burglary metaphor was popularized primarily by computer security professionals, who were often
desperate to explain to the internet-illiterate in the 1990s what cracking meant. It was therefore an advantage that burglary not only
explained what cracking meant but also rang the alarm bells that many felt were necessary. For all these reasons, burglary became
during the 1990s, and remains, an oft-used metaphor for cracking. However, when more closely examined, the metaphor begins to
appear confusing and, under sustained analysis, misleading. Examining this makes clear that the burglary metaphor for cracking does not
work as an accurate representation of cracking but instead its inaccuracy functions to establish moral judgements about cracking.
What criminal breaks into someone’s home and steals their television by taking an exact copy of that television, leaving both the victim
and the criminal with a television? No burglar does this of course, it is impossible, but this is what a cracker does. Crackers do not,
usually, remove digital objects, they copy them. This point has often been noted when criticizing burglary as a metaphor, and it is the first
step in seeing that digital burglary is not really like physical burglary. There are some other differences that quickly appear as more is
found out about cracking. For example, crackers hold publicly advertised conferences, which is not a usual practice for burglars or
criminals, and crackers sometimes ring up the sites they have cracked to advise systems administrators on their failures and how to fix
the problem, which is again not a usual or familiar criminal practice. The latter is a practice still alive in 2011 when the hacking group
LulzSec broke into part of Nintendo but reported the breach to Nintendo because of their proclaimed love for Nintendo gaming
(Winterhalter, 2011). Both in the types of actions taken – copying versus taking – and in their attitudes to what is done – open discussion
versus secrecy – crackers do not seem to fit an obvious understanding of what a burglar does.
The recognition of such inaccuracies sometimes leads to the reformulation or extension of the metaphor of burglary to try and make it
stick. A computer-systems manager Bernie Cosell offered the following adjustment:
There is a great difference between trespassing on my property and breaking into my computer. A better analogy might be finding a
trespasser in your high-rise office building at 3am and learning that his back-pack contained some tools, some wire, a timer and a
couple of detonation caps. He could claim that he wasn’t planting a bomb, but how can you be sure? (Cosell, cited in Jordan and
Taylor, 1998, p. 772)
We can note that this retains many elements of burglary, breaking and entering, particularly, but shifts the sense of what occurs after
breaking in. A then-UK-government official, Mike Jones, attempted a similar adjustment both trying to retain the sense of threat and
danger involved in burglary but acknowledging that burglary and cracking are dissimilar.
Say you came out to your car and your bonnet was slightly up and you looked under the bonnet and somebody was tampering with
the leads or there looked like there were marks on the brake-pipe. Would you just put the bonnet down and say ‘oh, they’ve
probably done no harm’ and drive off, or would you suspect that they’ve done something wrong and they’ve sawn through a brake
pipe (Jones, cited in Taylor, 1999, p. 111)
Warming to his adjustment of the metaphor, Jones enunciated a second reinterpretation of cracking as burglary shifting it further to
forms of illicit access that carry an implied threat, this time moving from cars to airplanes.
Say a maintenance crew arrived at a hanger one morning and found that somebody had broken in and there were screw-driver
marks on the outside casing of one of the engines, now would they look in side and say ‘nothing really wrong here’ or would they
say, ‘hey, we’ve got to take this engine apart or at least look at it so closely the we can verify that whatever has been done hasn’t
harmed the engine.’ (Jones, cited in Taylor, 1999, pp. 111–12)
From a house to an office to a car and then a plane, the metaphorical position of the computer that is being cracked shifts as each
attempt tries to retain an ethical sense of what a ‘crack’ means while failing to equate the physical and digital realms.
The difficulty with these metaphors points towards two conclusions. First, in this case the metaphors are primarily a means of
establishing an ethical view of cracking, not of representing cracking accurately (Jordan and Taylor, 1998, pp. 770–5). Second, and this
is the key present point, a metaphor that seems obviously and intuitively correct between acts in physical space and acts in digital space
does not work and is significantly misleading. Things appear to be different when a seemingly similar action is taken over the internet
and in a house. However intuitively similar these acts are, they are in fact quite distinct. A second example will help further explore this
point in the creation by hacktivists of mass civil disobedience on the internet using the model of the street protest.

Metaphors and their failures: the metaphor of protest


In the mid-1990s, a number of political activists began to explore the consequences for civil disobedience of the emergence of the
internet. Activists had not only adopted email, electronic fora and other communication possibilities produced by the internet to help
organize but had also begun to think about how to take direct action online. Activists began to explore and develop ways in which
familiar offline protests such as boycotts, blockades and other forms of non-violent direct action could be recreated in online
environments, leading to a politics called ‘hacktivism.’ Out of this came one particular strand of online direct action in an attempt to
recreate mass street demonstrations online. The logic was that if information flows have become as important to centres of power as
physical flows, then there needed to be a way of blocking information flows that was equivalent to the ways street demonstrations
obstructed physical flows (CAE 1996, 10–15; Jordan and Taylor 2004, 67–74).
The equivalence between mass street and mass online demonstrations can most clearly be seen in examples where a virtual
demonstration is timed to coincide with street demonstrations. The anti-World Trade Organization demonstrations in Seattle in 1999 were
both virtual and non-virtual. The actions that made most of the headlines were those in the streets, where demonstrators sought to block
roads with the mass of many bodies so that conference delegates were unable to get into the conference building. For example, early in
the morning of 30 November, demonstrators took over the main intersections around the conference venue, several different marches
then brought more demonstrators into the area. With numbers of demonstrators much higher than expected, they had effectively blocked
all the streets and the key intersections around the conference venue, blocking some police inside a ring of protesters. This meant that
conference delegates could not pass through the demonstrators. Police attempted to break the encircling demonstration and join up with
police already trapped inside. Beginning as a non-violent demonstration, its very success led to police attempts to forcibly break the lines
to remove demonstrators. The presence of violent protesters also contributed to the emergence of the now-iconic pictures of destruction
and fighting that led to the demonstration being called ‘The Battle in Seattle’ (Gautney, 2010).
Here is a classic street demonstration which effected its politics using human bodies, and ingenuity, to physically block space and to
prevent others using those spaces. At the same time, human ingenuity was being used to block the electronic wires supporting the WTO
conference. A protest group called the ‘Electrohippies’ (also Ehippies) set up an action to run concurrently with the street
demonstrations that would allow anyone unable to physically be in Seattle’s streets to attend virtually. The Electrohippies set up a means
of bombarding the WTO computer network with requests; essentially anyone could participate by going to a website set up by the
Electrohippies and by clicking on a link that then automatically repeated requests for certain pages from the WTO site. The
Electrohippies claim that this was a successful action, believing that they stopped the WTO servers on 30 November and had 450,000
uses of their links (Jordan and Taylor 2004, pp. 74–9). And such actions continue having now entered the repertoire of political activists.
For example, in March 2010, the Electronic Disturbance Theatre organized a virtual sit-in at the President of the University of
California’s online portal to coincide with street demonstrations against fee increases and other issues at the University of California
(Goodin 2010).
Yet the validity of such political actions was challenged by other online activists who did not accept the equation of an online blockade
with an offline blockade. These activists rejected the metaphor and in so doing exposed its confusions. The fundamental criticism was
that the body that helps constitute a blockage in a street is not the same as the ‘body’ that blocks connections on the internet. One way
of seeing this is to note that it is easier for one person to block connections to a particular site on the internet than it is for thousands of
people to do so. Attacks on websites that flood them with data and so block their connection to the internet making them disappear are
well known as denial of service (dos) attacks and have rendered invisible many major online presences. Most of these attacks are
conducted by one person or a few automating the production of information requests to the target, for example, by infecting a wide
range of computers with ‘zombies’ that can be set to suddenly produce large flows of requests to connect to the one target at the one
time. All this can be done by a single person. Such attacks are characteristic of the dos attacks in 2010 orchestrated by activist group
Anonymous to strike back at organizations they felt were attacking WikiLeaks. Though several Anonymous members participated – for
example, five were arrested in the United Kingdom in late 2010 for their alleged participation – each attack utilized a massive
reproduction of information, reputedly based on the software package LOIC, and thus multiplied information hugely over the number of
bodies participating. In this way, such sites as MasterCard were claimed to have been slowed and taken down for short periods (Addely,
2010).
But the actions of those like the Ehippies or Electronic Disturbance Theater (EDT) must avoid the accusation that they are single or
just a few people, because they need the mass of bodies to be able to claim to be a public protest that expresses a legitimate political
claim precisely because it is, like a street protest, a mass. Somewhere embedded in the idea of mass street protest is the legitimacy
conferred on this protest by the numbers of people involved, and this political claim needs to be translated into mass online protests. Such
online protests therefore often utilize technologies that limit the powers of the internet and avoid the ability that Anonymous and others
using dos attacks have in multiplying protesting bodies rapidly and massively. The virtual protest body only corresponds to a street protest
body by limiting the capabilities the internet offers.
This leads to the paradoxical situation in which the most technologically advanced mass protests must utilize impaired forms of
technology to retain political legitimacy. The Ehippies protest offered two links to click on depending whether a protester had a fast or
slow connection; the fast link reloaded six pages on the WTO site automatically while the slow loaded two. The Ehippies could have set
these reloads to be much higher or could have launched automated dos attacks but they had to utilize technology that was less effective
at taking down the WTO site so that they retained the political legitimacy conferred by being a mass protest.
The issue of political legitimacy and its different manifestations online and offline demonstrates how misleading the equation of street
and online mass protests is despite that equation having been a basis for the creation of this political tactic. There are also other
differences that can be quickly found. For example, online protests have been criticized for their ease and lack of danger, the comparison
between clicking a mouse and running from riot police suggests a very different level of commitment between the two protest types. A
further difference is that one of the key issues with a mass street protest is the logistics required to get a large number of people
together in the right place at the right time; again this differs radically with online protests where such logistics generally involve turning
on a computer, perhaps after having received notification through an automated email list (Jordan and Taylor, 2004, p. 80). The more the
nature of a mass online protest is probed, the more such protests seem different to offline mass protests. The use of classic civil
disobedience to present online protest as a metaphor, such as when the Critical Arts Ensemble calls for ‘electronic civil disobedience,’
turns out to be initially attractive but substantively misleading.
Despite the seeming immediacy and accuracy of many metaphors of offline for online phenomena, they turn out to be misleading in
case after case. We can enter ‘chat’ rooms and ‘talk’ to people when in fact we are typing, and everyone can talk all at once and retain
full communication. We ‘go’ to ‘places’ without moving an inch from our chairs, with just the pixels rearranging themselves on our
computer screens. And it is not that we fail to move on the internet, just that using the space we know that is not involved with internet
technologies as a metaphor or guide to the spaces that internet technologies are part of producing, will initially beguile us but also mislead
us. This failure is a clue to the larger issue; to what extent are social and cultural norms, ethics and practices different or similar when
they are or are not dependent on internet technologies?
Moreover, such metaphors contribute to the way debates over the effects of the internet have often become polarized. The misleading
understanding analogies and metaphors offer us, allow the comforting claim that something that seems new is actually familiar. When
they fail, as they habitually do, they also then open the door to the opposite claim that something entirely new that supersedes the old has
appeared. Analysis can then be caught in an opposition between claiming nothing ‘really’ new has appeared or its opposite that
something radically new has appeared, rather than comparing and delineating what is new and what is the same. The present argument
pursues the change that the failure of metaphors like street protest for online protest suggest exist, but does so to be clear that there are
likely to be both similarities and differences between communication before and after the advent of internet technologies. To explore this,
there will be a need to grapple with both the mess and complexity of variable interactions between technologies, groups, individuals,
signs, actions and more through which communication is lived and routine and habitual practices that in their repetition also make up
communicative practices. The first stage in this analysis is to take this clue that failed metaphors offers and turn it into a hypothesis
based on existing studies of communication and the internet.

A hypothesis of communicative practice after the internet


The failure of metaphors drawn between non-virtual and virtual spaces suggests differences between the two. To develop this
difference and focus it on communication I will propose the following hypothesis. The difference between online and offline can be
taken as a sign of the existence of two concurrent and interacting communicative practices: one communicative practice was developed
in Western societies prior to the emergence of internet technologies and is familiar to the point of being nearly entirely taken for granted;
and, there is a second communicative practice that has arisen with the emergence of internet technologies and has been rapidly
developed and assimilated by many.
A hypothesis here can be thought of as the first suggestion that explains some of the behaviour indicated by the failure of metaphors
between online and offline and that is also being studied in the quickly grown field of internet studies. Further, ‘hypothesis’ can be
understood in its older meaning from Ancient Greece when a hypothesis was a summary of the plot of an ancient drama. Such
hypotheses acted as something like a preface giving the story, its setting, main characters and the context for a play’s initial production
(Vlastos, 1994; Kovacs, 2005, pp. 384–5). If the modern drama at stake in this book is ‘Has communication and culture changed with
the arrival of the internet?,’ then another way of understanding what I mean by hypothesis is that it summarizes the story’s plot by
outlining its main meanings and conceptual protagonists. A hypothesis of this type is well served by telling the story once in a small way
and then retelling it with conceptual and empirical complexity.
The hypothesis, or storytelling, has implicitly begun in the identification of the possible difference between phenomena that are offline
and online. The phenomena that were used to suggest this possibility were each based centrally on communicative contexts, whether
that of illicit communication to computers or of destroying communication to targeted protest sites. Putting communication and practice
together suggests exploring sets of social and cultural relations played out through material practices that establish ways in which people
may communicate. Material practices here refer to repeated actions emphasizing that they involve empirical and tangible resources.
Communicative practices set out how we, normally unthinkingly, stabilize the elements of communication and how in daily practice we
easily answer questions such as: What is the identity of the sender? How does the receiver know this message is from the sender? What
is the identity of the receiver? How is the self-identity of the message maintained? How can the message be read? Communicative
practices focus not on the moment of transmission, when meaning passes from a sender to a receiver, but instead on the means by
which such transmissions are created and are able to be repeated across masses of people. The hypothesis being developed can address
communication before and after the internet by setting out the nature of communicative practice prior to internet technologies and then
comparing them to communicative practice dependent on internet technologies. I will briefly sketch in these stories.
Communicative practices prior to the internet began from those derived from face-to-face communication. These are based on a
collapse between a physical body and an identity that then legitimizes authors, recipients and messages. All these elements can be
swiftly negotiated when face-to-face because all parties to the communication are present. The development with face-to-face
communication is one in which there are masses of authors and recipients who are at a distance to each other. This creates the problem
of authorizing a communication when the author and recipient’s identities and physical bodies cannot be automatically known to be the
same. The era of communicative practices prior to the internet derives from this development from face-to-face forms of authorization
of communication because of the separation of communicative identities from communicating bodies that is required by at-a-distance
communication.
Communicative practices for at-a-distance communication create transmission based on authorizing the coincidence of body and
identity using material practices involving letters, stamps, signatures, voice and so on. Where being at a distance pulls the body and
identity of face-to-face apart, these practices of communication now authorize a reconnection of communicative identity to body by
creating a communicating body. One example of this is the signature, which is a practice in which the performance of inscribing certain
shapes produces a coincidence of name and body, because the signature establishes that the body of whoever is named in the signature
touched and produced a message, much as if it had been spoken aloud. Signatures can be traced back to royal practices of seals in
which the person of the monarch, the body of the king, was legitimized as the author of a communication (whether the communication
was personal, state, legal or other was often reflected in a different seal and signed name). The physical body of the monarch was
attached to a communication through a device which could not be activated unless that physical body was tangibly at the communication
(hence, also the practice of seals, particularly personal seals, being made into a ring and so being intimately attached to a body that
‘owned’ that seal) (Clanchy, 1993, pp. 51–77). The development of written languages and the extension of literacy integrate into a range
of different media this way of stabilizing the transmission of messages.
The central dynamic of pre-internet at-a-distance communicative practice is the use of written language on a variety of media that is
legitimated as coming from one identity through practices and technologies that authorize the message as having come from a physical
body co-terminus with the sender’s identity. The problem of separation of identity and body is solved through a range of practices that
stabilize the two as one and legitimize certain performed marks as mediators which state that a certain body is attached to a certain
identity that produced the message. For example, characteristic styles of handwriting, or particular styles of language use, or certain
types of salutations and ways of signing off can all be interpreted, when they are known and repeatedly used, as stabilizing a body and
identity as the author of a message, just as seals and signatures can. Through these practices the physical body and identity of
communicants is not reflected but is produced through fragments that stand in for and are taken to authorize the communicant.
Such a complex set of attachments stabilizes and underpins communication through the pre-internet era. This form of communicative
practice is flexible enough to continue through a range of new developments. For example, the telephone created little disturbance to the
basic structure of communication because it provided another means of authorizing a physical body through fragments found in the
timbre, intonation and characteristics of someone’s voice. Other forms of communication, such as the telegram, posed more challenging
problems with its restricted vocabulary undermining strategies of identifying through performances within messages and carrying only
the barest of signatures. While telegrams are part of pre-internet communicative practice, this may only be because of the exceptional
nature of telegraphic messages within the vast weight of other such forms of communication.
In contrast, internet-dependent communicative practices no longer stabilize communication through material performances that merge
identity and body. Instead, the body as a means of stabilizing identities fades away as a locus of authority because the internet
characteristically offers faulty and suspicious markers of identity leaving the body overshadowed by practices in which styles of
messaging stabilize a communication. This is caused by a communicative context in which markers of identity – such as email address,
forum name, Facebook name – are unstable and themselves need to be authorized. The extent of the instability of this communicative
practice may be a marker of its novelty, perhaps first initiated in telegrams but only coming into widespread use towards the end of the
twentieth century (Standage, 2007). In this communicative practice, styles of message become evermore important and so the symbolic
content of messages becomes more closely integrated into the means of stabilizing communication. The invention and use of new forms
of text communication, such as emoticons or ‘text speak,’ alongside choices about what new styles one does and does not use become
evermore important to authorizing who has created and who is receiving a message and whether that message can be understood.
For example, in many online fora if a post is made under one name and is followed immediately by another post using a different name
whose content either strongly agrees or disagrees with the first post, many will immediately suspect that the two posts come from the
same person. The suspicion is that ‘trolling’ is going on in a deliberate attempt to spark an argument for the sake of the argument. In
such a case, the identity-markers claim two different communicants are at work but the style of the interaction is read contrary to the
identity-markers to instead assume that there is only one person sending messages. Other markers may buttress this kind of reading. For
example, if a forum offers a post-count of the number of times a particular name has posted a message then if the first post has a high
post-count and the second with a different name has a very low post-count (or vice versa), this will emphasize suspicion that the two are
from the same identity (one from the user’s normal and highly used account and another from a rarely used one) (Donath, 1998). A
second example is the experience of someone who sends mass advertising emails, or spam, illicitly taking over an email address and
routing the advertising mails through that address to the person’s contact list. In this case, what may well be a very familiar email
address associated automatically with a particular body offers up a style of message radically at odds with the expected style of the
communicant. If someone you know and whose email is familiar suddenly sends advertisements for viagra, for enhancements to body
parts or suggests new dating sites, then most will immediately assess the email from the style it offers rather than from the email
address. Styles of communication, particular themes, forms of writing, characteristic examples and other such markers of a particular
way of communicating, have become the means of stabilizing communication from a sender to recipient.
Two communicative practices, each made up of many and varied material practices, have been hypothesized and their differences
revolve around the ways in which messages are legitimized as coming from one identity and are received by another identity and ways in
which the nature of the message can be constructed and maintained. The key shift is from the body to style. But these practices should
not be thought of as mutually exclusive or sequential in the sense of one inevitably taking over from the other. If we take the viewpoint
of a particular individual then it is not that any one person will experience these two communicative practices separately but s/he is likely
to experience the mess of everyday life flitting in-between and within two sets of communicative practices that themselves pull in
different directions, have different standards and are potentially dissonant to one another.
This hypothesis is a first approximation to understanding what the clue found from the failure of metaphors between offline and online
means, all it does is to open a way forward towards understanding what has happened to communication. The hypothesis tells the first
story. The question now becomes how best to study this hypothesis? If this first telling of the story leads to the suggestion of two
different cultures that sustain different ways of transmitting and receiving messages, then the task becomes finding a way both to
understand and test the story. It becomes a project of retelling the story in a more complex and empirically grounded way to see whether
the story remains coherent and sensible or whether it comes apart and disintegrates. This however sets a number of interesting
methodological problems.

Methods: theory, comparison, difference, intensity


A theoretically complex and empirically informed retelling of the hypothesis is necessary. What methods can do in this context is to give
a specific form to the retelling that offers the greatest chance of finding out whether the story remains coherent once it becomes
complex. A number of components to such a method are needed. Theoretical complexity has to produce an understanding of
communication that stretches from pre-internet to internet-dependent historical periods. While the latter is not so long, the former
stretches far back into communication history. Analysing both periods for their communicative form then provides a basis on which
comparison may be conducted. However, confusion is possible because internet-dependent communication does not replace and is not
mutually exclusive from pre-internet communication, but rather continues to exist alongside and to interpenetrate with internet-dependent
practices. One way to minimize this potential is to take a case study of pre-internet and one of internet-dependent communication that
are as clearly representative of each as possible. To ensure comparison can be done meaningfully, it is important for the case studies to
acutely express the specific nature of their communicative contexts. It will be useful to clarify these two aspects of the method being
employed; comparison and difference.
To create the possibility of comparing pre-internet and internet-dependent practices, a theory of communicative practices that applies
to both will need to be articulated. The hypothesis already implies significant conceptual work because of the extensive use in it of terms
that have themselves been subject to considerable conceptual controversy over, at least, the last 30 years. What is meant by message?
What is meant by identity? What is meant by body? What is meant by transmission? Is a theory of performativity (and which one)
needed or is a theory of practice or both? These kinds of concepts need to be taken into account to fully understand what the hypothesis
might be claiming, and this theory also needs to outline a view of communication that can confidently be used across the eras of pre-
internet and internet-dependent communication.
This theoretical task will be undertaken by drawing on two related but not always connected areas of analysis. Communication studies
will be a key resource, particularly in the debates around the meaning of transmission of messages and cultures of transmission that have
developed around the term ‘communicative practice’. The work of Carey, Peters and others will be taken up here. Not always
connected to this work have been developments in cultural studies around language and the body which also deal with issues of how
communication is created and maintained. Connecting this cultural studies work, particularly as derived from Derrida and Butler, to
communication studies will create a complex view of communication that takes many issues back to an abstract foundation in the ways
in which the transmission of messages is created and maintained (see Chapter 2). While the meaning of communicative practice will be
defined abstractly, the theorization also requires that each communicative form will be located in particular times and spaces. Such a
theory outlines how it is possible that the particular communicative practices that operate in pre-internet and internet-dependent times
and spaces can be defined and compared. Abstractly both pre-internet and internet-dependent communication are communicative
practices, but in practice they exist in specific times and spaces and have particular forms.
To counter the potential confusion produced by these factors, the empirical evidence will be collected from case studies of intense
forms of communication. Intense, or ‘extreme,’ here does not mean unusual but rather communication that is heightened by the
particular time and space it exists in. Comparing two case studies of intense forms of communication should provide the clearest possible
examples of communicative practices and allow conclusions about their differences and similarities to be drawn. For similar reasons, a
historical view that starts prior to the internet and traces the emergence of internet-dependent communication is potentially subject to
confusion given the more gradual change over time provided by a historical narrative rather than the abrupt comparison of
communication from two different eras. This does not mean a historical view of communication is either inaccurate or untenable, only
that the more direct route to understanding the differences of communication at stake here is to focus on two clear comparable case
studies. The final element of the methods underpinning this book is then to define the case studies and why they are ‘intense’ forms that
offer clear evidence of communication in their era.
For pre-internet communication, it seems advisable to move prior to the telegraph to remove the possibility that the telegraph first
brought internet-like communication (Standage, 2007). One way of identifying an intensive form of pre-internet and pre-telegraph
communication, that is also amenable to research, is to look at communication in letters that is radically at a distance. If the letter writers
and receivers are themselves so distant that effectively all communication between them is carried by letters, then examining those
letters will put the researcher in as close contact as is possible to pre-internet communication by offering the researcher nearly all that
constituted the communication when it first happened. One case study that fits this specification is letters to colonial Australia in the
early nineteenth century, and archives of such letters were examined (see Chapter 3). In this case, not only were several series of
letters between individuals found but also case studies of business letters and of state letters. These were supported by work in other
archives to form a case study of pre-internet communication. The first case study is then an archival study of letters to and from
colonial-era Australia.
The second case study needed is of ‘intense’ internet-dependent communication. While it might seem obvious to compare letters to
email, and clearly this can be a productive research method (Milne 2010), there is also the difficulty of further confusion caused by
similarities in form between emails and letters. In addition, more immersive environments are possible based on internet technologies,
environments which cannot be imagined without such technologies, whereas email lies at least partly within the imagination of letters. A
communicative environment unimaginable before and without internet technologies would be an intensive form of internet-dependent
communication, and these can be found in virtual worlds. Such worlds offer physically dispersed individuals access to an online space
that presents itself as a new world, some of the best known of which are World of Warcraft (WoW) and Second Life. The second case
study takes up this sense of intensity by conducting ethnographies in virtual worlds, primarily in the massive multiplayer online games
WoW and Dark Age of Camelot (DAOC). These ethnographies aim to produce empirical evidence for the ways communicative
practices that are dependent on internet technologies enable and maintain the transmission of messages.
One of the costs of this approach is that the two case studies are generated using different methods, suggesting it might be difficult to
compare the results. Two points can be made about this. First, any case-study-based comparison of communication before and after the
rise to mass use of internet technologies will face this problem because moving prior to computer-mediated communication, and the
telegraph, means studying phenomena from different eras. Such a comparison is nearly certain to need different techniques to grasp the
full communicative contexts because such contexts are about more than the content of messages. What needs to be studied is how the
content of messages is created and moved and how receivers and senders are authorized, identified and maintained. This means paying
attention to the materiality of communication in order to grasp how transmission is created and maintained, rather than focusing on the
meaning of what was transmitted. This kind of study necessarily means mixing case studies researched through different methods
because of a need to study phenomena from different times and spaces. Second, the comparison is of communicative practices and as
long as the methods employed produce a good analysis of the nature of communication in each particular time and space, then it should
be possible to compare them as such practices. That is, if the case studies produce an understanding of how communicative practices
are created and maintained then it should be possible to compare these understandings, even if different methods have had to be
employed to generate results.
A way forward to testing the hypothesis by retelling it in ever greater theoretical and empirical complexity is now clear. First, a more
detailed theorization is required to make sense of the concepts used in the hypothesis of communicative practice. Identity, body,
message, authority, legitimacy and so on all require conceptualization (see Chapter 2). This theorization will hinge on connecting the
fields of communication studies and cultural studies which, while not complete strangers to each other, are also often not as closely
connected as they could be. Second, such conceptualization must be done in relation to material practices, while this does not mean
theory and practices must be written about simultaneously, it does mean theory cannot remain abstract while neither can material
practices be understood atheoretically. Two case studies informed by the theorized hypothesis of communicative practices and engaged
with the materiality of communication will take up this task. One case study focuses on pre-internet communication through a study of
letters to colonial Australia in the early nineteenth century (see Chapter 3), while the second case study focuses on immersion in
internet-dependent communication through an ethnography of multiplayer online games in the early twenty-first century (see Chapter 4).
In both case studies, the aim is to generate as clear as possible a view of communication in their times. Finally, the results of these
analyses can be reflected on to produce insights consequential to understanding communication, culture and society in the twenty-first
century, particularly in the embedding of a form of communicative anxiety deeply within cultural practice (see Chapter 5).
As this study unfolds, it will become ever clearer that the state of being ‘after the internet’ is not being without the internet or, in a
circular sense, returning to something prior to the internet, but of constantly negotiating and dealing with two broad communicative
practices; one that existed prior to and that continues to exist after the rise of the internet and the other that is dependent on and could
not exist without the internet. The points of intersection, whether of contradiction, unimportance or reinforcement of each other, will
need to be teased out by telling the story of two communicative practices whose coexistence constitutes being after the internet.

Note
1 Hacking is a term that refers to a number of things; for this example, it is being taken as referring to cracking. For a full examination
of its various meanings and their interrelations, see Jordan, 2008.
2
Communicative Practices
Introduction
The rise of internet technologies is the primary marker of new mass ways of communicating. That is, across various societies and
cultures there are, inextricably intertwined with the use of internet technologies, new moments of communication enacted in the
everyday that accumulate into and are enabled by wider collective practices. These new everyday moments and collective practices
exist and are interrelated with pre-existing forms of communication. The key issues that need to be conceptualized then are defined by
two related questions: What is communication in the everyday? And, what does it mean to conduct and repeat, that is to practice,
communication?
To answer this question, it will be important to draw on both communications theory and cultural theory. To begin with the everyday-
moment existing theories of communication as transmission will be touched on, and this will make it possible to contrast the everyday and
transmission with ideas about communicative practices. Such a combination leaves problems, as, within communications theory, the
everyday and practices have sometimes been opposed to each other as visions of communication rather than linked together to form
communication. Following this, Milne’s work on emails, letters and postcards introduces the idea of presence in communication to
provide an understanding of what must be established for transmission to become possible. Milne begins to connect cultural studies and
communication theory on the issue of presence, and this is developed subsequently through the work of Heidegger, Levinas and Derrida.
Further complications emerge in the need to conceptualize both materiality, drawing on social studies of science, and performativity,
relying on work by Butler and again Derrida, to fully conceptualize communication. In summary, it will be argued that communicative
practices refer to the ways in which the possibility of the everyday transmission of messages is based on the creation of presence
through materially enacted performatives.

Transmission and the problem of communication


Though there are a range of different understandings of communication, the term ‘communicative practices’ emerged within
communication studies partly as a response to the conceptualization of communication as the everyday moment of passing a message
from A to B (Craig, 1999, p. 7; Peters, 1999, pp. 10–29). Views such as the latter are centred on what has been called the transmission
model of communication, that is often exemplified by the mathematical model of communication of Shannon and Weaver. At its simplest,
their model is one in which a message is emitted from a point A, passes through the possibility of distortion or noise and is then received
at point B. Transmission involves a sender, receiver, message and means of messaging, with the core problem being noise that interferes
with the message. This definition of a general communication system has a notable feature.
The fundamental problem of communication is that of reproducing at one point either exactly or appropriately a message selected at
another point. Frequently the messages have meaning; that is they refer to or are correlated according to some system with certain
physical or conceptual entities. These semantic aspects of communication are irrelevant to the engineering problem. The significant
aspect is that the actual message is one selected from a set of possible messages. (Shannon, 1948, p. 379)
The envelope does not care what is written on the letter inside, the waves that carry radio sounds do not care if it is music or talk and,
perhaps most strikingly, the internet carries digital packets which can increasingly be any type of media object as increasingly all media
objects can be digitized. Dropping concern for the nature of the message in favour of the method of messaging is key to transmission
models of communication in which a message A is passed from B to C. Transmission also corresponds to an intuitive or common-sense
view of communication because it most closely reflects how communication is experienced in the everyday at individual instants when
the event of communication happens. A letter is received, an email opened, a phone call answered, a text sent; in all such cases, the
instant in which such communicative action happens usually appears to participants to be one in which a message is received having
been sent (Carey, 2009, p. 33).
Yet, despite such a seemingly intuitive starting point for understanding communication, a range of objections have been made to
transmission models. From within communication theory, it has been argued that transmission models are mechanical, solipsistic and
ahistorical (Craig, 1999, p. 7). Outside of communication theory, the flaws of the common sense model of communication have also been
pointed out. Both Luhman and Derrida, from rather different theoretical contexts, articulate the transmission model in order to critique it.
Luhman pointed out three assumptions within such models: (1) that transmission assumes the message is lost to the sender and gained by
the receiver, (2) that transmission implies a hierarchy in which the sender chooses what the receiver gains and (3) that transmission
assumes the self-identity of the message which stays the same between sender and receiver. All three assumptions are false Luhman
argues, pointing towards communication as a process in which messages, in sending, travel and reception, are negotiated within social
and cultural norms (Luhman, 1995, pp. 139–41). Derrida only rarely examines the concept of communication directly, though much of his
extensive work on language implies communication. Where he does directly consider communication, he takes up the transmission
model, arguing that the model is inscribed within semiotics but that transmission has to presume the existence of objects and subjects and
that these are affected by processes of difference, meaning they are not straightforwardly stable. If difference is necessary to these
elements of a transmission model then this requires communication to have a context which clarifies and stabilizes the equivocations
difference produces, and this context must both be what contains transmission and what a focus on transmission tends to conceal
(Derrida, 1981, pp. 23–8; 1982a, pp. 209–10).
One of the most extensive and influential analyses of transmission as a model of communication is found in Carey’s work. Carey
argues that there are two models of communication that have dominated conceptualization of communication in the United States since
the nineteenth century; the transmission model and the ritual model (Carey, 2009, p. 12). Carey’s view of the nature transmission is the
same as already discussed, effectively the passing of message A from B to C. He argues there is a complementary ritual model of
communication ‘directed not toward the extension of messages in space but toward the maintenance of society in time; not the act of
imparting information but the representation of shared beliefs’ (Carey, 2009, p. 15). Communication as ritual is here complementary to
transmission, and Carey does not dismiss or refute the transmission model; rather, he argues that transmission has taken over views of
communication even though it only represents a partial view. This opens the possibility that transmission should be viewed as occurring
within rituals. ‘A ritual view does not exclude the processes of information transmission. . . . It merely contends that one cannot
understand these processes aright except insofar as they are cast within an essentially ritualistic view of communication and social
order’ (Carey, 2009, p. 17).
Carey argues that the reason why transmission has become the dominant and common-sense view of communication, despite being
flawed, is a historical one, and here he makes a second fundamental contribution to communication studies in his argument about the
significance of the telegraph. Carey argues that widespread use of the telegraph was the moment when communication was separated
from transportation because the message could travel faster than the transport of physical goods. This meant that such messages could
control and model the transportation of physical goods both unifying geography, for example in such things as the formation of time zones
or the unification of railroad timetables, and creating virtual economies in the separation of the message from its referent, for example in
the formation of futures markets (Carey, 2009, pp. 164–5 and pp. 170–1). Carey argues that during the twentieth century, because of
these developments, transmission became the dominant understanding of communication, eclipsing a ritualistic view that ‘conceives
communication as a process through which a shared culture is created, modified and transformed’ (Carey, 2009, p. 33).
Carey’s views have been influential within the history of ideas about communication and have given rise to further developments in
what is meant by a ritual view of communication (McCarthy et al., 2005). This development has mainly occurred in what
communications theory means by the term ‘communicative practices’ (Craig, 1999, pp. 124–8). However, several theorists of
communicative practices do not agree with Carey about transmission and instead develop critiques that question transmission’s
coherence paralleling Luhman and Derrida’s points, for example in Deetz and Peters work (Peters, 1993; Deetz, 1994). This work
provides an understanding of communicative practices developing the idea that communication is a means by which transmission is
constructed in culture and society rather than seeing practice and transmission as developing together. The two innovations of separating
transmission of messages from a shared culture of communication and outlining the historic effects of separating transport from
communication emphasized within communication studies a sense of the importance of the creation of communication through shared
social and cultural practices. Carey’s work leads in this way to a shift of communication theory away from transmission and towards a
broad sense of social and cultural theory.
Theories of communicative practice that follow in this tradition then, quite naturally, tend to emphasize the cultural, as the key point
being made is that communication is a cultural practice and not a transmission of an object between independent subjects. However, this
tends to lose the specificity of communicative practices which begin to fade into general cultural and social actions, which then underpin
how in particular historical circumstances communication practices work. Communication as a specific object of analysis begins to be
lost because such theories are effectively equivalent to general social and cultural theories. Peters offers an influential tracing of theories
of communication that draws on Carey and generates a similar issue. Peters repeats the role of the telegraph in communication in a way
that implies the loss of the material from communication: ‘In principle the coefficient for signals – but not bodies – was reduced to zero,
even though access and cost kept the telegraph from being the utopia of universal contact’ (Peters, 1999, p. 139). This attitude is
paradoxical in both Peters and Carey because at other points they are clearly aware of the importance of technologies. Peters also
considers the challenge to cultural practices of the radio.
How to compensate for the fact that people could be in touch without appearing ‘in person’ was the acute question in the early
history of radio and its development into a huge commercial entertainment empire. New forms of authenticity, intimacy, and touch
not based on immediate physical presence had to be found. (Peters, 1999, p. 214)
But as we will see in Milne, and as subsequent chapters in this account will show, such techniques were already in existence in the ways
the materialities of letters were negotiated as communicative practices. In the techniques of seals, signatures and the descriptions of
bodies and selves in letters, there were many existing techniques for authenticity, touch and intimacy that were not based on physical
presence. This is paradoxical as Peters is clearly aware of letters and discusses them in the context of whether a message arrives or not
(Peters, 1999, p. 151), but having developed Carey’s theory of the telegraphic break, that tends to emphasize the cultures of
communicative practices, he fails to address the technologies of letters that made possible letter writing as communication at a distance
and had done so for several hundred years prior to the telegraph. The result is then not a dismissal of technology but lessening attention
paid to the everyday materiality of communicative practices, which then directs attention away from communicative technologies and
towards broader cultural and social rituals.
The result is a tendency for theories of communicative practice to become more like general theories of social or cultural relations
rather than being specifically theories of communication. Craig is an example of this process of shifting from transmission, to shared
cultures, to communicative practices and finally to social and cultural practices.
A stance on communication as a practice is not opposed to using communication techniques or trying to improve communication
outcomes by applying scientific theory and research. Those are perfectly legitimate practices. However, it is important to see those
practices within a bigger picture. Contrary to a narrow scientific-technological view, practice involves much more than using
conscious techniques to achieve predetermined goals. The discourse about a practice is fundamentally normative, fundamentally
about defining elements that constitute the practice, coordinating and regulating activities, deciding what goals are important, making
evaluative judgements, and the like. (Craig, 2006, p. 41)
Communication theory in such accounts is pulled strongly towards more general social and cultural theory, leaving a gap related to how
to analyse communication. Communication studies then becomes hard to distinguish from cultural and social theory. It is the refocusing
away from transmission that seems to lead to a loss of focus on communication in favour of social rituals. This suggests a need to
integrate transmission in some form as part of communication analysis even though this means understanding how its contradictory
elements, as identified by Luhman, Derrida, Carey and others, may be maintained.
Understanding communication from the present arguments involves taking forward the insights that communicative practices are
material, most obviously in their technologies, that they are in some senses the production of shared cultures and that transmission of
messages involves the contradictions of transmission that need to be maintained by communicative practices. There are then at least two
theoretical issues that come into focus: one need is to theorize materiality within communicative practices to ensure communication is
specifically addressed, while the second need is to understand a specifically communicative sense of shared cultural practice which also
shows how transmission can occur. We can begin with the latter based on a recent articulation of what communication as a practice
means in the context of comparing internet- and non-internet-based forms of communication in Milne’s substantial and path-breaking
study comparing letters, postcards and email.

Presence one: Milne, Derrida and self-presence


Milne’s study analyses forms of communication in nineteenth-century letters, late nineteenth- and early twentieth-century postcards and
an early twenty-first-century email-based discussion list. Milne’s study is rich in empirical detail of communication that is at a physical
distance providing insights into the nature of communication across pre- and post-internet communication. Based on this empirical detail,
her conclusion helps identify one component of communication consonant with arguments in the previous section.
the fantasy of, and desire for, presence is a key element in the exchanges, communications and performances enabled by these
three systems . . . the material systems of letters, postcards and email enable complex exchanges, experienced as the intimate
presence of a correspondent whose corporeal body remains invisible. (Milne, 2010, p. 202)
Milne argues that presence is a common element across the different forms of communication that use the technologies of letter,
postcard and email list. She draws presence from Derrida’s work while giving it a particularly communicative focus: ‘Presence is a term
that need not refer always to material, corporeal presence. Rather, presence is an effect achieved in communication . . . when
interlocutors imagine the psychological, or sometimes, physical presence of the other’ (Milne, 2010, p. 2). For Milne, the overall point is
that something like presence cannot be assumed but is produced or created and that across the three technologies – disparate as they
are in historical specificity and everyday practices – each constructs a particular form of presence.
Peters recognizes the importance of such a view on communication, defining it historically as a school of thought associated with
Heidegger which Peters argues is based on a view of ‘Communication as the revelation of being to itself through language’ (Peters,
1999, p. 17). Peters offers a more pragmatic and historically situated approach to communication, as he makes clear when addressing
arguments of Derrida’s about presence and the priority given to speech over writing:
With his war on ‘the metaphysics of presence,’ Derrida is right to combat the philosophical principle that behind every word is a
voice and behind every voice an intending soul that gives it meaning. But to think of the longing for the presence of other people as
a kind of metaphysical mistake is nuts. (Peters, 1999, p. 270)
Whether Derrida’s thought is ‘nuts’ is thankfully beyond this text, what is relevant in Peters is another angle on Milne’s empirically
based assertion of presence as the key to seeing communication in emails, postcards and letters. Peters’ pragmatic view of presence
confirms both its fragility and failures and its necessity. ‘Because we can share our mortal time and touch only with some and not all,
presence becomes the closest thing there is to a guarantee of a bridge across the chasm. In this we directly face the holiness and
wretchedness of our finitude’ (Peters, 1999, p. 271). Peters’ view is also useful as he articulates it beyond a human-centred vision,
noting that ‘Communication is something we share with animals and computers, extra-terrestrials and angels’ (Peters, 1999, p. 227). He
offers examples in the Turing Test, Wittgenstein’s lion (who if it could talk we could not understand it) and the SETI Project’s search for
extraterrestrial life to demonstrate how we are in communication with, in the sense of practicing a form of presence with, these non-
humans, and that if we place the human at the centre of such analysis we are making a political choice (Peters, 1999, p. 230). In his care
to include the non-human and the recognition of the political choice that is made if the human is implicitly or explicitly taken as the centre
of analysis, and hence as the measure of value, Peters both draws on and extends other influential post-human and non-human analysts
such as Haraway (Haraway, 2008, 1991).
Peters and Milne can both be understood as asserting that communication depends on the fallible creation of presence. Understanding
this means exploring the nature of presence further which can be done most obviously by looking at the theorist Milne who primarily
draws on Derrida and Peters who contrasts with Derrida. The key elements of Derrida’s arguments in this context can be found in his
analysis of the priority of speech over writing in Husserl’s work, a priority Derrida considers foundational of Western metaphysics.
Derrida, early on in his analysis of Husserl, introduces presence in relation to repetition. ‘In order that the possibility of this repetition
may be open, ideally to infinity, one ideal form must assure this unity of the indefinitely and the idea: this is the present, or rather the
presence of the living present’ (Derrida, 1973 p. 6). And one type of living present forms presence, that is forms the means by which the
stability of meaning is known, and this is speech. The quality of speech that allows it to play this role is that the meaning uttered is
present to the utterer in the utterance.
The ‘apparent transcendence’ of the voice thus results from the fact that the signified, which is always ideal by essence, the
‘expressed’ Bedeutung, is immediately present in the act of expression. This immediate presence results from the fact that the
phenomenological ‘body’ of the signifier seems to fade away at the very moment it is produced; it seems already to belong to the
element of ideality. . . . This effacement of the sensible body and its exteriority is for consciousness the very form of the
immediate presence of the signified. (Derrida, 1973, p. 77)
Derrida locates Husserl’s prioritization of speech in this absolute sense of self-presence because ‘the speaking subject hears himself
[sic] in the present’ (Derrida, 1973, p. 78; 1976, pp. 7–8). Derrida then points out that even here difference and repetition are at play,
being constituent to the very division that separates the self-presence of speech from the non-self-presence of writing.
Even while repressing difference by assigning it to the exteriority of the signifiers, Husserl could not fail to recognize its work at the
origin of sense and presence. Taking auto-affection as the exercise of the voice, auto-affection supposed that a pure difference
comes to divide self-presence. In this pure difference is rooted the possibility of everything we think we can exclude from auto-
affection: space, the outside, the world, the body, etc. As soon as it is admitted that auto-affection is the condition for self-presence,
no pure transcendental reduction is possible. But it was necessary to pass through the transcendental reduction in order to grasp this
difference in what is closest to it – which cannot mean grasping it in its identity, its purity, or its origin, for it has none. We come
closest to it in the movement of differance. (Derrida, 1973, p. 82)
Differance is Derrida’s combination of ‘differing’ and ‘deferring’ that turns out to be the foundational moment underpinning Husserl’s
logic. While Husserl, Derrida argues, felt he had reached absolute self-presence in speech, this self-presence is itself produced by
differing and deferring that cannot be in the auto-affection of speech and so is outside presence understood as speech. Accordingly,
what alone is inevitable is differance.
Derrida extends and complicates this argument through a range of interventions. His detailed essay on differance notes that the turn
he identifies is found in the work of Heidegger, Nietzsche and Freud in which presence turns from being a power to synthesize and
instantly reassemble meaning into an effect of a system that is itself based on differance (Derrida, 1982b, pp. 16–17) and states in
related work: ‘The system of “hearing (understanding)-oneself-speak” through the phonic substance – which presents itself as the
nonexterior, nonmundane, therefore nonempirical or noncontingent signifier – has necessarily dominated the history of the world during
an entire epoch’ (Derrida, 1976, pp. 7–8). Such a framing of this period in Derrida’s work gives it much of its millennial or revolutionary
feel with its seeming war on the domination of writing by speech and the implied high stakes that involve revolutionizing Western
metaphysics.
Derrida’s analysis defines the notion of presence within the debate about whether speech produces a privileged type of presence – in
which the self is transparently present to the self – and in exposing how speech as presence is itself produced on the basis of other
factors, he also locates presence as occurring within certain contexts, both historical and philosophical. This is the key lesson Milne
draws and which she argues her evidence confirms, ‘As Derrida reminds us, “presence” is not an empirical neutral fact. Rather,
presence is an effect generated through various representational systems by the desires shaped by specific cultural and philosophical
ideologies’ (Milne, 2010, p. 72). For example, Milne examines the way letter writers represent their bodies in the text of their letters,
arguing that a key element of epistolary practices in the nineteenth century was the written production of a body in letters which helped
construct presence between the communicants. Milne argues this representation of the writer’s body, which remained materially distant,
was important enough that actually meeting and so confronting the imagined body with the physical body might destroy the presence that
had been developed in letters.
The sense of presence they experience in letters may be destroyed by a physical meeting . . . when the materiality of the epistolary
system is used as a metonym for the corporeal body . . . references to the corporeal body often create a sense of ‘presence,’ in the
Derridean understanding of this concept. The body is used to signify a presence that exists outside of, or is in excess of, the realm
of the physical encounter. Arguably, this is a defining feature of the familiar letter: its ability to convey virtual presence by using
signs of the material and corporeal. (Milne, 2010, p. 90)
Presence in the context of communication is then a product of material and cultural practices. From these arguments drawn from
Derrida and Milne, I can begin to define communicative practices as the ways and means of creating presence outside of the
presumption that senders and receivers of messages are automatically present in the message’s utterance. The core elements of Derrida
that Milne draws on are in a sense a negative argument by which any sense of absolute self-presence is disturbed and revealed as, for
Derrida, dependent on differance, and, for Milne, dependent on differance as engaged by various ideologies and technologies. Accepting
this, we still need to ask if presence is created or constructed, as Milne shows so well in her analyses of letters, postcards and emails,
and if Derrida makes it clear there is no obvious ‘self-presence,’ then what is it that is being created? If presence is not a self-evident
and transparent presence of the self to the self then what is a created or constructed communicative presence?

Presence two: Heidegger, Levinas and face-to-face


If presence is not transparent and absolute self-presence that founds an autonomous and self-consistent subject, then Milne’s suggestion
of a communicative presence needs to be expanded and understood. This raises a question of being and Being that is within presence
and communication because this questions the nature of the self. Derrida argued that to follow the critique of presence, which Milne
draws on, the path is through Heideggerian philosophy (Derrida, 1976, p. 23).1 The point is not that Heidegger’s thought is the end of the
theory of Being, but rather that it is essential to reach an understanding of presence ‘by way of’ Heidegger’s thought. Having picked up
the trail based on Milne’s work, leading to Derrida we can now continue down this path, taking up Derrida’s pointer that Heidegger is a
necessary interlocutor.
Peters also points towards Heidegger who, he argues, creates a sense of communication which does not see communication as the
openness of one mind to another, but as part of our fundamental ‘being-with’ others. Peters says of Heidegger:
To be human is to be linguistic and social. Speech can make our relations explicit, but there is no question for Heidegger of
communication’s failing between people any more than there is of people’s ceasing to dwell in societies and in language. We are
bound together in existential and lived ways before we even open our mouths to speak. Communication here does not involve
transmitting information about one’s intentionality; rather, it entails bearing oneself in such a way that one is open to hearing the
other’s otherness. (Peters, 1999, p. 16)
Peters here invokes the idea of ‘being-with’ that is always already there. This also invokes the core Heideggerian concept of Dasein or
Being. It should be noted that the work of Heidegger and work on Heidegger are vast, complex and at times troubling but, for the
purposes of this account, it is important to follow the thread that is relevant to communication and this has led to being-with and Dasein,
which will here be drawn from their formulation in Being and Time.2
Heidegger’s notion of Being is, from the start, Being in the everyday and he argues Being as experienced by beings has been passed
over often precisely because it has this ‘average everydayness’ (Heidegger, 1980, p. 69). Accordingly as he begins to uncover the form
of Dasein, Heidegger begins with beings in ordinary interactions; for example in buying a book, in walking around a field, looking at
someone else’s boat or discussing work (Heidegger, 1980, pp. 153–4). A number of things are important about this, not only does
Heidegger start with the way Being works in everyday interactions of beings, he also shows this means that there is no outside to beings.
In clarifying Being-in-the-world we have shown that a bare subject without a world never ‘is’ proximally, nor is it ever given. And
so in the end an isolated ‘I’ without Others is just as far from being proximally given. If, however, ‘the Others’ already are there
with us in Being-in-the-world . . . even this should not mislead us into supposing that the ontological structure of what is thus
‘given’ is obvious, requiring no investigation. (Heidegger, 1980, p. 152)
Our being-there in the world is always as part of interactions with others, often simple and habitual, but this is only the beginning of
necessary analysis, Heidegger argues, and does not reveal the nature of Being in being-in-the-world or in being-there. For this Heidegger
begins to explore the nature of Dasein.
The result, for Heidegger, of recognizing that beings are always in the world related to others is that for each of us our Being is
always ‘one’s own,’ or ‘has mineness’; Dasein is personal, while at the same time we always encounter others engaged in their kind of
‘being-in-the-world’. Being-with is thus integral, it is an ‘existential characteristic of Dasein’ (Heidegger, 1980, pp. 156–7). ‘Not only is
Being towards Others an autonomous irreducible relationship of Being: this relationship, as Being-with, is one which, with Dasein’s
Being, already is’ (Heidegger, 1980, p. 162). The Being of beings is a relationship that always already exists between beings and their
others, expressed generally as between Self and Other. Dreyfus’ account of Being-with identifies this point in Heidegger.
Heidegger’s basic point is that the background familiarity that underlies all coping and all intentional states is not a plurality of
subjective belief systems including mutual beliefs about each others’ beliefs, but rather an agreement in ways of acting and judging
into which human beings, by the time they have Dasein in them, are ‘always already’ socialized. Such agreement is not conscious
thematic agreement but is prior to and presupposed by the intentionalistic sort of agreement arrived at between subjects. (Dreyfus,
1995, p. 144)
Being is accordingly about various ways of being-with others. However, Heidegger points out that empathy with others is not a
‘primordial existential phenomenon, any more than knowing in general’ (Heidegger, 1980, p. 163) because empathy only arises
consequent on one’s own Dasein already being-with others. The gap opened up here is that certain primordial existential phenomena, so
understood because they are part of Being-with-one-another and Dasein, mislead from empathy.
Our analysis has shown that Being-with is an existential constituent of Being-in-the-world. Dasein-with has proved to be a kind of
Being which entities encountered within-the-world have as their own. So far as Dasein is at all, it has Being-with-another as its kind
of Being. This cannot be conceived as a summative result of the occurrence of several ‘subjects’. Even to come across a number
of ‘subjects’ becomes possible only if the Others who are concerned proximally in their Dasein-with are treated merely as
‘numerals’. (Heidegger, 1980, p. 163)
The others are encountered not as a full beings-with-and-towards-one-another because Heidegger understands knowing and empathy as
appearing after the encounter with the Other. Prior to knowing and empathy, the Other (others) are encountered numerically, as a series
of others with which our or mine Dasein cannot encounter as full being-with. Authentic Dasein is here submerged or absorbed into the
world of its concerns, its everyday concerns.3
This diversion from authentic Dasein introduces both the quest to recover Dasein and the main barrier to such a recovery in
Heidegger’s account of the ‘they’ or das Man. By this Heidegger refers to the Other who is not a definite other but others as
conglomerated and represented within the generality of Other. Each specific other, who could or should give rise to being-with, becomes
a generalized and equalized other, such that one’s Dasein, one’s mineness, becomes part of the generalized ‘they’ that distances
ourselves from being-with (Heidegger, 1980, pp. 163–5). The ‘they’ of this conglomerated Other is a dictatorship of the average and a
drive to reduce all to what is publicly part of each other; for example, we dress either with or against a fashion which is driven by ‘they’
but in either case we are defined in fashion terms by this ‘they’.
Overnight, everything that is primordial gets glossed over as something that has long been well known. Everything gained by a
struggle becomes just something to be manipulated. Every secret loses its force. This care of averageness reveals in turn an
essential tendency of Dasein which we call the ‘levelling down’ of all possibilities of Being. (Heidegger, 1980, p. 165)
Heidegger has now defined the quest to reveal Being or to recover the revelation of Being in authentic Dasein that he has already
realized but which the ‘ordinary’ folk, the dictatorship of the average, prevent realization of in the everyday. Having found the
fundamental nature of existence to be ‘being-with,’ Heidegger’s argument for the concealment of this turns on his rejection of others as
inauthentic and mired in a reduction of all to the average. From finding the ordinary and mundane everyday at the core of Being as
multiple, differential relations of being-with, Heidegger argues this seemingly similar mundane conceals the revelation of Being’s
meaning.
Yet this seems odd and I can ask, in relation to communication and presence, why is the everyday both the meaning of Being and the
barrier to realization of this meaning? It does not seem immediately clear that ordinary activities such as buying a book or sitting at a
train station are necessarily routines that demand we subject ourselves to the average in each other. Peters and Milne have already
argued that in regard, at least to communication, the everyday may be fragile but it is certainly capable of sustaining communication and
that this itself points to the existence of presence and being-with. The point they make is not of a fundamental failure of the possibility of
selves and others being-with in communication, but their work demonstrates such communication occurs and infer from this that there
must be presence and being-with, even if fallible, leaving the question of how such presence is theorized. Such accounts do not seem to
square easily with Heidegger’s in which the everyday is the arena of failed being-with but rather accord more closely with an account
like Haraway’s focus on the entanglements that make up each being-with. Here Haraway considers Heidegger’s means of freeing
Dasein to unconceal the truth.
To achieve this great voiding of illusion, to grasp ‘negativity’, to be free, to understand one’s captivity rather than merely live it as an
animal, . . . a man in Heidegger’s story allows the terrible experience of profound boredom to drench his whole self. . . . Only from
this great destroying and liberating antiteleological negativity, this perfect indifference, can Dasein . . ., true human being, emerge.
Only from this ‘open’ can man grasp the world with passion, not as stock and resource, but in unconcealment and disclosure freed
from technique and function. My ‘open’ is quite other, if similarly lustful for nonteleological understanding. It emerges from the
shock of ‘getting it’: This and here are who and where we are? What is to be done? How can respect and response flourish in this
here and this we, even as this we is the fruit of entanglement? . . . Never certain, never guaranteed, the ‘open’ for companion
species becomes possible in the contact zones and unruly edges. (Haraway, 2008, p. 367–8)
If Heidegger’s mistrust of the masses is questioned then it is possible to refuse to see Being as concealed in the way Heidegger argues it
must be. As Haraway suggests, we can exist within the unruly and not see these as necessarily concealing the truth of existence. This
means that while Heidegger establishes presence as forms of being-with, to provide a specifically communicative sense of this presence,
it is worth examining a further theoretical resource that is consonant with the idea of being-with but, following Haraway, is dissonant to
Heidegger on the question of betrayal through the average everydayness of the Other. This can be found in Levinas’ work which also
revolves around a key concept for internet and non-internet communication in what it means to be ‘face-to-face’.
What do we mean when we say we are face-to-face? The question of co-presence may be contained in that question. For Levinas,
the face we see is the face of someone else, someone other than us, an other, an other’s face. The general conditions for understanding
what significance a face has will involve understanding the Other; that which convinces us we are not the sole entity and centre of all
worlds, that we are not unproblematically the same. Such an encounter is the inescapable assumption we must make in order to reach an
understanding of the face. If we argue there are no others, then the selves can see no face and there can be no face-to-face. This
accords with the idea of being-with in Being. Thus, as we refuse to presume that we know anything except that there is a face-to-face
we are led to consider the general terms of Self and Other, with no presumptions concerning distance, the physical or bodies. We can
immediately see how this is similar to Heidegger’s being-with but also different in its assumption of what happens in the encounters of
selves and others. Levinas offers an analysis of the face, that both draws on the Heidegger while also specifying presence differently.
The way in which the other presents himself, exceeding the idea of the other in me, we here name face. . . . The face of the
Other at each moment destroys and overflows the plastic image it leaves me, the idea existing to my own measure and to the
measure of its ideatum – the adequate idea. It does not manifest itself by these qualities. . . . It expresses itself. The face brings a
notion of truth which . . . is not the disclosure of an impersonal Neuter, but expression: the existent breaks through all the
envelopings and generalities of Being to spread out its ‘form’ the totality of its ‘content’, finally abolishing the distinction between
form and content. (Levinas, 1969, pp. 50–1)
What does Levinas see in a face? He sees the Other, the fact that the Self – myself – is not the only existent, not the only existing thing
meaning the world, my world, cannot revolve solely around my desires, conceptions and understanding; ‘the phenomenon that is the
apparition of the Other is also face’ (Levinas, 2006, p. 31). This breaking up, this moment in which any self realizes it is caught up in the
Self and the Other is foundational.
What is exceptional . . . is that I am ordered toward the face of the other. . . . All the negative attributes which state what is beyond
the essence become positive in responsibility, a response answering to a non-thematizable provocation thus a non-vocation, a
trauma. This response answers, before any understanding, for a debt contracted before any freedom and before any consciousness
and any present, but it does answer, as though the invisible that bypasses the present left a trace by the very fact of bypassing the
present. That trace lights up the face of a neighbour, ambiguously him before whom (or to whom, without any paternalism) and him
for whom I answer. (Levinas, 1981 pp. 11–12)
Face is the presence of the Other to the Self and of founding Being in the inescapable recognition of other beings. This is not far distant
from Heideggerian being-with but construes the Self and Other encounter differently, seeing the multiple relations of selves and others
that make up Self and Other but not mistrusting all the others. It is in this way a rejection of Heideggerian mistrust and an opening to
Harawayian joy, entanglement and encounter. But what is the relationship that each being experiences in feeling or finding others and
which is constitutive of Being in the general relationship of the Self to the Other? When I say ‘experience,’ it is not an experience in any
everyday sense of the word, it is the experience on which everydays may be founded. Levinas argues it cannot be anything but a
primary and inescapable responsibility, such that he asks, ‘But isn’t this servitude? Not being able to get out of responsibility?’ (Levinas,
2006, p. 52), and he considers the hostage to be a profound understanding of this relationship in which responsibility for others and to
others is always already there.
The hostage remains an important implication of Being in which the Self is understood as primordially responsible to the Other, but it is
only one model. Levinas also terms this relationship a conversation. The conversation does not contradict the hostage as an expression
of Being but instead interprets it differently, away somewhat from responsibility, the implication of the interaction of selves and others,
and towards the interaction itself.
Conversation, from the very fact that it maintains the distance between me and the Other, the radical separation asserted in
transcendence which prevents the constitution of totality, cannot renounce the egoism of its existence; but the very fact of being in
a conversation consists in recognizing in the Other a right over this egoism, and hence in justifying oneself. (Levinas, 1969, p. 40)
Being face-to-face can thus be understood as a fundamental expression of existence, of what is inescapable about existing. This is the
relationships of selves to others which cannot be escaped, avoided or denied, whether expressed in the intense intimacy of mother-child
or the multifarious encounters of the everyday. Returning again to Haraway, instead of boredom disclosing authenticity we find play in
these intermingled being-withs. Play which ‘also requires something . . . namely, joy in the sheer doing. . . . Play makes an opening.
Play proposes. . . . Play is not making a living; it discloses living’ (Haraway, 2008, p. 240). This is not play as just something trivial but
play as also revealing what it is to live. Being is here constituted in the serious play of relations. Being is both the conversation and a
relationship of hostage between Self and Other and both express the deepest and inescapable responsibility of beings to each other. It is
a change of being-with to becoming-with that, I would argue, is substantially similar to Levinas’ name for this relationship as the Face
and to be face-to-face is to encounter the Other.
A relation whose terms do not form a totality can hence be produced within the general economy of being only as proceeding from
the I to the others, as a face to face, as delineating a distance in depth – that of the conversation, of goodness, of Desire –
irreducible to the distance the synthetic activity of the understanding establishes between the diverse terms, other with respect to
one another, that lend themselves to its synoptic operation. (Levinas, 1969, p. 39)
Being face-to-face in Levinas’ thinking is a fundamental moment in which the self is forced to extend beyond itself and, in that
extension, to realize the existence of many others leading to the realization of the Other. Levinas argues that this realization of the
necessity of the Other’s face, of the reality of living beyond the Self, because it extends a being beyond itself, takes the form of a
conversation and a hostage taking, and that this means it is a relationship of responsibility.
While Levinas’ concern is with fundamental ontological questions, my arguments are looking for something a little less fundamental in
an understanding of communicative presence, which can now be summarized drawing on the preceding arguments. Both Levinas and
Heidegger take up a sense of being-with. However, where Heidegger argues there is an immediate loss of presence in the midst of the
average masses, Levinas sees responsibility and this is given a communicative direction by being interpreted as both conversation and
hostage. It is in this sense that it becomes closer to Haraway’s idea of becoming-with. It is this sense of being-with/becoming-with as
conversation that can be taken forward to understand presence in communication, based on its two-edged sense of both care and
capture. This does not go as far as Levinas does in claiming a fundamental moment of Being, but it asserts the idea that presence in
communication is the unstable, difference-dependent creation of being-with/becoming-with or the face-to-face, whose establishment in
specific spaces and times makes transmission of messages possible. Building on Levinas and Haraway helps to define presence in
communication means as the construction or creation or recognition of a face-to-face in which selves and others are, hostage-like,
related in a conversation and play. Building on Heidegger, this conversation is made in the average everydayness of social life. Building
on Derrida, this conversation engages differance and the necessary instability and performative nature of relations that differance
entails. Finally, building on Milne and the prior work of communication theorists like Carey and Peters, communication exists when there
is presence which enables transmission.
This means that for communication to happen there must be presence. Further, this means that though there will be a form of
presence within conditions of differance and everydayness in any form of communication, the nature of this presence and its conditions
cannot be known outside of specific and particular communicative forms. To understand a spatially and historically specific form of
communication, the way a particular face-to-face as presence is created and maintained within conditions of differance and
everydayness will need to be specified. This presence then opens the possibility of transmission. Each such understanding of a particular
form of communicative presence and the transmission it enables is what is meant in the following by a communicative practice. Put
another way, a communicative practice is a historically and spatially specific way of constructing presence and enabling transmission.
Knowing this however still leaves two concepts to be explicated for the theory of communication presented here to be clear;
performativity or practice and materiality. Though the term ‘practice’ and ‘performative’ have been used, these need to be explored to
understand what communicative actions in the everyday mean, and because presence is specific in particular times and spaces,
communication is something material which also needs conceptualization. Performativity and practice will be examined next, after which
suggesting a concept of matter will complete a full conceptualization of communicative practices.

Performativity
Derrida’s (contested) use of Austin’s concept of the speech-act and Butler’s subsequent extension and criticism of him form a way of
understanding performativity and its relation to practice; this extends and connects to the points opened up by Milne’s use of Derrida on
presence while also adapting influential work in cultural theory on performativity. The argument reconnects to the previous discussion
when Derrida analysed Husserl to claim that differance is inescapable and opens up the instability of presence. What was outlined but
not discussed in relation to differance is the meaning of iterability within differance. It is here that Derrida argues that repetition or
iterability is a problem because repetition seeks to return the same but each return is necessarily of something different. Put another
way, if it were not different in some way, then it could not be a repetition but would in fact be the same thing, but if it is different, then it
cannot be a repetition. Further, in communicative practice, as so far defined, presence creates the possibility of transmission which
requires repetition to be an ongoing form of communication. Communication requires iterability in which the same is repeated but only on
condition of a necessary difference (Derrida, 1988; Loxley, 2007, pp. 62–87).
Butler picks up this point and notes what appears to be an opposition or contradiction in Derrida’s work on differance and iterability
between that which exists across different significations and the particular signification itself. She asks: ‘What guarantees the
permanence of this crossed and vexed relation in which the structural exceeds and opposes the semantic, and the semantic is always
crossed and defeated by the structural?’ (Butler, 1997, p. 150). Immediately after posing this question Butler argues that it is a question
to take seriously if one wants to think through ‘the logic of iterability as a social logic’ (Butler, 1997, p. 150).
To see the importance of this social logic and its role in repetition and iterability, it is important to open up performativity as a particular
kind of relation. Performativity is the relation in which the performance produces both the performed and the performer. Butler suggests
that performativity can be understood through two closely linked sets of concepts: repetition, iteration and citation, on the one hand, and
practices, on the other hand.
If a performative provisionally succeeds . . . then it is not because an intention successfully governs the action of speech, but only
because that action echoes prior actions, and accumulates the force of authority through the repetition or citation of a prior
and authoritative set of practices. It is not simply that the speech act takes place within a practice, but that the act is itself a
ritualized practice. (Butler, 1997, p. 51)
And the repetition and citation performs the particularly singular function of performativity: ‘Indeed, is iterability or citationality not
precisely this: the operation of that metalepsis by which the subject who “cites” the performative is temporarily produced as the
belated and fictive origin of the performance itself?’ (Butler, 1997, p. 49). Practices are referred by Butler to two key concepts in
Austin’s of the speech-act and Althusser’s of interpellation. Both these conceptualize the ways in which a performative produces both
the subject and object of itself, the way that a performative produces the ‘effects that it names’ (Butler, 1993, p. 1).
But this performativity still relies on and is troubled by the difficulty Derrida argued attends to repetition and iteration because of the
impossibility of repetition. Butler builds on performativity to argue that Derrida has, in a sense, conceptualized the problem of iterability
as being universal. ‘Derrida appears to install the break as a structurally necessary feature of every utterance and every codifiable
written mark, thus paralyzing the social analysis of forceful utterance’ (Butler, 1997, p. 150). Derrida, in Butler’s argument, makes it
difficult to analyse the politics of communication or utterance because utterance is subject to the universal problem of iteration and
repetition. For this reason, Butler argues she needs an account of the ‘social iterability of the utterance’ (Butler, 1997, p. 150). To
understand this social iterability Butler needs to break out of a structural dominance in which every utterance is iterated and hence is
suspect for philosophical reasons. She takes up ideas of social sedimentation in which repetition builds on previous repetitions that are
maintained socially through performativity’s ability to create performer and performed in performance.
Butler argues that to overcome the abstract problem of difference, there must be a force that is both integrated into performatives, in
fact is essential to them, but at the same time is beyond their intelligibility. This she argues is the irreducibility of the speaking body; ‘the
abiding incongruity of the speaking body, the way in which it exceeds its interpellation, and remains uncontained by any of its acts of
speech’ (Butler, 1997, p. 151). It is the speaking body that causes a ‘scandal’ in the processes of iterability as social sedimentation and
so opens up the possibility that something like the same can traverse the necessary difference.
I would agree with Bourdieu’s critique of some deconstructive positions that argue that the speech act, by virtue of its internal
powers, breaks with every context from which it emerges. That is simply not the case, and it is clear to me, especially in the
example of hate speech, that contexts inhere in certain speech acts in ways that are very difficult to shake. On the other hand, I
would insist that the speech act, as a rite of institution, is one whose contexts are never fully determined in advance, and that the
possibility for the speech act to take on a non-ordinary meaning, is one whose contexts are never fully determined in advance, and
that the possibility for the speech act to take on a non-ordinary meaning, to function in contexts where it has not belonged, is
precisely the political promise of the performative. (Butler, 1997, p. 161)
The ability to break with the sedimentation of iterations is a political promise that, for Butler, comes from the body. It is this body that
Butler posits as the means by which a break can be made, against Bourdieu’s dismissal of performativity.
But what is a body and a speaking body? These seem to be to Butler a way of constructing social iterability which allows
performativity, but this turns on the idea of a speaking body whose nature is, in turn, unclear. Some, particularly Barad, argue that within
Butler’s invocation of the body there is a sense of materiality, of the body as a form of matter, and that Butler is looking to bring matter
and discourse into closer proximity, but in fact does not do so. ‘Questions about the material nature of discursive practices seem to hang
in the air like the persistent smile of the Cheshire cat’ (Barad, 2007, p. 64). Barad argues that the issue is not just that of bodies but
behind bodies of the nature of matter. While Barad adopts a similar approach to performativity as Butler, she does so to open up a way
beyond divisions which leave matter out of analysis. ‘A performative understanding of scientific practices, for example, takes account of
the fact that knowing does not come from standing at a distance and representing but rather from a direct material engagement with
the world’ (Barad, 2007, p. 49). In the present context, if communication is now understood as the creation of presence through certain
performatives, to fully understand such performatives and how they overcome the problem of repetition, we need to insert matter into
this and ask, what does materiality mean in such a form of communication? Moreover, Butler’s assertion of the body and Barad’s
analysis of this assertion suggests that performativity cannot be understood fully without understanding matter and its relations to the
social logics of performativity.
While Derrida and Butler allow us to understand performatives as particular ways of asserting the performer, performed and
performance in the one action, they still struggle to establish the sociality or social logic of performativity as a way of limiting or
regulating the effects of the necessary failure of repetition. Butler looks to help from a third concept that has also already emerged as
being important to theorizing communication in matter and the body. Examining matter will allow presence and performativity to be
brought together as a definition of communicative practices.

Matter and communication


As it is Barad I have drawn on to make the connection between performativity and materiality, it is worth taking up her account to help
articulate a compatible understanding of matter. Barad’s work explicitly attempts to put matter back into play in social and cultural
theory; she is important for having enforced a head-on collision between 30 years of post-structural, constructivist science studies,
performativity theory and the idea of matter. She also concisely puts the case for what is at stake in the idea of matter and why it needs
to be analysed.
It is difficult to imagine how psychic and sociohistorical forces alone would account for the production of matter. Surely it is the
case – even when the focus is restricted to the materiality of ‘human’ bodies (and how can we stop there?) – that there are
‘natural’, not merely ‘social’, forces that matter. . . . What is needed is a robust account of the materialization of all bodies –
‘human’ and ‘nonhuman’ – including the agential contributions of all material forces (both ‘social’ and ‘natural’). This will require
an understanding of the relationship between discursive practices and material phenomena. (Barad, 2007, p. 66)
Barad takes forward the notion of the performative, which argues that we may make our being through practices in which produced and
performer are created in the performance, by arguing that understanding of the performative has been flawed by its failure to account
for the material. I have noted the importance of the body for Butler’s account of the social logic of performativity and the importance of
an idea of materiality within the idea of the body. Barad builds up her conceptualization of matter through an encounter with classical
quantum mechanics in Niels Bohr’s work. Barad interprets Bohr’s work on complementarity as, in part, resulting in the conclusion that
the nature of an object depends on the way it is measured, allowing some objects to have apparently contradictory properties (Barad,
2007, p. 107). Such a view is usually closely connected to Heisenberg’s uncertainty principle but Barad focuses on a specific reading of
Bohr’s concerning complementarity.
Bohr’s argument for the indeterminable nature of measurement interactions is based on his insight that concepts are defined by the
circumstances required for their measurement . . . . Bohr’s indeterminacy principle can be stated as follows: the values of
complementary variables (such as position and momentum) are not simultaneously determinate. The issue is not one of
unknowability per se; rather, it is a question of what can be said to simultaneously exist. (Barad, 2007, pp. 108 and 118)
Barad argues that for Bohr objectivity is fixed at the point at which the measuring apparatus is fixed. One of Bohr’s famous thought-
experiments demonstrated that light could have either a wave or particle form depending on how it is measured, thus giving light
contradictory qualities. Barad’s reading of Bohr is that this contradiction never comes to exist because light is resolved as being either a
wave or a particle when a particular apparatus is set up that measures a particular instance of light and in doing so objectifies it. There
are, of course, considerable complexities and arguments behind this interpretation of Bohr, but for present purposes the important point is
not the historical accuracy of Barad’s account of Bohr but that Barad then generalizes her reading as a discursive and materialist
theory, refusing to prioritize one over the other while asserting the necessity of both.
For Barad, the notion of the apparatus can be generalized so that it becomes the condition of any phenomena existing and not just
laboratory-based experimental phenomena. With the refusal of primacy to either the discursive or material and a commitment to
understanding phenomena as performed and not simply given, Barad adds the notion of the apparatus as the moment when possibilities
are ‘cut’ or objectified.
In my agential realist elaboration of Bohr’s account, apparatuses are the material conditions of possibility and impossibility of
mattering; they enact what matters and what is excluded from mattering. . . . the apparatus specifies an agential cut that enacts a
resolution (within the phenomenon) of the semantic, as well as ontic, indeterminacy. Hence apparatuses are boundary-making
practices. (Barad, 2007, p. 148)
Apparatuses can make cuts, on an analogy to measurements, that stabilize a particular state to which material and discursive
contributions are made and remade. Matter and discourse each refer to ways of making contributions, of intra-acting, to entanglements
of bodies, signs, matters, humans, animals, post-humans, all of which become a particular phenomenon out of their multifarious
possibilities when the cut is made. Phenomena are then part of sedimented worlds in which particular ways of being and doing become
‘normalized’ by their cuts being repeated. Thus despite the seeming instability and multiplicity of Barad’s account, she argues for the
stability of the world we live in through the iterations of performatives that have the characteristics of apparatuses.
Since different agential cuts materialize different phenomena . . . our intra-actions do not merely effect what we know and
therefore demand an ethics of knowing; rather our intra-actions contribute to the differential mattering of the world. Objectivity
means being accountable for marks on bodies, that is, specific materializations in their differential mattering. We are
responsible for the cuts that we help enact not because we do the choosing (neither do we escape responsibility because ‘we’ are
‘chosen’ by them), but because we are an agential part of the material becoming of the universe. Cuts are agentially enacted not by
willful individuals but by the larger material arrangements of which ‘we’ are a ‘part’. (Barad, 2007, p. 178)
Barad’s work pushes the material back into an accounting for bodies and the world, while at the same time retaining the power of the
discursive. Her account goes further in understanding the nature of matter in the attempt to understand the body. Yet it is important to
consider some difficulties that this last accounting for responsibility brings to the fore.
Despite Barad’s complex account, it seems that responsibility remains caught in a duality of something like a structure (even when
structure is understood as a sedimented series of cuts that stabilize multiple and unstable entanglements of matter and discourse) and
something like an agent (the role we all have in a cut being made). It is striking in the quotation just given: how cuts we do not choose to
make still cut and we are chosen by cuts but we are also not free from the choices we make by virtue of being entangled within a cut
which chooses us. It begins to feel like the dualities that Barad has found Bohr so helpful in overcoming are here coming apart and
reasserting themselves. This gives Barad’s account of responsibility and agency a feeling of having contradictory views sewn together
and that this sewing is itself a cut, in Barad’s technical sense, and so forms the phenomena of agency and responsibility as
simultaneously and always both the responsibility to make choices in ‘cutting’ and having been chosen by a cut.
This strain in overcoming the dualisms of so many fundamental categories of thought and practice – matter and language, ontology
and epistemology, human and post-human, structure and agency – sometimes suggests that Barad’s own language reintroduces these
divisions. ‘Intra-actions are nonarbitrary, nondeterministic, causal enactments’ (Barad, 2007, p. 179). Such statements begin to appear
problematic because instead of the complex but determining moment in which a cut stabilizes objects, Barad now interprets this as
causes that do not determine. Similarly,
matter is a dynamic intra-active becoming that is implicated and enfolded in its iterative becoming. Matter(ing) is a
dynamic articulation/configuration of the world. In other words, materiality is discursive (i.e., material phenomena are
inseparable from the apparatuses of bodily production; matter emerges out of, and includes as part of its being, the ongoing
reconfiguring of boundaries), just as discursive practices are always already material (i.e., they are ongoing material
[re]configurings of the world). (Barad, 2007, pp. 151–2)
Rather than overcoming the divisions and boundaries of a matter and discourse duality, Barad has engaged them in a process in which
they are constantly entangled in multiple ways with multifarious forms of contribution.
This driving, complex attempt to push theory of matter forward and the use of an understanding of science make Barad’s work both
fascinating and important, yet Barad also finds the categories she seeks to overcome both must be asserted at the beginning of her work
and, I argue, they resurrect themselves at the conclusion. The cost of this emerges in a prioritization of processes over categories.
Everything for Barad begins as becoming and ends as becoming and it is only in such processes that all entanglements are made. This
ultimately falls short for processes cannot exist or dominate the categories they require to make a process happen, this is not to suggest
that categories should be dominant but to point out that Barad has strongly prioritized the means by which phenomena are produced such
that what seems to matter is not what a particular phenomena ‘is’ but that it ‘moves’. This undermines her identification of the moment
when a thing, a category, is made in the cut because the cut is undermined as a moment of categorization or of stasis by the becomings
that make things move. Can a cut ever be made within such ongoing processes of becoming?
Barad sets up an opposition or duality between the discursive and the material that she then seeks to reconcile, and this is the key
duality that seems to me to recur within her work rather than being resolved. Perhaps this means my points are less a criticism of her
logic than a disagreement with her that there is such a duality that needs resolving. The idea of the cut emerges as a powerful suggestion
because it conceptualizes how even within discourses a moment may occur that objectifies. Barad tangles with contemporary accounts
of matter by asserting the entanglement of the given and the word. ‘Matter and meaning are not separate elements. They are
inextricably fused together, and no event, no matter how energetic, can tear them asunder’ (Barad, 2007, p. 3). Barad pursues matter as
itself being active and how this activity has been missed or mislaid within discursively dominated accounts. However, Barad’s reaching
for matter seems to give way to accounts that drift back into the very categories of discourse and matter that her account of
performativity was intended to move beyond.
I feel that despite Barad’s account as soon as she asserts, ‘It is difficult to imagine how psychic and sociohistorical forces alone would
account for the production of matter’ (Barad, 2007, p. 66) then there is an irreconcilable duality of matter and discourse which returns
within her work and is a perennial difficulty many feel for discourse theory in the face of matter. This difficulty manifests itself in a
desire for matter or a given, a desire which can only be articulated through discursive practices that themselves necessarily cannot reach
matter because they are discursive. Serres registers a similar desire when pursuing something that is beyond language while recognizing
the irony that language always reclaims whatever seems beyond language: ‘The given I have called hard is sometimes, but not always,
located on the entropic scale: it pulls your muscles, tears your skin, stings your eyes, bursts your eardrums, burns your mouth’ (Serres,
2008, p. 113). Yet as soon as this desire for the given is enunciated, Serres recognizes the infuriating and inevitable failure to fulfil that
desire: ‘Is there a single given independent of language? If so, how do we apprehend it? The discussion is over as soon as it begins: no-
one knows how to say what is given, independently of language. Any description of the aforementioned things is merely presenting data
in relation to the language being employed. The thing itself flees along the infinite asymptote of utterance’ (Serres, 2008, p. 112). Butler
registered a related difficulty when reflecting on her analysis of the body.
I began writing this book by trying to consider the materiality of the body only to find that the thought of materiality invariably moved
me into other domains. I tried to discipline myself to stay on the subject but found that I could not fix bodies as simple objects of
thought. Not only did bodies tend to indicate a world beyond themselves, but this movement beyond their own boundaries, a
movement of boundary itself, appeared to be quite central to what bodies ‘are’. I kept losing track of the subject. I proved resistant
to discipline, Invariably, I began to consider that perhaps this resistance to fixing the subject was essential to the matter at hand.
(Butler, 1993, p. ix)
Butler here opens up a way of using the performative approach to bodies and matter to move past the difficulties so far seen in
understanding matter beyond discourse. Perhaps the inability to focus on matter is part of its nature. Perhaps matter is that which goes
beyond our discursive abilities and so becomes unspeakable; Serres calls on stings and tears and the irony that these must be called in
language, Butler finds she is constantly shifted beyond her subject as the boundary moved and Barad asserts both that matter is not
discourse and the two are inextricably fused. Barad’s ‘cut’ might also be interpreted as being a way of naming the moment when, rather
than resolving discourse and matter into an observed phenomenon, the cut instead produces matter from the discursive by performatively
making it into matter. In such a reinterpretation of the cut performatives of matter are performatives that attempt to name the
unnameable in order to indicate that which is beyond culture and which cannot be part of social relations. However, this also changes the
idea of the cut from something that resolves discourse and matter to being something that does not begin from or recognize such a
distinction. A performative of matter can then be understood as the moment when a performative puts something into matter and beyond
discourse by creating that very distinction. Such performatives of matter, instead of cuts or as reinterpreted cuts, begin from the
discursive and look to understand how something that is taken to be non-discursive can be enacted.
In this interpretation, matter is made by a particular kind of performative through which we are able to talk about and act on that
which is beyond social or cultural relations. The moment of mattering, of making matter, does not resolve a distinction of matter and
discourse but instead creates a specific form for such a distinction. This means a performative of matter is the process of discoursing
about things which we can know nothing social or cultural about. But this appears to be an impossibility because the moment discourse is
capable of naming or acting on something that was beyond the discursive then by definition discourse brings it within the discursive and
within language.
The performatives of matter thus cannot be pre-social and pre-discursive, yet they seem to be reaching for that very outside. Does
this simply mean the performatives of matter are a constant failure? That they are the endless of task of pursuing an impossibility? This
seems unlikely given the extraordinary power and depth of knowledge that, for example, scientific knowledges, which are the primary
forms of discourse devoted to matter, are capable of producing and continue to produce. Matter as an impossible discursive pursuit
seems unlikely given the success of science in pursuing matter and bringing it into social use.
Rather the performative of matter can be seen to be the means by which some norms, characteristics or practices are taken to be
beyond the social and cultural. Matter is thus not a given, nor is it in contrast to discourse, it is instead the result of kinds of performatives
that mediate when something is beyond the social, thereby creating in a specific context a discursive distinction between matter and
discourse. It is a social logic to produce asocial things. These will be sedimented, well-known performatives, that produce discursive
results of great power, for something beyond the social has to be taken as a given and remain unquestioned socially, simply because it is
outside any social relationship. The great power of the performatives of matter will be to construct things that we not only can rely on
but which we must submit to. We can see this, for example, in feminist theory which, similar to anti-racist work, has often brought what
were thought to be beyond social characteristics of the abject into the social, thereby making something that was matter, social again.
And this is done because when it is ‘matter’ or natural that women are nurturing homebodies then there is no argument over whether
they should work outside the home, it is simply beyond argument. This understanding of matter has similarities with that of the ‘black
box’ in actor-network theory. In some such theories, it is argued that social relations are built out of a series of black boxes that close
down and contain various social arrangements of actants (both human and non-human). All is built on series of these boxes that are held
closed so that the whole arrangement can work or are opened up to disturb a particular arrangement (Callon and Latour, 1981).
However, theorizing matter as a performative is more specific because for Callon and Latour all kinds of social arrangements, as well as
material, can be black boxed. The account I am suggesting that makes matter a particular kind of performative is similar to black boxes,
while being more specific in its definition of the cut-like moment when a performative of matter is performed and the specificity of the
performative of matter in making something unquestionable and hence imbuing it with a certain kind of power.
The performative of matter consists of sets of practices that are repeated and cited by each other, in whose performance an object of
the practice is put beyond sociality, thereby gaining a specific form of authority, or is brought into the social, thereby gaining a partiality
and a politics. This is performative because the object of the citations is a materiality that is itself produced through the citations and
which then becomes the origin of the citations.
This also finally clarifies what I mean by the social logic of performativity which always remains within the discursive. What counts as
a difference and what counts as a repetition will be defined through such social logics, even while the abstract problem of difference that
Derrida defines remains. Within performatives, both of matter and other kinds of performatives, we socially and culturally learn what
may count as a repetition or as a difference, what is same and what is other. In this sense, nothing is outside the relation of care and
capture and on this basis certain types of caring and capture, of play, resolve socially and make forms of being-with/becoming-with.
With this in mind, we can turn back to communication and try to theorize it fully, noting its three main conceptual foundations of
presence, performativity and materiality.

A theory of communicative practices


Communicative practices are material performatives that create presence. Materiality is itself a particular kind of performative, one that
does the work of splitting the discursive from an asocially authoritative sense of matter. This reflects the sedimented nature of
performatives while also specifying which particular kinds of performatives, with their associated particular kinds of repeated citations or
actions, such as signing a letter, constitute communication. Performatives are the sets of citations that create in their performance both
the subject and object of the performance. The performatives construct presence in the interrelations between communicants that
creates the communicants and their types of messages resulting in the possibility of a successful transmission of meaning.
Such communicative practices exist in the everyday, as part of repeated individual actions of communicants, while at the same time
their repetition/iteration ensures they are part of historically specific and historically sedimented sets of practices. Communicative
practices may be specific and local, perhaps expressed among very few people in a local slang or dialect, or may be global and
generalized, perhaps expressed among, for example, the (in 2010) 12 million players of World of Warcraft. The abstract theory is
applicable to a range of communicative contexts, meaning that it will be possible to identify communicative practices in specific places
and times, operating with the social logic Butler identifies, each with their own sense of presence based on material performatives and
creating the possibility of a particular form of transmission. This is the answer as well to Derrida’s problem of repetition, because though
repetition remains philosophically a problem each communicative practice will have to resolve this problem socially by identifying
particular repetitions as significant enough to construct a socially stable form of repetition. To return to the question of pre-internet and
internet-dependent communicative practices, now dragging along an extended theoretical framework, I return to the hypothesis and
restate it.
Pre-internet communicative practices construct transmission based on performatives that put the body beyond social construction by
employing performatives that identify an individual’s subjectivity with their physical form. Presence in these communicative practices
relies on and elicits itself through performatives that allow the identification of physicality with subjectivity, thereby stabilizing the
communicants, the message and forms of messaging. The selves and others of this form of communicative presence come into being
through the identification of a body with a subjectivity. Each performative and its everyday instances are subject to the necessary
difference of repetition and iteration; for example, no two signatures are exactly alike yet their repetition is essential. This difference
through sameness is held together in pre-internet communicative practices by social conventions and collective practices established in
technological and cultural mechanisms such as the signature, forms of greeting and farewell, telling of personal stories, sealing with wax
and so on. These are the core performatives that establish presence and so form transmission in pre-internet communication.
Communicative practices based on internet technologies construct transmission with performatives that identify the style of someone’s
transmissions with a subjectivity. Presence in these communicative practices is based on performatives that create identifications
between particular types of messages and individual subjectivities. Each such identification is constructed out of performatives that
attempt to move the question of which subjectivity to attach to which style of transmitting messages into a matter performative and so
out of the social. Various social conventions and practices are created to stabilize transmission utilizing collective histories of types of
transmitting of messages, repertoires of jargon, collective memories of individual types of transmission and so on.
Prior to the internet, communicative practices for at-a-distance communication attempted to replicate a physical face-to-face form of
communication by assuming that the body and subjectivity were necessarily identified. Such an assumption needed to be put into practice
by creating performatives that authorized the body/subjectivity of senders and receivers and hence the integrity of the message, whose
meaning does not affect the body/subjectivity but is separated from them. Since the rise of internet-technology-mediated communication,
communicative practices have developed in the face of a radical instability of markers that would identify a body and subjectivity.
Instead practices have developed that stabilize sender and receiver by identifying each communicative subject with a style of
communication. These two hypothesized communicative practices will now be focused on in turn, first with a study of letters to and from
colonial Australia 1835–58 and second with a case study of communication in game-based virtual persistent worlds.

Notes
1 Derrida writes, ‘One must therefore go by way of the question of being, as it is directed by Heidegger and by him alone at and beyond
onto-theology, in order to reach the rigorous thought of that strange nondifference and in order to determine it correctly’ (Derrida,
1976, p. 23).
2 Of course, this does not deny the importance and extent of Heidegger’s work or comment on it. Nor does it deny the importance of
the controversy over Heidegger’s membership of and support for the Nazi Party (Derrida, 1989; Ott, 1993). The focus here however
is not on overviews of thinkers’ work but on taking up core concepts in the context of understanding communicative practices.
3 See Schatzki for a discussion of Dreyfus and Olafson, which is close to this point (Schatzki, 2005, pp. 239–41).
3
Letters: Pre-Internet Communicative Practices
I have been looking over all the letters that I have received to day, and there are only three in which the writer does not say
that he (or she) has nothing to say, which is a most preposterous fact.
Henry Howard Meyrick
The letters I receive from home create much too powerful an excitement in my mind to call it a pleasurable sensation. It is a
painful sensation occasioned by pleasure and memorie’s softening influences over friendship, distant but not forgotten, that
makes me deeply sensible of the strength of that tye that binds me to home, perhaps more powerful in its influence than even
the allurement of gain or riches.
Niel Black

Introduction1
To be a colonizer in Australia in its early settler years was to be truly at a distance from family, friends and business partners who were
more often than not located in Great Britain. Communication was reliant almost entirely on letters, with the only occasional adjunct being
verbal reports when, for example, someone returned to Great Britain and was able to pass on first-hand news and reports of those still in
the colony.
Letters from the period 1788 until 1872 (when Australia was linked to the United Kingdom by telegraph) were not only physically at a
distance but they were also temporally distant, emphasizing that they travelled between two faces that were no longer visible to each
other. One of the series of letters that will be discussed below was written by settler Henry Howard Meyrick to his family in Great
Britain. Meyrick arrived in Melbourne, Australia, in 1840 and wrote 28 surviving letters to England (Meyrick, 1939). The fastest time a
letter took to reach the post office near his family was just over four-and-a-half months, the longest was nearly eight months and the
average was just over seven months. What could happen to a son and brother in the months between writing and reading? As we will
see, Meyrick’s letters reflect physical, emotional and economic changes of profound kinds, all of which had to be communicated through
the medium of a letter. Letters to Australia from this period provide a particularly intense example of communicative practices in action.
The hypothesis of pre-internet communicative practices directs a focus on certain aspects of these letters. Unlike models of
communication that exclude the content of messages, the analysis that follows includes such meanings. However, unlike many analyses
of epistolary practices, the aim is not to understand those who are communicating and the content of their letters seen in relation to their
intellectual, political or artistic achievements – for example, in the extensive correspondence between Mary Mitford and Elizabeth
Barrett Browning (Milne, 2010, pp. 51–71) – but to understand how such communication is possible in the first place. This requires a
shift in focus from relating the content of letters to the lives and contexts of the readers and writers to the forms of letter writing and
reading, including their technologies and cultures. This does not exclude the contexts provided by the lives of readers and writers but it
diminishes their importance, pushing forward comparison of how communication happened.
To achieve this, there will first be a quantitative analysis of what was found and what seemed to be key means of creating stable
communication. Following this, three case studies from within the body of letters will be explored. One will be of the extraordinary
record found in the letters of Henry Howard Meyrick. The second will be of the business letters of Niel Black. Finally, communication
that came from the founding settlers of Melbourne will provide a view of letter writing outside of stable postal institutions.

Letters to and from Australia: 1835–59


Two hundred and six letters and seven closely related documents from this period were examined. The letters were of all types, from
short arrangements to call, to matter-of-fact business letters to the most soulful and distressing accounts of death in the bush and of
genocide. Such a mix is appropriate to examining communicative practices as it offers a range of types of communication, hoping to find
what is common between them. To keep a broad track of the differences between types of letters, they were designated in four
categories; personal, business, personal and business or state.
Each letter was read, with nearly all letters being handled in the original, this was an important consideration given some of the
material aspects of letters that needed attention, and letters were coded along two axes. One axis attempted to distinguish the particular
materialities and technologies used in the letters. Materialities and technologies were interpreted broadly to include not only types of
paper and methods of folding but also the facts of signatures, and the placing of greetings and farewells. The second axis attempted to
identify various routines within the meaning of letters. Here analysis tracked such things as whether self-identifying anecdotes or
recollections of personal history or tales of personal exposure were present. While interlinked, the difference between the two axes is
exemplified by the fact that in both axes greetings and farewells are examined; in the first axis this is simply the fact of there being in a
particular place on each letter a greeting and farewell, whereas the second axis traces the content and nature of farewells and greetings
(Table 3.1).
In terms of institutional context, this period is one in which at the beginning the postal service charged per piece of paper sent and not
in terms of weight. The most common letter was one sheet of paper folded in such a way as to write the address on the exposed section
while the message was written, usually, hidden inside the folds which were closed by a wax seal. Later in the period, letters which were
contained within envelopes emerged. This occurred variably; for example, within one sequence of business letters from 1859, letters sent
from Melbourne continued to be folded and sealed single sheets of paper, while from the same person at roughly the same time but now
in Sydney letters appear to have been placed in envelopes. Within one sequence of letters sent by the Bank of Australasia on 19 May
1859, the letter was sent using the single, folded piece of paper technique, and on 20 May, envelopes began to be used and continued to
be so (MS8996 Folder B-Ban Black letters). Coding of materialities leads to a number of quantitative measures that are worth comment
(see Table 3.2).
Table 3.1 Coding categories

Though rounded up to 100 per cent, there were in fact three exceptions to a greeting and farewell placed in a letter, though these
exceptions demonstrate the rule. One instance occurred in a letter that was contained within another letter. This dealt with the death of a
daughter, whose mother was sending a letter trying to find her son; the letter is distraught and not signed by the mother. This mother’s
plea was contained within another letter sent by the missing son’s uncle, which explained the situation and which contained a greeting
and farewell (MS8996 Box 20, 17 September1849). The other two instances were invitations from the aristocracy to visit, the inviting
Duke did not put a greeting and though there appears to be a salutation at the end there was no signature, and it is possible these were
hand delivered (MS8996 Box 20, 14 June 1843; 13 June 1848). These examples underline how unusual a lack of greeting and farewell
was in framing the content of a message. The greeting and farewell in their near universality stabilize the content of the letter by
indicating where meaning starts and stops. Even the examples of postscripts confirm this as they are strongly indicated by a smaller
greeting (often a dash or a ‘ps’) and are often themselves closed by a shorter version of a farewell (sometimes just initials). The content
or meaning of the letter is in this way bounded and identified.
Table 3.2 Materialities: percentage of letters with material practice

Seals and signatures establish an identity for the author of the letter by the physical marking of the letter with ink and wax in a way
that has no other meaning than to refer to an identity. In these practices, the inevitable uncertainty about who is writing at such distances
is contained by the assurance that this particular body – of a brother, son, friend – touched this letter and accordingly is the author of its
contents, themselves bounded by a greeting and farewell that further marks out the identity of the author. These technologies seem to
strongly resolve several key uncertainties, thereby providing some basis for the emergence of presence between writer and reader(s)
and so for a transmission in which the content is understood to retain its self-identity and come from the body of the author to the
reader(s). The lower percentage of letters with seals mirrors the distribution between numbers of folded letters and letters in envelopes.
No envelopes were found during the research and accordingly it is impossible to tell if seals were used on envelopes or not. When
handling folded letters it is easy to verify if a seal was used due to markings on the paper, even if the seal has been lost.
In contrast to these universal and near-universal techniques, some other material techniques were not consistently found. Issues
related to ink and paper were tracked but not in relation to whether they were used or not, because this is obviously rather a self-fulfilling
criteria (no exceptions were found to the use of some form of ink and paper). However shifts and changes in their use or mentions of
difficulty with them were tracked with the result that there were very few mentions of ink, pens or paper. A rare mention is by Meyrick,
who at one point states, ‘I am far from sure that you will be able to read a word of this, as I have manufactured the ink out of blacking
and have got a steel pen which runs thro’ the paper at ever third word’ (MS 7959 H15789–H15816, 20 March 1841), though the letter
was, even nearly two hundred years later, entirely legible. Meyrick also mentions using a black swan’s quill though he considers ‘The
black swan’s quill does not succeed’ (MS 7959 H15789–H15816, 10 September 1841). Nowhere else were there found mentions of the
basic technological items of ink, paper, sealing wax and so on.
Similarly, potential changes in handwriting were tracked but none were obviously found and no mention was made in any letter of
someone’s handwriting, whether of it improving, worsening, staying the same or anything related. It was however noticeable while
handling letters that, and this may seem obvious but it was striking, the signature and handwriting were clearly thematically linked being
born from the same style of writing of an individual. Thus the handwriting, whose mere form must have been familiar to some readers,
was reinforced and confirmed as identifying someone through the ‘look and feel’ of the signature being close to that of the message.
Rather than presenting this as separate quantitative result it is integrated into the signature’s role in establishing the body that writes,
because of the role of the shape of handwriting in reinforcing the signature’s relation to the handwriting in the message.
This analysis establishes an initial uniform set of practices for writing letters. These are a greeting and a farewell, placed at beginning
and end, a signature on all and a seal on folded letters, with contributory practices of identification between the shape of handwriting and
the shape of the signature. There were other practices we might intuitively have expected for which no routine or pattern was found.
Two such are a date and location placed at the start of the letter above the greeting. Dates were irregularly used in letters, both in terms
of actually stating the date and where it was stated. For example, dates might be mentioned as part of the letter’s discussion of an event
or in identifying a business deal but it was usually unclear if this was also the date of the letter or near it, so it was unclear if dates were
part of the meaning of letters or of what I am separating out here as material practices. All that was clear was that a practice of writing
a date near the greeting at the beginning of the letter was not routine. It may simply be that writers and readers were able to assume the
date of the letter from the postmark from when it is sent, after all with folded letters the postmark would always be present, unlike with
envelopes when the letter might be retained and the envelope with the postmark discarded.
Similarly, stating where the letter was written from was not a routine practice. Again, letters variably stated locations, though with no
clear pattern of stating where the writer’s location was, but this appeared to be more closely related to the telling of stories within letters
than to a routinized practice of stating the location. Again, postmarks usually stated locations and it may be that no need to state the
location was felt as the postmark would be on the same piece of paper as the message.
Even more so than the previous category of material practices, practices of ‘meaning’ as communicative practices are primarily a
qualitative set of procedures and routines. For example, it was not possible to quantitatively code the shifts in the content of greetings
and farewells as these were closely dependent on their contexts for their significance. Accordingly, more will be said about these kinds
of practices in subsequent sections. However, three kinds of broad routines of meaning were able to be coded (Table 3.3).
First, it was possible to identify in a general way when the content of letters contained self-identifiers. These were remarks of the kind
that could only be made by the writer of the letter, and so performed a function of reinforcing the identity of the sender. In business
letters, this often took the form of mentioning other occasions when the writer and receiver had made business deals with each other.
Many of the combined personal and business letters became personal because the writer drew on some personal connection or
knowledge to establish their identity, and sometimes to try and persuade. The difference in percentages between business letters and
mixed personal and business letters for this category is therefore something of an artefact of coding, because mentioning some personal
self-identification anecdote or story was one of the key ways of transforming a business into a business and personal letter. Yet, even
so, nearly 40 per cent of purely business letters contained some kind of confirmation of personal identity.
Table 3.3 Cultures: percentage of letters with routines of meaning

Second, writers often referred in one letter to other letters that they had sent or had received. There was often an anxiety about
maintaining contact and understanding the sequences of letters. This is perhaps unsurprising given the distance letters travelled and the
time they took – as noted already, the Meyrick letters range from just under five to nearly eight months – and the fact that those moving
around the colony, either for sightseeing or more likely as they try to find a better position to make a new economic life, may not pick up
their letters for some time. One way of establishing communication is to talk about the specific communications that are going on
between individuals and groups. It was therefore possible to code letters that made explicit reference to other letters sent and received.
Finally, the most difficult coding exercise undertaken was to identify in letters when writers made clear displays of their personal
identity. This is not the use of anecdotes or stories that were tracked in the first category, but the explicit self-exposure of states of
emotion, of bodily changes or developments or of ways of expressing the writer’s understanding of their life and changes they are coping
with. In contrast to telling stories that both writer and reader will recognize as bits of memory that will bind writer and reader together,
here it was noticeable on reading letters that many writers were reaching out through the ink by discussing their lives. This is to be
expected as, after all, what is a letter for but to keep one’s identity in front of the identities of others. Yet, what was looked for here was
not the simple recounting of any event, such as a reflection on the weather, on government regulations, current economic conditions and
so on, but clear and explicit reflections on a bodily or emotional state of the writer. Despite the obvious difficulty of identifying these
clearly, it was such a striking practice, even showing up in a third of business letters, that it seemed worth trying to quantify. The
overwhelming numbers of mixed personal and business and personal letters reflect the importance of this practice.
Keeping in mind the difficulty in coding quantitatively some of the phenomena touched on in the tables above, it is still striking that a
number of practices can be considered universal across letters. These practices, in their universality, form something like an unthought
binding for messages, establishing some of the basic practices that all those involved in these kinds of communicative practices used so
commonly as to render them obvious.
This binding consists in a number of elements that establish both the placement of messages and the identity of sender and intended
recipient. In terms of stabilizing where the message can be expected to be found, the placement of greeting and farewell are key.
Further the greeting establishes who the intended recipient is and accordingly provides clues as to how the writer is expecting the letter
to be read. We will see in examples in following case studies how writers shift their form of address and content depending on who the
intended recipient is. Similarly, the farewell is universal and provides an identification of the writer, particularly when linked to the
signature, and closing the contents. This is marked in some letters which have either a lack or an abundance of things to write about. In
the former case, there are blank spaces in the letter making the farewell and signature necessary to tell the reader that the message has
ended. In the latter, the normal practice with folded and sealed letters was that only one piece of paper was used but this did not prevent
the writer writing on every piece of unexposed paper and then sometimes turning the letter perpendicular and writing over the top of
existing writing creating a cross-hatched effect. In these latter cases, the writing can become so confusing that a farewell and signature
is essential to identifying where the message finishes and which lines need to be distinguished as having been written at which angle.
Reinforcing these binding and universal practices are a series of other practices which particularly for personal letters ensure the
person who is writing is identifying themselves to the readers. While it may seem obvious that individuals will refer to themselves and
expose their inner feelings in personal letters, it should not be overlooked that these are done in a context which identifies one person as
the writer and which imagines one or more people as the readers. Similarly referring to previous letters, to letters just received,
complaining of not receiving letters or warning that few letters will be forthcoming constructs in-between the letters a connection that
imagines an ongoing relationship between the writer and his/her readers. Why business letters require less of this most likely relates both
to keeping matters away from the personal, and in this sense is partly an artefact of the construction of coding categories, while also
gesturing towards business as dispassionate and opening the question of whether business letters reinforce in some way the
identifications of writer and reader to compensate for some of the content which is found in personal letters. This latter question will be
taken up in the largely business letters of Niel Black.
These routines provide a series of strong binding practices which locate the content of a message as emanating from one body or
subjectivity and that the intentions of this body imbue who the letter is directed to, and hence how it is written and to be read. The
communicative practice suggests that presence will be created and stabilized based on these material performances, the strong bindings,
which create a body and identities for the writer and readers, on the basis of which transmission is made possible. One example is the
constant presence of greeting and farewell which frames the message that is to be transmitted, clearly establishing where the writer
believes the message starts and finishes and indicating this to the readers. With this practice in place, the message is in part created and
meaning may be transmitted. The strong bindings are powerful in their universality and their characteristics are to construct a writer
whose fingers have guided the pen’s nib and traced the ink on the page; they confirm the body touched the paper that conveys the
identity. In this way, a sense of presence between writer and readers can be created which stabilizes communication and produces the
moment of transmission, when a reader can take meaning from the page as conveyed by the writer. At the distance of months in time,
thousands of miles in space and gulfs of culture between the centuries-old United Kingdom and the years- and decades-old colonial
Australia, we find a writer identified as having touched to produce a message whose readers are able to comprehend instantly through
stable and binding communicative practices.
While recognizing that what are fundamentally qualitative routines have been quantified and that this must inevitably be somewhat
crude, it is striking that various cultures of meaning repeatedly occur in letters in ways that stabilize the identity of a writer and attempt to
connect this to the identity or identities of readers. If we take these cultural practices and place them together, as they are in every
letter, with the more mute material practices, we already gain a view of communication in which writers and readers are familiar with a
range of routines and procedures that can produce simple markers of identity alongside complex enunciations of identity. To begin to
draw on this quantitative introduction, it will be useful to see letters as communication in action in three case studies, starting with the
remarkable series of letters written by Henry Howard Meyrick from colonial Victoria to his brother, sister and mother in the United
Kingdom.

Henry Howard Meyrick: 1823–47


H. H. Meyrick2 left a series of 24 letters tracing his arrival in Australia in 1840, when he was 17, travelling with one cousin (Alfred) to
Another random document with
no related content on Scribd:
The Project Gutenberg eBook of The cup; and
The falcon
This ebook is for the use of anyone anywhere in the United
States and most other parts of the world at no cost and with
almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away
or re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License
included with this ebook or online at www.gutenberg.org. If you
are not located in the United States, you will have to check the
laws of the country where you are located before using this
eBook.

Title: The cup; and The falcon

Author: Baron Alfred Tennyson Tennyson

Release date: December 4, 2023 [eBook #72318]

Language: English

Original publication: London: MacMillan and Co, 1884

Credits: Charlene Taylor and the Online Distributed


Proofreading Team at https://www.pgdp.net (This file
was produced from images generously made available
by The Internet Archive/American Libraries.)

*** START OF THE PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK THE CUP;


AND THE FALCON ***
THE CUP
AND
THE FALCON

THE CUP
AND
THE FALCON

BY
ALFRED
LORD TENNYSON
POET LAUREATE

London
MACMILLAN AND CO.
1884
THE CUP
A TRAGEDY

“The Cup” was produced at the Lyceum Theatre, under the


management of Mr. Henry Irving, January 3, 1881, with
the following cast:—
GALATIANS.

Synorix, an ex-Tetrarch Mr. Henry Irving.


Sinnatus, a Tetrarch Mr. Terris.
Attendant Mr. Harwood.
Boy Miss Brown.
Maid Miss Harwood.
Phœbe Miss Pauncefort.
Camma, wife of Sinnatus, afterwards Priestess
in the Temple of Artemis Miss Ellen Terry.

ROMANS.

Antonius, a Roman General Mr. Tyars.


Publius Mr. Hudson.
Nobleman Mr. Matheson.
Messenger Mr. Archer.

ACT I.

Scene I. —Distant View of a City of Galatia. (Afternoon.)


” II. —A Room in the Tetrarch’s House. (Evening.)
” III. —Same as Scene I. (Dawn.)

ACT II.
Scene —Interior of the Temple of Artemis.
ACT I.
Scene I.—Distant View of a City of Galatia.

As the curtain rises, Priestesses are heard singing in the Temple.


Boy discovered on a pathway among Rocks, picking grapes. A
party of Roman Soldiers, guarding a prisoner in chains, come
down the pathway and exeunt.

Enter Synorix (looking round). Singing ceases.

Synorix.

Pine, beech and plane, oak, walnut, apricot,


Vine, cypress, poplar, myrtle, bowering-in
The city where she dwells. She past me here
Three years ago when I was flying from
My Tetrarchy to Rome. I almost touch’d her—
A maiden slowly moving on to music
Among her maidens to this Temple—O Gods!
She is my fate—else wherefore has my fate
Brought me again to her own city?—married
Since—married Sinnatus, the Tetrarch here—
But if he be conspirator, Rome will chain,
Or slay him. I may trust to gain her then
When I shall have my tetrarchy restored
By Rome, our mistress, grateful that I show’d her
The weakness and the dissonance of our clans,
And how to crush them easily. Wretched race!
And once I wish’d to scourge them to the bones.
But in this narrow breathing-time of life
Is vengeance for its own sake worth the while,
If once our ends are gain’d? and now this cup—
I never felt such passion for a woman.
[Brings out a cup and scroll from
under his cloak.

What have I written to her?

[Reading the scroll.

“To the admired Camma, wife of Sinnatus, the Tetrarch, one


who years ago, himself an adorer of our great goddess, Artemis,
beheld you afar off worshipping in her Temple, and loved you for
it, sends you this cup rescued from the burning of one of her
shrines in a city thro’ which he past with the Roman army: it is
the cup we use in our marriages. Receive it from one who
cannot at present write himself other than
“A Galatian serving by force in the Roman Legion.”

[Turns and looks up to Boy.

Boy, dost thou know the house of Sinnatus?

Boy.

These grapes are for the house of Sinnatus—


Close to the Temple.

Synorix.

Yonder?

Boy.

Yes.

Synorix (aside).

That I
With all my range of women should yet shun
To meet her face to face at once! My boy,
[Boy comes down rocks to him.

Take thou this letter and this cup to Camma,


The wife of Sinnatus.

Boy.

Going or gone to-day


To hunt with Sinnatus.

Synorix.

That matters not.


Take thou this cup and leave it at her doors.

[Gives the cup and scroll to the Boy.

Boy.

I will, my lord.

[Takes his basket of grapes and exit.

Enter Antonius.

Antonius (meeting the Boy as he goes out).

Why, whither runs the boy?


Is that the cup you rescued from the fire?

Synorix.

I send it to the wife of Sinnatus,


One half besotted in religious rites.
You come here with your soldiers to enforce
The long-withholden tribute: you suspect
This Sinnatus of playing patriotism,
Which in your sense is treason. You have yet
No proof against him: now this pious cup
Is passport to their house, and open arms
To him who gave it; and once there I warrant
I worm thro’ all their windings.

Antonius.

If you prosper,
Our Senate, wearied of their tetrarchies,
Their quarrels with themselves, their spites at Rome,
Is like enough to cancel them, and throne
One king above them all, who shall be true
To the Roman: and from what I heard in Rome,
This tributary crown may fall to you.

Synorix.

The king, the crown! their talk in Rome? is it so?

[Antonius nods.

Well—I shall serve Galatia taking it,


And save her from herself, and be to Rome
More faithful than a Roman.

[Turns and sees Camma coming.

Stand aside,
Stand aside; here she comes!

[Watching Camma as she enters with


her Maid.

Camma (to Maid).

Where is he, girl?

Maid.

You know the waterfall


That in the summer keeps the mountain side,
But after rain o’erleaps a jutting rock
And shoots three hundred feet.

Camma.

The stag is there?

Maid.

Seen in the thicket at the bottom there


But yester-even.

Camma.

Good then, we will climb


The mountain opposite and watch the chase.

[They descend the rocks and exeunt.

Synorix (watching her).

(Aside.) The bust of Juno and the brows and eyes


Of Venus; face and form unmatchable!

Antonius.

Why do you look at her so lingeringly?

Synorix.

To see if years have changed her.

Antonius (sarcastically).

Love her, do you?

Synorix.
I envied Sinnatus when he married her.

Antonius.

She knows it? Ha!

Synorix.

She—no, nor ev’n my face.

Antonius.

Nor Sinnatus either?

Synorix.

No, nor Sinnatus.

Antonius.

Hot-blooded! I have heard them say in Rome,


That your own people cast you from their bounds,
For some unprincely violence to a woman,
As Rome did Tarquin.

Synorix.

Well, if this were so,


I here return like Tarquin—for a crown.

Antonius.

And may be foil’d like Tarquin, if you follow


Not the dry light of Rome’s straight-going policy,
But the fool-fire of love or lust, which well
May make you lose yourself, may even drown you
In the good regard of Rome.

Synorix.
Tut—fear me not;
I ever had my victories among women.
I am most true to Rome.

Antonius (aside).

I hate that man!


What filthy tools our Senate works with! Still
I must obey them. (Aloud.) Fare you well.

[Going.

Synorix.

Farewell!

Antonius (stopping).

A moment! If you track this Sinnatus


In any treason, I give you here an order

[Produces a paper.

To seize upon him. Let me sign it. (Signs it.) There


“Antonius leader of the Roman Legion.”

[Hands the paper to Synorix. Goes


up pathway and exit.

Synorix.

Woman again!—but I am wiser now.


No rushing on the game—the net,—the net.
[Shouts of “Sinnatus! Sinnatus!” Then horn.
Looking off stage.] He comes, a rough, bluff, simple-looking
fellow.
If we may judge the kernel by the husk,
Not one to keep a woman’s fealty when
Assailed by Craft and Love. I’ll join with him:
I may reap something from him—come upon her
Again, perhaps, to-day—her. Who are with him?
I see no face that knows me. Shall I risk it?
I am a Roman now, they dare not touch me.
I will.

Enter Sinnatus, Huntsmen and hounds.

Fair Sir, a happy day to you!


You reck but little of the Roman here,
While you can take your pastime in the woods.

Sinnatus.

Ay, ay, why not? What would you with me, man?

Synorix.

I am a life-long lover of the chase,


And tho’ a stranger fain would be allow’d
To join the hunt.

Sinnatus.

Your name?

Synorix.

Strato, my name.

Sinnatus.

No Roman name?

Synorix.

A Greek, my lord; you know


That we Galatians are both Greek and Gaul.
[Shouts and horns in the distance.

Sinnatus.

Hillo, the stag! (To Synorix.) What, you are all unfurnish’d?
Give him a bow and arrows—follow—follow.

[Exit, followed by Huntsmen.

Synorix.

Slowly but surely—till I see my way.


It is the one step in the dark beyond
Our expectation, that amazes us.

[Distant shouts and horns.

Hillo! Hillo!

[Exit Synorix. Shouts and horns.

Scene II.—A Room in the Tetrarch’s House.

Frescoed figures on the walls. Evening. Moonlight outside. A couch


with cushions on it. A small table with flagon of wine, cups, plate
of grapes, etc., also the cup of Scene I. A chair with drapery on
it.

Camma enters, and opens curtains of window.

Camma.

No Sinnatus yet—and there the rising moon.

[Takes up a cithern and sits on couch.


Plays and sings.

“Moon on the field and the foam,


Moon on the waste and the wold,
Moon bring him home, bring him home
Safe from the dark and the cold,
Home, sweet moon, bring him home,
Home with the flock to the fold—
Safe from the wolf”——

(Listening.) Is he coming? I thought I heard


A footstep. No not yet. They say that Rome
Sprang from a wolf. I fear my dear lord mixt
With some conspiracy against the wolf.
This mountain shepherd never dream’d of Rome.
(Sings.) “Safe from the wolf to the fold”——
And that great break of precipice that runs
Thro’ all the wood, where twenty years ago
Huntsman, and hound, and deer were all neck-broken!
Nay, here he comes.

Enter Sinnatus followed by Synorix.

Sinnatus (angrily).

I tell thee, my good fellow,


My arrow struck the stag.

Synorix

But was it so?


Nay, you were further off: besides the wind
Went with my arrow.

Sinnatus.

I am sure I struck him.

Synorix.

And I am just as sure, my lord, I struck him.


(Aside.) And I may strike your game when you are gone.

Camma.

Come, come, we will not quarrel about the stag.


I have had a weary day in watching you.
Yours must have been a wearier. Sit and eat,
And take a hunter’s vengeance on the meats.

Sinnatus.

No, no—we have eaten—we are heated. Wine!

Camma.

Who is our guest?

Sinnatus.

Strato he calls himself.

[Camma offers wine to Synorix, while


Sinnatus helps himself.

Sinnatus.

I pledge you, Strato.

[Drinks.

Synorix.

And I you, my lord.

[Drinks.

Sinnatus (seeing the cup sent to Camma).

What’s here?
Camma.

A strange gift sent to me to-day.


A sacred cup saved from a blazing shrine
Of our great Goddess, in some city where
Antonius past. I had believed that Rome
Made war upon the peoples not the Gods.

Synorix.

Most like the city rose against Antonius,


Whereon he fired it, and the sacred shrine
By chance was burnt along with it.

Sinnatus.

Had you then


No message with the cup?

Camma.

Why, yes, see here.

[Gives him the scroll.

Sinnatus (reads).

“To the admired Camma,—beheld you afar off—loved you—


sends you this cup—the cup we use in our marriages—cannot
at present write himself other than
“A Galatian serving by force in the Roman Legion.”

Serving by force! Were there no boughs to hang on,


Rivers to drown in? Serve by force? No force
Could make me serve by force.

Synorix.
How then, my lord?
The Roman is encampt without your city—
The force of Rome a thousand-fold our own.
Must all Galatia hang or drown himself?
And you a Prince and Tetrarch in this province——

Sinnatus.

Province!

Synorix.

Well, well, they call it so in Rome.

Sinnatus (angrily).

Province!

Synorix.

A noble anger! but Antonius


To-morrow will demand your tribute—you,
Can you make war? Have you alliances?
Bithynia, Pontus, Paphlagonia?
We have had our leagues of old with Eastern kings.
There is my hand—if such a league there be.
What will you do?

Sinnatus.

Not set myself abroach


And run my mind out to a random guest
Who join’d me in the hunt. You saw my hounds
True to the scent; and we have two-legg’d dogs
Among us who can smell a true occasion,
And when to bark and how.

Synorix.

You might also like