Textbook What Is A Mathematical Concept 1St Edition Elizabeth de Freitas Ebook All Chapter PDF
Textbook What Is A Mathematical Concept 1St Edition Elizabeth de Freitas Ebook All Chapter PDF
Textbook What Is A Mathematical Concept 1St Edition Elizabeth de Freitas Ebook All Chapter PDF
https://textbookfull.com/product/what-is-a-family-answers-from-
early-modern-japan-mary-elizabeth-berry/
https://textbookfull.com/product/new-environmentalism-managing-
new-zealand-s-environmental-diversity-1st-edition-chris-r-de-
freitas/
https://textbookfull.com/product/what-is-a-social-movement-1st-
edition-hank-johnston/
https://textbookfull.com/product/what-is-a-human-what-the-
answers-mean-for-human-rights-1st-edition-evans/
What Kinship Is And Is Not 1st Edition Marshall Sahlins
https://textbookfull.com/product/what-kinship-is-and-is-not-1st-
edition-marshall-sahlins/
https://textbookfull.com/product/the-monkey-is-the-messenger-
meditation-and-what-your-busy-mind-is-trying-to-tell-you-first-
edition-de-la-rosa/
https://textbookfull.com/product/the-happiness-effect-how-social-
media-is-driving-a-generation-to-appear-perfect-at-any-cost-1st-
edition-donna-freitas/
https://textbookfull.com/product/the-monkey-is-the-messenger-
meditation-and-what-your-busy-mind-is-trying-to-tell-you-ralph-
de-la-rosa/
https://textbookfull.com/product/mathematics-anxiety-what-is-
known-and-what-is-still-missing-1st-edition-irene-c-mammarella-
editor/
i
Responding to widespread interest within cultural studies and social inquiry, this book
addresses the question of what a mathematical concept is by using a variety of vanguard
theories in the humanities and post-humanities. Tapping into historical, philosophi-
cal, sociological and psychological perspectives, each chapter explores the question of
how mathematics comes to matter. Of interest to scholars across the usual disciplinary
divides, this book tracks mathematics as a cultural activity, drawing connections with
empirical practice. Unlike other books in this area, it is highly interdisciplinary, devoted
to exploring the ontology of mathematics as it plays out in different contexts. This book
will appeal to scholars who are interested in particular mathematical habits –creative
diagramming, structural mappings, material agency, interdisciplinary coverings –that
shed light on both mathematics and other disciplines. Chapters are also relevant to
social sciences and humanities scholars, as each one offers philosophical insight into
mathematics and how we might live mathematically.
Alf Coles’ recently published Engaging in School Mathematics: Symbols and Experiences
draws on more than 20 years of work as a teacher-researcher at both primary and secondary
levels. He is on the executive committee of the British Society for Research into Learning
Mathematics and is an active member of the Mathematics Education Special Interest Group
of the British Educational Research Association. His current interests include drawing his
work in mathematics education into closer dialogue with issues of sustainability.
ii
iii
Nathalie Sinclair
Simon Fraser University
Alf Coles
University of Bristol
iv
www.cambridge.org
Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9781107134638
DOI: 10.1017/9781316471128
© Elizabeth de Freitas, Nathalie Sinclair and Alf Coles 2017
This publication is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception
and to the provisions of relevant collective licensing agreements,
no reproduction of any part may take place without the written
permission of Cambridge University Press.
First published 2017
A catalogue record for this publication is available from the British Library.
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
Names: De Freitas, Elizabeth. | Sinclair, Nathalie. | Coles, Alf.
Title: What is a mathematical concept? / [edited by] Elizabeth de Freitas,
Manchester Metropolitan University, Nathalie Sinclair, Simon Fraser University,
Alf Coles, University of Bristol.
Description: Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2017. |
Includes bibliographical references and index.
Identifiers: LCCN 2016059487 | ISBN 9781107134638 (hard back)
Subjects: LCSH: Mathematics – Social aspects. | Mathematics – Philosophy.
Classification: LCC QA10.7.W43 2017 | DDC 510.1–dc23
LC record available at https://lccn.loc.gov/2016059487
ISBN 978-1-107-13463-8 Hardback
Cambridge University Press has no responsibility for the persistence or accuracy of URLs
for external or third-party Internet Web sites referred to in this publication and does not
guarantee that any content on such Web sites is, or will remain, accurate or appropriate.
v
Contents
Introduction 1
Part I
Part II
Part III
v
vi
vi Contents
Part IV
Part V
Part VI
Part VII
Part VIII
Index 285
vii
Images
vii
viii
ix
Notes on Contributors
ix
x
x Notes on Contributors
was adapted as a book: Being Alongside: For the Teaching and Learning of
Mathematics (2013). His research covers early number development, creativity
in learning mathematics, working on video with teachers and links between
mathematics education and sustainability education. His latest book, Engaging
in School Mathematics was published by Routledge in 2015.
David Corfield is Senior Lecturer in Philosophy at the University of
Kent. He works in the philosophy of science and mathematics and is a co-
director of the Centre for Reasoning at Kent. He is one of the three owners of
the blog The n-category Café, where the implications for philosophy, mathematics
and physics of the new language of higher-dimensional category theory are
discussed. In 2007, Corfield published Why Do People Get Ill? (co-authored with
Darian Leader), which aims to revive interest in the psychosomatic approach to
medicine.
Brent Davis is Professor and Distinguished Research Chair in Mathematics
Education in the Faculty of Education at the University of Calgary. He is the
author of two books on pedagogy and co-author of three books on learning,
teaching and research. He has served as editor of For the Learning of Mathematics
(2008–2010), co-editor of JCT: Journal of Curriculum Theorizing (1995–1999),
and founding co-editor of Complicity: An International Journal of Complexity
and Education (2004–2007).
Simon B. Duffy received a PhD in Philosophy from the University of
Sydney in 2003 after a Diplôme d’Etudes Approfondies (MPhil equivalent) in
Philosophy from the Université de Paris X-Nanterre (1999). He has taught at
the University of Sydney, the University of New South Wales and the University
of Queensland, where he was a postdoctoral fellow in Philosophy at the Centre
for the History of European Discourses. Dr Duffy is the author of Deleuze
and the History of Mathematics: In Defense of the New (2013) and The Logic
of Expression: Quality, Quantity and Intensity in Spinoza, Hegel and Deleuze
(2006). He is editor of Virtual Mathematics: The Logic of Difference (2006),
and co-editor with Sean Bowden of Badiou and Philosophy (2012). He is also
translator of Albert Lautman’s Mathematics, Ideas and the Physical Real (2011).
Elizabeth de Freitas is a professor at the Education and Social Research
Institute at Manchester Metropolitan University. She is the co- author
of Mathematics and the Body: Material Entanglements in the Classroom
(Cambridge University Press, 2014) and Alternative Theoretical Frameworks for
Mathematics Education Research: Theory meets Data (2016). Her work focuses
on the philosophy and history of mathematics and its implications for theories
xi
Notes on Contributors xi
xii
Introduction
1
2
2 Introduction
1
We have changed Bostock’s term “conceptualist” to “cognitive” better to name its focus on
mental concepts, and to avoid any confusion with how the term is used in our book.
3
Introduction 3
4 Introduction
Introduction 5
perspective today focus strongly on the role that language and tools play in
learners’ concept formation, as well as on the teacher actions that support
the process of internalization (see, for example, Mariotti, 2013).
The tendency for researchers influenced by both Piaget and Vygotsky
to focus almost exclusively on the psychological nature of concepts may
account for DiSessa and Sherin’s (1998) critique of current educational
work on concepts. In their attempt to formalise “conceptual change”, they
note that one of the main difficulties in most accounts is “the failure to
unpack what ‘the very concepts’ are in sufficiently rigorous terms” (p. 1158).
This frustration might stem in part from the fact that researchers cannot see
the schemes or structures that are posited by Piaget’s account of reflective
abstraction, or even the process of internalisation described by Vygotsky.
In the context of education research, concepts are often distinguished
from memorized facts and procedures, and often qualified in terms of mis-
conceptions and protoconceptions. Curriculum policy advocates for the
importance of conceptual understanding, and typically stipulates which
mathematical concepts are most important in teaching and learning. But
this kind of listing of key concepts offers little insight into the specific nature
of mathematical concepts and the material-historical processes associated
with them.
Recent developments in post- constructivist learning theories have
shown how concepts are performed, enacted or produced in gestures and
other material activities (Davis, 2008; Hall & Nemirovsky, 2011; Radford,
2003; Roth, 2010). This new theoretical shift draws attention to how con-
cepts are formed in the activity itself rather than in the rational cognitive
act of synthesizing (Brown, 2011; Tall, 2011). This work reflects a paradig-
matic shift in learning theory, driven in large part by offshoots of contem-
porary phenomenology, better to address the role of the body in coming to
know mathematics.
There are yet further developments on this front, developments that
build on the phenomenological tradition, and diverge from it in significant
ways. For instance, Deleuze and Guattari (1994), whose work is cited often
in this book, reanimate the concept as part of their philosophy of imma-
nence. They propose a “pedagogy of the concept”, by which concepts are to
be treated as creative devices for carving up matter, rather than pure forms
subject only to recognition. This pedagogy of the concept aims to encoun-
ter and engage with the conceptual on the material plane; a concept brings
with it an entire “plane of immanence” (Cutler & MacKenzie, 2011, p. 64).
For Stengers (2005), Deleuze’s pedagogy is about learning “the ‘taste’ of con-
cepts, being modified by the encounter with concepts” (p. 162). de Freitas
6
6 Introduction
Introduction 7
which such claims might be misleading. The first relates to what we might
call frequency of use. Netz shows several examples of a concept existing in
a certain culture without it becoming widespread or frequently used. The
second, perhaps more interesting to mathematicians, relates to conceptual
hierarchy. By showing persuasively how Archimedes used the concept of
actual infinity, Netz troubles common assumptions that the concept of
actual infinity depends on the concept of set. As Barany’s meaning finitism
would make evident, the particular ways in which knowledge is classified
(ordered, related) is highly contingent and cannot be assumed to play out
in the same way in different historical periods and different geographical
locations. Indeed, Netz highlights how different mathematical practices give
rise to different concepts.
The next two chapters continue to look at the material practices of math-
ematical activity, exploring how mathematical concepts live through various
media. Juliette Kennedy examines the role of visualization and diagramming
in mathematics, and asks whether some mathematical concepts are irreduc-
ibly visual. She focuses on the role of these informal “co-exact” characteris-
tics of mathematical drawing for the part they play in logical inference, first
tracking the historical separation of the visual from the logical. The chapter
by Elizabeth de Freitas and Nathalie Sinclair attends to the historical division
between logic and mathematics in a related way, looking at the concept of the
mathematical continuum, to show that number and line are mathematical
concepts which are the source of persistent philosophical questions about
space, time and mobility. Just as Kennedy talks about the “bidirectionality”
of mathematical practice (between body and symbol) and the “ambivalence”
entailed in mathematical positioning, de Freitas and Sinclair suggest that
mathematical concepts are always rumbling beneath the apparent foun-
dations of mathematical truth. They draw on the ideas of Gilles Châtelet
and Ian Hacking to show how concepts thrive through material media and
historical material arrangements. These two chapters challenge readers to
reconsider the way that proof and reasoning is at play in mathematics.
Kennedy first distinguishes between drawings that are directly consti-
tutive of a mathematical proof and others that are informal, “incidental”
aspects of mathematical activity, discussing how both kinds function fruit-
fully in mathematics. She discusses “world-involving inference” and logical
inference, seeking a middle synthetic ground where mixtures of reason-
ing operate. Drawing on the reflections of the architect Juhani Pallasmaa
about “the thinking hand”, Kennedy argues that the manual activity of
mathematical drawing must be considered as we ask the question: What
is a mathematical concept? Mathematicians move around a mathematical
8
8 Introduction
diagram much like one might move around a building, and it is through
this habitation and spatial practice that the concepts become known. This
chapter also links to that by Nemirovsky, who describes how one comes to
inhabit a concept over time, through habitual carving out of its contour and
meaning.
The chapter by de Freitas and Sinclair continues the theme that Kennedy
opens, regarding the relationship between the logical and the mathematical.
They cite Hacking (2014), who argues that the connection between symbolic
logic and mathematics “simply did not exist” until the logicist movement
of the nineteenth century (advocated by Frege, above all), which aimed to
reduce mathematics to logic, and replaced Aristotelian logic with what was
termed “symbolic logic” (p. 137). This chapter proposes the term “virtual”
to describe the indeterminate dimension in matter that literally destabi-
lizes the rigidity of extension. They suggest that concepts such as line, point
and circle can be conceived using a genetic definition that emphasizes the
dynamic and mobile aspects of mathematical concepts. Concepts –such
as squareness, fiveness, etc. –thus retain the trace of the movement of the
eye, hand and thinking body. This chapter is linked to the one by Netz, as
they both present images of mathematical practice as an applied or prac-
tical affair, grounded in material conditions and experiments rather than
exclusive appeals to logic.
Chapters by Arkady Plotnitsky and Simon Duffy explore the ways in
which mathematical concepts spring from and sustain rich problem spaces.
They both draw on the powerful ideas of Gilles Deleuze and Felix Guattari
to develop a theory of mathematical concepts, and then show its relevance
to other discourses. Deleuze, in particular, offered deep insights into the
history of mathematics, tapping particular ideas –from Galois, Riemann,
Poincaré, Lautman and others –to rethink the relationship between con-
cepts and problems. We see in Plotnitsky and Duffy’s chapters a theoreti-
cal move that explores the speculative position of a “mathesis universalis”
(Deleuze, 1994, p. 181), but not one that posits a definite system of math-
ematical laws at the base of nature. Rather, these two chapters delve into
the mathematical concept as that which operates through a rich dynamic
ontology of problems that are in some way shared with other discourses
and contexts.
Plotnitsky explores the contributions of Bernhardt Riemann around
non-Euclidean geometry, also drawing on the insights of Deleuze. Riemann’s
work is known as a conceptual rather than axiomatic approach to exploring
non-Euclidean geometries. Plotnitsky uses the work of Riemann to show
that a mathematical concept (1) emerges from the co-operative confrontation
9
Introduction 9
10 Introduction
Harris refuses to offer criteria for what makes a concept “good”, he draws
attention to the many social and historical factors –such as the connection
to Grothendieck and perhaps even the endearing personality of Scholze –
that converged to make the perfectoid the ‘right’ concept for solving a set of
diverse mathematical problems. He chronicles the way in which the perfec-
toid concept was put to work extensively by Scholze and others, almost like
a kind of mutant offspring of current theories. This suggests that the appli-
cability of a concept (where the application is across mathematics, rather
than outside of mathematics), is a highly generative process whereby new
practices emerge that change the entire field.
Similarly, Corfield provides a compelling argument for the “goodness”
of homotopy type theory, which has developed a strong footing in the past
decade. Corfield describes how this theory, and type theory more generally,
exploits the vertical unity of mathematics. Such unity entails consistency
demands, but perhaps also points to uncharted pedagogical terrain. There
are some important nuances to keep in mind, which Corfield highlights in his
discussion of Mark Wilson’s insistence on the “wandering” nature of concepts
and his warning that “hazy holism” can often misleadingly lead us to believe
in the unity of concepts, which are more often than not “patched together
from varied parts” (p. 129). The very practice of patching becomes pivotal to
Corfield’s considerations of the ‘spatial’ nature of homotopy type theory.
Thus we might also see the vertical unity as arising from a patching together
of different kinds of mathematical practices, much as we saw in Harris’ chap-
ter. That strong analogies can be seen across basic arithmetic and homotopy
is convincingly and carefully shown by Corfield, but one look at the syntactic
complexity required to “express” addition or inverse in homotopy type theory
is enough to remind us that these are not the same concepts. We are reminded
of Thurston’s (1994) description of the different ways of thinking about the
derivative. While the differences may “start to evaporate as soon as the mental
concepts are translated into precise, formal and explicit definitions” (p. 3), they
are much more real in the particular contexts in which they are actually used.
Staying close to particular practices –rather than erasing those differences
within a reductive set theory –allows Corfield to seek out other important
“unities” across other concepts, such as formal and concrete duality.
The notion of vertical unity seems to us an interesting one for math-
ematics education, for how it troubles conventions about developmental
conceptual change and curriculum. School mathematics has long been
considered an edifice whose stairway must be climbed one step at a time.
Vertical unity brings about some different imagery: express elevators,
the possibility of starting at the penthouse of homotopy type theory, a
11
Introduction 11
12 Introduction
Introduction 13
14 Introduction
References
Bostock, D. (2009). The philosophy of mathematics: An introduction. New York: Wiley
Blackwell.
Brainerd, C. (1979). The origins of the number concept. New York: Praeger Publishers.
Brown, J. R. (2008). Philosophy of mathematics: A contemporary introduction to the
world of proofs and pictures (2nd Ed.). New York: Routledge.
Brown, L. (2011). What is a concept? For the Learning of Mathematics, 31(2), 15–17.
Cutler, A., & MacKenzie, I. (2011). Bodies of learning. In L. Guillaume & J. Hughes
(Eds.), Deleuze and the body (pp. 53–72). Edinburgh: Edinburgh University
Press.
Davis, B. (2008). Is 1 a prime number? Developing teacher knowledge through con-
cept study. Mathematics Teaching in the Middle School (NCTM), 14(2), 86–91.
de Freitas, E., & Sinclair, N. (2014). Mathematics and the body: Material entangle-
ments in the classroom. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Deleuze, G. (1994). Difference and repetition, trans. P. Patton. London: Athlone.
15
Introduction 15
{656}
"We favor the reduction and speedy repeal of the war taxes,
and a return to the time-honored Democratic policy of strict
economy in governmental expenditures.
"This currency law destroys the full money power of the silver
dollar, provides for the payment of all government obligations
and the redemption of all forms of paper money in gold alone;
retires the time-honored and patriotic greenbacks,
constituting one-sixth of the money in circulation, and
surrenders to banking corporations a sovereign function of
issuing all paper money, thus enabling these corporations to
control the prices of labor and property by increasing or
diminishing the volume of money in circulation, thus giving
the banks power to create panics and bring disaster upon
business enterprises. The provisions of this currency law
making the bonded debt of the Republic payable in gold alone
change the contract between the Government and the bondholders
to the advantage of the latter, and is in direct opposition to
the declaration of the Matthews resolution passed by Congress
in 1878, for which resolution the present Republican
President, then a member of Congress, voted, as did also all
leading Republicans, both in the House and Senate. We declare
it to be our intention to lend our efforts to the repeal of
this currency law, which not only repudiates the ancient and
time-honored principles of the American people before the
Constitution was adopted, but is violative of the principles
of the Constitution itself, and we shall not cease our efforts
until there has been established in its place a monetary
system based upon the free and unlimited coinage of silver and
gold into money at the present legal ratio of 16 to 1 by the
independent action of the United States, under which system
all paper money shall be issued by the Government and all such
money coined or issued shall be a full legal tender in payment
of all debts, public and private, without exception.
{657}
"We favor the immediate admission into the union of States the
Territories of Arizona, New Mexico, and Oklahoma.
{658}
"Until now the policy which has turned the Filipinos from warm
friends to bitter enemies, which has slaughtered thousands of
them and laid waste their country, has been the policy of the
President. After the next election it becomes the policy of
every man who votes to re-elect him and who thus becomes with
him responsible for every drop of blood thereafter shed.
{659}
{660}
"Tenth—Equal civil and political rights for men and women, and
the abolition of all laws discriminating against women.
The canvass preceding the election was much less excited than
that of 1896. The confusion of issues greatly lessened the
intensity with which they were discussed. Mr. Bryan again took
the field in person, travelling widely through all parts of
the country, making great numbers of speeches to immense
audiences everywhere; and Governor Roosevelt did the same on
the Republican side, to a somewhat less extent.
Total, 292.
Total, 155.
"(1) Many men of each party abstained from voting, for the
total was only 45,132 greater than in 1896, whereas the
increase in population adds about a million to the electorate
every four years. The total vote last year was 13,970,234. Mr.
McKinley received only about 100,000 more than in 1896, and
Mr. Bryan 130,000 less. Many men in each party, then, were
dissatisfied with their candidate and platform.