Hume On The Self and Personal Identity Dan Obrien Full Chapter PDF
Hume On The Self and Personal Identity Dan Obrien Full Chapter PDF
Hume On The Self and Personal Identity Dan Obrien Full Chapter PDF
Dan O'Brien
Visit to download the full and correct content document:
https://ebookmass.com/product/hume-on-the-self-and-personal-identity-dan-obrien/
More products digital (pdf, epub, mobi) instant
download maybe you interests ...
https://ebookmass.com/product/locke-on-persons-and-personal-
identity-ruth-boeker/
https://ebookmass.com/product/the-developmental-psychology-of-
personal-identity-massimo-marraffa/
https://ebookmass.com/product/self-and-identity-trenton-merricks/
https://ebookmass.com/product/complex-systems-and-clouds-a-self-
organization-and-self-management-perspective-1st-edition-dan-c-
marinescu/
Vicarious Identity in International Relations: Self,
Security, and Status on the Global Stage 1st Edition
Christopher S. Browning
https://ebookmass.com/product/vicarious-identity-in-
international-relations-self-security-and-status-on-the-global-
stage-1st-edition-christopher-s-browning/
https://ebookmass.com/product/on-being-ones-self-clinical-
explorations-in-identity-from-john-steiners-workshop-sharon-numa/
https://ebookmass.com/product/what-matters-in-survival-personal-
identity-and-other-possibilities-1st-edition-douglas-ehring/
https://ebookmass.com/product/ethnographic-research-and-analysis-
anxiety-identity-and-self-1st-edition-tom-vine/
https://ebookmass.com/product/on-the-self-discourses-of-mental-
health-and-education-julie-allan/
PHILOSOPHERS IN DEPTH
Series Editor
Constantine Sandis
Department of Philosophy
University of Hertfordshire
Hatfield, UK
Philosophers in Depth is a series of themed edited collections focusing
on particular aspects of the thought of major figures from the history of
philosophy. The volumes showcase a combination of newly commis-
sioned and previously published work with the aim of deepening our
understanding of the topics covered. Each book stands alone, but taken
together the series will amount to a vast collection of critical essays cov-
ering the history of philosophy, exploring issues that are central to the
ideas of individual philosophers. This project was launched with the
financial support of the Institute for Historical and Cultural Research at
Oxford Brookes University, for which we are very grateful.
Constantine Sandis
Dan O’Brien
Editor
© The Editor(s) (if applicable) and The Author(s), under exclusive licence to Springer Nature
Switzerland AG 2022
This work is subject to copyright. All rights are solely and exclusively licensed by the Publisher, whether
the whole or part of the material is concerned, specifically the rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of
illustrations, recitation, broadcasting, reproduction on microfilms or in any other physical way, and trans-
mission or information storage and retrieval, electronic adaptation, computer software, or by similar or
dissimilar methodology now known or hereafter developed.
The use of general descriptive names, registered names, trademarks, service marks, etc. in this publication
does not imply, even in the absence of a specific statement, that such names are exempt from the relevant
protective laws and regulations and therefore free for general use.
The publisher, the authors and the editors are safe to assume that the advice and information in this book
are believed to be true and accurate at the date of publication. Neither the publisher nor the authors or
the editors give a warranty, expressed or implied, with respect to the material contained herein or for any
errors or omissions that may have been made. The publisher remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional
claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.
This Palgrave Macmillan imprint is published by the registered company Springer Nature Switzerland AG.
The registered company address is: Gewerbestrasse 11, 6330 Cham, Switzerland
All the fives crock Henrietta
She’s a mean go-getter
Gotta write her a letter…
Reference Conventions for Hume’s Works
vii
Acknowledgements
ix
Contents
1 How
Sceptical Is Hume’s Theory of Personal Identity? 3
Andrew Ward
2 H
ume’s Bundle 21
Donald C. Ainslie
3 W
hat I Call Myself 47
Galen Strawson
4 Hume
and Kames on the Self and Personal Identity 85
Josef Moural
5 Character
Development in Shaftesbury’s and Hume’s
Approaches to Self107
Ruth Boeker
xi
xii Contents
6 Sympathy,
Self and Others131
Dan O’Brien
7 ‘Scottish
Sympathy’: Hume, Smith, and Psychoanalysis153
Louise Braddock
8 What
Is Humean Autonomy?177
Anik Waldow
9 A
Fragmented Unity: A Narrative Answer to the Problem
of the Unity of the Self in Hume201
Lorenzo Greco
10 Candrakīrti
and Hume on the Self and the Person225
Jay L. Garfield
11 Husserl
(and Brentano) on Hume’s Notion of the Self251
Hynek Janoušek
12 Disguising
Change: Hume and Cognitive Science on the
Continued Existence of Selves275
Mark Collier
B
ibliography295
I ndex313
Notes on Contributors
xiii
xiv Notes on Contributors
earlier account of the self and, ever since, much ink, toner and pencil lead
have been spent attempting to work out why he was dissatisfied. This is
far from clear, and it’s one of the questions that the papers in Part I
address.
Andrew Ward argues, at odds with the standard interpretation, that
the Appendix does not express Hume’s dissatisfaction with the bundle
theory or with his scepticism concerning personal identity. The Appendix,
rather, is designed to clarify and strengthen Hume’s scepticism: after pub-
lishing the Treatise Hume realises that there is not only no introspectable
evidence for realist accounts of personal identity, but that such accounts
are self-contradictory. This is the message of the Appendix.
Don Ainslie turns to the bundle problem. Hume identifies the mind
with a bundle of perceptions and claims that our belief in its unity and
identity across time is generated solely by the imagination (as is the case
with pencils and pumpkins). One influential interpretation of the
Appendix is that Hume came to recognize that he is unable to explain
how perceptions come together in a bundle. Why is this particular set of
perceptions bundled together into me, and another set bundled together
into you? Why is this experience of seeing red in my bundle and not in
yours? Ainslie argues, however, that Hume did not recognize a bundling
problem since his empiricism allows him to accept such bundles as
brute facts.
Galen Strawson agrees that Hume is not concerned with the bundle
problem. Hume is too much of a sceptic to make any metaphysical claims
concerning the constitution of the mind. A bundle of perceptions may be
the only empirically respectable account of the mind, but its true meta-
physical nature is unknown. Strawson also rejects the no-self interpreta-
tion. Selves cannot be purged from the bundle of perceptions because it’s
a necessary truth that perceptions must be had by perceivers. It’s therefore
perceivings-by-perceivers that are bundled together in experience and not
mere standalone perceptions. Hume’s scepticism, though, means that the
nature of these perceivers or selves is hidden from view: there may, for all
we know, be a series of short-lived selves, or perhaps all perceptions may
be perceived by the same enduring self.
Part I closes with Josef Moural’s suggestion that new light may be cast
on the Appendix by considering Henry Home’s criticisms of the Treatise.
xxii Introduction
The Appendix deals mainly with two topics—the nature of belief and
personal identity—and Home (later to be Lord Kames) published essays
on both. Moural investigates Hume’s intriguing comment in a letter to
Home that ‘I lik’t exceedingly your Method of explaining personal iden-
tity as more satisfactory than any thing that had ever occur’d to me’.
The papers in Part II turn to Hume’s treatment of the self in Books 2
and 3 of the Treatise. There he moves away from consideration of a simple
self—that we (falsely) believe remains identical across time—to the more
complex ideas we have of our ever-changing, flesh and blood selves, those
with emotional lives, character traits of which we may be proud or
ashamed, practical goals, and social relations with others.
Ruth Boeker examines the role that character development plays in
Shaftesbury’s and Hume’s approaches to self. Shaftesbury offers a devel-
opmental approach to self that aims at character development and self-
improvement, and in Books 2 and 3 of the Treatise, perhaps influenced
by Shaftesbury, Hume recognizes the importance of developing stable
character traits which contribute to the formation of selves. There are,
though, differences in how they understand character development and
selfhood: Shaftesbury’s view involves intellectual reflection, whereas
Hume’s approach is closely intertwined with his account of sympathy
and how we are deeply embedded in our social community.
Dan O’Brien focuses on the role that sympathy plays in Hume’s
account of how we come to share the emotions and thoughts of others,
and how it is involved in our coming to have a sense of ourselves as per-
sons. We are praised by others for our virtues, achievements and standing
in society (and criticized for our vices and shortcomings), and this leads
to our feeling proud (or ashamed). Such passions are self-directed and
Hume’s account of the generation of these passions is in turn an account
of how we come to conceive of and experience our selves. We feel the
approval of others via sympathy, and the proud self that I am now—will,
in turn, go on to sympathize with future approval (or disapproval) of my
life and actions. My existence is constituted by a spiral of self-creation
into the future, constantly fed by the reactions of others.
Louise Braddock also focuses on sympathy—’Scottish sympathy’; that
which plays a central role in the philosophies of Hume and Adam Smith.
She argues that this is an important philosophical resource for
Introduction xxiii
A. Ward (*)
University of York, York, UK
e-mail: [email protected]
© The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2022 3
D. O’Brien (ed.), Hume on the Self and Personal Identity, Philosophers in Depth,
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-04275-1_1
4 A. Ward
I
What is Hume’s bundle theory? It is the view that the identity of the self
consists in—or, at any rate, can only be known to consist in—a series of
conscious states (or ‘perceptions’, as he calls them) with nothing genu-
inely unifying the serial perceptions. Of course, Hume acknowledges that
we believe that all the perceptions of that series, which each of us calls his
or her own, do belong to a single self, mind, or person (he uses these three
terms interchangeably). But this belief, he holds, lacks any justification
and results merely from the way in which the disparate perceptions are
felt to be unified when we reflect on them in the memory.
In the Treatise section entitled ‘Of personal identity’, Hume attacks
two realist accounts of personal identity, not one as it is sometimes main-
tained. He first attacks a substance (or Cartesian) account, according to
which our identity is constituted by the continuous existence of a sub-
stance that underlies the whole series of perceptions. He does not, how-
ever, stop there; for he also attacks a real connection account, according
to which our identity is secured by connections that hold between the
serial perceptions. His attack on both accounts is very similar and comes
down to the claim that, when we examine the series of perceptions
(through recollecting them in memory), all we can ever discover is a suc-
cession of perceptions which, although their ideas feel unified in the
memory, are not found to have anything underlying or really connect-
ing them.
Accordingly, after having rejected the substance account─on the
grounds that all our perceptions are distinct and separable
existences─Hume allows that the ascription of identity to the mind
would still be warranted provided there was something really connecting
or binding these distinct perceptions together:
As Hume notes, with plants and animal bodies, we accept that, over
time, the form as well as the substance making them up can undergo a
total change (through growth, decay, and replacement). But while, in
such cases, ‘we do not give rise to such a fiction [as that of a common
substance of inhesion]…we are apt to imagine something unknown and
mysterious, connecting the parts…and this I take to be the case with the
identity we ascribe to plants and vegetables’ (T 1.4.6.6). So, as Hume sees
it, when identity is not ascribed on the basis of a belief in a common
substance of inhesion, we may still be drawn to ascribing identity to an
object because of a belief in something that is really connecting the
object’s parts together—and this is precisely what occurs in the case of
our ascription of identity to plants and animal bodies. Yet, although we
believe that there really is something connecting the changing parts of
such organisms, all that is observable is a succession of varying parts
together with the association of their ideas in our imagination. That is
why Hume thinks that the identity we ascribe to organisms is fictitious
and that is why, analogously, he thinks that our ascription of identity to
the mind or person is equally fictitious:
6 A. Ward
The identity, which we ascribe to the mind of man, is only a fictitious one,
and of a like kind with that which we ascribe to vegetables and animal bod-
ies. (T 1.4.6.15)
Despite drawing these analogies between the mind and certain organ-
isms, it is not easy to decide which view of the self Hume does ascribe to
us. Thus, when he first discusses how it is we come to ascribe identity to
the succession of perceptions, he says that ‘we’ feign ‘a soul, and self, and
substance’ to disguise the variations in our perceptions (T 1.4.6.6): appar-
ently suggesting, therefore, that we naturally believe in a substance view
of the self ’s identity. Yet, as I have just indicated, Hume also maintains
that ‘the identity we ascribe to the mind…is of a like kind to that which
we ascribe to plants and vegetables’—which is the ascription of ‘some-
thing unknown and mysterious, connecting the parts’. And there are sev-
eral other references in the section to the analogy between the mind’s
supposed identity and that of plants and animal bodies. On balance, I am
inclined to think that Hume supposes that some of us do accept a sub-
stance view, while others, especially those who have been influenced by
John Locke’s analogy of the identity of a person with that of plants and
animal bodies,1 are drawn to a real connection view. The essential point,
however, is that Hume holds that both views are unwarranted.
In short, the position that Hume is arguing for in the main body of the
Treatise is intended to be a thoroughly sceptical one. Personal identity
would be secured if there were either a substance in which all the serial
perceptions inhere (the Cartesian view) or a real connection coming
between each successive perception (as we suppose the changing parts of
plants and animals are really connected). Since, however, neither is dis-
coverable, we lack any justification for the belief in our own identity.
II
At the same time, given Hume is in no doubt that, in our daily lives, we
do believe in the identity of the self, he needs to produce a convincing
psychological story of the generation of our belief, and one that does not
presuppose the continued existence of the self. Many have doubted that
1 How Sceptical Is Hume’s Theory of Personal Identity? 7
III
Although I have maintained that Hume’s psychological explanation of
the genesis of belief in personal identity fits into his theory of the associa-
tion of ideas, it may seem open to the objection that it cannot be employed
in defence of a sceptical account of personal identity. For, it may be urged,
his psychological story, relying as it does on memory, must presuppose
the existence of a continuously existing mind (first to lay down traces
deriving from the original succession of perceptions and, later, to bring
the stored traces to consciousness as memory-impressions). Without such
a continuant, the a priori probability of a series of memory-impressions
matching an original succession of perceptions would be extremely low;
whereas, by presupposing such a continuant, this matching is entirely
unsurprising. Hence, the objection concludes, Hume cannot reasonably
remain sceptical about personal identity, given his own psychological
story of the generation of belief in that identity.4 There is a further, related
objection which runs as follows. On Hume’s version of empiricism, there
is no way in which he could presuppose a continuously existing mind. To
do so, he would have to appeal to an idea which, by his own lights, he
could not conceivably have. Since Hume affirms that there are no rele-
vant impressions from which the alleged idea answering to the term ‘a
continuously existing mind’ can be derived, that term must be dismissed
by him as without descriptive meaning. Consequently, he has ruled out
any determinate reference to the very resource which would have enabled
him to explain how his principles of association, and thereby his psycho-
logical story of the generation of our belief in personal identity, could
possibly come into play.5
Despite their plausibility, both objections fail. To see why, let us con-
sider the first objection. It is true that Hume, like the realist, is taking for
granted that memory-impressions will (generally) be an accurate repre-
sentation of earlier perceptions; for both parties agree that it is by using
memory that we come to the belief in our continuous existence. However,
even on the assumption that there is a continuously existing mind, in
which traces deriving from the original perceptions are laid down and
stored, the a priori probability that the resultant memory-impressions
10 A. Ward
will match the earlier perceptions is no greater than the a priori probabil-
ity that, if there is no such continuant between the original past percep-
tions and the later memory-impressions, these impressions will match the
earlier perceptions. Either way, the a priori probability of a match between
the original perceptions and the later memory-impressions is correspond-
ingly small. It is correspondingly small because, a priori, there are just as
many ways in which memory traces might, accurately or inaccurately, be
laid down and stored in the mind as there are ways in which, without any
continuously existing mind, the later memory-impressions might, accu-
rately or inaccurately, resemble the original perceptions. There is, conse-
quently, nothing to favour the realist’s claim that, on the evidence, we
have good reason to accept a continuously existing mind rather than a
mere series of discrete perceptions. After all, the only datum both sides
have to go on is that belief in the self ’s identity arises from our reflecting
on memory-impressions as they pass smoothly through consciousness
(and which are taken to be accurate representations of earlier percep-
tions). And this datum is as consistent with the non-existence as with the
existence of a continuously existing mind.
Of course, if it is assumed that, on the supposition of a continuously
existing mind, the memory-impressions are bound to match the contents
of the earlier perceptions, it would be more reasonable to believe in a
continuously existing mind rather than a mere series of perceptions. It
would be more reasonable because, without the existence of such a mind,
the a priori probability of the memory-impressions matching the earlier
perceptions is exceedingly low; whereas, if there is a continuously existing
mind—which, ex hypothesis, is accurately laying down and reliably stor-
ing traces of the earlier succession—the matching of memory-impressions
with original perceptions is precisely what one would expect. However,
on the evidence available, there is no more reason to suppose that, if there
is a continuously existing mind, the way in which the traces have been
laid down and stored will enable the later memory-impressions to match
the original perceptions than there is reason to suppose that, without a
continuously existing mind, the later memory-impressions will match
the original perceptions. In both cases, the a priori probability is equally
low. Hence, the fact that the memory-impressions do match the original
perceptions (as both parties are taking for granted) does not favour the
1 How Sceptical Is Hume’s Theory of Personal Identity? 11
IV
Before turning to my own view of why Hume wrote the Appendix on
personal identity, I will briefly consider one further attempt to explain
Hume’s misgivings about his original discussion.
Hume, it is alleged, became dissatisfied because his psychological
explanation of the belief in personal identity already requires perceptions
to be placed into separate bundles. The idea is that, for the belief to be
generated, Hume needs to presume that, out of all the mass of percep-
tions that exist, the only perceptions to which we each have access are
those that we come to think of as belonging to or constituting our own
mind. And, for this to be possible, the perceptions we ascribe to our mind
must, from the outset, be partitioned from the mass of other perceptions.
What, on this criticism, Hume is acknowledging (and bemoaning) in the
Appendix is just this realist requirement, viz. that the mass of perceptions
must be parceled into individual bundles before his psychological mecha-
nism can produce the belief that the perceptions of any given bundle are
unified. The requirement is problematic for him because he cannot accept
any principle of connection that could provide the necessary parceling;
hence, his attempt to explain the belief in personal identity must fail.6
Not only is there, as far as I can see, no explicit evidence to suggest that
Hume is worried by his alleged failure to restrict the range of perceptions
12 A. Ward
to those that we do in fact call our own, there is strong evidence that this
would not be a source of worry to him. For, in the earlier section of Book
1, Part 4 of the Treatise, ‘Of scepticism with regard to the senses’ (T 1.4.2),
and, again, in the concluding section, ‘Conclusion of this book’ (T 1.4.7),
Hume takes it that the belief in personal identity arises logically prior to
any belief in external objects, let alone to any belief in the existence
of other centres of consciousness (which would be inferred from the
behaviour of certain of these external objects). He does not begin with a
large mass of perceptions (only some of which make up the bundle which
we come to believe belongs to or constitutes our own mind). If that were
his starting point, there might, indeed, be a question of why or how some
perceptions of this mass are divided from the rest, i.e. are bundled
together.
Instead, according to Hume’s sceptical strategy in Part 4 of Book 1 of
the Treatise, all that can be taken initially to exist is that succession of
perceptions which we come to believe, albeit illegitimately, belongs to or
constitutes a single, continuously existing, self or mind. Once this belief
has been formed, we go on to believe (again, without legitimate ground)
in the existence of external objects by ‘breaking off’ certain of these per-
ceptions from the mind and supposing them to have a continuous and
distinct existence from the mind (see ‘Of scepticism with regard to the
senses’; T 1.4.2). Following production of the belief in external objects,
the mind can then, on the basis of behaviour, seek to infer (legitimately
or not) the existence of further centres of consciousness associated with
certain external objects (human and animal bodies). The belief in the
existence of these other centres of consciousness is entirely dependent on
the belief in external objects. It is no part of Hume’s strategy to take it as
a given that there is a mass of perceptions, over and above that succession
that we believe belongs to or constitutes one continuously existing mind.
Far from it: we are only able to form the belief in other centres of con-
sciousness when they are inferred from, and tied to, certain external
objects. In fact, the very idea of our own mind, together with that of other
minds, can only be formed once we have come to believe in external
objects and inferred the existence of further centres of consciousness from
the behaviour of some of these external objects.
1 How Sceptical Is Hume’s Theory of Personal Identity? 13
V
But if none of these objections explain Hume’s expressed dissatisfaction
with the original section on personal identity, what grounds could he
have had for later composing an Appendix to that section?
The point of the Appendix is not to indicate any inherent difficulty
with his bundle theory. It is, to the contrary, aiming to do two things.
First, to reiterate briefly and clearly the grounds for his rejection of both
the realist accounts he had discussed in the main body of the Treatise: that
is, not only a substance (or Cartesian) account of the self but, also, a real
connection account, according to which the serial members of the origi-
nal succession of perceptions are taken to be really connected amongst
themselves (analogous to the way we suppose that the changing parts of
plants and animal bodies are so connected). Why should Hume wish to
provide a summary of these grounds? Because when, at the end of the
section on personal identity, he considers how it comes about that we
believe the succession of perceptions to be united by identity, despite
there being no justification for supposing that the succession inheres in a
common substance, his words and analogies can readily be misconstrued
as suggesting that he thinks the successive perceptions really are con-
nected or tied together. The second aim of the Appendix is to reveal—
what he had formerly not recognized himself—that he has the materials
to hand for concluding that it must be self-contradictory to attempt to
defend either of these two realist accounts and not merely, as he had, in
reality, formerly held, that there is insufficient evidence for justifying
either of them. So understood, the Appendix seeks to clarify and
strengthen his sceptical position, not to weaken or reject it.
14 A. Ward
As memory alone acquaints us with the continuance and extent of this suc-
cession of perceptions, ’tis to be considered, upon that account chiefly, as
the source of personal identity. Had we no memory, we never should have
any notion of causation, nor consequently of that chain of causes and
effects, which constitute our self or person. (T 1.4.6.20)
In this respect, I cannot compare the soul more properly to anything than
to a republic or commonwealth, in which the several members are united
by the reciprocal ties of government and subordination, and give rise to
other persons, who propagate the same republic in the incessant changes of
its parts. (T 1.4.6.19)
we ‘suppose’ (n.b.) that their various parts ‘bear to each other, the recipro-
cal relations of cause and effect in all their actions and operations’ (T
1.4.6.12). For Hume, we can no more really discover ‘reciprocal ties’
between the parts of a commonwealth or republic than we can discover
‘reciprocal relations of cause and effect’ between the parts of a vegetable
or animal body. Yet, it looks as if, by employing the analogy of a republic
or commonwealth, Hume is contending that the human mind does truly
form a whole: not, of course, because its serial perceptions inhere in a
common substance, but because they bear among themselves the recipro-
cal ties of cause and effect, and in a parallel way to how a republic or
commonwealth forms a whole because its changing members ‘are united
by the reciprocal ties of government and subordination’. However, by
employing the analogy of a republic or commonwealth, Hume cannot be
intending to imply that the human mind is genuinely united by means of
the reciprocal ties of cause and effect. His point, with regard to the earlier
analogy of plants and vegetables, on the one hand, and the later analogy
of a republic or commonwealth, on the other, must be that, on the avail-
able evidence, we are mistaken in supposing that the changing parts of
these phenomena are connected by any reciprocal ties of cause and effect.
Remember that, earlier, Hume had said that the identity we ascribe to
vegetables and animal bodies is a fiction; and if that ascription is a fiction,
so too must be the identity we ascribe to a republic or commonwealth
(since the ascription, in both cases, is made on the same ground). Far
from the analogy of a republic or commonwealth corroborating any gen-
uine connections, ties, or links between our serial perceptions, its inten-
tion, like the analogy with vegetables and animal bodies, is to point out
how such supposed connections are unjustifiably ascribed in other cases
too. But, owing to the smoothness with which their changing parts are
felt to pass through memory, we are beguiled into believing in the exis-
tence of reciprocal causal connections in the case of both these analogies
just as we are beguiled, by the ‘smooth and uninterrupted progress’ of the
succession of perceptions in the memory, into believing in the existence
of reciprocal causal connections between the succession of perceptions
themselves.
In sum, what I am suggesting is that in the section ‘Of personal iden-
tity’, Hume starts by attacking both a substance (or Cartesian) account
1 How Sceptical Is Hume’s Theory of Personal Identity? 17
question in the face of the difficulties Hume has uncovered. Still, I doubt
whether this consideration is foremost in his thought if it is present at all.
Rather, I take his closing comment to be, first and foremost, a piece of
Humean irony. To engage in more mature reflection requires a further act
of consciousness; and so, on Hume’s own theory, the person currently
reflecting cannot be the same person—or, at least, cannot be known to be
the same person—who will be giving the matter more mature consider-
ation. By his own theory, therefore, neither I myself nor anyone else,
presently existing, will be around—or, anyhow, can be known to be
around—to consider, whether with greater maturity or not, the problem
of personal identity.
Notes
1. Locke (1975, 2.27 [‘Of Identity and Diversity’], sections 4, 5, and 10).
This chapter was first published in the second edition (1794).
2. Strictly, what Hume here refers to as ‘impressions of the memory’ are
ideas; but owing (in general) to their greater force and liveliness than the
ideas of the imagination, he often terms them ‘impressions’ (see
T. 1.1.3, 1.3.5).
3. See (T 1.4.6.6, 22). Cf. ‘Of the ancient philosophy’ (T 1.4.4.2–4) where
a parallel account is offered of belief in material substance.
4. For a clear statement of this well-known objection, see Mackie (1976,
200–201).
5. See Strawson (2011, 2012).
6. Among those who have argued along these lines, see especially Stroud
(1977, 118–40) and Garrett (2011).
7. The general point at issue here is summed up in a very clear passage in his
later Enquiry concerning human understanding: ‘The first time a man saw
the communication of motion by impulse, as by the shock of two billiard
balls, he could not pronounce that the one event was connected: but only
that it was conjoined with the other. After he has observed several instances
of this nature, he then pronounces them to be connected. What alteration
has happened to give rise to this new idea of connexion? Nothing but that
he now feels these events to be connected in his imagination, and can read-
ily foretel the existence of the one from the appearance of the other’ (EHU
20 A. Ward
7.28). It is not, I suggest, of any relevance that, with the self, we are con-
cerned with the conjunction of perceptions (frequently recalled) rather
than the conjunction of material objects (frequently observed). In each
case, we believe we are acquainted with a causal connection between the
given data; whereas all that is discoverable is one event regularly following
another, together with the association of their ideas in the imagination.
That we talk of a cause having the power to produce an effect is no proof,
Hume adds, that ‘we are acquainted, in any instance, with the connecting
principle between cause and effect’ (EHU 7.29n17.2).
8. As a number of commentators have pointed out, Hume had previously
denied that there are any difficulties or contradictions in the theories con-
cerning the nature of the mind: see the opening paragraph of ‘Of the
immateriality of the soul’ (T 1.4.5).
Bibliography
Garrett, D. (2011) ‘Rethinking Hume’s Second Thoughts about Personal
Identity’ in The Possibility of Philosophical Understanding: Essays for Barry
Stroud, ed. J. Bridges, N. Kolodny, and W.-H. Wong. Oxford: Oxford
University Press, 15–40.
Mackie, J. L. (1976) Problems from Locke. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Strawson, G. (2011) The Evident Connexion: Hume on Personal Identity. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Strawson, G. (2012) ‘“All My Hopes Vanish”: Hume on the Mind’ in The
Continuum Companion to Hume, ed. A. Bailey and D. J. O’Brien. London:
Continuum, 181–98.
Stroud, B. (1977) Hume. London: Routledge and Kegan Paul.
2
Hume’s Bundle
Donald C. Ainslie
D. C. Ainslie (*)
University of Toronto, Toronto, ON, Canada
e-mail: [email protected]
© The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature Switzerland AG 2022 21
D. O’Brien (ed.), Hume on the Self and Personal Identity, Philosophers in Depth,
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-031-04275-1_2
22 D. C. Ainslie
time (T 1.4.6.1).3 Hume rejects this view in part because of what he finds
when he introspects:
For my part, when I enter most intimately into what I call myself, I always
stumble on some particular perception or other, of heat or cold, light or
shade, love or hatred, pain or pleasure. I never can catch myself at any time
without a perception, and never can observe any thing but the percep-
tion…. If any one upon serious and unprejudic’d reflection, thinks he has
a different notion of himself, I must confess I can reason no longer with
him. (T 1.4.6.3; italics added on ‘notion’)
the soul, as far as we can conceive it, is nothing but a system or train of dif-
ferent perceptions, those of heat and cold, love and anger, thoughts and
sensations…. As our idea of any body, a peach, for instance, is only that of
a particular taste, colour, figure, size, consistence, &c. So our idea of any
mind is only that of particular perceptions, without the notion of any thing
we call substance, either simple or compound. (T Abs. 28; italics added)
In the Appendix itself, he says: ‘we have no notion of [the mind], distinct
from the particular perceptions’ (T App. 19). Thus Thiel, Strawson, and
similarly minded interpreters are not wrong to find a semantic or episte-
mological strand in Hume’s discussion of the mind, where his focus is
what we can know of the mind or how we can think of it.
That said, Hume also makes many more metaphysically sounding
assertions, sometimes in these very same passages:
particular perception from the mind; that is, in breaking off all its relations,
with that connected mass of perceptions, which constitute a thinking
being. (T 1.4.2.39)
They are the successive perceptions only, that constitute the mind.
(T 1.4.6.4)
[I]t must be our several particular perceptions, that compose the mind. I
say, compose the mind, not belong to it. (T Abs. 28)
The annihilation, which some people suppose to follow upon death, and
which entirely destroys this self, is nothing but an extinction of all particu-
lar perceptions; love and hatred, pain and pleasure, thought and sensation.
These therefore must be the same with self; since the one cannot survive the
other. (T App. 17)
In these passages, Hume seems to identify the mind with the bundle of
perceptions, or at least with the bundle of related perceptions (see Sect.
2, below).
Resolving Hume’s ambivalence about how semantic claims relate to
metaphysical ones requires an interpretation of his scepticism, perhaps
the most vexed problem in Hume scholarship. It is notable, however, that
in Part 2 of Book 1 of the Treatise, he starts by discussing the divisibility
of our perceptions of space and time, but then moves quickly to a discus-
sion of the divisibility of space and time themselves. The ‘adequacy’ of
some of our ideas enables precisely this inference (T 1.2.2.1).4 When it
comes to claims about the mind and its perceptions, Hume is similarly
open to a transition from a claim about our ideas of perceptions to claims
about perceptions themselves. For example, his so-called copy principle—
that (almost) all ideas must ultimately acquire their content from prior
simple impressions (T 1.1.1.7)—is not hedged by the suggestion that
2 Hume’s Bundle 25
this is merely a claim about our idea of ideas and ideas of impressions.
Rather, throughout the Treatise, he reaches conclusions about the mind
and its operation on the basis of introspective reflection. Indeed, Thiel’s
and Strawson’s interpretations require that Hume be able to successfully
identify our ideas of various kinds of entities.
What of Hume’s claim that ‘the essence of the mind [is] equally
unknown to us with that of external bodies’ (T Intro. 8)? One problem is
that, later in the Treatise, Hume rejects ‘antient’ metaphysical terms such
as ‘substance’, ‘accident’, ‘faculty’, and ‘occult quality’ for being merely
linguistic inventions that mask confusions (T 1.4.3.1, 10); in the
‘Abstract’ he adds ‘essence’ to this list (T Abs. 7). And, as Kenneth Winkler
points out (1991, 547–48), when Hume does seem to be using ‘essence’
in his own voice, he can be read simply as indicating an openness to regu-
larities in objects beyond those we have yet experienced.
I think that a useful lens for understanding Hume’s views on how per-
ceptions of objects relate to the objects themselves is found in the final
portions of his discussion of space and time, when he considers an objec-
tion that, in his account of the vacuum, he has explained ‘only the man-
ner in which objects affect the senses, without endeavouring to account
for their real nature and operations’ (T 1.2.5.25). His response is to ‘plead
guilty’ and to ‘confess that my intention never was to penetrate into the
nature of bodies, or explain the secret causes of their operations’ (T
1.2.5.26). In the Appendix, he indicates that a footnote is to be appended
to this paragraph:
1.D. The copyright laws of the place where you are located also
govern what you can do with this work. Copyright laws in most
countries are in a constant state of change. If you are outside the
United States, check the laws of your country in addition to the terms
of this agreement before downloading, copying, displaying,
performing, distributing or creating derivative works based on this
work or any other Project Gutenberg™ work. The Foundation makes
no representations concerning the copyright status of any work in
any country other than the United States.
• You pay a royalty fee of 20% of the gross profits you derive from
the use of Project Gutenberg™ works calculated using the
method you already use to calculate your applicable taxes. The
fee is owed to the owner of the Project Gutenberg™ trademark,
but he has agreed to donate royalties under this paragraph to
the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation. Royalty
payments must be paid within 60 days following each date on
which you prepare (or are legally required to prepare) your
periodic tax returns. Royalty payments should be clearly marked
as such and sent to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation at the address specified in Section 4, “Information
about donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation.”
• You comply with all other terms of this agreement for free
distribution of Project Gutenberg™ works.
1.F.
1.F.4. Except for the limited right of replacement or refund set forth in
paragraph 1.F.3, this work is provided to you ‘AS-IS’, WITH NO
OTHER WARRANTIES OF ANY KIND, EXPRESS OR IMPLIED,
INCLUDING BUT NOT LIMITED TO WARRANTIES OF
MERCHANTABILITY OR FITNESS FOR ANY PURPOSE.
Please check the Project Gutenberg web pages for current donation
methods and addresses. Donations are accepted in a number of
other ways including checks, online payments and credit card
donations. To donate, please visit: www.gutenberg.org/donate.
Most people start at our website which has the main PG search
facility: www.gutenberg.org.