False Universalism and The Geopolitics of Exclusion: The Case of Islam
False Universalism and The Geopolitics of Exclusion: The Case of Islam
False Universalism and The Geopolitics of Exclusion: The Case of Islam
7± 23, 1997
Richard Falk is Professor of InternationalLaw and Practice, Center of InternationalStudies, Princeton University,
Bendheim Hall, Princeton, NJ 08544-1022, USA.
inter-civilisational relations are newly of great signi® cance for world order
thinking, and particularly so with reference to human rights, political ideology
and the future of nationalism. But, I should hasten to add, not primarily because
of the issue of cultural relativism, and the related challenge to the purported
universalist claims put forward on behalf of international human rights standards
and procedures.
Rather my concern arises in relation to an exposed de® ciency of the human
rights enterprise, as broadly conceived, namely the discriminatory treatment of
non-Western civilisations, and especially of Islam, with respect to participatory
rights. My focus is not on the broad array of established human rights as such,
but on the posited human right to participate, directly or indirectly, in the
authority structures, processes and practices that together constitute world order
as here de® ned and understood. Each element of this perspective requires some
explanation and is somewhat controversial: how has Islam been the victim of
discrimination in this world order sense? if this is so, in what respects does it
raise issues that are properly treated as falling within the domain of human
rights? And, even if it is granted that human rights can be encroached upon at
a civilisational level, how can the character of such rights be validated and
implemented, and by what means? Can international law be extended to serve as
an effective vehicle for achieving equitable inter-civilisational participation in
world order structures and processes without eroding its achievements in
regulating state±society relations by way of protecting individual human rights?
Perhaps I can best clarify my point of departure by reference to what might
be called ` the geopolitics of exclusion, both with respect to the dynamics of
global governance and those substantive and symbolic issues that seem to be of
greatest concern to the Islamic world. By using such terminology, I am not
implying a conspiracy among Western leaders to achieve such exclusionary
goals, or even claiming a consistent, deliberate pattern of this character. Indeed,
the implementation of exclusion occurs mostly as a result of what might be
called ` false universalism’ , depicting the particular and partial as if it were
synonymous with the general, not only with respect to substantive results, but
more crucially in relation to the processes by which these results are reached.
Without entering upon the treacherous terrain of cultural constructivism, I
attribute this false universalism mainly to the Enlightenment Project, with its
reliance on decontextualised reason, as embodied in the language, ideas, diplo-
matic style, experience and rules of representation that originated in Western
Europe and gradually evolved into a global framework of sovereign, secular,
territorial states over a period of centuries that is conveniently, yet arbitrarily,
linked to the Peace of Westphalia in 1648. This evolution is convincingly
depicted by Stephen Toulmin in his book, Cosmopolis, which shares the view
that the era of statist dominance is coming to an end, but he sees the sequel as
global humanist, rather than as inter-civilisational or some more complex
tapestry of overlapping and intersecting identities, a conception of world order
that has often been analogised to the multiple, interpenetrating levels of authority
associated with Medieval Europe.2
In effect, the universalism that I am calling ` false’ is a mask worn to obscure
Western civilisational hegemony. This mask has been worn so long that it is
8
ISLAM AND THE GEOPOLITICS OF EXCLUSION
indistinguishable from the face itself for wearer and beholder alike. As would
be expected, such a hegemony is far greater than the sum of its political,
economic and even cultural parts, as it is civilisational, including distinctive
ideas, memories, beliefs, practices, misconceptions, myths and symbols that go
to the very core of human identity. In contrast, a true universality would
acknowledge signi® cant difference, as well as sameness, in constituting a world
order based on procedures and norms explicitly designed to ensure equitable
participation by each major world civilisation.3 Inter-civilisational equality, as a
constitutive principle of world order, seems to add a category to what David
Held, Daniele Archibugi and others have been so usefully describing and
advocating under the rubrics of ` cosmopolitan democracy’ and ` cosmopolitan
governance’ .4
My purpose here is not at all to enter into a discussion of the substance of
difference, or matters of relative merit, but only to support the view that the
neglect of civilisational participation for Islam has produced a series of partially
deformed institutions, practices and perceptions. In passing, it should also, of
course, be understood that it is accepted that there is an enormous range of
intra-civilisational differences in Islam that also need to be democratically
negotiated as part of a human rights process. My emphasis here is far more
limited, and in a sense preliminary, to the effect that at this historical juncture
civilisational identity is suf® ciently genuine for a suf® cient portion of the more
than one billion persons on the planet who consider themselves Muslim to be
treated as an essential category in evaluating the legitimacy of world order
structures and processes.5 Reinforcing this contention is the increasingly articu-
late expression of grievance and demand on the part of those who af® rm their
Islamic identity, and increasingly adopt a critical stance of normative and
emotive distance from the Western-emplaced, still largely prevailing, structures
and processes of world order, while themselves af® rming the quest for peace and
justice in the relations among the peoples of the world.6
The speci® c objective of this article is to link this analysis more directly to a
concern with human rights. The contours of this concern can be brie¯ y indicated:
we are in the midst of a period in international history in which the normative
architecture of international society has been increasingly expressed by reference
to a human rights discourse that combines, somewhat confusingly, ethical,
political and legal perspectives; these perspectives are intertwined in various
ways, but more in the form of claims, grievances and practices than as stages in
the articulation of binding rules and standards that are then implemented by
those with the authority to interpret and apply ` law’ . To a large extent, this
human rights discourse is unavoidably perceived, with varying degrees of
justi® cation and opportunism, as tainted by false universalism and its relations
to Western hegemony, one feature of which has been, and continues to be, the
suppression of civilisational identity and difference, with a particular historical/
political emphasis on the ` threat’ posed by Islam.7
This statement about the prevalence of human rights discourse can be
literalised somewhat by reference to the embodiment of the human rights
tradition in contemporary international law, primarily by means of a series of
declarations and agreements af® rmed by states, most notably including the
9
RICHARD FALK
discourse and its world order implications emerged, somewhat surprisingly, from
the concerted struggle of indigenous peoples in the 1980s and 1990s.13 This
struggle took shape against a background (and foreground) of exclusion, dis-
crimination and persecution, even extermination, assimilation and marginal-
isation that were expressive of confusing admixtures of arrogance, racism and
ignorance. These extraordinary efforts of indigenous peoples to protect the
remnants of their shared civilisational identity, an identity that was coherent and
self-consistent only in relation to the otherness of modernity, achieved two
results of direct relevance to this article: ® rst of all, it exposed the radical
inadequacy of a civilisationally ` blind’ approach to human rights, by which is
meant the utter failure of the modernist instruments of human rights to take
account in any satisfactory way of the claims, values, grievances and outlooks
of indigenous and traditional peoples; second, transnational activism by indige-
nous peoples in the last two decades has given rise to an alternative conception
of rights that represents an articulation after a long process by previously
excluded civilisational representatives.
In this regard, the contrast of this recent authentic expression of indigenous
peoples’ conception of their rights with that of earlier mainstream human rights
instruments is revealing. Also revealing is a comparison between these efforts by
indigenous peoples and the paternalistic efforts supposedly on their behalf in the
marginal arena provided by the International Labour Organisation. Such com-
parisons are con® rmatory of the contention that participatory rights are integral
to the acceptance of a political order as legitimate and to a reliable clari® cation
of grievance, demand and aspiration.14 This alternative conception has been
developed by indigenous peoples in an elaborate process of normative recon-
struction that involved sustained, and often dif® cult dialogue among the multi-
tude of representatives of indigenous traditional peoples, especially as these have
come together in recent years at the Informal Working Group on the Rights of
Indigenous Populations, set up under the Sub-Commission on Racial Discrimi-
nation and Persecution of the Human Rights Commission that has recently taken
the primary form of producing a Draft Declaration on the Rights of Indigenous
Peoples, which is now being considered within the wider UN system. It is
doubtful whether this Declaration of indigenous rights will eventually be
validated by state-centric procedures; in effect, these remain the gatekeepers
within the UN system of the still ascendant false universalism.15 The resistance
being mounted in reaction to this more adequate expression of human rights as
formulated by indigenous and traditional peoples in relation to their own destiny
is mainly centred on certain perceived tensions that could result if the right of
self-determination were to be legally con® rmed as possessed by indigenous
peoples. To what extent this struggle of indigenous peoples succeeds or fails is
conceptually and substantively beside the point of this inquiry into Islamic
exclusion, except to illustrate by analogy the surfacing of a different type of
inter-civilisational challenge within the same approximate historical time
interval.16 Of course, the indigenous struggle also reinforces the point that unless
authentic participation in the rights-creation process occurs, the results are not
likely to be genuinely representative and the whole process will be regarded as
illegitimate and alien.
11
RICHARD FALK
It is important, at this point, to recall the limited nature of this analysis: that the
geopolitical exclusion of Islam is real, that it has negative world order conse-
quences, that its recti® cation would be of bene® t to Islam, and that expanding
human rights coverage to include civilisational rights of participation provides
one, but only one, mode of recti® cation.
12
ISLAM AND THE GEOPOLITICS OF EXCLUSION
13
RICHARD FALK
the plausibility and structured character of Islamic grievances and the desirability
of a world order reconstructed to take into account inter-civilisational identities
and aspirations.
The main grievances enumerated by Davutoglu can be brie¯ y considered in
terms of their reasonableness.
Participation in the United Nations system. Despite having more than one
billion adherents spread across over 45 countries, no permanent member of the
Security Council is part of the Islamic world and, in most proposals for UN
reform, calls for the expansion of the Security Council usually do not propose
recti® cation. This, to be sure, in part, re¯ ects the statist and Eurocentric origins
of the United Nations at the end of World War II. And possibly it also re¯ ects
the failure of the Islamic countries to press harder for representation of this
character in the most symbolically important organ of the United Nations. But
the impression of exclusion is reinforced by the realisation that none of the
secretary generals of the UN to date have been of Muslim faith, and very few
of the important specialised agencies have been headed by a Muslim. Again this
can be explained, in part, by the contention that of® cials are selected on the basis
of secular criteria of merit and political support, not because of ethnic nor
religious identity. Yet when combined with other factors, there would be
reasonable grounds for believing that Islamic participation could make a
difference with respect to the role of the United Nations on such issues as
Palestinian self-determination and the status of Jerusalem, the approach to
international terrorism, and the maintenance of the nuclear non-proliferation
regime.
The Bosnian diplomatic and peace process can also be viewed as one that
denies the Islamic world a sense of equitable participation: each of the factions
except for the main victims of atrocity and aggression, the Bosnian Muslims,
were represented by an external actor with civilisational ties;24 Turkey, the only
European state with an Islamic identity and a steadfast member of the Western
alliance, although highly secularised at the level of the ruling elites, was not
included in ` the contact group’ of countries with a special role in the peace
process, while Russia, with fewer claims in many respects, was included. In
isolation, this pattern in Bosnia would perhaps not warrant comment, but as part
of the larger picture, it does seem to add a dimension to the geopolitics of
exclusion.
Other con¯ icts that have involved Islamic victims of violent abuse, such as
Bosnia, Chechnya and Kashmir, are con® rmatory of the accusation of double
standards to the extent that it is probable that, if the identities of victim and
perpetrator were reversed, the international response would have been altered.
Such a pattern exists, and although each instance can be partially explained by
other factors such as deference to state coercive power, deployed within
territorial limits, or the infeasibility of challenging major states acting within
their own geographical zone of dominance, the cumulative weight of instances
and the selective reliance on international law to condemn and condone gives the
accusation of double standards a rather strong presumption of validity.
Punitive peace. It is worth contrasting the way in which Serbia and Iraq have
been treated after the cessation of hostilitiesÐ lifting sanctions and a rapid
restoration of normalcy in one instance, compared to intrusive intervention and
the maintenance of sanctions well-known to have caused prolonged great
suffering and loss of life to the poorest sectors of Iraqi society without
contributing to the downfall of Saddam Hussein’ s regime, in the other.28 Janna
Nolan points out that the insistence on the extensive demands for Iraqi veri® ed
destruction of portions of its military capabilities, especially those relating to
weaponry of mass destruction, ` have some parallels to the Allied program to
16
ISLAM AND THE GEOPOLITICS OF EXCLUSION
disarm Germany after World War I’ .29 The failure of the Versailles punitive
approach to a defeated enemy led to the abandonment of an imposition of
humiliating and punitive conditions in the wake of military victory partly
because it was seen as contributing to the rise of Fascism, but now it has been
resurrected against Iraq, an approach extended in certain respects to Iran mainly
by unilateral action. There seem good grounds, then, for regarding such policy
approaches to countries in the Islamic world as part of the broader pattern of the
geopolitics of exclusion, even to the extent of adapting the language of
containment, central to the West’ s posture vis-aÁ-vis the Soviet Union, in relation
to Iran and Iraq. This latter policy is being discussed by Washington policy-
makers under the rubric of ` double containment’ .
Policy making and participation in the world economy. As with the permanent
membership of the Security Council, the directorate of the world economy, the
Group of Seven, or G-7, includes no Islamic state. Would not Indonesia,
Malaysia or Saudi Arabia have as good a claim as Canada or Italy? In an era of
globalisation, with the Asia±Paci® c region in the ascendancy, it would seem
reasonable to expect greater representation for Islamic countries. The same
pattern of exclusion pertains, as well, to the Bretton Woods institutions that are
administered by top of® cials normally drawn from the West. A further source of
suspicion is the drastic, terminal manner of dealing with the disclosures of fraud
on the part of the Bank of Credit and Commerce International (BCCI), leading to
the immediate dissolution of the only international bank with primary Islamic
funding and direction.30
Islamic defendants in New York, where the atmosphere was probably more
adversely in¯ amed.31
The right to democratic governance. After the Cold War the West proclaimed
its commitment to the spread of democratic governance, which meant especially
the encouragement of constitutionalism in the form of multiparty elections. Yet
its concern with the spread of political Islam apparently led it to overlook the
coup that occurred in Algeria to deprive Islamicists of an electoral victory in
1990.33
produced would probably be more balanced, and viewed as such from Islamic
perspectives, if assessed on an inter-civilisational basis. Such an analysis is
minimalist in the sense that it does not give weight to the anti-modernist,
anti-secularist, anti-globalisation dimensions of the Islamic critique of the
structures of world order or to the contention that positive Islamic contributions
by way of balancing community values against individualist claims would
contribute to a more stable foundation for social relations and inter-civilisational
understanding.
Notes
This is a revised version of a paper originally presented at a conference on ` Universalizing from Particulars:
Islamic Views of the Human and the UN Declaration of Human Rights in Comparative Perspective’ , under
the auspices of the Institute for the Transregional Study of the Contemporary Middle East, North Africa, and
Central Asia, Princeton University, 24±26 May 1996.
1
Of course, this orientation was hardly original to Huntington, but rests upon a civilisational exploration by
many others, most notably the extraordinarily important depiction of civilisational reality by Fernand
Braudel, The Mediterranean and the Mediterranean World in the Age of Philip II, New York: Harper
Collins, 1972, pp. 545±596. See also the monumental achievement of Arnold Toynbee, A Study of History.
For a negative perception of the impact of resurgent Islam see Adda B. Bozeman, Politics and Culture in
International History, New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction, 1994, esp. pp. xix±xxi. For a favourable Islamic
orientation and perspective see Ahmet Davutoglu, Civilizational Transformation and the Muslim World,
Kuala Lumpur: Mahir Publications, 1994.
2
Stephen C Toulmin, Cosmopolis: The Hidden Agenda of Modernity, New York: Free Press, 1990. For other
presentations of contemporary world order see James N Rosenau, Turbulence in World Politics: A Theory
of Change and Continuity, Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, 1990; RBJ Walker, One World/Many
Worlds: Struggles for a Just World Peace, London: Zed Press, 1988; and Richard Falk, On Humane
Governance: Towards a New Global Politics, College Park, PA: Penn State University Press, 1995.
3
The character of ` signi® cant difference’ is substantively complex, but procedurally relatively simple,
referring to relatively equal access, representation and status in principal arenas of formal authority, as well
as relatively equal treatment in the application of norms of behaviour and regimes of prohibition, for
instance, the regime prohibiting the proliferation of nuclear weaponry. The quali® cation of a civilisation as
`major’ is also potentially troublesome, raising the question of ` what counts as a civilisation?’ .
4
David Held, Democracy and the Global Order: From the Modern State to Cosmopolitan Governance,
Cambridge: Polity, 1995, esp pp 219±286; and Daniele Archibugi & David Held (eds), Cosmopolitan
Democracy: An Agenda for a New World Order, Cambridge: Polity, 1995.
5
The argumentative assertion here is the insistence on the word `essential’ , re¯ ecting a psycho-political, as
well as a legal and moral, assessment. There is, of course, no implication that Islam (or any other
civilisation) is monolithic, but only that the collective identity expressed by the label ` Islam’ is a meaningful
category in a manner analogous to the label ` Britain’ or ` France’ .
6
An eloquent and persuasive Muslim expression, both critical towards the West and visionary in relation to
Islamic contribution to an enhanced world order, is that of Chandra Muzaffar. See Muzaffar, Human Rights
and the New World Order, Penang: Just World Trust, 1993. In his role as founder and director of Just World
Trust Muzaffar has convened a series of meetings and issued many commentaries on world policy issues
that react against what I am describing as ` the geopolitics of exclusion’ . A particularly notable effort was
an international workshop, ` Images of Islam: Terrorising the Truth’ , 7±9 October 1995, Penang: Malaysia.
See also the publication of a collection of his essays that is more geopolitical than inter-civilisational in tone
under the title Dominance of the West over the Rest, Penang: Just World Trust, 1995.
7
For rather enlightened examples of recent literature, invoking as well the deep historical roots of the
encounter, see Graham E Fuller & Ian O Lesser, A Sense of Siege, Boulder, CO: Westview/RAND, 1995; John
L Esposito, The Islamic Threat: Myth or Reality, New York: Oxford University Press, 1992; and Fred
Halliday, Islam & the Myth of Confrontation, London: IB Tauris, 1996. In the context of human rights, the
uncritical call for universal human rights, without reference to inter-civilisational agency, is problematic. See
for example, Ralf Dahrendorf, The Modern Social Con¯ ict, London: Weidenfeld and Nicolson, 1988, p 181.
8
But see an important caveat relating to their contention that overlooking the inter-ideological cleavages of
the Cold War was a dangerous instance of false universalism. Harold D Lasswell & Myres S McDougal,
`Diverse and contending public order systems, in McDougal & Associates, Studies in World Public Order,
New Haven, CT: Yale University Press, 1960, pp. 3±42.
9
These efforts involved trying to insist upon sovereignty rights as a balance against interventionary claims
whose identity was associated with the jurist or diplomat responsible for the assertionÐ as, for instance, ` the
21
RICHARD FALK
Calvo clause’ , `the Drago doctrine’ Ð as well as efforts to put foreign and domestic investors on a level of
parity in relation to expropriation controversies.
10
The most prominent of these were the Declaration on the Establishment of a New Economic Order,
Programme of Action on the Establishment of a New International Economic Order and the Charter on the
Economic Rights and Duties of States. For convenient texts see Burns H Weston et al (eds), Basic
Documents in International Law and World Order, St Paul, MN: West Publishing, 1990, pp. 550±575.
11
For the most authoritative formulation see `Declaration on the Right to Development’ , adopted as UNGA
Res. 41/128, 4 December 1986, text in ibid, note 10, pp 485±488.
12
For a powerful argument along these lines that emphasises the importance of the acceptance of the right to
development as an integral element of human rights at the UN Conference on Human Rights held in Vienna,
June 1993, see Upendra Baxi, Mambrino’ s Helmet?: Human Rights for a Changing World, New Delhi:
Har-Anand Publications, 1994, pp 1±17, 22±54.
13
See Rosanne Ortiz, Indians of the Americas: Human Rights and Self-Determination, London: Zed Press,
1984.
14
See ILO Convention No 107, ` Concerning the Protection and Integration of Indigenous and Other Tribal and
Semi-Tribal Populations in Independent Countries’ , text in Weston et al, note 10, pp 335±340, for a prime
instance of paternalism; compare ILO Convention No 169 for a vastly improved formulation that re¯ ects
pressure from and participation by representatives of indigenous peoples, completed in 1989, text in Weston
et al, note 10, pp 489±497. For a sensitive account of the consequences over a period of centuries see James
Anaya’ s contribution to the Report of the Canadian Royal Commission on Aboriginal Peoples, 1995.
15
For a helpful account of the obstacles in the path of acceptance within the UN system see Nouvelles
Internationales (newsletter), 4 (1±2), 1996, pp 2±5.
16
The comparison is meaningful along a number of axes, including the tendencies toward ` orientalism’ and
`occidentalism’ , that is, the mutually demeaning, if not demonising, stereotypic images of the other that are
characteristic of inter-civilisational encounter, especially if combined with relations of domination and
subordination. Basic here, of course, is Edward Said’ s Orientalism, New York: Pantheon, 1978. Also
suggestive is Jean-FrancËois Lyotard, ` The other’ s rights’ , in Stephen Shute & Susan Hurley (eds), On
Human Rights, New York: Basic Books, 1993, pp 135±146. Also of relevance may be the shared element
of anti-modernism in both the indigenous/traditional and Islamic challenges, which may be one aspect of an
explanation for their co-emergence. For valuable varying perspectives on Islamic attitudes, see Akbar S
Ahmed, Postmodernism and Islam: Predicament and Promise, London: Routledge, 1992; and Fatima
Mernissi, Beyond the Veil: Male± Female Dynamics in Modern Muslim Society, Bloomington, IN: Indiana
University Press, 1987.
17
Davutoglu, Civilizational Transformation and the Muslim World.
18
Ibid, p 101; see also the discussion in immediately subsequent paragraphs.
19
Ibid, pp 103±104.
20
Ibid, p 27.
21
Ibid, pp 114±117.
22
It should be noted that leading thinkers of indigenous peoples make similar claims.
23
Esposito, The Islamic Threat; and Fuller & Lener, A Sense of Seige.
24
It is true that the Bosnian government understated their Islamic identity throughout the war, emphasising
their pluralistic character and their own refusal to emulate the ethnic cleansing of their Serbian and Croatian
adversaries.
25
On media bias see Edward Said, Covering Islam, New York: Pantheon, 1981.
26
For an excellent overall presentation of the non-proliferation regime that accords with my analysis see
Michael Klare, Rogue States and Nuclear Outlaws, New York: Hill & Wang, 1995. Klare points out that
Pakistan’ s strategic relationship with the West de® nitely moderated to some extent efforts to obstruct
Pakistan’ s efforts to acquire a nuclear weapons capability. See Klare, pp 156±157. On the Israeli weapons
programme as facilitated by anti-proliferation states see Seymour Hersh, The Sampson Option, New York:
Random House, 1991.
27
For a balanced analysis that supports this assessment, although not phrased in civilisational categories, see
Janna Nolan’ s ` Sovereignty and collective intervention: controlling weapons of mass destruction’ , in Gene
M Lyons & Michael Mastanduno (eds), Beyond Westphalia: State Sovereignty and International Interven-
tion, Baltimore, MD: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1995, pp 170±187. Nolan’ s conclusion is pertinent:
`The Achilles heel of nonproliferation initiatives, as such, is emerging regional powers’ perception of
discrimination in a system that continues to place a high value on weapons of mass destruction as an
indicator of state power and prestige, even while trying to promote the global prohibition of such weapons.’
(p 187)
28
See especially the Harvard report based on ® eld assessments by health specialists, International Study Team,
Health and Welfare in Iraq after the Gulf War: An In-Depth Assessment, Cambridge, MA: Harvard
University, October 1991. See also the report prepared by Eric Hoskins, Calvin Bauman & Scott Harding
of Gulf Peace Team Special Mission to Iraq: Health Assessment Team, Amman, Jordan, 30 April 1991; and
22
ISLAM AND THE GEOPOLITICS OF EXCLUSION
Francis A Boyle, ` Indictment, complaint, and petition by the 4.5 million children of Iraq for relief from
genocide by President George Bush’ , document, 18 September 1991. A useful discussion is to be found in
Sarah Graham-Brown’ s ` Intervention, sovereignty and responsibility’ , Middle East Report, 25, pp 2±12, 32.
For a more general condemnation by way of international law see Hans Kochler, The United Nations
Sanctions Policy and International Law, Kuala Lumpur: Just World Trust, 1995. An excellent overview,
with useful chapters on the impact of sanctions on Iraq is contained in David Cortright & George A Lopez
(eds), Economic Sanction: Panacea or Peacebuilding in a Post-Cold War World?, Boulder, CO: Westview,
1995; and Fred Tanner (ed), Effects of International Sanctions, Malta: Mediterranean Academy of
Diplomatic Studies, January 1996.
29
Nolan, ` Sovereignty and collective intervention’ , p 175.
30
This impression is supported by the unquestionably hostile treatment of the scandal by two sophisticated
books written by leading writers for the Wall Street Journal and the Financial Times, which nonetheless
make the striking point that many of BCCI’ s most dubious practices were in most respects identical with those
of mainstream international banking. See Peter Truell & Larry Gurwin, False Pro® ts: The Inside Story of
BCCI, the World’ s Most Corrupt Financial Empire, Boston, MA: Houghton, Mif¯ in, 1992; and Jonathon
Beaty & SC Gwynne, The Outlaw Bank: A Wild Ride into the Secret Heart of BCCI , New York: Random
House, 1993. Also relevant is the much less traumatising approach taken to deal with the savings and loan
scandal of the 1980s in the USA. See Kathleen Day, S & L Hell: The People and the Politics Behind the
$1 Trillion Savings and Loan Scandal, New York: Norton, 1993.
31
For a fuller discussion see Richard Falk, ` Contradictory images and conceptions of international terrorism’ ,
unpublished paper, 1994.
32
For a critique of Libyan policy by a non-Muslim, see Fan Yew Teng, The Continuing Terrorism Against
Libya, Kuala Lumpur: Egret Publications, 1993.
33
See Fuller & Lesser, A Sense of Seige, pp 49±50.
34
This gambling metaphor is borrowed from Mary Catherine Bateson’ s illuminating use of it in connection
with bias against and demoralisation of women. See Bateson, Composing a Life, New York: Atlantic
Monthly Press, 1989, p 205.
35
For the complexity of this latter extension of Westphalian thinking, see James Crawford (ed), The Rights
of Peoples, Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1988; and William Felice, Taking Human Rights Seriously: The
Importance of Collective Human Rights, Albany, NY: State University of New York Press, 1996.
36
A recent discussion of these conceptual issues in relation to the alleged erosion of sovereignty, with
particular reference to intervention under the auspices of the international community, is to be found in
Lyons & Mastanduno, Beyond Westphalia?.
37
For important extensions of the scope and orientation of human rights see Abdullahi Ahmed An-Na’ im (ed),
Human Rights in Cross-Cultural Perspectives: A Quest for Consensus, Philadelphia, PA: University of
Pennsylvania Press, 1992, esp ch by An-Na’ im, pp 19±43; Smitu Kothari & Harsh Sethi (eds), Rethinking
Human Rights: Challenges for Theory and Action, New York: Horizons, 1989; Myres S McDougal, Harold
D Lasswell & Lung-chu Chen, Human Rights and World Public Order, New Haven, CT: Yale University
Press, 1980; and Felice, Taking Human Rights Seriously.
23