Full Philosophical Perspectives On Suicide: Kant, Schopenhauer, Nietzsche, and Wittgenstein Paolo Stellino Ebook All Chapters

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 41

Full download test bank at ebook textbookfull.

com

Philosophical Perspectives on
Suicide: Kant, Schopenhauer,
Nietzsche, and Wittgenstein Paolo

CLICK LINK TO DOWLOAD

https://textbookfull.com/product/philosophica
l-perspectives-on-suicide-kant-schopenhauer-
nietzsche-and-wittgenstein-paolo-stellino/

textbookfull
More products digital (pdf, epub, mobi) instant
download maybe you interests ...

Biota Grow 2C gather 2C cook Loucas

https://textbookfull.com/product/biota-grow-2c-gather-2c-cook-
loucas/

Bad Words: Philosophical Perspectives On Slurs David


Sosa

https://textbookfull.com/product/bad-words-philosophical-
perspectives-on-slurs-david-sosa/

Philosophical Perspectives on Land Reform in Southern


Africa Erasmus Masitera

https://textbookfull.com/product/philosophical-perspectives-on-
land-reform-in-southern-africa-erasmus-masitera/

Wittgenstein and Interreligious Disagreement: A


Philosophical and Theological Perspective 1st Edition
Gorazd Andrej■ (Auth.)

https://textbookfull.com/product/wittgenstein-and-interreligious-
disagreement-a-philosophical-and-theological-perspective-1st-
edition-gorazd-andrejc-auth/
Delphi Collected Works of Arthur Schopenhauer
Illustrated Arthur Schopenhauer

https://textbookfull.com/product/delphi-collected-works-of-
arthur-schopenhauer-illustrated-arthur-schopenhauer/

Arthur Schopenhauer The World as Will and Presentation


1st Edition Arthur Schopenhauer

https://textbookfull.com/product/arthur-schopenhauer-the-world-
as-will-and-presentation-1st-edition-arthur-schopenhauer/

Wittgenstein Religion and Ethics New Perspectives from


Philosophy and Theology Mikel Burley

https://textbookfull.com/product/wittgenstein-religion-and-
ethics-new-perspectives-from-philosophy-and-theology-mikel-
burley/

Emotion in Sports Philosophical Perspectives Yunus


Tuncel

https://textbookfull.com/product/emotion-in-sports-philosophical-
perspectives-yunus-tuncel/

Unravelling the Soil Microbiome: Perspectives For


Environmental Sustainability Rama Kant Dubey

https://textbookfull.com/product/unravelling-the-soil-microbiome-
perspectives-for-environmental-sustainability-rama-kant-dubey/
Philosophical
Perspectives
on Suicide
Kant, Schopenhauer,
Nietzsche, and Wittgenstein

Paolo Stellino
Philosophical Perspectives on Suicide
Paolo Stellino

Philosophical
Perspectives on
Suicide
Kant, Schopenhauer, Nietzsche,
and Wittgenstein
Paolo Stellino
Nova Institute of Philosophy
Universidade Nova de Lisboa
LISBOA, Portugal

ISBN 978-3-030-53936-8    ISBN 978-3-030-53937-5 (eBook)


https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-53937-5

© The Editor(s) (if applicable) and The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature
Switzerland AG 2020
This work is subject to copyright. All rights are solely and exclusively licensed by the Publisher, whether
the whole or part of the material is concerned, specifically the rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of
illustrations, recitation, broadcasting, reproduction on microfilms or in any other physical way, and
transmission or information storage and retrieval, electronic adaptation, computer software, or by similar
or dissimilar methodology now known or hereafter developed.
The use of general descriptive names, registered names, trademarks, service marks, etc. in this publication
does not imply, even in the absence of a specific statement, that such names are exempt from the relevant
protective laws and regulations and therefore free for general use.
The publisher, the authors, and the editors are safe to assume that the advice and information in this book
are believed to be true and accurate at the date of publication. Neither the publisher nor the authors or
the editors give a warranty, expressed or implied, with respect to the material contained herein or for any
errors or omissions that may have been made. The publisher remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional
claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

This Palgrave Macmillan imprint is published by the registered company Springer Nature Switzerland AG.
The registered company address is: Gewerbestrasse 11, 6330 Cham, Switzerland
Preface

According to Baruch Spinoza, “a free person thinks about death less than
anything, and his wisdom is a meditation not on death but on life”
(Ethics, IV, 67). Writing a book on the philosophy of suicide does not
necessarily mean to meditate on death. This is what I tried to explain—
often with no success—to all those friends and colleagues that in recent
years kept asking me why I had chosen to work on such a gloomy subject.
Of course, I could have reminded them of Camus’ well-known opening
words of The Myth of Sisyphus: “There is but one truly serious philosophi-
cal problem and that is suicide.” But the fact is that whereas I am not
persuaded by Camus’ claim, I am truly convinced that meditating on
suicide means, to a great extent, meditating on fundamental questions
that directly concern life, not death. Among others, these questions are:
How do we conceive our obligations to society, friends, and family?
Which is the set of moral values according to which we choose to orien-
tate our life? Which is the value that we give to our autonomy and free-
dom? Is this value non-negotiable? And how do we conceive dignity? Is it
a “property” that, in specific situations, can be undermined or
deteriorated?
I began to take interest in these questions almost fifteen years ago
when, almost accidentally, I attended a session of the seminar of the
Bioethics Research Group of the University of Valencia. At the time, I
was still a PhD student and the subject of my dissertation (on Nietzsche
v
vi Preface

and Dostoevsky) had little to do with bioethics. Juan Carlos Siurana


Aparisi, the director of the research group, drew my attention to the fact
that Nietzsche’s stance on suicide was almost unexplored by bioethicists.
I began looking for Nietzsche’s remarks on suicide in his writings and
posthumous fragments. What struck me immediately was Nietzsche’s
joyous and almost poetical conception of free death. The possibility of
conceiving death differently, that is, as a festival was something new for me.
I left Spain in 2010. At the time, I had two main concerns: to find a
post-doc position and to work on the English translation of my disserta-
tion. I temporarily set aside my interest on the topic of suicide and
devoted myself completely to Nietzsche and Dostoevsky. It was an inter-
national conference on Kant and Nietzsche, held in 2012 in Lisbon, that
gave me the occasion to work again on the philosophy of suicide. From
that moment, suicide has been, somewhat intermittently, one of my main
topics of research. The idea of writing this book occurred to me some
years later, when I noticed that there was a fil rouge that linked Kant’s,
Schopenhauer’s, Nietzsche’s, and Wittgenstein’s views of suicide. I will
motivate my choice to place these four philosophical perspectives on sui-
cide side by side in the Introduction, so that there is no need to dwell on
it here.
Some chapters of this book are based on material previously published
in P. Stellino, “Nietzsche on Suicide”, Nietzsche-Studien, 42 (2013):
151–177, and in P. Stellino, “Kant and Nietzsche on Suicide”, Philosophical
Inquiry, 39/2 (2015): 79–104. Although in both cases I heavily reworked
their content for this book, I would like to thank both journals for per-
mission to revise and reuse these publications.
My research particularly benefited from the works of three specialists
on the philosophy of suicide: Margaret P. Battin, Héctor Wittwer, and
Michael Cholbi. Wittwer’s book Selbsttötung als philosophisches Problem:
Über die Rationalität und Moralität des Suizids particularly helped me at
the initial stage of my research to understand the complexities of the dif-
ferent arguments that are put forward in the debate concerning the ratio-
nality and morality of suicide.

LisbonPaolo Stellino
23 April 2020
Acknowledgements

I owe a great debt to the following friends and colleagues who read single
chapters of this book and provided me with extremely valuable feedback:
Roberta Pasquarè and Lorena Cebolla Sanahuja (chapter on Kant),
Christopher Janaway and Vilmar Debona (chapter on Schopenhauer),
Marta Faustino and Maria Cristina Fornari (chapter on Nietzsche), and
Vicente Sanfélix Vidarte and Modesto Gómez Alonso (chapter on
Wittgenstein). I am also most grateful to the anonymous reviewer for
providing very useful critical and constructive comments on the entire
manuscript.
I would like to thank Brendan George and Lauriane Piette, from
Palgrave Macmillan, and Charanya Manoharan, from Springer, for their
help and support. I would also like to thank João Constâncio for kindly
supporting my work since the first day I arrived in Lisbon. I should also
mention that this book would not have been possible without the sup-
port of the Portuguese Fundação para a Ciência e a Tecnologia (FCT).
A part of this book was written during my stay in Montpellier. I would
like to thank Pascal Nouvel for welcoming me at the Centre d’Éthique
Contemporaine. A special thought goes to Nadia El Eter and Guillaume
Bagnolini, who shared with me the daily routine at the Centre.
A word of gratitude goes to all the friends who, inside and outside
academia, near and far, have accompanied me during this journey. I can-
not help mentioning Maria Cristina Fornari, Luca Lupo, and Pietro
vii
viii Acknowledgements

Gori. In particular, I shared with Pietro all the ups and downs of the
academic life as well as the experience of building a new life in a new
country with our respective families.
Finally, I am deeply thankful to my family for their constant support,
and to Audrey for her love and for sharing her life with me (despite the
fact that I am a philosopher). E lucevan le stelle…
Contents

1 Introduction: Bringing Kant, Schopenhauer, Nietzsche,


and Wittgenstein Together  1
References  9

2 Immanuel Kant: The Moral Duty of Self-­Preservation 11


2.1 Contextualizing Kant’s Prohibition of Suicide  11
2.2 Arguments from the Lectures on Ethics  23
2.3 Arguments from the Published Writings  40
2.4 Concluding Remarks  64
References 66

3 Arthur Schopenhauer: The Metaphysical Futility of Suicide 71


3.1 Schopenhauer’s Critique of Religious and Philosophical
Arguments against Suicide  78
3.2 Schopenhauer’s Metaphysical Worldview  90
3.3 The Futility of Suicide 100
3.4 Concluding Remarks 117
References118

ix
x Contents

4 Friedrich Nietzsche: A Free Death at the Right Time123


4.1 Voluntary versus Involuntary Death 131
4.2 Free Death and Quick Death 143
4.3 Meaninglessness and Suicide 155
4.4 Concluding Remarks 173
References174

5 Ludwig Wittgenstein: Suicide as the Elementary Sin179


5.1 The Sources 189
5.2 Wittgenstein’s View of Ethics 199
5.3 Wittgenstein’s Remarks on Suicide 208
5.4 Concluding Remarks 221
References223

6 Conclusion: What Kant, Schopenhauer, Nietzsche, and


Wittgenstein Can Teach Us About Suicide227
References240

Index243
About the author

Paolo Stellino is Researcher at the Nova Institute of Philosophy, New


University of Lisbon, Portugal. His main fields of research interest are the
history of nineteenth- and twentieth-century philosophy, ethics, and phi-
losophy of cinema. He has published many articles in international peer-­
reviewed journals and has authored several book chapters. He is the
author of the book Nietzsche and Dostoevsky: On the Verge of Nihilism (2015).

xi
Abbreviations

Kant
References to Kant’s writings are cited according to the volume and page
number of the Academy Edition (Kants gesammelte Schriften).
A Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View
CPR Critique of Pure Reason [1781 cited as A/1787 cited as B]
CPrR Critique of Practical Reason
LE Lectures on Ethics
G Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals
MM The Metaphysics of Morals
NF Notes and Fragments
R Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason

Schopenhauer
References to Schopenhauer’s writings are cited according to the follow-
ing abbreviations and the page number of the editions listed in the
bibliography.

BM On the Basis of Morals


MR Manuscript Remains in Four Volumes
PP (I & II) Parerga and Paralipomena
WWR (I & II) The World as Will and Representation

xiii
xiv Abbreviations

Nietzsche
References to Nietzsche’s works are cited by abbreviation, chapter (when
applicable) and section number. For the sake of brevity, the chapter might
be identified only by a key word (for instance, Clever instead of Why I Am
so Clever). Nietzsche’s posthumous fragments are cited by year, group,
and fragment number according to the standard Colli and Montinari
edition. Nietzsche’s letters are quoted using the symbol # plus the stan-
dard reference number of the letter.

A The Anti-Christ
BGE Beyond Good and Evil
BT The Birth of Tragedy
EH Ecce Homo
GM On the Genealogy of Morality
GS The Gay Science
HH Human, All Too Human
HL On the Use and Disadvantage of History for Life
L Letters
NW Nietzsche contra Wagner
PF Posthumous Fragments
SE Schopenhauer as Educator
TI Twilight of the Idols
WS The Wanderer and His Shadow
Z Thus Spoke Zarathustra

Wittgenstein
Quotes from the Tractatus are cited by reference to the number of the
section. Quotes from the Notebooks and the Geheime Tagebücher are cited
by reference to the day of the entry.

CV Culture and Value


GT Geheime Tagebücher. 1914–1916
LE Lecture on Ethics
NB Notebooks. 1914–1916
TLP Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus
1
Introduction: Bringing Kant,
Schopenhauer, Nietzsche,
and Wittgenstein Together

In Ancient Greece death was seen as an exit door that led “from here to
yonder”, as Socrates puts in Plato’s Phaedo (117c/Plato 1997), that is,
from life on earth to the afterlife. One of the key philosophical questions
concerning death was whether man had the right to open the door. In an
earlier passage from the same dialogue, Socrates explains to Cebes that
“we men are in a kind of prison, and that one must not free oneself or run
away” (Phaedo, 62b)—at least, not “before a god has indicated some
necessity to do so” (Phaedo, 62c). Some centuries afterwards Epictetus,
the Stoic philosopher, expressed a different opinion. Life should be pre-
served as long as it is beneficial, but if it becomes unbearable, one can give
it up. As he writes in a well-known passage from the Discourses, “[h]as
some one made a smoke in the house? If he has made a moderate amount
of smoke I shall stay; if too much, I go outside. For one ought to remem-
ber and hold fast to this, that the door stands open” (Discourses I, XXV,
18/Epictetus 1956).
Since antiquity, the arguments put forward by philosophers have
become more solid and sophisticated. Nevertheless, the main question to
be answered remains the same: do we have a right to voluntarily put an
end to our life? This question can be essentially declined in two different,

© The Author(s) 2020 1


P. Stellino, Philosophical Perspectives on Suicide,
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-53937-5_1
2 P. Stellino

but strictly related, questions: (1) is suicide morally permitted? and (2)
can suicide be considered (at least in certain situations) a rational act? An
analytic approach to this question is typical of recent, contemporary phi-
losophy of suicide, which is now treated as an independent branch of
philosophy. With few exceptions (like St. Thomas Aquinas and Hume),
past philosophers have considered the question of the morality and/or
rationality of suicide in a rather fragmentary way, so that their arguments
in favour or against suicide, often to be found in detached passages of
different works, must be pieced together in order to get a general view. As
will be shown, this is precisely the case with the four philosophers consid-
ered in this book.
Nowadays, there are several valuable studies that offer an overview of
the several philosophical (and religious) arguments that can be put for-
ward in support or against one’s right to commit suicide. The works of
Cosculluela (1995), Battin (1996), Wittwer (2003), and Cholbi (2011)
are good examples of this. The scope of these studies is often introduc-
tory. This means that, in presenting the several arguments pro and con
they gain in comprehensiveness, but inevitably lack in depth.1 The aim of
this book is to address some of the same questions that these studies
address. To this end, however, a different approach is followed. Attention
is focused on four modern perspectives, which can be considered as rep-
resenting or illustrating four different views of suicide. Putting forward
seven different arguments against suicide and defending a strict prohibi-
tion of this act, Kant is a representative of the anti-libertarian view.
Schopenhauer also essentially opposes suicide, but he does it as a conse-
quence of his metaphysical view of the world, which is thoroughly pes-
simistic. His stance exemplarily shows that a pessimistic worldview does
not necessarily go hand in hand with a pro-attitude towards suicide.
Contrary to Kant, Nietzsche is rather favourable to voluntary death, at
least in certain specific situations. His stance, reminiscent of the Stoics’,
can be thus considered as representative of the libertarian view. Finally,
Wittgenstein considers suicide from the standpoint of his mystical–reli-
gious worldview, conceiving it as the elementary sin. Addressing these

1
Due to its length, Wittwer’s study combines, to a certain extent, comprehensiveness and depth.
1 Introduction: Bringing Kant, Schopenhauer, Nietzsche… 3

different but, as will be shown, complementary positions, this book pro-


vides an unusual way of understanding the phenomenon of suicide in an
integrated way. The book of course does not pretend to have an exhaus-
tive character on the immense topic it touches upon, but what it lacks in
comprehensiveness it gains in depth.
The reason to consider Kant’s, Schopenhauer’s, Nietzsche’s, and
Wittgenstein’s views of suicide in the same book also derives from the fact
that, as mentioned in the Preface, there is a fil rouge that links these views
together. In the Appendix to the first volume of the World as Will and
Representation, Schopenhauer clearly acknowledges that “however differ-
ent the content of my line of reasoning is from that of Kant, it has clearly
been very heavily influenced by Kantian ideas, it necessarily presupposes
them, and takes them as its point of departure” (WWR I: 443/
Schopenhauer 2010). When it comes to morality and its grounding,
however, Schopenhauer’s view is “diametrically opposed to Kant’s in its
essential points” (BM: 122/Schopenhauer 2009). This can be clearly seen
in Schopenhauer’s negative evaluation of Kant’s view of suicide.
Schopenhauer is very critical of the way in which Kant approaches sui-
cide and several pages of his prize essay On the Basis of Morals are devoted
to criticizing some of the arguments put forward by the latter.
Nietzsche’s relation to Schopenhauer recalls, to a certain extent,
Schopenhauer’s relation to Kant. Nietzsche was deeply influenced by
Schopenhauer (“my great teacher”, he called him in the Preface to the
Genealogy of Morality; GM, Preface, 5/Nietzsche 2006) and this influence
is not limited to the former’s early philosophy, as is often believed. At the
same time, however, Nietzsche was a profound critic of Schopenhauer’s
life-denying philosophy. Thus Nietzsche partly elaborates his view of sui-
cide in opposition to his teacher’s, and, more in general, to pessimistic
attitudes to life. Indeed, due to the influence of Schopenhauer’s thought,
pessimistic philosophies were à la mode in the second half of the nine-
teenth century and Nietzsche knew them well. Furthermore, as men-
tioned, Nietzsche’s view is also antithetical to Kant’s—although this
antithesis is not the result of Nietzsche’s direct confrontation with Kant’s
arguments against suicide, but it rather depends on Nietzsche’s more gen-
eral critique of his moral theory.
If Schopenhauer criticizes Kant’s view of suicide, and if Nietzsche
opposes Schopenhauer’s (directly) and Kant’s (indirectly) approaches to
4 P. Stellino

suicide, Wittgenstein’s most important remarks on suicide date from the


early period, that is, at a time when his philosophy was strongly influ-
enced by Schopenhauer’s metaphysics (which takes Kant’s transcendental
idealism as starting point, as mentioned). Given that Schopenhauer
exerted a major influence on the early Wittgenstein’s understanding of
the world and of ethics, it is not surprising to see that this influence also
extends to the latter’s view of suicide. In passing, it should be also men-
tioned that although it is not possible to know whether Wittgenstein was
familiar with Nietzsche’s remarks on suicide, it is a fact that in 1914
Wittgenstein bought the eighth volume of Nietzsches Werke (GT 8.12.14/
Wittgenstein 1992), which contained several texts from 1888.
Wittgenstein was most interested in Nietzsche’s The Anti-Christ. In his
Wittgenstein biography, Ray Monk comments on Wittgenstein’s interest
in Nietzsche as follows: “More stimulating was a writer whose view could
not have been more antithetical to the Tolstoyan Christianity that
Wittgenstein had come to embrace: Friedrich Nietzsche” (Monk 1991:
121). In reality, Wittgenstein’s interest in Nietzsche can be easily
explained. Indeed, although it is true that The Anti-Christ was a virulent
attack upon the Christian religion and that Wittgenstein was “deeply
affected” by Nietzsche’s hostility against Christianity (GT 8.12.14),
Nietzsche’s work was strongly influenced by Tolstoy’s view of Christianity
(Llinares Chover 2010). As will be shown, precisely this view contributed
to an important extent to shape Wittgenstein’s view of suicide.
As one can see, there is a clear connection between Kant’s,
Schopenhauer’s, Nietzsche’s, and Wittgenstein’s views of suicide. This
connection, however, does not constitute the only reason for this book.
Another reason is that, with the exception of Kant, the other three phi-
losophers considered here are often ignored in the field of philosophy of
suicide. This lack of attention seems to be motivated by reasons that are
different in each case. Schopenhauer’s opposition to suicide may be
regarded as unappealing since it presupposes his peculiar and, by now,
outdated metaphysics of the will. However, Schopenhauer is among the
philosophers who gave most importance to the topic of suicide (like
Hume, he dedicated a specific essay to suicide) and in his writings one
can find interesting considerations of various nature on this subject.
These considerations go far beyond his argument for the futility of
1 Introduction: Bringing Kant, Schopenhauer, Nietzsche… 5

suicide based on metaphysical grounds and Schopenhauer’s approach to


suicide is highly worthy of attention for the broadness of its scope and for
being ahead of his time, among other reasons. One of the aims of this
book is thus to revaluate Schopenhauer’s view of suicide and bring it to
the attention of contemporary scholars.
In the field of philosophy of suicide Nietzsche has received even less
attention than Schopenhauer. This may come as a surprise if one consid-
ers that his published writings contain several remarks on suicide and
that a speech from the first part of Thus Spoke Zarathustra is significantly
entitled On Free Death. This lack of attention can be differently accounted
for. One reason might be the fragmentary and unsystematic character of
Nietzsche’s approach to suicide. Another reason might be the strong rhe-
torical component of the texts in which he presents his view. As will be
shown, however, although Nietzsche tends to appeal to emotions instead
of defending his position with proper arguments, he nonetheless gives his
readers reasons that support his argumentation, and these reasons can be
scrutinized and examined just in the same way as Kant’s, Schopenhauer’s,
and Wittgenstein’s arguments can be. A third reason that might explain
why Nietzsche’s view of suicide is often ignored in secondary literature on
philosophy of suicide is the fact that, along with the notion of free death,
he also defends a quick death for all those who cling to life out of cow-
ardice and fear, and refuse to take a timely leave from it. Without denying
that considered from a contemporary perspective this latter notion
appears unsettling, one should resist here the temptation of decontextual-
izing Nietzsche’s words and reading them through the distorting prism of
our historical perspective. In any case, the notions of free and quick death
can and should be kept separated, so as to judge Nietzsche’s arguments in
favour of voluntary death without any bias.
Of the four philosophers considered in this study, Wittgenstein is the
one who has received less attention in the field of philosophy of suicide.
To my knowledge, the only in-depth study on Wittgenstein’s view of
suicide is the very recent paper by Gómez Alonso (2018) which, however,
mainly (although not uniquely) focuses the attention on the relation
between Wittgenstein’s early view of suicide and Schopenhauer’s meta-
physics of the will. This lack of attention may be explained by the fact
that Wittgenstein’s remarks on suicide are very few in number and that in
6 P. Stellino

order to grasp their meaning it is necessary to understand some of the


very complex and difficult notions that he introduces in his Tractatus
Logico-Philosophicus. Once this difficult step is overcome, however,
Wittgenstein’s view of suicide appears very insightful and directly linked
to some of the most profound thinkers of the nineteenth century such as
Tolstoy, Dostoevsky, Kierkegaard, and James, among others.
Unlike Schopenhauer’s, Nietzsche’s, and Wittgenstein’s views of sui-
cide, Kant’s view has been the subject of countless studies—as the
extended bibliography of the second chapter of this book clearly shows.
This should not be surprising, given that Kant’s moral theory has exerted
and continues to exert such an extraordinary influence on contemporary
bioethics and applied ethics. Even in this case, however, some clarifica-
tions are needed. First, although there are several informative studies on
Kant’s view of suicide, to my knowledge, there is no comprehensive study
in English on this subject. The only paper that presents an overview of
Kant’s several arguments against suicide is Wittwer’s (2001). However,
this paper is almost twenty years old (although the analysis developed in
it is still compelling) and is written in German, being therefore not easily
accessible to the anglophone audience. Second, existing literature usually
tends to focus the attention on Kant’s arguments from the published
writings, ignoring the arguments put forward in the Lectures on Ethics.
Almost no attention has been paid, for instance, to Kant’s freedom argu-
ment in the Collins lectures (see Sect. 2.2.3), according to which suicide
would imply a self-contradiction of freedom. This is very surprising, con-
sidering that a similar line of argumentation is sometimes advanced
within the context of the contemporary debate on assisted suicide. The
aim of the first chapter of this book is thus to provide a comprehensive
study of Kant’s view of suicide and an in-depth examination of all his
arguments against suicide. Third and finally, recent literature in English
on this subject tends to question the conventional reading of Kant as a
philosopher who categorically prohibits suicide. Some scholars even
argue that, in certain situations, Kant’s moral philosophy can be read as
justifying not only a right, but even a duty to suicide. As I will show in
the following chapter, these readings are often based on misunderstand-
ings deriving either from incomplete information or from a lack of philo-
logical accuracy.
1 Introduction: Bringing Kant, Schopenhauer, Nietzsche… 7

The methodology followed in this study primarily consists in a close


and attentive reading of the primary sources (published writings, Nachlass,
lectures, diaries, and letters). When necessary, attention is given to the
German original. The main aim is to provide a complete overview of
Kant’s, Schopenhauer’s, Nietzsche’s, and Wittgenstein’s views of suicide.
As far as possible, each stance is presented as a unitary whole. On the
other hand, however, chronological differences are taken into account.
Kant’s arguments from the Collins lectures (pre-critical period), for
instance, are distinguished from the arguments that can be found in the
published writings. At the same time, correspondences between the for-
mer and the latter are nevertheless emphasized. With the help of the rel-
evant bibliography on the subject, the arguments in favour of or against
suicide put forward by the four philosophers considered in this study are
explained, contextualized (when necessary), examined, and critically
assessed. The approach of this book is thus not so much historical as
philosophical in nature.
This book is constituted of four main chapters and a conclusion. To
each philosopher’s view of suicide is devoted one, single chapter. The fol-
lowing is a brief overview of the content of each chapter. Chapter 2 pro-
vides an in-depth examination of Kant’s arguments against suicide. After
a contextualization of Kant’s prohibition of suicide (§2.1), following
Wittwer (2001), I identify seven different arguments against the moral
permissibility of suicide: three from the Lectures on Ethics (§2.2) and four
from the published writings (§2.3). For each of them, I present the argu-
ment (and possible variations), point out strengths and flaws, and discuss
possible objections and counter-objections, taking into consideration the
abundant bibliography on the subject. I conclude that, against a recent
trend in secondary literature, which tends to read Kant as justifying not
only a right, but even a duty to suicide, Kant does not allow for any
exception to his strict prohibition of suicide.
Chapter 3 provides a full and complete analysis of Schopenhauer’s
view of suicide. Drawing on the limited secondary literature on this sub-
ject (essentially, Fox (1980), Birnbacher (1985), Jacquette (1999, 2000),
and Janaway (2017)), I first focus on Schopenhauer’s dismissal of previ-
ous religious and philosophical arguments against this act, giving particu-
lar attention to his critique of Kant’s arguments (§3.1). Subsequently, I
8 P. Stellino

briefly review the main points of his metaphysical worldview. Particular


attention is given to Schopenhauer’s gloomy understanding of human
condition and to his conception of death (§3.2). Having sketched the
main features of what is commonly known as Schopenhauer’s pessimism,
I finally examine Schopenhauer’s own argument for the futility of suicide
as well as his position on asceticism and on voluntary death by starva-
tion (§3.3).
In Chap. 4 I turn my attention to Nietzsche. Given his unsystematic
approach to suicide, I piece together his remarks and observations on the
subject in order to get a unitary picture. What is characteristic of
Nietzsche’s view of suicide is that he approaches this topic from two dif-
ferent, but interrelated points of view. On the one hand, he considers the
question of whether, in certain specific situations, voluntary death can be
a fully rational and natural choice. Within this context, he defends the
idea of a free death at the right time. On the other hand, Nietzsche con-
siders suicide from what might be defined as a proto-existentialist stand-
point: the problem is to judge whether life is or is not worth living in a
world devoid of meaning and purpose. Given the difference between the
two approaches, I consider them separately. Thus, after a brief introduc-
tion in which I contextualize Nietzsche’s view of suicide, I first consider
his arguments in favour of the rationality of voluntary death (§4.1).
Subsequently, I turn my attention to the notion of “free death”, focusing
particularly on some puzzling aspects that we are faced with when con-
sidering Nietzsche’s view of suicide. I also contrast Nietzsche’s free death
with his polemic notion of “quick death” (§4.2). Finally, I consider how
Nietzsche deals with the aforementioned question of whether life is worth
living in a world devoid of meaning and purpose. Following a chrono-
logical order (early, middle, and late Nietzsche) and giving special atten-
tion to previous literature (essentially Young 2003 and Loeb 2008), I
conclude that Nietzsche’s answer to this question is affirmative (§4.3).
Chapter 5 is devoted to Wittgenstein’s view of suicide. Attention is
focused on the early period. This choice is motivated by two main rea-
sons: first, Wittgenstein’s most interesting remarks on suicide date from
this period, and second, suicide was an intensely personal matter and a
relatively recurrent thought for the young Wittgenstein. After an intro-
duction in which I show how Wittgenstein’s early life was affected by
1 Introduction: Bringing Kant, Schopenhauer, Nietzsche… 9

several suicides and how he himself often thought of this possibility, I


first consider some of the important sources that influenced and shaped
his view of suicide (§5.1). Subsequently, in order to contextualize his
otherwise obscure remarks on suicide, I offer an overview of Wittgenstein’s
peculiar worldview, as it is presented in the Tractatus, as well as of his
understanding of ethics (§5.2). Finally, in the third and last section, I
turn the attention to Wittgenstein’s remarks on suicide, explaining their
meaning and elucidating Wittgenstein’s peculiar view of suicide (§5.3).
In Chap. 6, I present the most important conclusions that can be
drawn when Kant, Schopenhauer, Nietzsche, and Wittgenstein are put
into dialogue with each other. What do these philosophers have to say
about suicide? What can we still learn from them? Here I address these
questions, pointing out limits and merits of the four approaches consid-
ered in this book.

References
Battin, M. P. (1996). The Death Debate. Ethical Issues in Suicide. Englewood
Cliffs, NJ: Prentice Hall.
Birnbacher, D. (1985). “Schopenhauer und das ethische Problem des
Selbstmords”, Schopenhauer-Jahrbuch, 66: 115–129.
Cholbi, M. J. (2011). Suicide. The Philosophical Dimension. Peterborough, ON:
Broadview Press.
Cosculluela, V. (1995). The Ethics of Suicide. New York/London: Garland
Publishing.
Epictetus. (1956). The Discourses as Reported by Arrian, the Manual, and
Fragments (Vol. 1). Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press; London:
Heinemann (Loeb Classical Library).
Fox, M. (1980). “Schopenhauer on Death, Suicide and Self-Renunciation”, in:
id. (ed.), Schopenhauer: His Philosophical Achievement. Brighton:
Harvester Press.
Gómez Alonso, M. (2018). “Wittgenstein, Schopenhauer and the Metaphysics
of Suicide”, Revista de Filosofia Aurora, 30 (49): 299–321.
Jacquette, D. (1999). “Schopenhauer on Death”, in: C. Janaway (ed.), The
Cambridge Companion to Schopenhauer. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 293–317.
10 P. Stellino

Jacquette, D. (2000). “Schopenhauer on the Ethics of Suicide”, Continental


Philosophy Review, 33: 43–58.
Janaway, C. (2017). “Schopenhauer’s Consoling View of Death”, IFCoLog
Journal of Logics and their Applications, 4 (11): 3705–3718.
Llinares Chover, J. B. (2010). “The Early Wittgenstein, Tolstoy’s Kurze Darlegung
des Evangelium and Nietzsche’s Der Antichrist”, in: L. Perissinotto, V. Sanfélix
(eds.), Doubt, Ethics and Religion. Wittgenstein and the Counter-Enlightenment.
Frankfurt a. M.: Ontos Verlag, 105–128.
Loeb, P. S. (2008). “Suicide, Meaning, and Redemption”, in: M. Dries (ed.),
Nietzsche on Time and History. Berlin/New York: de Gruyter, 163–190.
Monk, R. (1991). Ludwig Wittgenstein. The Duty of Genius. London:
Vintage Books.
Nietzsche, F. (2006). On the Genealogy of Morality. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Plato. (1997). Complete Works. Indianapolis/Cambridge: Hackett
Publishing Company.
Schopenhauer, A. (2009). The Two Fundamental Problems of Ethics. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press.
Schopenhauer, A. (2010). The World as Will and Representation (Vol. I).
Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Wittgenstein, L. (1992). Geheime Tagebücher. 1914–1916. Vienna: Turia & Kant.
Wittwer, H. (2001). “Über Kants Verbot der Selbsttötung”, Kant-Studien,
92: 180–209.
Wittwer, H. (2003). Selbsttötung als philosophisches Problem. Paderborn: Mentis.
Young, J. (2003). The Death of God and the Meaning of Life. London/New York:
Routledge.
2
Immanuel Kant: The Moral Duty
of Self-­Preservation

2.1  ontextualizing Kant’s Prohibition


C
of Suicide
According to Margaret P. Battin, underlying the 2000-year-old theoretical
debate about how we die and which should be the individual’s role in his or
her death is the Stoic/Christian divide: “whether one’s role should be as far
as possible active, self-assertive, and responsible and may include ending
one’s own life—or, on the other hand, acceptant, obedient, and passive in
the sense of being patient, where ‘allowing to die’ is the most active step that
should be taken” (Battin 2005: 6). Despite his willingness to recognize that
there seems to be something moral in the Stoic attitude to suicide and that
sometimes suicide is a mark of great heroism, Kant follows the Christian
tradition in his consideration of self-preservation as “the first, though not the
principal, duty of man to himself” (MM, 6/Kant 1991: 421).
In recent times, several studies have questioned the conventional read-
ing of Kant as a philosopher who categorically prohibits suicide.1 This has

1
See Cosculluela (1995: 39), James (1999), Cholbi (2000, 2010, 2015), Brassington (2006),
Cooley (2006, 2007a, 2013, 2015), Rhodes (2007), and Harter (2011). See also Gregor (1963:

© The Author(s) 2020 11


P. Stellino, Philosophical Perspectives on Suicide,
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-53937-5_2
12 P. Stellino

led Michael Cholbi (2015: 607) to claim that, “thanks to recent scholar-
ship, Kant is no longer seen as the dogmatic opponent of suicide that he
appears to be at first glance.” Scholars have argued that, in certain situa-
tions, Kant’s moral philosophy can be read as justifying not only a right
but even a duty to suicide. Dennis R. Cooley (2007a, 2007b, and 2015),
for instance, defends a Kantian moral duty for the soon-to-be demented
to commit suicide. Other scholars focus attention on the casuistical ques-
tions presented in the Metaphysics of Morals (MM, 6: 423f.), arguing that
some of them seem to permit suicide.2
One may wonder why, if Kant thought that in some occasions suicide
could be permitted or even be considered as obligatory, he is reported to
have said that suicide is not permitted “under any condition” (LE, Collins
27/1997: 372) and “under any circumstances” (LE, Vigilantius 27: 603).
That Kant was unsympathetic to suicide is also shown by his cold and
almost indifferent reply to Maria von Herbert, an Austrian woman and a
student of his philosophy who, on the verge of suicide, wrote to him ask-
ing for his help and advice. Von Herbert was desperate because of a
heartbreak and sought comfort in Kant’s philosophy but could not find
it. As a result, in August 1791 she wrote to Kant asking for help, for com-
fort or for counsel to prepare her for death. Kant answered in spring 1792
but was unable to relieve the young woman’s grief. Von Herbert wrote
again in January 1793 but Kant never replied. Eventually, the woman
took her life in 1803.3
To this, one must add that Kant’s views of suicide are very derogatory.
In the Lectures on Ethics, suicide is described as “the most abominable of
the crimes that inspire horror and hatred [das abscheulichste Laster des
Grausens und des Haßens]” (LE, Collins 27: 347) and as “the most dread-
ful thing [das schrecklichste] that a man can do to himself ” (LE, Collins
27: 391). By committing it, the human being “puts himself below the

135–136) and Battin (1996: 108–112). On the other hand, for a reading of Kant as opposing
suicide in all circumstances, see de Vleeschauwer (1966), Brandt (1975), Wittwer (2001), Unna
(2003), and Schüssler (2012). Hill (1991: 85) ascribes to Kant a “rigoristic opposition to suicide.”
He nonetheless finds Kant’s position untenable and claims that “the spirit of his idea of humanity
as an end in itself […] leads to a more tenable position.”
2
See, particularly, James (1999).
3
On this, see Langton (1992).
2 Immanuel Kant: The Moral Duty of Self-Preservation 13

beast” (LE, Collins 27: 372) and “makes himself into a monster” (A, 7:
259). How can these categorical and harsh claims be reconciled with the
reading according to which “Kant does implicitly and explicitly allow
exceptions to the general rule” (Cooley 2007a: 38)?
In reality, some of the interpretations that defend the view according
to which Kant would have allowed exceptions to his categorical prohibi-
tion of suicide are based on misunderstandings deriving either from
incomplete information or from a lack of philological accuracy. Kant’s
consideration of Cato’s suicide is, in this sense, paradigmatic.4 In the
Lectures on Ethics, Kant introduces Cato’s suicide by claiming that “sui-
cide can also come to have a plausible aspect [scheinbare Seite], whenever,
that is, the continuance of life rests upon such circumstances as may
deprive that life of its value; when a man can no longer live in accordance
with virtue and prudence, and must therefore put an end to his life from
honourable motives” (LE, Collins 27: 370). Cato had only two options
available to him: either to fall into Caesar’s hands—something which he
considered dishonourable—or to take his life and preserve his honour. As
Kant puts it, “he viewed his death as a necessity; his thought was: Since
you can no longer live as Cato, you cannot go on living at all” (LE,
Collins 27: 370f.).
According to Kant, Cato’s suicide constitutes “the one example [das
einzige Beyspiel] that has given the world an opportunity of defending
suicide” (LE, Collins 27: 371). Scholars often refer to this passage to
show that Kant’s attitude towards suicide is not as dogmatic as it prima
facie appears to be.5 Surprisingly, the same scholars have failed to remark
that later in the same lecture Kant again discusses Cato’s suicide. If on the
one hand Kant claims that Cato’s suicide was a mark of heroism and
courage, he also adds, on the other, that “if Cato, under all the tortures
that Caesar might have inflicted on him, had still adhered to his resolve
with steadfast mind, that would have been noble; but not when he laid
hands upon himself. Those who defend and teach the legitimacy of

4
Cato the Younger or “Uticensis” (95–46 BC) was a Roman statesman and Stoic, known for his
moral integrity. He was one of the defeated of the Great Roman Civil War (49–45 BC). Unwilling
to live in a world governed by Caesar, whom he considered a tyrant, Cato decided to commit sui-
cide, thus becoming a symbol of virtue.
5
See Battin (2006: 107), Cooley (2006: 333, 336; 2007a: 38; 2013: 367), and Harter (2011).
14 P. Stellino

suicide inevitably do great harm in a republic”6 (LE, Collins 27: 374). As


Yvonne Unna (2003: 464) points out, “Kant’s reasoning suggests that it
is one thing to sympathize with a person’s wish to die an honorable death,
yet another to justify the act of suicide. A violation of honor does not
justify ‘self-murder’.”
Another source of misunderstanding stems from the five casuistical
questions that follow the section dedicated to suicide in the Metaphysics
of Morals7 (MM, 6: 423f.). Given the fact that Kant poses the questions
but does not provide an answer (at least, not in the Metaphysics of Morals),
scholars have often taken the casuistical questions either to be open and
unanswered, or even to permit suicide in some cases. So, for instance,
both Battin (1996: 110) and James (1999: 49, 52) claim that Kant seems
to consider Curtius’ suicide as morally justifiable. Yet, Vigilantius reports
Kant as saying that “it can never be allowable for me deliberately to yield
up my life, or to kill myself in fulfilment of a duty to others; for example,
when Curtius plunges into the chasm, in order to preserve the Roman
people, he is acting contrary to duty” (LE, Vigilantius 27: 629).
In 2003, Yvonne Unna published a very detailed and compelling study
of Kant’s casuistical questions in the Kant-Studien. Unna’s purpose was to
put to rest any possible speculation about how Kant would have answered
these questions by showing that Kant had actually answered or suggested
an answer to four of the five casuistical questions of the Metaphysics of
Morals elsewhere—more precisely, in the Anthropology, in the Vigilantius
lectures, and in the Nachlaß. Unna’s conclusion was that “all of Kant’s
replies confirm that he categorically rejects suicide as immoral”8 (Unna
2003: 454). It is unfortunate to observe that Unna’s paper has been often
ignored by later studies on Kant’s view of suicide. For instance, Cooley
claimed on various occasions that Kant seems to consider the suicide of

6
On this, see Seidler (1983 : 446).
7
The first three questions refer to the following historical figures: Curtius (hurling oneself to certain
death to save one’s country), Seneca (killing oneself to preserve one’s honour), and Frederick the
Great (carrying lethal poison in war to be able to commit suicide rather than be captured and
forced to agree to conditions that would prove harmful to the state). The fourth question is about
a man bitten by a mad dog, who prefers to take his life rather than cause harm to others. The fifth
and final question concerns the moral permissibility of smallpox inoculation, which at that time
could cause death.
8
See also Schüssler (2012: 77–81).
2 Immanuel Kant: The Moral Duty of Self-Preservation 15

the man bitten by the rabid dog (MM, 6: 423f.) not only morally permis-
sible but also morally obligatory.9 This cannot be the case, for as Unna
(2003: 461f.) rightly points out, Kant dismisses this possibility in a pas-
sage from the Lectures on Ethics.10 It is, therefore, not true that “Kant the
casuist was more conciliatory than Kant the doctrinarian”11 (De
Vleeschauwer 1966: 254) nor that “many ‘casuistical questions’ remain”12
(Cholbi 2000: 172).
As this brief analysis shows, there has been some misunderstanding on
Kant’s attitude towards suicide in past years due to partial reading of
Kant’s writings, lectures, and Nachlaß, incomplete information on exist-
ing bibliography, and lack of philological accuracy in reading the texts,
among other factors. Needless to say, this does not mean that all studies
that aim to refute Kant’s alleged rigorism are based on false premises or
lack philological accuracy. On the contrary, there exist plausible interpre-
tations that point to concrete difficulties in Kant’s view of suicide. One of
these difficulties particularly concerns the fact that some of the examples
chosen by Kant to strengthen his argumentation are in reality ad hoc
examples. Another problem concerning Kant’s stance on suicide is linked
to the intricate relation between suicide and concepts such as dignity and

9
See Cooley (2006: 333; 2007a: 38–39; 2013: 367; 2015: 284). In his reply to Cooley’s paper
(2007a) on a Kantian moral duty for the soon-to-be demented to commit suicide, Stephen
R. Latham (2007: 50) draws the attention to Unna’s paper. Apparently, this reference has gone
unobserved by Cooley.
10
See LE, Vigilantius 27: 603: “To destroy oneself, therefore, through an act voluntarily under-
taken by the sensory being, can never be permitted, so that a suicide (autocheiria) can never, under
any circumstances, be regarded as allowable. Suppose, if you will, such cases as that of a slave, for
example, who should lose his life in consequence of an attempted but abortive bid for freedom; or
that one bitten by a mad dog should feel quite plainly the effects of madness; can either of them
take his own life? The first considers a life of slavery to be no such life as is suited to humanity; the
second foresees his own death, and the possibility, likewise, of harming others through his urge to
bite. Nevertheless, they both frustrate all attempts whereby they might be freed from their unhappy
condition and are preserved from harm, e.g., by having themselves tied up at the appropriate time;
quite recently a remedy for the mad dog’s bite has been found, in administering oil to the victim
internally, and trying to anoint him completely on the outside.”
11
As a general rule, I have personally translated all citations in languages other than English.
12
I acknowledge my mistake in Stellino (2015: 98, n. 48; due to an unfortunate misunderstanding
with the publisher, this article was not published in its final and revised version). According to
Schmidt and Schönecker (2017: 164–165), “The crucial point of [Kant’s] casuistry is not the ques-
tion whether there are exceptions to the rule, that is, whether suicide ‘in specific cases’ can be per-
mitted, but rather whether concrete cases of self-disembodiment [Selbstentleibung] entail self-murder
[Selbstmord].”
16 P. Stellino

autonomy—concepts that play a pivotal role in Kant’s philosophy as well


as in contemporary bioethics. I will address these issues later in this chap-
ter. For now, I will present Kant’s arguments for the immorality of suicide
and consider some of the critiques that have been addressed or can be
addressed to them.
Before I proceed with the analysis of Kant’s arguments, however, I
must draw attention to a fundamental distinction between Kant’s ethics
and Kantian ethics. Following Allen W. Wood (2008: 1), we can say that
Kant’s ethics is “the theory Kant himself put forward,” whereas Kantian
ethics is “an ethical theory formulated in the basic spirit of Kant.” When
considering Kant’s attitude towards suicide, it is essential to distinguish
between what Kant actually said and what one could say without betray-
ing the spirit of his philosophy. There is a non-negligible difference
between claiming that in certain occasions Kant seems to justify a right
or a duty to suicide, and claiming that on certain occasions a Kantian
right or duty to suicide seems to be justifiable. Thomas E. Hill (1991:
85), for instance, ascribes to Kant a “rigoristic opposition to suicide.” He
nonetheless finds Kant’s position untenable and defends a modified
Kantian view according to which “some suicides are justified and even
commendable” (id.: 95). In what follows, I will only focus attention on
Kant’s attitude to suicide, leaving aside the rather different question of
whether a Kantian right or duty to suicide might be, on certain occa-
sions, justifiable.
With this distinction in mind, we can now consider Kant’s several
arguments for the impermissibility of suicide. As Seidler (1983: 440)
points out, the topic of suicide “is virtually absent in Kant’s pre-critical
works, but it began to occupy him seriously in the mid-1770s and
received explicit treatment in all major ethical writings thereafter.” The
relevant passages, though not the only ones, can be found in the
Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, the Critique of Practical Reason,
the Metaphysics of Morals, the lectures recorded by Collins and Vigilantius,
and the Nachlaß.13 The German word that Kant uses to refer to the act of

13
See G, 4: 421–422, 429; CPrR, 5: 44; MM, 6: 422–424; LE, 27: 190–192, 208–210, 342–347,
369–378, 601–603, 627–630; NF 6801, 19: 165–166. See also § 77 of the Anthropology from a
Pragmatic Point of View (7: 258–259).
Another random document with
no related content on Scribd:
1.C. The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation (“the
Foundation” or PGLAF), owns a compilation copyright in the
collection of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works. Nearly all the
individual works in the collection are in the public domain in the
United States. If an individual work is unprotected by copyright law in
the United States and you are located in the United States, we do
not claim a right to prevent you from copying, distributing,
performing, displaying or creating derivative works based on the
work as long as all references to Project Gutenberg are removed. Of
course, we hope that you will support the Project Gutenberg™
mission of promoting free access to electronic works by freely
sharing Project Gutenberg™ works in compliance with the terms of
this agreement for keeping the Project Gutenberg™ name
associated with the work. You can easily comply with the terms of
this agreement by keeping this work in the same format with its
attached full Project Gutenberg™ License when you share it without
charge with others.

1.D. The copyright laws of the place where you are located also
govern what you can do with this work. Copyright laws in most
countries are in a constant state of change. If you are outside the
United States, check the laws of your country in addition to the terms
of this agreement before downloading, copying, displaying,
performing, distributing or creating derivative works based on this
work or any other Project Gutenberg™ work. The Foundation makes
no representations concerning the copyright status of any work in
any country other than the United States.

1.E. Unless you have removed all references to Project Gutenberg:

1.E.1. The following sentence, with active links to, or other


immediate access to, the full Project Gutenberg™ License must
appear prominently whenever any copy of a Project Gutenberg™
work (any work on which the phrase “Project Gutenberg” appears, or
with which the phrase “Project Gutenberg” is associated) is
accessed, displayed, performed, viewed, copied or distributed:
This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere in the United
States and most other parts of the world at no cost and with
almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away
or re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License
included with this eBook or online at www.gutenberg.org. If you
are not located in the United States, you will have to check the
laws of the country where you are located before using this
eBook.

1.E.2. If an individual Project Gutenberg™ electronic work is derived


from texts not protected by U.S. copyright law (does not contain a
notice indicating that it is posted with permission of the copyright
holder), the work can be copied and distributed to anyone in the
United States without paying any fees or charges. If you are
redistributing or providing access to a work with the phrase “Project
Gutenberg” associated with or appearing on the work, you must
comply either with the requirements of paragraphs 1.E.1 through
1.E.7 or obtain permission for the use of the work and the Project
Gutenberg™ trademark as set forth in paragraphs 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.

1.E.3. If an individual Project Gutenberg™ electronic work is posted


with the permission of the copyright holder, your use and distribution
must comply with both paragraphs 1.E.1 through 1.E.7 and any
additional terms imposed by the copyright holder. Additional terms
will be linked to the Project Gutenberg™ License for all works posted
with the permission of the copyright holder found at the beginning of
this work.

1.E.4. Do not unlink or detach or remove the full Project


Gutenberg™ License terms from this work, or any files containing a
part of this work or any other work associated with Project
Gutenberg™.

1.E.5. Do not copy, display, perform, distribute or redistribute this


electronic work, or any part of this electronic work, without
prominently displaying the sentence set forth in paragraph 1.E.1 with
active links or immediate access to the full terms of the Project
Gutenberg™ License.
1.E.6. You may convert to and distribute this work in any binary,
compressed, marked up, nonproprietary or proprietary form,
including any word processing or hypertext form. However, if you
provide access to or distribute copies of a Project Gutenberg™ work
in a format other than “Plain Vanilla ASCII” or other format used in
the official version posted on the official Project Gutenberg™ website
(www.gutenberg.org), you must, at no additional cost, fee or expense
to the user, provide a copy, a means of exporting a copy, or a means
of obtaining a copy upon request, of the work in its original “Plain
Vanilla ASCII” or other form. Any alternate format must include the
full Project Gutenberg™ License as specified in paragraph 1.E.1.

1.E.7. Do not charge a fee for access to, viewing, displaying,


performing, copying or distributing any Project Gutenberg™ works
unless you comply with paragraph 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.

1.E.8. You may charge a reasonable fee for copies of or providing


access to or distributing Project Gutenberg™ electronic works
provided that:

• You pay a royalty fee of 20% of the gross profits you derive from
the use of Project Gutenberg™ works calculated using the
method you already use to calculate your applicable taxes. The
fee is owed to the owner of the Project Gutenberg™ trademark,
but he has agreed to donate royalties under this paragraph to
the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation. Royalty
payments must be paid within 60 days following each date on
which you prepare (or are legally required to prepare) your
periodic tax returns. Royalty payments should be clearly marked
as such and sent to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation at the address specified in Section 4, “Information
about donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation.”

• You provide a full refund of any money paid by a user who


notifies you in writing (or by e-mail) within 30 days of receipt that
s/he does not agree to the terms of the full Project Gutenberg™
License. You must require such a user to return or destroy all
copies of the works possessed in a physical medium and
discontinue all use of and all access to other copies of Project
Gutenberg™ works.

• You provide, in accordance with paragraph 1.F.3, a full refund of


any money paid for a work or a replacement copy, if a defect in
the electronic work is discovered and reported to you within 90
days of receipt of the work.

• You comply with all other terms of this agreement for free
distribution of Project Gutenberg™ works.

1.E.9. If you wish to charge a fee or distribute a Project Gutenberg™


electronic work or group of works on different terms than are set
forth in this agreement, you must obtain permission in writing from
the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation, the manager of
the Project Gutenberg™ trademark. Contact the Foundation as set
forth in Section 3 below.

1.F.

1.F.1. Project Gutenberg volunteers and employees expend


considerable effort to identify, do copyright research on, transcribe
and proofread works not protected by U.S. copyright law in creating
the Project Gutenberg™ collection. Despite these efforts, Project
Gutenberg™ electronic works, and the medium on which they may
be stored, may contain “Defects,” such as, but not limited to,
incomplete, inaccurate or corrupt data, transcription errors, a
copyright or other intellectual property infringement, a defective or
damaged disk or other medium, a computer virus, or computer
codes that damage or cannot be read by your equipment.

1.F.2. LIMITED WARRANTY, DISCLAIMER OF DAMAGES - Except


for the “Right of Replacement or Refund” described in paragraph
1.F.3, the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation, the owner
of the Project Gutenberg™ trademark, and any other party
distributing a Project Gutenberg™ electronic work under this
agreement, disclaim all liability to you for damages, costs and
expenses, including legal fees. YOU AGREE THAT YOU HAVE NO
REMEDIES FOR NEGLIGENCE, STRICT LIABILITY, BREACH OF
WARRANTY OR BREACH OF CONTRACT EXCEPT THOSE
PROVIDED IN PARAGRAPH 1.F.3. YOU AGREE THAT THE
FOUNDATION, THE TRADEMARK OWNER, AND ANY
DISTRIBUTOR UNDER THIS AGREEMENT WILL NOT BE LIABLE
TO YOU FOR ACTUAL, DIRECT, INDIRECT, CONSEQUENTIAL,
PUNITIVE OR INCIDENTAL DAMAGES EVEN IF YOU GIVE
NOTICE OF THE POSSIBILITY OF SUCH DAMAGE.

1.F.3. LIMITED RIGHT OF REPLACEMENT OR REFUND - If you


discover a defect in this electronic work within 90 days of receiving it,
you can receive a refund of the money (if any) you paid for it by
sending a written explanation to the person you received the work
from. If you received the work on a physical medium, you must
return the medium with your written explanation. The person or entity
that provided you with the defective work may elect to provide a
replacement copy in lieu of a refund. If you received the work
electronically, the person or entity providing it to you may choose to
give you a second opportunity to receive the work electronically in
lieu of a refund. If the second copy is also defective, you may
demand a refund in writing without further opportunities to fix the
problem.

1.F.4. Except for the limited right of replacement or refund set forth in
paragraph 1.F.3, this work is provided to you ‘AS-IS’, WITH NO
OTHER WARRANTIES OF ANY KIND, EXPRESS OR IMPLIED,
INCLUDING BUT NOT LIMITED TO WARRANTIES OF
MERCHANTABILITY OR FITNESS FOR ANY PURPOSE.

1.F.5. Some states do not allow disclaimers of certain implied


warranties or the exclusion or limitation of certain types of damages.
If any disclaimer or limitation set forth in this agreement violates the
law of the state applicable to this agreement, the agreement shall be
interpreted to make the maximum disclaimer or limitation permitted
by the applicable state law. The invalidity or unenforceability of any
provision of this agreement shall not void the remaining provisions.
1.F.6. INDEMNITY - You agree to indemnify and hold the
Foundation, the trademark owner, any agent or employee of the
Foundation, anyone providing copies of Project Gutenberg™
electronic works in accordance with this agreement, and any
volunteers associated with the production, promotion and distribution
of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works, harmless from all liability,
costs and expenses, including legal fees, that arise directly or
indirectly from any of the following which you do or cause to occur:
(a) distribution of this or any Project Gutenberg™ work, (b)
alteration, modification, or additions or deletions to any Project
Gutenberg™ work, and (c) any Defect you cause.

Section 2. Information about the Mission of


Project Gutenberg™
Project Gutenberg™ is synonymous with the free distribution of
electronic works in formats readable by the widest variety of
computers including obsolete, old, middle-aged and new computers.
It exists because of the efforts of hundreds of volunteers and
donations from people in all walks of life.

Volunteers and financial support to provide volunteers with the


assistance they need are critical to reaching Project Gutenberg™’s
goals and ensuring that the Project Gutenberg™ collection will
remain freely available for generations to come. In 2001, the Project
Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation was created to provide a
secure and permanent future for Project Gutenberg™ and future
generations. To learn more about the Project Gutenberg Literary
Archive Foundation and how your efforts and donations can help,
see Sections 3 and 4 and the Foundation information page at
www.gutenberg.org.

Section 3. Information about the Project


Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation
The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation is a non-profit
501(c)(3) educational corporation organized under the laws of the
state of Mississippi and granted tax exempt status by the Internal
Revenue Service. The Foundation’s EIN or federal tax identification
number is 64-6221541. Contributions to the Project Gutenberg
Literary Archive Foundation are tax deductible to the full extent
permitted by U.S. federal laws and your state’s laws.

The Foundation’s business office is located at 809 North 1500 West,


Salt Lake City, UT 84116, (801) 596-1887. Email contact links and up
to date contact information can be found at the Foundation’s website
and official page at www.gutenberg.org/contact

Section 4. Information about Donations to


the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation
Project Gutenberg™ depends upon and cannot survive without
widespread public support and donations to carry out its mission of
increasing the number of public domain and licensed works that can
be freely distributed in machine-readable form accessible by the
widest array of equipment including outdated equipment. Many small
donations ($1 to $5,000) are particularly important to maintaining tax
exempt status with the IRS.

The Foundation is committed to complying with the laws regulating


charities and charitable donations in all 50 states of the United
States. Compliance requirements are not uniform and it takes a
considerable effort, much paperwork and many fees to meet and
keep up with these requirements. We do not solicit donations in
locations where we have not received written confirmation of
compliance. To SEND DONATIONS or determine the status of
compliance for any particular state visit www.gutenberg.org/donate.

While we cannot and do not solicit contributions from states where


we have not met the solicitation requirements, we know of no
prohibition against accepting unsolicited donations from donors in
such states who approach us with offers to donate.

International donations are gratefully accepted, but we cannot make


any statements concerning tax treatment of donations received from
outside the United States. U.S. laws alone swamp our small staff.

Please check the Project Gutenberg web pages for current donation
methods and addresses. Donations are accepted in a number of
other ways including checks, online payments and credit card
donations. To donate, please visit: www.gutenberg.org/donate.

Section 5. General Information About Project


Gutenberg™ electronic works
Professor Michael S. Hart was the originator of the Project
Gutenberg™ concept of a library of electronic works that could be
freely shared with anyone. For forty years, he produced and
distributed Project Gutenberg™ eBooks with only a loose network of
volunteer support.

Project Gutenberg™ eBooks are often created from several printed


editions, all of which are confirmed as not protected by copyright in
the U.S. unless a copyright notice is included. Thus, we do not
necessarily keep eBooks in compliance with any particular paper
edition.

Most people start at our website which has the main PG search
facility: www.gutenberg.org.

This website includes information about Project Gutenberg™,


including how to make donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary
Archive Foundation, how to help produce our new eBooks, and how
to subscribe to our email newsletter to hear about new eBooks.

You might also like