Instant Ebooks Textbook Heidegger and Unconcealment Truth Language and History 5th Edition Mark A. Wrathall Download All Chapters
Instant Ebooks Textbook Heidegger and Unconcealment Truth Language and History 5th Edition Mark A. Wrathall Download All Chapters
Instant Ebooks Textbook Heidegger and Unconcealment Truth Language and History 5th Edition Mark A. Wrathall Download All Chapters
com
https://ebookgate.com/product/heidegger-and-
unconcealment-truth-language-and-history-5th-
edition-mark-a-wrathall/
https://ebookgate.com/product/heidegger-s-platonism-1st-edition-
mark-a-ralkowski/
https://ebookgate.com/product/a-history-of-the-english-
language-5th-edition-albert-c-baugh/
https://ebookgate.com/product/truth-and-truth-bearers-meaning-in-
context-volume-ii-1st-edition-mark-richard/
https://ebookgate.com/product/heidegger-and-happiness-dwelling-
on-fitting-and-being-1st-edition-heidegger/
The Earth and Its Peoples A Global History 5th Ed 5th
Edition Richard W. Bulliet
https://ebookgate.com/product/the-earth-and-its-peoples-a-global-
history-5th-ed-5th-edition-richard-w-bulliet/
https://ebookgate.com/product/the-death-of-truth-5th-edition-
steven-brill/
https://ebookgate.com/product/kant-art-and-art-history-moments-
of-discipline-mark-a-cheetham/
https://ebookgate.com/product/the-earth-and-its-peoples-a-global-
history-vol-c-5th-ed-5th-edition-richard-bulliet/
https://ebookgate.com/product/truth-history-and-politics-in-
mongolia-memory-of-heroes-chris-kaplonski/
Heidegger and Unconcealment
Truth, Language, and History
This book includes ten essays that trace the notion of unconcealment
as it develops from Martin Heidegger’s early writings to his later
work, shaping his philosophy of truth, language, and history.
Unconcealment is the idea that what entities are depends on the
conditions that allow them to manifest themselves. This concept,
central to Heidegger’s work, also applies to worlds in a dual sense:
first, a condition of entities manifesting themselves is the existence of
a world; and second, worlds themselves are disclosed. The unconceal-
ment or disclosure of a world is the most important historical event,
and Heidegger believes there have been a number of quite distinct
worlds that have emerged and disappeared in history.
Heidegger’s thought as a whole can profitably be seen as working
out the implications of the original understanding of unconcealment.
MARK A. WRATHALL
University of California, Riverside
For Amy, Hannah, Damon, Madeline, and Nicholas
Contents
Acknowledgments page ix
Credits xi
Introduction 1
1 Unconcealment 11
Appendix on Tugendhat 34
2 The Conditions of Truth in Heidegger
and Davidson 40
3 On the “Existential Positivity of Our Ability
to be Deceived” 57
4 Heidegger on Plato, Truth, and Unconcealment:
The 1931–1932 Lecture on The Essence of Truth 72
PART II LANGUAGE
vii
viii Contents
9 Between the Earth and the Sky: Heidegger on Life After the
Death of God 195
10 Nietzsche and the Metaphysics of Truth 212
ix
x Acknowledgments
Robert Pippin, Richard Rorty, Hans Ruin, Charles Siewert, Hans Sluga,
Charles Taylor, Iain Thomson, Ari Uhlin, and Julian Young. Finally, I
am grateful to Beatrice Rehl, Emily Spangler, and Luane Hutchinson
at Cambridge University Press for their patience, encouragement, and
professionalism.
Credits
xi
Introduction
1
2 Heidegger and Unconcealment
(and this is a nonexhaustive list): the formal sense (der formale Sinn), the
original sense (der ursprünglichen Sinn), the authentic sense (der eigentlichen
Sinn), the essential sense (der wesentlichen Sinn), and the ontological sense
(der ontologische Sinn). It would be worthwhile to tease out the subtle distinc-
tions between each of these different senses, but for present purposes we
must summarize.
Heidegger defines sense in general in the following way:
Sense is that within which the intelligibility of something holds itself, without itself
expressly and thematically coming into view. “Sense” means the “onto which” of the
primary projection, from out of which something can be grasped as that which it is
in its possibility. Projecting opens up possibilities, which is to say that it makes
possible. (GA 2: H. 151)
What matters most in reading Heidegger is travelling at his side along his
ways, letting him guide us through the philosophical landscape until we
begin to discern the phenomena and understand the philosophical issues
posed by the phenomena. His philosophy is meant to afford us an appren-
ticeship in seeing and describing unconcealment.
Heidegger’s account of unconcealment emerged from his efforts to think
through the essence of truth, as well as the conditions that make truth
possible. The essays in the first section explore Heidegger’s account of
propositional truth and his argument that propositional truth necessarily
depends on unconcealment. Chapter 1 looks at the various facets of
6 Heidegger and Unconcealment
Alêtheia means, translated literally: unconcealment. Yet little is gained with liter-
alness . . . . Alêtheia does not mean “truth,” if by that one means the validity of
assertions in the form of propositions. It is possible that what is to be thought in
alêtheia, speaking strictly for itself, does not yet have anything to do with “truth,”
whereas it has everything to do with unconcealment, which is presupposed in every
determination of “truth.” (GA 15: 403)
The first chapter in the second section, Chapter 5, explores the sense in
which, in Being and Time, Heidegger thinks of linguistic meaning as depend-
ent on a socially disclosed world. The next essay explores the meaning of one
of Heidegger’s most famous assertions – “language is the house of being” – as
a way of understanding how Heidegger’s account of language develops but
always remains closely tied to a notion of unconcealment. This chapter
chronicles how Heidegger moved from using the word language in the
ordinary sense to an ontologically broad use of the term in his later works
to name the structure of gathering significations that characterizes any
particular world disclosure. The final essay in the section can be thought of
as a particular application of this account of originary language, drawing on
both Heidegger and Pascal to explore a phenomenological account of the
role the Bible plays in opening up the Christian world. By focusing on
the Christian world, this essay also serves as a transition to the final section
of the book, which looks at Heidegger’s understanding of history as a series
of epochs of unconcealment.
The first essay in the history section of the book offers an overview of the
idea that history should be thought of in terms of unconcealment and thus as
a sequence of different world disclosures. The history that interests
Heidegger is a history of different ways in which entities are able to show
themselves. The “essence of history,” Heidegger explains, shows itself in
the “separation of the truth of entities from possibilities of essence that
are kept in store and permitted but in each case not now implemented”
8 Heidegger and Unconcealment
(GA 69: 162). From the perspective of unconcealment, then, historical ages
are understood as the establishment of a “truth of entities” – a truth about
what entities really are – which is secured in its truth by separating off one set
of possibilities from other admissible sets of possibilities, sets of ways to
understand and use and relate the entities.
On this view, different entities show themselves in different historical
ages, because each age is grounded in a different unconcealment of being,
with correspondingly different possibilities showing up as definitive of enti-
ties. The transition from one age to another thus poses a danger that entities
will be denied the context within which they can show what they once were
(or could be). This happened, for instance, when God was drawn into a
world that understands constitutive relations in terms of efficient causality:
In whatever manner the destiny of disclosing may prevail, unconcealment, in which
everything that is shows itself at any given time, holds the danger that human beings
mistake themselves in the midst of what is unconcealed and misinterpret it. In this
way, where everything presencing presents itself in the light of connections of cause
and effect, in our representations of him even God can lose all that is high and holy,
the mysteriousness of his distance. In the light of causality, God can be degraded to a
cause, to the causa efficiens. He then even becomes the God of the philosophers,
namely that which determines the unconcealed and concealed according to the
causality of making, without ever considering the origin of the essence of this
causality. (GA 7:30)
Heidegger was particular concerned that the technological age, our con-
temporary age, was closing off possibilities that allow us to realize the “high-
est dignity of our essence as human beings.” Our highest dignity, and thus
what we are engaged in when we are most fully realizing what it is to be
human, is “to guard over the unconcealment of every essence on this earth”
(GA 7: 36). Chapter 9 explores Heidegger’s hope that we could escape from
the technological age by means of a new disclosure of the world, one opened
up by our relationship to the fourfold of gods, mortals, the earth, and the sky.
Chapter 10 draws the book full circle by using Heidegger’s critique of
Nietzsche’s account of truth to illuminate how Heidegger understands our
current historical age, as it reviews Heidegger’s interpretation of Nietzsche
as the thinker of this technological epoch. It also outlines how Heidegger
thinks of the history of philosophy as a history of metaphysics, and explores
his account of metaphysics in terms of the truth of entities.
The chapters in this book span the last ten years of my own engagement
with Heidegger’s thought. Like Heidegger himself, I have experimented
with different ways to approach the matter to be thought. These essays
manifest a variety of approaches to understanding and expressing his
views. For this collection, I have made some changes to these essays. But I
also have tried to be tolerant of the fact that I would no longer express many
of these ideas in the way I did when I first set out on the trail of
unconcealment.
part i
Unconcealment
During the two decades between 1925 and 1945, the essence of truth is a
pervasive issue in Heidegger’s work. He offers several essay courses devoted
to the nature of truth, starting in 1925 with Logik. Die Frage nach der
Wahrheit, (GA 21), and continuing with Vom Wesen der Wahrheit. Zu Platons
Höhlengleichnis and Theätet (Winter Semester 1931–2, GA 34), Vom Wesen der
Wahrheit (Winter Semester 1933–4, GA 36–7), and Grundfragen der
Philosophie. Ausgewählte “Probleme” der “Logik” (Winter Semester 1937–8,
GA 45). He also includes a significant discussion of the essence of truth
in virtually every other lecture course taught during this period.
Particularly notable in this regard are the Parmenides lecture course of
1942–3 (GA 54), Einleitung in die Philosophie (Winter Semester 1928–9,
GA 27), and Nietzsches Lehre vom Willen zur Macht als Erkenntnis (Summer
Semester 1939, GA 47).
Heidegger’s writings during this period also reflect his preoccupation
with truth. In addition to the essay “Vom Wesen der Wahrheit” (GA 9),
many of his other works include extended discussions of the essence of
truth. These include Being and Time (GA 2), essays like “Vom Wesen des
Grundes” (GA 9), “Der Ursprung des Kunstwerkes” (GA 5), and “Was ist
Metaphysik?” (GA 9), and unpublished works like the Beiträge (GA 65) and
Besinnung (GA 66).
After 1946, by contrast, there are few extended discussions of truth in
Heidegger’s writings. Indeed, in the last few decades of his work, Heidegger
rarely even mentions the essence of truth (des Wesen der Wahrheit) or the
question of truth (die Wahrheitsfrage; although other locutions like the truth
of being, die Wahrheit des Seins, persist, albeit infrequently, right to the end;
Research for this chapter was funded in part by the David M. Kennedy Center for International
and Area Studies at Brigham Young University.
11
12 Truth and Disclosure
see, for example, the 1973 “Seminar in Zähringen,” GA 15: 373). But this
should be seen as a merely terminological shift. For Heidegger, the essence
of truth is always understood in terms of unconcealment, and Heidegger
never stops inquiring into unconcealment. Indeed, one is hard-pressed to
find any work in Heidegger’s vast corpus that does not have some discussion
of unconcealment.
The terminological shift from talk of truth to unconcealment is a result
of his recognition of the misleadingness of using the word truth to name
unconcealment – a recognition brought about by the gradual realization
that the metaphysical tradition’s blindness to unconcealment is largely a
result of a rather narrow notion of truth. “In the beginning of metaphysics,
it was decided that the essence of truth as alêtheia (unconcealment and
revealing) would henceforth retreat before the determination of truth as
likening (homoiôsis, adaequatio), . . . a determination that was first rooted in
truth as unconcealment.” From that point on, Heidegger argues, truth’s
“character of opening up and revealing sinks unquestioned into oblivion”
(GA 6.2: 286). And as he explains in 1949:
In its answers to the question concerning entities as such, metaphysics operates
with a prior representation of being necessarily and hence continually. But meta-
physics does not induce being itself to speak, for metaphysics does not give thought
to being in its truth, nor does it think such truth as unconcealment, nor does it
think this unconcealment in its essence. (GA 9: 369/280)
From this point on, Heidegger speaks and writes consistently of the essence
of unconcealment, rather than the essence of truth. It is also clear that,
despite using the word truth to name the subject matter of his thought, his
primary interest was always unconcealment. As he notes self-reflectively
during the “Heraclitus Seminar” (1966–7), “Alêtheia as unconcealment
occupied me all along, but ‘truth’ slipped itself in between” (GA 15: 262).
But while he is occasionally critical of his own earlier views of the essence
of truth (see, e.g., GA 65: 351–2), his view of it remains unchanged in its
fundamental outline.
The fundamental outline, or what I call the platform, of Heidegger’s
view of truth forms the basis both for his critique of the metaphysical
tradition of philosophy, and for his own constructive account of ontology
and the nature of human being. It includes the following planks.
1. Propositional truth (correctness, Richtigkeit). An assertion or proposi-
tion is true when it corresponds with a state of affairs.
Heidegger understands correspondence (Übereinstimmung) as the condition
of being successfully directed toward the world in a propositional attitude:
What makes every one of these statements into a true one? This: in what it says, it
corresponds with the matters and the states of affairs about which it says some-
thing. The being true of an assertion thus signifies such corresponding. What
Unconcealment 13
(a) The disclosure (Erschlossenheit) of Dasein and of the world. The idea is
that entities can only be available for comportment on the basis of a
prior disclosure of the world as the meaningful relational structure
within which entities can show up as what they are. In addition, since
entities are uncovered in terms of their availability for comportment,
14 Truth and Disclosure
What both (3a) and (3b) have in common is the insight that entities can
only be manifest on the basis of a prelinguistic understanding of and affec-
tive disposedness to what makes something the being that it is.
Heidegger eventually comes to believe that the truth of being depends on:
UNCONCEALMENT IN GENERAL
1
These include discoveredness (Entdecktheit) and uncoveredness (Unverdecktheit); disclosedness
(Erschlossenheit), unveiledness (Enthülltheit), and disconcealedness (Entborgenheit).
2
Friedrich Nietzsche, On the Genealogy of Morals (Douglas Smith, Trans.). Oxford, England:
Oxford University Press, 1996, p. 13.
18 Truth and Disclosure
1. Propositional Truth
One typically thinks of truth as a property of things that have as their
content a proposition – things like assertions and beliefs. The truth of
propositions is, for Heidegger, the right starting point for thinking about
unconcealment, because truth or unconcealment (alêtheia) has often been
understood exclusively as a property of propositions, but also because in a
phenomenology of propositional truth, we quickly discover that the truth
of propositions depends on the uncovering of entities. Thinking about
propositional truth thus leads to an inquiry into more fundamental forms
of unconcealment.
Heidegger accepts that many propositions are true by corresponding to,
or agreeing with, the way things are. But recognizing this fact, for Heidegger,
is less an explanation of truth than a basis for further inquiry into its nature.
The old received definition of truth: veritas est adaequatio Intellectus ad rem, homoiôsis,
measuring up, conformity of thinking to the matter about which it thinks – is
indeed basically (im Ansatz) correct. But it is also merely a starting point (Ansatz)
and not at all that which it is commonly taken to be, namely, an essential determi-
nation of truth or the result of an essential determination of truth. It is merely the
starting point . . . for the question: in what in general is the possibility of measuring
up to something grounded? (GA 29/30: 497)
entities consists in entities not being available as that toward which or with
which we can comport.
Comportment (Verhalten) is a very broad term that is meant to include
every instance in which we experience something, and everything that we
do. Excluded from comportment, then, are physiological or merely causal
events or behaviors. When I grow hair or hiccup, there is no sense in which
I am comporting myself. Unlike such causal events or behaviors, comport-
ments have a meaningful structure. But comportment is broader than the
class of deliberate actions (although, naturally it includes them), because
comportment involves things I do or experience without an occurrent
mental state in which I intend to do it or register the experience. Thus
comportment includes automatic reflexes, for example, which reflect a
responsiveness to the meaning of a situation.
All comportments involve relationships to entities. When I swat at a fly,
I am comporting myself toward the fly. When I hear a symphony, I am
comporting myself to the symphony (as well as all the instruments, musi-
cians, the conductor, etc.) An entity is concealed, then, when I cannot
comport myself toward it – when it is not available as something toward
which I can direct myself in a basic intentional comportment or when it
plays no role in setting the meaningful structure of the situation I am in.
The opposite of uncoveredness, Heidegger says, “is not covering up, but
rather lack of access for simple intending” (GA 21: 179). The fly is
concealed in a sense when I cannot find it to swat at it. And yet even
then, it is uncovered to some extent, given that the situation I find myself
in is structured by my desire to swat the fly. A more radical concealment
of the fly, then, would obtain if I do not feel motivated in any way to react
to it. Similarly, the symphony would be concealed if I lacked an under-
standing of symphonic form (that is, I might be able to hear beautiful
music, but I could not hear it as a symphony). The contrast of comport-
ments with behaviors allows us to see that something can be concealed,
even if it is physically operative on my body. But because comportment is
broader than intentional action, something is not necessarily concealed,
even if I have no awareness of it whatsoever – there is a sense in which it
is unconcealed as long as it figures meaningfully in my overall comport-
mental stance.
The unconcealment of entities, then, will be a privation of the state of
affairs in which something is unavailable for comportment. But, as I have
been suggesting, there are a variety of different ways in which something
can be unavailable for comportment:
For that which is unconcealed, it is not only essential that it makes that which
appears accessible in some way or other and keeps it open in its appearing, but
rather that it (that which is unconcealed) constantly overcomes a concealedness of
the concealed. That which is unconcealed must be wrested away from concealment,
Unconcealment 23
it must in a certain sense be stolen . . . . Truth is thus in each case a wresting away in
the way of revealing. What is more, the concealment can be of various kinds: closing
off, hiding away, disguising, covering up, veiling, dissimulating. (GA 9: 223)
Thus the unconcealment of entities occurs in all the different ways we have
of making something available for comportment. But, Heidegger believes,
in order to understand uncovering, the primary mode of comportment to
focus on is that in which we have a practical mastery of things. It should be
obvious that this sort of uncovering does not require the mediation of
language. I can learn to deal with things without any explicit instruction in
them or even any names for them, simply by picking them up and starting
to manipulate them, or by being shown how they work. Heidegger writes:
The predominant comportment through which in general we uncover innerworldly
entities is the utilization, the use of commonly used objects (Gebrauchsdingen): deal-
ing with vehicles, sewing kits, writing equipment, work tools in order to . . . equip-
ment in the widest sense. We first get to know the equipment in dealing with it.
It is not that we have beforehand a knowledge of these things in order then to
put them to use, but rather the other way around . . . . The everyday dealing with
innerworldly entities is the primary mode – and for many often the only mode – of
uncovering the world. This dealing with innerworldly entities comports itself – as
utilization, use, managing, producing and so forth – toward equipment and the context
of equipment . . . we make use of it in a “self-evident manner.” (GA 25: 21–2)
The basic reason is that entities are independent of us and our wishes,
desires, intentions, and purposes for them, as well as our beliefs about
them. This fact gives rise to a fundamental concealment in at least two
ways. First, it means that uncovering an entity – making it something with
which we can comport easily and transparently – demands something of
us. It requires us to struggle to foster and develop the right skills, attitudes,
and bodily dispositions for dealing with it, that is, those skills that will let
it show itself in its own essence. Heidegger illustrates this through the
example of walking into a shoemaker’s workshop. “Which entities are
there and how these entities are available, in line with their inherent
character, is unveiled for us only in dealing appropriately with equipment
such as tools, leather, and shoes. Only one who understands is able
to uncover by himself this environing world of the shoemaker’s” (GA
24: 431). This means that, for most of us, the entities in the workshop
are not fully uncovered, and could only become uncovered as we acquire a
shoemaker’s skills. What holds of the shoemaker’s shop, of course, holds
for the world as a whole:
it is only in the tiniest spheres of the beings with which we are acquainted that we
are so well versed as to have at our command the specific way of dealing with
equipment which uncovers this equipment as such. The entire range of intra-
worldly beings accessible to us at any time is not suitably accessible to us in an
equally original way. There are many things we merely know something about but
do not know how to manage with them. They confront us as beings to be sure, but
as unfamiliar beings. Many beings, including even those already uncovered, have
the character of unfamiliarity. (GA 24: 431–2)
skillful we get in dealing with entities, Heidegger argues, there will always
be something about them that we cannot focus on or pay attention to:
“each being we encounter and which encounters us keeps to this curious
opposition of presenting, in which it always holds itself back in a conceal-
ment” (GA 5: 40/BW 178). But this concealment “is not in every case
primarily and merely the limit of knowledge,” rather, it is precisely what
makes it possible for us to deal with the thing in the first place: it is “the
beginning of the clearing of what is cleared” (GA 5: 40/BW 178–9). We
get a grip on entities in the world, in other words, by generalizing, by
dealing with them as instances of a known type. This leads to the possibility
that established ways of dealing with things will make it harder to uncover
other possible ways of dealing with them. When “what is familiar becomes
known,” Heidegger notes, “with that the concealedness of the unfamiliar
deepens, and all that is not-known becomes more insistent in its conceal-
ment” (GA 28: 361).
That our familiarity depends on getting a certain more or less familiar
grasp on things leads to the possibility that we treat something as an instance
of the wrong type – that is, that based on a superficial similarity between a
strange thing and a familiar thing, we take the strange thing as something
it is not (or, as Heidegger puts it, “a being appears, but presents itself as
other than it is”; GA 5: 40/BW 179). Thus something can be uncovered
in one sense but covered over in another sense.
To recap, the specific nature of the unconcealment involved in the
uncoveredness of entities needs to be understood as a privation of the
fundamental covered-up-ness of entities. They are covered up to the extent
that we lack the skills necessary to allow them to figure in the overall grasp we
get on a situation. We uncover them by fostering a receptivity to them, a
receptivity that helps us secure our practical grasp on the situation.
Human Dasein – a being that finds itself situated in the midst of beings, comporting
itself toward beings – in so doing exists in such a way that beings are always
manifest as a whole. Here it is not necessary that this wholeness be expressly
conceptualized: its belonging to Dasein can be veiled, the expanse of this whole
is changeable. This wholeness is understood without the whole of those beings that
are manifest being explicitly grasped or indeed “completely” investigated in their
specific connections, domains, and layers. Yet the understanding of this wholeness,
an understanding that in each case reaches ahead and embraces it, is a surpassing
in the direction of world . . . . World as a wholeness “is” not a being, but that from
out of which Dasein gives itself the signification of whatever beings it is able to
comport itself toward in whatever way. (GA 9: 156/121)
itself an original view (form) that is not explicitly grasped, yet functions
precisely as a paradigmatic form for all manifest beings” (GA 9: 158/123).
Heidegger subsequently develops this idea in terms of the truth of
essence – plank 3b) In the 1929–30 lecture course on The Fundamental
Concepts of Metaphysics, Heidegger argues that the world should be under-
stood as the prevailing of a “pre-logical manifestness” of beings “as such
and as a whole” (GA 29/30: 512–13). But any sufficient inquiry into the
origin of the “as” in the “as such” and “as a whole” – that is, that as that entities
show up – “must open up for us the whole context in which that, which
we intend with ‘manifestness of beings’ and with the ‘as a whole’, comes
into its essence (west)” (GA 29/30: 435–6). A comment is in order here
on the way that Heidegger thinks of essences.
For some reason, most translators and many commentators are hyper-
sensitive about Heidegger’s use of Wesen (essence) and related neologisms
like Wesung (essencing) and wesen with a small “w” – that is, wesen as a verb,
meaning “to essence” or “to come into its essence.” These commentators
have really taken to heart Heidegger’s warning that he does not mean to
use Wesen in the traditional sense – so much so that they seem to translate
the word randomly (as, e.g., perdurance or presence or, my favorite
example from the translation of the Beiträge, essential swaying). All such
choices avoid any metaphysical baggage, but at the cost of confusion or
incomprehensibility. I think it is better to translate Wesen in the straight-
forward way as essence but then explain how Heidegger thinks of essences
(as hard as that might be).
As I understand it, Heidegger’s disagreement with many views of es-
sences are that they define what a thing is in terms of some necessary
property that all X things must have, or some universal property that all X
things in fact have. In the “Origin of the Work of Art,” Heidegger calls this
kind of essence the unimportant/indifferent essence (das gleichgültige
Wesen) or the unessential essence (des unwesentliche Wesen). The traditional
way of thinking of an essence, Heidegger notes, thinks of it in terms of the
common features in which all things that share an essence agree.
The essence gives itself in the generic and universal concept, which represents the
one feature that holds indifferently for many things. This indifferent essence (essen-
tiality in the sense of essentia) is, however, only the unessential essence. In what does
the essential essence of something consist? Presumably it lies in what the entity is
in truth. The true essence of a thing is determined from out of its true being, from
the truth of the given entity. (GA 5: 37/BW 175–6, translation modified)
to the world in the second way uncovers it, she will take the essential
properties to be whatever it is about it that allows us to break it down into
a resource, and flexibly switch it around and order it, since our background
sense for technological efficiency shapes our experience of everything.
In fact, there is, in principle, an indefinite if not infinite number of
ways to characterize the properties of any particular thing. A piece of
gold, for instance, has a color and a weight and a texture and a shape,
but also all sorts of other properties like being good (or bad) for making
jewelry, gleaming in a way that seems divine, being directly in front of my
favorite chair, and so on. When we decide what kind or type of thing this
particular object is, we will do it on the basis of just those particular
properties we are responding to, and these properties will be some subset
of an indefinite or infinite set of properties we could be responding to.
Given that this is the case, before anything can show up as anything, we
must have some particular, prelinguistic disposition or readiness for the
world that leads us to see certain features as more important than others.
All understandings of what things are thus arise on the basis of a back-
ground disposition to the world. We disclose the essences that we do,
according to Heidegger, because the way we are moved by or disposed to
things allows a particular style of being “to be ascendent” (see GA 45: 129).
As a result, there is no longer any need to see (C) and (D) as incompat-
ible. There might be a culture whose sensibilities for the world lead it to
uncover an instance of gold as having just those essential properties speci-
fied in (D) – in fact, Heidegger would probably argue, those are just the
essential properties we would find in a lump of gold if we were oriented to
the world in a technological fashion. We do not need to see (D) as true a
priori, because whether it is true is up to the world. Instead, we will use our
technological disposition to pick out objects as instances of that kind of
resource; from there, it is an empirical matter which features of it make it that
kind of a resource. In our age, it seems plausible to say that gold’s essential
features (in the traditional sense) are found in its atomic structure, because
knowledge of the atomic structure gives us the best grasp on how to turn
gold into a resource. The possibility of truth is secured because there is a way
that the world opens itself up or is unconcealed, a coherent mode of being,
and thus the world can serve as a standard for our thoughts and words.
In summary, then, the unconcealment of beings is the “anticipatory
gathering” that lays out certain properties and relationships as salient
(see GA 45: 121). This means that essences are historical – they show up
differently as dispositions for the world change.
This brings us to the last, and most difficult, feature of Heidegger’s plat-
form of unconcealment. Because of the historical nature of the disclosure
Unconcealment 33
presence, and grants the possible presencing of that presence itself” (GA 14:
75/BW 445). We will explore examples of this function of unconcealment
in the chapters on history (see Chapters 8–10), because Heidegger under-
stands the movement of history as a series of different modes of presence.
The clearing makes it possible for a certain understanding of being – a
particular mode of presence – to come to prevail among entities. For
possibilities to be live possibilities, however, it requires a space from which
other incompatible possibilities are excluded. The clearing maintains a
world by keeping back (concealing) possibilities that are incompatible with
the essence that is currently operative. In order for some possibilities to
shape our experience of the world, any other possibilities cannot be live
possibilities, they cannot be possible for us, they must be kept from us.
This might make it sound like the clearing is a gallery of possibilities –
that it keeps different determinate ways of being in the world locked in
the back room while exhibiting one at a time. But this would be to think
about it incorrectly – it would be to treat ways of being as if they were
themselves in being. But ways of being are not unless entities are consti-
tuted by them. So the clearing is not a hiding of other modes of being, any
more than a clearing in the forest is a hiding of trees. The forest clearing
does not work by keeping some particular trees or shrubs on hand but out
of the way. Rather, the forest clearing is nothing but the condition that
there are no trees or shrubs growing.
Similarly, the clearing makes some possibilities possible, not by putting
some determinate possibilities in cold storage, but by making it the case
that there are no other determinate possibilities available. For the available
possibilities to have authority as possibilities, moreover, we cannot be
aware that other possibilities are being ruled out or concealed from us.
Our experience of the natural world as resources, for example, could not
authoritatively shape our experience of the world if we were aware that
one would be equally justified in experiencing it as God’s creation. This
means that, paradoxically, the clearing only works as a clearing when it is
not uncovered – when it is not something toward which we can comport.
Thus the clearing does not only keep back other possibilities, but it keeps
back that it is keeping back other possibilities. The clearing conceals the
possibility of other understandings of beings. It is not “the mere clearing
of presence, but the clearing of presence concealing itself, the clearing of
a self-concealing sheltering” (GA 14: 79/BW 448).
APPENDIX ON TUGENDHAT
3
Ernst Tugendhat, “Heidegger’s Idea of Truth,” in Hermeneutics and Truth (Brice
R. Wachterhauser, Ed.). Evanston, IL: Northwestern University Press, 1994, p. 85.
4
Heidegger, Language, and World Disclosure, p. 116.
36 Truth and Disclosure
5
“Why Tugendhat’s Critique of Heidegger’s Concept of Truth Remains a Critical Problem,”
Inquiry 50 (2007): 164.
6
Heidegger, Language, and World Disclosure, p. 123.
Another random document with
no related content on Scribd:
ambition of Julius resulted in disgrace to himself, and humiliation to
the institution which he so eagerly sought to glorify.
A gentleman, one dark night, riding home through a wood, had the
misfortune to strike his head against the branch of a tree, and fell
from his horse, stunned by the blow. The animal immediately
returning to the house which they had left, about a mile distant,
found the door closed and the family retired to bed.
He then pawed at the door, till one of them, hearing the noise,
arose and opened it, and to his surprise found the horse of his
friend. No sooner was the door opened than the horse turned round,
and the man, suspecting there was something wrong, followed the
animal, who led him directly to the spot where his master lay on the
ground in a state of insensibility.
Eccentric Characters
richard dickinson.
Hunting adventures.
Some time now passed without any remarkable event. After a
hunting or war expedition, the Indian men usually spend a large part
of their time in idleness. For several weeks after their return, the
warriors might be seen stretched at full length in their wigwams
upon the beds of skins, and often, during the day, upon the bare
ground, basking in the warm sunshine.
Thus they would repose day and night, sleeping a part of the
time, and dozing away the rest of the hours. When hungry, they
arose and ate the meal provided for them by the women, and then
returned to their rest. At this period, they seemed like mere animals,
such as wolves or foxes, idly slumbering in their caves, careless of
the past, the present and the future.
Once in a while these men would rouse themselves from their
indolence, and spend a night in a wild war-dance, or in other sports.
When excited in their amusements, they shook off their lethargy and
seemed totally changed from the stupid beings which they appeared
to be, a few hours before. Their black eyes would now flash with
fiery excitement; their parted lips would display their white teeth;
their long, black hair would stream in the wind; their hands and
arms would exhibit the most animated gestures, and their whole
form seem to be animated by intense excitement. After the sport
was over, these warriors would relapse into the same state of merely
animal existence, as if they had no minds, no cares, no plans, no
fears or hopes.
Thus some weeks passed away, but at last, it became necessary
that a supply of food should be obtained. It is true that some small
game was obtained by the boys, and some of the men, almost every
day. This consisted of the heath hen, which resembles the partridge
or pheasant of the Atlantic states; black and grey squirrels, rabbits
and hares, wild turkeys, raccoons, prairie dogs, &c. These creatures
were abundant, and I often accompanied the young Indians in
hunting them.
There were some guns and rifles in the tribe, but the chief
weapons were the bow and arrow. The boys and most of the young
men had no other. It was surprising to see with what precision and
force the arrows were thrown. I have often seen a squirrel, perched
upon the limb of an aged tree, and being nearly a hundred feet in
air, look down as if to laugh and jeer at the sportsman below; when
the arrow was sent from the string, and, striking him in the head,
brought him whirling and sprawling to the ground.
In these hunts I took a keen delight; and such was my enterprise
and success, that I soon became rather famous as a hunter of the
lesser game. My agility in pursuing a wounded bird or quadruped,
and the facility with which I threaded the tangled forests, gave me
the title of Jumping Rabbit, which long continued to be my name.
In these hunts, we seldom wandered to any great distance from
the encampment, and rarely remained out over night. In a few
instances, we were absent for two or three days, and extended our
excursions to the distance of twenty or thirty miles.
I recollect that in one of these expeditions, we came to a
considerable lake, entirely surrounded with dense forests. It was
difficult even to peep through the woods, for the trees stood very
close together, and the spaces between them were choked up with
dead trunks and branches, woven and wedged together, as if the
whole constituted one fabric.
With a great deal of labor, creeping and winding like serpents
through the openings, we made our way through the forest, and
came to the shores of the lake. Accustomed, as I then was, to
nature in her wild moods, the scene that then presented itself,
greatly surprised me. The forest that encircled the lake, consisted, to
a great extent, of lofty firs, which stood close to the water, and
formed, around its whole border, what seemed to be a dark green
wall, rising almost to the clouds, and thus bestowing upon the spot
an aspect of the most perfect protection and seclusion.
As if won to the place by its security and repose, myriads of
aquatic birds were there, some resting upon its bosom, some wading
in its depths, some standing along its borders, and thousands
winnowing the air above its surface. There were flocks of swans,
with arching necks and snowy bosoms; multitudes of pelicans, either
darting down upon their prey, or lazily digesting their food as they
stood upon the rocks along the shore; and wild geese, and ducks
almost without number. There was the pensive heron, standing half
leg deep in the water, and patiently waiting to snap up some luckless
frog or fish; there was the tall crane, with crested head, and spiteful
countenance, looking keenly into the mud for his meal; and red
flamingoes, standing in rows that looked like files of soldiers.
The scene presented the idea of a paradise for water-birds; a spot
unknown to man, and wholly secured to the use and behoof of its
feathered tenantry. The birds themselves seemed so to regard it, for
such were their habits of confidence, that when we approached
them, they hardly noticed us, or moved from us. We shot a few
arrows among them, and killed several, but this created no general
alarm. One of our party had a rifle, and taking aim at the leader of a
long file of swans that glided upon the water near us, he fired, and
the noble bird, uttering a faint scream, spread his wings for flight,
and fell dead upon the surface. His companions rose heavily from
the lake, and sweeping round and round in the air, settled again
upon the water, encircling their dead companion.
Loaded with game, we now set out for our return; but this
expedition was destined to be signalized by adventures. In our
progress homeward, we had occasion to cross a deep valley, through
which a small rivulet found its way. On the high rocky banks of this
stream our party sat down to rest themselves for an hour or two,
and then set forward. It happened that I had crept into the bushes
and fallen asleep; and when my companions went away, not
observing me, they left me soundly wrapt in repose.
They had been gone a considerable time when I was awoke by a
noise, and looking up, I saw a huge grisly bear at a little distance,
looking steadfastly at me. I knew that the next moment he would be
upon me, and seizing my bow and arrows, I sprang forward, and at
a single bound leaped over the high bank, into the stream. It was
not more than forty feet in width—and I had hardly crossed it, when
I heard the heavy plunge of the bear behind me. Clambering up the
opposite bank with the quickness of a wild-cat, I seized upon the
drooping branches of a tree, and rapidly mounted it. The fierce
beast came close upon me, and seizing the boughs with its claws
and teeth, tore them in a hundred pieces. By this time, however, I
had ascended beyond its reach.
The grisly bear is twice the size of the common bear, and from its
savage disposition and great strength, is altogether the most
dreadful beast of the American continent. But, happily for me, it
does not often climb trees. I therefore felt secure. Pausing on a large
limb of the tree, I looked down at my shaggy acquaintance below.
He had now got over his fury, and gazing in my face with a look of
the deepest interest, he seemed to think, if he did not say—“Oh how
I love you!”
After sitting upon the tree for some time, I began to grow
impatient to be released—but Bruin seemed to have no idea of
parting with me thus. He continued for several hours, sitting upon
his rump, in a kind of brown study, but occasionally looking at me.
At last, growing weary, I reclined against the trunk of the tree, and
my grisly jailer, as if to torment me, lay down upon the ground, and
putting his nose to his tail, seemed to say that he had made up his
mind to stay till I should come down. I waited for some time in
silence, to see if he would not fall asleep and allow me an
opportunity of escape; but the moment I moved a foot or hand, I
could see his keen eye twinkle, thus showing that the sentinel was
awake and watchful.
At last I got out of patience, and selecting a good arrow, I sent it
fiercely at his head. It struck him over the eye, and evidently gave
him great pain, for he growled terribly, and rubbed the wounded
place with his huge paw; and finally he looked up at me, at the
same time curling his lip and showing a set of teeth that made me
shudder. I could easily understand this pantomime, and I knew it to
mean something like this: “Sooner or later, my lad, you must come
down, and these teeth shall take due revenge upon you.”
Night at length came—and still the beast remained at his post. I
caught a little sleep, but I was too fearful of falling to the ground to
get any sound repose. In the morning I heard the call of my
companions, and now knew that they had missed me, and were
come to find me. I answered their shout with a cry that filled the
valley with echoes. The old bear seemed startled; he rose, shook his
shaggy coat, and gazed wistfully around.
Directed by my voice, my friends soon drew near; and when they
came to the opposite bank of the river, I told them my situation and
pointed out Bruin at the foot of the tree. In a moment the rifle was
levelled at my tormentor, and the ball entered his side. Stung with
pain, but not mortally wounded, the monster turned towards his new
enemy. Leaping into the stream, he began to swim across; but his
head being exposed, several arrows were aimed at him, some of
which took effect. As he ascended the rocky bank of the river, the
rifle being re-loaded, was again discharged, and, the ball passing
through his heart, he fell backward, and rolled with a heavy plash
into the stream.
But I have wandered a little from my track. I said that the
necessity of obtaining a supply of food, at last roused the men of the
encampment from their repose. After making due preparation, by
providing themselves with knives, bows and arrows, &c., about
twenty of them departed; and as I was now a tolerably expert
hunter, I was permitted to accompany the party. The events which
followed, will be described in the next chapter.
Always have a book within your reach, which you may catch up at
your odd minutes. Revolve in your mind what you have last been
reading.
LITTLE LEAVES FOR LITTLE READERS.
Mamma’s Lessons.
I once knew two little children, who had a great deal of
knowledge, for their age, and yet they were not taught altogether by
books. They had a good mother, who took great pains with their
education, and she managed in such a way as to make her lessons
very pleasing.
I will tell you one method of teaching which she adopted—and it
was this. She would get her two children around her, and then would
ask them what creatures lived in the air? what lived in the water?
what lived on the earth, &c. The children would give such answers
as they pleased; if they were right, they were told so; if wrong, they
were corrected.
That you may understand how this affair went on, I will give you
a dialogue, which will set the matter clearly before you. You will
remember that the children were named Dick and Lydia.
Mother. Now tell me, my children, what animals live in the air?
Dick. Birds.
M. Do all birds live in the air?
Lydia. No, mother; the ostrich is said never to fly, and it seems to
me that many other birds, such as hens, partridges, quails, and
others, rarely fly, and therefore cannot be said even to live in the air.
M. What birds live most in the air?
D. I should think the swallows, for they seem to me to be dodging
about from morning to night. And, mother, I have heard Ben
Halliard, the sailor, say that there is a sea-swallow that is always
flying; he declares that the creature never lights and that he hatches
his eggs under his wing!
M. The sea-swallow, or mother Cary’s chicken, is a bird that can
remain on the wing for a long time; but like all other birds, it goes
sometimes to the land. It builds its nest on the uninhabited islands
of the sea; many of them may be seen in the unfrequented rocky
islands near Florida.
L. Mother, it is said the birds of Paradise live always on the wing.
M. This is also an error; the sailors, who frequented the seas near
the Asiatic islands, where these lovely birds are often seen on the
wing, fancied them to be creatures of the air; and being always in
the spicy breath of those charming regions, they called them birds of
Paradise. But now, that we are better acquainted with the islands of
the Pacific we know that the birds of Paradise live chiefly on the
land, and sport, like others of the feathered race, amid the branches
of the trees.
L. Well, mother, I think there are other creatures that live in the
air, beside birds. I mean insects, such as butterflies, bees, wasps,
and other little flying creatures.
M. You should rather say, my dear, that these animals live a part
of the time in the air. It is with these insects, as with birds, that
though we see them often on the wing, they really spend but a part
of the time in flying. Let me now ask you to tell what animals live in
the water?
D. Fishes.
L. Beside fishes, there are other things; such as lobsters, crabs,
oysters, clams, and many other creatures.
D. Yes; but these are fishes,—are they not, mother?
M. They are called shell-fish, but they are quite distinct from
fishes, properly so called. The latter have no legs, and possess fins,
by which they push themselves along in the water. They have a long
skeleton, upon which the flesh is formed; whereas, in the shell-fish,
there is no interior skeleton, but the flesh and muscles are attached
to an exterior shell. Thus you see that the whole structure of the
proper fishes and of the shell fish are very distinct.
D. That is very curious, indeed; but there are some creatures that
live partly in water and partly on the land.
M. Yes; and these are called amphibious.
L. That puts me in mind of a story, mother. A traveller went once
to the Tower of London, to see the wild animals. There was a man
there who made it his business to show them and describe them.
Well, there was a young alligator among the animals, and when the
showman came to describe him, he said, “Here, ladies and
gentlemen, is a halligator, which came from Merriky, in the state of
Georgia; it was ketched in the great river Mississippi, which runs all
the way up hill. This creature is amphibious, which means that he
cannot live in the water and dies on the land; he is six feet and a ’alf
from the tip of his tail to the tip of his nose, and seven feet ten
inches from the tip of his nose to the tip of his tail. Like all
Merrikens, the halligator is fond of young niggers, and the night
afore he was ketched, he made his supper upon two of them!”
M. That story is absurd enough; though it is quite true that the
showman at the Tower of London, does tell some queer stories. If
he makes such mistakes and shows such prejudice, in respect to our
country, as the story represents, he is certainly like many English
travellers, who ought to know better. I think Mr. Dickens, who writes
such nonsense about our country, should be employed to show the
animals at the Tower. But let me now ask what class of animals live
entirely on the land?
L. Quadrupeds, or four-footed beasts.
M. That is right; most quadrupeds spend their time wholly on the
land; the only one of them that can fly, is the bat; and this creature
is formed almost as much like a bird as a four-footed beast. Some of
the amphibious animals, such as lizards, toads, frogs and tortoises,
are quadrupeds; and though these creatures live a part of their time
in the water, most of them still spend the greater portion of their
time on the land.