Download as TXT, PDF, TXT or read online on Scribd
You are on page 1/ 14
THE EMERGENCE OF CLASS
"The owl of Minerva," Hegel wrote, "flies at twilight." In no area of sociology is
the appositeness of this maxim more striking than with respect to the study of social class. Only after the historic and essential bases of social class in European society had become tenuous and uncer-tain, had become threatened by forces such as political centralization, citizenship, and mass education-forces which would, in the long run, make class the weakest of all the traditional social unities under the modern regime did the study of social stratification burst forth in full. brilliance. Central to sociology's interest in stratification is its sharp dis-tinction, from Tocqueville on, between social class and social status. Interest in social hierarchy is not, to be sure, peculiar to the nineteenth century. The far-reaching idea of "the great chain of being" that had, from Plato down to the modern Enlightenment, fascinated European philosophers, suffusing metaphysics, biology, and cosmography, could nor but have included the notion of a social chain of being: one that stretched from the lowly peasant through intermediate ranks and stations to monarch or emperor. References to "ranks," "orders," and "degrees" are strung out continuously in social and moral thought from the late Middle Ages on. A great deal of the social philosophy of Thomas Aquinas concerns the hierarchy of the organic community. Aside from a few religiously inspired equalitarian groups spawned for the most part by the Reformation-the chiliastic, millennial, and apocalyptic-it is hard to find moral philosophers prior to the mid- seventeenth century who would not have concurred with Shakespeare's words: "Take but degree away, untune that string, and hark! what discord follows; each thing meets in mere oppugnancy." Elizabethan dramatists and philosophical STATUS 175 essayists were literally obsessed by rank, estate, and station and their absolute necessity in the social order.' When we come to Hobbes, however, in the middle of the seventeenth century, we find a suspicion of both aristocracy and the middle class; a suspicion founded on Hobbes's distrust of all intermediate social bodies in the monolithic structure of his Leviathan.? In natural-law theory as a whole in the century there is, with the one remarkable exception of Althusius, an exclusion of social class and rank from systematic con-sideration. The hostility that natural-law theorists manifested for the most part toward guilds and other corporations was extended, in theory at least, to aristocracy. Unlike such essential concepts as those of indi-vidual, state, and contract, the concept of social class had little if any theoretical role. Althusius, as I have suggested, is a major exception. His vision of society had as much room in it for the ordered gradations of social hierarchy as for community and corporation. But he stands alone. With the onset of the Enlightenment, we see a sharp rise in criticism of traditional hierarchy-proceeding from the philosophes' general distaste for everything feudal in origin-and also in analytical interest in stratification. Rousseau's Discourse on the Origin of Inequality, for all its polemical overtones, contains a remarkable account of social stratification set within a developmental perspective and pivoted upon private property. Some of the Scottish moral philosophers-Hume, Ferguson, Adam Smith, and especially John Millars-gave searching attention to stratification. The latter's Observations Concerning the Distinction of Ranks in Society is a masterpiece of historico-ethnographic description and analysis. But all of this is nothing compared to the intensity and comprehensiveness of treatments of stratification to be observed after the forces of revolutionary democracy and industrialism had gotten well under way in the nineteenth century. Conservatives, liberals, and radicals alike made the concept of social class fundamental to their writings. Such indeed was the rascination that the word "class" came to exert on the minds of intellectuals that John Stuart Mill was led to write in 1834: "They revolve in their eternal circle of landlords, capitalists and laborers, until they seem to think of the distinction of society into those three classes as if it were one of God's ordinances, not man's, and as little under human control as the division of day or night. Scarcely any one of them seems to have said to himself as a subject of inquiry, what changes the relations of those classes to one another are likely to undergo in the progress of society." a Mill's words applied to the economists, certainly, but not to 176 THE UNIT-IDEAS OF SOCIOLOGY the sociologists. As I shall emphasize in this chapter, it was of the very essence of sociology to be concerned with the future of class under the operation of historical forces. Indeed, in this concern lay the basis of the central conflict among sociologists in the century, with Tocqueville at one point on the continuum and Marx at the other. The concept of social class, in distinction from the earlier concepts of hierarchy, is late eighteenth century. As Asa Briggs has written: "The concept of social 'class' with all its attendant terminology was a product of the large-scale economic and social changes of the late eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries. ... There was no dearth of social conflicts in pre-industrial society, but they were not conceived of at the time in straight class terms. The change in nomenclature in the late eighteenth and early nineteenth centuries reflected a basic change not only in men's ways of viewing society but in society itself." 4 Why did social class seem so paramount a reality to many minds when, as we have seen, processes of individualization, leveling, and fragmentation were endemic in the transition to the modern regime? Putting the question differently, why did the age-old conception of the continuity of hierarchy in society, the notion of a chain of being, now become supplanted by presentiments of discontinuity, even of conflict, among classes? The answer lies, in considerable part, in what Ostrogorski has called the "new species of subordination" that arose in the industrial world. "When manufacturing took the place of domestic labour, direct intercourse between the owners of factories and the shifting masses of workmen became impossible; henceforth their only points of contact were work and wages, governed by the stern law of supply and demand; they became anonymous abstractions one to the other; they came together and parted without seeing each other. ... They now belonged to different strata of society ... marked by distinctions which varied according to the income of their members, and each distinction constituted a new line of demarcation and separation." & Whether these new strata were simply levels-—tenuous and evanescent in the long run—or the hard social classes Marx thought them to be is not here the point. What is important is the sudden appearance of the terminology of class, a terminology that was to remain vital in social science for a full century. It is even possible, as Raymond Williams has shown, to date the successive appearances of the new terms of class. "It is only at the end of the eighteenth century that the modern structure of class, in its social sense, begins to be built up. First comes lower classes to join lower orders, which appears earlier in the eighteenth century. Then, in the 1790s we STATUS 177 get higher classes; middle classes and middling classes follow at once; working classes in about 1815; upper classes in the 1820s. Class preju-dice, class legislation, class consciousness, class conflict and class war follow. ..." e THE MODEL OF CLASS Something must be said of the significant role held by the English landed class in the minds of those who, from the late eighteenth century on, were concerned with the probable shape of stratification in the new society that was forming around industry. Nothing quite like the English landed class existed on the Continent, a fact emphasized by the references to it that we find in French and German writings throughout the nineteenth century. That this class was, in one way or another, a model for all those in England whose intellectual roots lay in Burke's admiration for it is hardly strange. It also excited the respect of Hegel, Tocque-ville, and Taine. I am more interested, however, in its conceptual function in providing the pattern, so to speak, of what writers were to take as the substance of true class, in whatever context. I believe it was the English landed class above any other that became the analytical model for what, it was widely assumed, would be fulfilled, mutatis mutandis, in the new economy of capitalism. The English landed class was, I think we are justified in saying, the known from which many students of stratification —including Marx—mapped their way into the new unknown of industrial society. A good many radicals and conservatives alike foresaw the industrial bourgeoisie as the successor of the landed class, like it in struc-ture, status, and power, differing only in economic context. The relevance of the English landed class to both radical and conservative theories lies in its detachment from any formal system of political law and from any apparent external force. In France and on the Continent in general social classes of the older order had been more nearly in the nature of estates, bounded, reinforced, and maintained by laws of the realm. Not so in England. Despite the powerful role that this class played in political affairs, it was not a creature of law and nothing in the English constitution pertained to it. There was, first, its economic unity founded largely upon landed property. It would be wrong to say that no other forms of property were recognized, but it is fair to note that men who made their fortunes in commerce and business did not usually gain recognition from this class 178 THE UNIT-IDEAS OF SOCIOLOGY until they had acquired land and based their existence upon it. From generation to generation landed property tended to remain in the same family hands. Equally notable was the political unity of the class. Economic ownership and political power coalesced almost perfectly. This was to be seen not merely in the overwhelming number of Parliamentary seats that went to members of the landed class and in the astonishing degree of consensus that reigned among them, but in the monopoly they held of administrative functions in local and county government. "The great un-paid," as they were to be called by a later historian, is an apt term. Without formal compensation of any kind, without indeed any position in the law of the land, they performed throughout England the essential tasks of administration, including much of the dispensing of justice. It was the generally high sense of responsibility with which this class operated at local levels- coupled with the absence of the kind of aggressive and independent legal profession that France had produced-that for long restrained a true bureaucracy in England and made of this class a model for all conservatives. There was little if any element of caste. No legal boundaries existed to mark classes and no restrictions of a legal sort prevented others from participating. We know that occasionally men did rise from below to attain influential places in goverment and society. But they were rare for, although the landed class was not closed, openings were few and could close with extraordinary speed. Overwhelmingly, national politics, local administration, justice, and service in the commissioned areas of the armed forces were the functions of this one, socially homogeneous class. So too was there a high degree of convergence of the various attributes of social status. Except for the handful of intellectuals largely concentrated in London, the only people of education were members of this class, and both the public schools and the two great universities were shaped in purpose and result by landed class needs. The norms of what constituted an educated man were universally understood. Language, including accent, could identify a man in a moment as belonging to this class. All were of the Established Church, most of the higher clergy were themselves products of the landed group, and even when they weren't, their loyalties to it were strong. Over the whole structure towered the governing conception of the gentleman. Hard to define in abstract terms, perhaps, the reality of the gentleman was nevertheless as unmistakable and as universal as that of STATUS 179 the land itself. In dress, opinion, taste, and conviction the landed gentleman set the life style of all that was invested with prestige and power. It was the pervasive image of the gentleman that had so much to do with maintaining the solidarity of this class, with shoring up its political and economic strength, and with making its behavior and desires so universal in England of that day. All of this we know from the countless letters and diaries of the age. We should note that this class was functional in sociological re-spects. Between the social attributes of prestige and the realities of economic and political power there was an almost perfect convergence, leading to a degree of solidarity and self-awareness that could hardly have been exceeded. Criteria of class were clear, easily identifiable, and substantially the same everywhere in England. Knowledge of a family's standing with respect to any one of the criteria was sufficient to place that family fairly accurately with respect to other criteria. Finally, there was stability of this convergence of attributes from one generation to another. In sum, if it was the social norm of the gentleman that surmounted the structure, it was the near monopoly of political power and its deep roots in property that provided the foundations. The rugged strength of this landed class may be inferred from the extent to which its purely cultural properties— intellectual interests, edu-cation, mode of speech, life style in general- -remained evocative in Eng- land after its real economic and political roots had been cut by economic change and political reform. Nowhere else in Europe, much less in the United States, has the cultural reality of an upper class remained so vivid, s. continuously influential in all spheres of government and soci-ety, as in England. Despite profound changes in political structure and in the character of wealth, despite the broadening of the educational base, an upper-class culture remains even today significant beyond anything known elsewhere in Western society. And no matter what the diversity of economic channels through which this culture flows today— industrial, governmental, and other—its historical source is the landed class I have just described. THE CHALLENGE TO CLASS From our point of view, however, the essential significance of this class in the nineteenth century was conceptual. It became, as I have sug-gested, a kind of ideal type, a theoretical model, of what substantive 180 THE UNIT-IDEAS OF SOCIOLOGY social class is and what its political and economic power in society might be. This class was, of course, pre-capitalist, quasi-feudal in character. It had a great deal more to do with the stability of the new economic and political orders than spokesmen of either of the latter were willing to admit. They, chiefly the economists— classical and socialist alike—con-tented themselves with describing the new classes that capitalism was supposedly ushering in: industrial owners and workers. Given the abstract mode of economic analysis and the assumption of an autonomous, self-operating economic order, the reinforcing and often vital influence of the landed class was rarely perceived. Nor were the intricate inter- weavings of landed and industrial wealth in both old and new families. Economists, for the most part, were prisoners of categories bequeathed by Smith and Ricardo. But to the sociologically minded the outlines of the old, landed class were distinct and brilliant. And a large number of minds sought in the new economic strata of capitalism the same convergence of political, economic, and cultural elements that were so plain in pre-capitalist classes of aristocracy and peasantry. Why, it was asked, should not the future of capitalism reveal the development of an upper and a lower class within its own economic structure that would be as politically and socially distinct, as culturally pervasive, as anything to be found in the pre-capitalist order? It was in reply to this question that the two major types of evaluation of European stratification were predicated. The major controversy in the study of stratification, at least among the sociologists, was not that of social class versus equalitarianism. It was the subtler and theoretically more fundamental one of social class versus social status: of a view of the new society resting upon the assumed existence of solid, substantive social class opposed to a view resting upon the assumption of the erosion of class and its replacement by fluctuant, mobile, status groups and by status-seeking individuals. We may put the question in this fashion: Was the new society that was being ushered in, a society founded upon citizen, entrepreneur, and technologist, a society based on the imperious, if uncertain and often misled, will of the masses, dominated by new structures of administrative power and flooded by new forms of wealth, driven by novel and incessant pressures for educational, religious, and social equality; was this society to be, as had been all previous forms of society, organized primarily in terms of class layers, each holding the same union of economic, intellectual, educational, and political properties that had characterized social ranks in the old order? Or, in sharp contrast, could the acids of STATUS 181 modernity be seen working in as destructive a fashion upon the bases of social class—in any viable sense of that word—as they were upon village community, extended family, and the whole network of moral-cultural relations that had also been born in the pre-capitalist, pre-democratic, pre-rationalist age? Answers to these questions form a major aspect of sociology in the century and they are, of course, closely related to treatments of other elements of the social and political order. That is, how one approached the problems of community and authority foretold much of how he would approach the problem of stratification. Bias was as vivid here as it was in all other major issues in the century. On the one hand were those who argued that social, political, and economic inequalities in the new, emerging society could be as accurately described in terms of social class as the inequalities that had been contained in the old order. In the bour-geoisie, exponents of this view—radicals for the most part-could see, or foresee, the same kind of formidable unity of power, wealth, and status in the industrial world that had characterized the landed aristocracy for hundreds of years in Europe and was even yet a force to be reckoned with. Marx became, as we know, the pre-eminent representative of this body of interpretation, and the impress of his ideas is with us still. On the other hand, and in sharp contrast, were those who, from the very beginning, saw no more likelihood of substantive social class forming within the new order than they did genuine community, of which class, in their eyes, was a notable type. The fragmentation of the old order, resulting in the release of long-pent-up elements of wealth and power and status, would lead, it was argued, to a scrambling of social categories, to an individualization of stratification that would result in the ascendancy not of class but of social status-which is at once more mobile, individually autonomous, and diversified than class. Tocqueville is the major representative of this view. I do not wish to overdraw the contrast. It is not black and white. None of the sociologists was oblivious to class in one degree or another. Even Tocqueville could refer to the "class" of manufacturers and to an economic power wielded by manufacturers that seemed to him fraught with danger to democracy. But, as we shall see, Tocqueville uses the term class in so denatured a sense that it is left merely as a kind of level, at best an interest group; not a social stratum characterized by the kind of solidification of political, economic, and social elements that had characterized the structure of the landed aristocracy. 182 THE UNIT-IDEAS OF SOCIOLOGY The difference between political conservatives and radicals on the nature and reality of social class is a kind of anagram of the existential and the utopian. Conservatives, beginning with Burke, said, in effect, that while social class should be one of the supports of a truly stable and free society, it was all too likely that the combined effect of political centralization, social atomization, new types of wealth, and the transfer of the center of political gravity from rural to urban areas would in fact destroy the substance of social class, reduce it to mass rubble. No single element is more central to the social philosophies of Burke, Coleridge, and Carlyle in England, to Bonald, Maistre, and Balzac in France, and to Haller and Hegel in Germany than that of social hierarchy. And, equally, nothing is more common to these writers than the assumption that economic and political modernism was rapidly destroying the contexts of hierarchy. Auguste Comte was powerfully affected by conservative veneration for hierarchy, and we find in his early writings sharp criticism of the egalitarian doctrines of Enlightenment and Revolution and, in his Positive Polity, rigorous prescription for the organization of the Positivist utopia in terms of distinct social classes. Radical thinkers, on the other hand, took the position that while the extermination of social hierarchy had the highest priority in social action and while equality was, even over freedom, the sovereign value in their axiology, the harsh facts were that capitalist society would be as class-structured, as class-dominated, and class-oriented as was any preceding stage of man's social development. And political democracy would not, could not, affect this. From William Cobbett in England, through Proudhon in France, to Marx in Germany, radical doctrine made the reality of social class in capitalism fundamental to its thinking. These two ideological positions are, so to speak, magnetic poles in the study of stratification in the nineteenth century. Among the sociolo gists, Tocqueville is as perfectly expressive of the one as Marx is of the other, and what eventually emerges chiefly in Weber-as the dominant sociological view of stratification is best seen as a resultant of the two forces represented by Tocqueville and Marx. If for a long time the Marxian view exerted the greater influence, it was never absolute (except among Marxists), and more recently it is clear that Tocqueville's perspective has become ascendant. 300 THE UNIT-IDEAS OF SOCIOLOGY THE CRYSTALLIZATION OF CLASS-MARX In Germany the situation is strikingly different. It would be hard to And any social concept possessed of more pivotal importance after 1849 than the concept of class. Even when, as with Tönnies and Weber, we find major modifications of the class perspective, class and the whole terminology of stratification retain a degree of importance lacking in French thought. Marx is, of course, the prime source of all this. In Marx we find no picture of social class pulverized by the forces of modernism, of power passing from social hierarchy to political masses, of frenzied competition for status. What Marx gives us is a view of modern society resting upon the solid reality of class, a reality in which power, wealth, and status are as class-based as they were under feudalism. He might have been directing the following words at Tocqueville: "The modern bourgeois society that has sprouted from the ruins of feudal society has not done away with class antagonisms. It has but established new classes, new conditions of oppression, new forms of struggle in place of old ones. Our epoch, the epoch of the bourgeoisie, possesses, however, this distinctive feature: it has simplified the class antagonisms. Society as a whole is more and more splitting up into two great hostile camps, into two great. classes directly facing each other: bourgeoisie and proletar-iat." B7 Some students of Marx's thought have suggested that beneath his vision of the two great classes in capitalism-bourgeoisie and proletariat —lies the model of ancient master and slave classes. But I do not think we need go back so far in history. We need look only to the classes of landed gentry and peasant that were still solid structures in Marx's time to find his model. As I have suggested, English landed society alone was sufficient in this respect. Did it not prove that there could be united in a single social class the attributes of political power, wealth, social status, and all the controlling forces for a society reflected in culture, life style, education, and religion? Was it not obvious that what had existed for centuries in the landed aristocracy was now forming in an industrial aris-tocracy, the bourgeoisie, to survive until the gathering forces of revolution would destroy this class, just as revolutions had destroyed all preceding forms of class in history? Only this time there would be left not still another sovereign class but, for the first time in history, the structure of a society without any classes at all. Marx's fascination with the bourgeoisie is at the heart of his theory. STATUS 201 No spokesman for Manchester could have given us more laudatory words on this class than Marx wrote in the early pages of the Manifesto: "The bourgeoisie, during its rule of scarce one hundred years, has created more massive and colossal productive forces than have all preceding generations together." 68 The development of scientific technology, the command of nature's resources, the erasure of local and national bound-aries, the rise of cities, the spread of communications, the creation of a world market, and the rise of common people into political areas previously governed by nobility alone—all of this, Marx tells us, is the work of a single social class: the bourgeoisie. In Marx's praise there is of course special and revolutionary intent. All that he gives in revolutionary importance to the bourgeoisie in the making of modern Europe he transfers to the proletariat for the making of future Europe: the socialist, classless society which must, Marx argued, evolve as inexorably as each preceding stage of society had evolved. What the bourgeoisie has done in our era to dislocate the landed aristoc-racy, the proletariat must do eventually, through operation of identical dialectical- historical forces, to the bourgeoisie. For the present, however, the health of the bourgeoisie is absolutely essential to the embryonic development of the proletariat. On this point Marxian "science" rested squarely. "The development of the industrial proletariat is, in general, conditioned by the development of the industrial bourgeoisie. Only under its rule does the proletariat gain that extensive national existence which can raise its revolution to a national one and does itself create the modern means of production, which become just so many means of its revolutionary emancipation. Only its rule tears up the material roots of feudal society and levels the ground on which alone a proletarian revolution is possible." &8 Elsewhere, as in the Communist Manifesto and The German Ideology, Marx would emphasize the international aspect of the development of the proletariat. "Empirically, communism is possible only as the act of the dominant peoples 'all at once,' or simultaneously, which presupposes the universal development of productive forces and the world intercourse bound up with them. ... The proletariat can thus exist only world historically, just as communism, its movement, can only have a 'world-historical' existence." & But the bourgeoisie is absolutely fundamental to the development of the proletariat. The bourgeoisie is for Marx what democracy is for Tocqueville: the cause and the shape of all that is central in the modern regime. In stark contrast to Tocqueville, Marx sees ever more extreme in-202 THE UNIT-IDEAS OF SOCIOLOGY equality as the dominant social characteristic of the time. Tocqueville had stressed the bland and uniformitarian aspects of modernism: aspects that would eventually sterilize all significant social and political differ-ences. Marx, however, saw social and political differences among men increasing and, given the structural contradictions of capitalism, made ever more revolutionary in implication. Where Tocqueville saw at best economic levels in industrial society, Marx saw classes and, between them, inevitable and relentless struggle. Class struggle is for Marx a principle, the principle, of history: comparable in scope and force to Comte's law of three stages, to Tocqueville's political centralization, to Weber's rationalization. Class struggle is the most fundamental social manifestation of the dialectic in history; it is the "efficient cause" of the movement of society from one stage to another. The modern emergence of the bourgeoisie is the conse quence of "a series of revolutions in the modes of production and ex-change." The bourgeoisie has, from dialectical necessity, become a revolutionary force, the most revolutionary indeed in all history. Wherever it has got the upper hand, Marx tells us in one of his most celebrated state-ments, it has put an end to all forms of relationship-kinship, religious, professional, personal—founded on assertedly moral or personal values.« Only "cash-payment" is left. Let us look more closely at the Marxian conception of the nature of class. Despite the fact that social class is the very basis of Marxian soci-ology, and despite the abundance of general references to social class-most notably to the bourgeoisie and the proletariat—a clear, analytical conception of social class is not easy to derive from a reading of Marx. The one place in his works where it would appear that a genuine sociological analysis is under way—at the very end of the third volume of Capital-the discussion comes to a quick and uncertain ending. We shall return to this momentarily. It is first necessary to deal with the larger picture of social class that Marx gives us. We begin with the centrality of work. For Marx, what man does economically is the single most important and determining thing about his life. The type of work he performs, his position in the larger system of production in society, and the differential rewards he receives for his work—these are the essential elements on which a sociology of class must be built. Given the crucial role of work in man's life, it follows that the position man holds in society's stratification of work and rewards is bound to affect not only the degree of power he possesses but also his social status and even his personality. STATUS 203 "The general conclusion at which I arrived and which, once reached, continued to serve as the leading thread in my studies may be briefy summed up as follows: In the social production which men carry on they enter into definite relations that are indispensable and independent of their will; these relations of production correspond to a definite stage of development of their material powers of production. The sum total of these relations of production constitutes the economic structure of society-the real foundation, on which rise legal and political superstructures and to which correspond definite forms of social conscious-ness. The mode of production in material life determines the general character of the social, political, and spiritual processes of life." ®2 This principle is as relevant to the societies of the ancient world as it is to those of the present. It was the system of production that divided ancient economies into master and slave, feudal society into noble and serf, and modern capitalism into capitalist and worker. Social movement in history is always caused by revolution in which the struggle between classes is the central element. This struggle is invariably the consequence of a contradiction that develops between "material forces of production" (technology) and "existing relations of production" (the social classes). "From forms of development of the forces of production these relations turn into their fetters. Then comes the period of social revolution. With the change of the economic foundation the entire immense superstructure is more or less rapidly transformed. ... In broad outlines we can designate the Asiatic, the ancient, the feudal, and the modern bourgeois methods of production as so many epochs in the progress of the economic formation of society. The bourgeois relations of production are the last antagonistic form of the social process of production-an-tagonistic not in the sense of individual antagonism, but of one arising from conditions surrounding the life of individuals in society; at the same time the productive forces developing in the womb of bourgeris society create the material conditions for the solution of that antagonist." 83 The relation between social class and the rest of society is therefore direct and unalterable. So is the relation between social class and ideas, which form, in their totality, an ideology—that is, a set of mental repre-sentations-of class position. "The ideas of the ruling class are, in every age, the ruling ideas: i.e., the class which is the dominant material force in society is at the same time its dominant intellectual force. The class which has the means of material production at its disposal has control at the same time over the means of mental production, so that in consequence the ideas of those who lack the means of mental production 204 THE UNIT-IDEAS OF SOCIOLOGY are in general subject to it. The dominant ideas are nothing more than the ideal expression of the dominant material relationships, the dominant material relationships grasped as ideas, and thus of the relationships which make one class the ruling one; they are consequently the ideas of its dominance." es What has been true in the historical past is equally true of the bourgeois- dominated present. Literature, art, music, along with prevailing ideas of the good society, morality, and even metaphysics, are all, in their dominant forms, bourgeois representations. Only through revolution or, for the immediate future, through disciplined awareness of the necessity of revolution and of identification with the interests of the working class, is it possible for one to escape the total cultural domination of the bourgeoisie. Hence the Marxian emphasis on the necessity of developing a proletarian class interest and, with it, a proletarian mind, culture, and world view. The end of bourgeois culture and ideology is, of course, foredes-tined b, the laws of historical development and of internal capitalist con-tradiction: Just as each dominant class in past ages has sown the seeds of its own destruction, so has the bourgeoisie. "Modern bourgeois society •.. is like the sorcerer who is no longer able to control the powers of the nether world whom he has called up by his spells. . . . The weap ons with which the bourgeoisie felled feudalism to the ground are now turned against the bourgeoisie itself. But not only has the bourgeoisie forged the weapons that bring death to itself; it has also called into existence the men who are to wield those weapons, the proletarians." 85 "In proportion as the bourgeoisie, i.e., capital, is developed, in the same proportion as the proletariat, the modern working class, developed —a class of laborers, who live only so long as they find work, and who find work only so long as their labor increases capital. These laborers, who must sell themselves piecemeal, are a commodity, like every other article of commerce, and are consequently exposed to all the vicissitudes of competition, to all the fluctuations of the market." &e Out of the workingman's awareness of the class position which is forced upon him will come, must come, collective proletarian awareness. But for this to be accomplished, conflict with the bourgeoisie is an iron necessity. Despite the importance of work and productive role in the formation of class, it is the conflict of classes that exercises the major influence in Marx's mind in fixing the class structure of loyalties and consciousness and in preventing the fragmentation of class ties that would, apart from conflict, reduce class to a tenuous "level." We must STATUS 205 stress this point. Too many contemporary students of class assume, with a naïveté that Marx would scarcely relish, that while class conflict is a negligible feature of contemporary social democracy, the lines and loyalties of class remain strong nevertheless. Marx was much more sophisti-cated. "The separate individuals form a class insofar as they have 10 carry on a common battle against another class; otherwise they are on hostile terms with each other as competitors. On the other hand, the class, in its turn, achieves an independent existence over against the indi-viduals, so that the latter find their conditions of existence pre-destined, and hence have their position in life and their personal development assigned to them by their class, become subsumed under it. This is the same phenomenon as the subjection of the separate individuals to the division of labor and can only be removed by the abolition of private property and of labor itself." ®7 "Economic conditions had first transformed the mass of the people of the country into workers. The domination of capital has created for this mass a common situation, common interests. This mass is thus already a class as against capital, but not yet for itself. In this struggle, of which we have noted only a few phases, this mass becomes united, and constitutes itself as a class for itself. The interests it defends become class interests. But the struggle of class against class is a political strug-gle." 88 The context of Marx's view of class and of the functional necessity of conflict to the preservation of class was formed in his earliest essays. The following passage, published in 1844, is indicative of the relationship that conscious conflict held to class consciousness in Marx's mind. "For a popular revolution and the emancipation of a particular class of civil society to coincide, for one class to represent the whole of society, another class must concentrate in itself all the evils of society, a particular class must embody and represent a general obstacle and limi-tation. A particular social sphere must be regarded as the notorious crime of the whole society, so that emancipation from this sphere appears as general emancipation. For one class to be the liberating class par excellence, it is essential that another class should be openly the oppressing class." Be For Marx, consciousness is absolutely essential to true class. It is not enough that a group of individuals occupy the same objective position in the economic structure of society. There must be subjective awareness. It is the crucial condition of class and of its historic role in 206 THE UNIT-IDEAS OF SOCIOLOGY economic and political conflict. Marx's views on this may be inferred from his negative comments on the peasantry in France. "The small peasants for a vast mass, the members of which live in similar condi-tions, but without entering into manifold relations with one another. Their mode of production isolates them from one another, instead of bringing them into mutual intercourse ... Insofar as millions of families live under economic conditions of existence that divide their mode of life, their interests and their culture from those of other classes, and put them into hostile contrast to the latter, they form a class. Insofar as there is merely a local interconnection among these small peasants, and the identity of their interests begets no unity, no national union, and no political organization, they do not form a class." 70 Marx never discounted the importance of creating, or helping to create, a sense of class. This was a part of the mission of Communists, of those who would be the vanguard of the proletariat's emergence on the world stage. His analytical system can never be really separated from his vivid sense of man's making history. But the fact remains that in Marx's mind there had to be the substance and logic of industrialism and of the dialectic of history manifesting itself through iron development, for this calculated vanguarding to be other than chimerical. For Marx, social class is what the nation was to Hegel, the truest repository of history. Social class is also, plainly, the dominating, even exclusive, category of the Marxian explanation of the larger problem of social stratifi-cation. Is there in Marx even a faint understanding of the kind of multiplicity of patterns of power, economic strata, and status systems in nineteenth-century Europe that Tocqueville had emphasized and that Weber and Simmel were to stress in their fundamental departures from the Marxian view? Can one sense even a dim awareness in Marx of class fragmentation, of status mobility, status invasion and status anxieties, the study of which was to prove the really original contribution of European sociology in the nineteenth century? Here and there, yes. A fragment in a letter, a contemptuous parenthetical aside, a passing jeer at the landed class. But that is all. What is central and constitutive for Marx in the society around him is not the fragmentation but the congealing of class ties; not the dislocation of social status and political power from economic class, but the ever firmer uniting of these three elements. There is rich irony in the fact that the reasons why social class has never attained anything like the importance in capitalism that Marx ascribed to it flow from the very factors citizenship, moral ideals of equality, religion, and education-that Marx and his followers relegated STATUS 207 to subordinate and reflected status in history. For Marx all struggles within the state, "the struggle between democracy, aristocracy, and mon-archy, the struggle for the franchise, etc. etc. are merely the illusory forms in which the real struggles of the different classes are fought out among one another ..." 71 That nationalism, rather than class, would achieve major appeal to the mass of twentieth-century workers; that the spread of administrative bureaucracy into social and economic areas would itself negate conflict and struggle in those areas; that reform movements, commonly engineered by the bourgeoisie, in the areas of civil and social rights would become ascendant; that, of all forces, education would prove to be the major force of sterilization; that institutional rather than class conflicts would attain ascendancy in modern history— conflict between state and economy, between religion and economy, and so on--that the whole sway of economic forces might be drastically lessened from the in fact historically rare importance these held in Marx's day: all of this was inconceivable to Marx, as it has been, for the most part, to his followers. But in a sense this is of negligible importance. For whatever its intellectual omissions, Marxism became, before the nineteenth century was out, and remains even today, the single most influential idea system in European history since the rise of Christianity. There is irony here, too. For it was Marx's proud boast that he had put ideas in their proper, subordinate, status and had shown that ideas were but the pale reflection of the true dynamic forces of history. That his own ideas should have become, almost independently of the forces they sought to describe, among the key determinants of the modern world-in Asia, Africa, Latin America, as well as in Europe—is a fact sufficient to mark their greatness measured in strictly historical terms. Even apart from their direct political and "religious" influence, Marxist ideas have had almost undisputed influence in theoretical treatments of social stratification until two or three decades ago. Vague though the Marxist formulation of class was, it maintained a tenacious hold upon the study of stratification. Only within the past few years has the Marxist model of society begun to be supplanted in empirical studies by more imaginative, more flexible, and more relevant insights —insights that have closer relation to the intuitions and impressions of Toc queville than to what may be found in the Marxian canon. But it would take a rash soul to say that the influence of Marx is altogether gone. He has been, so to speak, the Ptolemy of the subject for a hundred years now, and although his writ is no longer magisterial, no Copernicus has yet 208 THE UNIT-IDEAS OF SOCIOLOGY come onto the field. We can say only that the reflection-neutralizing. attention- narcotizing icons of Proletarian and Capitalist have, at long last, largely vanished from the altars of Western intellectuals. In Schumpeter's vivid phrase, Marxist rosaries are no longer being fingered. Marx's influence on the theory of stratification has been strikingly like that of Darwin on the ideas of evolution and natural selection. In each instance we have an impressive shoring up of eighteenth-century ideas. The initial manner of statement in both theories had the effect of persuading readers of an originality and break with tradition that did not in fact exist. In precisely the same way that Darwin's ideas are deeply rooted in eighteenth-century ideas of development, so Marx's ideas on the nat re of social stratification are rooted in eighteenth-century analyses of inequality. If Darwin had his Lyell, Marx had his Rousseau (vide the Discourse on the Origin of Inequality). That Darwin's statement of continuous and cumulative variation in genetic change has had a degree of acceptance in biology that Marx's statement of dialectical change in society has not had in sociology is not the point. The point is simply that the prestige of one in the study of biological evolution has been precisely paralleled in the prestige of the other in the study of social stratification, and that in each we are dealing with ideas that have deep eighteenth-century roots. CLASS AS GESELLSCHAFT-TÖNNIES The conceptual unity that Marx gave to social class did not last even in Germany except in the ranks of the politically committed. The discrepancies between the modern order and the Marxist conception of that order were too great to be contained in a theory that aspired to coalesce all the complex elements of power, status, and wealth into one simple theory of social class. What we see in the generation of sociological thought following Marx in Germany is the gradual disengagement of each of these elements from the others and the formation of new and more complex theories of stratification of which Max Weber's was to prove the most notable and to be by far the most influential on subsequent sociological thought. It was, however, Tönnies' fertile typology of Gemeinschaft and Gesellschaft that prepared the way. Whereas Marx with his progressive philosophy of history treated social class as organizational and dynamic in modern society, it was in-CLASS VERSUS STATUS-WEBER The distinction between political power, economic class, and social status is brought to full theoretical explicitness in Weber's work. Weber sees contemporary power in terms that are only incidentally connected with the role of classes and social-status strata. For Weber it is bureaucracy on the one hand and the political party on the other which have largely inherited the political component that once lay in the hierarchical structure of estate or rank. With the increasing assimilation of social conflicts in the framework of the constitutional state, political parties have become the heirs, so to speak, of contending social forces that in earlier times were not only outside the king's jurisdiction, but often formidable rivals to it. Parties, Weber points out, began as personal followings in the Middle Ages witness the Guelphs and the Ghibellines-and they largely retained this character until the advent of mass democracy in the nineteenth century. To a considerable extent pre-nineteenth-century parties were also closely welded to kinship great families and to aris-tocracy. ?8 Unlike the modern connotation of party, which is of a kind of para-political organization, "officially unofficial, unofficially official," the earlier form of party was, in fact, an offshoot of traditional society, a part of the regular hierarchy. Thus, apart from the upper classes in eighteenth-century England, parties in politics are scarcely imaginable. The breakup of the old order changed this. Modern forms of party "stand in sharp contrast to this idyllic state in which circles of notables and, above all, members of Parliament rule. These modern forms are the children of democracy, of mass franchise, of the necessity to woo and organize the masses, and develop the utmost unity of direction and the strictest discipline." ? It is not necessary to repeat what has already been said of Weber's theory of power. All I wish to do here is emphasize the fact that in dealing with the problem of stratification in modern soci-ety, the first, crucial step taken by Weber, thus allying himself with Tocqueville rather than with Marx, was to deal with power as something that must be distinguished from social class. Political parties, as Weber put it in a memorable phrase, "live in a house of power." 80 Weber's second step follows both Tocqueville and Tönnies: it is the strict limitation of class to the economic sphere. "The genuine place of 'classes' is within the economic order, the place of 'status groups' is within the social order. ..." This does not mean hermetic insulation of three elements. In any individual case, "parties may represent interests STATUS 213 determined through 'class situation' or 'status situation' and they may recruit their following respectively from one or the other." But, Weber emphasizes, they need be neither purely "class" nor purely "status" parties. They can have, and modern politics shows them increasingly to have, a virtually independent status.81 For the separate elements of class, status, and party to have been released in modern times, more than the negative force of fragmentation is involved. There must also have been created through the centuries an environing structure in which these are subordinate to the larger struc-ture. Most of us today would see this as a result of the process of politicization in modern European history. Weber's word for it is "societaliza-tion." Diversification has been possible only through "a comprehensive societalization and especially a political framework of communal action within which they operate." 82 If the political party has inherited most of the political functions of medieval orders, it is class alone that today dominates in the economic sphere just as the status group does in the social sphere. Class has, plainly, a very different significance in Weber from anything to be found in Marx. "In our terminology 'classes' are not communities; they merely represent possible, and frequent, bases of communal action. We may speak of a 'class' when (1) a number of people have in common a specific causal component of their life chances, insofar as (2) this component is represented exclusively by economic interest in the possession of goods and opportunities of income and (3) is represented under the conditions of the commodity or labor markets." 83 For Weber, class rests thus entirely on economic interest. Evea so, he recognized that the concept of "class interest" is an ambiguous one: "it is ambiguous as soon as one understands by it something other than the factual direction of interests following with a certain probability from the class situation for a certain 'average' of those people subjected to the class situation." For, there are many and diverse interests and motivations that enter the individual's mind in modern society, and since by its nature class is not communal (which Weber defines as governed by the feeling of the actors that they belong together), the rise of communal action from a common class situation is by no means a certain or universal phenomenon. Neither, for that matter, is a societal action (rationally motivated adjustment of interests). "To treat 'class' conceptually as having the same value as 'commu-nity' leads to distortion. That men in the same class situation regularly react in mass actions to such tangible situations as economic ones in the 214 THE UNIT-IDEAS OF SOCIOLOGY direction of those interests that are most adequate to their very number is an important and, after all, simple fact for the understanding of historical events. Above all, this fact must not lead to that kind of pseudoscientific operation with the concepts of 'class' and 'class interests' so frequently found these days, and which has found its most classic expression in the statement of a talented author, that the individual may be in error concerning his interests but that the 'class' is 'infallible' about its interests." 8t Such is Weber's reply to the Marxists! "The great shift which has been going on continuously in the past, and up to our times, may be summarized, although at the cost of some precision: the struggle in which class situations are effective has progressively shifted from consumption credit toward, first, competitive struggles in the commodity market and, then, toward price wars on the labor market. The 'class struggles' of antiquity-to the extent that they were genuine class struggles and not struggles between status groups were initially carried on by indebted peasants, and perhaps also by artisans threatened by debt bondage and struggling against urban creditors .. • The propertyless of antiquity and of the Middle Ages protested against monopolies, preemption, forestalling, and the withholding of goods from the market in order to raise prices. Today the central issue is the determination of the prices of labor." 85 The third element in the modern stratification picture is the status group. This is, for Weber, as distinct from class as each is from the political party. Between the status group and a given social class there can be, of course, liaisons, persistences of common interest, but the differences are nonetheless crucial. "In contrast to classes, status groups are normally communities. They are, however, often of an amorphous kind. In contrast to the purely economically determined 'class situation' we wish to designate as 'status situation' every typical component of the life fate of men that is determined by a specific, positive or negative, social estimation of honor." 86 Tocqueville, it will be remembered, had made the idea of honor central in his treatment of traditional European society, and his own history of the value was set in the context of the decline of social hierarchy and the emergence of more individualized, autonomous notions of honor in modern democracy. Weber is close to Tocqueville, though he goes beyond him, looking to the ways in which honor and desire for community have combined in modern society. He finds this in style of life. STATUS 215 Status lines may be linked with those of class and party, but normally they are not, and for the most part status "stands in sharp opposition to the pretensions of property." 7 The basis of the social system lies in the incorporation of honor and in its rigorous identification with a life style. "In content, status honor is normally expressed by the fact that above all else a specific style of life can be expected from all those who wish to belong to the circle. Linked with this expectation are restrictions on 'social intercourse (that is, intercourse which is not subservient to economic or any other of business's 'functional' purposes). These restrictions may confine normal marriages to within the status circle and may lead to complete endogamous closure." 88 It is in the United States that status groups of the modern type are most clearly to be seen. There the absence or disappearance of the kind of society still to be seen in Europe leads to a stringent emphasis on fashion. Only certain neighborhoods, certain modes of dress, certain kinds of cultural tastes will be accepted at any given time in society. There is strict submission to fashion. "This submission to fashion also exists among men in America to a degree unknown in Germany. Such submission is considered to be an indication of the fact that a given man pretends to qualify as a gentleman. This submission decides, at least prima facie, that he will be treated as such . . . The development of status is essentially a question of stratification resting on usurpation. Such usurpation is the normal origin of all status honor." 8o Where status considerations have been realized to their full extent, status groups harden into a closed caste. "Social distinctions are then guaranteed honor not merely by conventions and laws but also by ritu-als." For the most part, however, "caste" of this sort arises only where there are underlying differences which are held to be ethnic. Dignity is closely related to honor. "Only with the negatively privileged status groups does the 'sense of dignity' take a specific deviation. A sense of dignity is the precipitation in individuals of social honor and of conten- tional demands which a positively privileged status group raises for the deportment of its members." so Such is the picture of stratification in contemporary society that Weber presents. I have stressed its close relation to Tocqueville's earlier analysis, but it would be unjust if we did not emphasize two important aspects of Weber that are not to be found in Tocqueville. The first is methodological. What Weber does is convert the concepts of power, class, and status into a framework of analysis flexible enough to be used as a comparative perspective in the study of all societies. In Tocqueville 216 THE UNIT-IDEAS OF SOCIOLOGY the three elements are not only largely implicit, but they are confined to his empirical observation of the United States and Western Europe. They are, thus, more nearly historical than sociological in temper. The second element follows from the first. The concept of status is employed by Weber on a world-wide scale and is made the point of departure of study of specific institutions: particularly religion. Thus, for Weber, the concept of status group becomes an indispensable means of analyzing ancient Judaism, the formation of caste in India, and the rise of the Junkers in modern Prussia. Status becomes a tool of analysis, an explicit framework of observation, through which matters as diverse as religion, econ-omy, education, and political behavior are illuminated. From Weber more than any other sociologist has come contemporary sociology's varied use of status and status group in the analysis of human behavior. Down until the nineteen-thirties. Marx's monolithic and unwieldy vision of class tended to dominate the study of stratification. No doubt what proved necessary to end the spell of Marx in modern sociology was not so much the accumulation of new data as the political spectacle of Sta- & K M. COLLEGE MOBILE: 8130462424 lin's Russia and consequent ideological disaffection. But the result, however gained, was the same: the gradual supersession of "class" by G "status" as the key concept in sociological studies of stratification. Today, as a sociological concept, class is dead. THE AUTONOMIZATION OF STATUS-SIMMEL There are two quite distinct principles of social organization posited by Simmel which, taken together, go far to explain, or to provide a theoretical setting for, the view of status that had its origin in Tocqueville and received its most creative statement in Weber. The first of these principles is autonomization; the second is objectification. That the referent of each of these principles is by no means limited by Simmel to the sphere of stratification does not affect the relevance of both to the concept of status in modern society. Autonomization, for Simmel, is a basic principle of social develop-ment, one through which the disengagement or separation of elements previously united is achieved in an institution or a social form. Such elements "become autonomous in the sense that they are no longer inseparable from the objects which they formed and thereby made available to our purposes. They come to play freely in themselves and for their own sake; they produce or make use of materials that exclusively serve their own operation or realization." ®I Prime examples of "autonomiza-
(Themes in Comparative History) Pamela M. Pilbeam (Auth.) - The Middle Classes in Europe, 1789-1914 - France, Germmany, Italy and Russia-Macmillan Education UK (1990)
(Historical Materialism Book Series) Craig Brandist - The Dimensions of Hegemony_ Language, Culture and Politics in Revolutionary Russia-Brill (2015)-11-60
(Themes in Comparative History) Pamela M. Pilbeam (Auth.) - The Middle Classes in Europe, 1789-1914 - France, Germmany, Italy and Russia-Macmillan Education UK (1990)
(Historical Materialism Book Series) Craig Brandist - The Dimensions of Hegemony_ Language, Culture and Politics in Revolutionary Russia-Brill (2015)-11-60