Nietzsches Revaluation of All Values
Nietzsches Revaluation of All Values
Nietzsches Revaluation of All Values
Revaluation
About the Series
Friedrich Nietzsche is one of the most
Series Editors
Kaitlyn Creasy
of All Values
important and influential philosophers California State
of the nineteenth century. This University,
Cambridge Elements series offers
concise and structured overviews of
a range of central topics in his thought,
San Bernardino
Matthew Meyer Thomas H. Brobjer
University of
written by a diverse group of experts Scranton
with a variety of approaches.
NIETZSCHE’S
REVALUATION OF ALL
VALUES
Thomas H. Brobjer
Uppsala University
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
Shaftesbury Road, Cambridge CB2 8EA, United Kingdom
One Liberty Plaza, 20th Floor, New York, NY 10006, USA
477 Williamstown Road, Port Melbourne, VIC 3207, Australia
314–321, 3rd Floor, Plot 3, Splendor Forum, Jasola District Centre,
New Delhi – 110025, India
103 Penang Road, #05–06/07, Visioncrest Commercial, Singapore 238467
www.cambridge.org
Information on this title: www.cambridge.org/9781009539470
DOI: 10.1017/9781009421652
© Thomas H. Brobjer 2024
This publication is in copyright. Subject to statutory exception and to the provisions
of relevant collective licensing agreements, no reproduction of any part may take
place without the written permission of Cambridge University Press & Assessment.
When citing this work, please include a reference to the DOI 10.1017/9781009421652
First published 2024
A catalogue record for this publication is available from the British Library
ISBN 978-1-009-53947-0 Hardback
ISBN 978-1-009-42163-8 Paperback
ISSN 2976-5722 (online)
ISSN 2976-5714 (print)
Cambridge University Press & Assessment has no responsibility for the persistence
or accuracy of URLs for external or third-party internet websites referred to in this
publication and does not guarantee that any content on such websites is, or will
remain, accurate or appropriate.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
Nietzsche’s Revaluation of All Values
DOI: 10.1017/9781009421652
First published online: November 2024
Thomas H. Brobjer
Uppsala University
Author for correspondence: Thomas H. Brobjer, [email protected]
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
Contents
References 63
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
Nietzsche’s Revaluation of All Values 1
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
2 Philosophy of Friedrich Nietzsche
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
Nietzsche’s Revaluation of All Values 3
statements imply that the revaluation will mean an inversion of values so that
the values held in low esteem today will be held in high, and conversely.
Furthermore, the present Christian values are regarded as anti-natural. On
several occasions, Nietzsche implies that the revaluation has already begun,
and even occurred, through Nietzsche himself and his equals. It follows that
Nietzsche’s affirmative values are the values associated with the healthy side of
the dichotomy. Finally, we are in fact given an example of a revaluation from
decadence to health in the form of the Renaissance, and Nietzsche closely
associates the present revaluation to that of the Renaissance – ‘my question is
its question’.
Apart from these general statements, we are also given three concrete
examples of what Nietzsche means by the revaluation. First, he refers to his
understanding of Greek tragedy as his first revaluation of all values: ‘the soil
out of which I draw all that I will and can’. Second, he claims that the free
spirits already constitute a revaluation of all values. Furthermore, Nietzsche
ends Ecce Homo with the statement: ‘Dionysus against the Crucified’, where
Dionysus represents healthy and life-affirming values, while the Crucified
represents Christian and present values.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
4 Philosophy of Friedrich Nietzsche
differently, if it is his intention to pour us new wine: ‘The answer is: No. [. . .]
In other words, the “revaluation” was a war against accepted valuations, not
the creation of new values’ (1974: 111). The revaluation is ‘the diagnosis itself’.
However, strangely enough, Kaufmann adds that ‘this consists in nothing
beyond what Socrates did’, referring to Socrates in his role as a ‘gadfly’ and
quoting Nietzsche’s use of him in this sense. This is unfortunate, for Nietzsche
also regarded Socrates as one of the most important revaluators of the first
negative revaluation, the one from antiquity to moralization and Christianity.
Kaufmann’s conclusion is clearly that the revaluation is a critical project: ‘The
revaluation is thus the alleged discovery that our morality is, by its own stand-
ards, poisonously immoral’ (1974: 113). However, he also mentions, but with-
out drawing conclusions or consequences, that ‘The “revaluation” is not a new
value-legislation but reverses prevalent valuations that reversed ancient valu-
ations’ (1974: 111).
Ackermann’s book Nietzsche: A Frenzied Look is one which attempts ‘to
sketch Nietzsche in movement’ in which much of Nietzsche’s later thought is
related back to his earlier writings and to his sympathy with the pre-Socratics.
Without going into details, he nonetheless claims in the preface: ‘I try to show
Nietzsche’s thoughts develop and ramify from his early, concentrated vision of
Greece before Socrates, a vision that Nietzsche never abandons and a vision that
is the source of his shocking new tables of values’ (1989: ix).
One work that does take the ‘revaluation of all values’ as a central thought in
Nietzsche’s philosophy is Beat Kissling’s 400-page PhD dissertation entitled
Die Umwertung der Werte als Pädagogisches Projekt Nietzsches (1992). It also
acknowledges the importance of early Greek thought for Nietzsche, but the
emphasis in the book is on interpretations of Nietzsche’s views by later thinkers,
and on its relevance for pedagogics.
This general lack of discussions about the revaluation is surprising and
unfortunate. It is surprising, considering Nietzsche’s own emphasis, which is
as much, or more, on this theme as on any other. It is unfortunate, since this is
closely associated with Nietzsche’s own affirmative or constructive values. A
disregard of the revaluation is associated with an over-emphasis on Nietzsche’s
critical philosophy at the price of under-valuating his constructive and affirma-
tive alternative. It is also ‘unfortunate’ because we are confused about and lack
understanding of values, and Nietzsche is one of the few philosophers who have
thought profoundly about values.
A work that frequently mentions revaluation is Bernard Reginster’s The
Affirmation of Life: Nietzsche on Overcoming Nihilism (2006), where his main
claim is the truism that according to Nietzsche, for us to overcome nihilism, we
need to revalue the values that leads to nihilism (50). Reginster uses a rather
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
Nietzsche’s Revaluation of All Values 5
analytical approach and divides nihilism into two forms, nihilism of despair
and nihilism of disorientation (a dichotomy that Nietzsche does not set up). He
assumes that Nietzsche regarded that ‘the essential inhospitality of this world’
leads to despair (100). However, Nietzsche seems to regard life-affirmation
as being natural (and therefore refers to natural and anti-natural, i.e., decadent,
values), especially before the first revaluation (performed by the Jews,
Christianity, and Plato). Nietzsche emphasizes the richness and superabun-
dance of life, nature, and the world. He thus, counter to Reginster, regards
affirmation as the default view (Nietzsche rejects pessimism as well as nihil-
ism). Nowhere does the book discuss or even mention the first ‘negative’
revaluation nor the four-volume literary project, Revaluation of All Values,
that Nietzsche worked hard on for the last four to five years of his active life.
Reginster bases much of his arguments on the somewhat unreliable collection
of late notes, The Will to Power, rather than on the much more reliable KSA
(which also is much more chronologically reliable).
A full-length study of Nietzsche’s revaluation is E. E. Sleinis’ Nietzsche’s
Revaluation of Values: A Study in Strategies (1994). His emphasis is ‘on the
theoretical feasibility of such an enterprise’. His main concern is to examine the
apparently impossible attempt to revalue all values. Can values be revalued
without recourse to values? For this purpose, he examines the methods and
strategies Nietzsche uses. He argues that Nietzsche has a naturalistic conception
of value and that the source of all value lies within valuing beings. Further, he
asserts that for Nietzsche there exists an objective measure of value and that this
is power. In four chapters, he deals with truth, moral values, religious values,
and aesthetic values, and their relation to a revaluation. For example, in the
chapter on religious values, Sleinis correctly argues that Nietzsche performs
a meta-revaluation in that he views religions not as an ontological thesis but as
essentially concerned with value. Concretely, he argues that Nietzsche’s higher-
order values are those that result in the invigoration and the enrichment of life.
This book thus contains both more and less than its title seems to promise.
There is no examination of what Nietzsche said or meant when he referred to
revaluation, nor any discussions of the concrete values that Nietzsche referred to
as healthy values. What it does contain is an analytical account of much of
Nietzsche’s philosophy in general and especially regarded values. However, the
gap between what Nietzsche actually says and Sleinis’ analysis is often so great
that the analysis becomes less interesting and all too abstract. Nowhere in the
book is there any reference to, or discussion of, Nietzsche’s many statements
that a revaluation has already occurred between antiquity and Christianity.
These and many other of Nietzsche’s references to revaluation give us important
information about what Nietzsche meant by revaluation. To me, it seems very
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
6 Philosophy of Friedrich Nietzsche
clear that it is not an abstract revaluation of all our present values, including all
of Nietzsche’s own values, into something completely new. Instead, the revalu-
ation refers to the change from one set of (life-denying) values to another and
opposing set of (life-affirming) values. Some of these values will be new, but
many will be old in the sense that we are aware of them today and that they were
even more prevalent during antiquity and the Renaissance. With such a view,
many of Sleinis’ investigations appear abstract and irrelevant, but a number of
side issues are clarified and his examination of many of Nietzsche’s strategies
remains relevant and illuminating. A related study is Aaron Ridley’s article
‘Nietzsche and the Re-Evaluation of Values’ (2005) that also, in an analyt-
ical manner, attempts to clarify what a revaluation would entail. Both studies
conclude that a revaluation is at least theoretically feasible.
John Richardson has recently written a valuable study, Nietzsche’s Values
(2020), that contains many interesting and good arguments and insights.
Especially valuable, it seems to me, is his emphasis on value, on truth, and on
using historical approaches. However, oddly enough, revaluation is not much
discussed in the book. There is no chapter or subchapter that discusses it, nor
does he refer to the only full book-length study of revaluation, that of Sleinis
(discussed earlier), and in the index the term ‘Revaluation’ has only five pages
listed, and these pages do not contain much discussion of it. He, like a better
Sleinis, works mostly on a theoretical level. There is little discussion of actual
values Nietzsche revalues, and there is no discussion or even mention of the
four-volume literary project, Revaluation of All Values, that Nietzsche worked
on. Nonetheless, Richardson correctly points out that ‘genealogy is indispens-
able for a revaluation of our values’ (325) because it discloses the origin of our
values and because it creates a necessary distancing effect that history always
has. He further argues that what Nietzsche wants is ‘spiritual’ growth, not
a technological, an economic or one of physical power, but ‘understanding of
itself and especially of its own willing and valuing’ (456). He continues:
He further points out that ‘the overall way Nietzsche means to “revalue” our
norms is by “de-moralizing” them’ (457). These, and many other observations,
are valuable, but it seems to over-emphasize the social and long-term aspects
of a revolution of values, and miss the more concrete revaluations (e.g., of
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
Nietzsche’s Revaluation of All Values 7
Christian and moral values) Nietzsche most frequently argues for, and his
claims, at least in part, to already have performed.
Andreas Urs Sommer has in his Friedrich Nietzsches ‘Der Antichrist’ (2000)
insightfully discussed several aspects of the theme revaluation, and especially
emphasized Nietzsche’s use of false coinage and fraudulence, e.g., in The
Antichrist, 12, for references to those who argue for the false present values
(from the perspective of the healthy and true early values). He argues that one
of the senses of the hammer, in the subtitle of Twilight of the Idols, is a
‘Prägehammer’, which determines which coins are valid and which are false.
‘Nietzsche’s revaluation reinstalls that, which due to the “false coinage” of
the idealists, Christians and other bad company had been regarded as invalid
coinage’ (155). Joseph Kranak has written an interesting dissertation entitled
Nietzsche’s Revaluation of All Values (Marquette University, 2014), that examines
many different aspects of Nietzsche’s philosopheme as an unfinished concept
(and unfinished work), but without using any German language material.
Much remains to be studied to better understand Nietzsche’s revaluation and
his views of and relation to value. Perhaps it is also possible for us to use
Nietzsche to better understand values and evaluation in general. In a note at the
end of the first essay of On the Genealogy of Morals (GM I 17, Nietzsche’s
note), he writes, ‘All the sciences have from now on to prepare the way for the
future task of the philosophers: this task understood as the solution of the
problem of value, the determination of the order of rank among values.’
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
8 Philosophy of Friedrich Nietzsche
revaluation will only succeed if we understand the power and genesis of present
values. In this sense, On the Genealogy of Morals is a preparatory study for the
revaluation. This is also how Nietzsche describes the three essays that constitute
the book in Ecce Homo after having stated that Christianity is ‘a counter-
movement, the great revolt against the domination of noble values’ and that it
was born out of a spirit of ressentiment: ‘Three decisive preliminary studies of
a psychologist for a revaluation of all values’ (EH ‘Books’ GM). Though not
obvious from the title, The Case of Wagner concerns a revaluation of aesthetic
values, mainly in the sense parallel to Beyond Good and Evil and The Antichrist,
i.e., in the form of a critique of the decadent values of which Wagner is ‘the most
instructive case’.1 Or as he says in the discussion of the work in Ecce Homo:
‘What is it I suffer from when I suffer from the destiny of music? From this: that
music has been deprived of its world-transfiguring, affirmative character, that it
is décadence music and no longer the flute of Dionysus’ (EH ‘Books’ CW:1).
The title of the next work, Twilight of the Idols (Götzen-Dämmerung), stands for
a testing and smashing of idols – i.e., of old truths and values, and that these
truths and values are on their way out. He presents the book in Ecce Homo with
the words:
Anyone who wants to get a quick idea of how topsy-turvy everything was
before I came along should make a start with this work. What the title page
calls idol is quite simply what till now has been called ‘truth’. Twilight of the
Idols – in plain words: the old truth is coming to an end. (EH ‘Books’ TI:1)
1
For aesthetic values, as is also the case in regard to moral values, the healthy values are the
classical ones. This is most evident in the epilogue to The Case of Wagner: “In its measure of
strength every age also possesses a measure for what virtues are permitted and forbidden to it.
Either it has the virtues of ascending life: then it will resist from the profoundest depths the virtues
of declining life. Or the age itself represents declining life: then it also requires the virtues of
decline, then it hates everything that justifies itself solely out of abundance, out of the overflowing
riches of strength. Aesthetics is tied indissolubly to these biological presuppositions: there is an
aesthetics of decline, and there is a classical aesthetics.” The same distinction is discussed in GS,
V, 370 (and reprinted in Nietzsche contra Wagner) under the title: “What is romanticism?” where
he makes the main distinction regarding all aesthetical values concerning whether “it is hunger or
superabundance that has here become creative?” The values associated with an over-fullness of
life are repeatedly referred to as Dionysian.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
Nietzsche’s Revaluation of All Values 9
Since at least 1884 (but really already from 1881), Nietzsche had planned to
write a major magnum opus, that he called his Hauptwerk, from 1886 using the
expression ‘revaluation of all values’ either in the title or in the subtitle, as I will
discuss in Section 2 of this Element. The Antichrist was the first and the only
finished volume of this Hauptwerk, but his notebooks contain plans and notes
for the three following volumes.
2
Sometimes Umwerthung is translated, less accurately, as transvaluation. This translation is less
suitable since the meaning of Umwerthung for Nietzsche is closer to revaluation than to trans-
valuation, as will be shown next. This is also shown by the synonyms which he uses for
Umwerthung, such as Umkehrung (= reversal) and umkehren (= turn back) and Umdrehung
(= turn, revolution, rotation) and umdrehen (= turn round, turn over, turn back). Finally, consid-
ering that Nietzsche was no stranger to the coining of words and phrases, it seems likely that
he would have coined the words Transwerthung and transwerthen if transvaluation was what
he meant.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
10 Philosophy of Friedrich Nietzsche
interpretation, which can be called the critical interpretation, has even less
to say about the future revalued values and hence also about Nietzsche’s
affirmative values.
3. The third interpretation understands the revaluation as a reversal of values,
today’s high values will after the revaluation become low values and the low
ones high. This interpretation can be called a reversal interpretation. It
implies that the new values are defined in terms of a reversal of the present
values. It can find support in the texts of Nietzsche but remains problematic
since it is rarely obvious what the opposite of most values are without some
other measure or criterion. This interpretation is probably unusual, at least
among Nietzsche scholars. Some of those critical of Nietzsche’s philosophy
may hold this view.
4. The fourth interpretation understands the revaluation as essentially a
re-valuation, i.e., back to earlier ancient, noble, and healthy values. This
interpretation is the only one with a fairly clear view of what the new values
should be like – with similarity and kinship to the old ancient values – and is
thus perhaps more open to falsification than the other three. This interpret-
ation can be called a dichotomy interpretation for it assumes that there exist
two value-paradigms, the noble and natural contra the anti-natural and
decadent, the ancient contra the modern (Christian). This view has often
been a minor supplement to the utopian and critical interpretations, but
rarely defended as the main interpretation.
It is unlikely that any one of these four interpretations, as ideal types, will alone
yield a complete and perfect interpretation. Rather, each of them has its own
virtues and strengths and a certain degree of mixture is to be expected.
Nonetheless, there are strong arguments that the last, the dichotomy interpret-
ation, is superior to the others.
The dichotomy interpretation does not assume a complete copying of Greek
values, only that there are two opposing sets of fundamental values. A copying
of values would be both undesirable and impossible (compare KSA 8, 7[1]:
‘A culture, which copies a Greek one, can create nothing new’). There is an
important ingredient of something new and something different that possibly is
understated in its name. This can be seen in Nietzsche’s emphasis on creativity,
on the new, and on the future.
The supporters of the utopian interpretation make use of a section in Twilight
of the Idols:
In the ear of the Conservatives. – What was formerly not known, what is
known today or could be known – a reversion, a turning back in any sense and
to any degree, is quite impossible. We physiologists at least know that. But all
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
Nietzsche’s Revaluation of All Values 11
priests and moralists have believed it was possible – they have wanted to take
mankind back, force it back, to an earlier standard of virtue. Morality has
always been a bed of Procrustes. (TI ‘Expeditions of an Untimely Man’ 43)
This appears to strongly favour the ‘utopian’ interpretation, or at least falsify the
‘reversed’ and the ‘dichotomy’ interpretations. However, this is not the case. Such
an understanding of this statement would be comparable to viewing Nietzsche’s
critique of liberal theologians and free thinkers such as David Strauss as indicating
that Nietzsche was a Christian. His view is rather that the conservative and the free
thinker are not radical enough. They remain within one value-paradigm and either
dilute these values or attempt to return to older outlived versions of the same
values. A few sections below in Twilight of the Idols, Nietzsche again makes a
statement that at first appears to confirm the ‘utopian’ interpretation but, after
closer inspection, actually fits the dichotomy interpretation better.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
12 Philosophy of Friedrich Nietzsche
interpretations are forced to deny the dichotomy of values since they must
assume at least a third alternative for the future. Considering the prominent
place of the dichotomy in Nietzsche’s discussions of the revaluation, this is
a very serious flaw. This denial also means that they are forced to interpret
Nietzsche’s references to the reversal of values much more metaphorically than
they are intended. They also ignore the hints that the revaluation already has
occurred, with Nietzsche and his equals. In conclusion, this means that they
ignore or under-value many of Nietzsche’s most fundamental affirmative values
associated with, for example, tragedy, antiquity, the Renaissance, and nobility.
The ‘critical’ interpretation is correct in discussing the critique of our present
values. In the preface to On the Genealogy of Morals Nietzsche writes: ‘Let us
articulate this new demand: we need a critique of moral values, the value of these
values themselves must first be called in question [. . .] One has taken the value of
these “values” as given, as factual, as beyond all question’ (GM ‘Pref’ 6). Our
present values are, according to Nietzsche, anti-natural and there is a sense in
which a critique of these values is likely to lead to a return to natural values, i.e.,
noble values, like those of the Greeks and the Renaissance. However, in the
absence of affirmative values, such critique could also lead to a deepened nihilism
or, as was the case with Luther’s criticism, to a revival. However, not only does
the critical interpretation ignore Nietzsche’s affirmative values, but it also ignores
or rejects the dichotomy, and this gives its critique of the present values a false
perspective. It exchanges the utopian aspects of the previous interpretation for an
overly critical interpretation. In ignoring the constructive side of the revaluation,
they lay themselves open to Nietzsche’s critique: ‘Those are my enemies: they
want to overthrow but not to build up. They say: “all that is without value” – but
do not want to create any value’ (KSA 10, 5[1], 218). In what it ignores, the
‘critical’ interpretation has the same flaws as the previous one.
The third interpretation, which regards the revaluation as a reversal of today’s
values, is based on Nietzsche’s many references to a reversion and inversion of
values, and on his critique of our present values. However, this interpretation
makes little sense unless one accepts a dichotomy of values, for the meaning of
a reversal of values generally, without a dichotomy, is not obvious. The second
problem with this interpretation is that it starts with today’s values and attempts
to invert them. This is a reactive response that fails to take Nietzsche’s affirma-
tive ideals into sufficient consideration. When this is done, the interpretation
becomes similar to the fourth one, the ‘dichotomy’ interpretation.
We have seen that the ‘dichotomy’ interpretation is the one most compatible
with Nietzsche’s statements regarding the revaluation of all values. However,
the revaluation need not be regarded as a return to earlier values, for Nietzsche’s
view is probably better described as claiming that there exist two systems of
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
Nietzsche’s Revaluation of All Values 13
value – life- and reality-affirming and life- and reality-denying – always and
independently of history.3 However, it remains true that the greatest example of
a life-affirming epoch is that of the early Greeks and that we have much to learn
from them. There need not be any contradiction between Nietzsche’s praise
of antiquity and his emphasis on creating values. A large part of the emphasis
on the creation of values is directed against merely obeying present values,
and choosing values is part of the creation of values. When Nietzsche talks of
Greece as a prototype and example, he is not referring to a slavish copying, but
to a creative inspiration.
Already by the first occurrence of the word revaluation and of the concept
‘revaluation of all values’ in Nietzsche’s published writings, Beyond Good and
Evil 46, he clearly sets up a dichotomy and claims that a revaluation has already
occurred. The dichotomy is between freedom, pride, and self-confidence on one
side and enslavement, self-mockery, and self-mutilation on the other, where the
latter is associated with Christianity. Then Nietzsche states: ‘the paradoxical
formula “god on the cross” [. . .] promised a revaluation of all the values of
antiquity’ (BGE 46), a dichotomy between ancient and Christian values is
constructed. He continues by pointing at the psychology behind the revaluation:
slave-natures with ‘the great hidden suffering’ (BGE 46), i.e., resentment at
those more privileged than themselves, like the Jews against the Roman nobility
with their tolerance. Thus, in this first occurrence, the revaluation referred to is
the earlier and negative one from antiquity to Christianity. The second reference
to the concept, in Beyond Good and Evil 203, now refers to a positive revaluation:
Those who are to carry it out would have to be healthy, strong, and hard but it
is still not clear what this revaluation would entail. The emphasis still concerns
a critique of the present set of ‘Christian-European’ values, which has led, and
leads to an ever-greater diminution of man. However, in the previous section,
Nietzsche defined modern morality in the terms: ‘Morality is in Europe today
herd-animal morality’ and we can thus see how Nietzsche strengthens the
3
In KSA 13, 14[25], written in early 1888, Nietzsche says: “the word classical here used not in the
historical sense, but in the psychological one.”
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
14 Philosophy of Friedrich Nietzsche
Note that he claims that tragedy and the Greeks constitute ‘the soil out of
which I draw all that I will and can’. It is difficult for him to be more explicit as
to where the foundation of his affirmative values lies. He makes a similar claim
in a notebook from 1884: ‘The knowledge of the great Greeks has formed me’
(KSA 11, 26[3]).5
There are three important explicit references to ‘revaluation of all values’
in The Antichrist. The first gives a third description of what this revaluation
4
“This is our difference from the Greeks: their morality grew out of the ruling casts.” KSA 11,
25[163], early 1884.
5
“Die Kenntniß der großen Griechen hat mich erzogen: an Heraclit Empedocles Parmenides
Anaxagoras Democrit ist mehr zu verehren, sie sind voller” [than the great philosophers like
Kant, Hegel, Schopenhauer and Spinoza].
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
Nietzsche’s Revaluation of All Values 15
means: ‘Let us not undervalue this: we ourselves, we free spirits, are already
a “revaluation of all values”’ (A 13). This shows that the revaluation is already
occurring and it shows the strong ethics of virtue nature of Nietzsche’s thinking,
i.e., that the personality is primary and values and actions only secondary. The
free spirits are further down in the section associated with realism, scientific
method and scepticism. In the penultimate section of The Antichrist, we are
presented with perhaps the clearest expression of what the revaluation of all
values means. Nietzsche here claims that a second revaluation already has been
attempted and for a time succeeded, but in the end failed:
Notice that Nietzsche here, and earlier, refers to ‘the opposing values’ (my
italics), not a set of opposing values or just opposing values, strongly implying that
it is a question of only two alternatives, i.e., a dichotomy of systems of values.
Nietzsche constantly praises the Renaissance highly. Like antiquity, but more
rarely and on a lower level, it constitutes an example and model for him. He refers
to it as the ‘last great age’ (TI ‘Expeditions’ 37) and claims that ‘in the modern
time it is the Italian Renaissance which has brought man the highest’ (KSA 10,
7[44]). Both Goethe and Napoleon are associated with the Renaissance (KSA 12,
9[179] and GS 362). He highly commends its sense of virtù. Modern man is
inferior to the man of the Renaissance but ‘the man of the Renaissance, is inferior
to the man of antiquity’ (KSA 12, 16[111]). The Renaissance is generally regarded
as a rebirth of antiquity and was so viewed also by Nietzsche: ‘There was [. . .]
in the Renaissance an uncanny and glittering reawakening of the classical ideal,
of the noble mode of evaluating all things’ (GM I 16). Thus, when he claims that
‘my question is its question’ (A 61), he refers to the Renaissance revaluation of
Christian values into essentially ancient values.
In the last section of The Antichrist, Nietzsche again reaffirms his attack on
the present values (so concisely and provocatively expressed in the title of the
work itself):
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
16 Philosophy of Friedrich Nietzsche
The last sentence is equivocal but an important sense is surely ‘all (Christian)
values have been revalued’. Nietzsche has disclosed Christianity (including
secularized Christianity) and shown us the alternative. We shall not forget that
while writing The Antichrist and Ecce Homo, he planned three further volumes on
the theme of the revaluation. That last sentence is probably also a (half-hidden)
reference to these three further volumes under the main title of Revaluation of All
Values.
Nietzsche’s Ecce Homo was written after The Antichrist but was intended to be
published before it. In the first sentence of the preface, Nietzsche explains the
purpose of the book as a presentation of ‘who I am’ – ‘I am the disciple of the
philosopher Dionysus’ – before he will make the heaviest demand on mankind,
that is, the revaluation of all values. The ‘revaluation of all values’ is the Leitmotif
throughout the work and it contains eleven explicit references to it. In the first
two chapters, ‘Why I am So Wise’ and ‘Why I am So Clever’, Nietzsche seems to
describe the revaluation as the goal and meaning of his life, and he attempts to
show why he is able to see and do what no one else sees or does.
At the end of his discussion of The Birth of Tragedy in Ecce Homo, without
using the word revaluation, Nietzsche clearly refers to a revival of Greek values:
‘Everything in this essay [The Birth of Tragedy] is prophetic: the proximity of
the return of the Greek spirit, the necessity for counter Alexanders to retie the
Gordian knot of Greek culture after it had been untied . . . Listen to the world-
historic accent with which the concept “tragic disposition” is introduced’ (EH
‘Books’ BT:4). With this, Nietzsche also implies that the ‘revaluation’ is a
theme in his writing from his first book onwards. In the sixth section of his
discussion of Human, All Too Human he states that the revaluation is a conse-
quence of historical knowledge, and hence rejects ‘utopian’ interpretations.
The importance of history for the revaluation, and more concretely, what in
history, is expressed in a note from the first half of 1888: ‘I sought in history
the beginning of the construction of reverse ideals (the concepts “pagan”,
“classical”, “noble” newly discovered and expounded –)’ (KSA 13, 16[32]).
In his discussion of Dawn, he describes the revaluation as ‘an escape from
moral values’ which, of course, is fully consistent with his view of himself and
Zarathustra as immoralists. A bit later in the same section, he refers to morality
as the morality of ‘unselfing’. Almost always when Nietzsche speaks of
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
Nietzsche’s Revaluation of All Values 17
morality, he refers to modern and Christian morality. Thus, even though it does
not appear so, the statement ‘an escape from all moral values’ allows for
alternative moral values, for an ancient or master morality. Recall, if you will,
Nietzsche’s critique of Socrates and Plato for having moralized the world.
Nietzsche further in this section describes the positive side of the revaluation:
‘in an affirmation of and trust in all that has hitherto been forbidden, despised,
accused’. This shows, pace the utopian and critical interpretations, that the new
values are not unknown, only at present de-valued. This appears to confirm the
reversal interpretation, but on closer inspection, it fits the dichotomy interpret-
ation of the revaluation better.
In the first section of Nietzsche’s discussion of Beyond Good and Evil in
Ecce Homo, he claims that the affirmative part of his task was already done
after having written Dawn, The Gay Science, and, most importantly, Thus
Spoke Zarathustra – ‘it was the turn of the denying, the No-saying and
No-doing part: the revaluation of existing values themselves, the great war’.
This view of Zarathustra as affirmative and of Thus Spoke Zarathustra as an
affirmative book is consistent with all Nietzsche’s statements about Zarathustra –
possessing ‘great health’ and as ‘this most affirmative of all spirits’ – and of his
enormous appraisal of the work. What is the nature of the values and the
Weltanschauung in this work? For Nietzsche Thus Spoke Zarathustra is
a tragic work.6 We need to recall that tragedy is for Nietzsche an affirmative art
and Weltanschauung: ‘the affirmative pathos par excellence, I call the tragic
pathos’ (EH ‘Books’ Z:1). When Nietzsche introduces Zarathustra for the first
time, in The Gay Science 342, this section is called ‘Incipit tragoedia’, i.e., ‘the
tragedy begins’, and the section also ends with these words. He uses the same
words when he refers to Thus Spoke Zarathustra after it was written, in The Gay
Science, V, 382. From this section he also quotes in Ecce Homo at length. In his
discussion of Thus Spoke Zarathustra in Ecce Homo, he refers to it, or aspects of
it, five or six times as the concept Dionysus and as being Dionysian, and he refers
to the language of Zarathustra as dithyrambic. The Weltanschauung is thus,
according to Nietzsche, akin to ancient tragedy. We cannot examine all the values
expounded in Thus Spoke Zarathustra here, but those of ‘that decisive chapter’
(EH ‘Books’ Z:1) ‘Of Old and New Law-Tables’, so suitable for a study of the
revaluation of all values, can be commented upon. The theme of this chapter in
Thus Spoke Zarathustra is clearly one of revaluation even if the expression is not
used. About half of the thirty sections of this, the longest chapter in Thus Spoke
Zarathustra, are critical and give different versions of ‘shatter the old law-tables’.
6
For an excellent work on Nietzsche and tragedy, and of Thus Spoke Zarathustra as a tragic work,
see May (1990: especially Ch. 7). See also Higgins (1987: Ch. 2) and Meyer (2024: Ch. 1).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
18 Philosophy of Friedrich Nietzsche
This critique culminates in the command: ‘Shatter, shatter the good and the just!’
The new law-tables are only half-written, lying among the old shattered ones. We
are given a rather long list – in the form of metaphors and similes – of virtues,
descriptions, and imperatives, summarizing most of what has been said earlier in
Thus Spoke Zarathustra. (Nietzsche did not publish part four of Thus Spoke
Zarathustra and therefore this section which is placed near the end of part three,
can well be seen as a summary.) The affirmative part of this chapter claims that
what is good and evil depends on the goal, and the goal is the Übermensch. To
this theme, a number of concepts are associated: the future, a new nobility,
wanting to rule, and life and society as an experiment. We are further given
a description of ‘the highest soul’ and a very large number of ‘virtues’ are
described and recommended: the bestowing virtue, honesty (realism), creativity,
courage, dance and laughter, pride and self-love, self-overcoming, and becoming
better than the best (compare Nietzsche’s interest and praise of the Greek
concepts agon and aristeuein), and willingness to sacrifice oneself and one’s
neighbours. It culminates in: ‘This new law-table do I put over you, O my
brothers: Become hard!’ – for the noble and the creative are hard, and the soft
will inevitably adapt themselves to the present values.
The interpretation of Thus Spoke Zarathustra as the culmination of Nietzsche’s
affirmative values is confirmed a little later in Ecce Homo, where Nietzsche
claims that the domination of Christian values was due to the fact that ‘above all,
a counter-ideal was lacking – until Zarathustra’ (EH ‘Books’ GM). Thereafter
Nietzsche refers to the tremendous task of the revaluation and speaks of it as
a shattering thunderbolt, explaining thereby the title of the last chapter: ‘Why
I am a Destiny.’ In this chapter Nietzsche claims: ‘But my truth is dreadful: for
hitherto the lie has been called truth. – Revaluation of all values: this is my
formula for an act of supreme coming-to-oneself on the part of mankind which in
me has become flesh and genius’ (EH ‘Destiny’ 1). Nietzsche here suggests, as
he has also done earlier, that the two value systems are not equivalent – not only
are they different and of different value, but one is also natural while the other is
not. Therefore, the turning, or returning, to the ancient paradigm can be regarded
as a ‘supreme coming-to-oneself’. Nietzsche continues: ‘I contradict as has never
been contradicted and am nonetheless the opposite of a negative spirit.’ The same
statement is repeatedly made about Zarathustra. The reason he can make this
apparently paradoxical statement is because he contradicts within one ‘para-
digm’, while praising or pointing at another – or, alternatively, he regards himself
as a philosophical physician who is negating a negation, who is attacking a
disease and thus, by negating, being curative. Nietzsche continues on this theme
in section seven: ‘Indeed, this is my insight: the teachers, the leaders of humanity,
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
Nietzsche’s Revaluation of All Values 19
theologians all of them, were also, all of them, decadents: hence the revaluation of
all values into hostility to life, hence morality’ (EH ‘Destiny’ 7).
In section eight, he reconnects to Thus Spoke Zarathustra and gives several
examples of truths and concepts created by Christian morality but absent among
healthy values:
Have I been understood? I have not just now said a word that I could not have
said five years ago through the mouth of Zarathustra – The unmasking of
Christian morality is an event without equal, a real catastrophe. He who
exposes it is a force majeure, a destiny [. . .] The concept ‘God’ invented as
the antithetical concept to life [. . .] The concept ‘soul’, ‘spirit’, finally even
‘immortal soul’, invented so as to despise the body, so as to make it sick [. . .]
The concept ‘sin’ invented together with the instrument of torture which goes
with it, the concept of ‘free will’ [. . .] Finally – it is the most fearful – in the
concept of the good man common cause made with everything weak, sick, ill-
constituted, suffering from itself [. . .] an ideal made of opposition to the
proud and well-constituted, to the affirmative man, to the man certain of the
future and guaranteeing the future – the latter is henceforth called the evil
man . . . And all this was believed in as morality! – Ecrasez l’infâme! (EH
‘Destiny’ 8)
We can note that according to Nietzsche none of these ‘inventions’ (with the
exception of the immortal soul accepted by, for example, Pythagoras and
Empedocles) – the Christian God, sin, free will, and ‘goodness’ – existed in pre-
Socratic Greece. The last section of Ecce Homo, essentially Nietzsche’s last
words, consists of only a few words: ‘Have I been understood? – Dionysus
against the Crucified.’
The first two occurrences of the expression ‘revaluation of all values’ in
Nietzsche’s writings can be found in a notebook covering the period of summer
and autumn 1884, i.e., about one year before Nietzsche wrote Beyond Good
and Evil where it first appeared in print (KSA 11, 26[259] and 26[284]).7 Its very
first appearance is as a catchword, as a subtitle to a planned work: ‘Philosophy of
Eternal Recurrence: An Attempt at the Revaluation of All Values’, that probably
represents an early version of Nietzsche’s plans for a Hauptwerk. The second
occurrence is in a note, consisting of three short numbered sections, outlining the
planned content of this work. First, the idea of eternal recurrence, its presupposi-
tions, and its consequences are to be introduced. Second, discussion of eternal
recurrence as the heaviest thought: and its probable effect if it is not prevented by
means of a revaluation of all values. Third, the revaluation of all values is
introduced as the means of enduring the idea of eternal recurrence. Pleasure at
7
Thereafter come six occurrences in a notebook that covers a full year, from approximately when
Nietzsche started writing Beyond Good and Evil until it was published.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
20 Philosophy of Friedrich Nietzsche
uncertainty (rather than certainty), creativity, power, and pride are associated with
the revaluation.
The expression ‘revaluation of all values’ occurs in two slightly different
senses in Nietzsche’s notebooks. In a first sense, it is used mainly as a catchword
in drafts for titles or subtitles (usually for Nietzsche’s Hauptwerk). The second
sense is more general and similar to how it is used in the published works
already discussed. I have found about two score occurrences, about half of them
as title or subtitle, and half of them as an expression used or discussed.
Of the more general references to revaluation in Nietzsche’s notebooks,
several are more or less duplicates of one another, and several are drafts and
very similar to the published statements already discussed. In several of them,
he emphasizes that the old values necessarily lead to pessimism and nihilism.
He emphasizes the strength and importance of the revaluation by claiming that it
will be very costly, a theme discussed in greater detail in Ecce Homo, and he
asks questions such as ‘How would these men have to be constituted who took
upon themselves this revaluation?’ Only four notes will here be used to supple-
ment the previous discussion. All four discuss the revaluation of moral values
and set up slightly different versions of the same dichotomy, that between
a morality of self-denial and one of self-affirmation. In the first of these,
Nietzsche states: ‘The ignored main fact: There is a contradiction between
‘becoming more moral’ and the lifting up and making stronger the type man’
(KSA 12, 2[131]). In the second: ‘What has been deified? The value instincts in
the community (that which made possible its continued existence). What has
been slandered? That which set apart the higher men from the lower, the desires
that create clefts’ (KSA 13, 16[15]). In the third: ‘Not the “moral corruption” of
antiquity, but precisely its moralization is the prerequisite through which alone
Christianity could become master of it. Moral fanaticism (in short: Plato)
destroyed paganism, by revaluating its values and poisoning its innocence’
(KSA 13, 16[15]). In the last of these four notes, the dichotomy is made most
explicit:
Nietzsche thus wants to see come about, what during the Renaissance most
clearly occurred in the arts: the centre of gravity moved from God, religion,
8
Part of this long note was used in EH “Destiny” 7.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
Nietzsche’s Revaluation of All Values 21
symbolism, and the ‘beyond’ and instead man and individual men were put in its
place.
Nietzsche also uses a large number of synonyms for revaluation. Most frequent
are Umdrehung and Umkehrung, but many others are also used.9 His use of these
is very similar to his use of revaluation and therefore little new information is
contained in these expressions for us here. Only one example will be mentioned
here. There he claims that really great humans are lacking, and the reason is our
herd-animal morality – which ‘in Europe today is simply called “morality” – as if
there were no other morality and could be no other’. He continues:
Whoever has thought profoundly about where and how the plant man has
hitherto grown most vigorously must conclude that this has happened under the
reverse conditions [. . .] A morality [must appear] with such reverse intentions,
which desires to train men for the heights, not for comfort and mediocrity [. . .]
To prepare a reversal of values for a certain strong kind of man of the highest
spirituality and strength of will [. . .] whosoever reflects on this becomes one of
us, the free spirits – to be sure, a different kind of ‘free spirit’ from those before
us; for the latter wanted approximately the opposite of what we do. To us, it
seems to me, belong [. . .] all those critics and historians who courageously
carry forward the happily-begun discovery of the world of antiquity – it is the
work of the new Columbuses of the German spirit (for we stand at the
beginning of this conquest). For in the world of antiquity there reigned
a different, more lordly morality than today; and the man of antiquity, raised
in this morality, was a stronger and deeper man than the man of today – he alone
has hitherto been ‘the man who turned out well’. (KSA 11, 37[8])
Close readings of Nietzsche’s late books and his late notes make it possible to
identify a rather large number of concrete values that he revalues, such as pity,
pride, the ‘good man’, and the herd animal man.10
9
Other synonyms or near synonyms are Umdrehung, Umkehrung, entgegengesetzter Werthe,
Werth-Gegensatz, auf den Kopf, transcendence, Umtaufung, entwerthen, Wandel der Werthe,
and Umsturz.
10
I have discussed such concrete revalued values in some of the late books, in my studies Brobjer,
2021, 2023a and 2023b. In a slightly different context, Richardson discusses the revaluing of pity
and altruism in Nietzsche’s New Darwinism (2004: Ch. 5).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
22 Philosophy of Friedrich Nietzsche
are based upon) does not discuss the revaluation of all values before Beyond
Good and Evil (1886), except briefly in regard to Nietzsche’s childhood
essay ‘Fatum und Geschichte’ and regarding a statement in the third Untimely
Meditation. The valuable entry in the Nietzsche Handbuch, written by Andreas
Urs Sommer, mentions nothing before 1884, but his immensely rich commen-
taries Friedrich Nietzsches ‘Der Antichrist’: Ein philosophisch-historischer
Kommentar (2000) and Kommentar zu Nietzsches Der Antichrist, Ecce Homo,
Dionysus-Dithyramben und Nietzsche contra Wagner contain much interesting
and relevant material. Philippa Foot, in her ‘Nietzsche: The Revaluation of
Values’, in Nietzsche: A Collection of Critical Essays, edited by Robert Solomon
(1973), 156–168, refers to no work earlier than Thus Spoke Zarathustra. Richard
Schacht’s Nietzsche (1983) contains a long chapter on ‘Value and Values’, includ-
ing a long subchapter entitled ‘Toward a Revaluation of Values’, but only uses and
refers to post-Thus Spoke Zarathustra books and the notes published as The Will to
Power (i.e., notes from 1885 to 1888). However, three studies, by Higgins, Ridley,
and Owen, seem, without discussion, to place its beginning significantly earlier, in
the works Dawn (1881) and The Gay Science (1882).
The place and development of the revaluation theme in Nietzsche’s thought
can be summarized as follows.
11
Historisches Wörterbuch der Philosophie, “Umwertung.” However, Andreas Urs Sommer has
shown (private communication) that the word Umwertung existed before Nietzsche, in literature
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
Nietzsche’s Revaluation of All Values 23
dealing with economics, but Nietzsche still seems to be the first to have used it in a philosophically
relevant sense.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
24 Philosophy of Friedrich Nietzsche
1. ‘Change of valuation.’
2. ‘One needs, by means of a radical scepticism in regard to values, first of all
to overthrow all value judgments, to have free opportunity.’
3. ‘Everything which we now call immoral has somewhere and sometime
once been moral. What guarantees that it does not yet again change its
name?’
4. ‘Christianity made everything interesting again, by turning upside down
every value judgment.’
5. ‘[A] great task has arisen on the horizon before it, namely the revision of
every valuation: however, before all things are laid on the scales, the scale
itself is necessary – I mean that sort of highest sense of judgment of the
highest intelligence.’
12
The revaluation theme is also, but much more vaguely, visible in sections 115, 116, 301, and 335.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
Nietzsche’s Revaluation of All Values 25
6. ‘For that new values are needed. First a critique and removal of the old.’
7. ‘Either value other things than are valued or value things differently than
they are valued.’
8. ‘For the purpose of changing people: we for once need to assume that our
values about good and evil acts are false and arbitrary, everything needs to
be examined anew.’
9. ‘Main question: according to what is the table of values determined and
changed? So that one property appeared more valuable than another?’
10. ‘Change of valuation – is my task’ (KSA 9, 1[56], 3[54, 66, 116, 158],
5[25], 6[175, 378] and 11[20, 76]).
We can note that all of these statements were made before his ‘discovery’ of
eternal recurrence in August 1881, and that Nietzsche’s concern with values and
the change of values constituted an important context of that discovery. In fact,
one can regard the thought of eternal recurrence as the answer to what he asks
for and discusses in many of his notes in 1880/81 as the thing that can help one
change and evaluate values.
That Nietzsche discovered and developed the theme of revaluation in 1880/
81 is also consistent with his own claims in Ecce Homo, where he, in his
discussion of Dawn, with its motto ‘There are so many daybreaks that have
not yet dawned’ writes: ‘Where does its author seek that new dawn [. . .]? In
a revaluation of all values, in an escape from all moral values, in an affirmation
of and trust in all that has hitherto been forbidden, despised, accused.’ This
could have been an example of how Nietzsche reinterpreted his earlier writings
in line with his later thought, but the notes from 1880/81 show that this claim
was not just a later construction, but was based on, at least in part, views already
present at that time. We can also note that there is a dramatic increase in
Nietzsche’s use of the word ‘value’ and derivations of that word in 1880/81
(as well as an increase in his use of the word morality and its derivations). We
can especially note the increase in his use of the word ‘esteem’, or setting the
value of, ‘Werthschätzung’ and the word value-judgement, ‘Werthurtheil’
(which he had never used before 1880). What happened in 1880/81 is that
Nietzsche became concerned with values and evaluation in general.13
13
It is, of course, possible to go beyond 1880 and find traces of this idea and concern earlier. As any
historian will know, it is almost always possible to find earlier traces of anything and any thought.
However, these earlier traces are merely traces, not signs of a conscious concern with this
concept and idea. Such scattered traces can, for example, be found in Nietzsche’s early Germania
essay “Fate and History” from 1862 and in the third Untimely Meditation, Schopenhauer as
Educator, 3 (1874), and I will discuss a few of them in the chapter “Nietzsche and Ancient
Values.” What happened in 1880/81 is that the problem of value, morality and change of
valuation became a theme or major theme in Nietzsche’s thought.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
26 Philosophy of Friedrich Nietzsche
The ten most immediate references to the revaluation theme from 1880/81,
quoted earlier, fall into four groups. These seem to correspond well to many of
Nietzsche’s later and more well-known statements regarding the revaluation of
all values.
There seems to be no one specific context that proves itself much more
important than several other ones for the development of the revaluation
theme. It is true that the revaluation of all values has a sort of origin in
Nietzsche’s critique of Christianity, but it is approximately equally true that
it has its origin in the context of a more general critique of contemporary
values, and in the problems of pessimism (in Nietzsche’s important wresting
with Schopenhauer), in the contrast expressed by ancient Greek values, and
by eastern values, in insight into the errors of old values, and by the simple
effect of relativism. Other contexts of these early revaluation-notes include
discussions of the devil (and hence evil), increasing critique of anthropocen-
trism, the debate between egoism and altruism and a general critique of
superstition and metaphysics (which many old values are rooted in, according
to Nietzsche).
One interesting consequence of dating the origin of the revaluation of all
values to 1880/81 is that it affects our view of Nietzsche’s overall thought and
its development. It is common to divide his thought and writing into three
periods: the early (1869–76), the middle (1877–82), and the late (1883–88).
There is truth in this view, and Nietzsche himself emphasized both it and the two
‘breaks’ which it implies. However, in many respects, it is misleading, and
a different view is better, as emphasized by Montinari. This second view
emphasizes primarily two periods: pre-1880, as the time before Nietzsche
fully came into his own (and it can be divided into two further periods,
a more idealistic/romantic and a more positivistic one), and one from c. 1880,
that of the mature Nietzsche. The difference between these views can be seen as
moving the second ‘break’ from 1882/83 to 1879/80/81 (the time he left his
professorship in Basel, began his nomadic period, and made several of his
philosophical ‘discoveries’).14 When referring to Nietzsche’s published
books, both pictures can be regarded as approximately equally accurate, but
14
I discuss many of these “discoveries” or themes on pages 82–89, and in the extensive notes, in
my book Nietzsche’s Philosophical Context: An Intellectual Biography (2008).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
Nietzsche’s Revaluation of All Values 27
when it comes to his life, thoughts and notes, the latter is in several respects
better since it does not deny the importance of his thought in the early 1880s
(such as his severe critique of morality, Christianity and his new concern with
values), but instead connects it with his later, post-1882 thought. However, one
should be aware that such divisions into two or three periods are constructs, and
although they can aid our understanding of Nietzsche’s thought, one should use
them with care and certainly not as dogma. In important ways, there is, of
course, also a continual development throughout Nietzsche’s life.15
15
For a very different periodization of Nietzsche’s works, see the discussion in Matthew Meyer’s
Reading Nietzsche through the Ancients (2014: 277f.).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
28 Philosophy of Friedrich Nietzsche
In the very first section of Zarathustra’s speeches, ‘On the Three Trans-
formations’, he describes the development of the higher soul, from that of
a camel via a lion to a child. These are also the fundamental stages along the
road to revaluation – from being diligent and steadfast (holding on to and
defending values), to rebelling (negating values) to creating new values (revalu-
ation). The creation of new values is emphasized and is that which characterizes
the third stage of the transformation, the ‘child’. This emphasis on revaluation
or creation of new values is then explicitly repeated in two sections in the first
book: ‘The noble man wants to create what is new and a new virtue’ (Z I ‘Tree
on the Mountainside’), and: ‘Around inventors of new values the world
revolves’ (Z I ‘Flies of the Marketplace’). Thereafter it is again strongly
emphasized in the last section, ‘On the Bestowing Virtue’: ‘Verily, this is a
new good and evil! [. . .] and may the value of all things be posited anew by you!
For that you shall be fighters! For that you shall be creators!’
The creation of new values and the revaluation theme is slightly less empha-
sized in the second book, but still explicitly present in several sections. In the
first, it is referred to by the expression ‘and weeds are called wheat’, i.e., that it is
the wrong values that are praised (Z II ‘The Child with the Mirror’). In another,
he repeats the claims from book 1, ‘Not around the inventors of new noise, but
around the inventors of new values does the world revolve; inaudibly it
revolves’ (Z II ‘On Great Events’). He also develops the theme further by
emphasizing the close connection between creating and destroying: ‘And who-
ever must be a creator in good and evil: verily, he must first be an annihilator and
shatter values. Thus does the highest evil belong to the highest good: but this
latter is the creative’ (Z II ‘On Self-Overcoming’).
In the third book the concern with values and new values is again more
explicitly present, especially in ‘Of Old and New Tablets’, the longest section in
all of Thus Spoke Zarathustra, which seems to summarize much of the contents
of the first three books, and in which it becomes the main theme:
Each one thought he had long since known what was good and evil for man.
[. . .] But he it is who creates a goal for mankind and gives the earth its meaning
and its future: he it is who creates the quality of good and evil in things. [. . .]
now he [Zarathustra] sits here and waits, old shattered law-tables around him
and also new law-tables – half-written (Z III ‘On Old and New Tablets’).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
Nietzsche’s Revaluation of All Values 29
The fourth book of Thus Spoke Zarathustra (not published by Nietzsche) can
be regarded as primarily dealing with an example of a revaluation of the value of
‘Mitleid’ (pity or compassion).
Nietzsche emphasizes in Thus Spoke Zarathustra that it is the human subject,
the I, ‘this creating, willing, valuing I, that is the measure and value of things’
(Z I ‘On Believers in a World Behind’). Later in the text, he defines man as the
valuator:
The human being first put values into things, in order to preserve itself – it
created a meaning for things, a human’s meaning! Therefore it calls itself
‘human’ – that is: the evaluator. Evaluating is creating: hear this, you cre-
ators! Evaluating is itself the treasure and jewel of all valued things. Through
evaluating alone is there value: and without evaluating the kernel of existence
would be hollow. Hear this, you creators! Change of values – that means
change of creators. Whoever must be a creator always annihilates. (Z I ‘On
the Thousand Goals and One’)
16
See Brobjer (2003).
17
Compare also the notes KSA 11, 40[66] and 41[9], also written for a reworking of Human, All
Too Human.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
30 Philosophy of Friedrich Nietzsche
The four major themes in Thus Spoke Zarathustra, the death of God, eternal
recurrence, revaluation, and Übermensch are closely related and interwoven
with one another. Very briefly and simplified: The death of God reflects a crisis
of value. This crisis is both further recognized, and ways to heal it are suggested,
by the idea of eternal recurrence (which both intensifies our experiences of the
crisis and suggests a solution or way towards a solution) and the revaluation of
values (which makes a fundamental dichotomy of values apparent and presents
more life-affirming values) and the Übermensch represents a concrete living
solution of a new type of human who is able to live and affirm life and reality
without a belief in God and metaphysics.
In Nietzsche’s own discussion of Thus Spoke Zarathustra in his last book,
Ecce Homo, it is the two themes of eternal recurrence and revaluation that he
emphasizes.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
Nietzsche’s Revaluation of All Values 31
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
32 Philosophy of Friedrich Nietzsche
in the sense that he refers to the superiority of Greek human beings: ‘Greeks the
genius among the peoples [. . .] The individual raised to his highest powers
through the polis’ (KSA 8, 5[70]) and ‘the verdict of the philosophers of ancient
Greece on the value of existence says so much more than a modern verdict does
because they had life itself before and around them in luxuriant perfection’
(Untimely Meditation III 3). Nietzsche also refers to Greek culture as
a standard: ‘When the Greek body and the Greek soul “bloomed” [. . .] there
arose that mysterious symbol of the highest world-affirmation and transfigur-
ation of existence that has yet been attained on earth. Here we have a standard
by which everything that has grown up since is found too short, too poor, too
narrow’ (KSA 11, 41[7]).18 That the greatness of the Greeks was according to
Nietzsche due, at least partially, to their morality is shown in the following
quotation: ‘For in the world of antiquity there reigned a different, more lordly
morality than today; and the man of antiquity, raised in this morality, was a
stronger and deeper man than the man of today – he alone has hitherto been “the
man that has turned out well”’ (KSA 11, 37[8]). Most explicitly, Nietzsche’s
view is expressed in a note from 1883: ‘I regard Greek morality as the highest so
far’ (KSA 10, 7[44]).
Greek antiquity also frequently occurs as an example in the writings of the
late Nietzsche: ‘The highest types hitherto, the Greeks’ (KSA 11, 35[47]) and
‘the highest type [of ideal]: the classical ideal’ (KSA 13, 11[138]). It would be
easy to add many more examples.19
Occasionally, Nietzsche in line with the revaluation also attempts a valuation
of present phenomena, values, and thought in terms of antiquity or by asking
what would the ancients have thought of it: ‘The ancient world has in fact
always been understood only in terms of the present – and will the present now
be understood in terms of the ancient world?’ (KSA 8, 3[62]) and ‘I do not doubt
that the first thing an ancient Greek would remark in us Europeans of today
would also be self-diminution – through that alone we should be “contrary to his
taste”’ (BGE 267).
Nietzsche’s constant high praise of the Renaissance, including calling it an
attempted revaluation, can and ought also to be regarded as relating to a revival
of antiquity, and to healthier values.
18
This whole note is pertinent. In it, Nietzsche claims that “Dionysus is a judge” in the sense that
antiquity is the judge of modernity.
19
A few other examples of late references to Greece as an example and ideal are: “The best turned
out, most beautiful, most envied type of humanity to date, those most apt to seduce us to life, the
Greeks” (BT “ASC” 1).“Oh, those Greeks! They knew how to live!” (GS “Pref” 4).“The whole
labour of the ancient world in vain: I have no word to express my feelings at something so
dreadful” (A 59).“Den Menschen über sich hinaus steigern, gleich den Griechen” (KSA 10,
9[29]).“Heimisch sein in der griechischen Welt!” (KSA 11, 41[4]).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
Nietzsche’s Revaluation of All Values 33
In the last section of the first essay of On the Genealogy of Morals (GM I 17),
Nietzsche speaks of ‘that greatest of all conflicts of ideals’ and then rhetorically
asks, ‘Must the ancient fire not some day flare up much more terribly, after much
longer preparation? More: must one not desire it with all one’s might? even will
it? even promote it?’
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
34 Philosophy of Friedrich Nietzsche
contents of the Hauptwerk, in line with the previous note, but now with much
more detail (KSA 12, 2[131]). Also, the sixth time he uses it is again in a draft of
a title of the Hauptwerk, in four volumes (KSA 12, 5[75]). In the autumn of
1888, he several times used both these expressions, revaluation and eternal
recurrence, in his draft for the Hauptwerk, both under the title Will to Power and
Umwerthung aller Werthe (KSA 13, 18[17], 19[8] and 22[14]).
We can thus see that the first ten times he uses the term ‘revaluation’ he
almost always does so together with the expression ‘eternal recurrence’, and in
relation to his Hauptwerk.
How are we to understand this close relation between the idea of eternal
recurrence and the revaluation of all values? Normally they are by scholars
and commentators discussed and elaborated on individually and separately,
but Nietzsche connects them. I believe that especially the idea of eternal
recurrence is easier to understand when treated together with the revaluation
of all values.
Already in the first note where Nietzsche discusses the idea of eternal
recurrence, he emphasizes that its effect is the ‘eternal importance’ of our
knowledge, errors, our habits, our lives (he will soon add our values). ‘Now
comes the most difficult knowledge [eternal recurrence] and makes all sorts of
life dreadfully serious.’ Imagine the whole of history eternally repeated, he
writes: ‘Not to be thrown over by that thought, our sense of compassion must
not be great.’ But taking on ourselves all of past and future suffering is too
much for us, Nietzsche argues in this early note, ‘but whether we still want to
live is the question, and how!’ (KSA 9, 11[141]). Immediately thereafter
Nietzsche writes in another note: ‘If you fully accept the thought of thoughts
[i.e. the idea of eternal recurrence] it will transform you. For everything you
want to do, the question becomes: “Is it so that I want to do it infinitely many
times?” this is the greatest weight’ (KSA 9, 11[143]). Shortly thereafter he
writes: ‘Let us press the image of eternity on our life! This thought contains
more than all religions, which teaches this life as a brief contempt and to look
for an undetermined other life’ (KSA 9, 11[159]). Soon Nietzsche argues that
to live with this thought, to affirm this life, we need to get rid of sin and
morality – and to revalue our values.
The main point of Nietzsche’s thought of eternal recurrence is not a physical
theory about that everything is repeated, but a thought experiment or hypoth-
esis that forces us to take and experience life as thousandfold more important
than before. This leads us to want to value life so that we want to live again.
For that, we need to take away, revalue, things that reduce our valuation of life
and our desire to live again. Most obviously this means for Nietzsche sin,
morality and Christianity (which makes us seek meaning and value beyond
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
Nietzsche’s Revaluation of All Values 35
life), but equally obvious, pessimism (which precisely says that life is not
worth living) and nihilism (which says that nothing matters, nothing has any
value).
(i) Nietzsche never stated that he gave up on the project (since he did not).
That he (possibly) did so is a (faulty) conclusion of modern scholars based
merely on that Nietzsche after about 20 November 1888 referred to The
Antichrist in a few letters as ‘the Revaluation of All Values’ rather than as
‘the first book of the Revaluation of All Values’. This does not necessarily
mean that he had given up on the project. On the contrary, there can be
several reasons for this and I will show that he had referred to The
Antichrist as the Revaluation already earlier (when there can be no doubt
that he regarded it as part of his four-volume magnum opus), and, more
importantly, quote two occasions where he as late as in middle of December
1888, just weeks before his mental collapse, still refers to The Antichrist as
‘the first book of the Revaluation of All Values’.
(ii) Even if Nietzsche had given up on the project at the end of November 1888,
almost certainly as a consequence of his impending mental collapse, this
changes almost nothing. First, it still means that he planned and worked
hard to write a four-volume magnum opus for about five years or more,
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
36 Philosophy of Friedrich Nietzsche
including while writing his late books, from Thus Spoke Zarathustra
onwards. If he changed his mind after having written Twilight of the
Idols, The Antichrist and Ecce Homo in 1888, it is merely of biographical
interest. Second, he did no philosophical work after late November 1888; at
least we have no serious philosophical notes from this time or later. The
work on a philosophical magnum opus remains Nietzsche’s by far largest
and most prolonged philosophical project!
For those who are interested in Nietzsche’s thought and philosophy, this is his
most important and relevant project – far more so than any of his published
books. It has one major drawback for us. Of the four planned volumes, three
remain uncompleted or unfinished. This is a disadvantage, but not only so. It
seems to me that it is quite suitable for a thinker of such dynamic philosophy as
Nietzsche’s that what we have is not merely a static set of finished positions, but
rather ample material for developing many of his most interesting thoughts,
including the revaluation of all values.
I will in this second part of this study show that we possess many hundreds of
pages of interesting and detailed notes and tables of contents for how Nietzsche
planned to develop his thought. We are not only left with The Antichrist and
three further unwritten volumes about which we know little or nothing. We
possess much information about the planned contents of the three unfinished
volumes, and there are things to learn from the first volume, The Antichrist,
about the planned further three volumes. Nietzsche even, immediately after
having finished The Antichrist, began working and drafting large sections of
volume 3, The Immoralist, notes that seem not even to have been translated into
English until very recently. These notes cover approximately ten pages that
he worked on until or near 15 October 1888 (KSA 13, 23[3–7]). Thereafter
Nietzsche’s notebooks only contain another thirty-three pages in the KSA
version. Most of these are filled with notes for Ecce Homo, a few late additions
for Twilight of the Idols and some general notes on other topics.
A great part of Nietzsche’s notes for the Hauptwerk is from, or were revised
in, 1887 and 1888, and thus represents Nietzsche’s last evolving philosophical
views. Furthermore, among these are detailed plans of the contents of the four
planned volumes, plans that Nietzsche used when drafting the contents of
volume 1 during the spring of 1888, then dealing with truth and nihilism.
When he decided in September 1888 that volume 1 instead was to deal with
a critique of Christianity, and the previous volume 1 then became volume 2, he
again used these plans and notes to draft the contents of The Antichrist.
Nietzsche had a remarkably consistent view about the contents of the planned
Hauptwerk. The last three volumes of the magnum opus remain unwritten, but
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
Nietzsche’s Revaluation of All Values 37
2.2 The Debate and Controversy about the Planned Magnum Opus
2.2.1 The Status of Nietzsche’s Notes
The most common attitude towards Nietzsche’s late notes today is that they
represent discarded material,20 and that they, when not overlapping with what is
said in his published books, should not be taken as Nietzsche’s view. We see a
similar view in Hollingdale:
The Nachlass can be read with profit only by someone familiar with
Nietzsche’s published works, the reason being the above-mentioned fact
that its content is rejected material [sic] [. . .] the only principle which does
not impose a spurious order upon it is that of comparison and collation with
the published work. It falls into two large divisions: (i) preliminary drafts or
parallel formulations of something already published, and therefore rejected
as superfluous; and (ii) material set aside as being for one reason or another
unacceptable. [. . .] in the latter [case] one must [. . .] exclude the aphorism
from any formulation of Nietzsche’s philosophy, since this is precisely what
Nietzsche himself did. And one must be capable, of course, of distinguishing
between the former kind of material and the latter. The basic consideration to
be kept in mind all the time is that anything in the Nachlass which cannot be
paralleled in the published works is not valid.21
the Nachlass does present a great deal of philosophical material that never
makes its way into the published texts. [. . .] The status of this material has
been controversial: should it be used to support interpretations of Nietzsche’s
published works? Should its failure to appear in the published works be taken
as evidence that Nietzsche definitively rejected the ideas? In many cases,
especially in the late Nachlass, it is simply impossible to tell whether an idea
was set aside as unworthy or simply never returned to because of Nietzsche’s
collapse. For the Nietzsche scholar, this is, I believe, a reason to be extremely
cautious in terms of presenting the ideas in the Nachlass as Nietzsche’s ideas.
(Had he written something and later added: ‘but this is wrong!’, we would
20
See Magnus (1988: 161), who refers to Nietzsche’s notes as “dustbin manuscripts” (and in the
connecting footnote 23, Nietzsche’s notes are dismissed as “discarded” material). See also
Magnus (1986).
21
Hollingdale (1999: 223).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
38 Philosophy of Friedrich Nietzsche
have a different case, but he rarely does this.) Several years ago, Bernd
Magnus drew a distinction between two approaches to Nietzsche’s
Nachlass, dividing Nietzsche’s principal commentators into ‘lumpers’
(including Heidegger, Jaspers, Danto, Schacht, Deleuze, and Müller-
Lauter), for whom the status of the Nachlass is unproblematic, thus treating
it as on at least a par with Nietzsche’s published writings; and ‘splitters’
(including Alderman, Hollingdale, Strong, Montinari, and himself), who
‘distinguish sharply between published and unpublished writings’. Since
Magnus first drew this distinction, and since the Colli-Montinari edition has
become the canonical edition, the number of scholars who simply lump all of
Nietzsche’s writings together, treating published and unpublished works in
the same way, has dwindled to near zero, especially in the English-speaking
Nietzsche scholarly community.
This is claimed without any motivation, and without showing that this is the
case, for example by showing that much of what can be found in Nietzsche’s
Nachlass is rejected material. Nietzsche, in fact, often did strike out many notes,
unlike what Schrift implies. He struck out about 10 per cent of the notes in
the three notebooks W II 1–3, used in 1887 and 1888, visible in KGW IX,
but not mentioned in KSA or the standard KGW (I-VIII). He seems to have done
this mostly because either he had used them for writing The Case of Wagner,
Twilight of the Idols or The Antichrist, or because he had copied them over into
other later notebooks.
However, oddly enough, Magnus, Hollingdale, Schrift, et al. ignore that
Nietzsche, in the last active five years of his life, had great plans and collected
many notes to be used for his Hauptwerk, but then suddenly collapsed on
3 January 1889. These notes, the majority of which are from the last years,
were obviously not discarded and do not fall into the unfortunate dichotomy
between either published notes (and variants of this) or discarded notes (which
actually seem to be very few). They instead fall into a third category of notes
Nietzsche wrote, collected, organized, and revised for use in his planned four-
volume Hauptwerk.
Jing Huang has recently written an excellent paper on how Nietzsche’s
notes have been viewed in the Anglo-Saxon world, summarizing much of the
debate. She correctly points out that ‘We should not forget that Nietzsche’s
work was interrupted forever in one of the most productive periods of his life’,
and summarizes the fact that Nietzsche wanted some of his notes, a small
amount, burnt in 1888, which ‘neither suggests the abandonment of the
project of the will to power [the Hauptwerk], nor warrants a devaluation of
the Nachlass’.22
22
Huang (2019: 1206 and 1196).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
Nietzsche’s Revaluation of All Values 39
23
This essay has also been published, in slightly different forms, in several other publications,
including in the commentary volume to Nietzsche’s works, KSA 14, as well as translated into
English in Reading Nietzsche (2003), 80–102.
24
The difficulty to know exactly what Nietzsche meant is made more difficult by the fact that this
is stated at the very beginning of the letter, which is likely to be a response to a letter by Fuchs
that is no longer extant, so that we lack a context to the claim, or to Nietzsche’s previous letter
(that probably is lost). If Fuchs in his letter discussed The Antichrist and/or Nietzsche’s life
(Ecce Homo) and/or critique of Christianity, Nietzsche’s statement would seem to refer to
these works. In his last pervious extant letter to Fuchs, 9 September 1888 (KSB 8:1104),
Nietzsche speaks about Twilight of the Idols, The Case of Wagner and then adds: “the next that
then comes is the Revaluation of All Values (which first book is almost finished).” When
Nietzsche later in the letter from 11 December (KSB 8:1187) says that one can now say things
about him that two years later will seem like silliness, it seems possibly to refer to the further
three volumes of the Hauptwerk that will need time to be written and published. Furthermore,
Nietzsche’s statement can be influenced by his request that Fuchs should write something
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
40 Philosophy of Friedrich Nietzsche
The second part, that Nietzsche gave up the idea of publishing a four-volume
Hauptwerk, is based on the fact that Nietzsche refers to The Antichrist as
the Umwerthung aller Werthe, and no longer only as the first volume of
the Umwerthung in two letters from late November 1888. Furthermore, he
sometime in December wrote a new title page with the subtitle, instead of
the original ‘the First Book of the Revaluation of All Values’ with only
‘Revaluation of All Values’. However, he kept the original title page so there
are thus two slightly different title pages in the printer’s manuscript copy, so it
is not certain that he changed his mind. The changed subtitle may not neces-
sarily reflect a change in the number of volumes, but merely that each of them
could be read in any order, and independently of the others (and all four could
then have the latter subtitle, Revaluation of All Values), which is consistent
with how The Antichrist is written. The standard interpretation is thus mainly
based on a few of Nietzsche’s letters, the earliest to Brandes, 20 November and
to Deussen, 26 November 1888 (KSB 8:1151 and 1159). It is not altogether
unlikely that what Nietzsche referred to in these letters was his present work,
and that he simply decided not to speak of the three remaining forthcoming
volumes. Nietzsche had, in fact, in letters already before mid-November
seemingly referred to The Antichrist as the complete Umwerthung aller
Werthe in that manner, by not referring to it as the first volume, though,
clearly, he regarded it as only the first volume at that time. Furthermore, the
fact that Nietzsche twice thereafter, in the second half of December, refers to
The Antichrist as the first book of the Revaluation seems to nullify Montinari’s
and the standard interpretation, as well as that interpretation of the letter to
Fuchs.
Montinari’s interpretation of this, that Nietzsche had decided not to go on
and write the remaining three books of the planned Hauptwerk, seems perhaps
possible, but it is not the only interpretation. Against this stands the fact that
Nietzsche referred to The Antichrist as the first book of the Revaluation in
several letters as late as in mid-November 1888 (to Overbeck and Meta von
Salis, 13 and 14 November 1888, KSB 8:1143 and 1144), after which there are
no philosophical notes and work. Nietzsche had for over five years been
planning and working on a four-volume work, and he had also promised in
print, as we will see, in most of his late books to publish such a work. There is
nothing in Nietzsche’s few notes or in his many letters from mid-November
that seems to reflect such a major change in his thought as giving up these
plans would be. Furthermore, in the proofs for the Ecce Homo manuscript
about him (and then it is obviously better if things are finished), and the letter is obviously
influenced by Nietzsche’s impending collapse.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
Nietzsche’s Revaluation of All Values 41
(as well as in an unused note for Nietzsche contra Wagner), The Antichrist is
referred to as ‘the first book of the Revaluation of All Values’ in the second half
of December (as I will show). We also know that after he had finished The
Antichrist, he set to work on The Immoralist, and worked on that until he in
mid-October decided that he needed to write Ecce Homo as preparatory to the
Revaluation.
Alan Schrift, in ‘Nietzsche’s Nachlass’ (quoted earlier), while discussing
Nietzsche’s plans for a Hauptwerk, follows Montinari in every detail.
Julian Young, in his Friedrich Nietzsche: A Philosophical Biography (2010),
does not really discuss Nietzsche’s plans and work on a Hauptwerk during five
years. However, he has a separate chapter dealing with Nietzsche’s plans for
a Hauptwerk, placed after he had finished dealing with Nietzsche’s active life,
including 1888, chapter 26: ‘The Rise and Fall of “The Will to Power”.’ He
limits his discussions exclusively to the plans for the Hauptwerk while it was
entitled Der Wille zur Macht, that is from August 1885 to August 1888, and
closely associates it with Nietzsche’s philosopheme will to power. He argues
that Nietzsche gave up on this theme (although Nietzsche actually continues to
refer to it also in Ecce Homo), and therefore also on the Hauptwerk. Young
thereby fails to see the larger picture and ends up discussing a pseudo-problem,
why Der Wille zur Macht was never completed rather than why the planned
magnum opus was never completed and why it was renamed (534). Nonetheless,
Young admits that ‘the Revaluation [can be seen] as a continuation of the
‘masterwork’ project’ (541), but argues like Montinari, without referring to
him, that the two letters from the end of November show that it ‘in the end
abbreviated itself into The Antichrist’ (542). He does not refer to Nietzsche’s
later references to The Antichrist as the first book of the Hauptwerk, nor to the
degree that the decision was influenced or determined by Nietzsche’s mental
state. However, he does, I believe correctly, reject Nietzsche’s very late change
of the subtitle of The Antichrist to Curse on Christianity, because ‘Nietzsche
was almost certainly insane when he created it’ (542).
However, to repeat, the second problem with Montinari’s interpretation (if it
was to be correct) is that it accepts the collapsing of Nietzsche’s statements
as annulling his earlier view, which is much more relevant, for that was when he
worked as a philosopher, from 1884 to late in 1888, from Thus Spoke Zarathustra
to Ecce Homo. The Montinari interpretation uses a few statements from when
Nietzsche was mentally unstable to interpret backwards. Throughout Nietzsche’s
late period, he intended and worked on a Hauptwerk, which was never com-
pleted, but nonetheless affected the contents of all of his late books and late notes.
Even if Nietzsche changed his mind, during the end of November or December
1888, just weeks before his total collapse (at a time when he no longer wrote any
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
42 Philosophy of Friedrich Nietzsche
philosophical notes, and his judgement was clearly affected by the impending
collapse) it does not change that while he was healthy and wrote his late books
and notes he planned to write a four-volume Hauptwerk. At a minimum, one
needs to be aware of this when discussing these books and these notes. Actually,
there are good grounds to assume that there is much interesting material in
Nietzsche’s late notes that is not present or developed in his published books,
since he saved it for the Hauptwerk. There is much material that awaits closer
examination and discussion in the future.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
Nietzsche’s Revaluation of All Values 43
between the late notes and the published works.25 The only exception seems to be
Friedrich Würzbach’s attempt Umwertung aller Werte: Aus dem Nachlass zusam-
mengestellt und herausgegeben (München, second ed. 1969). In fact, both of
these versions are more like subjective selections from Nietzsche’s notes and
attempts at organizing them (and thus really not all that different from the many
shorter and more random selections from the late Nietzsche’s notebooks that have
been published) rather than attempts to follow Nietzsche’s own intentions. It is, in
fact, at least in outline, possible to follow Nietzsche’s intentions, but this has not
been done.
Still more surprising, considering that it coloured and partly determined much
of Nietzsche’s life and work during the last five years of his active life, is that the
question of his attempt to write a Hauptwerk has received almost no in-depth
discussion in the many biographies of Nietzsche. It is, for example, only briefly
discussed by Janz, and hardly mentioned at all in most other ones, by, e.g.,
Rüdiger Safranski, Nietzsche: Biographie seines Denkens (2000), Josef Rattner,
Nietzsche: Leben – Werk – Wirkung (2000), Curtis Cate, Friedrich Nietzsche
(2002), Julian Young, Friedrich Nietzsche: A Philosophical Biography (2010),
and Sue Prideaux, I Am Dynamite (2018).
Essentially, all discussions of the question of whether Nietzsche intended to
write a magnum opus, or of the relevance of his late notebooks, have exclu-
sively focused on the project ‘Der Wille zur Macht’, and inevitably got bogged
down in discussions of Elisabeth’s and Peter Gast’s selection of notes. That has
been a serious mistake, for Nietzsche’s intention to write a Hauptwerk influ-
enced and shaped what he published (and did not publish) during his whole late
period.
Many readers of Nietzsche find it surprising and frustrating that he himself
claims that the idea of eternal recurrence is so profound and fundamental, but
that he hardly elaborates on it at all. In fact, his most comprehensive published
‘discussion’ of it is in its very first presentation in The Gay Science and more
poetically in Thus Spoke Zarathustra. Thereafter he frequently alludes to it –
see, for example, the last sentence of Twilight of the Idols – but he does not carry
out any discussion of it or its consequences. There was, however, a reason for
this, and that was that he saved it to constitute the pinnacle of his Hauptwerk, as
is shown in almost all of his drafts. The same frustrated expectation can be held
about several other aspects or topics of Nietzsche’s late thought, especially
regarding the revaluation of all values and nihilism. In fact, for the latter case,
Nietzsche has even at the end of On the Genealogy of Morals promised that
25
There is not even an entry for discussions of Nietzsche’s planned Hauptwerk in the most
extensive of Nietzsche bibliographies, the Weimarer Nietzsche-Bibliographie.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
44 Philosophy of Friedrich Nietzsche
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
Nietzsche’s Revaluation of All Values 45
systematic manner than most Nietzsche scholars assume or are aware of, as he
stated, and as we can see by the first and only finished volume, The Antichrist.
I will show herein that we are able to know fairly much about the intended
content of the Hauptwerk.
At least from 1884, he stated in several letters that Thus Spoke Zarathustra
only represented a ‘Vorhalle’ or ‘entrance hall’ to his philosophy, the ‘main
building’ he planned to work through in the next years. From 1886, he began to
explicitly refer to that projected work as a Hauptwerk. The evidence for this
intention to write a Hauptwerk can be seen in his published works, in his letters
and in his notebooks. Let us examine the evidence in more detail.
The intention of writing a Hauptwerk is visible in all of Nietzsche’s books
after Thus Spoke Zarathustra (and perhaps also in Zarathustra, with its incon-
clusive ending), but this presence has been ignored or gone unnoticed by almost
all commentators. He avoided using the material intended for the Hauptwerk
when he wrote and put together his first book after Thus Spoke Zarathustra,
Beyond Good and Evil (1886) and also On the Genealogy of Morals (1887), as
stated by Montinari (KSA 14, 346). As we have seen, the subtitle of Beyond
Good and Evil refers to the Hauptwerk, and it was also announced as a work in
progress on the back cover. At the end of On the Genealogy of Morals he
explicitly refers to his future intention: ‘I shall probe these things more thor-
oughly and severely in another connection (under the title “On the History of
European Nihilism”; it will be contained in a work in progress: The Will to
Power: Attempt at a Revaluation of All Values)’ (GM III 27).27 Shortly after
having finished writing the three essays of On the Genealogy of Morals, he
writes to Gast, on 15 September 1887, that he has more to say than what is
written in them, with obvious reference to his forthcoming Hauptwerk. He
planned a second volume of On the Genealogy of Morals, with at least three
further essays, that later was merged with the plans for the third volume of the
Hauptwerk, The Immoralist. After having finished On the Genealogy of Morals,
Nietzsche intended to work more or less exclusively on his Hauptwerk for
a longer period of time – and this was largely what happened. However, he made
two short ‘pauses’ to write The Case of Wagner and Twilight of the Idols during
the following year, both of which he regarded as resting places in the midst of
the greater and much more difficult task of writing his Hauptwerk. In The Case
of Wagner (1888), he again explicitly refers to the content of his coming
27
As a typical example of how Nietzsche’s intention and work on this Hauptwerk is assumed to be
irrelevant (since no such work was finished) and is associated with the problematic selection of
Elisabeth and Gast, and thus, it is implied, is best ignored; see Maudemarie Clark and Alan
Swensen’s translation of and comments to this work (1998: 167).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
46 Philosophy of Friedrich Nietzsche
28
See Brobjer (1999) and (2023a).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
Nietzsche’s Revaluation of All Values 47
a shadow over him who sets it up – such a destiny of a task [i.e. writing the
Hauptwerk and revaluing values] compels one every instant to run out into
the sunshine so as to shake off a seriousness grown all too oppressive. Every
expedient for doing so is justified, every ‘occasion’ a joyful occasion [i.e., this
book, as well as his previous book, The Case of Wagner, are welcomed pauses
in that much more difficult task].
29
Nietzsche writes the German Umwerthung aller Werthe in exactly the same way in the two
quoted texts from the preface, while in English one is forced to choose between a statement in
italics or a title.
30
Nietzsche at a very late stage during the proofreading added the final chapter “What I Owe to the
Ancients” (which actually was written for Ecce Homo) to the manuscript.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
48 Philosophy of Friedrich Nietzsche
(which first book is almost completed)’. Two days later, he writes to Deussen
(KSB 8:1111):
In December 1888, just weeks before his mental collapse, after having just
received the printed book, he refers to it in a letter to H. Taine, 8 December
(KSB 8:1179), as: ‘in relation to that which it prepares, almost a piece of fate’,
and on a postcard to Naumann, 20 December 1888 (KSB 8:1202), as ‘short and
in the highest degree preparatory’. That for which it was meant to be preparatory
was his forthcoming Hauptwerk.
When Nietzsche wrote The Antichrist (in September 1888, although it was not
published until 1895) it constituted the first volume of four of his Hauptwerk.
This was stated, as we have seen, in the preface of Twilight of the Idols, as well as
in the subtitle to The Antichrist: ‘The first book of the Revaluation of All Values.’
In the preface to the work, Nietzsche states that this book belongs to (i.e., can only
be understood by) the very few, possibly those who understood his Thus Spoke
Zarathustra, thus connecting his Hauptwerk to his previous masterpiece.31 The
first fourteen sections of the book are more general and say something about the
overall Hauptwerk. He there emphasizes the importance of being willing and
creating higher human beings, which so far have only been ‘lucky hits’. This
should be seen as a parallel to his Übermensch-theme in Thus Spoke Zarathustra.
Still more importantly, in these sections, he makes a strong dichotomy between
ancient (healthy) and modern and Christian (decadent) values, which much of his
attempt at a revaluation relates to. By section 15, he begins to more concentrate
on the main theme of the first book of his Hauptwerk, a revaluation of Christian
values and a harsh critique of religion and Christianity.
It is surprising – and unfortunate – that these first fourteen sections have
never been read and discussed as representing part of his greater Hauptwerk,
rather than just being part of The Antichrist. Such an analysis (especially in
combination with an examination of the late Nietzsche’s notes for that work)
would yield much interesting material for the direction of the late Nietzsche’s
thought. In section six, for example, he speaks explicitly of a theme he planned
31
I have discussed of the relationship between the projected Hauptwerk and Thus Spoke
Zarathustra in Brobjer (2023b).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
Nietzsche’s Revaluation of All Values 49
32
Compare Montinari (1982: 122) “Der erste und zweite Bogen des Ecce homo waren von
Nietzsche am 18. Dezember 1888 ‘Druckfertig’ nach Leipzig zurückgeschickt worden.”
Compare Nietzsche’s letter to Naumann, 18 December 1888 (KSB 8:1198).
33
KSA 14, 459. See also the first page of the proofs which are extant.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
50 Philosophy of Friedrich Nietzsche
18 December 1888, that The Antichrist is ‘das erste Buch der Umwerthung aller
Werthe’.34 When Nietzsche revised his Nietzsche contra Wagner, which he had
begun writing and compiling on 12 December, in the middle part of December
(before 22 December), he then again refers to The Antichrist as the ‘first book of
the Revaluation of Values’ in a revision of this text that he eventually did not
use.35 This again severely contradicts any claim that The Antichrist had become
the whole Revaluation of All Values already in November.
The last book Nietzsche discussed in Ecce Homo was The Case of Wagner,
and at the very end of the discussion, he explicitly refers to his coming
Hauptwerk: ‘And so, about two years before the shattering thunder of the
Revaluation which will set the earth into convulsions, I sent the “Wagner
Case” into the world.’ He thus planned to publish the Hauptwerk in or near
1890. In a letter to Overbeck, 13 Nov. 1888 (KSB 8:1143), he writes: ‘At the end
of next year, the first book of the Revaluation will be published. It lies here
finished.’
The last chapter of Ecce Homo, ‘Why I Am a Destiny’, is to a large part
centred upon his coming work: ‘Revaluation of All Values: this is my formula
[and also the title of his coming Hauptwerk] for an act of supreme coming-to-
oneself on the part of mankind [. . .] I am a bringer of good tidings such as there
has never been’ (section 1).
Nietzsche’s intention to write a Hauptwerk is still more prominent in his
letters than in his published books. In them, we also get some hints as to the
nature of the Hauptwerk. He explicitly refers to such a work as his Hauptwerk in
a number of letters between 1886 and 1888, but an intention to write such a
work is clear already from at least 1884 onwards.
Nietzsche began to feel a new and intensive sense of purpose with his
‘discovery’ of the idea of eternal recurrence (and other related ‘discoveries’
34
I have included a picture of the proofs of this page of Ecce Homo, with Nietzsche’s handwritten
comments from 18 December 1888, and with his statement that the text is now ready to be
printed (with the text: “The first book of the Revaluation of All Values,” etc.), on p. 93 of my
Nietzsche’s ‘Ecce Homo’ and the Revaluation of All Values (2021). According to Montinari, just
days before Nietzsche’s mental collapse, 30 or 31 of December 1888, he apparently sent
instructions (on a not extant postcard) to his publisher to strike out the words “the first book
of” and changed the text to: “The Revaluation of All Values, the Songs of Zarathustra, and, as
relaxation, the Twilight of the Idols, my attempt to philosophize with the hammer – all of them
gifts of this year, of its last quarter even!” (KSA 14, 462f).
35
In this planned addition to Nietzsche contra Wagner, “Wir Antipoden,” Nietzsche wrote (some-
time near the middle of December): “Dieser Satz, hart und schneidig geworden unter dem
Hammerschlag der historischen Erkenntniß (– lisez: erstes Buch der Umwerthung der
Werthe –),” and so on. Montinari does not refer to it in his essay “Nietzsches Nachlaß von
1885 bis 1888 oder Textkritik und Wille zur Macht,” in Nietzsche lesen (1982). However, as
a reliable editor, he gives the text as an eventually not used addition to “Wir Antipoden” (KSA
14, 525f).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
Nietzsche’s Revaluation of All Values 51
made near that time) in early August 1881. He then began to refer to his ‘task’, ‘life-
task’, ‘fundamental task’, and ‘main task’ (Aufgabe, Lebensaufgabe, Hauptsache,
and Hauptaufgabe), and similar expressions, and that he will require several years’
time to develop it.36
The intention to write a Hauptwerk becomes explicit in five letters from the
spring of 1884 where Nietzsche speaks of Thus Spoke Zarathustra as merely an
‘entrance hall’ to his philosophy, and that he was working on the main building.
In the second of these letters, to Meysenbug, end of March 1884 (KSB 6:498),
he writes that he has finished his Thus Spoke Zarathustra and thereafter calls
that work ‘an entrance hall to my philosophy – built for me, to give me courage’,
and he hints at that he is working on ‘the main building’.
In three further letters, he refers to Thus Spoke Zarathustra as merely the
‘Vorhalle’ to his philosophy, and he refers to his strong sense of purpose and
mission. It seems clear that he had in mind a more philosophical (and less
metaphorical) work than Thus Spoke Zarathustra, but which, in all likelihood,
would elaborate on similar fundamental ideas.
Now, after that I for me have built this entrance hall to my philosophy, I will
have to start again and not grow tired until the main building also stands
finished before me. (Letter to Meysenbug, early May 1884, KSB 6:509)
In fact, this was not only an intention, for during much of 1884 Nietzsche
actually planned and worked on this Hauptwerk or ‘main building’ of his
philosophy. In early autumn, Nietzsche seems to confirm that he had fulfilled
his plans.
I have practically finished the main task which I set myself for this summer;
the next six years will be for working out a scheme which I have sketched for
my ‘philosophy’. It has gone well and looks hopeful. (Letter to Gast,
2 September 1884, KSB 6:529)
36
See, for example, letter to Elisabeth, 18 August 1881 (KSB 6:138), to Overbeck, 20/21 August 1881
(KSB 6:139), to Ida Overbeck, 19 January 1882 (KSB 6:188), to Gast, 3 September 1883 (KSB
6:461), and to Overbeck, 12 February 1884 (KSB 6:488).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
52 Philosophy of Friedrich Nietzsche
37
Nietzsche re-read his On the Genealogy of Morals during July–August 1888, shortly before he
wrote The Antichrist, and Montinari has suggested that these essays constituted a model and
stimulus for how he was to write his Umwerthung aller Werthe. I agree that this seems likely.
38
See letters to Gast, 3 September 1883 (KSB 6:461), Seydlitz, 17 August 1886 (KSB 7:737), to
Overbeck, 24 March 1887 (KSB 8:820), to Brandes, 4 May 1888 (KSB 8:1030), to Overbeck,
7 April 1884 (KSB 6:504), to Gast, 2 September 1884 (KSB 6:529) and to Naumann,
7 September 1888 (KSB 8:1103).
39
Here only a superficial overview of this information can be given since they cover about 1,500
printed pages in the KSA-version. Actually, in the new KGW IX-version, they cover about 4,000
pages.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
Nietzsche’s Revaluation of All Values 53
The final period covers the autumn 1887 until the late autumn 1888, when he
worked intensively on his projected Hauptwerk, but taking two resting-breaks
and writing The Case of Wagner and Twilight of the Idols. He then began to use
three large bound notebooks exclusively for collecting notes for his Hauptwerk.40
He during the first half of this period wrote and copied down from earlier
notebooks in legible handwriting a large number of notes into them, which led
to over 500 notes on over 450 printed pages of notes for the project. He later
returned to them, organized, and numbered 374 of them. These notes can be
regarded as Nietzsche’s most extensive draft for his Hauptwerk. This is obviously
not a finished work to be published by Nietzsche, but together with his later
revisions of these notes and his later notes, this constitutes an important source for
anyone interested in Nietzsche’s thought and philosophy.
This work on his Hauptwerk he refers to in a letter to Elisabeth, 15 October 1887
(KSB 8:925):
On the other hand, there is not the slightest chance once my magnum opus
[mein Hauptwerk] is finished to bring it to the world other than through ‘self-
print’. [. . .] Forgive me, if I due to these worries about the future (that is about
making my magnum opus possible, in which the problem and the task of my
life is concentrated) now behave in regard to financial questions with unwill-
ing worry and hesitation.
In February 1888, he began using a new fourth notebook,41 and filled half of it
with an ‘index’ to the three previous notebooks, in which these notes are briefly,
usually in one sentence, summarized and numbered 1–372 (the same as in the
other notebooks). The first three hundred of these summaries are also attributed
to the four volumes of his Hauptwerk by using Roman numerals. There is also
a plan for the whole Hauptwerk, in four volumes divided into twelve chapters
(KSA 13, 12[2]).42 These notes can be regarded as Nietzsche’s most extensive
and consistent draft for his Hauptwerk. In letters to Overbeck and to Gast, from
mid-February 1888, he calls this extensive collection of notes ‘the first written
40
“W II 1” (KSA 12, 9), “W II 2” (KSA 12, 10), and “W II 3” (KSA 13, 11). These are large
hardcover notebooks. The contents of them have been published in facsimile and diplomatic
transcription in KGW IX.6 and IX.7.
41
“W II 4” (KSA 13, 12[1 and 2]), a bound notebook of originally 127 pages. Used as “index” for
the three notebooks “W II 1, 2, 3” (listing with a one-line summary of each of the numbered notes
intended for use in his Hauptwerk) on sixty handwritten pages in the notebook and in the 17-page
-long note KSA 13, 12[1], written in February 1888. As with almost all of the notebooks,
Nietzsche wrote in them from back to front. In this notebook, about twenty pages have been
ripped or cut out – possibly because Nietzsche wanted to use the notes somewhere else (?).
Between the “index,” 12[1], which is written on every second page, and the table of contents of
the four books of the Hauptwerk, 12[2], there are a fairly large number of pages and cut out
pages, not visible in KSA 13.
42
This note is published in diplomatic transcription in KGW IX.7, W II 4, p. 4.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
54 Philosophy of Friedrich Nietzsche
43
In letters to Overbeck and to Gast, both dated 13 February 1888 (KSB 8:990 and 991): “die erste
Niederschrift meiner ‘Umwertung aller Werthe’ ist fertig.” In the letter to Gast he expresses it
similarly: “Ich habe die erste Niederschrift meines ‘Versuchs einer Umwertung’ fertig.”
44
He had done likewise, in his earlier outline of the Hauptwerk (for what seems to be volume 1
about nihilism and truth in three chapters, in May–June 1888, that later becomes volume 2), KSA
13, 17[1], from May 1888, which also contains seven references to that index and these 374
notes.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
Nietzsche’s Revaluation of All Values 55
Furthermore, we know which notes of the 300 are allocated to which volumes
(but not to which chapters Nietzsche intended them, with a few exceptions). In
one note, where he takes an overview of the whole project, he plans 50 pages per
chapter and thus 150 pages per volume (KSA 13, 13[4], from the early part of
1888), and we can see that the attributed full notes in notebooks W II 1–3
constitute a substantial working material for writing such chapters.
During September, Nietzsche in several letters expressed his optimism and
sense of achievement, but thereafter, in November and December 1888, there
were few notes and none of them philosophical. These last two months before
the collapse, Nietzsche was busy writing, editing, correcting, proofreading
a number of works, including Ecce Homo, and he wrote well over a hundred
letters. However, that which prevented the completion of the Hauptwerk was, in
my view, apart from the mental collapse, less that he was busy, but more that
there was no hurry. He had decided to write, finish, and publish Ecce Homo
before and as preparatory, and thus the work on the Hauptwerk could and had to
wait. Still more important were the signs of mental instability during these two
last months, visible especially in his letters. We have no evidence that he
consciously decided to give up the plan for a Hauptwerk. Between 1881 and
1885, there are many different titles used, but from the summer of 1885, there
are only two, used consecutively, first Will to Power and then Revaluation of All
Values, the latter that earlier had been the subtitle to the former.
45
I have done a partial such study in my book The Close Relationship between Nietzsche’s Two
Most Important Books (2023b).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
56 Philosophy of Friedrich Nietzsche
Table 1 The evolution of the planned titles of Nietzsche’s magnum opus, from
autumn 1881 to December 1888
g
1884)
We can get much further information by examining the titles of the planned
four books, and the chapters they were planned to contain. When we limit
ourselves to the final situation, from September 1888 onwards, we can observe
that we possess seven drafts for or lists of titles of the books of the Umwerthung
aller Werthe, from after he began writing The Antichrist, all very similar.46
However, these contain no listing of chapter titles, as some of the earlier listings
do. Using the consistent divisions into four books after that The Antichrist was
decided upon; we can go back to the more detailed divisions from earlier in
1888 and classify these chapter titles according to these new book divisions. It
turns out that this is relatively straightforward using the three most detailed
chapter divisions. This information is presented in Table 2 and gives us
a reasonably detailed view of Nietzsche’s plans for the three remaining volumes
of the Umwerthung aller Werthe.
46
KSA 13, 19[2 and 8], 11[416], 22[14 and 24], and 23[8 and 13].
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
Table 2 Planned Chapter Titles for Nietzsche’s Hauptwerk from earlier in 1888, here classified and organized according to the book divisions
from September to December 1888
Umwerthung aller Table of contents from early Table of contents from May or June Table of contents from
Werthe 1888 of 1888 26 August 1888
Sept.–Dec. 1888 KSA 13, 12[2] KSA 13, 16[51] KSA 13, 18[17]
.............................. ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ...
Book 1
The Anti-Christ: Critique of the Christian ideals The religious man as typical décadent The homines religiosi
Attempt at a Critique
of Christianity
The pagan in religion Thoughts about Christianity
.............................. ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ...
Book 2
The Free Spirit: Nihilism, considered to its final The true and the apparent world The psychology of errors
Critique of conclusion
Philosophy as ‘Will to truth’ The philosopher as typical décadent The value of truth and error
a Nihilistic Culture, Civilization, the Science against philosophy The will to truth
Movement ambivalence of the ‘modern’
Nihilism [and its opposite] The metaphysicians
To the history of European nihilism
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
Table 2 (cont.)
Umwerthung aller Table of contents from early Table of contents from May or June Table of contents from
Werthe 1888 of 1888 26 August 1888
.............................. ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ...
Book 3
The Immoralist: The origin of ideals The good human being as typical The good and the improvers
Critique of Morality How virtue becomes victorious décadent
as the Most Herd-instincts
Dangerous Kind of Morality as the Circe of the
Lack of Knowledge philosophers
Psychology of the ‘will to power’
.............................. ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ... ...
Book 4
Dionysus: The Life-prescriptions for us The will to power as life: Peak of the The principle of life: ‘Order of rank’
Philosophy of historical self-consciousness
‘Eternal recurrence’ The two ways
Eternal Recurrence The will to power: as discipline
Great politics The eternal recurrence
Nietzsche’s Revaluation of All Values 59
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
Notes on Texts, Translations,
and Abbreviations
Quoted texts from Nietzsche’s letters and notes have been translated by me,
unless otherwise stated.
BGE Jenseits von Gut und Böse (1886): translated as Beyond Good and Evil. In
Beyond Good and Evil, trans. R. J. Hollingdale. London: Penguin (1990).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
Notes on Texts, Translations, and Abbreviations 61
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
62 Notes on Texts, Translations, and Abbreviations
WP Der Wille zur Macht (1883–1888); translated as The Will to Power. In The
Will to Power, ed. W. Kaufmann, trans. W. Kaufmann and R. J. Hollingdale.
New York: Vintage (1968). Der Wille zur Macht was originally put together
from Nietzsche’s notes by E. Förster-Nietzsche and Peter Gast in 1901, with
an enlarged second edition in 1906.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
References
Ackermann, Robert J. (1989). Nietzsche: A Frenzied Look. Amherst: University
of Massachusetts Press.
Brobjer, Thomas H. (1999). ‘Götzen-Hammer: The Meaning of the Expression
“to Philosophize with a Hammer”’. Nietzsche-Studien 28: 38–41.
(2003). ‘Nietzsche’s Affirmative Morality: An Ethics of Virtue’. Journal of
Nietzsche Studies 26: 64–78.
(2008). Nietzsche’s Philosophical Context: An Intellectual Biography. Urbana:
University of Illinois Press.
(2021). Nietzsche’s ‘Ecce Homo’ and the Revaluation of All Values: Dionysian
versus Christian Values. London: Bloomsbury Academic.
(2023a). Twilight of the Idols and Nietzsche’s Late Philosophy: Toward
a Revaluation of Values. London: Bloomsbury Academic.
(2023b). The Close Relationship between Nietzsche’s Two Most Important
Books. London: Palgrave Macmillan.
Cate, Curtis (2002). Friedrich Nietzsche. London: Hutchinson.
Deussen, Paul (1883). Das System des Vedânta. Leipzig: F. A. Brockhaus.
Foot, Philippa (1973). ‘Nietzsche: The Revaluation of Values’. In Solomon
(1973, 1980), 156–168.
Gilman, Sander L. (1981). Begegnungen mit Nietzsche. Bonn: Bouvier Verlag.
Higgins, Kathleen (1987). Nietzsche’s Zarathustra. Philadelphia, PA: Temple
University Press.
Historisches Wörterbuch der Philosophie, Band 12 (2004) Basel: Schwabe.
(2006). ‘Rebaptizing our Evil: On the Revaluation of All Values’. In A
Companion to Nietzsche, Keith Ansell Pearson, ed., 404‒418. Malden,
MA: Blackwell Publishing.
Hollingdale, Reginald J. (1999). Nietzsche: The Man and His Philosophy. 1965,
reprinted with additions 1999. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Huang, Jing (2019). ‘Did Nietzsche Want His Notes Burned? Some Reflections
on the Nachlass Problem’. British Journal of the History of Philosophy 27:
1194–1214.
Janz, Curt Paul (1993). Friedrich Nietzsche: Biographie, 3 vols. 1978, second
revised edition 1993. München: Carl Hanser Verlag.
Jaspers, Karl (1985). Nietzsche: An Introduction to the Understanding of His
Philosophical Activity, trans. C. F. Wallraff and F. J. Schmitz. New York:
University Press of America.
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
64 References
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
References 65
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
For Anna
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
Philosophy of Friedrich Nietzsche
Kaitlyn Creasy
California State University, San Bernardino
Kaitlyn Creasy is Associate Professor of Philosophy at California State University, San
Bernardino. She is the author of The Problem of Affective Nihilism in Nietzsche (2020) as well
as several articles in nineteenth-century philosophy and moral psychology.
Matthew Meyer
The University of Scranton
Matthew Meyer is Professor of Philosophy at The University of Scranton. He is the author of
three monographs: Reading Nietzsche through the Ancients: An Analysis of Becoming,
Perspectivism, and The Principle of Non-Contradiction (2014), Nietzsche’s Free Spirit Works: A
Dialectical Reading (Cambridge, 2019), and The Routledge Guidebook to Thus Spoke
Zarathustra (2024). He has also co-edited, with Paul Loeb, Nietzsche’s Metaphilosophy: The
Nature, Method, and Aims of Philosophy (Cambridge, 2019).
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652
Philosophy of Friedrich Nietzsche
Downloaded from https://www.cambridge.org/core. IP address: 108.14.83.103, on 05 Dec 2024 at 17:35:30, subject to the Cambridge Core terms of
use, available at https://www.cambridge.org/core/terms. https://doi.org/10.1017/9781009421652