Jump to content

Toleration: Difference between revisions

From Wikipedia, the free encyclopedia
Content deleted Content added
m Cleaned up 21 ISBNs using toolforge:anticompositetools/hyphenator #hyphenator
 
(25 intermediate revisions by 18 users not shown)
Line 1: Line 1:
{{Short description|Allowing or permitting a thing, person, or idea of which one disapproves}}
{{Short description|Allowing or permitting a thing, person, or idea of which one disapproves}}
{{Use dmy dates|date=January 2023}}
{{redirect|Tolerate|other uses|Tolerance (disambiguation){{!}}Tolerance}}
{{redirect|Tolerate|other uses|Tolerance (disambiguation){{!}}Tolerance}}
{{Use dmy dates|date=January 2023}}
{{Discrimination sidebar}}
{{Discrimination sidebar}}
[[File:Für Toleranz.jpg|thumb|Sculpture ''Für Toleranz'' ("for tolerance") by [[Volkmar Kühn]], [[Gera]], Germany ]]
[[File:Für Toleranz.jpg|thumb|Sculpture ''Für Toleranz'' ("for tolerance") by [[Volkmar Kühn]], [[Gera]], Germany ]]
'''Toleration''' is when one allows or permits an action, idea, object, or person that they dislike or disagree with.
'''Toleration''' is the allowing, permitting, or [[acceptance]] of an action, idea, object, or person which one dislikes or disagrees with. Political scientist Andrew R. Murphy explains that "We can improve our understanding by defining "toleration" as a set of social or political practices and "tolerance" as a set of attitudes."<ref name="Murphy">{{Cite journal |last=Murphy |first=Andrew R. |year=1997 |title=Tolerance, Toleration, and the Liberal Tradition |journal=Polity |publisher=The University of Chicago Press Journals |volume=29 |issue=4 |pages=593–623 |doi=10.2307/3235269 |jstor=3235269 |s2cid=155764374}}</ref> ''[[Random House Dictionary]]'' defines tolerance as "a fair, objective, and permissive attitude toward those whose opinions, beliefs, practices, racial or ethnic origins, etc., differ from one's own".<ref>{{Cite web |title=Definition of tolerance &#124; Dictionary.com |url=https://www.dictionary.com/browse/tolerance |access-date=2 January 2023 |website=dictionary.com |language=en}}</ref>


Political scientist Andrew R. Murphy explains that "We can improve our understanding by defining 'toleration' as a set of social or political practices and 'tolerance' as a set of attitudes."<ref name="Murphy">{{Cite journal |last=Murphy |first=Andrew R. |year=1997 |title=Tolerance, Toleration, and the Liberal Tradition |journal=Polity |publisher=The University of Chicago Press Journals |volume=29 |issue=4 |pages=593–623 |doi=10.2307/3235269 |jstor=3235269 |s2cid=155764374}}</ref> ''[[Random House Dictionary]]'' defines tolerance as "a fair, objective, and permissive attitude toward those whose opinions, beliefs, practices, racial or ethnic origins, etc., differ from one's own".<ref>{{Cite web |title=Definition of tolerance|url=https://www.dictionary.com/browse/tolerance |access-date=2 January 2023 |website=dictionary.com |language=en}}</ref> The [[Merriam-Webster Dictionary]] associates toleration both with "putting up with" something undesirable, and with neglect or failure to prevent or alleviate it.<ref>Merriam-Webster Dictionary, [https://www.merriam-webster.com/thesaurus/tolerate tolerate verb], accessed 13 February 2024</ref>
Both these concepts inherently contain the idea of [[alterity]], the state of ''otherness.''<ref name="van Doorn">{{Cite news |last=van Doorn |first=Marjoka |date=October 2014 |title=The nature of tolerance and the social circumstances in which it emerges |volume=62 |pages=905–927 |publisher=Current Sociology}}</ref> Additional choices of how to respond to the "other," beyond toleration, do exist. Therefore, in some instances, toleration has been seen as 'a flawed virtue' because it concerns acceptance of things that were better overcome.<ref name="van Doorn2">{{Cite journal |last=van Doorn |first=Marjoka |year=2012 |title=Tolerance |url=http://www.sagepub.net/isa/admin/viewPDF.aspx?&art=Tolerance.pdf |journal=Sociopedia |publisher=Sage}}</ref> Toleration cannot, therefore, be defined as a universal good, and many of its applications and uses remain contested.<ref name="van Doorn2" />{{rp|2}}


Both these concepts contain the idea of [[alterity]]: the state of ''otherness''.<ref name="van Doorn">{{Cite journal |last=van Doorn |first=Marjoka |year= 2014 |title=The nature of tolerance and the social circumstances in which it emerges |volume=62 |number=6|pages=905–927 |journal=Current Sociology}}</ref> Additional choices of how to respond to the "other", beyond toleration, exist. Therefore, in some instances, toleration has been seen as "a flawed virtue" because it concerns acceptance of things that were better overcome.{{r|van Doorn}} Toleration cannot, therefore, be defined as a universal good, and many of its applications and uses remain contested.{{r|van Doorn|page=2}}
[[Religious toleration]] may signify "no more than forbearance and the permission given by the adherents of a dominant religion for other religions to exist, even though the latter are looked on with disapproval as inferior, mistaken, or harmful".<ref name="Zagorin" /> Historically, most incidents and writings pertaining to toleration involve the status of [[minority influence|minority]] and dissenting viewpoints in relation to a dominant [[state religion]].<ref>{{Cite magazine |last=Vahland |first=Joachim |year=2017 |title=Tolerance discourses |magazine=Zeno |issue=37 |pages=7–25}}</ref> However, religion is also sociological, and the practice of toleration has always had a political aspect as well.<ref name="Gervers">{{Cite book |title=Tolerance and Intolerance: Social Conflict in the Age of the Crusades |publisher=Syracuse University Press |year=2001 |isbn=978-0-8156-2869-9 |editor-last=Gervers |editor-first=Peter |editor-last2=Gervers |editor-first2=Michael |editor-last3=Powell |editor-first3=James M.}}</ref>{{rp|xiii}}


[[Religious toleration]] may signify "no more than forbearance and the permission given by the adherents of a dominant religion for other religions to exist, even though the latter are looked on with disapproval as inferior, mistaken, or harmful".<ref name="Zagorin">{{Cite book |last=Zagorin |first=Perez |title=How the Idea of Religious Toleration Came to the West |year=2003 |publisher=Princeton University Press |isbn=978-0-691-09270-6 |location=Princeton, N.J. |oclc=50982270}}</ref> Historically, most incidents and writings pertaining to religious toleration involve the status of [[minority influence|minority]] and dissenting viewpoints in relation to a dominant [[state religion]].<ref>{{Cite magazine |last=Vahland |first=Joachim |year=2017 |title=Tolerance discourses |magazine=Zeno |issue=37 |pages=7–25}}</ref> However, religion is also sociological, and the practice of toleration has always had a political aspect as well.<ref name="Gervers">{{Cite book |title=Tolerance and Intolerance: Social Conflict in the Age of the Crusades |publisher=Syracuse University Press |year=2001 |isbn=978-0-8156-2869-9 |editor-last=Gervers |editor-first=Peter |editor-last2=Gervers |editor-first2=Michael |editor-last3=Powell |editor-first3=James M.}}</ref>{{rp|xiii}}
Toleration assumes there is a conflict over something important, something that cannot otherwise be resolved through normal negotiation without resorting to war or violence. As political lecturer Catriona McKinnon explains, when it comes to questions like what is "the best way to live, the right things to think, the ideal political society, or the true road to salvation, no amount of negotiation and bargaining will bring them to an agreement without at least one party relinquishing the commitments that created the conflict in the first place. Such conflicts provide the circumstances of toleration{{nbsp}}... [and] are endemic in society."<ref name="McKinnon">{{Cite book |last=McKinnon |first=Catriona |title=Toleration: A Critical Introduction |publisher=Routledge |year=2006 |isbn=978-0-415-32289-8 |location=New York}}</ref>{{rp|6}} "The urgency and relevance of this issue is only too obvious: without tolerance, communities that value diversity,<ref>{{Cite web |title=Diversity As A Core Value – What Does It Mean To Value Diversity? |url=https://www.emexmag.com/diversity-as-a-core-value/ |access-date=10 June 2016 |website=emexmag.com}}</ref> equality and peace could not persist (Vogt, 1997)."<ref name="van Doorn2" />{{rp|1}}


Toleration assumes a conflict over something important that cannot be resolved through normal negotiation without resorting to war or violence.{{citation needed|reason=can't I be tolerant of e.g. my bunkmate's snoring or my co-worker's bad jokes?|date=August 2023}} As political lecturer Catriona McKinnon explains, when it comes to questions like what is "the best way to live, the right things to think, the ideal political society, or the true road to salvation, no amount of negotiation and bargaining will bring them to an agreement without at least one party relinquishing the commitments that created the conflict in the first place. Such conflicts provide the circumstances of toleration... [and] are endemic in society."<ref name="McKinnon">{{Cite book |last=McKinnon |first=Catriona |title=Toleration: A Critical Introduction |publisher=Routledge |year=2006 |isbn=978-0-415-32289-8 |location=New York}}</ref>{{rp|6}} "The urgency and relevance of this issue is only too obvious: without tolerance, communities that value diversity,<ref>{{Cite web |title=Diversity As A Core Value – What Does It Mean To Value Diversity? |url=https://www.emexmag.com/diversity-as-a-core-value/ |access-date=10 June 2016 |website=emexmag.com}}</ref> equality, and peace could not persist."<ref>{{cite book|last=Vogt|first=W.P.|year=1997|title=Tolerance & Education: Learning to Live with Diversity and Difference|location=Thousand Oaks, Calif.|publisher=Sage Publications, Inc.}}</ref>{{r|van Doorn|page=1}}
An overview of the history of toleration and different cultures in which toleration has been practiced, and the ways in which such a paradoxical concept has developed into a guiding one, illuminates its contemporary use as political, social, religious, and ethnic, applying to [[LGBT]] individuals and other minorities, and other connected concepts such as human rights.

An examination of the history of toleration includes its practice across various cultures. Toleration has evolved into a guiding principle, finding contemporary relevance in politics, society, religion, and ethnicity. It also applies to minority groups, including [[LGBT]] individuals. It is closely linked to concepts like [[human rights]].


==Etymology==
==Etymology==
Originally from the [[Latin]] ''tolerans'' ([[present participle]] of ''tolerare''; "to bear, endure, tolerate"), the word ''tolerance'' was first used in [[Middle French]] in the 14th century and in [[Early Modern English]] in the early 15th century.<ref>{{Cite web |title=tolerance (n.) |url=https://www.etymonline.com/word/tolerance#etymonline_v_15343 |access-date=19 November 2018 |website=[[Online Etymology Dictionary]]}}</ref> The word ''toleration'' was first used in English in the 1510s to mean "permission granted by authority, licence" from the French ''tolération'' (originally from the Latin [[past participle]] stem of ''tolerare'', ''tolerationem''), moving towards the meaning of "forbearance, sufferance" in the 1580s.<ref name="toleration (n.)">{{Cite news |title=toleration (n.) |work=[[Online Etymology Dictionary]] |url=https://www.etymonline.com/word/toleration#etymonline_v_15344 |access-date=19 November 2018}}</ref> The notion of religious toleration stems from [[Sebastian Castellio]]<ref name="Zagorin">{{Cite book |last=Zagorin |first=Perez |url=https://www.worldcat.org/oclc/50982270 |title=How the Idea of Religious Toleration Came to the West |date=2003 |publisher=Princeton University Press |isbn=978-0-691-09270-6 |location=Princeton, N.J. |oclc=50982270}}</ref> and the [[Toleration Act 1688]].<ref name="toleration (n.)" />
Originally from the [[Latin]] {{lang|la|tolerans}} ([[present participle]] of {{lang|la|tolerare}}; "to bear, endure, tolerate"), the word {{lang|frm|tolerance}} was first used in [[Middle French]] in the 14th century and in [[Early Modern English]] in the early 15th century.<ref>{{Cite web |title=tolerance (n.) |url=https://www.etymonline.com/word/tolerance#etymonline_v_15343 |access-date=19 November 2018 |website=[[Online Etymology Dictionary]]}}</ref> The word ''toleration'' was first used in English in the 1510s to mean "permission granted by authority, licence" from the French {{lang|fr|tolération}} (originally from the Latin [[past participle]] stem of {{lang|la|tolerare}}, {{lang|la|tolerationem}}), moving towards the meaning of "forbearance, sufferance" in the 1580s.<ref name="toleration (n.)">{{Cite web |title=toleration (n.) |work=[[Online Etymology Dictionary]] |url=https://www.etymonline.com/word/toleration#etymonline_v_15344 |access-date=19 November 2018}}</ref> The notion of religious toleration stems from [[Sebastian Castellio]]<ref name="Zagorin" /> and the [[Toleration Act 1688]].<ref name="toleration (n.)" />


==Declaration of the Rights of Man and of the Citizen==
==Declaration of the Rights of Man and of the Citizen==
[[File:Declaration of the Rights of Man and of the Citizen in 1789.jpg|thumb|[[Declaration of the Rights of Man and of the Citizen]]]]
[[File:Declaration of the Rights of Man and of the Citizen in 1789.jpg|thumb|[[Declaration of the Rights of Man and of the Citizen]]]]
{{quote box|quote=For having lived long, I have experienced many instances of being obliged, by better information or fuller consideration, to change opinions even on important subjects, which I once thought right, but found to be otherwise. It is therefore that the older I grow the more apt I am to doubt my own judgment, and to pay more respect to the judgment of others.|source=[[Benjamin Franklin]]|width=250px}}
{{quote box|quote=For having lived long, I have experienced many instances of being obliged, by better information or fuller consideration, to change opinions even on important subjects, which I once thought right but found to be otherwise. It is, therefore, that the older I grow, the more apt I am to doubt my judgment and to pay more respect to the judgment of others.|source=[[Benjamin Franklin]]|width=20em}}
The [[Declaration of the Rights of Man and of the Citizen]] (1789), adopted by the [[National Constituent Assembly (France)|National Constituent Assembly]] during the [[French Revolution]], states in Article 10: "No-one shall be interfered with for his opinions, even religious ones, provided that their practice does not disturb public order as established by the law." ("Nul ne doit être inquiété pour ses opinions, mêmes religieuses, pourvu que leur manifestation ne trouble pas l'ordre public établi par la loi.")<ref>{{Cite web |title=Déclaration des droits de l'Homme et du citoyen de 1789 |url=http://www.textes.justice.gouv.fr/textes-fondamentaux-10086/droits-de-lhomme-et-libertes-fondamentales-10087/declaration-des-droits-de-lhomme-et-du-citoyen-de-1789-10116.html |access-date=2 January 2023 |website=justice.gouv.fr |language=fr-FR}}</ref>
The [[Declaration of the Rights of Man and of the Citizen]] (1789), adopted by the [[National Constituent Assembly (France)|National Constituent Assembly]] during the [[French Revolution]], states in Article 10: "No-one shall be interfered with for his opinions, even religious ones, provided that their practice does not disturb public order as established by the law." ("{{lang|fr|Nul ne doit être inquiété pour ses opinions, mêmes religieuses, pourvu que leur manifestation ne trouble pas l'ordre public établi par la loi.}}")<ref>{{Cite web |title=Déclaration des droits de l'Homme et du citoyen de 1789 |url=https://www.conseil-constitutionnel.fr/le-bloc-de-constitutionnalite/declaration-des-droits-de-l-homme-et-du-citoyen-de-1789 |language=fr-FR}}</ref>


==In the nineteenth century==
==In the nineteenth century==
===Mill===
===Mill===
In "[[On Liberty]]" (1859) [[John Stuart Mill]] concludes that opinions ought never to be suppressed, stating, "Such prejudice, or oversight, when it [i.e. false belief] occurs, is altogether an evil; but it is one from which we cannot hope to be always exempt, and must be regarded as the price paid for an inestimable good." He claims that there are three sorts of beliefs that can be had—wholly false, partly true, and wholly true—all of which, according to Mill, benefit the common good:<ref name="MillP72">Mill 1859, p. 72</ref>
In "[[On Liberty]]" (1859) [[John Stuart Mill]] concludes that opinions ought never to be suppressed, stating, "Such prejudice, or oversight, when it [i.e. false belief] occurs, is altogether an evil; but it is one from which we cannot hope to be always exempt, and must be regarded as the price paid for an inestimable good."<ref name=Mill>{{cite book|last=Mill|first=John Stuart|title=On Liberty|location=London|publisher=John W. Parker and Son|year=1859|url=https://archive.org/details/onlibertyxero00milluoft}}</ref>{{rp|[https://archive.org/details/onlibertyxero00milluoft/page/93/mode/1up 93]}} He claims that there are three sorts of beliefs that can be had—wholly false, partly true, and wholly true—all of which, according to Mill, benefit the common good:


{{quote|First, if any opinion is compelled to silence, that opinion may, for aught we can certainly know, be true. To deny this is to assume our own infallibility. Secondly, though the silenced opinion be an error, it may, and very commonly does, contain a portion of truth; and since the general or prevailing opinion on any subject is rarely or never the whole truth, it is only by the collision of adverse opinions that the remainder of the truth has any chance of being supplied. Thirdly, even if the received opinion be not only true, but the whole truth; unless it is suffered to be, and actually is, vigorously and earnestly contested, it will, by most of those who receive it, be held in the manner of a prejudice, with little comprehension or feeling of its rational grounds. And not only this, but, fourthly, the meaning of the doctrine itself will be in danger of being lost, or enfeebled, and deprived of its vital effect on the character and conduct: the dogma becoming a mere formal profession, inefficacious for good, but cumbering the ground, and preventing the growth of any real and heartfelt conviction, from reason or personal experience.<ref name=MillP72/>}}
{{blockquote|First, if any opinion is compelled to silence, that opinion may, for aught we can certainly know, be true. To deny this is to assume our infallibility. Secondly, though the silenced opinion is an error, it may, and very commonly does, contain a portion of truth; and since the general or prevailing opinion on any subject is rarely or never the whole truth, it is only by the collision of adverse opinions that the remainder of the truth has any chance of being supplied. Thirdly, even if the received opinion is not only true but the whole truth; unless it is suffered to be, and is, vigorously and earnestly contested, it will, by most of those who receive it, be held in the manner of a prejudice, with little comprehension or feeling of its rational grounds. Not only this, but, fourthly, the meaning of the doctrine itself will be in danger of being lost, or enfeebled, and deprived of its vital effect on the character and conduct: the dogma becoming a mere formal profession, inefficacious for good, but cumbering the ground, and preventing the growth of any real and heartfelt conviction, from reason or personal experience.{{r|Mill|page=[https://archive.org/details/onlibertyxero00milluoft/page/95/mode/1up 95]}} }}


===Renan===
===Renan===
[[File:Ernest Renan 1876-84.jpg|thumb|Renan]]
[[File:Ernest Renan 1876-84.jpg|thumb|Renan]]
In his 1882 essay "[[What is a Nation?]]", French historian and philosopher [[Ernest Renan]] proposed a definition of nationhood based on "a spiritual principle" involving shared memories, rather than a common religious, racial or linguistic heritage. Thus members of any religious group could participate fully in the life of the nation. "You can be French, English, German, yet Catholic, Protestant, Jewish, or practicing no religion."<ref>{{Cite web |last=Renan |first=Ernest |date=11 March 1882 |title='What is a nation?' Conference at the Sorbonne |url=http://fr.wikisource.org/wiki/Qu%E2%80%99est-ce_qu%E2%80%99une_nation_%3F |access-date=13 January 2011}}</ref>
In his 1882 essay "[[What is a Nation?]]", French historian and philosopher [[Ernest Renan]] proposed a definition of nationhood based on "a spiritual principle" involving shared memories rather than a common religious, racial, or linguistic heritage. Thus members of any religious group could participate fully in the nation's life. "You can be French, English, German, yet Catholic, Protestant, Jewish, or practicing no religion."<ref>{{Cite web |last=Renan |first=Ernest |date=11 March 1882 |title='What is a nation?' Conference at the Sorbonne |url=http://fr.wikisource.org/wiki/Qu%E2%80%99est-ce_qu%E2%80%99une_nation_%3F |access-date=13 January 2011}}</ref>


==In the twentieth century==
==In the twentieth century==
In 1948, the United Nations General Assembly adopted Article 18 of the [[Universal Declaration of Human Rights]], which states:
In 1948, the United Nations General Assembly adopted Article 18 of the [[Universal Declaration of Human Rights]], which states:
<blockquote> Everyone has the right to freedom of thought, conscience and religion; this right includes freedom to change his religion or belief, and freedom, either alone or in community with others and in public or private, to manifest his religion or belief in teaching, practice, worship and observance<ref>{{Cite web |year=1948 |title=The Universal Declaration of Human Rights |url=https://www.un.org/Overview/rights.html |access-date=1 June 2007 |publisher=United Nations}}</ref></blockquote>
<blockquote>Everyone has the right to freedom of thought, conscience, and religion; this right includes freedom to change his religion or belief and freedom, either alone or in community with others and in public or private, to manifest his religion or belief in teaching, practice, worship, and observance.<ref>{{Cite web |year=1948 |title=The Universal Declaration of Human Rights |url=https://www.un.org/en/about-us/universal-declaration-of-human-rights |access-date=1 June 2007 |publisher=United Nations}}</ref></blockquote>
Even though not formally legally binding, the Declaration has been adopted in or influenced many national constitutions since 1948. It also serves as the foundation for a growing number of international treaties and national laws and international, regional, national and sub-national institutions protecting and promoting human rights including the [[freedom of religion]].
Though not formally legally binding, the Declaration has been adopted in or has influenced many national constitutions since 1948. It also serves as the foundation for a growing number of international treaties and national laws and international, regional, national, and sub-national institutions protecting and promoting human rights, including the [[freedom of religion]].

== Tolerance and digital technologies ==
{{more citations needed|section|date=September 2019}}
The development of new digital technologies has resulted in an [[exponential growth]] in the volume of information and [[knowledge]] available, and made them more readily accessible to greater numbers of people throughout the world. As such, [[Information and communications technology|information and communication technologies]] can play an essential role in the sharing of knowledge and expertise in the service of [[sustainable development]] and in a spirit of solidarity. And yet, for many observers, the world is witnessing rising levels of ethnic, cultural and [[religious intolerance]], often using the same communication technologies for ideological and political mobilization to promote exclusivist worldviews. This mobilization often leads to further criminal and political violence and to armed conflict.<ref>{{Cite book |url=http://unesdoc.unesco.org/images/0023/002325/232555e.pdf |title=Rethinking Education: Towards a global common good? |publisher=UNESCO |year=2015 |isbn=978-92-3-100088-1 |page=24}}</ref> This also leads to new modes of intolerance such as [[cyberbullying]].


==Modern analyses and critiques==
==Modern analyses and critiques==
Contemporary commentators have highlighted situations in which toleration conflicts with widely held moral standards, national law, the principles of national identity, or other strongly held goals. Michael Walzer notes that the British in India tolerated the Hindu practice of [[suttee]] (ritual burning of a widow) until 1829. On the other hand, the United States declined to tolerate the [[Mormon]] practice of [[polygamy]].<ref>{{Cite book |last=Walzer |first=Michael |url=https://www.worldcat.org/oclc/47008086 |title=On Toleration |date=1997 |publisher=Yale University Press |isbn=978-0-585-34880-3 |location=New Haven |oclc=47008086}}</ref> The [[Islamic veil controversy in France|French head scarf controversy]] represents a conflict between religious practice and the French secular ideal.<ref>{{Cite magazine |last=Bowen |first=John |date=February–March 2004 |title=Muslims and Citizens |url=http://bostonreview.net/BR29.1/bowen.html |magazine=The Boston Review |access-date=25 January 2011}}</ref> Toleration of the [[Romani people]] in European countries is a continuing issue.<ref>{{Cite news |title=A long road |newspaper=The Economist |url=https://www.economist.com/international/2010/09/16/a-long-road |access-date=2 January 2023 |issn=0013-0613}}</ref>
Contemporary commentators have highlighted situations in which toleration conflicts with widely held moral standards, national law, the principles of national identity, or other strongly held goals. Michael Walzer notes that the British in India tolerated the Hindu practice of [[suttee]] (ritual burning of a widow) until 1829. On the other hand, the United States declined to tolerate the [[Mormon]] practice of [[polygamy]].<ref name=Walzer>{{Cite book |last=Walzer |first=Michael |url=https://archive.org/details/ontoleration00walz_0 | url-access=registration |title=On Toleration|series=The Castle lectures in ethics, politics, and economics |year=1997 |publisher=[[Yale University|Yale University Press]] |isbn=0300070195 |location=New Haven |oclc=47008086}}</ref> The [[Islamic veil controversy in France|French head scarf controversy]] represents a conflict between religious practice and the French secular ideal.<ref>{{Cite magazine |last=Bowen |first=John |date=February–March 2004 |title=Muslims and Citizens |url=https://www.bostonreview.net/articles/john-r-bowen-muslims-and-citizens/ |magazine=The Boston Review |access-date=25 January 2011}}</ref> Toleration of or intolerance toward the [[Romani people]] in European countries is a continuing issue.<ref>{{Cite news |title=A long road |newspaper=The Economist |url=https://www.economist.com/international/2010/09/16/a-long-road|url-access=subscription|date=2010-09-18 |access-date=2 January 2023 |issn=0013-0613}}</ref> [[Pope Francis]] refers to the "admirable creativity and generosity" shown by people who put up with their lives in "a seemingly undesirable environment" and learn "to live their lives amid disorder and uncertainty".<ref>Pope Francis (2015), [https://www.vatican.va/content/dam/francesco/pdf/encyclicals/documents/papa-francesco_20150524_enciclica-laudato-si_en.pdf Laudato si'], paragraph 148, accessed 13 February 2024</ref>


===Modern definition===
===Modern definition===
[[File:NYC Pride 2019 05.jpg|thumb|The [[NYC Pride March]] is the [[List of largest LGBT events|world's largest LGBT event]]. Regional variation exists with respect to toleration in different parts of the world.]]
Historian Alexandra Walsham notes that the modern understanding of the word "toleration" may be very different from its historic meaning.<ref name="Walsham06-233">{{Cite book |last=Walsham |first=Alexandra |url=https://www.worldcat.org/oclc/62533086 |title=Charitable Hatred: Tolerance and Intolerance in England, 1500-1700 |date=2006 |publisher=Manchester University Press |isbn=978-0-7190-5239-2 |location=Manchester |page=233 |oclc=62533086}}</ref> Toleration in modern parlance has been analyzed as a component of a liberal or [[Libertarianism|libertarian]] view of human rights. Hans Oberdiek writes, "As long as no one is harmed or no one's fundamental rights are violated, the state should keep hands off, tolerating what those controlling the state find disgusting, deplorable or even debased. This for a long time has been the most prevalent defense of toleration by liberals... It is found, for example, in the writings of American philosophers [[John Rawls]], [[Robert Nozick]], [[Ronald Dworkin]], [[Brian Barry]], and a Canadian, [[Will Kymlicka]], among others."<ref>{{Cite book |last=Oberdiek |first=Hans |url=https://www.worldcat.org/oclc/45604024 |title=Tolerance: Between Forbearance and Acceptance |date=2001 |publisher=Rowman & Littlefield Publishers |isbn=978-0-8476-8785-5 |location=Lanham, Md. |page=vi |oclc=45604024}}</ref>
Historian Alexandra Walsham notes that the modern understanding of the word "toleration" may be very different from its historic meaning.<ref name="Walsham06-233">{{Cite book |last=Walsham |first=Alexandra |title=Charitable Hatred: Tolerance and Intolerance in England, 1500–1700 |year=2006 |publisher=Manchester University Press |isbn=978-0-7190-5239-2 |location=Manchester |page=233 |oclc=62533086}}</ref> Toleration in modern parlance has been analyzed as a component of a liberal or [[Libertarianism|libertarian]] view of human rights. Hans Oberdiek writes, "As long as no one is harmed or no one's fundamental rights are violated, the state should keep hands off, tolerating what those controlling the state find disgusting, deplorable, or debased. For a long time, this has been the most prevalent defense of toleration by liberals... It is found, for example, in the writings of American philosophers [[John Rawls]], [[Robert Nozick]], [[Ronald Dworkin]], [[Brian Barry]], and a Canadian, [[Will Kymlicka]], among others."<ref>{{Cite book |last=Oberdiek |first=Hans |title=Tolerance: Between Forbearance and Acceptance |year=2001 |publisher=Rowman & Littlefield Publishers |isbn=978-0-8476-8785-5 |location=Lanham, Md. |page=vi |oclc=45604024}}</ref>


[[Isaiah Berlin]] attributes to [[Herbert Butterfield]] the notion that "toleration... implies a certain disrespect. I tolerate your absurd beliefs and your foolish acts, though I know them to be absurd and foolish. Mill would, I think, have agreed."<ref>{{Cite book |last=Berlin |first=Isaiah |url=https://www.worldcat.org/oclc/15227 |title=Four Essays on Liberty |date=1969 |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-500272-0 |location=London |oclc=15227}}</ref>
[[Isaiah Berlin]] attributed to [[Herbert Butterfield]] the notion that "toleration{{nbsp}}... implies a certain disrespect. I tolerate your absurd beliefs and your foolish acts, though I know them to be absurd and foolish. Mill would, I think, have agreed."<ref>{{Cite book |last=Berlin |first=Isaiah |title=Four Essays on Liberty |date=1969 |publisher=Oxford University Press |isbn=978-0-19-500272-0 |location=London |oclc=15227}}</ref>{{page needed|date=August 2023}}


[[John Gray (philosopher)|John Gray]] states that "When we tolerate a practice, a belief or a character trait, we let something be that we judge to be undesirable, false or at least inferior; our toleration expresses the conviction that, despite its badness, the object of toleration should be left alone."<ref>{{Cite book |last=John |first=Gray |url=http://worldcat.org/oclc/941437450 |title=Enlightenment's Wake: Politics and Culture at the Close of the Modern Age |publisher=Routledge |year=2015 |isbn=978-1-138-17022-3 |oclc=941437450}}</ref> However, according to Gray, "new liberalism—the
[[John Gray (philosopher)|John Gray]] states that "When we tolerate a practice, a belief or a character trait, we let something be that we judge to be undesirable, false, or at least inferior; our toleration expresses the conviction that, despite its badness, the object of toleration should be left alone."<ref>{{Cite book |last=John |first=Gray |title=Enlightenment's Wake: Politics and Culture at the Close of the Modern Age |publisher=Routledge |year=2015 |isbn=978-1-138-17022-3 |oclc=941437450}}</ref> However, according to Gray, "new liberalism – the
liberalism of Rawls, Dworkin, Ackerman and suchlike" seems to imply that "it is wrong for government to discriminate in favour of, or against, any form of life animated by a definite conception of the good".<ref>Gray (1995), p. 20.</ref>
liberalism of Rawls, Dworkin, Ackerman and suchlike" seems to imply that "it is wrong for government to discriminate in favour of, or against, any form of life animated by a definite conception of the good".<ref>Gray (1995), p. 20.</ref>


[[John Rawls]]' "theory of 'political liberalism' conceives of toleration as a pragmatic response to the fact of diversity". Diverse groups learn to tolerate one another by developing "what Rawls calls 'overlapping consensus': individuals and groups with diverse metaphysical views or 'comprehensive schemes' will find reasons to agree about certain principles of justice that will include principles of toleration".<ref name="auto">{{Cite web |title=Toleration &#124; Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |url=https://iep.utm.edu/tolerati/ |access-date=2 January 2023 |language=en-US}}</ref>
[[John Rawls]]' "theory of 'political liberalism' conceives of toleration as a pragmatic response to the fact of diversity". Diverse groups learn to tolerate one another by developing "what Rawls calls 'overlapping consensus': individuals and groups with diverse metaphysical views or 'comprehensive schemes' will find reasons to agree about certain principles of justice that will include principles of toleration".<ref name="auto">{{Cite web |first=Andrew|last=Fiala|title=Toleration| website = Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy |url=https://iep.utm.edu/tolerati/ |access-date=2 January 2023 |language=en-US}}</ref>


[[Herbert Marcuse]] wrote ''[[A Critique of Pure Tolerance]]'' in 1965 where he argued that the "pure tolerance" that permits all favors [[totalitarianism]], democracy, and [[tyranny of the majority]], and insisted the "repressive tolerance" against them.
[[Herbert Marcuse]], in the 1965 book ''[[A Critique of Pure Tolerance]]'', argued that "pure tolerance" that permits all can favor [[totalitarianism]] and [[tyranny of the majority]], and insisted on "repressive tolerance" against them.{{citation needed|date=September 2023}}


===Tolerating the intolerant===
===Tolerating the intolerant===
{{main article|Paradox of tolerance}}
{{main article|Paradox of tolerance}}
Walzer, [[Karl Popper]]<ref>{{Cite book |last=Popper |first=Karl |url=http://worldcat.org/oclc/1193010976 |title=The Open Society and Its Enemies |isbn=978-0-691-21206-7 |volume=1 |chapter=chapter 7, note 4 |oclc=1193010976}}</ref> and [[John Rawls]]<ref>{{Cite book |last=Rawls |first=John |url=https://books.google.com/books?id=TdvHKizvuTAC&pg=PA216 |title=A Theory of Justice: Original Edition |date=31 March 2005 |publisher=Harvard University Press |isbn=978-0-674-01772-6 |language=en}}</ref> have discussed the paradox of tolerating intolerance. Walzer asks "Should we tolerate the intolerant?" He notes that most minority religious groups who are the beneficiaries of tolerance are themselves intolerant, at least in some respects.<ref>{{Cite book |last=Walzer |first=Michael |url=https://www.worldcat.org/oclc/47008086 |title=On Toleration |date=1997 |publisher=Yale University Press |isbn=978-0-585-34880-3 |location=New Haven |pages=80–81 |oclc=47008086}}</ref> Rawls argues that an intolerant sect should be tolerated in a tolerant society unless the sect directly threatens the security of other members of the society. He links this principle to the stability of a tolerant society, in which members of an intolerant sect in a tolerant society will, over time, acquire the tolerance of the wider society.
Walzer, [[Karl Popper]],<ref>{{Cite book |last=Popper |first=Karl |title=The Open Society and Its Enemies |isbn=978-0-691-21206-7 |volume=1 |chapter=chapter 7, note 4 |oclc=1193010976}}</ref> and [[John Rawls]]<ref>{{Cite book |last=Rawls |first=John |title=A Theory of Justice: Original Edition |year=1971 |publisher=Harvard University Press |isbn=978-0-674-01772-6 |language=en|page=[https://books.google.com/books?id=TdvHKizvuTAC&pg=PA216 216]}}</ref> have discussed the paradox of tolerating intolerance. Walzer asks "Should we tolerate the intolerant?" He notes that most minority religious groups who are the beneficiaries of tolerance are themselves intolerant, at least in some respects.{{r|Walzer|pages=80–81}} Rawls argues that an intolerant sect should be tolerated in a tolerant society unless the sect directly threatens the security of other members of the society. He hypothetises that members of the intolerant sect in a tolerant society will, over time, acquire the tolerance of the wider society.


===Other criticisms and issues===
===Other criticisms and issues===
Toleration has been described as undermining itself via [[moral relativism]]: "either the claim self-referentially undermines itself or it provides us with no compelling reason to believe it. If we are skeptical about knowledge, then we have no way of knowing that toleration is good."<ref name="auto" />
Toleration has been described as undermining itself via [[moral relativism]]: "either the claim self-referentially undermines itself or it provides us with no compelling reason to believe it. If we are skeptical about knowledge, then we have no way of knowing that toleration is good."<ref name="auto" />


[[Ronald Dworkin]] argues that in exchange for toleration, minorities must bear with the criticisms and insults which are part of the freedom of speech in an otherwise tolerant society.<ref>{{Cite web |last=Dworkin |first=Ronald |date=14 February 2006 |title=Ronald Dworkin: Even bigots and Holocaust deniers must have their say |url=http://www.theguardian.com/world/2006/feb/14/muhammadcartoons.comment |access-date=2 January 2023 |website=The Guardian |language=en}}</ref> Dworkin has also questioned whether the United States is a "tolerant secular" nation, or is re-characterizing itself as a "tolerant religious" nation, based on the increasing re-introduction of religious themes into conservative politics. Dworkin concludes that "the tolerant secular model is preferable, although he invited people to use the concept of personal responsibility to argue in favor of the tolerant religious model."<ref>{{Cite web |date=18 April 2008 |title=Dworkin Explores Secular, Religious Models for Society |url=http://www.law.virginia.edu/html/news/2006_spr/dworkin.htm |access-date=21 March 2011 |website=Virginia Law School News and Events}}</ref>
[[Ronald Dworkin]] argues that in exchange for toleration, [[minority group|minorities]] must bear with the criticisms and insults which are part of the freedom of speech in an otherwise tolerant society.<ref>{{Cite web |last=Dworkin |first=Ronald |date=14 February 2006 |title=Even bigots and Holocaust deniers must have their say |url=https://www.theguardian.com/world/2006/feb/14/muhammadcartoons.comment |access-date=2 January 2023 |website=The Guardian |language=en}}</ref> Dworkin has also questioned whether the United States is a "tolerant secular" nation, or is re-characterizing itself as a "tolerant religious" nation, based on the increasing re-introduction of religious themes into conservative politics. Dworkin concludes that "the tolerant secular model is preferable, although he invited people to use the concept of personal responsibility to argue in favor of the tolerant religious model."<ref>{{Cite web |date=18 April 2008 |title=Dworkin Explores Secular, Religious Models for Society |url=http://www.law.virginia.edu/html/news/2006_spr/dworkin.htm |url-status=dead|archive-url=https://web.archive.org/web/20120118151728/http://www.law.virginia.edu/html/news/2006_spr/dworkin.htm|archive-date=2012-01-18|access-date=21 March 2011 |website=Virginia Law School News and Events}}</ref>


In ''[[The End of Faith]]'', [[Sam Harris (author)|Sam Harris]] asserts that society should be unwilling to tolerate unjustified religious beliefs about morality, spirituality, politics, and the origin of humanity, especially beliefs that promote violence.
In ''[[The End of Faith]]'', [[Sam Harris (author)|Sam Harris]] asserts that society should be unwilling to tolerate unjustified [[religious behaviour|religious beliefs]] about morality, spirituality, politics, and the origin of humanity, especially beliefs that promote violence.


==See also==
==See also==
Line 105: Line 104:
* {{Cite book |title=Beyond the Persecuting Society: Religious Toleration Before the Enlightenment |publisher=University of Pennsylvania Press |year=1997 |isbn=978-0-8122-3331-5 |editor-last=Laursen, John Christian |editor-last2=Nederman, Cary}}
* {{Cite book |title=Beyond the Persecuting Society: Religious Toleration Before the Enlightenment |publisher=University of Pennsylvania Press |year=1997 |isbn=978-0-8122-3331-5 |editor-last=Laursen, John Christian |editor-last2=Nederman, Cary}}
* {{Cite book |last=Murphy |first=Andrew R. |title=Conscience and Community: Revisiting Toleration and Religious Dissent in Early Modern England and America |date=2001 |publisher=Pennsylvania State University Press |isbn=978-0-271-02105-8}}
* {{Cite book |last=Murphy |first=Andrew R. |title=Conscience and Community: Revisiting Toleration and Religious Dissent in Early Modern England and America |date=2001 |publisher=Pennsylvania State University Press |isbn=978-0-271-02105-8}}
* {{Cite book |last=Oberdiek |first=Hans |title=Tolerance: between forebearance and acceptance |publisher=Rowman and Littlefield |year=2001 |isbn=978-0-8476-8785-5}}
* {{Cite book |last=Oberdiek |first=Hans |title=Tolerance: between forbearance and acceptance |publisher=Rowman and Littlefield |year=2001 |isbn=978-0-8476-8785-5}}
* {{Cite journal |last=Tausch |first=Arno |date=2017 |title=Are Practicing Catholics More Tolerant of Other Religions than the Rest of the World? Comparative Analyses Based on World Values Survey Data |url=https://www.ssrn.com/abstract=3075315 |journal=SSRN Electronic Journal |language=en |doi=10.2139/ssrn.3075315 |issn=1556-5068}}
* {{Cite journal |last=Tausch |first=Arno |date=2017 |title=Are Practicing Catholics More Tolerant of Other Religions than the Rest of the World? Comparative Analyses Based on World Values Survey Data |url=https://www.ssrn.com/abstract=3075315 |journal=SSRN Electronic Journal |language=en |doi=10.2139/ssrn.3075315 |issn=1556-5068}}
* {{Cite book |last=Tønder |first=Lars |title=Tolerance: A Sensorial Orientation to Politics |publisher=Oxford University Press |year=2013 |isbn=978-0-19-931580-2}}
* {{Cite book |last=Tønder |first=Lars |title=Tolerance: A Sensorial Orientation to Politics |publisher=Oxford University Press |year=2013 |isbn=978-0-19-931580-2}}
Line 114: Line 113:
{{wikiquote}}
{{wikiquote}}
{{wikibooks|God and Religious Toleration}}
{{wikibooks|God and Religious Toleration}}
* [https://www.learningforjustice.org/professional-development/test-yourself-for-hidden-bias Test Yourself for Hidden Bias]
* {{Cite web |title=Ontario Consultants on Religious Tolerance |url=http://www.religioustolerance.org/ |website=Various information on sensible religious topics |publisher=[[Ontario Consultants on Religious Tolerance]]}}
* {{cite IEP |url-id=tolerati |title=Toleration}}
* [http://www.unhchr.ch/udhr/miscinfo/carta.htm Background to the United Nations Universal Declaration of Human Rights]
* [http://www.religiousfreedom.com/conference/Germany/stango.htm History of Religious Tolerance]
* [http://cle.ens-lyon.fr/anglais/outline-for-a-discussion-on-toleration--253340.kjsp?RH=CDL Outline for a Discussion on Toleration (Karen Barkey)]
* [http://cfr.org/religion Religion and Foreign Policy Initiative], [http://cfr.org/religion Council on Foreign Relations]
* {{curlie|Society/Religion_and_Spirituality/Religious_Tolerance/|Religious Tolerance}}
* [http://www.tolerance.org/ Teaching Tolerance]
* [https://www.tolerance.org/professional-development/test-yourself-for-hidden-bias Test Yourself for Hidden Bias]
* [http://www.unhchr.ch/udhr/lang/eng.htm Text of the United Nations Universal Declaration of Human Rights]
* [http://firmstand.org/ The Foundation against Intolerance of Religious Minorities]
* [https://www.bbc.co.uk/programmes/p004y288 Toleration], BBC Radio 4 discussion with Justin Champion, David Wootton & Sarah Barber (''In Our Time'', 20 May 2004)
* [https://www.bbc.co.uk/programmes/p004y288 Toleration], BBC Radio 4 discussion with Justin Champion, David Wootton & Sarah Barber (''In Our Time'', 20 May 2004)


Line 132: Line 121:
{{Western culture}}
{{Western culture}}
{{Discrimination}}
{{Discrimination}}
{{Virtues}}


{{Authority control}}
{{Authority control}}


{{DEFAULTSORT:Religious Toleration}}
[[Category:Toleration| ]]
[[Category:Religion and politics]]
[[Category:Religion and politics]]
[[Category:Human rights by issue|Religion]]
[[Category:Human rights by issue]]

Latest revision as of 11:43, 21 October 2024

Sculpture Für Toleranz ("for tolerance") by Volkmar Kühn, Gera, Germany

Toleration is when one allows or permits an action, idea, object, or person that they dislike or disagree with.

Political scientist Andrew R. Murphy explains that "We can improve our understanding by defining 'toleration' as a set of social or political practices and 'tolerance' as a set of attitudes."[1] Random House Dictionary defines tolerance as "a fair, objective, and permissive attitude toward those whose opinions, beliefs, practices, racial or ethnic origins, etc., differ from one's own".[2] The Merriam-Webster Dictionary associates toleration both with "putting up with" something undesirable, and with neglect or failure to prevent or alleviate it.[3]

Both these concepts contain the idea of alterity: the state of otherness.[4] Additional choices of how to respond to the "other", beyond toleration, exist. Therefore, in some instances, toleration has been seen as "a flawed virtue" because it concerns acceptance of things that were better overcome.[4] Toleration cannot, therefore, be defined as a universal good, and many of its applications and uses remain contested.[4]: 2 

Religious toleration may signify "no more than forbearance and the permission given by the adherents of a dominant religion for other religions to exist, even though the latter are looked on with disapproval as inferior, mistaken, or harmful".[5] Historically, most incidents and writings pertaining to religious toleration involve the status of minority and dissenting viewpoints in relation to a dominant state religion.[6] However, religion is also sociological, and the practice of toleration has always had a political aspect as well.[7]: xiii 

Toleration assumes a conflict over something important that cannot be resolved through normal negotiation without resorting to war or violence.[citation needed] As political lecturer Catriona McKinnon explains, when it comes to questions like what is "the best way to live, the right things to think, the ideal political society, or the true road to salvation, no amount of negotiation and bargaining will bring them to an agreement without at least one party relinquishing the commitments that created the conflict in the first place. Such conflicts provide the circumstances of toleration... [and] are endemic in society."[8]: 6  "The urgency and relevance of this issue is only too obvious: without tolerance, communities that value diversity,[9] equality, and peace could not persist."[10][4]: 1 

An examination of the history of toleration includes its practice across various cultures. Toleration has evolved into a guiding principle, finding contemporary relevance in politics, society, religion, and ethnicity. It also applies to minority groups, including LGBT individuals. It is closely linked to concepts like human rights.

Etymology

[edit]

Originally from the Latin tolerans (present participle of tolerare; "to bear, endure, tolerate"), the word tolerance was first used in Middle French in the 14th century and in Early Modern English in the early 15th century.[11] The word toleration was first used in English in the 1510s to mean "permission granted by authority, licence" from the French tolération (originally from the Latin past participle stem of tolerare, tolerationem), moving towards the meaning of "forbearance, sufferance" in the 1580s.[12] The notion of religious toleration stems from Sebastian Castellio[5] and the Toleration Act 1688.[12]

Declaration of the Rights of Man and of the Citizen

[edit]
Declaration of the Rights of Man and of the Citizen

For having lived long, I have experienced many instances of being obliged, by better information or fuller consideration, to change opinions even on important subjects, which I once thought right but found to be otherwise. It is, therefore, that the older I grow, the more apt I am to doubt my judgment and to pay more respect to the judgment of others.

Benjamin Franklin

The Declaration of the Rights of Man and of the Citizen (1789), adopted by the National Constituent Assembly during the French Revolution, states in Article 10: "No-one shall be interfered with for his opinions, even religious ones, provided that their practice does not disturb public order as established by the law." ("Nul ne doit être inquiété pour ses opinions, mêmes religieuses, pourvu que leur manifestation ne trouble pas l'ordre public établi par la loi.")[13]

In the nineteenth century

[edit]

Mill

[edit]

In "On Liberty" (1859) John Stuart Mill concludes that opinions ought never to be suppressed, stating, "Such prejudice, or oversight, when it [i.e. false belief] occurs, is altogether an evil; but it is one from which we cannot hope to be always exempt, and must be regarded as the price paid for an inestimable good."[14]: 93 He claims that there are three sorts of beliefs that can be had—wholly false, partly true, and wholly true—all of which, according to Mill, benefit the common good:

First, if any opinion is compelled to silence, that opinion may, for aught we can certainly know, be true. To deny this is to assume our infallibility. Secondly, though the silenced opinion is an error, it may, and very commonly does, contain a portion of truth; and since the general or prevailing opinion on any subject is rarely or never the whole truth, it is only by the collision of adverse opinions that the remainder of the truth has any chance of being supplied. Thirdly, even if the received opinion is not only true but the whole truth; unless it is suffered to be, and is, vigorously and earnestly contested, it will, by most of those who receive it, be held in the manner of a prejudice, with little comprehension or feeling of its rational grounds. Not only this, but, fourthly, the meaning of the doctrine itself will be in danger of being lost, or enfeebled, and deprived of its vital effect on the character and conduct: the dogma becoming a mere formal profession, inefficacious for good, but cumbering the ground, and preventing the growth of any real and heartfelt conviction, from reason or personal experience.[14]: 95

Renan

[edit]
Renan

In his 1882 essay "What is a Nation?", French historian and philosopher Ernest Renan proposed a definition of nationhood based on "a spiritual principle" involving shared memories rather than a common religious, racial, or linguistic heritage. Thus members of any religious group could participate fully in the nation's life. "You can be French, English, German, yet Catholic, Protestant, Jewish, or practicing no religion."[15]

In the twentieth century

[edit]

In 1948, the United Nations General Assembly adopted Article 18 of the Universal Declaration of Human Rights, which states:

Everyone has the right to freedom of thought, conscience, and religion; this right includes freedom to change his religion or belief and freedom, either alone or in community with others and in public or private, to manifest his religion or belief in teaching, practice, worship, and observance.[16]

Though not formally legally binding, the Declaration has been adopted in or has influenced many national constitutions since 1948. It also serves as the foundation for a growing number of international treaties and national laws and international, regional, national, and sub-national institutions protecting and promoting human rights, including the freedom of religion.

Modern analyses and critiques

[edit]

Contemporary commentators have highlighted situations in which toleration conflicts with widely held moral standards, national law, the principles of national identity, or other strongly held goals. Michael Walzer notes that the British in India tolerated the Hindu practice of suttee (ritual burning of a widow) until 1829. On the other hand, the United States declined to tolerate the Mormon practice of polygamy.[17] The French head scarf controversy represents a conflict between religious practice and the French secular ideal.[18] Toleration of or intolerance toward the Romani people in European countries is a continuing issue.[19] Pope Francis refers to the "admirable creativity and generosity" shown by people who put up with their lives in "a seemingly undesirable environment" and learn "to live their lives amid disorder and uncertainty".[20]

Modern definition

[edit]
The NYC Pride March is the world's largest LGBT event. Regional variation exists with respect to toleration in different parts of the world.

Historian Alexandra Walsham notes that the modern understanding of the word "toleration" may be very different from its historic meaning.[21] Toleration in modern parlance has been analyzed as a component of a liberal or libertarian view of human rights. Hans Oberdiek writes, "As long as no one is harmed or no one's fundamental rights are violated, the state should keep hands off, tolerating what those controlling the state find disgusting, deplorable, or debased. For a long time, this has been the most prevalent defense of toleration by liberals... It is found, for example, in the writings of American philosophers John Rawls, Robert Nozick, Ronald Dworkin, Brian Barry, and a Canadian, Will Kymlicka, among others."[22]

Isaiah Berlin attributed to Herbert Butterfield the notion that "toleration ... implies a certain disrespect. I tolerate your absurd beliefs and your foolish acts, though I know them to be absurd and foolish. Mill would, I think, have agreed."[23][page needed]

John Gray states that "When we tolerate a practice, a belief or a character trait, we let something be that we judge to be undesirable, false, or at least inferior; our toleration expresses the conviction that, despite its badness, the object of toleration should be left alone."[24] However, according to Gray, "new liberalism – the liberalism of Rawls, Dworkin, Ackerman and suchlike" – seems to imply that "it is wrong for government to discriminate in favour of, or against, any form of life animated by a definite conception of the good".[25]

John Rawls' "theory of 'political liberalism' conceives of toleration as a pragmatic response to the fact of diversity". Diverse groups learn to tolerate one another by developing "what Rawls calls 'overlapping consensus': individuals and groups with diverse metaphysical views or 'comprehensive schemes' will find reasons to agree about certain principles of justice that will include principles of toleration".[26]

Herbert Marcuse, in the 1965 book A Critique of Pure Tolerance, argued that "pure tolerance" that permits all can favor totalitarianism and tyranny of the majority, and insisted on "repressive tolerance" against them.[citation needed]

Tolerating the intolerant

[edit]

Walzer, Karl Popper,[27] and John Rawls[28] have discussed the paradox of tolerating intolerance. Walzer asks "Should we tolerate the intolerant?" He notes that most minority religious groups who are the beneficiaries of tolerance are themselves intolerant, at least in some respects.[17]: 80–81  Rawls argues that an intolerant sect should be tolerated in a tolerant society unless the sect directly threatens the security of other members of the society. He hypothetises that members of the intolerant sect in a tolerant society will, over time, acquire the tolerance of the wider society.

Other criticisms and issues

[edit]

Toleration has been described as undermining itself via moral relativism: "either the claim self-referentially undermines itself or it provides us with no compelling reason to believe it. If we are skeptical about knowledge, then we have no way of knowing that toleration is good."[26]

Ronald Dworkin argues that in exchange for toleration, minorities must bear with the criticisms and insults which are part of the freedom of speech in an otherwise tolerant society.[29] Dworkin has also questioned whether the United States is a "tolerant secular" nation, or is re-characterizing itself as a "tolerant religious" nation, based on the increasing re-introduction of religious themes into conservative politics. Dworkin concludes that "the tolerant secular model is preferable, although he invited people to use the concept of personal responsibility to argue in favor of the tolerant religious model."[30]

In The End of Faith, Sam Harris asserts that society should be unwilling to tolerate unjustified religious beliefs about morality, spirituality, politics, and the origin of humanity, especially beliefs that promote violence.

See also

[edit]

Sources

[edit]

 This article incorporates text from a free content work. Licensed under CC-BY-SA IGO 3.0 (license statement/permission). Text taken from Rethinking Education: Towards a global common good?​, 24, UNESCO.

References

[edit]
  1. ^ Murphy, Andrew R. (1997). "Tolerance, Toleration, and the Liberal Tradition". Polity. 29 (4). The University of Chicago Press Journals: 593–623. doi:10.2307/3235269. JSTOR 3235269. S2CID 155764374.
  2. ^ "Definition of tolerance". dictionary.com. Retrieved 2 January 2023.
  3. ^ Merriam-Webster Dictionary, tolerate verb, accessed 13 February 2024
  4. ^ a b c d van Doorn, Marjoka (2014). "The nature of tolerance and the social circumstances in which it emerges". Current Sociology. 62 (6): 905–927.
  5. ^ a b Zagorin, Perez (2003). How the Idea of Religious Toleration Came to the West. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press. ISBN 978-0-691-09270-6. OCLC 50982270.
  6. ^ Vahland, Joachim (2017). "Tolerance discourses". Zeno. No. 37. pp. 7–25.
  7. ^ Gervers, Peter; Gervers, Michael; Powell, James M., eds. (2001). Tolerance and Intolerance: Social Conflict in the Age of the Crusades. Syracuse University Press. ISBN 978-0-8156-2869-9.
  8. ^ McKinnon, Catriona (2006). Toleration: A Critical Introduction. New York: Routledge. ISBN 978-0-415-32289-8.
  9. ^ "Diversity As A Core Value – What Does It Mean To Value Diversity?". emexmag.com. Retrieved 10 June 2016.
  10. ^ Vogt, W.P. (1997). Tolerance & Education: Learning to Live with Diversity and Difference. Thousand Oaks, Calif.: Sage Publications, Inc.
  11. ^ "tolerance (n.)". Online Etymology Dictionary. Retrieved 19 November 2018.
  12. ^ a b "toleration (n.)". Online Etymology Dictionary. Retrieved 19 November 2018.
  13. ^ "Déclaration des droits de l'Homme et du citoyen de 1789" (in French).
  14. ^ a b Mill, John Stuart (1859). On Liberty. London: John W. Parker and Son.
  15. ^ Renan, Ernest (11 March 1882). "'What is a nation?' Conference at the Sorbonne". Retrieved 13 January 2011.
  16. ^ "The Universal Declaration of Human Rights". United Nations. 1948. Retrieved 1 June 2007.
  17. ^ a b Walzer, Michael (1997). On Toleration. The Castle lectures in ethics, politics, and economics. New Haven: Yale University Press. ISBN 0300070195. OCLC 47008086.
  18. ^ Bowen, John (February–March 2004). "Muslims and Citizens". The Boston Review. Retrieved 25 January 2011.
  19. ^ "A long road". The Economist. 18 September 2010. ISSN 0013-0613. Retrieved 2 January 2023.
  20. ^ Pope Francis (2015), Laudato si', paragraph 148, accessed 13 February 2024
  21. ^ Walsham, Alexandra (2006). Charitable Hatred: Tolerance and Intolerance in England, 1500–1700. Manchester: Manchester University Press. p. 233. ISBN 978-0-7190-5239-2. OCLC 62533086.
  22. ^ Oberdiek, Hans (2001). Tolerance: Between Forbearance and Acceptance. Lanham, Md.: Rowman & Littlefield Publishers. p. vi. ISBN 978-0-8476-8785-5. OCLC 45604024.
  23. ^ Berlin, Isaiah (1969). Four Essays on Liberty. London: Oxford University Press. ISBN 978-0-19-500272-0. OCLC 15227.
  24. ^ John, Gray (2015). Enlightenment's Wake: Politics and Culture at the Close of the Modern Age. Routledge. ISBN 978-1-138-17022-3. OCLC 941437450.
  25. ^ Gray (1995), p. 20.
  26. ^ a b Fiala, Andrew. "Toleration". Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy. Retrieved 2 January 2023.
  27. ^ Popper, Karl. "chapter 7, note 4". The Open Society and Its Enemies. Vol. 1. ISBN 978-0-691-21206-7. OCLC 1193010976.
  28. ^ Rawls, John (1971). A Theory of Justice: Original Edition. Harvard University Press. p. 216. ISBN 978-0-674-01772-6.
  29. ^ Dworkin, Ronald (14 February 2006). "Even bigots and Holocaust deniers must have their say". The Guardian. Retrieved 2 January 2023.
  30. ^ "Dworkin Explores Secular, Religious Models for Society". Virginia Law School News and Events. 18 April 2008. Archived from the original on 18 January 2012. Retrieved 21 March 2011.

Further reading

[edit]
[edit]