Quantum Decoherence in A Pragmatist View: Dispelling Feynman's Mystery
Quantum Decoherence in A Pragmatist View: Dispelling Feynman's Mystery
Quantum Decoherence in A Pragmatist View: Dispelling Feynman's Mystery
DOI 10.1007/s10701-012-9681-5
Quantum Decoherence in a Pragmatist View: Dispelling
Feynmans Mystery
Richard Healey
Received: 3 April 2012 / Accepted: 6 September 2012 / Published online: 21 September 2012
Springer Science+Business Media, LLC 2012
Abstract The quantumtheory of decoherence plays an important role in a pragmatist
interpretation of quantum theory. It governs the descriptive content of claims about
values of physical magnitudes and offers advice on when to use quantum probabili-
ties as a guide to their truth. The content of a claim is to be understood in terms of
its role in inferences. This promises a better treatment of meaning than that offered
by Bohr. Quantum theory models physical systems with no mention of measurement:
it is decoherence, not measurement, that licenses application of Borns probability
rule. So quantum theory also offers advice on its own application. I show how this
works in a simple model of decoherence, and then in applications to both labora-
tory experiments and natural systems. Applications to quantum eld theory and the
measurement problem will be discussed elsewhere.
Keywords Decoherence Quantum interpretation Pragmatist
1 Introduction
This paper aims to show how a pragmatist account of the content and function of
statements in quantum theory is able to use decoherence to dispel the mystery Feyn-
man located at the heart of that theory. By decoherence, I mean the delocalization
of phase of a quantum system through interaction with its environment. Feynman [1,
Vol. III, Chap. 1] located the mystery already in a two-slit (or hole) interference
experiment with individual particleshe chose electrons. Focusing attention on the
proposition (A) that each electron either goes through hole 1 or it goes through hole
2 [and not both], he rehearsed a familiar argument with the (false) conclusion that
no interference fringes will appear on a detection screen placed behind the holes. As
R. Healey ()
Philosophy Department, University of Arizona, Tucson, AZ 85721-0027, USA
e-mail: [email protected]
Found Phys (2012) 42:15341555 1535
well as (A), the argument assumes that there are well-dened probabilities Pr(R&1),
Pr(R&2) for an electron to be detected in region R of the screen after passing through
hole 1, 2 respectively, whose values are independent of whether the other hole is open
or closed. Feynman [1, 19] concluded
if one has a piece of apparatus which is capable of determining whether the
electrons go through hole 1 or hole 2, then one can say it goes through either
hole 1 or hole 2. [otherwise] one may not say that an electron goes through
either hole 1 or hole 2. If one does say that, and starts to make any deduc-
tions from the statement, he will make errors in the analysis. This is the logical
tightrope on which we must walk if we wish to describe nature successfully.
But how could the absence of a piece of apparatus revoke ones right to free
speech? Presumably although one can assert (A) in any circumstances, Feynmans
advice was that one should do so only when the apparatus is present, because only
then is (A) meaningful and conducive to correct inferences. But the mystery remains:
How can the presence of a piece of apparatus render (A) both meaningful and correct,
and what exactly is meant by the presence of such a piece of apparatus? I will offer
answers to these questions as a way of dispelling the mystery.
An alternative is to locate the aw in the familiar argument in its assumptions
about probabilities. Grifths [2] consistent histories approach permits one to assume
(A) only in a framework corresponding to a history set {C
} satisfying a consis-
tency condition to ensure a well-dened probability for each history (specied by a
time-indexed sequence of projectors, each taken von Neumann-fashion to represent
a corresponding property of a system at that time). On this approach, Feynmans ar-
gument breaks down because there is no framework in which Pr(R&1), Pr(R&2) are
well-dened. But there is a framework that assigns probabilities Pr(S&1), Pr(S&2)
to histories of an electron passing through hole 1 (hole 2) and then being detected
somewhere (S). In such a framework, (A) may be assigned probability 1 and taken
as meaningful and true.
Now we have another mystery: (A) is meaningless in a framework including a
history corresponding to passage through hole 1(2) and being detected in region R,
but meaningful and true in another framework containing no such histories. The con-
sistent histories approach supplies formal framework-relativized rules governing the
making of statements ascribing properties to systems like electrons, but offers no ac-
count of the content of such statements and does not explain the point of making
them, in conformity to the rules.
While noting the inuence of Grifths prior work, Gell-Mann and Hartle [3, 4]
(see also Omns [5, 6]) stress the importance of environmentally-induced decoher-
ence in rendering a family of histories (at least approximately) consistent (or deco-
herent in their rival usage of that term). Gell-Mann and Hartle present their view as
a development of an Everettian formulation of quantum theory from which a more
standard formulation may be retrieved, given appropriate assumptions.
1
Their main
motivation for imposing decoherence/consistency conditions on histories is to ensure
1
But note that the characteristically democratic Everettian talk of multiple real branches no longer ap-
pears in the later [7].
1536 Found Phys (2012) 42:15341555
the application of probabilistic rules of quantum theorynot just to measurement
outcomes, but to properties of quantum systems whether or not these happen to be
measured. If successful, their approach would dispel part of Feynmans mystery by
replacing talk of the presence of a piece of apparatus by an account of how interac-
tions within a closed system can decohere the state of a subsystem through its interac-
tion with the rest of the system. But they say no more than Grifths about the content
of a statement that such a subsystem has a property corresponding to a projection,
or how to reconcile such a statement with another statement that it has a property
corresponding to a non-commuting projection from an alternative decoherent set of
histories.
Two things are needed to dispel Feynmans mystery:
(1) An account of how a statement ascribing a property to a quantum system acquires
any content at all, and what content it has in different circumstances.
(2) An account of the use of the probabilistic rules of quantum theory that shows
how and why their use must be restricted so as to ensure consistency.
I offer account (1) in Sect. 3.2, and (2) in Sect. 3.3 of this paper. The accounts are
connected by the natural requirement that the probabilistic rules of quantum theory
can be applied only to statements with well-dened content. These accounts depend
on what I call a pragmatist interpretation of quantum theory that I outlined in [8].
This governs the descriptive content of claims about values of physical magnitudes
and advises an agent on when to apply the Born Rule as a guide to their truth.
But, on this interpretation, it does so without representing the dynamic behavior
of physical systems: for while it is quantum states that are subject to environmental
decoherence, the quantum state does not serve to represent or describe physical sys-
tems. Because the familiar view that quantum models of environmental decoherence
offer representations of a physical process conicts with a non-representational view
of the quantum state, I explain in Sect. 2 how the quantum state functions, according
to this pragmatist interpretation.
Section 3 then shows in a simple model how decoherence governs the content of
descriptive claims about a qubit. The content of a claimis to be understood in terms of
what inferences an agent may draw from that claim and what would entitle an agent
to make it. This inferentialist pragmatism about content promises a better treatment
of meaning than that offered by Bohr and his followers.
2
Quantum theory assigns probabilities to claims about the values of magnitudes
through the Born Rule. But it is now well established that these magnitudes cannot
consistently all be taken simultaneously to possess precise values on each system,
distributed over a collection of similar systems in such a way that the fractions of
systems with particular values for each magnitude match the corresponding proba-
bilities owing from the Born Rule.
3
Consistency then restricts each application of
the Born Rule to a proper subset of all magnitudes. Conventionally, one species
2
Here I am indebted to the writings of Brandom [9, 10] and Price [11, 12]. Bohr expressed his views in a
number of essays collected in Bohr [1315].
3
See, for example, [1620].
Found Phys (2012) 42:15341555 1537
probabilities only for measurement outcomes, and postulates that only those magni-
tudes represented by pairwise commuting self-adjoint operators are simultaneously
measurable. But Bell [18, 21] raised powerful objections against incorporating mea-
surement into the basic principles of quantum theory, either as a primitive term or
when cashed out in equally unsatisfactory terms such as irreversible amplication,
classical system, or conscious observation. The pragmatist interpretation of [8]
relies on quantum models of environmental decoherence that involve no reference to
measurement to secure consistent application of the Born Rule. Section 3 shows how
this works.
The general account of Sect. 3 is illustrated in Sect. 4 by applying it to some more
realistic examples, both in a laboratory setting and in the universe at large. These
are intended to show how the details of environmental decoherence can affect the
signicance of descriptive claims licensed by a quantum state, and to exhibit both the
practical use of the Born Rule and its limitations.
In conclusion the paper summarizes the role of decoherence within the pragmatist
interpretation of quantum theory outlined in [8], contrasting this with the very differ-
ent role allotted to it in a recent pragmatist-inspired paper [22]; and it notes questions
that still need to be answered to understand just how decoherence can play this role.
2 The Function of the Quantum State
The delocalization of phase in a systems quantum state due to interaction with sys-
tems constituting its environment is generally regarded as a physical process. Quan-
tum models compare and contrast this process with other, more familiar, physical
processes such as dissipation due to energy loss into the environment. Quantum de-
coherence need not be accompanied by dissipation, though when it is, it is typically
a much faster process. Some say that quantum decoherence occurs as a result of a
system acting on its environment, whereas dissipation occurs because the system is
acted on by its environment. Such language in which discussions of environmental
decoherence are couched is thoroughly physical. Master equations and other mathe-
matical treatments of quantum decoherence are taken to represent how the physical
condition of a system changes in response to its interaction with its environment
when that interaction is represented by an interaction Hamiltonian. But the immedi-
ate content of such treatments concerns the evolution of a systems quantum state.
To read a representation of the evolution of a quantum state as a description of the
changing condition of the system to which it pertains is to adopt a particular interpre-
tative stance toward quantum states. It is to assume that a quantum state provides a
description of the physical condition of a system to which it is assigned.
But this is only one, disputed, view of the function of the quantum state. On the
present pragmatist understanding,
4
the function of the quantumstate is not to describe
4
Fuchs [23, 24] is a pragmatist who has proposed an alternative understanding of a quantum state as
merely a bearer of subjective probabilities representing an agents actual degrees of belief. He takes these
to be restricted only by minimal rationality requirements (unfortunately also called coherence!) necessary
and sufcient to warrant their mathematical representation as a probability measure. Fuchss subjectivist
quantum state represents an agents beliefs: it does not prescribe them. In the papers conclusion I comment
on his very different take on the role of quantum decoherence.
1538 Found Phys (2012) 42:15341555
but to prescribe: Aquantumstate does not provide even an incomplete description of a
physical system to which is assigned. Instead, by assigning a quantum state, an agent
using quantum theory takes the rst step in a procedure that licenses it
5
to express
claims about physical systems in descriptive language and then warrants it in partially
believing some such claims. The language in which these claims are expressed is not
the language of quantumstates or operators, and the claims are not about probabilities
or measurement results: they are about properties of physical systems. In this paper
I restrict attention to properties of a system corresponding to projections onto the
systems Hilbert space: so if M is a magnitude on a system, then the property M
locating its value in Borel set corresponds to the projection
P
M
() from
Ms
spectral measure.
An agent must be physically situatable to use quantum theory because a quantum
state and consequent Born probabilities can be assigned to a system only relative to
the physical situation of an (actual or hypothetical) agent for whom these assignments
would yield good advice. What one agent should believe may be quite different from
what another agent in a different physical, and therefore epistemic, situation should
nd credible. This relational character of quantum states and Born probabilities does
not make these subjective, and it may be neglected whenever users of quantum theory
nd themselves in relevantly similar physical situations.
6
Claims about properties
of a system are also objective, but, unlike claims pertaining to quantum states and
Born probabilities, they are not relational in this way: Whether they are true does not
depend on the physical situation of any actual or hypothetical agent.
A quantum state is objective because it provides authoritative guidance to an agent
on two important matters. It provides sound advice both on the content of statements
about properties of physical systems and on the credibility of some of these state-
ments. Environmental decoherence gures in both these roles of the quantum state.
Section 3.2 shows how decoherence enables the quantum state to play the rst ad-
visory role: Sect. 3.3 is concerned with its contribution to the second. Note that this
pragmatist interpretation does not deny that environmental decoherence involves a
physical process: but it does deny that the role of a systems quantum state is to de-
scribe or represent properties of systems involved in such a process.
An agent requires guidance in assessing the content of statements about systems
of interest. In the passage quoted in the introduction, Feynman begins by applying
a common view of meaning in quantum theory: that assignment of a value to an
observable on a system is meaningful only in the presence of some apparatus capable
of measuring the value of that observable. But some general account of meaning must
be offered in support of this claim, and the extreme operationist account that is most
naturally associated with it would be unacceptably vague even if it were otherwise
defensible.
5
I use the impersonal pronoun throughout to remind the reader that on this view an agent need be neither
human nor even conscious. In these respects my usage of agent is similar to Gell-Mann and Hartles
usage of their term IGUS (for Information Gathering and Utilizing System).
6
The relational character of quantum states has been emphasized by others, including [25], who showed
how much different state assignments can differ.
Found Phys (2012) 42:15341555 1539
Contemporary pragmatist accounts of meaning have the resources to provide a
better account of the meaning of a statement about a property of a system. It is strik-
ing that such an account is suggested by the way Feynman [1, 1.9] qualies his initial
ban on asserting proposition (A). A pragmatist like Brandom [9, 10] takes the content
of any claim to be articulated by the inferences in which it may gure as premise or
conclusion. These inferences may vary with the context in which a claim arises, so
the content of the claim depends on that context. The quantum state of a system mod-
ulates the content of claims about its properties by specifying the context in which
they arise. This depends on the nature and degree of environmental decoherence suf-
fered by this quantum state. A statement about a property M of a system whose
quantum state has extensively decohered in a basis of eigenstates of
M has a corre-
spondingly well-dened meaning: a rich content accrues to it via the large variety of
inferences that may legitimately be drawn to and from the statement in that context.
Only when a claim M about a system has a rich content because it is fully
integrated into a web of reliable inferences is it appropriate to apply the Born Rule to
assess the claims credibility. An agent may then apply the Born Rule to evaluate the
probability of the claim using the appropriate quantum state. If [
P
M
(),
P
N
( )] =
0, then the Born Rule will never be applicable to both claims M, N at once,
since there is no context in which they both have a sufciently well-dened content.
3 The Content and Credibility of Property Claims
3.1 A Simple Model of Decoherence
Consider a simple model of decoherence introduced by Zurek [26] and further dis-
cussed in Cucchetti, Paz and Zurek [27]. This features a single quantum system A
interacting with a second environment system E as in [27].
7
A is a single qubit,
and its environment E is modeled by a collection of N qubits. One can think of each
qubit as realized by a spin
1
2
system, so that | (|) represent z-spin up (down)
eigenstates of the Pauli spin operator
z
of A, while |
k
(|
k
) represent z-spin up
(down) eigenstates of
k
z
for the kth environment spin subsystem.
The individual Hamiltonians
H
A
,
H
E
of A and E are assumed to be zero, while
the interaction Hamiltonian
H
AE
has the form
H
AE
=
1
2
z
N
k=1
g
k
k
z
. (1)
If A, E are assumed to be initially assigned pure, uncorrelated states
A
=
_
a| +b|
_
, (2)
E
=
N
k=1
_
k
|
k
+
k
|
k
_
(3)
7
Zureks original model also included a third system S: his choice of notation then was intended to help
his reader bear in mind an application of the model to a system S interacting with a quantum apparatus A.
1540 Found Phys (2012) 42:15341555
then the initial state
(0) =
A
E
(4)
evolves according to the Schrdinger equation, becoming
(t ) =
_
a|
(t )
_
+b|
(t )
__
(5)
at time t where
(t )
_
=
N
k=1
_
k
e
ig
k
t
|
k
+
k
e
ig
k
t
|
k
_
=
(t )
_
. (6)
The state of A, calculated by tracing over the Hilbert space of E, is therefore
A
(t ) =|a|
2
|| +ab
r(t )|| +a
br
(t )|| +|b|
2
||. (7)
The coefcient r(t ) =E
(t )|E
k=1
_
cos 2g
k
t +i
_
|
k
|
2
|
k
|
2
_
sin2g
k
t
_
. (8)
Cucchetti, Paz and Zurek [27] show that |r(t )| tends to decrease rapidly with increas-
ing N and very quickly approaches zero with increasing t . More precisely, while
|r(t )|
2
uctuates, its average magnitude at any time is proportional to 2
N
, and, for
fairly generic values of the g
k
, it decreases with time according to the Gaussian rule
|r(t )|
2
e
2
t
2
, where depends on the distribution of the g
k
as well as the initial
state of E. This result is relatively insensitive to the initial state of E, which need not
be assumed to have the product form (3), though if the environment is initially in an
eigenstate of (1) |r(t )| = 1 so the state of A will suffer no decoherence. Since r(t )
is an almost periodic function of t for nite N, it will continue to return arbitrarily
closely to 1 at various times: but for N corresponding to a macroscopic environment
Zurek [26] estimated that the corresponding recurrence time exceeds the age of the
universe.
3.2 The Content of Property Claims in This Simple Model
Suppose an agent is considering what claims to entertain about the system A in this
simple model. The agent is not explicitly represented in the model itself. But since any
assignment of quantum states is from the perspective of some (actual or hypothetical)
physically situated agent, we must assume the agent has implicitly adopted such a
perspective by assigning the states that gure in the model. Magnitudes pertaining to
A correspond to self-adjoint operators on the Hilbert space H
A
. In this simple model,
any such operator
Q may be expressed as a real linear sum of Pauli spin operators
and the identity operator on H
A
as follows
Q=x
x
+y
y
+z
z
+c
I. (9)
Found Phys (2012) 42:15341555 1541
So we are considering claims about A of the form K : Q , where is a Borel
set of real numbers, and Q corresponds uniquely to the operator
Q. After setting
S
i
(/2)
i
(i =x, y, z) these include
I =1, (A)
S
x
{+/2, /2}, (B)
S
x
=+/2, (C)
S
x
=/2, (C
)
S
z
{+/2, /2}, (D)
S
z
=+/2, (E)
S
z
=/2. (E
)
The agents primary interest is in its entitlement to believe a claim K about A, in-
cluding each of the claims (A)(E
) given only the initial state (2) the agent assigns to A? That depends
on the inferential role of each claim. The agent may be tempted to infer claim (D)
about A from the fact that (2) expresses this state as a superposition of eigenstates
of
z
. But the initial state of A may be expressed equally well as a superposition of
eigenstates |, | of
x
A
=c| +d|, where c =
1
2
(a +b), d =
1
2
(a b) (10)
(or indeed of any operator
Q). So if the content of a claim of the form K then de-
pended only on the state (2) then our agent should be equally tempted to make claim
(B) (as well as every other similar claim assigning some eigenvalue of
Q to every
magnitude Q in that state).
The simple model represents no piece of apparatus capable of determining whether
(C) or (C
) is true, so Feynman would warn against saying (B) unless our agent de-
clines to make any inferences from (B). (B) is an exclusive disjunction, and the prob-
lematic inferences to be barred would proceed by deriving a (false) conclusion from
each disjunct separately and hence drawing that conclusion on the basis of the dis-
junction alone. In the two-slit experiment, the assumption that each electron goes
through one slit or the other leads to the false conclusion that the interference pattern
on the screen is the sum of a pattern formed by electrons going through slit 1 and a
pattern formed by electrons going through slit 2. But to derive that conclusion, one
needs further to assume that the behavior of an electron going through slit 1(2) is the
same whether or not slit 2(1) is openan assumption rejected by Bohmians, among
others.
This illustrates an important point. The inferences that contribute to the content of
a property claim like (B) are not restricted to mathematically and logically valid in-
ferences, but include what Sellars [28] called material inferences. Indeed, according
1542 Found Phys (2012) 42:15341555
to an inferentialist account of content like Brandoms [9, 10] it is precisely such ma-
terial inferences that contribute essentially to empirical content. But, as in this case,
what material inferences a claim licenses will depend on what other assumptions are
made.
The content of (C) and (C
(sin cos )
x
+(sin sin)
y
+cos
z
, (11)
where a = cos /2exp(i/2), b = sin/2exp(+i/2). This state may be repre-
sented on the Bloch sphere by a unit vector n with angular coordinates (, ). The
operator
S
n
= (/2)
corresponds to a component S
n
of angular momentum in
a spatial direction n with spherical coordinates (, ) dened with respect to the
(x, y, z) Cartesian coordinate system. Consider the claim
S
n
=+/2 (F)
Since (2) is an eigenstate of
S
n
with eigenvalue +/2, our agent may be tempted to
make claim (F) solely on the basis of that initial state assignment to A. But before
doing so, it should assess (F)s content.
Since the content of (F) is a function of its inferential role, the agent must con-
sider what could entitle it to infer (F) and what it could infer from (F). The agent
could immediately infer (F) from (2) in accordance with the interpretative principle
EigenState to EigenValue:
(SV) If a systems quantum state satises
P
i
= , where
P
i
projects onto
the eigenspace with eigenvalue q
i
of an operator
Q corresponding to magnitude
Q, then Q has value q
i
.
But the principle (SV) should be rejected as incompatible with the pragmatist de-
nial that a systems quantumstate provides any kind of description of it. Alternatively,
our agent might think to infer (F) using the EPR [29, p. 777] sufcient condition of
reality.
If, without in any way disturbing a system, we can predict with certainty (i.e.
with probability equal to unity) the value of a physical quantity, then there
exists an element of reality corresponding to this physical quantity.
The thought might be that application of the Born Rule to (2) would assign proba-
bility unity to the claim S
n
=+/2, and then (F) follows from (EPR)s reality condi-
tion. But this thought is mistaken whatever the status of that criterion. One is entitled
to apply the Born Rule to state (2) and assign a probability (unity) to (F) only if (F)
8
A similar conclusion in the 3-dimensional Hilbert space of a spin 1 system would be inconsistent with
Gleasons theorem [16].
Found Phys (2012) 42:15341555 1543
has sufcient content to permit that application. But the empirical content of (F) is
exactly what is in question. Clearly, it would be circular to assume that (F) has suf-
cient content to entitle one to apply the Born Rule to (F) in state (2) in order to argue
that (F) has any signicant empirical content! In fact the Born Rule is not applicable
to this claim in the simple model, in which the only interaction to which A is subject
is modeled by (1): to be entitled to apply the Born Rule to assign a probability to
(F) at t = 0, our agent would have to realize that A is subject to an interaction that
decohered eigenstates of
S
n
at t =0.
In state (2) one may infer from (F) to any claims validly deducible by logic and
mathematics alone, such as these:
S
n
{+/2, /2},
(S
n
=+/2) or (S
n
=+),
S
2
n
=
2
/4.
So it is not strictly correct to say that (F) is vacuous in this case. But in order to have
any physical content, (F) would have to permit material inferences that are neither
logically nor mathematically valid.
In classical physics, property claims typically permit material inferences of two
kinds: dynamic inferences and measurement inferences. An assumption of continuity
guarantees that ascription to a magnitude of a value in set at time t licenses a mate-
rial inference to its value in set
at t +, where
). The initial state (2) licenses an agent to make no physically signicant claims
about A.
But the agents resources are not conned to the assignment of an initial state to
A. Using this simple model of decoherence, our agent also species how the initial
quantum state of A evolves under the inuence of interaction with its environment.
It is the role of decoherence here that endows certain claims about A with empirical
signicance, according to the interpretation outlined in [8].
The quantum state initially assigned to A evolves, so that after a remarkably short
time T it will come to approach the diagonal form
A
=|a|
2
|| +|b|
2
||. (12)
If =0 or (i.e. |a|
2
or |b|
2
=1) in state (2), then claim (F) reduces respectively to
(E) or to (E
), but
not (A)(C
).
1544 Found Phys (2012) 42:15341555
While (A)(C
) have
empirical content because of the material inferences each supports. Our agent may
use (D) in inferences that assume that just one disjunct is true in state (12), even
with no empirical basis for claiming (E) as against (E
)
permits the dynamic and measurement inferences discussed three paragraphs back.
This illustrates the importance of environmental decoherence in endowing a prop-
erty claim with empirical content. Deployment of the simple model of decoherence
cannot by itself justify an agent in making a material inference either to (E) or to (E
).
Rather, as Sect. 3.3 explains, assignment of state (12) to A in the context of this model
justies the practical inference involved in adopting degree of belief (credence) |a|
2
in (E) and credence |b|
2
in (E
{+/2, /2} L
If is close enough to zero, then (1) will very rapidly, and quite stably, bring the state
of A almost as close to diagonal in a basis of eigenstates of
S
as of
S
z
. A material
inference to a claim of the form L in the context of the model will be almost as good
as the inference to (D), and the inferential power of a claim of the form L will be
almost as great as that of (D). More generally, the empirical content of a claim of the
form L here is a function of , varying continuously from its maximum value for
=0, to zero for =/2. It corresponds to the reliability of the inference from
the claim that S
has
that same eigenvalue at t + and that this would also be the result of a well-conducted
measurement of S
at time t +.
What is the relation between the interaction modeled by (1), the possibility of
measuring the value of a magnitude Q in the simple model, and what it takes to have
a piece of apparatus which is capable of determining the value of a magnitude Q? The
model itself makes no mention of any apparatus or measurement. But in applying the
model, an agent is effectively committed to counting the interaction modeled by (1) as
Found Phys (2012) 42:15341555 1545
itself a potential measurement of S
z
that excludes measurements of other magnitudes
S
. M
Empirical signicance has no natural cut-off here, or in any application of quantum
theory. So this restriction on application of the Born Rule does not yield a precise
selection criterion. This is a classic case of vagueness. The Born Rule is clearly ap-
plicable to claims (D), (E), (E) in the simple model, and clearly inapplicable to claims
(A), (B), (C), (C
(R
1
, R
2
) =(R
1
, R
2
)(R
1
R
2
) (13)
where the decoherence function (R
1
R
2
) represents the effect of decoherence on
the off-diagonal elements of the un-decohered reduced state (R
1
, R
2
). (It has no
effect on the diagonal elements, since lim
R
1
R
2
(R
1
R
2
) =1.)
Assuming photon emission is both isotropic and independent of R, is a function
only of the spectral photon emission rate. This is not the same as for a macroscopic
black body since the emitting particle is small and not in thermal equilibrium with a
heat bath, and the emission is assumed to take place at a xed internal energy rather
than temperature. Given the assumption that the emitting molecule has a denite
energy E, it can be associated with a microcanonical temperature T
given in terms
of the entropy S(E) by
T
(E) =
_
S(E)
E
_
1
. (14)
So to assign an internal temperature to a beam of C
70
molecules at each point in
the interferometer one must assume that each is always in a state of denite energy
except during photon emission, which is associated with a transition between energy
states. But what justies this assumption?
While it is decoherence of their center of mass quantumstate that is the focus of the
model, one must also consider decoherence of the internal state of the C
70
molecules.
Here a different model of decoherence is more appropriate. While the fullerenes in-
teract strongly with the electromagnetic eld of the laser beams that heat them before
entering the interferometer, their electromagnetic interactions inside it are very weak
at room temperature. Paz and Zurek [35] showed that in this quantum limit, the
reduced internal quantum state of a system rapidly becomes approximately diago-
nal in a basis of energy eigenstates as result of its interaction with the environment.
This is what justies an agent in claiming that each fullerene has a denite internal
11
In fact, assignment of a temperature to each molecule is a step that requires justication, as we shall see.
1550 Found Phys (2012) 42:15341555
energy within the interferometer, which may change if it emits a photon. So decoher-
ence plays a double role here. The model of (center of mass) decoherence relevant to
assigning empirical content to claims concerning the position of a fullerene in the in-
terferometer shows howthat decoherence depends on the fullerenes temperature. But
the justication for assigning empirical content to a claim asserting such dependence
rests on an independent model of the fullerenes (internal energy) decoherence.
12
Hackermller et al. [33] detected their fullerenes by ionizing them after the scan-
ning mask and measuring the intensity of detected ions. The detection process in-
volves focusing any ions produced on a conversion electrode, then detecting the emit-
ted electrons. How far does this indirect method of observing the interference pattern
affect the application of the Born Rule and the assignment of content to claims of
the form x about fullerenes at the scanning mask? As [34] shows, the geometry
of the interferometer in the experiment of Hackermller et al. [33] is such that the
probability density for fullerene x-position at the scanning mask predicted by unre-
ective application of the Born Rule to the un-decohered reduced state (R
1
, R
2
)
corresponds to a smoothed image of the rst gratinga pattern with the same period
d as the rst grating, with maximum intensity at the center of the image of a slit win-
dow in the rst grating and minimum intensity at the center of the image of a wall in
the rst grating.
The detector system employed by Hackermller et al. [33] operates by measuring
the ionization intensity for all C
70
molecules passing through the scanning mask at a
particular x-setting. So it is insensitive to through which slit in that third grating any
particular fullerene may (or may not) have passed. Since no apparatus is capable of
detecting through which slit of the second or third grating a fullerene passes, Feyn-
man would forbid one to say the fullerene passed through slit 1 or . . . or slit i or . . .
or slit N
j
of either the 2nd or 3rd (scanning mask) grating (j =2, 3).
On the present pragmatist interpretation, because no signicant decoherence oc-
curred at either grating, a claim of the form x
i
about a fullerene at the second or
third grating has little or no empirical content, where
i
species the opening interval
of the ith slit of either grating (i =1, 2, . . . , N
j
). The exclusive disjunction
(x
1
) . . . (x
i
) . . . (x
N
3
) (15)
regarding the position of a fullerene at the scanning mask therefore also lacks the em-
pirical content required to license its use as a premise in any inference. ((15) asserts
that exactly one (x
i
) (i =1, . . . , N
3
) holds.)
Since the object of the experiment of Hackermller et al. [33] is to investigate the
effect of thermal decoherence on the fringes produced by quantum interference of
single fullerenes, it is obviously important to be able to justify application of the Born
Rule to both decohered and un-decohered reduced states of fullerenes to compare
12
There is a further subtlety here, since no claimabout the entropy S or the microcanonical temperature T
dened in terms of it is a property claim (of the form M ). The entropy is a function of the quantum
state given by the von Neumann expression S = Tr( log), and so the interpretation of [8] denies
that a claim assigning a value either to S or to T