(Oxford Islamic Legal Studies) Anver M. Emon-Religious Pluralism and Islamic Law. Dhimmis and Others in The Empire of Law-Oxford University Press (2012)
(Oxford Islamic Legal Studies) Anver M. Emon-Religious Pluralism and Islamic Law. Dhimmis and Others in The Empire of Law-Oxford University Press (2012)
(Oxford Islamic Legal Studies) Anver M. Emon-Religious Pluralism and Islamic Law. Dhimmis and Others in The Empire of Law-Oxford University Press (2012)
Series Editors:
Anver M. Emon, Clark Lombardi, and Lynn Welchman
OX F OR D I S L A M IC L E G A L S T U DI E S
Series Editors:
Anver M. Emon, Clark Lombardi, and Lynn Welchman
Satisfying the growing interest in Islam and Islamic law, the Oxford Islamic
Legal Studies series speaks to both specialists and those interested in
the study of a legal tradition that shapes lives and societies across the
globe. Islamic law operates at several levels. It shapes private decision
making, binds communities, and it is also imposed by states as domestic
positive law. The series features innovative and interdisciplinary studies
that explore Islamic law as it operates at each of these levels. The series
also sheds new light on the history and jurisprudence of Islamic law and
provides for a richer understanding of the state of Islamic law in the
contemporary Muslim world, including parts of the world where Muslims
are minorities.
ALSO AVAILABLE IN THE SERIES
Narratives of Islamic Legal Theory
Rumee Ahmed
Religious Pluralism
and Islamic Law
Dhimms and Others in the Empire of Law
A N V ER M . EMON
DP
YY
Links to third party websites are provided by Oxford in good faith and
for information only. Oxford disclaims any responsibility for the materials
contained in any third party website referenced in this work.
For
Allyssa and Hafez Atticus
viii
eects that particular rules will have in society. Emon then compares
the pre-modern Islamic regimes with modern liberal democratic ones.
Provocatively, he concludes that if one looks at the social e ects each
system was supposed to produce, their regulatory dynamics prove to be
quite similar.
Clark B. Lombardi
Lynn Welchman
Acknowledgments
This book represents nearly eight years of research, conversation, and
dialogue with friends, colleagues, and mentors from various parts of the
globe. It is a better study because of them, and to them all I owe a deep
sense of gratitude. I alone am responsible for any failings that remain.
When I was a PhD student at UCLA writing my dissertation on Islamic
Natural Law Theories, I had the good fortune of completing an LLM at
Yale Law School, where I met Owen Fiss. A generous scholar committed
to expansive learning, he took an interest in my work on Islamic law. With
his support and the encouragement of the late Father Robert Burns, I
decided to undertake a second doctorate at Yale Law School. This book is
the result of that second research endeavoran endeavor enriched and
deepened by my conversations with Owen Fiss, Paul Kahn, and Anthony
Kronman, all of whom oversaw my research at Yale and have continued to
support me throughout my career ever since. Furthermore, through the
support of both Owen Fiss and Anthony Kronman, I had the good fortune
of presenting aspects of this work to international audiences at Yale
Law Schools Middle East Legal Studies Seminar, irst in Athens, Greece
(
) and later in Amman, Jordan (
). I wish to thank the members of
the MELSS community for their discussion of my work at those meetings
and for their camaraderie over the years. I want to speci ically mention
Asli Bali, Leora Bilsky, Bernard Haykel, Chibli Mallat, Andrew March,
Robert Post, George Priest, Aziz Rana, and Muhammad Qasim Zaman.
I speci ically want to acknowledge Adel Omar Sherif for his friendship
and generous spiritand for the long talks we have whenever we meet,
which are all too infrequent. I also want to acknowledge Wael Hallaq for
his early advice on this project and for his memorable intervention at the
Athens meeting.
The University of Toronto Faculty of Law has been my intellectual
home since
, and I am indebted to the support the institution and
my colleagues have given me over the years. My Dean, Mayo Moran, has
supported and encouraged my research and the di erent directions
it has taken me. My colleagues have been tremendously generous with
their time and advice as I sought to weave di erent threads of my
research together into this study. In particular, I would like to thank Lisa
Austin, Alan Brudner, Jutta Brunee, Yasmin Dawood, David Dyzenhaus,
Mohammad Fadel, Darlene Johnston (now at the University of British
Columbia), Karen Knop, Ian Lee, Sophia Moreau, Marianna Mota Prado,
Acknowledgments
Acknowledgments
xi
xii
Acknowledgments
have seen me through all the various stages of my life (academic and
otherwise), and remain steadfast in their love and support of me. My
heartfelt thanks go to the members of the Case family, who have shown
nothing but respect, support, and enthusiasm for the time Ive spent on
this project, including when I had to excuse myself from family events
from time to time. In fact, Elaine and Andrea brought their musical gifts
to my research as I struggled with the fugal nature of this project. Last
but not least, there is my spouse, Allyssa. Ive saved her for last in part
because it is not easy to put into words the gratitude I have for her love
and support. Words are inadequate to express my profound appreciation
for her unwavering support of my research, and most of all her patience
with me as I often lost track of time and space when working away at this
project. On top of all of that, as I was putting the inal touches to this book,
she gave birth to our son Hafez. To the two of them I dedicate this book.
Introduction
Well before the onset of the twenty- irst century, academic and
popular debates have either implicitly or explicitly positioned Muslims,
Islam, and Islamic law as the paradigmatic Other to be managed and
regulated through policies of multiculturalism and human rights. This is
especially the case in societies identi ied by such labels as western, liberal,
democratic, or some combination thereof. That paradigm is mirrored in
Muslim majority countries that both acknowledge an Islamic contribution
to their core values, and participate in a global network in which that
Islamic content is at times suspiciously viewed from the perspective
of liberal democratic approaches to good governance and individual
autonomy, which have become standard benchmarks of governance, or
at least are perceived to be so. The suspicions about Islam and Muslims
tend to beg one important question that animates considerable debate
in popular venues and the public sphere, i.e., whether or not Muslims,
in light of their faith commitments, can live in peace and harmony with
others, and treat all people, regardless of their faith traditions, with
equal dignity and respect. To use the more common terms of reference,
See, for example, Natasha Bakht, Family Arbitration Using Shara Law: Examining
Ontarios Arbitration Act and its Impact on Women, Muslim World Journal of Human
Rights , no. (
): Article . On religion in liberal constitutional legal systems more
generally, see Caryn Litt Wolfe, Faith-Based Arbitration: Friend or Foe? An Evaluation
of Religious Arbitration Systems and Their Interaction with Secular Courts, Fordham
Law Review
(
):
. For research centers and academic initiatives devoted
to the study of religion in the public sphere, see the University of Torontos Religion in
the Public Sphere Initiative; Columbia Universitys Institute for Religion, Culture and
Public Life. For a center devoted to the study of Islam and Muslims in particular, see the
University of Exeters European Muslim Research Centre.
For policy-oriented studies that negotiate the tensions this dynamic creates, see
United States Agency for International Development (USAID), Afghanistan Rule of Law
Project: Field Study of Informal and Customary Justice in Afghanistan (Washington D.C.:
USAID,
); Noah Feldman, What We Owe Iraq: War and the Ethics of Nation Building
(Princeton: Princeton University Press,
). For an analysis of how a Muslim majority country (i.e., Egypt) negotiates its commitments to its Islamic values alongside its
commitments to constitutional commitments to citizenship and equality for both its
Muslim majority and non-Muslim minority (i.e., Coptic Christians), see Rachel M. Scott,
The Challenge of Political Islam: Non-Muslims and the Egyptian State (Palo Alto: Stanford
University Press,
).
Such debates occur in both scholarly and public arenas. One highly public endeavor
has been the work of those behind the letter A Common Word Between Us and You,
which consists of a letter from Muslim clerics to Christians about their shared values. See
Introduction
Islamic lands. In doing so, it suggests that the Islamic legal treatment of
non-Muslims is symptomatic of the more general challenge of governing a
diverse polity. Far from being constitutive of an Islamic ethos, the dhimm
rules are symptomatic of the messy business of ordering and regulating a
diverse society. This understanding of the dhimm rules allows us to view
the dhimm rules in the larger context of law and pluralism. Further, it
makes possible new perspectives from which to analyze Shara as one
among many legal systems; and that far from being unique, it suers
similar challenges as other legal systems that also contend with the
dif iculty of governing amidst diversity. A comparison to recent cases
from the United States, United Kingdom, France and the European Court
of Human Rights shows that however dierent and distant premodern
Islamic and modern democratic societies may be in terms of time, space,
and tradition, legal systems face similar challenges when governing a
populace that holds diverse views on a wide range of values.
This study is organized around four major themes, all of which are interrelated. One might even ind the work fugal, in the sense that the basic
focus on the dhimm rules makes possible these thematic departures, all
of which are distinct and can stand alone from each other, and yet together
reverberate with a harmony that oers something richer and more robust.
The dhimm rules raise important thematic questions about tolerance;
rule of law and governance; and the way in which the aspiration for
pluralism through the institutions of law and and governance is a messy
business. A bottom line in the pursuit of pluralism is that it can result
in impositions and limitations on freedoms that we might otherwise
consider fundamental to an individuals well-being, but which must be
limited for some people in some circumstances for reasons extending
well beyond the claims of a given individual. This introduction will outline
the four basic themes that animate this study, showcasing their distinct
contributions to the study of the dhimm rules, and illuminating how, in
the aggregate, they raise important questions about the scope of freedom
possible through the law in a context of diversity and di erence.
Introduction
to maintain their distinct faith traditions and to live in peace under Muslim
rule. Under the terms of this contract, dhimms agreed to live by certain
conditions in return for peaceful residence in Muslim lands. The dhimm
rules were those conditions. Hence, the dhimm rules cannot be viewed
today in isolation as mere legal artifacts. They were part of the political
compromise made between the ruling authorities and the minority groups
that became subjected to the Muslim sovereign. The dhimm rules, in other
words, were a legal expression of the way in which the Muslim polity
contended with the fact of diversity and governed pluralistically.
As previously indicated, the dhimm rules often lie at the centre of
contemporary debates about whether the Islamic faith is tolerant or
intolerant of non-Muslims. Some suggest that these rules had, at one
time, only limited real-world application and thereby are not signi icant
for appreciating the tolerant nature of the Islamic tradition and history
today. Others suggest that these rules were possible because of the
inherent intolerance of the Islamic tradition of other faith traditions.
Both arguments are not without their justi ications. The former view
inds support in historical records that illustrate the important role nonMuslims played in Muslim-ruled lands, whether economically, politically,
or otherwise. The second view is bolstered by historical incidents of
persecution, premodern rules that discriminated on religious grounds,
and reports of human rights watch groups that detail incidents of
persecution (both of icial and unof icial) against non-Muslim citizens
of Muslim states today. These two perspectives are pitted against one
another in both the scholarly and popular arenas of debate and dialogue.
Furthermore, a mere cursory review of popular books written on the
subject reveals how tolerance provides the analytic frame for the
debate. For those inclined to the view of Islam as tolerant and peaceloving, the following are noteworthy:
Khaled Abou El Fadl, The Place of Tolerance in Islam (Beacon Press,
).
M. Fethullah Glen, Toward a Global Civilization of Love and Tolerance
(The Light, Inc.,
).
For those who consider Islam an intolerant faith, Robert Spencer has two
contributions of special note:
Religion of Peace? Why Christianity Is and Islam Isnt (Regnery Press,
).
The Truth about Muhammad: Founder of the Worlds Most Intolerant
Religion (Regnery Press,
).
This study suggests that the frame of tolerance does little to explain the
intelligibility of the dhimm rules. The weakness of the tolerance frame
is revealed once we consider how tolerance often hides the underlying
regulatory features of governance that spark the need to discuss
tolerance in the irst place.
De initions of tolerance vary, and this is not the place for a sustained
analysis of the vast literature on the issue. However, Leslie Greens
account oers us a useful starting point for our analysis: As a distinctive
moral and political ideal, tolerance has a particular structure: it involves
the notion that an activity is wrong or to be disapproved, together with
the idea that one has moral reasons for not acting on that disapproval in
certain ways. Tolerance is neither acceptance nor merely indierence.
It implies not simply allowing people to live peacefully with their
dierences, but instead a disapproval by some of the di erences of
others.
Importantly, tolerance is meaningful in a context of power relations,
such that being tolerant is at once to be disdainful of di erence while
also having the power and authority to grant the freedom to others to be
dierent. Bernard Williams, for instance, remarks that we may think of
toleration as an attitude that a more powerful group, or a majority, may
have (or may fail to have) toward a less powerful group or a minority.
Likewise D. Raphael states: Toleration is the practice of deliberately
allowing or permitting a thing of which one disapproves. One can
intelligibly speak of tolerating, i.e., of allowing or permitting only if one is
in a position to disallow. You must have the power to forbid or prevent, if
you are to be in a position to permit.
Tolerance is employed at levels formal and informal, private and public.
On the small, private scale, tolerance may be witnessed in the context of a
Leslie Green, Pluralism, Social Con lict, and Tolerance, in Pluralism and Law, ed. A.
Soetman (The Hague: Kluwer Academic Publishers,
), , .
Bernard Williams, Tolerating the Intolerable, in The Politics of Toleration:
Tolerance and Intolerance in Modern Life, ed. Susan Mendus (Edinburgh: Edinburgh
University Press,
), , .
D.D. Raphael, The intolerable, in Justifying Toleration: Conceptual and Historical
Perspectives (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
),
,
.
Introduction
religious family contending with the wayward son who has left the familys
faith tradition yet nonetheless welcoming him to family gatherings. On
a large, public scale (which is the main focus of this study), tolerance is
evident in the way public authorities use their legally proscribed powers
to contend with the extent and scope to which minority cultural and
religious practices can be accommodated. The law is not the only way
in which public authorities manifest tolerance, but it is a common one,
as suggested by various studies on tolerance that are concerned with
what sorts of laws should or should not exist to regulate di erence in
society. As Williams remarks, discussions of tolerance have often been
discussions of what laws should existin particular, laws permitting
or forbidding various kinds of religious practiceand the laws have
been determined by the attitudes of the more powerful group. When
tolerance is understood as a mask for governing diverse societies, we ind
that minority perspectives are not necessarily condemned, banned, or
otherwise excluded. Room may be made for minority group members to
act in accordance with their traditions. The scope of that room, however,
will be de ined (and restricted) in terms of the law in accordance with
majoritarian attitudes about the public sphere, the public good, and the
polity as a whole.
When the law is viewed in this fashionas an instrument that can be
deployed by some over and against otherswe cannot fail to recognize
that the language of tolerance, when used concomitantly with legal
doctrines associated with governance and regulation, operates as a
cover that hides the operation of power on the bodies of minorities. For
Wendy Brown, who critiques tolerance discourses in the liberal state,
the language of tolerance masks the role of the state in reproducing
the dominance of certain groups and norms. This is not to deny that
tolerance is an important value; it certainly has a place in contemporary
political discourse. But that should not allow us to forgo critiquing
the assumptions that underlie how polities draw the line between the
tolerable and the intolerable. Rainer Forst perspicaciously points out
that we must be suspicious of the way the limits of toleration have been
and are drawn between the tolerant and the intolerant/intolerable. One
Wendy Brown, Regulating Aversion: Tolerance in the Age of Identity and Empire
(Princeton: Princeton University Press,
), .
See Chapter for recent examples of court decisions, legislation, and constitutional
enactments.
Williams, Tolerating the Intolerable, .
Brown, Regulating Aversion, .
For both a critique of liberal individualist conceptions of tolerance, and a persuasive
argument for a group-based approach to tolerance, see Adam B. Seligman, Tolerance,
Tradition, and Modernity, Cardozo Law Review , no. (
):
.
always needs to ask who draws those limits, against whom, on the basis of
what reasons, and what motives are in play. To dress the dhimm rules
with the vocabulary of tolerance or intolerance masks their contribution
to a discourse of Shara as a mode of regulating a polity. Consequently,
this study draws upon the critiques of tolerance to o er an initial point of
departure in the study of the dhimm rules, namely to show how and why
the dhimm rules are best understood as symptomatic of the challenge
that arises when governing diverse societies.
THEME B: SH A R A A S RULE OF L AW
To describe Shara as a mode of regulating a polity is to imagine a
legal culture in which the law and the institutions of governance are
distinguishable and yet aligned in an ongoing enterprise of regulation
and management. Shara is more than legal doctrines ( iqh) or
interpretive activity (ijtihd), for instance; it is more than the work of
jurists operating outside the realm of governance and politics. Rather, as
posited herein, Shara oers a discursive site about the requirements of
justice as understood by premodern jurists within a legal, historical, and
political context, whether real or imagined. To capture this relationship
between law and governance, this study proposes that Shara is better
appreciated if understood as Rule of Law. To advance the view of Shara
as Rule of Law requires building upon and, to some extent, departing
from other approaches to the characterization of Shara. It also requires
explaining how Rule of Law is being used in this study and why it
oers an important contribution to the study of Shara generally, and
to an understanding of the dhimm rules in particular. This section will
introduce how Shara as Rule of Law oers an important vantage point
for conceptual and theoretical inquiries into Shara, and will address
how and why Rule of Law is being used in this study to characterize
Shara. A more developed and extensive analysis of these two issues is
provided in Chapter .
):
Introduction
law of God. Beyond these initial starting points, debate arises over
how to give further speci ication to the term. To introduce Shara as Rule
of Law, an analysis of two distinct but related approaches to Shara will
suf ice. The irst approach focuses on the distinction between Shara and
iqh, and the second approach focuses on the juristic class (as opposed to
the ruling regime) and their legal literature as the primary, if not sole,
source of material concerning and de ining the Shara.
The irst approach is re lected in the work of contemporary scholars
of Islamic law who de ine Shara in part by distinguishing it from iqh,
which are the doctrinal traditions developed by jurists over centuries.
They hold that
Gods law as an abstraction is called the Sharah (literally, the way), while
the concrete understanding and implementation of this Will is called iqh
(literally, the understanding) . . . The conceptual distinction between
Sharah and iqh was the product of a recognition of the inevitable failures of human eorts at understanding the purposes or intentions of
God. Human beings, the jurists insisted, simply do not possess the ability
to encompass the wisdom of God. Consequently, every understanding or
implementation of Gods Will is necessarily imperfect because . . . perfection belongs only to God.
10
Introduction
11
insist on their respective views and claim to be justi ied in doing so;
but to resolve the dispute, the parties must resort to a legal process,
namely adjudication. According to al-Juwayn, if they submit their
case to a judge or q, the judges decision, based on his own analysis,
is binding on both parties. The qs decision is authoritative not
because it accords with one speci ic legal rule or another; rather,
it is authoritative because of the imperium tied to his institutional
position. Abou El Fadl, however, disagrees with al-Juwayn and
suggests that in the hypothetical above, if the judge decides in favor of
the husband, the wife can and should resist as a form of conscientious
objection and thereby enjoy the protections a orded to her by the law
of rebellion in Islam (akm al-bught).
Where he writes about this hypothetical, Abou El Fadl is
principally interested in distinguishing the law of God from human
determinations of that law, and thereby preserving the moral standing
of the individual to assert his or her convictions before God without
the imposition of external agents. However, his argument about
rebellion betrays a tendency to view Islamic law as a jurists law that
speaks to the authority of the individual against all others. A Rule of
Law perspective on Abou El Fadls criticism of al-Juwayn and support
for the wife as conscientious objector might raise the following
observations and questions.
For instance, the fact that the husband and wife would go to a court at all
presumes that the parties live in an organized society where the court
holds some degree of jurisdiction and dominion and is answerable to the
governing authorities under which it operates. By submitting their case
to the judge, do the parties expressly or impliedly consent to the courts
jurisdiction?
By agreeing to be members of a political society governed by the Shara,
do the husband and wife enter into a social contract with each other (and
Ab al-Mal al-Juwayn, Kitb al-Ijtihd min Kitb al-Talkh (Damascus: Dr alQalam,
), .
Khaled Abou El Fadl, The Authoritative and Authoritarian in Islamic Discourses: A
Contemporary Case Study, rd ed. (Alexandria, Virginia: al-Saadawi Publications,
),
n. . He holds a similar position concerning a second hypothetical al-Juwayn posed.
See Abou El Fadl, Speaking in Gods Name, .
The force of Abou El Fadls argument is severely undercut if one considers a slight
variation on the same hypothetical. Suppose the judge decided in favor of the wife. Abou
El Fadls logic would suggest that the husband could also ignore the judicial outcome and
claim the protections of the law as a conscientious objector. Abou El Fadls logic would
eectively give some, though perhaps not full, legal protection to the husband if subsequently charged with rape. The odiousness of this particular outcome, which in fairness
Abou El Fadl does not address, o ers an important incentive to explore why the Rule of
Law perspective oers an important lens through which to view doctrinal treatises such
as the one by al-Juwayn.
12
Introduction
others in the polity) to forgo certain freedoms (like rebellion in the event
of an unfavorable court decision) so that they may maximize their enjoyment of other freedoms?
If the husband and wife undertake certain obligations and responsibilities to participate in organized political society, does it make sense to
suggest (without further consideration) that the wife in the above hypothetical can and should rebel?
Shara as Rule of Law suggests that to allow the wife to rebel in this
case implicates more than just simply whether the wife-jurist holds that
a divorce pronounced in anger is valid or not. The substantive doctrine
is certainly part of the calculus, but so too are the role and authority of
institutions and the political commitments individuals make (or are
presumed to make) to live in society organized pursuant to a law that
is enforced by of icials holding certain of ices. Shara as Rule of Law
reminds us that substantive doctrine is only one part of the calculus,
and perhaps not always the most important part. Furthermore and
perhaps most importantly, Shara as Rule of Law asks us to consider the
possibility that, when oering this hypothetical, al-Juwayn resolved the
con lict in light of the above considerations.
These questions and considerations illustrate that behind the
articulation of a legal doctrine lies a host of background assumptions
that link the Sharas doctrines to the institutional and political
framework within which those rules were intelligible. To view Shara as
Rule of Law forces a reconsideration of the near-monopoly of authority
granted to premodern jurists and their literary corpus in de ining
the content and intelligibility of Shara. Shara as Rule of Law is a
reminder to remain ever cognizant of the absences in the evidentiary
record, and the implication those absences may have on our ability to
re lect and represent Shara in a robust fashion. In particular, Shara
as Rule of Law requires that we acknowledge the multiple sites of
authority that animated and in luenced juristic writings about Islamic
legal doctrines, and which thereby constituted Shara as a whole, such
as the governing and institutional setting that animated the jurists
legal culture (whether real or imagined). Together, these constitutive
features contributed to the conceptual heft of Shara as a discursive
site for contestations about justice, amid competing authorities, not
all of which would necessarily lead to the same result. Shara as Rule
of Law is oered herein as a technical term of art that captures the
complex ways that law, society, and politics may have interacted to
discipline the way Muslim jurists interpreted and espoused the law
in light of a more general purpose of organizing life under an Islamic
system of governance.
13
14
Introduction
15
See, for example, Fareed Zakaria, The Rise of Illiberal Democracy, Foreign Affairs
(
): ; Charles E. Tucker, Jr, Cabbages and Kings: Bridging the Gap for More
Eective Capacity-Building, University of Pennsylvania Journal of International Law
(
): .
John K.M. Ohnesorge, The Rule of Law, Annual Review of Law and Social Science
(
): ,
.
16
Introduction
17
18
Introduction
vision (and the rules it informs) loses its intelligibility as shifts across
time challenge earlier presumptions of what once constituted the good
life or the best means to achieve it.
One presumption or condition underlying the premodern dhimm
rules that will be identi ied, named, and foregrounded is the relationship
between legal doctrine and argument on the one hand, and the underlying
governing enterprise that set a political backdrop to the premodern
juristic imagination on the other hand. Disrupting this presumption is the
key task of the third theme concerning the dhimm rules. The shape and
form that the claim space of Shara can take is in part determined by the
political and institutional order of which it is a part. In fact, in some cases,
the intelligibility of a particular legal doctrine may be deeply dependent
upon the assumed institutional and political environment in which that
rule was or will be applied or otherwise made manifest. Drawing upon
what some have called the institutional turn in legal philosophy,
this study will show that the intelligibility of legal doctrines such as the
dhimm rules is intimately linked to the enterprise of governance in a
mutually supportive and constitutive fashion.
That the conceptual contribution of Rule of Law generally, and Shara
as Rule of Law speci ically, should suggest a substantive, mutually
constitutive relationship between law and governance should not be
surprising. For instance, in his report to the Security Council, then-UN
Secretary-General, Ko i Annan, stated that Rule of Law:
refers to a principle of governance in which all persons, institutions and
entities, public and private, including the State itself, are accountable to
laws that are publicly promulgated, equally enforced and independently
adjudicated, and which are consistent with international human rights
norms and standards. It requires, as well, measures to ensure adherence
to the principles of supremacy of law, equality before the law, accountability to the law, fairness in the application of the law, separation of powers,
19
participation in decision-making, legal certainty, avoidance of arbitrariness and procedural and legal transparency.
United Nations Security Council, The Rule of Law and Transitional Justice in Con lict
and Post-con lict Societies: Report of the Secretary-General, S/
/
(New York: August
,
), para. (emphasis added).
US Agency for International Development (USAID), Guide to Rule of Law Analysis:
The Rule of Law Strategic Framework; A Guide for USAID Democracy and Governance
Of icers (Washington D.C.: USAID,
), (emphasis added). The report can be accessed
at: <http://www.usaid.gov/our_work/democracy_and_governance/publications/pdfs/
ROL_Strategic_Framework_Jan_FINAL.pdf> (accessed May ,
).
Tully, Public Philosophy, : .
20
Introduction
21
22
Introduction
23
. The problem identi ied here, though, is when upholding majoritarian interests
comes at the cost of minority claimants, whose claims might be viewed as challenges or
threats to the common good, social well-being, and so on.
24
Introduction
Europe and the United States justify limits on when, where, and how the
covered Muslim woman can cover or veil. Certainly the political systems
assumed by and underlying Shara as Rule of Law and contemporary
liberal constitutional states are vastly di erent. Ironically, though,
despite the dierence between their speci ic doctrines, legal systems,
and governing enterprises, the dynamics of governing amidst diversity
unite both systems in their respective hegemonic potential.
A N OV ERV IEW
The dhimm rules provide the vehicle for both exploring the analytic
purchase of considering Shara as Rule of Law, and uncovering
the hegemonic potential that lies at the intersection of the law and
the enterprise of governance when minorities make claims for
accommodation and inclusion. Rule of Law is oered as an alternative
to the all-too-common reliance on tolerance to study and characterize
the dhimm rules. As will be shown in Part I of this study, the dhimm rules
represent a premodern juristic vision of an imperial Islamic polity in
which governance through conquest and empire necessarily implied the
existence of non-Muslims who came under Muslim rule. Whether or not
jurists operated outside of and separate from the realm of government,
they nonetheless imagined and developed a jurisprudence that was itself
in luenced and informed by the demands of an enterprise of governance
that faced the challenge of governing amidst diversity.
Furthermore, the dhimm rules oer a departure point for appreciating
the historical dimension to the intelligibility of norms arising from
within a Rule of Law claim space. As the backdrop of governance has
changedshifting from an imperial model to a modern state model
the intelligibility of the dhimm rules has shifted as well. With the shifts
in underlying modes of governance, the dhimm rules no longer bear the
same intelligibility they once had. Although they often remain today part
of an informal discourse about identity, and in very limited cases, part
of formal legal regimes, the dhimm rules have since lost their original
intelligibility. The challenge today is to understand the implications on
the intelligibility of the dhimm rules when the imperial assumptions
underlying them give way to the realities of contemporary modes of
governance.
Perhaps one of the more provocative theses of this study is that the
dhimm rules are hardly unique in the hegemonic dynamic that they
reveal about the law, especially in cases where minorities make claims
upon and against the enterprise of governance. As will be explored
An overview
25
26
Introduction
Mahmoud Ayoub, Dhimmah in Qurn and Hadth, Arab Studies Quarterly , no.
(
):
; idem, The Islamic Context of MuslimChristian Relations, in Conversion
and Continuity: Indigenous Christian Communities in Islamic Lands, Eighth to Eighteenth
Centuries, eds Michael Gervers and Ramzi Jibran Bikhazi (Toronto: Ponti ical Institute of
Mediaeval Studies,
),
,
.
An overview
27
How could Islam claim to be a universal faith for all of humanity if,
under the Shara, non-Muslims were permitted to practice their
own faith traditions?
Were non-Muslims given a grant of autonomy that put them outside
the Islamic framework, despite living under Muslim sovereign rule?
If so, how much autonomy should be granted to them before the
sovereign authority of the ruling regime would be threatened?
If non-Muslims could have their own laws applied to them, would those
laws be applied through the general courts that applied Sharabased norms?
If so, did that mean other religious traditions were equally as
authoritative as Shara-based norms?
If so, how could that be reconciled with an underlying universalist
Islamic ethos that framed and otherwise legitimated various modes
of government action by reference to the application of Shara?
These are just some of the questions that animated premodern Muslim
jurists and which this study tracks for the purpose of illuminating the
conditions that made such questions intelligible in the irst place.
Part II transitions from the premodern period to the modern one by
addressing whether and to what extent the minority claimant in both
Muslim-majority states and liberal democratic ones eerily and ironically
suers the hegemony of the law for reasons that echo the rationale
of the dhimm rules of the premodern era. To facilitate the transition,
Chapter oers an extended inquiry into the conditions of intelligibility
of the premodern claim space of Shara, and examines the implication of
changes in those conditions on the ongoing intelligibility of premodern
Shara-based norms in the Rule of Law claim space of modern states.
By inductively drawing upon key doctrinal, education, and institutional
features of premodern Islamic legal history, Chapter gives content to the
idea of Shara as Rule of Law and thereby outlines its analytic purchase
when used to frame the dhimm rule in the premodern and modern
periods. Speci ically, Chapter explores premodern notions of authority,
epistemology, and institutional design to give content to a concept of
Chapter proceeds with the caveat that what we mean by Rule of Law, what Shara
as Rule of Law signi ies, and what premodern Muslim jurists had in mind when developing legal doctrines are distinct but related questions. For a recent contribution to the
ongoing debates about the ambiguity of Rule of Law as a phrase and ield of inquiry,
as well as the need to think about Rule of Law in comparative perspective (with special reference to the Islamic legal perspective), see Randy Peerenboom, The Future of
Rule of Law: Challenges and Prospects for the Field, Hague Journal of the Rule of Law
(
): . For a general overview of the meaning of Rule of Law and the implications of dierent approaches to de ining this concept, see Tamanaha, On the Rule
of Law.
28
Introduction
Shara as Rule of Law that, as suggested herein, identi ies the mutually
constitutive relationship between the law and enterprise of governance.
The features examined are meant to be illustrative and not exclusive. In
the aggregate, they help paint a picture of the boundaries that delimited
the premodern claim space of Shara, and thereby conditioned the
intelligibility of legal doctrines, such as the dhimm rules.
Chapter explores whether and to what extent the development of the
modern state in Muslim lands has altered the boundaries of the states
claim space of Rule of Law, and the implications of those changes on the
intelligibility of premodern Islamic legal rules, such as the dhimm rules,
in modern contexts. Muslim-majority countries have been criticized on
various grounds for invoking the dhimm rules or contributing to a culture
of religious intolerance that in some fashion draws upon the premodern
Islamic tradition. Human rights advocacy groups launch and justify their
critiques by relying on international human rights treaties and declarations
that uphold religious freedom and the right to be free from religious
discrimination. Wealthy nations impose sanctions or inancial constraints
on countries that violate such human rights norms. Yet, such strategies have
not been entirely successful. Leaders of Muslim states and Islamist groups
accuse human rights activists of a type of hegemony and colonialism that
has less to do with the merit of human rights than with the power of certain
groups to enforce their own particular moral vision. Indeed, some of the
most poignant examples that fuel the cultural relativists come from the
Muslim world and the doctrines so often associated with Shara.
To contend with the dhimm rules as they are invoked in contemporary
contexts suggests that any Rule of Law analysis will necessarily have
a historical component. Using the dhimm rules as a mechanism for
comparing premodern and modern conditions of intelligibility, Chapter
explores whether and how historical shifts in underlying sovereign
modelsnamely the shift from the imperial model, to the colonial model,
to the modern state in an international system of equally sovereign
statescalls for deliberation not only about the intelligibility of the
premodern dhimm rules, but also about Shara as Rule of Law across
historical periods. A review of two case studies from the countries of
Saudi Arabia and Malaysia will reveal that what made Islamic legal
doctrines intelligible in the premodern world, arguably, inhibits them
Elisabeth Reichert, Human Rights: An Examination of Universalism and Cultural
Relativism, Journal of Comparative Social Welfare , no. (
): ; Catherine E.
Polisi, Universal Rights and Cultural Relativism: Hinduism and Islam Deconstructed,
World Affairs
, no. (
): ; Abdullahi Ahmed An-Naim, Religious Minorities
under Islamic Law and the Limits of Cultural Relativism, Human Rights Quarterly , no.
(
): .
An overview
29
30
Introduction
1
Dhimms, Shara, and Empire
34
Menocal does not ignore the fact that tensions existed in the Andalusian
period. But those tensions were not always between religious groups.
Rather, as she notes, political friction existed among the Muslim ruling
elites, thereby rendering minority groups important political allies to
dierent elite factions among the Muslim populace.
Notably, Menocals work contributes to an ongoing debate within
Andalusian studies, namely whether the climate of tolerance existed,
or whether describing that period in terms of tolerance adopts a toopresentist perspective on any reading of the past. As Anna Akasoy
reminds, [p]opular attitudes still reveal a simplistic general picture, but
Mark Cohen, Medieval Jewry in the World of Islam, in The Oxford Handbook of Jewish
Studies, ed. Martin Goodman (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
),
; Roger M.
Savory, Relations between the Safavid State and its Non-Muslim Minorities, Islam and
ChristianMuslim Relations , no. (October
):
.
Maria Rosa Menocal, The Ornament of the World! How Muslim, Jews, and Christians
Created a Culture of Tolerance in Medieval Spain (Boston: Little, Brown and Company,
), .
36
debates among historians are now much more nuanced. That nuanced
historical reading reveals serious concerns about the available sources,
and the kinds of historical data that can be gleaned from them, keeping in
mind the historical Andalusian context, as opposed to any present context
or set of values. For Akasoy, an important lesson to be gained from the
recent ink spilled on Islamic Spain is how that history is instrumentalized
for contemporary, ideological purposes. She concludes: one lesson to be
learned not so much from history . . . but from the way it is presented is
just how much negotiating the past is part of negotiating the present.
The view that al-Andalus oers today a model for peace and harmony
ignores the fact that Muslim jurists writing in that period preserved
the dhimm rules. For example, even the famous philosopher Ibn Rushd
(Averroes), who was also a famous jurist, wrote about the dhimm rules
in his well-known treatise Bidyat al-Mujtahid wa Nihyat al-Muqtaid.
In other words, the historical argument concerning periods of peace and
harmony does little to address why and to what e ect the dhimm legal
doctrines were developed, taught, and perpetuated in premodern legal
sources during historical periods in which peace and tolerance arguably
prevailed.
Those adopting the myth of harmony do not ignore the dhimm rules.
They too are concerned about the facially discriminatory implications of
such rules. One approach they adopt regarding the rules is to deny that
the facially discriminatory legal treatment was historically signi icant
or was meant to disparage those of dierent religious traditions. For
example, some argue that the jizya tax was merely an administrative
matter used to organize society. Jizya was a non-Muslim tax, they argue,
whereas the zakt was the Muslim tax. Both groups paid taxes and,
as such, the jizya should not be considered a discriminatory tax that
speaks to an underlying Muslim intolerance of the religious Other.
Anna Akasoy, Convivencia and its Discontents: Interfaith Life in al-Andalus,
International Journal of Middle East Studies (
):
,
.
Akasoy, Convivencia and its Discontents,
.
Ibn Rushd al-a d, Bidyat al-Mujtahid wa Nihyat al-Muqtaid, eds Al Muawwa
and dil Abd al-Mawjd (Beirut: Dr al-Kutub al-Ilmiyya,
).
Abdelwahab Boudhiba, The Protection of Minorities, in The Different Aspects
of Islamic Culture: The Individual and Society in Islam, eds A. Boudhiba and M. Marf
al-Dawlib (Paris: UNESCO,
),
,
. See also, Ghazi Salahuddin Atabani,
Islamic Sharah and the Status of Non-Muslims, in Religion, Law and Society: A Christian
Muslim Dialogue (Geneva: WCC Publications,
), , who writes that religious classi ications in Islam are for making distinctions in the hereafter, but not in worldly terms.
He writes that the dhimm concept is not one of disparagement, but rather allowed historical minority communities to maintain the distinctiveness they needed to survive. In
other words, it was a means of preserving religious pluralism, not squashing it. Likewise,
see also Fazlur Rahman, Non-Muslim Minorities in an Islamic State, Journal Institute of
Muslim Minority Affairs (
): , , who writes that the jizya was a tax in lieu of
38
, who
translates an essay in which the dhimm is abused.
Haggai Ben-Shammai, Jew Hatred in the Islamic Tradition and the Koranic Exegesis,
in Antisemitism Through the Ages, ed. Shmuel Almog (Oxford: Pergamon Press,
), .
The same could be said about the analysis of the works above, which contribute to
the myth of harmony. But like Yeors work, the works of those above also contribute a
particular strain of argument within the ield of dhimm studies that cannot be ignored,
and indeed oer a signi icant historiographic contribution to the dhimm studies ield.
Robert Irwin, Book Reviews: Islam and Dhimmitude: Where Civilizations Collide,
Middle Eastern Studies , no. (
):
; Paul Fenton, Book Review: Islam and
Dhimmitude, Midstream , no. (
): ; Johann Hari, Amid all this panic, we
must remember one simple factMuslims are not all the same, The Independent, August
,
, .
Scholarly and not-so-scholarly sources on both sides of the tolerance debate are
many. See for instance, Robert Spencer, ed., The Myth of Islamic Tolerance: How Islamic
Law Treats Non-Muslims (New York: Prometheus Books,
); idem, The Truth about
Muhammad: Founder of the Worlds Most Intolerant Religion (Washington D.C.: Regnery
Publishing, Inc.,
); idem, Islam Unveiled: Disturbing Questions about the Worlds FastestGrowing Faith (San Francisco: Encounter Books,
),
; Aaron Tyler, Islam, the West
and Tolerance: Conceiving Coexistence (New York: Palgrave MacMillan,
); Khaled Abou
El Fadl, The Place of Tolerance in Islam (Boston: Beacon Press,
); Yohanan Friedmann,
Tolerance and Coercion in Islam (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
).
40
refers to the work of Bat Yeor on the dhimm under Islamic law, and the
way she and her work on the dhimm are marginalized and demonized.
He writes:
From Pakistan to Britain, from Nigeria to France, writers who express skepticism about the teachings or record of Islam risk violent death. Bat Yeor is
a very great scholar: original, authoritative, lucid . . . Her native language is
French, but her French publisher timidly let her book go out of print, despite
scholarly accolades and strong sales. When she spoke at Georgetown, irate
Muslim students shouted her down, unreprimanded by their university, and
the same thing happened to her at the University of London and at Brown.
Frum is less interested in the contents of Yeors actual scholarship. Yet she
and her scholarship are made to represent a value of truth and freedom, in
opposition to an Islamic intolerance and distortion. He concludes: under
the rules of Western civilization, fair and truthful criticism is not only
permissible: It is a duty. Yeors work informs not only debates about
Islam and tolerance, but also domestic US debates about truth on the one
hand, and the presumed inability of Muslims to be honest dealers on the
other hand. Even more, in
, the Center for Security Policy issued a
report, Sharah: The Threat to America, which relied in part upon Yeors
work to characterize Shara as the pre-eminent totalitarian threat of our
time. Members of the team that authored the report were thereafter
involved in a nationwide campaign to promote state legislation to
outright ban Shara. Furthermore, in his nearly ,
-page treatise,
Oslo terrorist bomber Anders Breivik justi ies his anger at European
multiculturalism policies and his antagonism against Islam in part by
citing extensively the work of Bat Yeor, prompting some to question
whether Yeor (and others who contribute to the polemics on Islam and
intolerance) bear some (moral) responsibility for Breiviks actions. So
while some might avoid referring to Yeors work, the themes she writes
about nonetheless contribute to an ongoing debate about Islam, human
rights, tolerance, and religious freedom. For that reason, her analysis
David Frum, Whats Right, National Review , no. (December ,
): .
Frum, Whats Right, .
Shariah: The Threat to America, an Exercise in Competitive Analysis, report of Team
BII (Washington D.C.: Center for Security Policy,
) <http://shariahthethreat.
org/wp-content/uploads/
/ /Shariah-The-Threat-to-America-Team-B-ReportWeb.pdf> (accessed October ,
).
For a review of the legislative bans and the security context that informed them,
see Anver Emon, Banning Shara, The Immanent Frame <http://blogs.ssrc.org/
tif/
/ / /banning-sharia/> (accessed October ,
).
Colby Cosh, The Making of a Monster, Macleans
, no. (August ,
): ;
Jim Lobe, Terror in Oslo, Washington Report on Middle East Affairs (SeptemberOctober
): .
42
Al-Qattan positions her article in part against a historiography that held that in the
Ottoman regime, dierent non-Muslim religious groups were organized into autonomous communities (millet) with their own judges to handle private matters governed by
their religious laws. Recent scholarship has suggested, though, that a centralized millet
system did not in fact materialize until the late Ottoman period. Rather, in the empires
eorts to deal with European powers and assure them of fair treatment of religious
minorities in the empire, the foreign of ice often employed the term millet to assure its
European neighbors that the minorities were respected and enjoyed autonomy over their
own a airs. Benjamin Braude, Foundation Myths of the Millet System, in Christians and
Jews in the Ottoman Empire: The Functioning of a Plural Society, eds Benjamin Braude and
Bernard Lewis, vols (New York: Holmes & Meier Publishers,
), : , ; idem,
The Strange History of the Millet System, in The Great OttomanTurkish Civilization, ed.
Kemal Cicek, vols (Ankara: Yeni Turkiye,
), :
.
Al-Qattan, Dhimmis in the Muslim Court,
.
Although the absence of dhimm court records leaves a gap in understanding what
the communal courts were doing, existing records reveal rabbinical directives forbidding Jews from using the Mahkama, thus implicitly suggesting that Jews may have been
using the Ottoman courts. Al-Qattan, Dhimmis in the Muslim Court,
. See also, Bert F.
Breiner, Shara and Religious Pluralism, in Religion, Law and Society: A ChristianMuslim
Discussion, ed. Tarek Mitri (Geneva: WCC Publications,
), ; Joseph R. Hacker,
Jewish Autonomy in the Ottoman Empire: Its Scope and Limits. Jewish Courts from the
Sixteenth to the Eighteenth Centuries, in The Jews of the Ottoman Empire, ed. Avigdor
Levy (Princeton: Darwin Press,
),
,
; Avigdor Levy, Introduction, in The
Jews of the Ottoman Empire, ed. Avigdor Levy (Princeton: Darwin Press,
), , .
Al-Qattan, Dhimmis in the Muslim Court,
.
Al-Qattan, Dhimmis in the Muslim Court,
.
Al-Qattan, Dhimmis in the Muslim Court,
. See also, Ronald C. Jennings, Zimmis
(Non-Muslims) in Early th Century Ottoman Judicial Records: The Shara Court of
Anatolian Kayseri, in Studies in Ottoman Social History in the Sixteenth and Seventeenth
Centuries: Women, Zimmis, and Shara Courts in Kayseri, Cyprus and Trabzon (Istanbul:
The Isis Press,
),
.
44
; Kemal Cicek, A
Quest for Justice in a Mixed Society: The Turks and the Greek Cypriots Before the Shara
Courts of Nicosia, in The Great OttomanTurkish Civilization, ed. Kemal Cicek, vols
(Ankara: Yeni Turkiye,
), :
.
46
47
48
Medina and began looking beyond its borders to expand the in luence
of the Muslim polity. Ultimately, he took control of Mecca itself in
CE,
and thereafter expanded his and the Muslim politys in luence across the
Arabian Peninsula.
The early history of Medina oers three examples of the cleansing
model, which Muammad used to govern amidst diversity. The three
examples concern the three Jewish tribes in Medina. These three Jewish
tribesthe Ban Nar, Bn Quraya, and Bn Qaynuqwere
deemed in an original founding document, the wathqat al-Madna,
to be part of the new polity founded by Muammad in Medina. That
document, often called the Constitution of Medina, set out the relations
between the various tribes in Medina and posited the Prophet as the
leader of the community with the authority to resolve and arbitrate
con licts. Whether the Constitution of Medina was a single document
or a collection of documents is debated by historians and is not central
to the analysis herein. Nonetheless, it seems from historical records that
Muammad and the Jewish tribes had treaties that delineated the latters
membership in the Medinan polity. Debate rages whether the Jewish
tribes were considered part of the new umma (nation) or an umma of
their own living alongside the new Muslim one.
At the conclusion of each battle with the Meccan troops, Muammad
had to contend with a Jewish tribe that was claimed to have violated
its treaty with Muammad. Each crisis with the Jewish tribes occurred
amidst existential concerns about the future of the Muslim polity in
Medina. In other words, the harsh treatment of the Jewish tribes occurred
in the context of pressing concerns about security and military threats
from external forces. Muammad had to govern a Medinan polity marked
by considerable diversity at a time of grave concerns about security and
war.
In these instances of cleansing, Muammad exercised what
contemporary political theorists along the lines of Carl Schmitt might call
the sovereign exception. In his recent development of Schmitts theory,
On the reliability of historical sources on the existence of Muammads treaties
with the Jews, see Michael Lecker, Did Muammad Conclude Treaties with the Jewish
Tribes Nar, Quraya, and Qaynuq? in Dhimmis and Others: Jews and Christians and
the World of Classical Islam, eds Uri Rubin and David Wasserstein (Tel Aviv: Eisenbrauns,
), . Notably, Lecker disputes whether the Jewish tribes were part of the Umma
treaty, in contrast to what is noted above. For the purpose of this analysis, the speci ic
point about the Jewish tribes inclusion in the wathqa is not at issue. For an overview of
disputes about the document, its authenticity, and how di erent versions of the document contribute to considerable debates about the inclusion of the Jewish tribes in the
Muslim polity, see Anver M. Emon, Re lections on the Constitution of Medina: An Essay
on Methodology and Ideology in Islamic Legal History, UCLA Journal of Islamic and Near
Eastern Law , no. (Fall/Winter
):
.
49
Paul Kahn recalls that the sovereign exception presumes a rule or norm
that operates and prevails under ordinary circumstances. The exception
is only meaningful as an exception when circumstances dictate, such as
the circumstances of emergency. The norm, Schmitt often says, requires
ordinary circumstances for its operation; the exception occupies those
circumstances that are lessor morethan ordinary. The quality of the
exception is always one of self-limitation: the exception cannot become
normal. The angst arising from Schmitts sovereign exception is
that such exceptional behavior will be rendered as normal and even
normative. Indeed, Kahn notes: the nature of norms is such that the
exception is always subject to normalization: law will seek to extend to
the exceptional decision. Viewing Muammads actions against the
Jewish tribes as a type of sovereign exception raises concerns about the
implication of this early history on the development of an Islamic ethos
toward the religious Other. It is therefore important, from a Rule of Law
perspective, to juxtapose this early historical record with later historical
developments and the later-developed dhimm doctrines to examine
the relationship between the evolving conditions of the enterprise of
governance and what ultimately became the legal norms governing
religious minorities under premodern Islamic law.
In the case of the Jewish tribes, the threat they posed to the project of
the new polity was managed and regulated using the model of cleansing,
which can hardly be called pluralistic. Indeed it is the complete opposite
of pluralism. The application of that model was made e ective and
legitimate in retrospect by the forceful logic of legality and legal
processes. For instance, after the Medinan victory against the Meccans
at the irst battle, the Battle of Badr ( /
), the Prophet gathered the
Jewish tribe of Qaynuq and proclaimed to them: Oh Jewish people, be
wary that God may descend [upon you] something akin to the vengeance
that has befallen the Quraysh. Submit, for you know that I am a dispatched
prophet, who you shall ind in your books and who God has assigned to
you. The people of Qaynuq did not submit to the Prophets request,
but nonetheless assured him of their support: Oh Muammad, you see
that we are your people (qawmuka). Yet they also warned him that his
easy victory at Badr would not mean an easy victory against the Ban
Qaynuq: By God, if we were to wage war against you, you would learn
Paul Kahn, Political Theology: Four New Chapters on the Concept of Sovereignty (New
York: Columbia University Press,
), .
Kahn, Political Theology, .
Ibn Hishm, al-Sra al-Nabawiyya, eds Muaf al-Saq, Ibrhm al-Abyr and Abd
al-a Shalb (Beirut: Dr al-Marifa, n.d.), : .
Ibn Hishm, al-Sra al-Nabawiyya, : .
50
51
52
the Meccans to revise their planned attack on the city. The one area where
the citys forti ications were weak was near the quarter controlled by
the Ban Quraya. But as that tribe had a treaty with the Prophet that
they were reluctant to breach, they had to be strongly induced to forgo
that treaty and help the Meccans defeat Muammad. uyay b. Akhab,
the leader of the Ban Narwhich was banished after Uudwas
with the Meccans and undertook the challenge of convincing the Ban
Quraya to abandon Muammad and his people. At irst the leader of
the Ban Quraya, Kab b. Asad, refused to change his tribes allegiance:
I have made a covenant (hadtu) with Muammad and I am not one to
repudiate what is between me and him. After much heated discussion,
Kab agreed to abandon the treaty-based relationship with Muammad.
When the Prophet heard about the Ban Qurayas defection, he sent
representatives to con irm the rumor. When these representatives made
their inquiries to members of the Ban Quraya, they were met with
de iance: Who is the messenger of God? There is no covenant or contract
between us and Muammad. Consequently when the Battle of the
Trench was concluded and Muammad and his followers were victorious,
their attention turned to the Ban Quraya. Muammad ordered his
army to lay siege to the area of the city inhabited by the Ban Quraya.
After many weeks of suering the siege, the Ban Quraya opened
the gates to the quarter and submitted themselves to Muammads
judgment. Members of one of the Arab tribes that had converted to Islam,
the Ban Aws, asked the Prophet to show leniency to the Ban Quraya.
In response, the Prophet asked whether they would prefer that a leader
of the Ban Aws decide the fate of the Ban Quraya. In particular he
asked: Would you be satis ied, oh people of Aws, if someone from among
yourselves decided (an yakuma) [their fate]? Here, the term used to
refer to decision and resolution is derived from the trilateral root -km, which was used above to refer to the Prophets authority to settle the
con lict between the Muslims and the Jews of Ban Qaynuq. That root
forms the origin of words that deal with adjudication, arbitration, and
rulings.
Sad b. Mudh, chief of the Ban Aws, was in Medina recovering from a
wound he received in battle, and was convinced that he would succumb to
it in a matter of time. Sad was vested with the authority to decide the fate
of the Ban Quraya. His decision: the men would be executed, the women
and children would become captives, and their property apportioned to
),
53
the conquering forces. The men were indeed executed, and the captives
and property were divided among all those who participated in the siege
of the Ban Quraya. In the case of the Ban Quraya, the trappings of
legality exist in terms of a contract governing a particular relationship,
and an arbitral process meant to control for various interests.
The three cases above illustrate a particular model of governing
amidst diversity, namely the model of cleansing. In each case, though, the
highly exceptional acts taken against the Jewish tribes were considered
justi ied (and even normalized) in premodern Islamic literature because
highly complex and politically fraught relationships were regulated (and
even reduced) by reference to documents and processes that re lected the
language and authority of the law. The legal elements included references
to arbitral authority (ukm), treaties (ahd), and a juridi ication of
complex relationships to a matter of either compliance or breach. What
these terms imply about the early history of Muammads prophecy is not
transparent if one were merely to read the relevant texts in their original
Arabic or in translation. Indeed, while some might be inclined to ask about
the historical details of the Prophets arbitral of ice, the facticity of that
of ice is less relevant for this study than the way in which the language
describing the Prophets role draws upon the images of legality that later
become signi icant for Muslim jurists seeking to develop a legal order.
The Jewish tribes are said to have conspired with the Quraysh against
the Muslims; in doing so, they were held to have violated a treaty struck
with Muammad. The punishment they received, though harsh, was
retrospectively justi ied by reference to legal arguments arising from
contract-based principles.
Signi icant for the purpose of this study is how each of the three cases
above intermingle legality with a vision of a nascent polity under threat.
The cleansing model can certainly contribute to the homogeneity of
a polity. Homogeneity may be an important feature in the early stages
of a politys formation, especially when it also faces an uncertain
political future. In this case, the exceptionality of the cleansing model is
normalized and rendered intelligible by reference to the law, despite (or
perhaps because of) the otherwise highly fractious and at times volatile
Medinan polity struggling simply to survive. As Fred Donner indicates,
Muammad pursued a policy of consolidation that required him to
establish his authority in Medina and quell the threat posed by the
Quraysh. The three battles noted above gave him the chance to do just
that. Thus the success against the Meccans at Badr appears to
have strengthened Muammads hand enough to allow him to exile the
Lings, Muhammad,
54
B. Qaynuq, and the collapse of the Meccan siege of Medina at the battle
of the Trench led to a swift and ghastly reckoning for the B. Quray,
who had tried to help the Meccans during the siege. These three
incidents oered the necessary conditions for Muammad to bolster
his authority and to ensure the sheer existence of a nascent Medinan
polity whose future was at best uncertain and plagued by insecurity.
That existential boost no doubt came at a serious cost to the minorities
who once lived in that polity. Those costs, though, were retrospectively
deemed justi ied by reference to legal arguments of contract. Premodern
Muslim historians and jurists put the law and legal arguments in service
of the nascent enterprise of governing the Medinan polity. Consequently,
while historians often view this early history as a narrative of political
maneuvering and consolidation, this analysis reveals a legal dimension
to that story. The pursuit of a stable polity through cleansing was later
justi ied and even normalized in part by reference to instruments and
arguments of legality that reduced highly complex and existentially
fraught situations into a binary legal calculation.
55
terms with the Islamic state, in part because it controlled the main agricultural and market centers in the ijz, upon which the nomads depended.
56
proceeds from the township. Since the inhabitants of Khaybar knew the
lands and had experience cultivating them, they were in a better, more
experienced position than the Prophet and his followers to maximize the
lands productivity. The Prophet agreed to the arrangement on condition
that if he wanted them to abandon the lands, they had to do so. The people
of Khaybar agreed to the condition; thus they retained possession of the
land and could cultivate it, but the land itself became spoils of war to be
divided among the Muslims (knat khaybar fay bayna al-muslimn). The
example of Khaybar illustrates how property regimes involving leasing
and rent can provide a legal device to manage diversity in an era of
imperial expansion. The people of Khaybar retained possession of their
property, and were able to work the land as long as they contributed to
the ongoing inancial needs of an expanding empire by paying rents into
the imperial coer. The lease was terminable at will, thereby asserting
the new sovereigns ultimate control over the underlying land. The lease,
combined with the rent, represented the expanding authority of an imperial
sovereign as inancial support for the empires expansion policies.
The treaty/tax model was an alternative to the lease/rent model.
Used in the context of diplomatic relation-building, the treaty/tax model
established diplomatic relationships of peace and security between the
Prophets polity and outlying tribes who required assurance of their
own security from assault or conquest. For example, after the Prophets
conquest of Mecca, it became clear to neighboring tribes that he and
the Muslim polity had assured themselves considerable authority and
longevity in the Arabian Peninsula. Tribes that were worried about
their autonomy sent diplomatic delegations (wufd) to negotiate terms
of mutual recognition and acknowledgement with the Medinan polity.
As Hugh Kennedy writes, these diplomatic missions were more often
initiated by the other tribes, which were anxious to enter into friendly
relations with so powerful an organization as the new umma. In the year
/
numerous tribes sent delegations (wufd) to make terms with the
Prophet. They came to acknowledge Muammad as the Prophet of Allah
and in many, but by no means all, cases agreed to pay the adaqa or alms
to Medina. In these cases, treaties and taxes such as the adaqa ensured
the mutual recognition of Muammads polity and the outlying tribes,
while granting to the anxious tribes a measure of security amidst the
expanding empire Muammad and his followers were otherwise cementing through conquest. The treaty/tax model, like the lease/rent model,
Ibn Hishm, al-Sra al-Nabawiyya, : .
Hugh Kennedy, The Prophet and the Age of the Caliphates: The Islamic Near East from
the Sixth to the Eleventh Century (London: Longman,
), .
57
oered a legal device that upheld and perpetuated the imperial design of
a newly expanding polity, in part by ensuring peaceful relations without
military conquest, and economic growth through taxes and tributes.
The treaty/tax model became particularly important in animating
if not justifying the later military expeditions led by Ab Bakr upon
the Prophets death. Muammads death in /
ushered a crisis of
legitimacy for the young polity. The most immediate crisis was how to
transfer leadership of the polity. In a series of dramatic political events,
which might have resulted in the break-up of the Medinan polity into
various factions, the Prophets companion Ab Bakr was selected as the
irst person to occupy the position of political leadership over the Muslim
polity: he assumed the of ice of caliph.
Ab Bakrs accession to this of ice did not necessarily mean that
the tribes that had made pacts with Muammad would honour Ab
Bakrs leadership. Many tribes that had made peace agreements with
Muammad and paid monetary tribute argued that they were no longer
obligated to pay tribute; the legitimacy of Medinan leadership died
with the Prophet, they held. Others, however, were of the view that
Muammads mission was not limited to matters of personal faith; that
the tribes could not forgo their obligation to pay their tribute tax to
Medina; and that they had to continue to honor their treaty obligations,
which were due to Ab Bakr in his capacity as caliph and leader of the
new Medina-based empire. Ab Bakr, convinced that the treaties must
hold and that the tribes could not rebuke them, waged war against the
recalcitrant tribes. These battles are called in Islamic sources the Ridda
Wars or Wars of Apostasy.
Whether the recalcitrant tribes can truly be considered apostates
is a matter of some debate. Some tribes may have reverted to their
old tradition and repudiated Islam. In some cases, certain individuals
declared themselves prophets for their people following Muammads
death, thus earning for themselves (in premodern chronicles) the title of
apostate or grand liar (al-kadhdhb). Importantly, other groups seemed
to consider their commitment to Islam to be separate and distinct from
For more on the history of succession after the Prophets death and the debates
that early history spawned, see Patricia Crone, Gods RuleGovernment and Islam: Six
Centuries of Medieval Islamic Political Thought (New York: Columbia University Press,
).
M. Lecker, al-Ridda (a.), Encyclopaedia of Islam, Second Edition, eds P. Bearman;
Th. Bianquis, C.E. Bosworth, E. van Donzel and W.E. Heinrichs (Leiden: Brill,
;
Brill Online, University of Toronto, at <http: www.brillonline.nl/subscriber/
entry?entry=Islam_SIM> accessed February ,
).
W. Montgomery Watt, Musaylima b. abb, Ab Thumma, Encyclopaedia of Islam,
eds P. Bearman, Th. Bianquis, C.E. Bosworth, E. van Donzel and W.P. Heinrichs (Leiden:
Brill,
; Brill Online, University of Toronto, accessed September ,
).
58
their political submission to the leadership of Ab Bakr and the Medinabased polity; as such they did not necessarily repudiate Islam, but they
refused to pay the tribute tax to Medina.
If taxes and treaties were legal devices that helped constitute the vision
and aspiration of the enterprise of governance, then any repudiation of
the tax and the treaty would be considered a direct attack against an
enterprise of governance that had been de ined in an expanding, imperial
fashion. Consequently, it matters little whether a tribe abandoned the
Muslim polity by renouncing its faith or merely by refusing to pay taxes.
Donner writes:
[E]very ridda movement represented at heart an attempt to oppose the
hegemony of the Islamic state based in Medina. This was as true of those
movements whose members declared themselves loyal to Islam but refused
to pay the tax to Medina as it was of those movements that rejected as well
Muammads claim to prophecy, and it applied as much to movements arising in areas once under direct Islamic rule . . . as to those arising in areas
never under Islamic rule . . . that wanted to remain free thereof.
The Ridda Wars represented a challenge not only to the cohesion of the
Muslim polity but also to its outward expansion. An imperial vision
provided a backdrop that gave intelligibility to the legalistic arguments
about treaties, taxes, and military engagements such as the Ridda Wars.
Ab Bakrs regime was principally spent maintaining the polity
and its integrity. His successors regime witnessed, on the other hand,
massive imperial expansion. The second caliph, Umar b. al-Khab
(r. /
59
Islamic state . . . In order to ensure the continued in low of taxes, the regime
attempted to secure the general stability of the countryside and clearly
realized that the productivity of the area depended upon the retention of
most of the lands by the native peasantry.
60
,
.
61
new millennium is the greatest missionary era. Christian NonGovernmental Organisations (NGOs) in Africa have been able to gain a
signi icant foothold in light of international changes in development
policy, which emphasize a reduced role for the state and an increased
role for non-state actors, such as voluntary organizations and NGOs.
The role of missionary NGOs in the new development context raises
important questions about how their missionary activities are folded
into the foreign policy agendas of dierent developed states, such as the
United States, which utilizes such organizations as part of its own foreign
policy. Julie Hearn writes that in Africa, the United States Government
has played a leading role in promoting NGOs, and distributes some forty per
cent of its global development assistance to them. This can be very clearly
seen in Kenya, where some ninety per cent of its aid programme, administered by the United States Agency for International Development (USAID),
is channeled through NGOs and the private sector. Of the NGOs with which
USAID works, US evangelical missions are a signi icant constituency, both
as direct grantees and, more generally, in furthering the US governments
broad policy goals.
62
63
have the eect of stabilizing them by casting the election itself as a mode
of patronage distribution. If authoritarian elections are principally
about the distribution of patronage, Lust concludes, international eorts
to promote democracy provide yet more resources to become the basis
of electoral competition over patronage. Democracy promotion,
therefore, has the potential to serve and maintain a hegemonic
imperative. In the cases of Egypt and Jordan, the hegemonic imperative
was to maintain authoritarian control through the promotion of indices
of democracy, such as elections.
The Islamic tradition has no shortage of materials professing that
the Qurn and prophetic message were not just for the Arabs of
Medina, but rather for all of humanity. Qurnic verses can be read as
characterizing the Qurn and the prophetic mission of Muammad
as having universal appeal and aspirations. In one verse in which the
Qurn addresses Muammads mission, the verse describes his mission
in terms of the aspiration of the Qurnic message: Say . . . This Qurn
has been revealed to me so that by it I can warn you and whoever it may
reach (wa man balagha). Later exegetes interpreted this verse to give
an expansive import to Muammads prophecy and the aspiration of
the Qurnic message. For instance, al-abar (d.
/
) held that the
warning the Prophet was to issue concerned Gods punishment of all
those who disbelieve. That warning extended beyond the con ines of
the Arabian Peninsula, where Muammad was met with opposition; it
applied to all people, without limitation (sir al-ns) since there is no
end to eectuating the Qurnic aspirations (in lam yantahin il al-amal
bi m hi). The later exegete al-Qurub (d.
/
) explained the
normative implications of the universal aspiration of the Qurnic
message. To have the Qurn and the Prophets tradition reach others was
to make a normative claim upon their obedience and allegiance. In other
words, once faced with the message of the Qurn, people could not deny
its existence or claim ignorance of it. Rather, according to al-Qurub,
for the Qurn and the Prophets tradition (sunna) to reach people was
immediately to imply that those people are commanded by God to accede
to the values and requirements elaborated therein (tablgh al-Qurn wa
al-sunna mamr bihim).
Ellen Lust-Okar, Reinforcing Informal Institutions through Authoritarian Elections:
Insights from Jordan, Middle East Law and Governance , no. (
): , .
Qurn : .
Muammad b. Jarr al-abar, Tafsr al-abar min kitbihi Jmi al-Bayn an Tawil
y al-Qurn, eds Bashshr Awd Marf and Im Fris al-arastn (Beirut: Muassasat
al-Risla,
), : .
Muammad b. Amad al-Qurub, al-Jmi li Akm al-Qurn (Beirut: Dr al-Kutub
al-Ilmiyya,
), : .
64
65
66
67
68
69
notable example was the Ban Taghlib; the demands of empire required
modi ication of the general rules. However, while the Ban Taghlib could
remain in the Muslim polity, they were subjected to speci ic regulations
that indirectly had the eect of upholding a universalist Islamic
message, while maintaining the ef icacy of an imperial enterprise of
governance that could not ignore the pragmatics of expansion.
As the empire expanded, the changing contexts presented new
challenges to the development of legal doctrines regulating the scope of
any pluralist commitment. For instance, as Muslims conquered parts of
Iraq and Persia, they came into contact with Magians, which generally
connotes Zoroastrians. Although the Qurnic verse on jizya technically
applies only to those who have received scriptural revelation, the
contingencies of conquest led Muslim conquerors to apply the rules of
jizya and the contract of dhimma to those outside the Abrahamic traditions. The practice of taking jizya from Zoroastrians may be explained
by simple pragmatics, but was legally justi ied by reference to traditions
of the Prophet in which he was reported to have done so. However, this is
not to suggest that the Zoroastrians were treated similarly to Christians
and Jews. According to some jurists, since Zoroastrians were deemed
equivalent to polytheists, Muslims could take the jizya from them, but
could not marry their women or eat their meat. The fact of diversity
and the imperative of imperial management may have led to an increase
in the scope of inclusion. The limiting content of that inclusion, though,
re lects a marginalization that vindicates the universalism of the Islamic
message while providing for ef icient imperial management.
70
71
For a list of such conditions reportedly in the original Pact of Umar and recorded
in later agreements with the non-Muslim community, see Hunwick, The Rights of
Dhimmis to Maintain a Place of Worship,
; Bosworth, The Concept of Dhimma
in Early Islam,
; Richard J.H. Gottheil, Dhimmis and Moslems in Egypt, in Old
Testament and Semitic Studies, eds Robert Francis Harber, Francis Brown and George
Foot Moore, vols (Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
), :
,
.
Despite Umars ban on employing non-Muslims in government posts, nonMuslims held signi icant government of ices throughout Islamic history. The ban on
building new churches arose consistently after
/ , but not before, thereby suggesting that imputing such bans to Umar is likely a later development. Early historical
sources such as those written by al-abar (d.
/
) and al-Baldhur (d.
/
)
do not mention restrictions on dress, again suggesting that such provisions were later
creations that were projected backward to the time of Umar to give the provisions
greater normative force. A.S. Tritton, The Caliphs and their Non-Muslim Subjects: A
Critical Study of the Covenant of Umar (London: Frank Cass and Co., Ltd,
). For those
following Trittons analysis, see, Ben-Shammai, Jew Hatred in the Islamic Tradition
and the Koranic Exegesis,
; Hunwick, The Rights of Dhimmis to Maintain a Place
of Worship,
; Gudrun Kramer, Dhimmi ou Citoyen: R lexions reformists sur le
statut de non-musulmans en socit Islamique, in Entre Reforme Sociale et Mouvement
National, ed. Alain Roussilon (Cairo: CEDEJ,
),
. Gottheil, Dhimmis and
Moslems in Egypt,
, who predates Tritton, also indicated as early as
that the
Pact of Umar was possibly fabricated.
Daniel C. Dennett, Conversion and the Poll Tax in Early Islam (Cambridge: Harvard
University Press,
), . For early versions of the document, see Muammad b. Jarr
al-abar, Tarkh al-abar, :
; Ibn Askir, Tarkh Madnat Damashq, ed. Umar b.
Gharma al-Amraw (Beirut: Dr al-Fikr,
), : .
72
Umar are historically authentic. This study is not concerned with the
authenticity of the Pact as such. Rather, of signi icant interest is how the
Pact, as part of the imagined conquest history, contributed to the way in
which later legal developments were concretized and legitimated.
For instance, the Pact of Umar was often reissued by subsequent
rulers as a means to contain the upward mobility of non-Muslims, and
thereby uphold the legitimacy of the ruler in the eyes of the Muslim
elite. The Pact also oered a point of reference for ongoing debates
about the scope of dhimm duties and the degree to which dhimms
could be constrained in new and dierent ways. For instance, under the
Latrines Decree in nineteenth-century Yemen, dhimms were required to
clean the latrines in the city. Muslims were considered above such labor,
and so the task was delegated to non-Muslims. But to impose this duty on
dhimms went beyond the express terms of the Pact of Umar. Some jurists
held that the Pact set for all time the rights and duties of the dhimms,
and so the dhimms could not be burdened with such tasks. Yet others,
such as al-Shawkn (d.
/
), said the Pact represents a historical
example that did not preclude the development of new rights and duties
of dhimms as circumstances changed. This debate, and al-Shawkns
point in particular, shows how the contract of protection o ered a site of
legal debate where Muslim jurists re lected on the ongoing challenge of
governing a Muslim polity amidst the fact of diversity.
1.6A genealogy of the dhimm rules: Dhimms in the Qurn and Sunna 73
For instance, the Qurn invokes a special status for certain nonMuslims living under Muslim rule in Qurn : :
Fight those who do not believe in God or the inal day, do not prohibit what
God and His prophet have prohibited, do not believe in the religion of truth,
from among those who are given revelatory books, until they pay the jizya
from their hands in a state of submission.
This verse raises various issues such as: who are those given revelatory
books, what is the jizya, and what does it mean to be in a state of
submission?
First, who are the people given revealed books? The interpretive
tradition suggests that the people intended by this verse were the Jews
and Christians, as they were (and still are) understood within Islamic
theology to have received divine revelation. Identifying which
Christians and Jews could take advantage of the jizya, for premodern
jurists, required inquiring into both the history and genealogy of those
claiming special status, as already discussed.
Second, what was the jizya? This was a special poll tax non-Muslim
permanent residents paid to maintain their faith and live peacefully
within the Muslim empire. Notably, premodern jurists debated
whether only Jews and Christians, as the People of the Book (ahl al-kitb),
were entitled to this option of peaceful coexistence within the Muslim
empire upon payment of the jizya. As the historical tradition suggests,
this entitlement was (not surprisingly) expanded to others as the
Muslim empire grew. Consequently, when Muslims conquered Persia
and encountered Zoroastrians, commanders allowed the local religious
population there to reside peacefully in the empire and maintain their
faith, as long as they paid the jizya. Likewise in India, when Muslims
conquered that region, polytheists were allowed to pay the jizya and live
a tolerated existence under Muslim rule. This is not to suggest that
the People of the Book and others were treated alike. Although all these
groups were able to live peacefully within the Muslim empire on condition
of payment of the jizya, the People of the Book were held in higher esteem
than others. That higher esteem was re lected in legal doctrines. For
Qurn, : .
In later periods of Islamic history, this term was extended to include others as well.
For a general overview of the phrase and its Qurnic roots, see G. Vajda, Ahl al- Kitb,
Encyclopaedia of Islam, eds P. Bearman et al.
Studies have shown that the poll tax was not a Muslim invention. The Byzantine
and Sassanian Empires both imposed a poll tax on Jews residing within their respective
territory. See, Morony, Iraq after the Muslim Conquest,
,
.
Al-Fatw al-Almgiryya = Al-Fatw al-Hindiyya Madhhab al-Imm al-Aam
Ab anfa al-Numn (Beirut: Dr al-Marifa,
), :
.
74
instance, Muslim men could marry the women of the People of the Book,
but not the polytheists. Muslims could eat the meat slaughtered by
People of the Book, but not by polytheists or Zoroastrians. Those
without revelation posed a tension in the lawthey were tolerated but
could not be embraced by Muslims in matters of kinship and trade.
The third issue is how premodern jurists understood what it meant
for those paying the jizya to be in a state of submission. Some held that
it referred to being in a state of subordination, thereby characterizing
the payment of jizya as a mechanism of subordination. Indeed, the
theme of subordination existed throughout the Islamic legal tradition.
For instance, in his
article, Richard Gottheil translated an essay
written by a Muslim who recounted how the Prophet allegedly cautioned
Muslims against trusting the non-Muslim. For instance, al-Miqdd b.
al-Aswad al-Kind, a friend of the Prophet, was traveling one day with
a Jewish man. When morning broke during their journey, al-Miqdd
suddenly remembered something the Prophet said: No Jew is on good
terms with a Moslem unless he has up his sleeve some scheme to trap
him. Al-Miqdd confronted his Jewish companion with his suspicion that
the latter was planning some scheme. The Jewish man, taken by surprise,
agreed to admit his scheme on the condition that al-Miqdd not harm
him. When al-Miqdd promised, the Jewish traveler said Since I have
been traveling with you, I have been planning for you to lose [sic] your
head, so that I might trample it under my foot. Contrary to traditions
of harmony, this one depicted the Prophet counseling cautious suspicion
when encountering non-Muslims. Whether this tradition is authentic or
not, it nonetheless reveals how Muslims writing after the early period of
Islam considered the religious Other as posing a threat to the security
and well-being of Muslims.
Friedmann, Classi ication of Unbelievers in Sunni Muslim Law and Tradition,
; Gudrun Kramer, Dhimmi or Citizen? MuslimChristian Relations in Egypt, in The
ChristianMuslim Frontier: Chaos, Clash or Dialogue? ed. Jorgen S. Nielsen (London: I.B.
Tauris,
), ; Morony, Iraq After the Muslim Conquest,
; Freidenreich, Foreigners
and Their Food,
.
Mahmoud M. Ayoub, The Islamic Context of MuslimChristian Relations, in
Conversion and Continuity: Indigenous Christian Communities in Islamic Lands, Eight to
Eighteenth Centuries, eds Michael Gervers and Ramzi Jibran Bikhazi (Toronto: Ponti ical
Institute of Mediaeval Studies,
),
; Ziauddin Ahmed, The Concept of Jizya
in Early Islam, Islamic Studies , no. (
):
1.6A genealogy of the dhimm rules: Dhimms in the Qurn and Sunna 75
Other jurists wrote that the reference to submission refers to how
payment of the jizya was a symbolic act of acknowledging the legitimacy
and imperium of the Shara under which the non-Muslim lived. The
Qurnic phrase was read, therefore, to ensure law, order, and authority,
but not humiliation. For instance, the premodern anbal jurist Ibn
Qudma wrote that the permanent contract of protection for dhimms
must meet two conditions: irst, the payment of the jizya must be made
on a regular basis; second, and most signi icantly, the contract must
provide for the application of the laws of Islam (iltizm akm al-islm),
namely the dhimms acceptance of any rulings against them in terms
of the enforcement of various claims, and their commitment to abstain
from prohibited conduct. An incident involving the Christian Arab
tribe of the Ban Najrn oers a historical example that supports the
law-and-order reading of the jizya verse. These Christians came to visit
Muammad in order to establish a political relationship with him and
his newfound polity. Although the Muslims and the Christians diered
in their understanding of the nature of Christ, they agreed to disagree.
On political matters, though, the Christians agreed to recognize the
legitimacy of Muhammads political authority and to pay taxes to him.
This historical example oered jurists a reconciliation of the claims of
universal truth, sovereign authority, and eective governance amidst
diversity using the legal model of treaty/tax.
A third position, held by jurists such as Fakhr al-Dn al-Rz
(d.
/
), was that the jizya requirement and other rules imposed
on dhimms were intended to provide an incentive for the non-Muslims
to convert. The purpose behind such provisions was not to humiliate
or subjugate, but to incentivize conversion to Islam. Humiliation or
subordination may be unavoidable, but they were not the principal aim
or purpose of the rules; rather, they were instrumental to the central
objective of conversion to Islam.
In the aggregate, these dierent readings of the Qurnic verse suggest
that as jurists debated how to govern amidst diversity, they contended
Ahmad Dallal, Yemeni Debates on the Status of Non-Muslims in Islamic Law,
Islam and Christian-Muslim Relations , no. (
),
,
; Haddad, Ahl al-Dhimma
.
Haddad, Ahl al-Dhimma,
, who refers to al-Mward in support of this
position.
Abd Allh b. Amad Ibn Qudma, al-Mughn (Beirut: Dr Iy al-Turth al-Arab,
n.d.), :
.
Goddard, Christian-Muslim Relations,
.
Jane Dammen McAulie, Fakhr al-Dn al-Rz on Ayat al-Jizya and Ayat al-Sayf,
in Conversion and Continuity: Indigenous Christian Communities in Islamic Lands, Eight to
Eighteenth Centuries, eds Michael Gervers and Ramzi Jibran Bikhazi (Toronto: Ponti ical
Institute of Mediaeval Studies,
),
.
76
with multiple and at times con licting trends. Some trends dominated
the debates on one legal dispute, while other trends informed a dierent
legal issue. Each trend carried weight, but in luenced legal outcomes
dierently depending on various circumstances associated with a
particular issue.
1.7 CONCLUSION
This chapter set out to undermine the usefulness of tolerance as an
organizing principle or concept for an analysis of the dhimm rules. As
various critics have argued, tolerance hides more than it reveals. In
particular, it hides the relationships of power and governance that
underlie most, if not all, debates about tolerance. Tolerance hides not only
asymmetries of power between majority and minority populations, but
it also pays too little attention to how those asymmetries are managed
and even normalized at the intersection of law and the enterprise
of governance. This study, therefore, acknowledges the signi icant
limitations of tolerance as an organizing concept and instead delves
into the details of legal debates about the dhimms to reveal how and to
what extent the intelligibility of the dhimm rules depends on viewing
them as indices of the challenge of governing pluralistically through an
imperial enterprise of governance that is legitimated by a universalist
attitude toward humanity.
The dhimm presents a site of contest between the aspirations of
universalism and the logistical realities of empire. As discussed above,
the feasibility of empire sometimes required that non-Muslims be
permitted to live peacefully in the empire. To suggest otherwise would
require cleansing the empire of diversity, which would actually work
contrary to the management requirements of an empire. Yet, to permit
the non-Muslim to remain non-Muslim in an Islamic polity might be
seen as contrary to the ethic of an Islamic universalism. The contract
of protection and the dhimm rules oered important mechanisms by
which to resolve this con lict. Consequently, the legal attempt to resolve
this con lict of ethical imperatives cannot be reduced to a single theme,
whether of persecution or harmony. Rather, as will be shown throughout
this study, the intelligibility of the dhimm rules for premodern Muslim
jurists was based on the image of an imperial enterprise of governance
that made manifest in a diverse world the universal message implicit in
the Qurn and Muammads prophetic mission.
2
Reason, Contract, and the Obligation to
Obey: The Dhimm as Legal Subject
As discussed in the introduction, Shara as Rule of Law is used in this
study to connote a claim space about the demands of justice, where the
intelligibility of any legal argument made from within that claim space
is in part determined by the boundaries that help de ine and delimit that
claim space. As will be discussed in Part in greater detail, the claim
space takes shape in light of a variety of factors, such as a curriculum
of training, institutions of learning, and institutional bodies devoted
to the settlement of disputes. Additionally, intelligibility is informed by
the authoritative doctrines jurists developed and recorded in numerous
volumes of iqh books. The dhimm, as a member of the Muslim polity,
existed in a society in which these boundary-features of the Shara
claim space were social facts, as was the dhimms presence in the polity.
The dhimm was not only the object of legal debate, therefore, but in his
or her very presence, constituted a certain factual reality that contributed to delimiting the claim space of Shara.
If Shara is understood to be a religious law, one might reasonably
ask why the dhimm should be subjected to a legal tradition that was not
his own. In other words, to consider Shara as purely religious begs a
fundamental (though very modern) question about the dhimm and the
Rule of Law: why not hold the dhimms, whether Jew or Christian, to their
own religious legal orders? The question is intelligible if the religious is
distinguished from the non-religious, or secular, and if the religious and
the secular are considered to aect and govern dierent and separable
aspects of life and social well-being. But the intelligibility of the question
above is signi icantly diminished once Shara is understood as Rule of
Law. If we appreciate the extent to which law is in a mutually constitutive
relationship with the enterprise of governance, then Shara is not a
religious tradition that merely regulates the private relationship
between the believer and his or her God. Rather, Shara as a claim space
Religious Pluralism and Islamic Law. Anver M. Emon.
Oxford University Press 2012. Published 2012 by Oxford University Press.
78
79
80
):
; idem, Islamic Natural Law Theories (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
).
Others opposing this view on usn/qub and the determination of the law where there is
no scripture (min qabla wurd al-shar), also believed it implicated the nature and de inition of obligation (taklf ). See Al b. Abd al-K al-Subk and Tj al-Dn al-Subk, al-Ibhj
Shar al-Minhj (Beirut: Dr al-Kutub al-Ilmiyya, n.d.), : .
81
82
83
violating Gods law, then they must have been obligated to abide by it. To
view reason as universally shared allows everyone equal access to the
same shared values, and thereby means that nothing fundamentally
prevents the dhimm from being legitimately subjected to Shara-based
obligations.
Nonetheless, jurists such as al-Ja allowed for some exceptions,
given the fact of diversity. To impose the full scope of Shara-based norms
on dhimms would fundamentally disrespect the dhimms dierences in
beliefs, thereby violating the Muslim regimes obligations toward the
dhimms under the contract of protection, as will be further discussed in
Chapter . But if all humans equally share a universal reason that gives
them access to public values of the good and the bad, how can dhimms
nevertheless be exempted from some parts of the Shara but not others?
Furthermore, which parts of the Shara can be suspended for them,
which parts cannot be waived away, and how does one tell the dierence?
Al-Ja recognized the conceptual dilemmas underlying this issue.
He knew that to believe in a universal reason can lead to the conclusion
that the full scope of Shara-based norms should be obligatory on all,
without limitation. However, he also recognized that the law granted
dhimms exceptions. Indeed, he could not ignore the inherited precedent
limiting the scope of the dhimms obligations. Consequently and perhaps
unsurprisingly, al-Ja stated: Like all [people, the dhimms] receive
the discourse about having faith. But they are able to avoid it and its laws
by [paying] the jizya. The reference to jizya here arguably operated
as al-Ja shorthand reference to the contract of protection and its
terms (i.e., the akm al-dhimma). For al-Ja, the dhimm was obligated
to abide by the Islamic message. Nonetheless, the reality of diversity
and prior precedent re lected a commitment to a pluralist enterprise
of governance, which informed how jurists such as al-Ja theorized
about the dhimms subject-hood and scope of liability under a Sharabased legal system.
This commitment and its contribution to the content of the law is
re lected in how al-Ja harmonized an Islamic universalist ethos
with support for pluralism. He could not ignore addressing how Muslims
could allow non-Muslims to enter a contract of protection that ultimately
perpetuates disbelief in Islamic lands, especially if universal reason
allows for the potential to know and appreciate the divine discourse.
Al-Ja held that implicit in the duty to obey the Shara is a certain
al-Muarrar, : , argues that this verse does not imply any obligation on the non-Muslim
in the mundane world, but does imply punishment in the hereafter.
Al-Ja, al-Ful, :
.
84
85
:
:
:
:
.
.
.
.
86
87
88
wrote about, the dhimm was both insider and outsider; dhimms may
have lived within the Muslim polity but they retained their di erences.
Dhimms thereby oer us an important discursive site to understand the
challenges that face an enterprise of governance imagined in terms of an
Islamic universalism, an ethic of empire, and the fact of diversity. Indeed,
the dhimm, the contract of protection, and the dhimm rules constitute
an important focal point for appreciating Shara as a claim space and its
relationship to the enterprise of governance.
According to the Sh iite jurist al-Mward (d.
/
), a nonMuslim could enter dierent types of contracts with the Muslim polity,
each of which had varying implications for the relationship between
the non-Muslim and the Muslim polity. The irst type of contract, hudna,
was an agreement made by the political ruler or imm with non-Muslim
enemies of the state (ahl al-arb) to negotiate cease ires. According
to al-Mward, the hudna was a negotiated peace treaty lasting for a
maximum of ten years and could even involve the Muslim polity paying
the non-Muslims a tribute to stave o ighting. Only the ruler had the
discretion to enter a hudna; he could do so if it was needed and was
indisputably in the public interest (uhr al-malaa). The hudna, or
peace treaty, however, had less to do with the way non-Muslims were
included within the Muslim polity, and more to do with the relationship
of peace between two otherwise warring polities.
The second contract, ahd, was a temporary agreement that allowed
non-Muslims to enter Muslim lands for a period not exceeding four months,
although some held that the maximum was one year. Like the hudna, the
ahd could only be issued by the ruling authority and was granted only
when it would provide some bene it (malaa) for Muslim society. But
unlike the hudna, the non-Muslim could pay for the entitlement to enter,
although payment was not a condition for issuing the ahd.
Like the ahd, the amn, or pledge of security, was a temporary permit
of residency of limited duration. Notably, the amn could be given by
While this analysis will refer to al-Mwards commentary on the dierent forms
of contract, other sources o er similar accounts. See for instance, Ibn Nujaym, al-Shar
al-Bar al-Riq (Beirut: Dr al-Kutub al-Ilmiyya,
), : ; Ibn Qudma, al-Mughn,
:
.
Ab al-asan al-Mward, al-w al-Kabr, eds Al Muammad Muawwa and
dil Amad Abd al-Mawjd (Beirut: Dr al-Kutub al-Ilmiyya,
), :
. The limit of
ten years is based on the peace treaty Muammad negotiated with the Quraysh, known
as the Treaty of udaybiyya, which had a ten-year time limit.
Al-Mward, al-w, :
.
The time limits for an amn vary; for some it is for four months; for others it is for
one year. J. Schacht, EI , s.v., Amn. On the pre-Islamic analogues of amn that may have
in luenced its development in Islamic legal thought, see Levy-Rubin, Non-Muslims in the
Early Islamic Empire, .
89
any Muslim to a non-Muslim. In other words, while the hudna and ahd
were given at the discretion of the ruling authority, private individuals
could issue pledges of safe conduct to non-Muslims, thereby rendering
them temporarily secure in Muslim lands. The term of art referring to
one who enjoyed the security of an amn was mustamin.
The ahd and amn were both temporary visitation permits that
allowed non-Muslims to enter the Muslim polity. The fact that they were
temporary emphasizes that their holder was an outsider to the Muslim
politysomeone who fundamentally did not reside among Muslims with
any permanency. Consequently, while these legal contracts certainly
provided ways for non-Muslims to enter Muslim society, they o er us
limited insight into how and why non-Muslims, who were part of Muslim
society, presented a lashpoint for debate at the intersection of law and
the enterprise of governance.
Literally translated as contract of protection, the aqd al-dhimma
was the legal mechanism by which a non-Muslim was deemed either
actually or ictively to contract into protected and permanent residency
status in Islamic lands. Whether the contract was actual or ictional
depended on whether the non-Muslims agreed to pay the jizya when
oered the option of peaceful surrender (i.e., uliyya) by conquering
Muslim forces, or whether they refused and had terms of settlement
imposed upon them through conquest (anwiyya). Additionally, a
contract may have been applied to later generations, despite the lack of
any actual consent from those subjected to its terms. In other words,
the invocation of a contract of protection did not necessarily imply an
actual written document with the terms and conditions of residence
noted therein. Rather, the contract of protection was a legal concept
that operated as a place-holder for the political agreement of dhimms
to abide by Shara-based norms, but not to the same extent as Muslims
who had, by virtue of their faith commitments, fully acquiesced to the
full scope of Shara-based obligations.
According to al-Mward, the contract of protection posed the most
signi icant type of contractual relationship (awkad al-uqd) between
non-Muslims and Muslim society because:
it provided security of residence;
it was conditional on the dhimms paying a poll tax or jizya;
Al-Mward, al-w, :
.
Ibn Rushd al-Jadd, al-Muqaddimt al-Mumahhidt, ed. Muammad ajj (Beirut:
Dr al-Gharb al-Islm,
), :
. For more on the signi icance of the distinction
between conquest and peaceful surrender (anwiyya and uliyya), see Levy-Rubin, NonMuslims in the Early Islamic Empire, .
90
2.3Conclusion
91
2.3 CONCLUSION
By examining competing theories of obligation, this chapter has argued
that the contract of protection oered the conceptual link between law
Aristotle, Nichomachean Ethics, trans. Harris Rackham (Hertfordshire: Wordsworth
Editions Limited,
),
; Amad b. Muammad Miskawayh, The Re inement of
Character, trans. Constantine K. Zurayk (Beirut: American University of Beirut,
),
. For the original Arabic, see Ibn Miskawayh, Tahdhb al-Akhlq wa Tahr al-Arf,
ed. Ibn al-Khab (n.p.: Maktabat al-Thaqfa al-Dniyya, n.d.),
; Ab Nar al-Frb,
Ful Muntazaa, ed. Fawz Najjr (Beirut: Dr al-Mashraq,
), .
92
2.3Conclusion
93
While the dhimms were permitted to reside in the Muslim polity and
were exempted from certain Shara-based obligations, as the quote from
al-Sarakhs suggests, nothing precluded the fact that dhimms were still
worthy of divine condemnation.
As will be shown in the next chapter, legal debates about the dhimm
rules contributed to political debates about the nature of the enterprise
of governance, and about the degree to which accommodation,
subordination, and marginalization of dierence contributed to the
legitimacy of the enterprise of governance. Even when they were
making exceptions for the dhimm so as to accommodate dierence,
jurists nonetheless justi ied the characterization and legal treatment
of the dhimm in terms whose intelligibility is best appreciated by
viewing the rules as stemming from a Shara claim space that was
bounded, in part, by an imperial vision of the enterprise of governance.
By granting freedom to the dhimms to live peacefully in the Muslim
polity, the rules that exempted dhimms from Shara-based liability
also de ined them as being dierent. Furthermore, the scope of their
Al-Sarakhs, al-Muarrar, :
94
3
Pluralism, Dhimm Rules, and the
Regulation of Dierence
Chapter
showed that whether or not jurists agreed if universal
reason could render dhimms obligated to abide by the Shara, they
agreed that the dhimms obligation to Shara-norms was dependent
upon the terms of a contract of protection. As suggested earlier,
though, the terms of the contract of protection were not entirely clear.
To appreciate the terms of the contract of protection is less a matter of
inding historical records, and more a matter of recognizing that the
contract of protection was a juridi ied site for debate about the scope
and limits of the dhimms inclusion and accommodation in the Muslim
polity. The contract of protection, in other words, was a conceptual
device that re lected the dynamics of Shara as Rule of Law, namely the
negotiative and mutually constitutive relationship between the law and
the enterprise of governance. Consequently, far from being indicative of
the tolerance or intolerance of Islam, the contract of protection and its
associated provisions (i.e., the dhimm rules) were symptomatic of the
more general challenge of governing amidst diversity.
This chapter introduces legal debates on various dhimm-related
topics to showcase how the legal arguments re lected a broader, more
general concern about the scope and extent to which the dhimm was
included and accommodated in the Muslim polity. Upon reviewing
a series of debates on dierent legal issues (e.g., the jizya, charitable
endowments, public displays of religious ritual, and so on), the chapter
concludes by suggesting that the dhimm rules were juridi ied attempts
to imagine, construe, and de ine the public sphere and the enterprise of
governance in light of the fact of diversity. In some cases, the contract
of protection igured prominently as a device that required dhimm
interests to be accommodated. At other times, principles about the
superiority of Islam over all other traditions were invoked to demarcate
the limits of inclusion and accommodation. In the aggregate, the analysis
Religious Pluralism and Islamic Law. Anver M. Emon.
Oxford University Press 2012. Published 2012 by Oxford University Press.
96
shows that the dhimm rules organized and strati ied a diverse society
for the purpose of ensuring the primacy of an Islamically de ined
public sphere in light of at times con licting imperatives of empire
and universalism. To read the dhimm rules in this fashion contributes
to the more general aim of this study, namely to understand how the
intelligibility of legal doctrines is best appreciated by recognizing them
as made within a claim space of justice that lies at the intersection of
both law and governance.
Shara is not unique, as legal systems go, in rendering the minority
(religious or otherwise) a site of politico-legal debate about the
core values of society, the character of the public sphere, and the
aspirations of the enterprise of governance. For instance, the Quebec
government in Canada established a commission to study attitudes
about religious accommodation and how to de ine and demarcate
the limits of accommodation without sacri icing the core values that
characterize the Quebec polity, however de ined. Additionally, recent
years have witnessed a backlash in European and North American
societies against the public presence of religious manifestations, as
will be further discussed in Chapter . This backlash has taken on a
particular attitude against Islam and Muslims since the tragic attack on
the World Trade Center on September ,
. The Swiss constitutional
referendum against the construction of minarets arguably expressed a
popular sentiment about the perceived inconsistency of a highly public
Islamic symbol such as the minaret with the character and identity of
Switzerland as a polity. Likewise, legislative enactments to ban the niqb
in many European countries re lect a concern that a particular spirit
or value in these countries may be lost if niqb-clad women walk the
streets of European cities. What the core values and public spirit are,
however, is not always clear or even articulated. Nevertheless, advocates
of such bans seem con ident that by legally regulating the presence of
minarets and niqbs, the core values at stake will survive intact.
These relatively recent constitutional and legislative enactments
and proposals share an important characteristic with the dhimm rules.
All are concerned about the preservation of a particular way of life,
political vision, or set of core values that are apparently threatened
by the visible presence of religious symbols of the group identi ied as
Other. In Islamic legal terms, the Other is the dhimm. In Europe and
North America, the Other has, in the years since September ,
,
See, the Report of the Reasonable Accommodation Commission of Quebec: Taylor
and Bouchard, Building the Future.
For more discussion on the Swiss constitutional referendum and the treatment of
the covered Muslim woman, see Chapter .
97
become Muslims. Although this chapter and the study focus speci ically
on the dhimm rules, more generally this study suggests that however
the Other is de ined, the public presence of the Other will constitute an
important site for the mutually constitutive relationship between law
and the enterprise of governance. Consequently, the Others inclusion
in the polity is vulnerable to the changing vicissitudes of history and
politics that aect the policies of enterprises of governance, and thereby
aect the intelligibility of arguments made within the claim space of
the law.
98
into? As this chapter will show, the dhimm rules were often rationalized
and justi ied by reference to the imagined Islamic polity into which the
dhimm sought entrancea society that was committed to a pluralism
de ined and delimited in light of an imperial Islamic universalism.
3.1.1Jizya history
The jizya seems to have provided a sizable tax base for the nascent
Islamic empire, as Muslims conquered vast lands in Iraq, Persia, and
Egypt, thereby bringing within their control large populations of nonMuslims. Imposing poll-taxes and other regulatory measures on
minority religious communities was not unique to the Islamic tradition.
Rather, discriminatory regulations were utilized by many polities
throughout antiquity, late antiquity, and the medieval period. As
Muslim forces expanded and conquered new lands, Muslims formed a
minority. According to Wadi Haddad, the jizya made perfect sense in the
early conquest period when the majority of those living under Muslim
dominion were non-Muslim. By taxing the non-Muslims, a revenue
low was generated that inanced ongoing military operations, the
construction of garrison towns, and various social support programs.
But, as non-Muslims began converting to Islam, and the Muslim minority
turned into a Muslim majority, the potential return on the jizya tax
began to diminish and adversely aected the abundance in imperial
Some studies question the nearly synonymous use of the terms kharj and jizya in
the historical sources. The general view suggests that while the terms kharj and jizya
seem to have been used interchangeably in early historical sources, what they referred
to in any given case depended on the linguistic context. If one inds reference to a kharj
on their heads, the reference was to a poll tax, despite the use of the term kharj, which
later became the term of art for land tax. Likewise, if one inds the phrase jizya on their
land, this referred to a land tax, despite the use of jizya which later came to refer to the
poll tax. Early history therefore shows that although each term did not have a determinate technical meaning at irst, the concepts of poll tax and land tax existed early in
Islamic history. Dennet, Conversion and the Poll Tax, ; Aijaz Hassan Qureshi, The
Terms Kharaj and Jizya and Their Implications, Journal of the Punjab University Historical
Society (
): ; Hossein Modarressi Tabtabi, Kharj in Islamic Law (London:
Anchor Press Ltd,
).
Michael Goodich, ed., Other Middle Ages: Witnesses at the Margins of Medieval Society
(Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press,
), ; Alan Watson, Roman Law &
Comparative Law (Athens, Georgia: University of Georgia Press,
), .
Haddad, Ahl al-Dhimma in an Islamic State,
.
State support of Muslims is connected with the payment registry called the diwn.
However, there is some research to suggest that even non-Muslims were at times
included on the diwn registry. Richard Gottheil, A Fetwa on the Appointment of
Dhimmis to Of ice, in Zeitschrift fur Ayriologie und Verwandte Gebiete, ed. Carol Bezold
(Strassburg: Verlag von Karl J. Trubner,
),
,
.
99
coers. This is not to suggest that the jizya institution died out; even
regimes as late as the Ottomans imposed the jizya on non-Muslims.
Beyond providing tax revenue for the empire, the jizya was also a tool
of both inclusion and humiliation, thereby ensuring and vindicating
Islamic universalist claims, and supporting the enterprise of empire.
Authors debate whether the jizya was meant to subjugate and humiliate
non-Muslims, or whether it was only intended as a service fee for
military protection. Muhammad Hamidullah argues that the jizya was
solely for protection. Without citing economic studies, he states, So, the
non-Muslims paid a little supplementary tax, the jizyah . . . which was
neither heavy nor unjust. Mahmoud Ayoub and Haddad argue instead
that it served both functions: it was both a mode of subservience and a
method of inclusion. Hamidullahs account re lects the imperatives of
the myth of harmony, while Haddad and Ayoub oer a historical account
of the jizyas complex social function in early Islamic history. To adopt the
view that the jizya was either inclusive or an instrument of subservience
ignores the possibility, indeed likelihood, that the jizya was neither one
nor the other, but rather was both in purpose and e ect. In this sense,
the jizya cannot easily be characterized exclusively as an instrument of
either harmony or persecution. Rather, the studies on the jizya, in the
aggregate, suggest that the jizya was a complex symbol which can be
viewed as a tool of marginalization or a mechanism of inclusion, but more
fruitfully is understood as both.
100
Notably, the inancial support the jizya provided the empire was
absent from al-Rzs list of rationales. This silence was common among
many jurists who articulated the rationale for the jizya. They viewed the
jizya as a legal rule directed at the Other, but remained silent on how the
jizya requirement inancially supported the enterprise of governance.
Identifying this silence is one thing; trying to interpret its signi icance is
another. It might mean that they viewed the legal rules of iqh as separable
from the enterprise of governance. It could re lect the fact that jurists
assumed the existence of the enterprise of governance to the point of
nearly taking it for granted. It could also signify that they were unwilling
to incorporate as part of the rationale of the jizya rule the importance
of providing inancial resources to the governing institutions. All of
these interpretations point to a similar conclusion: the fact that the
jizya provided inancial resources to the enterprise of governance was
an undeniable consequence of the jizya, but not its juridically stated
See also al-Ghazl, al-Was, : ; Ibn Rushd al-Jadd, al-Muqaddimt al-Mumahhidt,
:
, who said the jizya paid to provide security (tamn) and protection for non-Muslims
who maintain their state of disbelief (kufr); Shihb al-Dn al-Qar , al-Dhakhra, ed.
Sad Arb (Beirut: Dr al-Gharb al-Islm,
), : .
Fakhr al-Dn al-Rz, al-Tafsr al-Kabr (Beirut: Dr Iy al-Turth al-Arab,
),
: .
Al-Rz, al-Tafsr al-Kabr, : . See also the Mlik al-ab, who related a similar rationale for imposing the jizya on non-Muslims. Al-ab, Mawhib al-Jall, ed.
Zakariyy Amrt (Beirut: Dr al-Kutub al-Ilmiyya,
), :
.
Khalid Yahya Blankinship, The End of the Jihad State: The Reign of Hisham Ibn Abd
al-Malik and the Collapse of the Umayyads (Albany: State University of New York Press,
), .
102
104
tribe that challenged the universalist ethos of Islam, since the tribe
shared the Prophets ethnicity, culture, and language, yet remained
non-Muslim. Nonetheless, Umar permitted the Ban Taghlib to pay a
tribute and thereby remain Christian in the Arab Peninsula. Even more,
the Ban Taghlib did not agree to pay the jizya. For them, the jizya was
a demeaning tax that they did not want to pay. Umar was advised to
call their tribute by another name and permitted them to stay. Umars
surprising tolerance of Ban Taghlibs Christian commitments was
in large part a response to their potential alliance with the Byzantine
empire, which could pose a considerable challenge to Umars imperial
program. The examples of the Ban Najrn and Ban Taghlib reveal
that the content of Umars limited commitment to pluralism arose
from a negotiation between the demands of imperial dominion and a
commitment to an Islamic universalism. The story of the Ban Taghlib
illustrates how their religious otherness presented a dif icult dilemma
for Umar, if viewed through the lenses of both an Islamic universalism
and an imperial agenda.
One might consider these two examples from Umars reign as merely
pragmatic and having little to do with Shara as Rule of Law. Umar
wanted to expand the empire and could expel the Ban Najrn at no
political cost, while he could not do so with the Ban Taghlib given the
Byzantine threat. His contrasting treatment of the two tribes, therefore,
could be reduced to mere political pragmatism. While that is an entirely
reasonable way to read Umars actions, the problem with that reading
arises when considering the implication of Umars actions on the
development of an Islamic legal tradition in which Umar was viewed as
more than merely a political igure. Umar was both a Companion of the
Prophet and the second caliph of the nascent Islamic polity. As caliph he
was a political leader, but as a Companion he embodied in his words and
actions a normative content that was relevant for later jurists as they
studied and developed the law in subsequent centuries. For instance,
writing centuries later, the anbal jurist Ibn Qudma (d.
/
)
wrote about whether non-Muslims could reside in the Arabian Peninsula.
In recounting the legal debates among the various schools, Umars
actions during his reign as Caliph-Companion, along with the Prophets
The Ban Taghlib presented various challenges to the image of Islamic rule and
the competing notions of the Muslim polity and Muslim community. Al b. Ab lib
(r. /
), the fourth caliph, prohibited Muslim men from marrying the women
of Taghlib. Generally, Muslim men are permitted to marry Christian or Jewish women, but
Al prohibited marriage with the women of Taghlib because he was not sure whether the
tribe embraced Christianity before or after the corruption of the tradition. Friedmann,
Classi ication of Unbelievers,
.
106
3.2Inclusion and its limits: Contract theory and liability for theft 107
Jurists argued that the contract of protection was the mechanism by
which the dhimm was included within the ambit of the Muslim polity.
But how they understood the inclusive e ect of the contract di ered.
For example, al-Ghazl relied on a contract-based argument to hold that
a dhimm should suer the same liability as a Muslim for theft because
of his obligation to our laws (li ilzmihi akmin). By entering into
the contract of protection, he suggested that dhimms agreed to abide by
the Shara. In doing so, they derived a certain bene it from the security
of expectation interests that the law provided. E ectively, al-Ghazl
recognized the dhimm as a participant in Muslim society who bene itted
from the protections a orded by the law. As a participant, the dhimm
was not only entitled to the bene its of living in a political society ruled
by an enterprise of governance, but also had to endure the burdens.
By using a contract-based argument, al-Ghazl justi ied imposing the
Shara on dhimms; in doing so, he used the contract to include them
as part of the polity. Here, the dhimm was as equally entitled and
burdened as his Muslim neighbor, which implicitly re lected an attitude
of inclusion.
For other jurists, the contract approach above permitted too much
inclusion without suf icient demarcation and distinction between the
Muslim Us and the dhimm Other. For instance, al-Shrz argued that
the legitimacy of applying the penalty for theft against the dhimms was
that their own law and tradition forbade theft. Consequently, even if
they wished to assert their immunity on the grounds of their distinct
faith commitments, they could not avoid liability for theft. The fact
that their own tradition banned theft indicated their acceptance of the
underlying values that arose from the ban. As such, holding them liable
to the Shara ban did not violate their rights to autonomy and respect
under the contract of protection. Like al-Ghazl, al-Shrz suggested
that dhimms should bear the same burdens as Muslims. But al-Shrzs
argument was not premised on consent to Shara-based obligations via
entry into the contract of protection. Rather, by allowing the dhimms
to enter into a contract of protection, the law required the Islamic
enterprise of governance to respect the dhimms distinct tradition,
which just happened to coincide with the demands of Shara-based
doctrines on theft. It is as if al-Shrz said: The contract of protection
requires Muslims to respect the dhimms and their adherence to their
own traditions. Since the dhimms tradition also bans theft, they can be
Al-Ghazl, al-Was, : .
Ab Isq al-Shrz, al-Muhadhdhab Fiqh al-Imm al-Sh i, ed. Zakariy
Amrt (Beirut: Dr al-Kutub al-Ilmiyya,
), : .
108
held liable to our Shara bans on theft without any breach of contract.
Al-Shrz may have relied on the contract of protection to begin his
analysis, but ultimately his emphasis was on the dhimms otherness. In
the interest of respecting their diversity, al-Shrz implicitly othered
them to a degree not present in al-Ghazls argument of inclusion.
Admittedly, some might view the dierence between these two
approaches as one of degree rather than kind. Nonetheless, the contrast
between al-Ghazl and al-Shrz illustrates that even when seeking
to include the dhimm as a legal subject of the Islamic enterprise of
governance, the legal arguments used to justify their inclusion can have
dierent implications on their standing and status within the polity.
For al-Ghazl, the argument of contract emphasized the shared
experience of those living in organized society together. For al-Shrz,
the argument from contract emphasized the otherness of the dhimms
living in a Muslim polity. In both cases, the dhimm was subjected to
the Shara-based bans on theft, but the rationales employed showcase
dierent attitudes about the extent to which the dhimm was included in
the Muslim polity and also remained othered.
109
110
111
the legal debate about whether a dhimm could petition the enterprise of
governance to amputate the hand of a thief who stole the dhimms pork
or wine, on the basis of the Qurnic punishment for theft. Suppose a
dhimm stole wine or pigs from another dhimm. This is an interesting case
to consider because for both parties the items are presumably lawful for
them to consume. Indeed, the ana al-Ksn recognized that under the
dhimms law, the property was deemed as rights-conferring. But under
Shara-based doctrine, such property was not rights-conferring since it
was not mutaqawwam. Or as al-Mward noted, its destruction connoted
no value (l qma al mutla ihi). If the wronged dhimm sought redress
under Shara-based doctrines against the thieving dhimm, should the
Muslim judge punish the thieving dhimm with the Qurnic punishment?
If the judge did so, wouldnt that eectively be using the doctrine and
institutions of a Shara legal system to enforce a right to a kind of
property that is not regarded as value-conferring under Shara-based
norms, but that is value-conferring under the dhimms tradition? In other
words, wouldnt the judge be applying the dhimms tradition on property
to eectuate a Qurnically based punishment? This question not only
presented a certain irony to Muslim jurists. It also raised an important
question about the priority of Shara doctrines over and against any
other tradition of value. This was more than a mere con licts of law issue.
If viewed through the framework of Rule of Law, this problem posed a
challenge to the sovereign integrity of the enterprise of governance. To
apply the dhimms tradition would have involved channeling it through
an adjudicating institution that was constituted in part by Shara-based
norms as a source of its legal and political legitimacy. Put dierently,
the challenge for jurists was whether and to what extent the dhimms
tradition should or should not constitute, in part, the boundaries of the
claim space of Shara as Rule of Law, which was de ined in terms of an
Islamic enterprise of governance and Shara-based norms and values.
Certainly the dhimm should be able to have certain expectation interests and legal protection under the contract of protection, but at what
cost to the integrity of a Shara legal system embedded in an Islamic
imperial enterprise of governance?
These systemic questions seemed to underlie what might seem a
relatively straightforward question of whether the dhimm can demand
that the enterprise of governance punish the thief for stealing his wine
Al-Mward, al-w, :
.
A contemporary example that raises similar legal reservations is the current debate
in the United States about whether or not it is appropriate to invoke international law in
constitutional law disputes. See for instance, Kahn, Political Theology, . This particular
issue will be addressed at greater length in Chapter .
112
113
114
bequest raised concerns for jurists when property was donated for public
purposes that could contravene the public good. In other words, while
private property rights might be protected, the scope of protection was
limited in light of competing interests of a more general, public nature.
Consequently, the juristic debate about whether and to what extent
a dhimm could endow a charitable trust had to account for the need to
respect both the dhimms private property interests and the imperative
to protect the public good. Examining how jurists resolved this balance
will reveal the often implicit factors that contributed to their notion of
the public good and those that diminished it.
Two ways to create a charitable endowment were ( ) a bequest that
will take eect upon the testators death (i.e., waiyya), and ( ) an inter
vivos transfer of property directly into a trust (waqf ). Sh i and anbal
jurists generally agreed that dhimms could create trusts and issue
bequests to any speci ied individual (shakh muayyan), regardless of
religious background, although some jurists limited the bene iciaries to
ones kin group. This permissive attitude was based on the legal respect
for private ownership (tamlk) and the rights the property owner held
because of his claim on his property. Sh i and anbal jurists held
that the dhimms private property interest was suf iciently important to
warrant the right to bequeath property to other individuals.
However, if the dhimms bequest was to establish something that
might adversely aect the public interest (understood in terms of an
Islamic universalism), then the bequest was a sin against God and could
not be valid under the Shara. To hold otherwise would be to use the
institutions of an Islamic enterprise of governance to legitimate practices
that contravene an Islamically de ined public good. Consequently, if
a dhimm created a charitable trust to support building a church or a
school for Torah or Bible studies, Sh i jurists would invalidate the
Al-Ghazl, al-Was, :
. Al-Mward, al-w, :
, wrote that there
is a dispute about whether a non-Muslim can make a bequest to anyone other than
a free Muslim of legal majority; al-Nawaw, Rawa, : , held that a waqf could be for
the bene it of a dhimm, but not for an enemy of the state (arb) or apostate; al-Shrz,
al-Muhadhdhab, :
, allowed waqfs for speci ied dhimms but noted the debate
about waqfs for the bene it of apostates or enemies of the state.
Al-Ghazl, al-Was, :
. Ab Abd Allh b. Mu li, al-Fur, ed. Ab al-Zahr
zim al-Q (Beirut: Dr al-Kutub al-Ilmiyya,
), : ; Ibn Qudma, al-Mughn,
:
.
Al-Ghazl, al-Was, : ; al-Nawaw, Rawa, : , allowed a waiyya to be for
the bene it of dhimms, arbs, and apostates; Ibn Qudma, al-Mughn, : , analogized
a waiyya to a gift, and said that both could be given to dhimms and arbs in the dr
al-arb; Abu Abd Allh b. Mu li, al-Fur, : l; al-Baht, Kashshf al-Qin an Matn
al-Iqn (Beirut: Dr al-Kutub al-Ilmiyya,
), :
; al-Muaqqiq al-ill, Shar
al-Islm, :
.
115
116
117
did not violate any precept in the dhimms traditions or the Islamic one.
In other words, if the charitable endowment was lawful under both the
dhimms and the Islamic tradition, there was no real con lict; to allow
such bequests would uphold the Islamic values underly ing the enterprise
of governance, and respect the dhimms tradition pursuant to the
contract of protection. In such a case, the claim space of Shara would
not countenance something that would run contrary to Shara-based
doctrines, the public good, or an Islamic enterprise of governance.
Notably, the dhimm could not bequeath a charitable endowment
for something that was lawful under Islam but unlawful or of no legal
signi icance under the dhimms tradition, such as for instance the ajj.
Respect for the dhimms tradition, as required under the contract of
protection, arguably animated this legal outcome. Interestingly, though,
one cannot ignore the fact that the dhimms private rights of property
disposition are limited by his own tradition, regardless of how a
particular dhimm-grantor might feel about the matter.
The most dif icult issue had to do with whether the dhimm could create
a charitable endowment that upheld a value in his own tradition, but was
contrary to Islamic values. This is the case on which jurists disagreed,
as noted above. For some, to give legal eect to such endowments would
be tantamount to giving legal eect to sin. Moreover, some jurists went
so far as to consider such endowments security threats to the wellbeing of the polity. Others, such as some ana jurists, allowed for such
endowments. They recognized that the dhimms tradition considered
such endowments valuable, and Muslim rulers were required to respect
the dhimms traditions under the contract of protection.
To further complicate matters, the Mliks had their own approach,
which carved out a middle ground between the two positions noted
above. Mliks addressed the issue of charitable endowments by
reference to the religious association of the testator, the framework of
Islamic inheritance law, and the prevailing tax regime. Under Islamic
inheritance law, two-thirds of a decedents property was distributed
pursuant to a rule of inheritance that designated percentage shares for
speci ically identi ied heirs. The decedent could bequeath the remaining
one-third to non-heirs. Mliks asked, though, whether a Christian
dhimm with no heirs could bequeath all of his property to the head of the
Church. Generally, the Christian could give one-third of his estate to the
Patriarch, but the remaining two-thirds escheated to the Muslim polity,
On the rules of inheritance in the Qurn and Islamic law, see Qurn : ; David
Powers, Studies in Quran and Hadith: The Formation of the Islamic Law of Inheritance
(Berkeley: University of California Press,
).
118
which was considered his lawful heir in this case. Even if the testator
left a testamentary instrument that transferred his whole estate to the
Patriarchate, the above arrangement was to be carried out.
The application of this general rule, however, depended on whether
the dhimm-decedent was personally liable to the governing regime for
the jizya or whether the dhimms community was collectively liable for
the tax payment. If the dhimm was personally liable for paying the jizya
directly to the government, the above ruling on escheat to the government
applied. The rationale for this rule was as follows: with the death of the
dhimm, the enterprise of governance lost its annual tax revenue from
him. Consequently, the escheat of his estate was designed to account for
the regimes lost revenue.
But suppose the leaders of the dhimms community collected the
jizya from the communitys members and delivered the payment to the
ruling regime on behalf of the community. Furthermore, suppose the
community collectively paid a pre-established collective jizya, and that
the total sum did not decrease with deaths of community members.
Under such circumstances, many Mliks allowed individual dhimms
(presumably without heirs) to bequeath their entire estate to whomever
they wished. This particular ruling worked to the inancial bene it of
the enterprise of governance. The enterprise of governance still received
the same jizya tax revenues. Any inancial loss was distributed to the
dhimm community, since its tax liability did not diminish with the death
of its community members. To o set that inancial loss, the Mliks
permitted dhimms to bequeath their entire estate to the community
when they lacked any heirs.
In conclusion, when a dhimm sought to donate money to endow a
religious institution, Muslim jurists were concerned about giving such
charitable institutions legal recognition. To use Shara-based legal
categories and institutions to uphold non-Muslim religious institutions
would seem awkward and ironic at best, illegitimate at worst, given a
public good de ined in terms of a universalizing Islamic ethos. The legal
debate about the scope of the dhimms power to bequeath property for
Ibn Rushd al-Jadd, al-Bayn wa al-Tal (Beirut: Dr al-Gharb al-Islm,
),
:
.
Ibn Rushd al-Jadd, al-Bayn, :
. See also al-attb, Mawhib al-Jall, : ,
who relates this view, and critiques another that upholds the validity of any waiyya by a
k ir; al-Qar , al-Dhakhra, : .
Ibn Rushd al-Jadd, al-Bayn, :
. See also al-Qar , al-Dhakhra, : .
Ibn Rushd al-Jadd, al-Bayn, :
. However, Ibn Rushd did note others who
disagreed with him, and held that the estate escheats to the state when there is no heir.
Al-Qar , al-Dhakhra, : , held the same view as Ibn Rushd al-Jadd, but also noted the
disagreement on this issue.
119
religious purposes shows how Muslim jurists grappled with the eects of
diversity on the social fabric of the Muslim polity. The disagreements and
alternative outcomes can be appreciated as juridical attempts to account
for and respect the dhimms conception of piety and property interests,
the public good, and the integrity of the enterprise of governance. The
rules limiting the scope of the dhimms bequeathing capacity were
manifestations of a universalist ethos in the content and institutions of
law. Regardless of the analytic route any particular jurist adopted, the
legal debate in the aggregate illustrates that the intelligibility of the legal
doctrines depended on circumstances such as source-texts and legal
doctrine, as well as institutions (e.g., adjudication and taxation) of an
enterprise of governance legitimated by an Islamic universalism.
3.5.1Religious sites
The irst issue to address is whether dhimms could build new sites of
religious worship while living in an Islamic enterprise of governance.
120
121
122
123
3.5.2Religious sounds
A second issue, related to the one above, concerned the extent to which
dhimms were allowed to engage in public displays of religious practice.
Al-Marghnn, al-Hidya, :
Al-Ayn, al-Binya, :
.
Al-Mward, al-w,
Al-Ayn, al-Binya, :
.
124
Jurists of both Sunn and Sha schools generally agreed that while
dhimms could practice their faith in Muslim lands, they could not proselytize their faith, recite publicly from the Torah or Bible, or engage in
public rituals of religious signi icance, such as carrying a cross or ringing church bells (nqs). If they did so, jurists would not necessarily
consider the contract of protection breached, but they would allow the
ruling authority to subject the dhimm to discretionary punishment
(tazr). If through proselytization, dhimms directly or indirectly
caused dissension in the faith of Muslims, Sh i jurists would consider
the contract breached, thereby revoking the dhimms protected status
under the Islamic imperium and transforming him into an enemy of
the state. The legal eect of such revocation and redesignation was
that if the dhimm were killed while residing in the Muslim empire,
there would be no legal consequences on his killer, akin to what Giorgio
Agamben calls the homo sacer. These examples illustrate how the
dhimms otherness constituted not just an alternative set of values, but
was viewed as a potential threat. Recalling al-Shrzs concerns about
charitable endowments, dhimms who engaged in public displays of
religious ritual, and indeed went so far as to challenge Muslims in their
faith commitments, at the very least had to be punished and at most
were security threats against the polity.
Importantly, for some jurists the threat was not in the fact that
the dhimms performed their religious rituals, but rather that they
performed the rituals in public view. For example, the ana al-Ksn
did not permit dhimms to display the cross in public because the cross
was a sign of disbelief; but he did permit dhimms to display the cross
and ring their bells privately in their churches. In other words, dhimms
could practice their faith freely among themselves. Allowing them to
practice their faith in public, though, was an entirely di erent matter.
Such accommodation might be construed as granting their faith
tradition equal or equivalent standing with the Islamic values and
traditions that gave content to the public good of the Muslim polity, and
which the Islamic enterprise of governance upheld and protected.
Zaydn, Akm al-Dhimmiyyn,
. For Sh i authors see al-Mward, al-w,
: ; al-Muzan, Mukhtaar al-Muzan, in vol. of al-Sh i, al-Umm, :
; al-Shrz,
al-Muhadhdhab, : . See also the Sha Muh aqqiq al-ill, Shar al-Islm, :
.
Notably, whether breach of such conditions voided the contract or preserved
the contract while allowing discretionary punishment was a subject of debate. See
al-Nawaw, Rawa, :
,
; al-Ayn, al-Binya, :
.
Al-Mward, al-w, : ; al-Muzan, Mukhtaar al-Muzan, :
. For a similar conception of the enemy of the state, see Giorgio Agamben, Homo Sacer: Sovereign
Power and Bare Life, trans. Daniel Heller-Roazen (Palo Alto: Stanford University Press,
).
125
126
In this passage, al-Mward justi ied the purpose not only of the jizya,
but also of the dhimm rules more generally, by reference to a adth from
the Prophet in which the latter espoused the superiority of Islam over
all other faith traditions. For al-Mward, the import of the Prophets
statement suggested that the imm or ruler had to manifest that
superiority through the enterprise of governance and its legal regime.
Before turning to the building regulation, a brief analysis of the
supposedly prophetic statement is in order. There are two source-texts
that speak to both the wording and sentiment of the statement quoted
by al-Mward. In the irst one, a Jew came to Mudh b. Jabal (d. /
)
to seek testamentary advice concerning his heir, who was a Muslim. The
Jew was concerned that their dierence in religious belief might interfere
with his heirs inheritance rights. According to Mudh, the Prophet
stated that Islam increases ones opportunities, rather than diminishes
them (al-islm yuzdu wa l yunqiu). Mudh interpreted this tradition
to mean that the dierence in religion would not undermine the Muslim
heirs inheritance from his Jewish kin.
The second source-text is the one cited by al-Mward and is the more
commonly cited of the two. It reads: Islam is superior and not superseded
(al-Islm yal wa l yul). The tradition can be found in the collections
Al-Mward, al-w, : .
Amad b. anbal, Musnad al-Imm Amad b. anbal, ed. Samr aha al-Majzb
et al. (Beirut: al-Maktab al-Islm,
), :
( /
). Friedmann, Tolerance and
Coercion, , who also indicates variant traditions on the same theme.
In his commentary, al-Bayhaq explained that the underlying situation concerned
a child who was Muslim, but had at least one parent who was not. For al-Bayhaq,
nothing about ones Islamic belief should interfere with his inheritance. Islam, in other
words, increases and does not diminish ones opportunities: Ab Bakr al-Bayhaq,
al-Sunan al-Kubr, ed. Muammad Abd al-Qdir A (Beirut: Dr al-Kutub al-Ilmiyya,
), :
.
128
130
; al-Baht, Kashshf
131
132
133
that denied dhimms the legal capacity to use horses for transport. The
horse denoted honor, wealth, and power, all of which jurists denied to
dhimms, with certain exceptions, to ensure the latters sense of
subordination. The clothing restrictions appeared after the ban on
horses. Importantly, the clothing regulations did more than simply
distinguish the dhimm from the Muslim; they also served as a warning
of potential danger and risk. For instance, if dhimms attended the
communal bath, they had to distinguish themselves with particular
forms of dress. One jurist justi ied this requirement on the grounds
that the dhimms nakedness may pollute the water unbeknownst to the
Muslims therein. The dhimm was therefore not only marginalized
but was also deemed a threat to the health and purity of Muslims.
As was often the case with the dhimm laws, whether they were
actually enforced depended on the discretion of the ruler. Examples
of when they were enforced include the reign of the Abbsid caliph
al-Mutawakkil (r.
/
134
135
Muslims to walk through the centre. This rule both physically and
symbolically marginalizes the dhimm. While the contract of protection
permitted dhimms to reside in the Muslim polity, the dress and transit
regulations ensured that they were never considered equal or central
(literally and iguratively) to the well-being of the Muslim polity.
It is dif icult to see the dress and transport regulations as anything other
than marginalizing and subordinating. For instance, after recounting
various dhimm rules on clothing requirements, al-Ksn stated outright
that their purpose was to render the dhimm subservient and humbled
(athr al-dhill) in society. Furthermore, jurists emphasized this feature
of these rules, and even stated that the required modes of dress for
dhimms may need to dier from region to region in order to eectuate the
underlying purpose of the rules given changing cultural practices.
Given the purpose of these rules, it is not surprising that they feature in
contemporary debates about whether Islam is a tolerant or an intolerant
faith tradition. When read in isolation, it seems quite reasonable to think
that Islam and Islamic law counsel intolerance of the religious Other. In
fact, many who uphold the myth of persecution make reference to these
rules to illustrate the inherently intolerant nature of Islam, Islamic
law, and Muslims generally. Those who uphold the myth of harmony
may adopt a historicist approach and suggest that the rules were never
applied in actual fact. Between these two poles lie a multitude of
approaches, not all of which can be outlined here.
Considering these clothing and transport rules alongside the others
addressed herein, though, we can appreciate how these dress and
transport rules, through their marginalizing and subordinating eect,
contributed to the preservation of an enterprise of governance de ined
in terms of both an Islamic universalist ethos and an imperial model of
rule. The juristic debate on transport and dress requirements re lected
certain themes about the public presence of dhimms. Those themes reveal
Al-Ghazl, al-Was, :
; al-Nawaw, Rawa, :
; al-Shrz, al-Muhadhdhab,
: ; al-Ayn, al-Binya, :
; Ibn Nujaym, al-Bar al-Riq, : ; al-ab, Mawhib
al-Jall, :
; al-Qar , al-Dhakhra, :
, who states this rules comes from a adth in
the collections of Muslim (bb al-salm) and Ab Dwd (adab), via the companion Ab
Hurayra.
Al-Ksn, Badi al-ani, :
. The ana s Badr al-Dn al-Ayn and
al-Marghnn wrote that the purpose of distinguishing dhimms from Muslims was to
manifest the dhimms subordination (al-ighr alayhim) and to prevent any threat to
the faith of Muslims who might otherwise consider the dhimms as possible companions
and associates. Al-Ayn, al-Binya, :
; al-Marghnn, al-Hidya, :
. See also Ibn
Nujaym, al-Bar al-Riq, : .
Ibn Nujaym, al-Bar al-Riq, : .
Al-Mward, al-w, :
; al-Nawaw, Rawa, : . See also al-Muzan,
Mukhtaar al-Muzan, :
; al-Shrz, al-Muhadhdhab, : ; al-Qar , al-Dhakhra,
:
; Ab Abd Allh b. Mu li, al-Fur :
; al-Baht, Kashshf al-Qin, : .
136
137
138
139
140
argued that in such cases, the dhimm had no substantial incentive to lie.
In other words, the reason dhimms could not testify against Muslims
was because dhimms presumably so resented the fact of Muslim political
dominance and sovereignty that they would transfer that enmity to the
Muslim party in the court and thereby unfairly act against the individual
Muslims interest.
This ana exception is interesting because of how it linked the
exceptional rule allowing dhimms to witness in court to the overall wellbeing and security of the Islamic enterprise of governance. The exception
relies on certain presumptions that reveal how the presumed enterprise of
governance contributed to the rules intelligibility. The irst presumption
was that the dhimm resided in an Islamically de ined enterprise of
governance ruled in accordance with a Shara-based legal system. The
second is that dhimms were in a weak political position, which they
resented and would seek to overcome. The third is that dhimms would
transfer their resentment against the Muslim enterprise of governance
to individual Muslims, and thereby, for political reasons, would subvert
the justice to be meted out in a Shara-based legal proceeding. The
fourth is that while dhimms could not be witnesses either for or against
Muslims, they could participate as witnesses in cases involving other
dhimms, because while they did not share the same faith tradition,
they shared a similar subordinated socio-political status. Their shared
subordination countered any threat that a dhimm witness would alter
or adjust his testimony out of resentment against the reigning political
order. Because dhimms, whether Christian or Jew, lacked political power,
they could testify for or against each other without any worry that their
testimony might be prejudicial against a party to the case because of the
witnesss resentment about his subordinated status. Jurists assumed that
dhimms had a natural resentment against the Muslim government, and
consequently might target Muslim parties in court with false testimony
as a way to target indirectly the Muslim sovereign. Consequently, to
allow a dhimm to testify against a Muslim potentially threatened the wellbeing of the Muslim polity and its sovereign interests, albeit indirectly so.
In contrast, to allow a dhimm to testify against another dhimm posed no
threat against the enterprise of governance,
The analysis above suggests that the incapacity of dhimms to be
witnesses in court is intimately related to the way the law orders
and strati ies society and thereby contributes to the operation of the
Al-Marghnn, al-Hidya, : ; al-Ayn, al-Binya, : . Notably, both
authors denied mustamins the right to be witnesses since they have no residency in the
Muslim polity and cannot be trusted to act in others best interests.
3.9Conclusion
141
3.9 CONCLUSION
This chapter has analyzed various legal doctrines regulating dhimms.
The analysis shows that a fundamental principle animating the dhimm
rules was to recognize and manage diversity in a Muslim polity in terms
of both empire and an Islamic universalism. As indicated above, these
two imperatives did not always neatly coincide with one another, and
indeed even worked at cross purposes. The dhimm rules, thereby, were
legal symptoms of the more general challenge jurists faced when they
developed legal regimes for the purpose of governing amidst diversity.
All too often, scholars of Islamic law have researched the dhimm rules
in order to answer questions that arise in todays political climate: are
Islam, Islamic Law, and Muslims tolerant or intolerant of non-Muslims?
While it may be tempting to view these rules as indicative of either
the tolerance or intolerance of Islamic law, this chapter illustrates
that such an analytic frame is far too limiting. Indeed, the tolerance/
intolerance dichotomy poses a question that, no matter how it is
142
3.9Conclusion
143
rules together lays bare considerable insight into how public good
was itself an area of ongoing contestation and negotiation among jurists
using the instruments of law and legal argument. For instance, while
we found that dhimms were exempted from punishment for alcohol
consumption, they could not at the same time expect Muslim jurists
to protect their property interests in these items as they would other
items. This legal limit on the dhimms expectation interests illustrates
how the general ban on alcohol consumption, though not applied to the
dhimm, nonetheless contributed to a core value that jurists relied upon
to determine subsidiary rules in the areas of criminal and property law.
In this case, the ban on alcohol consumption became a juridi ied public
policy principle that gave speci ic content to the conception of the public
good, which in turn informed the jurists as they considered whether
the dhimm could petition the government to punish one who steals the
dhimms stock of alcohol.
In this example, the notion of the public good had a speci ic doctrinal
source (i.e., the source-text on alcohol consumption) that gave it content.
In other cases, the core value might be based on assumptions about the
enterprise of governance and the implication of diversity within the
polity. For instance, dhimms had the right to own homes and to bequeath
property. However, the question of whether dhimms could create
charitable endowments was not a clear matter. As noted above, the
answer depended on how the particular charitable endowment might
have contributed to and in luenced the public sphere. If the dhimms
charitable endowment was designed to feed the poor, jurists would not
object. But if the charitable endowment created and supported a Torah or
Bible reading school, the jurists were less than enthusiastic. On the one
hand, such charitable endowments would allow dhimms to ensure the
continuity of their communities, allowing the dhimms to pass on their
tradition to their children. But for some jurists, the existence of such
schools was counter to the imperatives of an Islamic universalism that
gave content and legitimating force to the enterprise of governance. Many
jurists (especially Sh i jurists) prohibited such endowments, since they
would perpetuate disbelief in Islamic lands. For others, such endowments
posed a security threat to the enterprise of governance. Indeed, al-Shrz
was notable in this regard when he equated supporting a charitable
endowment for a Torah or Bible reading school to an endowment that
armed the Muslim politys enemies. Notably, the justi ication of this legal
limitation is premised upon a particular political commitment to an
Islamic universalist ethos as de initive of the public sphere and thereby
the enterprise of governance, which jurists understood would (or should)
enforce the dhimm rules through its governing institutions.
144
4
The Rationale of Empire and the
Hegemony of Law
By viewing Shara as Rule of Law, this study has thus far aimed to
demonstrate how the intelligibility of the dhimm rules re lects the
mutually constitutive relationship between law and an enterprise of
governance that was characterized in terms of conquest, empire, and
Islamic universalism. That background factor of imperial aspiration
and organization, animated and justi ied by the universalist message
of Islam, contributed to categorizations and sub-categorizations
of dierent peopleMuslim and non-Muslim, permanent resident
(dhimm) and temporary resident (mustamin). Rules of law were then
developed to give the individuals within each category di erent degrees
of liberty and protection within the Muslim polity. The categories had
the eect of de ining who constituted the Us and the Them. Some
people, such as the dhimms, fell somewhere in between and thereby
fueled considerable legal debate about their status, liberty, and
expectation interests when living in a Muslim polity; hence the oftentimes confusing and contradictory legal doctrines on the dhimm.
The actual black letter doctrines are less central to this study than
the justi icatory arguments used to reach them, and the presumed
contextual features that made them both possible and intelligible. Those
contextual features were the subject of Chapter and gave content to the
boundaries of the claim space of Shara. As suggested thus far, Shara
as Rule of Law provides a conceptual frame that allows us to appreciate
how the law and enterprise of governance are constitutive features of
each other. Shara as Rule of Law accounts for how a governing model
(whether real or imagined) in luenced the development of doctrines
concerning the status and place of the Other in a Muslim polity. Indeed,
as suggested in Chapter , the early history of military conquest and
expansion contributed to the jurists political pre-commitments, which
146
in turn in luenced their arguments for and against certain legal doctrines
concerning the non-Muslim living under Muslim imperium.
While the focus thus far has been on the constitutive role of the imperial
model upon the content of the law, this chapter o ers a dierent approach
to the study of Shara as Rule of Law. This chapter seeks to appreciate
the way in which jurists contributed to a legal system that itself acted
hegemonically upon those who were subjected to it, speci ically
minorities. The design and operation of institutions of adjudication and
the modes of legal argument quite often operated hegemonically upon
the interests of minorities who came into the claim space of Shara to
seek justice. This chapter addresses two legal doctrines to showcase the
hegemonic nature of law when confronted with a minority claimant. The
two legal doctrines concern whether and why a dhimm was subjected
to stoning to death as a punishment of adultery, and whether or not the
dhimm could seek redress against someone who falsely accused him of
illicit sexual intercourse (qadhf, hereinafter sexual slander).
147
Jurists argued that the victim of such slander could only seek redress
against the slanderer if the former was muan.
Lexicographically, muan and its feminine form (muana) invoke
notions of chastity and purity (a f ). According to Ibn Manr (d.
/
), every chaste woman is muana . . . and every married
woman is muana. Furthermore, he wrote a muan man is [one
who is] married, where marriage renders him chaste (qad aanahu
al-tazawwuj). Accordingly, the term muan has been understood to
re lect marital status and chastity.
If we consider muan in its literal meaning, then a married dhimm
should be muan, thus being liable to stoning for adultery and entitled to
seek redress for sexual slander. But Muslim jurists denied that dhimms
are muan. Hence, they refused to permit dhimms to seek redress for
sexual slander (qadhf ). Interestingly, though, they held dhimms liable
to stoning for committing adultery. If dhimms were not muan for
purposes of sexual slander, how could they be stoned for adultery, which
required them to be muan?
The inconsistency in these legal rulings is attributable to a source-text
that was at the heart of premodern debates about the dhimms redress
for sexual slander. A tradition from Ibn Umar (d. /
), a companion
of the Prophet and the son of the second caliph Umar b. al-Khab,
reads as follows: Whoever disbelieves in God is not muan. Another
expedition, accompanied by his wife isha, who, while the forces were encamped, misplaced her necklace. She went out looking for it, and upon her return to the camp site she
discovered that everyone was gone. She stayed in that spot until the arrival of afwn
b. Muaal, who had fallen behind the army and was attempting to catch up with it. He
noticed isha and escorted her to the location of the expedition forces next camp. When
the expedition returned to Medina, isha fell ill and remained indoors. While she was
recuperating, the people of Medina began to spread rumors about an a air between
her and afwn. Exegetical sources report that Qurn : was revealed to exculpate isha. Al-Qurub, al-Jmi li Akm al-Qurn, : ; Ab al-Fal Mamd al-ls,
R al-Man Tafsr al-Qurn al-Am wa al-Sab al-Mathn (Beirut: Dr al-Fikr,
),
: ; Muhammad Husayn Haykal, The Life of Muhammad, trans. Ismail Ragi A. alFaruqi (n.p.: North American Trust Publications,
),
; M.A. Salahi, Muhammad:
Man and Prophet (Shaftesbury: Element,
);
; Martin Lings, Muhammad: His
Life Based on the Earliest Sources (Rocherster, Vermont: Inner Traditions International,
),
. Some commentators argued that a di erent verse (Qurn : ) arose
to prove ishas innocence, which speci ically refers to people who bring forth a false
allegation (i k). Al-abar, Tafsr al-abar, :
; al-Qurub, al-Jmi, : . Still others suggested that there is no speci ic historical context that the qadhf verse addresses.
Al-Qurub, al-Jmi, : .
Ibn Manr, Lisn al-Arab, : . See also al-Zabd, Tj al-Urs, ed. Al Shr
(Beirut: Dr al-Fikr,
), : .
Ibn Manr, Lisn al-Arab, : .
Al-Dr Qun, Sunan al-Dr Qun, : . This version is complemented by others with
similar meanings but dierent wording. Ab Bakr al-Bayhaq (d.
/
), when relating dierent versions of this tradition indicated how it is mawqf, which means that the
narration of the tradition stops at the Companion and does not re lect the words of the
148
version states: The people disbelieving anything about God are not
[muan]. In yet another tradition, Kab b. Mlik wanted to marry a
Jewish or Christian woman. He asked the Prophet, who advised him
against doing so and responded: She will not make you [muan]. In
other words, a Muslim man who marries a non-Muslim woman would not
be muan, given his wifes religious dierence. The dierent traditions
were subjected to critiques of authenticity; nonetheless substantively
they represent variations on a similar themenamely that non-Muslims
were not muan according to premodern Muslim jurists. Furthermore,
despite critiques of authenticity, these traditions in luenced legal debate
in no uncertain terms. In particular, jurists often cited Ibn Umars
version to deny dhimms the right to redress for sexual slander.
By denying that any non-Muslim could be muan, Ibn Umars
statement created a problem for jurists, who considered adultery to
be so harmful to society and the public good that they were unwilling
to create exceptions to the general ban for dhimms. Muslim jurists
generally considered adultery to violate a right of God (aqq Allh),
which was a technical term that often referred to the social implications
arising from a particular oense. Such acts were considered corrupt,
Prophet. Al-Bayhaq, al-Sunan al-Kubr, :
. See also Ibn al-Jawz, al-Taqq Adth
al-Khilf, ed. Muammad Fris (Beirut: Dr al-Kutub al-Ilmiyya, n.d.), :
. G.H.A.
Juynboll, Mursal, Encyclopaedia of Islam, Second Edition. Eds P. Bearman et al.; ub
li, Ulm al-adth wa Mualaatuhu (
; reprint, Beirut: Dr al-Ilm li al-Malyn,
),
.
Al-Bayhaq, al-Sunan al-Kubr, :
. This tradition involves a chain of transmission
linking Sufyn al-Thawr and Ms b. Uqba. According to al-Bayhaq, this link in any
chain of transmission is rejected (munkar).
Al-Bayhaq, al-Sunan al-Kubr, :
.
Al-Bayhaq, al-Sunan al-Kubr, :
; Ibn al-Jawz, al-Taqq, :
. This tradition is problematic because one of the narrators in the chain of transmission (Ab Bakr
b. Ab Maryam) is considered a weak link (af ) and because two of the narrators in the
chain never knew each other.
The authenticity of these traditions is not at issue here. Debates on the authenticity of adth (sing. adth) are well known, but are not central to my discussion of the
way Muslim jurists internalized a certain logic of the law and used reasoning and tradition to justify a legal decision. For the scholarly debate on adth authenticity, see Joseph
Schacht, The Origins of Muhammadan Jurisprudence (Oxford: Clarendon Press,
); M.
Mustafa al-Azami, On Schachts Origins of Muhammadan Jurisprudence (New York: John
Wiley & Sons,
); Harald Motzki, The Origins of Islamic Jurisprudence: Meccan Fiqh
Before the Classical Schools, trans. Marion H. Katz (Leiden: Brill Publications,
).
In fact, while Muslim jurists debated whether mawqf traditions can be used as legal
authority, they nonetheless were comfortable relying on Ibn Umars statement to justify
a regime of criminal liability that distributed entitlements and liabilities on the basis of
religious belief, as illustrated below. li, Ulm al-adth,
.
The fact that the term of art invokes God does not necessarily suggest such wrongs
are the most contemptible. Rather, an implication of labeling an act as violating a right of
God is, among other things, to empower the governing authorities to act on behalf of the
public to deter and ultimately punish such conduct.
149
and thus punishing them was deemed a way of ridding the world of
corruption (ikhl al-lam an al-fasd). Since adultery was deemed
to pose a public harm, it would be inconsistent for the ruling authorities
to punish only some adulterers and not others. Consequently, given the
social impact jurists imputed to adultery, they were unwilling to exclude
dhimms from punitive liability for adultery. However, a precondition
for stoning someone for adultery is that the adulterer be muan; but
the doctrine on sexual slander holds speci ically that dhimms are not
muan. Consequently, the logical implication is that dhimms should not
be stoned for adultery under Islamic law.
To subject dhimms to stoning for adultery, Muslim jurists read and
interpreted competing source-texts in light of the accommodative spirit
of the contract of protection, and the ethic of Islamic universalism. Jurists
argued that holding dhimms liable for adultery could be justi ied on an
alternative ground, namely the contract of protection. They said that if
the dhimms tradition prohibited adultery, then they shared the same
belief as Muslims about its evil and corrupt nature. Hence, punishing them
for the crime did not violate their tradition or the contract of protection.
Consequently, dhimms were prohibited from committing adultery on the
authority of the dhimms tradition as introduced into the legal analysis
via the contract of protection.
Yet if that was the case, it also raised concerns for jurists that alternative
legal doctrines (i.e., the dhimms tradition) other than Shara-based
ones could have some normative authority in an Islamic polity, though
channeled through the contract of protection. This implication, if left
unchecked, could have a signi icant impact on the constitutive features of
the claim space of Shara. Certainly, the contract of protection operated as
a Shara-based frame of analysis within which the dhimm tradition was
incorporated; further, it rendered justi iable the punishment of stoning
for adultery. Nonetheless jurists worried that doing so would introduce
the dhimms tradition as an implicit basis for legal justi ication. As such,
this legal approach raised important questions about the priority and
superiority of Shara over and against other possible authorities of law.
Al-Ayn, al-Binya, : . For others who held a similar view about the role of the
uqq Allh in generally ridding the world of corruption for the betterment of society, see
Ibn Nujaym, al-Bar al-Riq, : ; al-Khurash (also, al-Kharsh), shiyat al-Khurash
al Mukhtaar Sayyid Khall, ed. Zakariyya Umayrt (Beirut: Dr al-Kutub al-Ilmiyya,
), :
; Marghinn, al-Hidya, :
; li Abd al-Sam al-b al-Azhar, Jawhir
al-Ikll, ed. Muammad Abd al-Azz al-Khlid (Beirut: Dr al-Kutub al-Ilmiyya,
),
: . The Mlik jurist Sann wrote that when a dhimm steals, the punishment for the
add crime of theft must be applied and his hand cut o because the harm posed is a
general evil ( fasd i al-ar). But the punishments associated with drinking alcohol and
fornication are not to be applied to the dhimm. Sann, al-Mudawwana al-Kubr, :
.
150
,
.
This narrative is reported in various sources of adth. See for instance al-Nawaw,
Shar a Muslim, :
.
151
152
153
whether and to what extent the ethic of Islamic superiority was or should
be a constitutive factor of the intelligibility of Shara-based norms on the
dhimm, and whether other counteracting values could also contribute to
their intelligibility. For instance, jurists relied on Ibn Umars tradition
that an unbeliever is not muan to permit only Muslims to seek the
Qurnic form of redress for sexual slander. To explain the underlying
logic of this ruling, jurists resorted to the theme of an Islamic and Muslim
superiority and, by implication, dhimm subordination. Al-Mward, for
example, scoed at the idea that a dhimm might seek redress against a
Muslim for sexual slander. For him, a Muslim could not su er on account
of a non-Muslims dignity. The Mlik Ibn Rushd al-a d (a.k.a.
Averroes, d.
/
) explained that in invokes notions of virtue and
moral excellence ( fala), which are absent when Islamic commitment is
lacking.
Yet the superiority/subordination thematic dynamic could not hide
the fact that the sexually slandered dhimm suered an actual injury.
Indeed, jurists recognized that to disallow completely any redress for
the slandered dhimm would be unjust. In other words, an ethic of Islamic
superiority and, thereby, of dhimm subordination, may be used to
diminish the standing of the dhimm in the Muslim polity; but it could not
completely erase the fact that the dhimm suered an injury from sexual
slander. Dierence in religious conviction did not change the fact that
sexual slander harmed all people across society, regardless of how they
might otherwise be strati ied.
Consequently, while jurists did not grant the dhimm redress on
Qurnic grounds, they empowered the ruler to provide redress to
the dhimm on alternative legal grounds. They held that the ruler, as
leader of the enterprise of governance, could use the authority vested
in his of ice to enact and enforce his own ordinances to provide an
alternative legal ground by which the dhimm could seek redress.
This discretionary authority of the ruler was known as tazr. Tazr
referred to the power and authority of the ruler to legislate on an ad
hoc basis. As discussed in Chapter , tazr fell within the more general
framework of siysa shariyya and was a power that jurists granted to
the ruler to ill the lacuna that existed when no source-text addressed
Al-Mward, al-w, :
. See also al-Shrz, al-Muhadhdhab, :
.
Al-Mward, al-w, :
. The corollary of this ruling, though, is that dhimms
who sexually slander Muslims could be punished. The conditions for being a perpetrator of sexual slander did not distinguish between being Muslim and non-Muslim.
Al-Mward, al-w, :
; al-Shrz, al-Muhadhdhab, :
.
Ibn Rushd al-a d, Bidyat al-Mujtahid, :
.
Al-Shrz, al-Muhadhdhab, :
.
154
an injury that the legal system, in the interest of justice, could not
ignore. On the basis of the authority of his of ice, the ruler could
create rules by which the dhimm could seek redress for sexual slander.
These grounds would give the dhimm a form of legal redress, but on
grounds and with sanctions separate and distinct from the Qurnic
crime.
If Islamic law were purely intolerant toward the non-Muslim, it makes
little sense to grant dhimms a mode of redress in this case. Yet Islamic
law was clearly not completely tolerant and egalitarian towards the
Other, since the grant of an alternative ground for sexual slander only
emphasized the dhimms strati ied and subordinated position in the
Islamic polity. Instead of relying solely on the authority of source-texts
to ground the dhimms redress (or rather, lack thereof), the jurists
invoked a dierent authority entirely, namely the authority of the
enterprise of governance to grant legal relief to sexually slandered
dhimms. This example not only de lates the myths of tolerance or
intolerance, but it also discloses the mutually constitutive relationship
between law and the enterprise of governance. The development of
Shara-based doctrines in this case was premised upon an appreciation
of an enterprise of governance that could give relief when other
authorities fell short. By permitting the ruler to enact regulations of
his own, jurists gave dhimms legal relief; in doing so, their arguments
reveal the way in which the content of the law was developed in light of
background assumptions about the enterprise of governance. Likewise,
the authority that the enterprise of governance could lawfully exercise
(i.e., tazr) was de ined and delimited by jurists, thus showcasing how
law and legal argument constituted and ordered the polity. Reading
these rules on sexual slander together, we can appreciate the denial of
relief on Qurnic grounds and the grant of an alternate basis of relief
as re lecting the fact that the intelligibility of both rules was tied to
source-texts and institutions of authority, all of which were factored
together as jurists developed doctrines to enable e ective governance
amidst diversity.
4.3Traditions and their context: Ibn Umar and Abd Allh b. Salm 155
156
4.3Traditions and their context: Ibn Umar and Abd Allh b. Salm 157
about the muan was informed by this background of military expansion
and conquest, and not a pluralist imperial enterprise of governance.
Whatever Ibn Umar may have meant, jurists considered his tradition
a source-text for the legal de inition of muan, without regard to the
historical context that may have informed his statement. The possibility
that Ibn Umars words were framed by his narrow context of military
conquest posits a serious and signi icant conceptual distance between
what Ibn Umar may have meant, and how jurists contending with a
pluralist imperial enterprise of governance gave his words a meaning
that was informed by the challenges of governing amidst diversity.
To acknowledge this distance is to recognize that the legal content of
Ibn Umars words cannot so easily be divorced from the underlying
enterprises of governance (whether in fact or as imagined ideal) that
operated in the background for both Ibn Umar and the later jurists who
interpreted his words. In other words, to view Shara as Rule of Law is to
recognize the inevitability that the law and the enterprise of governance
are mutually constitutive. Muslim jurists, caught between the authority
of Ibn Umars tradition and a pluralist imperial vision of governance
more generally, held that to be muan, one had be free and not a slave,
had to have consummated a marriage, and had to be Muslim.
By limiting the muan to Muslims only, jurists ran up against a
dilemma. To be stoned for adultery, one must be muan. But if only
Muslims could be muan, then non-Muslims could never be stoned for
adultery, even if they were married. But as suggested above, this outcome
seemed incoherent to premodern Muslim jurists, given their concern
about a public sphere that could be threatened by unchecked illicit sexual
activity. Why should the adultery of a non-Muslim be considered any
dierent from the adultery of a Muslim? Yet, to ask this question begs the
question, why should the dignity interest of a non-Muslim be dierent
than that of a Muslim? These questions loomed large for Muslim jurists,
who relied on the various themes of contract, Islamic universalism,
subordination, and the challenge of governance amidst diversity to
harmonize competing and at times con licting source-texts, albeit often
at the expense of dhimm entitlements, as already addressed above.
158
potential of the law low from its literary style. Indeed, the narrative
shows that the dhimm rules are an example of how the law generally,
and Islamic law in particular, (re)instantiates its own authority by
demarcating between peoples, or in other words between Us and
the Other. This hegemonic dynamic is embedded in the very features
and fabric of the law, or rather in the conditions of its intelligibility. To
illustrate the hegemonic potential of legal argument and reasoning, the
tradition of the adulterous Jews will be analyzed, with special attention to
the relationships between the various participants in this legal narrative.
Of particular interest is Abd Allh b. Salm, a Jewish convert to Islam
who demanded the Torah be re-read. Abd Allh b. Salm was a Medinese
Jewish convert to Islam who was a revered Companion of the Prophet.
Reports suggest that he converted to Islam shortly after the Prophets
migration to Medina. Upon converting, he told the Prophet: O messenger
of God, the Jews are a slanderous people (qawm buht). If they learn of
my conversion, they shall slander me. To prove his point, Abd Allh
asked the Prophet to invite members of his former Jewish community
and ask their opinion of him and his conversion. When the Jews came to
Muammad, he asked for their opinion of Abd Allh. They said he was a
learned, religious man of their community. The Prophet then asked how
they would feel about Abd Allh if they learned he converted to Islam.
They expressed disdainful astonishment, after which Abd Allh came
forward to certify that he had converted. After that, the Jews said he was
ignorant, contradicting their earlier position. Abd Allh turned to the
Prophet and said: O messenger of God, didnt I tell you that they are a
slanderous people?
What it meant for Abd Allh b. Salm to be a learned Jew is unclear,
since the seventh-century Arabian Peninsula not only experienced the
continued development of Rabbinic Judaism in the Gaonic period, but
also witnessed the rise of Karaitism as a schismatic response. These
are two dierent traditions within Judaism, and both demand of their
experts dierent competencies. Consequently, when Abd Allh b. Salm
was represented as a learned Jew, to what tradition of Jewish thought and
law did that refer?
The Rabbinic account of Karaitism places its beginning in the second
half of the eighth century under the leadership of Anan b. David. Recent
scholarship, however, suggests that the Karaite movement existed during
the period of the Muslim conquests in the seventh century. Furthermore,
prior to the rise of Karaitism, other schismatic movements existed in
the region that shared a similar attitude against Rabbinic Judaism.
Al-Dhahab, Siyar, :
4.3Traditions and their context: Ibn Umar and Abd Allh b. Salm 159
Consequently, whether the Karaites existed in seventh-century CE Arabia
or not, there were schismatic Jewish movements in the area that shared
basic principles on religious authority, namely that the Bible was the sole
source of divinely inspired law. Schismatic Jewish movements, such as the
Karaites, rejected the authority of Rabbinic and Talmudic Judaism, which
are based on the Oral Tradition and proer interpretive approaches to
the Bible that depart from literal readings of the source-text.
The ambiguity in the identity of the Jews in the above narrative is
important if the reader is to appreciate who these Jews were, their
relationship to the Torah, and the way in which they would have
constructed its meaning for themselves. In other words, due attention to
the historical context of this group and the presumptions they held about
law and legal expertise prompt the reader to re lect upon how these Jews
represented their tradition to the Prophet, and how the Prophet applied
it to them sitting as adjudicator. If these Jews were Rabbinic Jews who
engaged in midrash and halakhic debates, the literal meaning of the Torah
would be less signi icant than how later Rabbis developed compelling
interpretations by which this particular community abided. If this were
the case, then their act of hiding the verse may have had more to do with
their concern about the Prophet adopting a literal reading of the sourcetext and not appreciating their interpretive traditions that surrounded
the Torah at this time. If they were a schismatic group that upheld the
centrality of the Biblical text, it might be reasonable to assume that they
would adopt a literal, textualist approach to reading the Torah. But if that
were the case, then why hide the verse? Perhaps their act of hiding the
verse might have been an act of duplicity before the Prophets court. But
why would they have brought the two adulterous Jews to the Prophet in
the irst place if they did not trust the Prophets judgment? The historical
account is not suf icient to answer any of these questions. Nonetheless,
the analysis above shows that the Jewish youths act of hiding a verse of
the Torah is not an easy matter to understand unless we could be better
acquainted with the background beliefs and values of the Jews depicted
in this tradition.
Even though we do not know whether these Jews were Rabbinic or
schismatic, or whether they had alternative modes of resolution at their
Leon Nemoy and W. Zajaczkowsk, Early Karaism, The Jewish Quarterly Review , no.
(
):
; L. Nemoy and W. Zajczkowski, Karaites, Encyclopaedia of Islam, Second
Edition, IV:
; Samuel C. Heilman, Karaites, Encyclopedia of the Modern Middle East and
North Africa, eds Philip Mattar et al. (New York: Macmillan Reference,
), :
;
Daniel Lasker, Eli Citonne and Haggai Ben-Shammai, Karaites, Encyclopaedia Judaica,
Second Edition, eds Michael Berenbaum and Fred Skolnik (Detroit: MacMillan Reference,
), :
; Daniel Frank and L. Nemoy, Karaites, Encyclopedia of Religion, Second
Edition, ed. Lindsay Jones (Detroit: Macmillan Reference,
): :
.
160
disposal, we can presume from the narrative that Abd Allh b. Salm
would have known. This raises a fundamental question of why he was
there to begin with, and about his role in the narrative of adjudication.
If they were Rabbinic Jews, then his focus on the text of the Torah
would have shown considerable bad faith and manipulation. If they
were schismatic, then perhaps his focus on the text might have been an
attempt to cross-examine others whom he felt were (mis)representing
a foreign legal tradition, out of respect for the integrity of the Prophets
adjudicatory role as both fact inder and legal adjudicator. Without any
information about the Jews at issue, we cannot determine whether it was
the Jews or Abd Allh b. Salm who was acting in good or bad faith when
covering or uncovering the relevant verses of the Torah.
The act of hiding the verse has still more to say about the concept of
Shara as Rule of Law. Hiding the verse was represented as a mark of
Jews disingenuity and dishonesty with respect to the scriptural text.
Later jurists viewed it as an attempt to depart from the word of God. If
anything, the narrative of condemnation operated as a vindication of the
authority of the text, which re lects an important value in Islamic law and
legal reasoning. In other words, if the Jews in the narrative were Rabbinic,
it might make sense for them to hide the verse if they were concerned that
the Prophet would not understand or appreciate their approach to Jewish
law. The later reprobation of their act in Islamic sources arguably has
less to do with these Jews conception of the Torah, and more to do with
vindicating the Islamic legal approach to the primacy of the scriptural
text as an authoritative source of law.
If the story has more to do with the dynamics of Islamic legal authority
and interpretation, and less to do with the Jews and their representation
of the Torah, then a critical reader should pay heed to the dynamics of
the adjudication itself. Between Abd Allh and the Jews sat the Prophet
as the arbitrator. The Prophet sat, observed, inquired, and decided. He
was far from being the animating force behind the drama; indeed, his
distance from the human and community drama permits the reader to
see the Prophet as representing a dispassionate justice.
On the intimate connection between the Torah and Talmud for Rabbic Judaism in
the th century CE, see Rosenberg and Rosenberg, Of Gods Mercy,
. On the role of
custom in the Gaonic period see Gideon Libson, Jewish and Islamic Law: A Comparative
Study of Custom During the Gaonic Period (Cambridge: Harvard Law School,
).
In this case, we may wonder why the Jews brought their case to the Prophet at all,
if they were worried about how the Prophet would understand their law. There is little in the evidence to answer this question. What we have, though, is a narrative about
recourse to an institution of justice, without any awareness of whether alternative
modes of resolution existed for this Jewish community.
4.3Traditions and their context: Ibn Umar and Abd Allh b. Salm 161
Abd Allh, however, had an interest in proving his loyalty to Islam
by testifying against his former community. Abd Allh b. Salm was
represented as both knowledgeable of the Jewish tradition, and as a
righteous member of the Muslim polity. In the narrative, he was, in other
words, one of Us; but because of his special knowledge of the Jews, he
played the role of the native informant, helping the Us understand and
regulate the Other. Why the Jews sought the Prophets adjudication is
not clear from the tradition. But they clearly had an interest in presenting
the Torah on their terms, and not on someone elses.
In the end, though, the Prophet had to decide. He consulted all parties
involved and even showed judicial restraint and humility by requesting
a Jewish law expert to inform him about the demands of Jewish law. As
arbiter, the Prophet evoked a respect for the defendants, the Jewish
tradition, and the neutrality of the judicial of ice in the interests of
justice. And yet, he did not defer to the Jews construction of their law.
Their representation, eectively, became nulli ied. Instead he looked to
Abd Allh, operating in the narrative as a native informant, to ensure
that the Prophets justice was done. The Prophet was neither protagonist
nor antagonist in the human drama, but he was the legal authority
who decided the outcome and the way in which the Others law was
represented and given eect.
Arguably, one implication of this tradition, if viewed through the
lens of Shara as Rule of Law, is that legal systems do not contend with
legal pluralism very well. Alternative normative bases of decision may
be brought to a court or adjudicator, but no matter how di erent that
alternative basis may be, the court will nonetheless understand it, and
thereby (re)present it on its own terms. In this case, at the same time
that the Prophet sought to respect the Other by learning his or her
tradition, he could not entirely trust the Jews representation of their
tradition. Recall that after the Jews presented their communitys
treatment of adulterers, the Prophet asked them to bring the Torah to
con irm their position and to ensure that they were being truthful (i.e.,
in kuntum diqn). To trust the Jews in this case would be akin to
granting legal authority to a dierent normative tradition, and to
operationalize it within the prevailing mechanisms of law. The more
any foreign law does not conform to the prevailing legal order, the
more the adjudicator will re lect and represent that foreign tradition
in a manner that most accords with the prevailing legal system, in
Elsewhere, I have shown that this occurred to Muslims and the construction of
Islamic law under the colonial period of the th and th centuries. See Anver M. Emon,
The Limits of Constitutionalism in the Muslim World: History and Identity in Islamic
Law, in Constitutional Design for Divided Societies, ed. Sujit Choudhry (Oxford: Oxford
162
4.4 CONCLUSION
The juxtaposition of Chapters
and
provides distinct analytic
approaches to the dhimm rules while building on the same, fundamental
theme that lies at the heart of this study. In Chapter , with each
examination of a legal rule, the reader was introduced to the ways in
which general rules of application coexisted with rules of exception for
the express purpose of illustrating the complex challenges of governing
amidst the fact of diversity. Chapter has o ered a deeper historical and
textual analysis of the dhimm rules to show how Shara as Rule of Law
reveals how legal argument and reasoning have their own hegemonic
potential. Both chapters, together, show that Muslim jurists made
choices in their reasoning processes that had to do with more than just
University Press,
),
; idem, Islamic Law and the Canadian Mosaic: Politics,
Jurisprudence, and Multicultural Accommodation, Canadian Bar Review , no. (
,
forthcoming); idem, Conceiving Islamic Law in a Pluralist Society,
.
Premodern Islamic legal theory (ul al- iqh) upholds the priority of the apparent
meaning (aqq, hir) over the literary or metaphorical (majz). Mohammad Hashim
Kamali, Principles of Islamic Jurisprudence, rd ed. (Cambridge: Islamic Texts Society,
),
. See also, Hossein Modarressi, Some Recent Analysis of the Concept of
majz in Islamic Jurisprudence, Journal of the American Oriental Society
, no. (
):
; Wol hart Heinrichs, On the Genesis of the aqqa-majz Dichotomy, Studia
Islamica (
): .
4.4Conclusion
163
164
5
Shara as Rule of Law
Part I focused on the treatment of non-Muslims under premodern Islamic
legal doctrines. It analyzed various legal doctrines to accomplish two
distinct, but interrelated theoretical interventions. First, the analysis
showed that to frame the dhimm rules in terms of tolerance/intolerance
overdetermines their meaning and implication. Indeed, that particular
frame more often has less to do with the historical jurisprudence of
Islamic law, and more to do with contemporary debates (and often
polemics) about Islam and Muslims today. Second, the analysis has oered
an alternative conceptual frame for analyzing the dhimm rules, namely
Shara as Rule of Law. As noted at the outset of this study, Rule of Law
here is used to re lect the claim space within which claims of justice are
made. Equally important is that the claim space connoted by Rule of Law
is bounded or disciplined in light of considerations that extend beyond
the parties to a particular case, and include systemic concerns that
make justice (and its enforcement) possible, intelligible, and legitimate.
In other words, what allows claims to resonate as legal argumentto
be intelligible as a species of legal argumentare the boundaries that
delimit the claim space.
The aim of this chapter speci ically, and Part II more generally, is to
explore in greater detail the nature of those boundaries, and appreciate
how their alteration over time shifts the intelligibility of a claim about the
law. With respect to the intelligibility of Islamic legal arguments, Part II
will reveal that the historical shift in the enterprise of governance, from
the imperial to the international state system, has altered the conditions
of intelligibility for the dhimm rules today. But beyond focusing on the
Islamic context, Part II will also feature an analysis of court decisions
from the United States, United Kingdom, and France concerning the
covered Muslim woman. The juxtaposition of the legal treatment of
the Other in premodern Islamic law, the modern Muslim state, and the
modern constitutional democratic state will show that regardless of
168
169
Abou El Fadl, Speaking in Gods Name ; Emon, To Most Likely Know the Law,
.
For a discussion on the relevance of the distinction between Shara and iqh, and
its relationship to philosophical themes such as authority and objectivity, see Emon, To
Most Likely Know the Law.
170
governance, and ensure their capacity to interpret and engage the religiolegal tradition.
Certainly, the modern state of a airs of Shara is distinct from what
existed in the premodern period, where the doctrines of the historical
tradition are viewed as having developed outside the enterprise
of governance, and where the moral authority of the Shara was
principally held, in ideal terms, by jurists working outside the enterprise
of governance. In contrast, in the modern world, law-making and
legitimized coercion are often considered to be rightfully and legitimately
in the hands of a centralized sovereign state government that issues
decrees or legislation de ining the law for a region that is delineated by
geo-political territorial boundaries. Indeed, the centralizing feature
of the modern state is perhaps its most notable characteristic for some
political theorists. The state operates within an international system
in which all states are considered equal sovereigns and entitled to their
territorial integrity. These states engage each other as actors on a global
stage, whether through trade negotiations, diplomatic relations, or
international organizations such as the United Nations.
The rise of the modern state has led some commentators to fear that
Shara is dead, and instead has become a tool of political elites. The
death of Shara, they argue, can be traced to a variety of factors: the
nineteenth-century reformist e orts in the Muslim world; the advent
of the modern, bureaucratic state; or the degeneration of Muslim civil
society institutions that had, in the premodern period, contributed to
vibrant intellectual discourse and debate. Those states, whose territory
was once under the rule of Islamic empires, often incorporate Islamic
Emon, Islamic Law and the Canadian Mosaic,
, emphasizes the role of European transplants in displacing the jurisdiction of a historically de ined Islamic law in the Muslim
world.
171
law in their legal systems, but only in piecemeal fashion. Such states
generally adopt only premodern Islamic family law in modern personal
status codes, while borrowing or modifying legislative schemes
from European and North American states on matters of obligations,
procedure, commercial law, inance, and so on. Modern lawyers in
Muslim states that apply Islamic law do not often study Islamic law in
the fashion once taught in premodern madrasas (Islamic law colleges)
centuries ago, but instead take a few courses on the topic, while focusing
mainly on a secularized legal curriculum. In fact, Lama Abu-Odeh
has vociferously argued that to understand Islamic law in the modern
day, one need not concern oneself with the premodern period at all.
Islamic law today is immersed within a complex, bureaucratic state
system, in which Islamic law is a partial source, if even that, for legal
systems that are primarily based on European models of civil law and
governance.
If this captures the modern Shara today, why should anyone take an
interest in considering Shara as Rule of Law? We cannot ignore that
many Muslim majority states espouse in their constitutions that Islam is
the religion of the state and that the laws of Islam are a or the source
of law for the state. They incorporate aspects of Islamic law in their
legislation. And Islamic law features in contemporary political debates
about the nature and future of many regions and countries in the world.
Perhaps such states are engaged in a delusion, which indeed some have
suggested. Perhaps such states are making an e ort to incrementally
Islamize over a period of time. Or perhaps such states are using Shara in
a more general contest over political legitimacy. This study is mindful of
the competing views on Shara today, while remaining agnostic on what
Muslim states (and their elites) are intending to do by invoking Islamic
law. What seems clear for the purposes of this study, though, is that Shara
Abu-Odeh, The Politics of (Mis)representation,
,
.
Abu-Odeh tells of her own legal education in Jordan, where she took only three
courses on Islamic law (marriage, divorce, and inheritance) over a four-year legal curriculum: Abu-Odeh, The Politics of (Mis)recognition,
.
Abu-Odeh, The Politics of (Mis)recognition.
For an analysis of such provisions in state constitutions in the Muslim world, see
Clark Lombardi, State Law as Islamic Law in Modern Egypt (Leiden: Brill,
). See also,
Emon, The Limits of Constitutionalism in the Muslim World,
(Oxford: Oxford
University Press,
).
Hallaq, Can the Shara be Restored?
See for example, Muhammad Taqi Usmani, The Islamization of Laws in Pakistan:
The Case of Hudud Ordinances, Muslim World , no. (April
):
, who writes
about the onerous but important task of Islamizing.
For the political implications of Shara, see Anver M. Emon, Techniques and Limits
of Legal Reasoning in Shara Today, Berkeley Journal of Middle Eastern & Islamic Law ,
no. (
): .
172
173
aspects of the boundary that demarcated the claim space of Shara that
premodern Muslim jurists imagined. Re lecting on those aspects will
provide a historical comparator for the later discussion in this chapter
and Chapter on the intelligibility of the dhimm rules speci ically, and
Islamic law more generally, in the modern Muslim majority state.
Contemporary scholars suggest that premodern Islamic law is
best characterized as decentralized and pluralistic, in the domain of
jurists and not state agents. But that does not mean that those who
claimed to represent Shara did not imagine themselves as somehow
contributing to the governance of society, whether in terms of either
an idealized Islamic polity or holding actual of ice. Indeed, the political
legitimacy of a premodern Muslim regime was often considered, in
part, dependent upon the application of Shara within the polity.
Likewise, the development of Shara-based doctrines cannot be
divorced from the social and institutional context in which jurists
found themselves. That social context may have included transmitted
doctrines, the institutionalization of the scholarly profession, and even
the institutions of justice within which jurists participated (either
directly or indirectly).
An example will help illustrate the nexus between legal debate
and the enterprise of governance in the work of premodern Muslim
jurists. The irst example concerns whether the crime of qadhf or false
accusation of illicit sex (sexual slander) presented a public wrong or
a private one (aqq Allh or aqq al-ibd). While most jurists agreed
that it was an oense against both the public and the individual,
they debated whether it was primarily a public wrong or primarily a
private wrong. Their answer to that question made possible a series of
procedural rules. For instance, the more they considered the o ense a
public wrong, the more likely would they expand the standing of those
who could petition for redress, or deny the victim the ability to waive
any redress whatsoever. The more they considered qadhf a private
wrong, the more they empowered the individual victim to bring suit or
waive any redress, and so on.
Abdullahi Ahmed An-Naim, Islam and the Secular State: Negotiating the Future of
Shara (Cambridge: Harvard University Press,
), ;
; S.D. Goitein, A Turning
Point in the History of the Muslim State, in Studies in Islamic History and Institutions
(Leiden: Brill,
),
,
; Abou El Fadl, Speaking in Gods Name, . For further
discussion on this point, see below.
Crone, Gods Rule, Government and Islam; Ann K.S. Lambton, State and Government in
Medieval Islam: An Introduction to the Study of Islamic Political Theory: The Jurists (Oxford:
Oxford University Press,
).
Emon, uqq Allh,
.
174
175
176
177
reason was only authoritative because the Qurn said it is: Ibn Rushd,
as noted above, derived the authority of reason from the authority of
the Qurn.
The signi icance of approaching Shara as Rule of Law is that the
elements of reason and authority are equally part of the analysis. One
is not excluded in favor of the other; rather, both are recognized as
mutually contributing to the intelligibility of arguments made from
within the claim space of Shara, in which reasoned deliberation
operated within bounds de ined by authoritative features that both
disciplined the scope of reasoned argument and granted it legitimacy.
178
179
180
181
182
183
the enterprise of governance. Tazr and siysa shariyya were legal terms
of art that jurists used to juridify the zone within which the political
leader could legitimately delineate new rules in light of new situations
without recourse to substantive Shara-based doctrines. Jurists
recognized their own limitations in delineating legal doctrines or iqh,
yet used the law to give limited authority to those entrusted with the
enterprise of governance to govern as they saw it. The jurists were not
able to determine the content of such discretionary regulations; but they
nonetheless sought to de ine the zone within which such regulations
could legitimately arise. By juridifying this zone of discretionary
authority, jurists used legal doctrine both to constitute and to delimit the
enterprise of governance.
This section has juxtaposed two seemingly distinct areas of discourse
in which premodern Muslim jurists both articulated how traditions of
value conditioned the legitimacy an enterprise of governances sovereign
can enjoy, and created zones of authority within which the ruling
authority could exercise administrative discretion. At one and the same
time, jurists conditioned and de ined the terms by which an enterprise
of governance could claim legitimacy, and granted that same enterprise
the authority to act pursuant to its own discretion. The ruler could decide
how to regulate matters pursuant to metrics having little or no basis in
arguments of legality. Such regulations, though, were authoritative and
legitimate because they fell within the area of discretion granted to the
ruler by the law. The juxtaposition of these two lines of inquiry show that
conceptualizing Shara as Rule of Law allows us to appreciate the mutually
constitutive relation between the law and the enterprise of governance.
Far from checking the excesses of the enterprise of governance, the law
legitimated the rulers discretionary decision-making power. Indeed,
Shara as Rule of Law oers a frame for us to recognize and understand
the dual role jurists played when developing the law: establishing the
conditions of legitimacy of an enterprise of governance, while enabling
its operation pursuant to a zone of discretionary power that was not
necessarily subjected to legal review.
184
185
186
187
n.
188
why one of them should yield to the opinion of the other. According
to al-Juwayn, the parties had to submit their con lict to a judge to
resolve the dispute. According to al-Juwayn, the judge would decide
the matter as he or she saw it. Importantly, though, the authority of
the judges determination did not rest on the substantive rule of law
relied upon to resolve the dispute. Rather the judges determination
was authoritative, for al-Juwayn because of the imperium tied to his
institutional position.
In this example, al-Juwayn implicitly revealed how the background
factor of the enterprise of governance informed his analysis of this
particular hypothetical. The signi icance of this assumption can be
determined by asking a corollary question about al-Juwayns analysis.
Reasoning counter-factually, suppose al-Juwayn made no assumptions
at all about an enterprise of governance, or even more, suppose he
assumed there was no enterprise of governance at all. In such a case, he
arguably would not have referred to the q, since the q would not
have been a factor to incorporate into his analysis. He would have had
to decide the con lict between the parties on other grounds, not making
recourse to this particular procedural approach. What those alternative
grounds might have been are hard to speculate on al-Juwayns behalf.
Nonetheless, the counterfactual illustrates how presumptions about the
enterprise of governance not only contributed to, but also made certain
legal outcomes intelligible.
This section suggests that any neat bifurcation between the jurists
and the ruling elite becomes blurry once Shara is viewed as Rule of Law.
The respective arenas of law and governance necessarily overlapped.
Not only did jurists accept appointments to government of ices, but
they also took into account the facticity of those governmental of ices
as they developed their jurisprudence and legal doctrines. This is not
to suggest that Shara as Rule of Law collapses law into the realm of
politics, or that law bears no autonomy whatsoever. Indeed, as Sherman
Jacksons work on al-Qar suggests, the corporate identity of the
madhhab could hold back an enterprise of governance that sought to
exert authority, if not dominance, in the realm of law. But it would be
far too simplistic, if not nave, to think that the law and the enterprise of
governance ever were or could be separable in anything but some form
of ideal theory.
189
190
),
.
George Makdisi, The Rise of Colleges: Institutions of Learning in Islam and the West
(Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press,
), . Many other authors stress that the
subject matter taught in the masjids was the law, and that it is this early concern for
the law that eventually gave the madrasa its character as a college of law. Jonathan
Berkey, Transmission of knowledge in Medieval Cairo: A Social History of Islamic Education
(Princeton: Princeton University Press,
), ; Pedersen and Makdisi, Madrasa,
.
Notably, there is some disagreement on this point. See A.L. Tibawi, Origin and Character
of Al-Madrasah, Bulletin of the School of Oriental and African Studies , no. (
):
191
Makdisi indicates, though, that under the Mlik school, such a possibility does not
exist. The Mliks do not permit a donor to appoint himself or herself as the administrator of a waqf-based institution he or she endowed. Makdisi, Rise of Colleges,
.
Pedersen and Makdisi, Madrasa,
.
Writing in
, Ulrich Haarmann noted that no comprehensive study of the beginnings of waqf was available. Ulrich Haarmann, Mamluk Endowment Deeds as a Source
for the History of Education in Late Medieval Egypt, Al-Abhath (
): , .
For studies on the ulam, see Cl. Gilliot, R.C. Repp, K.A. Nizami, M.B. Hooker, ChangKuan Lin, and J.O. Hunwick, Ulam, Encyclopaedia of Islam, Second Edition Eds P.
Bearman et al.; Muhammad Qasim Zaman, The Ulama in Contemporary Islam: Custodians
of Change (Princeton: Princeton University Press,
).
Pedersen and Makdisi, Madrasa,
.
192
arts. It was this early history of the pre-madrasa period that de ined
what would be taught in the madrasa, thus constituting a curriculum
of education that gave content, and thereby shape, to the claim space of
Shara.
The course of study to become a jurist generally included four years
of training in religious law and ten or more graduate years, leading to
a license to teach. The graduate students were trained in the scholastic
method, and studied various topics in the course of becoming a jurist,
such as the following:
Qurn: including interpretive sciences, exegesis, and the various
readings of the text;
adth: including the interpretive tradition, biographies of
transmitters;
Principles of Religion (ul al-dn);
Principles of Law (ul al- iqh), i.e., the sources and methodologies
of law;
the legal doctrine of the school of law to which one belongs;
the divergent doctrines within one school and across legal schools.
This curriculum required the student to engage foundational sources
of authority whose provenance was understood according to Islamic
jurisprudence to originate with God (e.g., Qurn) and the normative
practice of the Prophet. Given the foundational role these and other
sources played in the curriculum of Shara-based education, the
curriculum gave disciplinary content to the claim space of Shara, and
thereby helped de ine and delimit it.
The ful illment and satisfaction of curriculuar requirements would
culminate in an ijza or diploma of successful completion of a course of
study, thus guarantee[ing] the transmission of authoritative religious
knowledge. An ijza could be issued upon completing a single book or
mastering an entire subject area. These diplomas could also authorize
the recipient to teach and issue legal responsa (ijza al-tadrs wa al-ift).
The conclusion of a course of study in the Islamic educational process
was marked by the student receiving such certi ication. Hence the ijza
assumed a central place within the system of education; it was a measure
193
194
law school af iliations. Each had their own teachers and institutions for
appointing faculty. While Makdisi would agree that the jurists constituted
a signi icant political force, he shows that any attempts to control the
ulam, or jurists, via the Nimiyya were doomed to failure because of
the diversity of schools, with their attendant diversity of opinions, in the
vicinity.
Furthermore, Jonathan Berkey suggests that the institutional setting
of the madrasa was less signi icant to the education of a jurist than the
informal relationship a student had with his teacher. Berkey argues
that the informality of teacherstudent relationships, rather than
the formality of madrasa institutions, characterized the premodern
Islamic educational system, thereby making the political contest over
the madrasa less signi icant for Berkey. [T]he institutions themselves
played no actual role in Islamic education . . . Islamic education
remained fundamentally informal, lexible, and tied to persons rather
than institutions. Berkey bases his argument, though, on negative
evidence. He argues that many deeds of trust for madrasas do not
mention salaries to teachers or stipends for students. Furthermore, he
notes that biographical dictionaries generally do not mention the speci ic
schools where scholars taught or studied. Berkey recognizes that none of
this evidence suggests that teaching did not occur in such institutions.
Rather, he argues that premodern contemporaries considered the
venue of instruction and education to be of secondary importance: what
was critical was the character and knowledge of the individuals with
whom one had studied.
Between Tibawi, Makdisi, and Berkey, we ind competing views
about the signi icance of the madrasa, as both a site of legal education
and a site of political contest. Often this di erence plays into arguments
about the autonomy of legal learning from government manipulation
or centralization. The more one emphasizes the personal relationship
between the teacher and student, the more one implicitly supports the
thesis of decentralization between the jurists and the ruling elite. This
historical debate has the potential to fuel contemporary debates about
the nature of Shara, and whether modern state e orts to codify Islamic
law are legitimate, true, or authentic. This study remains agnostic on the
dierent positions noted above about the site of legal education in the
premodern period. Furthermore, even if Berkey is correct in asserting
the priority of the teacherstudent relationship, nothing denigrates the
institutional role of the madrasa in organizing and ensuring a system
Makdisi, Muslim Institutions.
Berkey, Transmission, .
Berkey, Transmission,
196
.
On the early history of adth and its contribution to legal analysis, see Coulson, A
History of Islamic Law,
; Ignaz Goldziher, Introduction to Islamic Theology and Law,
trans. Andras and Ruth Hamori (Princeton: Princeton University Press,
); Bernard
Weiss, The Spirit of Islamic Law (Athens, Georgia: The University of Georgia Press,
).
On the authority and canonization of adth, see Jonathan Brown, The Canonization
of al-Bukhr and Muslim (Leiden: Brill,
).
198
200
indebted inancially. Indeed, if the thief were poor, the debt might be so
burdensome as to be tantamount to a second punishment. Therefore,
the Mliks concluded that if the thief was suf iciently wealthy from
the moment he stole to the moment his hand was amputated, he had to
pay compensation. But if he was poor in that period, he owed no
compensation. For the Mliks, the prospect that such a inancial debt
might be punitive seemed unduly retributive.
What we see in this brief iqh analysis is the role of the jurist as
interpreter of the laws. As interpreter, the jurist was presumed to bring
a wealth of training about the Qurn and prophetic traditions, methods
of interpretation, and knowledge of the vast body of rulings of his own
legal school and others. Bringing them all to bear in his legal analysis
required an awareness of the authority of source-texts, where they were
dispositive, where they were ambiguous, and the lacuna in the sourcetexts that needed to be supplemented with reasoned legal analysis.
Between the source-texts and the iqh rules lay the jurist as interpreter
who, as a product of a curriculum of training, derived rules of law.
The dierent legal opinions and rationales illuminate why iqh is a
particulary appropriate term for these rulings, given that they represent
a human attempt to understand Gods will. The Arabic triliteral root f-q-h
linguistically refers to the capacity and e ort to understand, all the while
implicitly recognizing, in the context of law, the epistemic vulnerability
of any legal determination. Premodern jurists were well aware of
the need to interpret; but they also recognized that the inescapability
of interpretation introduced a degree of indeterminacy and fallibility
into the law. Too much indeterminacy and fallibility could undermine
the authority of the law and thereby the con idence in an enterprise of
governance whose legitimacy was in part dependent on enforcing that
law.
To embrace the imperative of interpretation and to limit its adverse
implications on the authority of the law and the enterprise of governance,
jurists debated about the appropriate quali ications for and scope of
legal interpretation. Their concern about authority and its limits, in large
part, animated their debates about ijtihd and feeds the present studys
interest in the boundaries of Shara as a claim space. Furthermore, given
that jurists were the ones engaging in ijtihd, the theoretical debates on
the conditions for engaging in ijtihd beg further questions about the
authority of legal doctrines proered by an interpretive agent who was
202
and thereby implies that law is a much more creative and constructive
enterprise. Legal analysis, given this latter theological view, would
be less about inding or discovering the immanent law and more
about constructing a legal rule that is mindful of God but nonetheless
responsive to the highly contingent realities of everyday life.
Those who believed there was only one right answer justi ied their
position by reference to two adths. In the irst one, Muammad
stated: There are three types of judgments: one leads to heaven and
two lead to hell. The one leading to heaven [concerns] one who knows
the truth and decides in accordance with it. One who knows the truth
but deviates from ruling [according to it] goes to hell, and one who
ignorantly adjudicates for the people goes to hell. This tradition sets
up the importance of epistemic excellence in adjudication. Even if one
adjudicates but is ignorant, the adjudicator is condemned for lacking the
appropriate expertise to undertake the task he ultimately did anyway.
Whether the ignorant adjudicator gets the right answer does not seem
to matter. As Ibn Qayyim al-Jawziyya wrote, whoever adjudicates in
a state of ignorance will go to hell, even if his judgment is right. Of
course, this should not render the substantive judgment irredeemable.
Its provenance may raise doubts about its authority, but presumably
that could be recti ied by a later jurist who ful ills the necessary due
diligence.
The second adth was critically important to the right answer thesis.
In it, Muammad said: When a judge interprets to adjudicate and gets
the right answer, he receives two rewards. If he adjudicates and gets the
wrong answer, he gets one reward. This adths meaning, however,
draws upon an implicit intertextuality between it and the irst adth
noted above. In other words, the reference to the judge in the second
adth should be read as invoking someone with the requisite training
and expertise to engage in ijtihd. When reading the two traditions
together, the second adth assumes that those who are rewarded for
their ijtihdwhether right or wrongperformed their due diligence
Ibn Qayyim al-Jawziyya, Awn al-Mabd: Shar Sunan Ab Dwd (Beirut: Dr
al-Kutub al-Ilmiyya,
), :
; Ibn Mjah, al-Sunan, eds Muammad Nir al-Dn
al-Albn and Al al-alab al-Athar (Riyadh: Maktabat al-Marif,
), :
. For
reference to this tradition, see also al-Nawaw, Shar a Muslim, / :
; Ibn
ajar al-Asqaln, Fat al-Br, : .
Ibn Qayyim al-Jawziyya, Awn al-Mabd, :
.
For various accounts of this tradition, see Ibn Mjah, al-Sunan, :
; Ab Bakr b.
al-Arab, riat al-Awadh b Shar a al-Tirmidh (Beirut: Dr al-Kutub al-Ilmiyya,
), : ; al-Mubrak Fr, Tufat al-Awadh bi Shar Jmi al-Tirmidh (Beirut:
Dr al-Kutub al-Ilmiyya, n.d.), :
; Ibn Qayyim al-Jawziyya, Awn al-Mabd,, :
;
al-Nawaw, Shar Sa Muslim, :
; al-Ayn, Umdat al-Qr, :
; Ibn ajar
al-Asqaln, Fat al-Br, : .
204
206
5.6The modern state & disruptions of history in claim space of Shara 207
The boundaries of the Rule of Law claim space can shift for a variety of
reasons. In the Islamic context, such shifts arose as a result of colonial
domination; the rise of the modern state system; and a diversi ication
(as well as internationalization) of legal education, legal disputes,
and legal adjudication. The premodern image of Shara as Rule of Law
today suers from a discontinuity brought on by European colonialism
and the introduction of the modern state in an international system of
equally sovereign states. When we speak of Islamic law today, we must
recognize that we are subject to a distinctively di erent enterprise of
governance than what animated the premodern juristic imagination.
We are also embedded in a context of considerable legal pluralism,
wherein the historical tradition of Shara o ers only one among many
traditions that can and do constitute the boundaries of the claim spaces
of modern states. This last section oers a brief account of the shifts and
changes in the way the modern state governs (in contrast to the imperial
vision discussed earlier). Those shifts not only rede ined the boundaries
of the claim space of Shara, but also the very intelligibility of a Sharabased argument today.
208
Jasper Y. Brinton, The Mixed Courts of Egypt, rev. ed. (New Haven: Yale University
Press,
), .
Brinton, The Mixed Courts, .
For a history of the Mixed Courts of Egypt, see Brinton, The Mixed Courts.
David S. Powers, Orientalism, Colonialism, and Legal History: The Attack on
Muslim Family Endowments in Algeria and India, Comparative Studies in Society and
History , no. (
):
,
.
5.6The modern state & disruptions of history in claim space of Shara 209
To challenge the continuity of these family awqf, two tactics were
adopted: marginalize Islamic law by substituting new legal orders, and
reinterpret and re-assert Islamic law for Muslims, who were deemed
unable to see the truth of their own tradition. However, as Powers
explains, the new legal regimes were not suf icient to settle the matter
of waqf land held in perpetuity. While the government developed new
legislative schemes, French jurists began expounding on various features
of Islamic law, in particular the family waqf. As Powers notes, French
orientalist scholars rede ined Islamic law so that it would be in harmony
with French legal conceptions.
Importantly, this pattern of limiting or removing the jurisdiction
of Shara-based doctrines and institutions was not perpetuated only
by colonial administrators and of icials. It was done by Muslim elites
themselves, working within the prevailing systems of governance while
contending with the increasing plurality of legal regimes with which
they came into contact. For instance, in the late nineteenth century, the
Ottoman Empire initiated a series of legal reforms that involved adopting
and mimicking European legal codes as substitutes for Islamic legal
traditions. This imitation of form should not be viewed narrowly as
an attempt to modernize by abandoning the Islamic tradition. Frederick
F. Anscombe oers an important insight into the logic of this Ottoman
reform period, known as the Tanzimat. Given domestic contests over
power and legitimacy within the Ottoman Empire, the Tanzimat were
attempts to modernize, but not at the cost of Islam; on the contrary,
Anscombe argues that the reforms were meant to bolster the regimes
religiously based legitimacy. Although labelled as westernization, such
reforms, when considered alongside prevailing domestic political issues,
were fundamentally shaped by, and for, Muslim interests: healing
divisions within the community of believers, reconciling their enduring
goals, and concentrating their energies upon defense against external
threats. Nevertheless, for the purposes of this study, the Tanzimat
reforms and others like them were indigenous responses to colonial
advancement and legal imposition. In the language of post-colonial
theory, they might be understood as subaltern resistance against colonial
domination. In oering their own interpretations and codi ications of
Powers, Orientalism, Colonialism, and Legal History.
Powers, Orientalism, Colonialism, and Legal History,
.
The reforms emanating from this period are called collectively, the Tanzimat. For
a history of the reforms in this period, see Herbert J. Liebesny, The Law of the Near &
Middle East: Readings, Cases and Materials (Albany: State University of New York Press,
), .
Frederick F. Anscombe, Islam and the Age of Ottoman Reform, Past and Present
(August
):
,
.
210
5.6The modern state & disruptions of history in claim space of Shara 211
Egyptian court systems: the Mixed Courts, the secular National Courts,
and the Shara courts. Then, in
Egypt adopted a uniform civil
code borrowed mostly from the French Civil Code, and which also
incorporated minimal elements of Islamic law. Subsequently, in
the
Shara courts were disbanded in the country.
These examples illustrate how, under colonial in luence, the space for
Shara diminished as legal reforms were implemented, thereby creating
a claim space whose boundaries were de ined no longer by Sharabased doctrines or even presuppositions of an imperial enterprise of
governance. Rather, in the colonial context, the intelligibility of prior
Shara-based doctrines, to the extent they were even applied, assumed a
new meaning and signi icance. They were embedded in highly pluralist
legal contexts in which the Rule of Law claim space was no longer de ined
in the same way premodern Muslim jurists may have assumed.
For a discussion of the gradual demise of Shara courts in Egypt, see Nathan
Brown, The Rule of Law in the Arab World: Courts in Egypt and the Gulf (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press,
).
For a historical account detailing the move from Islamic to secular law in Egypt,
see Brown, The Rule of Law in the Arab World, esp. .
212
The following four examples will illustrate how modern Rule of Law
systems shift the conditions of intelligibility of Shara-based doctrines.
For instance, the modern legal curriculum in law schools across the Muslim
world is substantially dierent from what prevailed in the premodern
madrasa. The course of study to become a legal specialist in the premodern
period involved considerable study of source-texts such as the Qurn
and adth of the Prophet, theories of interpretation and legal reasoning,
theology, and so on. In Muslim states where Islamic law is a feature of the
legal system, students of law still take courses in Islamic law and legal
methodology. However, as Lama Abu-Odeh recounts her legal eduction in
Jordan, law students only take two or three courses on Islamic law during
the course of legal study, which often spans a number of years.
A second example concerns the drafting of modern civil codes and the
space for Islamic legal content in determining the law of Muslim states.
For instance, when Abd al-Razzq al-Sanhr drafted the Egyptian Civil
Code of
, he relied heavily on the French Civil Code. He was careful,
though, to create some space for the potential contribution of Islamic
law to the new Egyptian legal order. Reducing the meaning of Shara
to doctrinal premodern rules of law (or iqh), he held that the iqh could
ill in any lacuna in the Code or customary law, so long as no iqh ruling
contravened a general principle of the Code.
A third example, related to the second one just noted, concerns the
limited extent to which Islamic legal doctrines are actually legislated and
applied in Muslim countries. The one ield of Islamic legal doctrine that
is most commonly found in modern state legal systems is Islamic family
law (al-awl al-shakhiya). Both colonial administrators and Muslim
nationalist assemblies preserved Islamic family law in codi ied form
while modernizing other legal areas such as commercial law, contract law,
property law, and so on. Indeed, Muslim majority states often implement
modi ied versions of premodern Islamic family law in modern personal
status codes, while borrowing or modifying legislative schemes from
European and North American states on matters of obligations, procedure,
commercial law, inance, and so on. This preservation of family law
Abu-Odeh, Politics of (Mis)recognition,
.
Abd al-Razzq al-Sanhr, al-Was Shar al-Qnn al-Madan al-Jadd, ed.
Amad al-Margh (Cairo: Dar al-Nahda al-Arabiyya,
), : .
For an introduction to the premodern doctrinal tradition of family law and its
implementation in modern states in the Muslim world, see Jamal J. Nasir, The Islamic Law
of Personal Status, rd ed. (London: Graham & Trotman,
).
For a study on the development of Jordans Islamic family law regime, see Lynn
Welchman, The Development of Islamic Family Law in the Legal System of Jordan,
International and Comparative Law Quarterly , no. (
):
.
Abu-Odeh, The Politics of (Mis)recognition,
,
.
5.6The modern state & disruptions of history in claim space of Shara 213
arguably placated Islamists who felt threatened by modernization and
considered the preservation of traditional Islamic family law to be
necessary to maintain an Islamic identity in the face of an encroaching
modernity. Yet the preservation of these premodern doctrines in
modern statutory format runs contrary to these same states commitments to human rights treaties, many of which address, for instance,
gender equality. The con lict between these two regimes, of law (Islamic
family law and human rights law) raises important questions about the
intelligibility of these states family law regimes in large part because
modern Muslim states not only legislate premodern Islamic family law,
but they also ratify international human rights treaties and appear before
treaty bodies to account for and explain their eort (or failure) to improve
the conditions of gender equality under their domestic legal regimes.
A fourth and inal example involves the resort to constitutionalism as
a means of imposing structure and limits on the state and protecting the
rights of the states subjects, such as religious minorities, for example.
Locating an authentic past on the bodies of women within the family has been
used to construct modern national identities in post-colonial societies where the past
provides an authentic basis for the national identity of new states immersed in a modern
world. Traditional family law regimes may be used to bring the values of the past into the
present national consciousness to provide a sense of identity in opposition to the norms
perceived to emanate from the colonizing world. For an excellent analysis of women, family, and nationalism, see Anne McClintock, Family Feuds: Gender, Nationalism and the
Family, Feminist Review
(
): . For studies on Islamic law, women, and the
state, see Denise Kandiyoti, Women, Islam and the State, Middle East Report
(
):
; Mervat F. Hatem, Modernization, the State, and the Family in Middle East Womens
Studies, in A Social History of Women & Gender in the Modern Middle East, eds Margaret
Meriwether and Judith E. Tucker (Boulder, Colorado: Westview Press,
), . One
exception to this colonial-inspired narrative about the narrowing of Shara is the case of
Saudi Arabia. Colonial powers did not seem to exert as much control over Saudi Arabia,
and consequently the colonial narrative does not universally apply across the Muslim
world. However, I would suggest that the narrative about the reduction of Shara is not
dependent on colonization as its only topos. Rather, the colonial topos is only part of the
narrative, which fundamentally involves a relationship between power, law, and the formation of political/nationalist identities. For instance, colonists used a reductive but
determinate notion of Islamic law to bolster their legitimacy and ensure administrative
ef iciency, while also marginalizing the tradition when necessary to attain colonial goals.
Likewise, the Saud familys use of Wahhabism as an ideological narrative that trumped
tribal loyalties in the Najd, has also allowed the Saudi state to utilize a reductive, often
literalist approach to Islamic law to bolster its own political legitimacy and authority.
On the con lict between Islamic family law and international human rights law,
see Women Living Under Muslim Laws, Knowing Our Rights: Women, Family, Laws and
Customs in the Muslim World (New Delhi: Zubaan,
); Ann Elizabeth Mayer, Islam and
Human Rights: Tradition and Politics, rd ed. (Boulder: Westview Press,
). For an
analysis of the dialogue between international treaty bodies and Muslim states regarding gender equality, see Ann Elizabeth Mayer, Internationalizing the Conversation on
Womens Rights: Arab Countries Face the CEDAW Committee, in Islamic Law and the
Challenges of Modernity, eds Yvonne Yazbeck Yaddad and Barbara Freyer Stowasser
(Walnut Creek: AltaMira Press,
),
.
214
For analysis of the historical rules of Shara as well as critiques of how Muslim
states use Shara to discriminate against non-Muslims, see Zaydan, Ahkm al-Dhimmiyn;
An-Naim, Toward an Islamic Reformation; Dallal, Yemeni Debates on the Status of NonMuslims in Islamic Law, ; Atabani, Islamic Sharah and the Status of Non-Muslims,
; Rahman, Non-Muslim Minorities in an Islamic State, ; Faruqi, The Rights of
Non-Muslims under Islam, .
See for example, Bahrain (Art. ), Mauritania (Art. ), Malaysia (Art. ); Morocco
(Art. ), Saudi Arabia (Art. ), Yemen (Art. ), Tunisia (Art. ).
See, for example, Albania (Art. ).
See, for example, Ethiopia (Art. ), Azerbaijan (Art. ).
See, for instance, Bahrain (Art. ), Egypt (Art. ), Kuwait (Art. ), Oman (Art. ),
Qatar (Art. ), Syria (Art. ). For a sustained review of constitutions in the Arab world,
see Nathan J. Brown, Constitutions in a Non-Constitutional World: Arab Basic Laws and the
Prospects for Accountable Government (SUNY Press,
).
5.6The modern state & disruptions of history in claim space of Shara 215
clauses are listed among the earliest provisions of basic rights and
occur without limitation or restriction.
Additionally, Muslim-majority countries may include rights provisions
that protect ones religious freedom. Article ( ) of Indonesias
constitution provides: The State guarantees all persons the freedom of
worship, each according to his/her own religion or belief. Other countries
adopting this unrestrictive approach include: Bosnia-Herzegovina
(Art. II, Para. ), Eritrea (Art. ), Malaysia (Art. ), Mali (Art. ), and
Morocco (Art. ).
But some Muslim countries provide qualifying remarks concerning
the scope of ones religious freedom. Article
of Bahrains constitution reads: Freedom of conscience is absolute. The State shall guarantee the inviolability of places of worship and the freedom to perform
religious rites and to hold religious processions and meetings in accordance with the customs observed in the country. Article of Kuwaits
constitution reads: Freedom of belief is absolute. The State protects the
freedom of practicing religion in accordance with established customs,
provided that it does not con lict with public policy or morals. Both
examples illustrate how a statement of absolute freedom is coupled
with ambiguous limiting language about customs, public policy, and
morals.
As noted earlier in the case of the dhimm rules, the ambiguity of terms
like public policy or public good raise important questions about who
is the relevant public and what is its conception of the good or the moral.
The constitutions noted above do not oer any express de inition of such
terms, and thereby cause concern to some that to preserve public policy,
core values, or morals, the rights of individuals (i.e., religious minorities)
will be curtailed and limited. As will be shown in the next chapter, this
concern is not unfounded.
For the purpose of re lecting on Rule of Law as an analytic lens for
understanding Shara as Rule of Law, the four examples addressed
(curriculum, legal pluralism, Islamic family law, and Islamic constitutionalism) reveal how the intelligibility of Islamic legal argument
today requires a close analysis of the constitutive features of a given
Article of the Eritrean Constitution allows for limits on the rights enumerated
in the constitution on the grounds of national security, public safety, economic wellbeing of the country, or the public morals and public order of the nation.
However, the substantive protection these provisions provide religious minorities is subject to further speculation. For instance, although Malaysias Article grants
all people the right to profess and practice their religion, the Malaysia case involving
Lina Joy suggests that the courts may abdicate their protective role. See Chapter for an
extended analysis of that case.
Emphasis added.
Emphasis added.
216
5.6The modern state & disruptions of history in claim space of Shara 217
legitimacy and distinguish itself internationally without at the same time
isolating itself on the global stage.
In looking to the past for a sense of identity, Muslim states certainly
had options from the Islamic intellectual tradition. Perhaps u ism, with
its mystical tradition, could have been a source of national identity.
Likewise, the Islamic philosophical tradition raised considerable
questions about religion, politics, and identity that could have been
harnessed for creating a sense of the political self. But such substantive
modes arguably lack a determinacy that, as already noted above in the
case of ijtihd, could pose challenges to the legitmacy and authority of an
enterprise of governance.
If determinacy was important for purposes of authority and
legitimacy in the twentieth centurys post-colonial context, it remains
important for anchoring a national identity for post-colonial states in
the twenty- irst century. It is unsurprising that these states turned
to historical Islamic legal norms (i.e., iqh), since those doctrines
provided an easy and ef icient option for newly fashioned Muslim
states in the twentieth century. The determinacy of Islamic rules of
law can give content to an otherwise nascent modern state, and
thereby constitute (in part) the boundaries of newly developed,
modernizing legal regimes. Muslim states have incorporated
Islamic law in their legal systems to o er determinate content for
their legal systems, and thereby contribute to the authority and
legitimacy of the new Muslim majority state. From a Rule of Law
perspective, we can appreciate how historical doctrines have played
two distinct but related roles, namely to give content to the legal regime,
and to contribute to the authority and legitimacy of an enterprise of
governance arising from the ashes of colonialism.
On how Islamic fundamentalists anchor disputes on political identity by reference
to historical tradition, see Roxanne Euben, Enemy in the Mirror: Islamic Fundamentalism
and the Limits of Modern Rationalism: A Work of Comparative Political Theory (Princeton
University Press,
).
Historians have noted how Su i movements have provided an impetus for independence movements against colonial occupation. Itzhak Weismann, Taste of Modernity:
Su ism, Sala iyya, and Arabism in Late Ottoman Damascus (Leiden: Brill,
).
Euben, in her Enemy in the Mirror, writes about the communitarian logic underlying Islamic fundamentalism. Her important work is signi icant for understanding
the role of tradition and its perceived continuity into the present as a basis for identity
construction.
In fact, the th-century Muslim reformer Muammad Abduh argued that a
nations laws respond to its prevailing contexts, and thereby suggests that the meaningfulness of law depends on whether it re lects the circumstances, mores, and identity of
its people: Abduh, Ikhtilf al-Qawnn bi Ikhtilf Awl al-Umam,
.
See Hallaq, Can the Shara be Restored? This is especially true in light of the
fact that most Muslim countries do not use Islamic law throughout their legal systems,
218
but only in piecemeal fashion in areas like family law and less often in criminal
law.
M. Cherif Bassiouni, Leaving Islam is not a Capital Crime, Chicago Tribune (April
,
), C ; Margaret Wente, Death to the Apostate, The Globe and Mail (March ,
), A ; Wesal Zaman and Henry Chu, Afghan case dropped but not closed, Los
Angeles Times (March ,
), A . For an extended analysis of that case, see Anver M.
Emon, On the Pope, Cartoons and Apostates: Sharia
, Journal of Law and Religion
, no. (
):
.
For the Iraqi Constitution, see <http://www.uniraq.org/documents/iraqi_constitution.pdf> (accessed March ,
).
Abu-Odeh, The Politics of (Mis)recognition.
5.7Conclusion
219
The ongoing relevance of Islam and Islamic law in the Muslim world,
though, does not change the fact that by taking a reductive, piecemeal,
and at times ambiguous approach to Shara, colonial powers and Muslim
elites fundamentally shifted the conditions of intelligibility of Sharabased normative claims. For many, Shara is rigid and static: a divine
legal system comprised of dogmatic rules and incapable of revision.
As this study suggests, this reductive vision of Shara as rules of law
(and not Rule of Law) re lects the way in which modern legal systems
in Muslim states constitute a claim space where the boundaries have
drastically shifted. Consequently, the modern resort to premodern
rules of Shara arguably re lects less about the premodern tradition of
Shara, and more about the contested conditions of legality, legitimacy,
and authority in the modern post-imperial and post-colonial Muslim
state.
5.7 CONCLUSION
De ining Shara is never an easy matter. Some note its lexical meaninga
way to the watering holethereby emphasizing the sustaining life
force that Shara oers to those who pursue and adhere to it. Others
focus on the rules and treatises that re lect the substantive doctrine of
the tradition. Yet others concentrate on the theoretical literature of
Interview with Dr. Rabab El-Mahdi, Middle East Law and Governance , nos &
(
):
,
. On the distinct and divergent trends within Islamist groups, such as the
Muslim Brotherhood of Egypt, see Carrie Rosefsky Wickham, The Muslim Brotherhood
and Democratic Transition in Egypt, Middle East Law and Governance , nos & (
):
.
For a discussion of the impact the rei ied and static version of Islamic law had on
Muslims under colonial occupation, see the excellent study by Scott Alan Kugle, Framed,
Blamed and Renamed: The Recasting of Islamic Jurisprudence in Colonial South Asia,
Modern Asian Studies , no. (
):
.
Ibn Manr, Lisn al-Arab, : .
Laleh Bakhtiar and Kevin Reinhart, Encyclopedia of Islamic Law: A Compendium of
the Major Schools (Chicago: Kazi Publications,
).
220
5.7Conclusion
221
222
This study avoids adopting any particular narrative about the fate
of Shara. To put it dierently, the issue is not about whether Shara
remains alive or is dead, or is a delusion of Islamists. Indeed, even a
cursory review of contemporary political science journals suggests that
Islam and Islamic law are not disappearing. Far from it. Instead, what
has changed is the underlying conditions of intelligibility, in particular
the enterprise of governance. This change has dramatic implications
on the constitution of the claim space within which Shara-based
claims are made, and thereby on the intelligibility of old rules that are
re-implemented in the modern state. In other words, by viewing Shara
as Rule of Law, the intelligibility of legal doctrines can be tracked over
time as the mutually constitutive relationship between the law and the
enterprise of governance changes as each constituent element changes.
This historical dimension to Rule of Law analysis presents an important
implication for any methodology of Islamic legal scholarship: any change
to the enterprise of governance will change the intellgibility of rules
developed under one model of governance but applied in another. As the
enterprise changes, so too will the claim space within which Sharabased claims are made, and thereby the conditions of intelligibility that
gave meaning to premodern legal doctrines and discourses. The modern
state, immersed in an international system, is beset by a plurality of legal
regimes, of which Shara-based doctrines are one; all of them help de ine
the claim space of modern Rule of Law systems, and all of them claim a
degree of authority in conferring legitimacy to the governing process.
To suggest that the alteration to the conditions of intelligibility heralds
the death of Shara or renders Shara a delusion is e ectively to render
Shara into an ideal type insulated from the conditions of goverance in
which nonetheless it was and remains embedded. Envisioning Shara as
Rule of Law, however, avoids such essentialization. The history of shifts
in the enterprise of governance reveals a fundamental di erence
between the premodern imagination of the conditions of intelligibility
and the modern conditions; yet what the di erent sets of conditions
share is how both the law and the enterprise of governance are mutually
constitutive, conferring content, authority, and legitimacy to each
other in dierent and distinct ways. By avoiding the essentialization of
Shara, and instead viewing Shara as Rule of Law, the reader can
appreciate the multitude of ways in which the law, in this case Islamic
law, is both constitutive of and constituted by the evolving context of
governance, and how the circumstances of that relationship contribute
to the intelligibility of a given claim about the demands of justice.
6
The Dhimm Rules in the Post-Colonial
Muslim State
In the twenty- irst century, debates about Islamic law and the dhimm
rules are embedded in a social, cultural, and political context that is
not only far removed from what existed centuries ago, but which also
gives to the dhimm rules an intelligibility that is quite di erent from
what transpired in the premodern period. For instance, for proponents
of the myth of persecution to read the dhimm rules as evidence of the
intolerance of Islam, from the time of the Medinan polity till today, is
implicitly to ask a modern question about tolerance concerning rules
of law that were answers to premodern questions of considerably
dierent provenance than our own. The implicit question is not wrong
so much as misdirected. Likewise, for Islamists to adhere to the dhimm
rules as an Islamic model of tolerance and pluralist community is to rely
on premodern answers to questions that arise from modern dynamics
of the international state system and transnational networks of
community and exchange.
To understand the meaning and signi icance of the dhimm rules
today requires an appreciation of how the political and legal landscape
has shifted since the premodern period. For instance, as suggested
in Chapter , Muslim jurists developed their legal doctrines in the
context of a discipline of legal study and a juristic profession, and were
likely cognizant of the ways in which the discipline of their profession
contributed to, and was also constituted by, the various features of an
enterprise of governance. The jurists discipline of inquiry rested upon
theories of authority, a corpus of foundational source-texts, institutions
of adjudication, and a constantly evolving and often tense relationship
between them and the ruling authorities. The previous chapters have
shown how premodern Muslim jurists developed legal rules pursuant to
their interpretive authority, which was itself embedded in a discipline,
224
225
often than not is made to refer to premodern texts and doctrinal rules
that re lect a political, social, and cultural context long gone, and with
few if any institutional structures that provide continuity in the process
of mediating between text and context. When we speak of Islamic law
today, we are not generally referring to Shara as Rule of Law, but
rather to Shara-based doctrines as one among many constitutive
features of a modern Rule of Law claim space. For modern Muslims living
as minorities and for Muslim-majority states that consider themselves
Islamic, the historical shifts in law and the enterprise of governance
present a new context in which old answers lose their relevance.
Old answers are neither right nor wrong, but rather fail to account for
what David Scott calls, in his acclaimed critique of post-colonial theory,
a history of the present. Scott argues that the present poses a new set of
questions that the anti-colonial answers of the early twentieth century
no longer answer. The rise of former colonies to the status of independent
nation states may have constituted the hoped-for future for anti-colonial
theorists of the late nineteenth and early twentieth centuries, but at the
beginning of the twenty- irst century, Scott poignantly recognizes that
the anti-colonialists hopes, fashioned against the colonial enterprise,
have not materialized with the independence of former colonies. He
writes painfully and powerfully:
In many parts of the once-colonized world . . . the bankruptcy of postcolonial regimes is palpable in the extreme . . . The acute paralysis of will and
sheer vacancy of imagination, the rampant corruption and vicious authoritarianism, the instrumental self-interest and showy self-congratulation
are all themselves symptoms of a more profound predicament that has, at
least in part, to do with the anxiety of exhaustion. The New Nations project
has run out of vital sources of energy for creativity, and what we are left
with is an exercise of power bereft of any pretense of the exercise of vision.
And consequently, almost everywhere, the anticolonial utopias have gradually withered into postcolonial nightmares.
226
227
.
Eleanor Abdella Doumato, Manning the Barricades: Islam According to Saudi
Arabias School Texts, Middle East Journal , no. (Spring
):
,
.
228
229
the English is translated begs various questions not only about the
intelligibility of the dhimm rules in the context of this premodern text,
but also (and most importantly) about the signi icance and intelligibility
of Reliance as a text of general educational reference for a transnational,
post-colonial Muslim readership. For example, the Arabic text provides
that dhimms:
must abide by Islamic law;
are punished for illicit sexual relations and theft, but not for being
intoxicated;
must dress dierently from Muslims to be distinct and dierent;
and
may not erect their buildings higher or of equal height as the
buildings of Muslims.
The Arabic text also provides that dhimms are forbidden to build new
churches, but it provides an exception to this general ban: if there is
a treaty between Muslims and non-Muslims, non-Muslims are not
prevented from building religious places of worship if they so choose.
Importantly, this exception is in brackets in the Arabic text; Keller did
not translate this exception into English. So while he translated the rule
demanding that dhimms wear distinctive dress, he did not translate the
exception that permits non-Muslims to build churches in the event of a
treaty. This exception is not the only Arabic phrase he failed to translate.
He did not translate, for instance, the rule permitting non-Muslims to
ride mules and asses but not horses.
Kellers translation of Umdat al-Slik, therefore, is not a full or
complete translation of a premodern text. Keller states in his introduction
that [n]ot a single omission has been made from [the Arabic text],
though rulings about matters now rare or nonexistent have been left
untranslated unless interesting for some other reason. Parts untranslated are enclosed in brackets [in the Arabic]. When he chooses not
to translate selections of the Arabic text, Keller encloses the relevant
Arabic passages in brackets, but does not indicate in the English text
when and where he omits his translation. He refuses to include ellipses
in the English section since the omitted section is provided fully in
Arabic and in brackets, which he writes was felt to suf ice. At most,
Reliance of the Traveller is a modern (re)presentation of a premodern text.
Consequently, its intelligibility and signi icance cannot be measured in
terms of the historical context in which the original text was written.
Al-Mir, Reliance, Ix.
230
Nor can the words on the page, in particular the English words, be read
uncritically, as if their meaning is transparent.
Without an express explanation from Keller, any assessment of why
certain portions are translated and others are not translated is tentative.
But a comparison of Kellers choices with the rationales of the rules
as noted in Chapter may reveal how Reliance is very much a modern
project. As noted in Chapter , premodern Muslim jurists debated
whether dhimms could erect new religious buildings or renovate
dilapidated ones. As was discussed earlier, whether dhimms could do so
depended on the type of land they occupied, their land tax liability, and
whether the Islamic enterprise of governance took control over the land
by conquest or treaty. But in the modern context, none of these factors
would seem relevant given the absence of an Islamic imperial enterprise
of governance. There is no Islamic empire that is conquering new lands
with non-Muslims residing therein. The exception in the original Arabic
re lects a premodern imagination about the mutually constitutive
relationship between law and an imperial enterprise of governance. In
the absence of such an enterprise of governance, the exception to the
general ban is hardly relevant to the modern Muslim. However, and
most tellingly, the same could be said about the general ban itself. In
the absence of an imperial enterprise of governance, why the need to
preserve the general ban on the construction of churches? Perhaps the
general ban is translated without the exception to pro er a romantic
image of a Muslim world re-possessed of its former imperial glory. The
translation of the ban, without the exception, gives Muslims a telos of
redemption, a romantic image of hope, at a time when Muslims live in a
post-imperial and post-colonial world where the former glory of Muslim
empire has ended. It acts like a balm to the modern pain of subservience
Muslims and Muslim majority states suer in their post-imperial and
post-colonial condition.
Indeed, some who adopt the myth of persecution read the English text in Kellers
Reliance as if it were transparently meaningful. They do not problematize the text,
nor consider the ideological aim of the translator as equally, if not more, signi icant to
the design and structure of the text. See, for instance, Spencer, Islam Unveiled,
.
However, as suggested above, such a reading of Reliance ignores how the text is doing
more than simply conveying the past tradition to a modern audience. It is reshaping it
and repackaging it in light of conceptions of identity and community that are not explicitly acknowledged in the text.
Scholars and Muslim reformists have deeply criticized the e ect of the West and
modernity on the nature and organic integrity of Islam for Muslim today. These criticisms are perhaps so ingrained in and accepted by those such as Keller and the authors of
the Saudi textbooks as to animate a framework of analysis that requires no justi ication.
Much has been written on Islam and modernity. For some useful references, see Bassam
Tibi, The Crisis of Modern Islam: A Preindustrial Culture in the Scienti ic-Technological Age,
trans. Judith von Sivers (Salt Lake City: University of Utah Press,
); Fazlur Rahman,
231
232
While other countries may not be explicit about their reliance on the dhimm rules,
they nonetheless distinguish between religious groups, thereby perpetuating at the very
least the ethos of di erence, and at the very most, the ethos of Islamic superiority.
233
234
235
236
237
who was once Muslim and later abandoned Islam, and so became a nonMuslim, could still enjoy the bene it of an Islamic identity over and against
someone born, raised, and murdered as a non-Muslim.
Muslim jurists defended this discriminatory application of qi
liability by reference to a adih in which the Prophet said: A believer
is not killed for an unbeliever. Importantly, the full tradition states: A
believer is not killed for an unbeliever or one without a covenant during
his residency. Jurists who constructed discriminatory rules of liability
relied on the irst half of the adth. Furthermore, they argued that these
discriminatory rules re lected the fact that Muslims were of a higher
class than their non-Muslim co-residents. For instance, the Sh i jurist
al-Mward argued that, as a matter of law, someone from a lower class
(al-adn) could be executed to vindicate the interests of someone from
a higher class (al-al), but the opposite could not occur. He justi ied
this legal distinction in eschatological terms by citing Qurn : ,
which states: The companions of the hell ire are not equivalent to the
companions of heaven. From this he concluded that just as the Qurn
denies any equivalence between these groups in eschatological terms,
the law should deny any equivalence between them in material terms.
Furthermore, using the logical inference of a minore ad maius, al-Mawardi
held that just as a Muslim bears no liability for sexually slandering a
dhimm (see Chapter ), he cannot be liable for killing one, a much more
serious oense.
238
This is not to suggest that all Muslim schools of law held to this
discriminatory application of capital punishment. As explained
below, ana jurists rejected such discriminatory legal applications,
especially when considering the above adth with both halves together.
Anticipating a ana critique, though, al-Mward narrated an incident
involving the important premodern ana jurist Ab Ysuf (d.
/
).
According to the story, Ab Ysuf sentenced a Muslim to death for
killing a non-Muslim, which was consistent with Hana i doctrine. But he
subsequently received a disconcerting poem criticizing him for doing so.
The poem read as follows:
O killer of Muslims on behalf of unbelievers!
You commit an outrage, for the just are not the same as the oppressor.
O those of Baghdad and its vicinity, jurists and poets!
Ab Ysuf [commits] an outrage on the faith when he kills Muslims for
unbelievers.
Make demands, cry for your faith, and be patient, for reward belongs
to the patient.
Troubled by the thought of a public outcry, Ab Ysuf informed the
Abbsid caliph Hrn al-Rashd (r.
/
) about his
predicament. Al-Rashd advised him to use a technical legal loophole
to avoid the execution sentence, and thereby dodge any social discord
( itna). Speci ically, Ab Ysuf learned that the victims family could not
prove that they paid their poll-tax ( jizya). Therefore, they could be denied
the full protection of and entitlements under the contract of protection.
As a result, Ab Ysuf did not execute the Muslim, and instead held him
liable for wrongful death damages. Al-Mward, however, glossed the
entire story by suggesting that since the original decision led to public
dissatisfaction (i.e., itna), it was right and good to avoid that decision
generally.
Despite this story and al-Mwards gloss on it, ana jurists justi ied
executing a Muslim for killing a non-Muslim by reference to a tradition
in which the Prophet did so, saying: I am the most ardent to uphold
[ones] security. The ana Badr al-Dn al-Ayn explained that jurists
of other schools discriminated against non-Muslims because they
Al-Mward, al-w, : .
Al-Mward, al-w, : .
Muammad b. al-asan al-Shaybn, Kitb al-Al :
(Wizrat al-Marif lilukma al-liyya al-Hindiyya,
), required that the murder be intentional (amd);
al-Ayn, al-Binya, : ; al-Marghnn, al-Hidya, :
.
Al-Ayn, al-Binya, : ; Ibn Nujaym, al-Bar al-Riq, : ; Ab Bakr al-Kasn,
Badi al-ani, :
. Notably, al-Mward, al-w, : , held this tradition to be
weak.
239
240
the same protections under the law. Religious commitment was not a
relevant factor for them to determine the scope of ones legal entitlements
to wrongful death damages. Rather, what mattered for the ana s was
whether or not the non-Muslim claimants had a contract of protection,
thus rendering them dhimms and bringing them within the polity on
equal grounds as Muslims.
To justify their position, the ana s looked to Qurn : , which
addresses the case of a Muslim who has killed another: and if he [the
victim] is from a people with whom you have a treaty (mithq), his people
are entitled to a diyya musallama, and [the killer] must free a believing
slave. The reference to diyya musallama is not entirely clear. Literally, it
refers to an agreed upon amount. What that amount might be, though,
was subject to debate among premodern jurists. For ana s, the diyya
(compensation) owed should not be reduced in the case of dhimms;
for them, Muslims and non-Muslims were entitled to the same diyya for
wrongful death. As additional support for the ana position, Ibn
Nujaym referred to the view of the fourth caliph, Al b. Ab lib (d. / ),
who held that since dhimms were obligated in the same way as Muslims,
they also enjoyed the same entitlement to damages for personal injury.
The above discussion illustrates how Muslim jurists contended with
competing themes of subordination, inclusion, and accommodation
to determine the rules of tort liability amidst religious di erence in
the Muslim polity. The dierent views indicate that no single position
was objectively true or inevitable. Rather, jurists ruled in the light
of competing presumptions about identity, community, and political
society that constituted the conditions of intelligibility that gave shape
to the claim space of Shara.
Beyond the juristic debates, however, one issue remains to be
addressed, namely the initial animus for a premodern rule that
halved the dhimms wrongful death compensation. The early Muslim
historian al-Zuhr recounted that during the era of the Prophet and
his irst four successors, non-Muslims would receive the same wrongful
Al-Ayn, al-Binya, : ; Ibn Nujaym, al-Bar al-Riq, : ; al-Ksn, Badi
al-ani, :
; al-Marghnn, al-Hidya, :
; Ab Abd Allh al-Marwaz, Ikhtilf
al-Fuqah (Riydh: Maktabat Adwa al-Salaf,
),
.
Al-Ksn, Badi al-ani, : .
Al-Ksn, Badi al-ani, : ; al-Qurub, al-Jmi li Akm al-Qurn,
:
. Al-Qurub relates competing positions among the legal schools, including a
tradition from the Prophet in which Muammad decreed for the People of the Book half
the diyya of a Muslim.
Ibn Nujaym, al-Bar al-Riq, : .
For a biography and analysis of al-Zuhrs historical contributions, see A.A. Duri,
The Rise of Historical Writing Among the Arabs (Princeton: Princeton University Press,
).
241
242
243
But Saudi Arabia has not rati ied this convention, and so recourse to it
will yield little by way of persuasive, let alone coercive force.
Certainly these international documents are important references for
those committed to international human rights. They may even bolster
the eorts of various states to put pressure on a country such as Saudi
Arabia to modify its legal system to comport with general human rights
principles. However, the problem with the mere resort to human rights
documents is that it prioritizes one form of legal authority without
adequately accounting for the others that, in the aggregate, contribute
to the conditions of intelligibility within a Saudi Arabian Rule of Law
claim space. This is underscored by the fact that many Muslim countries
ratify international humanitarian conventions with reservations that
limit their acceptance of the conventions to the extent that they require
violation of the Shara. As noted above, Saudi Arabias Basic Law
emphasizes the authority of the most fundamental source-texts of Islamic
law, the Qurn, and traditions of the Prophet. Saudi Arabias national
Mayer, Islam and Human Rights; idem, Internationalizing the Conversation on
Womens Rights,
; Belinda Clark, The Vienna Convention Reservations Regime
and the Convention on Discrimination Against Women, The American Journal of
International Law (
):
.
244
vision and legitimacy has been built upon its commitment to Islam, albeit
a particular approach to Islam associated with the eighteenth-century
reformer Muammad b. Abd al-Wahhb.
An alternative approach, premised on the separation of church and
state, might emphasize the need to create a state that treats its citizens
equally and opts out of the business of legislating on or about Islam or
Islamic law. The separation approach, much like the human rights
approach, is committed to improving the status of religious minorities
in Saudi Arabia by emphasizing the idea of the citizen as the natural
category of belonging in the modern state. To pro er this solution,
though, is to ignore the history of Saudi Arabia and the way in which Islam
and Islamic law have cast the nation, or in other words, have constituted
the enterprise of governance. Indeed, such an approach continues to
fail because it does not account for the way in which the law and the
enterprise of governance are mutually constitutive.
The authority of international legal authorities exists alongside the
authority of Islamic legal sources, and both contribute to the boundaries
of Saudi Arabias Rule of Law claim space. They have di erent
provenances, and will have dierent weights in dierent states,
depending on what legal issue is at stake. A Muslim state such as Tunisia
may show an af inity for certain human rights norms over and against
a more strict reading of Islamic legal rules on marriage and polygamy.
For Saudi Arabia, its Islamic ethos is a cornerstone of its claim to
legitimate sovereignty. As such, while it participates in the international
system, it will often do so only to the extent that abiding by international
norms does not violate principles of Shara. But importantly, unlike
the premodern context, only the government has the power to decide
For an example of this argument, see An-Naim, Islam and the Secular State.
Tunisia has banned polygamy, despite various Islamic legal sources that permit it.
Abdullahi Ahmed An-Naim, Islamic Family Law in a Changing World: A Global Resource
Book (London: Zed Books,
),
.
For a useful resource of countries and the international treaties (humanitarian
and otherwise), see the website maintained by the International Committee of the Red
Cross (<http://www.icrc.org/ihl.nsf>) , which includes a list of humanitarian conventions which Saudi Arabia has signed, rati ied, or to which it has acceded. To the extent
that Saudi Arabia has rati ied international humanitarian treaties and conventions, it
does so with reservations in favor of Shara. This practice is common among Muslim
states: Michele Brandt and Je rey A. Kaplan, The Tension between Womens Rights and
Religious Rights: Reservations to Cedaw by Egypt, Bangladesh and Tunisia, Journal of
Law and Religion , no. (
):
; Andra Nahal Behrouz, Transforming Islamic
Family Law: State Responsibility and the Role of Internal Initiative, Columbia Law
Review
, no. (June
):
; Rebecca J. Cook, Reservations to the Convention
on the Elimination of All Forms of Discrimination Against Women, Virginia Journal of
International Law , no. (
):
.
245
what those principles are and when they will be violated in the interest
of abiding by alternative legal authorities.
None of this analysis should suggest that the resort to premodern rules
on diyya is insulated from critique. Rather, it is to argue for a model of
analysis and critique that irst understands why premodern answers are
being used to address modern questions before o ering alternatives.
Inadequately accounting for the dierent constitutive features of a Rule
of Law claim space, and failing to recognize the mutually constitutive
relationship between law and the enterprise of governance, analysts
will miss the larger context that gives intelligibility to a particular legal
doctrine. In the present instance, such failure would disregard the way
in which the Saudi state, in its formative period, relied on Islam as an
organizing principle at a time when much of the Muslim world was under
the yoke of European colonialism. Saudi Arabia may have had a dierent
experience with the physical colonialism that its neighbors experienced,
but it certainly has endured indirect colonialism. In fact, it continues to
endure such indirect hegemony in the form of global trade over natural
resources. Consequently, the resort to Islam as an organizing principle of
the state and its rules of law arguably functions as a form of anti-colonial
resistance. To dismiss the Saudi states adoption of Islam and Islamic law
as unintelligible, antiquated, or even anti-modern, ignores how both are
presented as answers to questions about the place and intelligibility of
the modern Muslim-majority state in the post-imperial, post-colonial
context.
246
247
248
249
of governance, but also reveal the ever present hegemony that arises
out of the mutually constitutive relationship between the law and the
enterprise of governance generally. The case also illustrates how the hope
for a redemptive Islamic state creates more dissonance than deliverance,
given the legal and demographic diversity that the modern Muslim state
contends with today. The Malaysian case shows that granting primacy
to Shara-based norms creates a dissonance in the trust the state can
claim from its subjects, given the plurality of legal authorities that de ine
and delimit Malaysias Rule of Law claim space. Before turning to a
consideration of that case though, a few words about Malaysias political
and legal history are in order.
The Muslim Malays of Malaysia constitute the majority of those who
live in the country. Alongside the Muslim Malays live Chinese, Indians,
and others, who are distinct on grounds of ethnicity, and often on grounds
of religion. Despite their numerical superiority, the Malay Muslims are
generally economically marginalized when compared to groups like
the ethnic Chinese or the Indians. The economic disparity between the
dierent ethnic groups has contributed to various tensions and con licts in
the country that have often pitted ethnic Malays against ethnic minorities.
Malaysia became a formally independent nation in
, comprising
eleven states of the Malay Peninsula. In
Singapore and the states
of Sabah and Sarawak joined the federation, although Singapore later
became an independent nation in
. Kuala Lumpur became a federal
territory, followed by Lubuan and Putrajaya. The Malaysian nation,
therefore, is comprised of dierent states, federal territories, and a
central government, all of which imply dierent jurisdictions of governance and legislative power. In particular, the division of power
between the federal and state governments is signi icant for understanding the role of Islamic law in the country.
The authority of Islam and Islamic law in Malaysia is enshrined in the
countrys constitution. Article of the Malaysian Constitution provides
that Islam is the religion of the Federation; but other religions may
be practiced in peace and harmony in any part of the Federation.
Furthermore, the legislation enacting Islamic legal provisions is
The observations about the nature of Shara discourses in Malaysia arise in part
from my ield research conducted while meeting with members of government, the judiciary, and civil society in July of
. I want to thank The Asia Foundation for bringing
me to the region, and Canadas Department of Foreign A airs and International Trade,
and especially its of icers at the High Commission in Malaysia for their programmatic
support during my visit.
Abdul Aziz Bari and Farid Shuaib, Constitution of Malaysia: Text and Commentary,
nd ed. (Selangor, Malaysia: Prentice Hall,
), .
Bari and Shuaib, Constitution of Malaysia, .
250
251
to change her name on her identity card, the cards did not designate
whether the card holder was Muslim or not. The NRD rejected her irst
application to change her name. On March ,
she submitted a
second application to change her namethis time to Lina Joystating
once again that her conversion to Christianity was her reason for seeking
a name change. She received no answer from the NRD. Lina issued a third
declaration to the NRD on August ,
, but this time she did not state
that her conversion motivated her name change. On October ,
,
the NRD granted her application to change her name and advised her to
apply for a new identity card. However, at or around this time, a change
in regulations required the NRD to print the religious identity of Muslim
card holders. Consequently while Lina Joys new identity card provided
her new name, it stated her religious identity as Muslimthe very
designation she wanted to avoid by her name change. Had this regulation
not come into force, Lina Joy would have received the necessary change
to her identity card, allowing her to participate socially and politically in
Malaysian society without contending with questions about her religious
upbringing given the Arabo-Islamic resonances of her given name. On
January ,
, Lina Joy made another application to the NRD to have
her religious designation removed from her card. The clerk refused to
accept her application because she provided no documentation from the
Syariah Court attesting to her renunciation of Islam.
It was at this point that legal proceedings began. Lina Joy claimed at
trial that her right to religious freedom, enshrined in Article of the
Malaysian Constitution, was violated. She also challenged the authority
of the NRD to require more than her own statement of conversion
to declare herself non-Muslim. Lina Joy lost her cases at all levels.
At the Court of Appeal, the parties agreed to limit their dispute to the
administrative law issue of the NRDs authority to require certi ication
of her conversion from the Shara court. Nonetheless, Article
was
still raised at the highest court by third-party intervenors to introduce
constitutional arguments relevant to the resolution of the case.
While the most signi icant issue for this section is the debate on Article
, the case was not ultimately decided on that issue. Nonetheless, a review
of the courts analysis of Article as it pertained to Lina Joy oers an
For the summary of relevant facts pertaining to the Lina Joy case, see the dissenting opinion of Federal Court Justice Richard Malanjum, paras . His opinion can be
found on the Malaysian Bar website: Lina Joy Case: Dissenting Judgment of Justice
Richard Malanjum, The Malaysian Bar: <http://www.malaysianbar.org.my/selected_
judgements/lina_joy_case_dissenting_judgment_of_justice_richard_malanjum.html>
(accessed September ,
). I want to thank Malik Imtiaz, one of the intervening parties at the Federal Court, for sharing his thoughts and re lections on the Lina Joy case, and
for clarifying the dierent issues at stake.
252
253
254
the competency of a Syariah Court. In the trial court and again in the
Federal Court, Lina Joys subjective and sincere assertion of her apostasy
and conversion to Christianity was of no legal signi icance. The fact
that she stated as part of her pleadings that she did not consider herself
Muslim fell on deaf ears. For example, the trial court still considered her a
Muslim under the law, and imposed upon her the requirement to seek the
necessary certi ication from a Shara court to authenticate her apostasy.
Furthermore, the Federal Court went so far as to construe the freedom of
religion to mean abiding by the dictates of ones faith, even when seeking
to exit it. In the Malaysian context, those dictates happen to include for
Muslims a separate Shara legal system. By interpreting the constitution
in this way, the court embedded the right of religious freedom in both the
language of constitutional rights and institutions of government.
The harmonization of the two constitutional provisions was
accomplished in large part by limiting the freedoms of Malaysias
Muslim citizens. Consequently, if one were to assure non-Muslims in
Malaysia of their secure position in the state, they might hold that the
Lina Joy decision actually works to the detriment of Malaysias Muslims
as individual rights holders. But by justifying that limitation by reference
to Article , the court construed the public good in terms of the integrity,
priority, and superiority of Islam as the public ethos of Malaysia, a point
emphasized by the Federal Court when it interpreted Article .
The prioritization of Islam in Malaysia should recall the various
themes of Islamic universalism, Muslim superiority, and (by implication)
the subordination of non-Muslims that informed the premodern dhimm
rules. By de ining Malaysia as a hybrid state and prioritizing Islam in that
otherwise hybrid state, the judges involved in the Lina Joy case gave legal
dressing to a form of Islamic exceptionalism that implicitly subordinated
the position of non-Muslims in the Malaysian polity. For instance, because
she was born a Muslim, Lina Joy was subjected to Islamic law, unlike
people born into other faiths. Not only are non-Muslims in Malaysia not
subjected to Islamic law, but they are not even held to their own religious
law to the same degree as Muslims are held to theirs. Members of other
faiths who convert to Islam are not subject to analogous religious court
oversight. Coupled with the various references to the preferential
status and sensitivities of Islam in the Malaysian Constitution, the
limits on Lina Joys religious freedom re lect how the predominance of
an Islamic ethos in Malaysia was read into the constitution (and thereby
Lina Joy [
] CLJ
at
.
Lina Joy (FC Maj.), .
The Federal Court limited its decision only to Muslims leaving Islam: Lina Joy (FC
Maj.), .
255
256
257
Shara (however rei ied and reduced) can be a calming salve. Its calming
eect, though, rests in its contribution to an anti-colonial narrative of
political legitimacy for a state that now exercises the technologies of
governance in a manner that perpetuates the dominance and hegemony
that it once fought against. Indeed, drawing upon the observations
of Anghie and David Scott noted above, this study uses Rule of Law to
illuminate the hegemonic tendencies that arise when minorities make
claims upon the enterprise of governance. At some point, the interests of
minority groups may be sacri iced in the interest of a public good that is
de ined in terms that the minority group may ind adversely imposing or
even hegemonic. That fact by itself is not unique to the Islamic tradition
or the Muslim world. Rather, it traverses both time and space.
258
259
make claims upon the Muslim state. To recall David Scotts critique of
post-colonial theorists, this chapter has argued that the tendency toward
hegemony is not simply limited to the era of European colonialism or
the modern Muslim state and its technologies of domination. Rather,
the hegemonic potential lies in the very relationship between law and
the enterprise of governance that this study has sought to highlight by
viewing Shara as Rule of Law.
The sobering point to take away at this stage in the study is that if
Rule of Law denotes a claim space de ined and delimited in part by the
mutually constitutive relationship between the law and the enterprise
of governance, then hegemony is an inevitable consequence. While postcolonial theorists may principally locate that hegemony in the European
colonial period of the nineteenth and twentieth centuries, this study
suggests that by viewing Shara as Rule of Law, that hegemonic potential
can be located no less in the premodern Islamic imperial past, than in
the European colonial period, and in the modern post-imperial, postcolonial present as Muslim elites (whether in minority or majority
contexts) continue to look to premodern iqh for answers to modern
questions about governance amidst the diversity of people and law. As
will be further illustrated in the chapter that follows, it need not matter
whether the Rule of Law claim space is Islamic or Western, or whether
the period under consideration is premodern or modern. Rather, the
hegemonic dynamic that is embedded in the mutually constitutive
relationship between law and the enterprise of governance seems to
make all-too-frequent appearances at the discursive site created by
the minority claimant who makes demands upon the enterprise of
governance.
7
Religious Minorities and the Empire of Law
This study has predominantly focused on the dhimm rules to
demonstrate how they are symptomatic of the challenges that arise
when governing amidst diversity. However, as suggested at the end of
Chapter , this study aspires to extend its paradigm of analysis beyond
Islamic legal history to address more generally the challenges that lie at
the intersection of law, governance, and pluralism. The dhimm, far from
presenting a unique dynamic, actually provides an entry point into the
more general challenge of governing amidst diversity. The focus on the
dhimm rules and the Muslim world should not suggest, therefore, that
the dhimm rules speci ically, and Islamic law more generally, are unique
in demonstrating the potential, if not inevitability, of such challenges.
Whether in the context of premodern Islamic law or modern democratic
constitutional states, governing amidst diversity presents an important
opportunity to re lect upon the implications of asymmetries in power on
the de inition of rights, the public good, and the scope of accommodation
for minority interests. To illustrate how this challenge is shared across
legal systems, this chapter will address the legal arguments used to
justify the regulation of religious minorities in what might be considered
modern, democratic, constitutional states, in particular the United
States, the United Kingdom, and France. Although the chapter addresses
dierent religious minority groups, the focus will be on three legal
decisions that regulate the scope and extent to which the covered Muslim
woman can cover herself pursuant to her religious beliefs without
suering adverse consequences justi ied under the law.
261
262
National unity, however, was not more or less important than religious
freedom; he recognized both as signi icant values. Yet he also knew that
just because someone happened to have a particular religious belief
did not mean that he or she could not be subjected to a general rule that
might run against the particular belief in question; rather, in some cases,
one value may trump another for reasons that are deemed necessary and
justi iable.
Among those reasons that could trump an individual rights claim,
according to Frankfurther J., was the preservation of order and
tranquility of the polity at large. He noted that in other cases posing a
similar con lict of values, the general laws in question, upheld in their
application to those who refused obedience from religious conviction,
were manifestations of speci ic powers of government deemed by the
legislature essential to secure and maintain that orderly, tranquil, and free
society without which religious toleration itself is unattainable. Order,
well-being, and tranquility, according to Frankfurter J., were important
features of society and required collective commitment. Without all
people participating in ways that contribute to such order, the very
framework of society that makes pluralistic coexistence possible would
break down. In other words, without a collective commitment to a
shared vision of the polity and its well-being, there could be no religious
freedom.
The fundamental question, though, was whether the failure to pledge
allegiance to the lag in a public school was such a threat to the order,
tranquility, and well-being of the polity such that the Gobitis childrens
religious freedom should be curtailed. For Frankfurter J., the childrens
actions gravely undermined and threatened the spirit of national unity.
He argued as follows:
The ultimate foundation of a free society is the binding tie of cohesive sentiment. Such a sentiment is fostered by all those agencies of the mind and
spirit which may serve to gather up the traditions of a people, transmit
them from generation to generation, and thereby create that continuity of
a treasured common life which constitutes a civilization. We live by symbols. The lag is the symbol of our national unity, transcending all internal
dierences, however large, within the framework of the Constitution. This
Court has had occasion to say that . . . the lag is the symbol of the nations
powerthe emblem of freedom in its truest, best sense . . . it signi ies government resting on the consent of the governed; liberty regulated by law;
the protection of the weak against the strong; security against the exercise
Gobitis,
US
at
(emphasis added).
263
of arbitrary power; and absolute safety for free institutions against foreign
aggression.
For Frankfurter J., national unity was an essential condition for order
and well-being. He went so far as to say that [n]ational unity is the basis
of national security. As such, he ruled against the Gobitis children.
Reframing his holding in terms of this studys Rule of Law framework,
Frankfurter J. proered a legal argument from within a claim space that
ultimately constituted and enhanced the enterprise of governance by
protecting the actions of the public school board against the challenge
posed by a minority claimant.
Writing in dissent, Justice Stone expressed grave concern about
permitting an institution within the prevailing enterprise of governance
such as the school board to require students to salute the lag in violation
of their liberty interests. The eect of the general rule, he suggested, was
far too invasive: For by this law the state seeks to coerce these children to
express a sentiment which, as they interpret it, they do not entertain, and
which violates their deepest religious convictions. He did not suggest
that liberties such as religious freedom must and should always trump
claims of national order and well being. He recognized and acknowledged
that the government must have the power to ensure the public good, even
if at times such eorts run against individual rights guaranteed in the
Bill of Rights. Indeed, one might even suggest that this form of hegemony
by the enterprise of governance is necessary if a community of people is
to be managed in an orderly fashion. He wrote that the constitutional
guaranties of personal liberty are not always absolutes. Government has
a right to survive and powers conferred upon it are not necessarily set
at naught by the express prohibitions of the Bill of Rights. For Justice
Stone, though, the Gobitis case did not provide an appropriate occasion to
override individual freedom in the interest of the states right to survive.
He wrote: [I]t is a long step, and one which I am unable to take, to the
position that government may, as a supposed educational measure and
as a means of disciplining the young, compel public af irmations which
violate their religious conscience.
Gobitis,
US
at
.
Gobitis,
US
at
.Frankfurter J. was aware of the stakes at issue in this
case. The claims of a religious minority were weighed against the demands of the
polity for national well-being and order. The legislation at issue was neither speci ic
nor particular; it was a general rule of law that was well within the power of the
legislature to put into e ect. Frankfurter J. seemed especially compelled to respect
the power of the legislation in matters such as education, as the Court lacked the
competence to advise on education policy.
Gobitis,
US
at
.
Gobitis,
US
at
(emphasis added).
Gobitis,
US
at
.
264
US
).
at
265
students parents, who were required by law to ensure that their children
of school age attended school. No provision was made to exempt Jehovahs
Witnesses from the lag salute requirement. The petitioners in Barnette
were Jehovahs Witnesses, and sought relief from the school boards
resolution as it pertained to them.
Delivering the opinion of the Court, Justice Jackson wrote that the
issue presented in Barnette was not one of con licting rights, but rather
a con lict between the authority of an institution of the enterprise of
governancea state Board of Educationand the right of individuals
to freedom of conscience. As he wrote: The sole con lict is between
authority and rights of the individual. The State asserts power to
condition access to public education on making a prescribed sign and
profession . . . The latter stand on a right of self-determination in matters
that touch individual opinion and personal attitude. In other words,
the Barnette case provides an important example, as does Gobitis, of when
minority claims upon the state showcase the hegemony that inevitably
arises when governing amidst diversity.
Jackson J. recognized that while the symbolism of the lag salute may
have its utility in fostering national unity, the power of the state to enforce
the lag salute was a wholly dierent issue. He did not consider the courts
function to determine what was an appropriate and e ective symbol of
national unity; however, it was the courts duty to consider whether the
state had the power to require and enforce the provisions in the Board
of Education resolution. Jackson J. wrote: validity of the asserted power
to force an American citizen publicly to profess any state of belief, or to
engage in any ceremony of assent to one, presents questions of power
that must be considered independently of an idea we may have as to the
utility of the ceremony in question.
Turning to the Gobitis decision, Jackson J. attacked it for assuming the
very thing that the Court had to decide, namely whether the state had the
power to require the lag salute at the cost of the individuals freedoms.
He noted that the Gobitis decision presumed that the enterprise of
governance had the power and authority to compel children to salute
the lag. Jackson J., however, rejected that presumption. He held that
while national unity was a noble goal to pursue, courts had to be wary of
granting the state the power to instill such unity by compelling a salute to
the lag against the freedom and liberty interests of individuals. In other
words, far from constituting and enhancing the enterprise of governance,
Jackson J. demanded that courts take special care in those cases when
individual freedoms are at stake, in particular those of minority groups
Barnette,
US
at
Barnette,
US
at
266
US
at
Barnette,
US
at
267
willing to prioritize the power and authority of the state over and against
the minority groups interests.
The juxtaposition of Gobitis and Barnette hints at how an appreciation of
the hegemonic potential of the law reveals the boundaries that demarcate
a Rule of Law claim space, and thereby begs important questions about
the content of those boundaries (e.g., public good, individual rights). For
instance, Bruker v Markovitz, a case from the Supreme Court of Canada,
involved a Jewish husband who refused to issue a religious divorce to
his wife so that she would be divorced under Jewish law. The couple had
signed a consent decree in the province of Quebec in which the husband
agreed to appear before a Rabbinical tribunal to issue the divorce, or Ghet.
He never did. His wife sued thereafter, and the husband retorted that the
case involved a religious matter that was outside the purview of the Court.
Abella J., writing for the Court, recognized the importance of protecting
diversity and religious freedom: Canadas Charter of Rights and Freedoms
upholds the fundamental freedom of conscience and religion. That
freedom, though, is subject only to such reasonable limits prescribed by
law as can be demonstrably justi ied in a free and democratic society.
By providing for these limits on fundamental freedoms, Section of the
Charter eectively contributes to de ining the claim space of justice by
invoking and incorporating the enterprise of governance as a constitutive
feature of the intelligibilty of a legal argument. Abella J. presumed this
constitutive feature of the law in her majority opinion when she wrote in
various places:
The right to have dierences protected, however, does not mean that those
dierences are always hegemonic. Not all dierences are compatible with
Canadas fundamental values and, accordingly, not all barriers to their
expression are arbitrary.
...
In my view, an agreement between spouses to take the necessary steps to
permit each other to remarry in accordance with their own religions constitutes a valid and binding contractual obligation under Quebec law . . . [Such]
agreements are consistent with public policy, our approach to marriage and
divorce, and our commitment to eradicating gender discrimination.
...
Leslie Green, On Being Tolerated, in The Legacy of H.L.A. Hart, eds M. Kramer et al.
(Oxford: Oxford University Press,
),
.
Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms, Part I of the Constitution Act,
, being
Schedule B to the Canada Act
, Ch. (UK), art. (a).
Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms, art. .
Bruker v Marcovitz,
SCC at para. (emphasis added).
Bruker,
SCC at para. (emphasis added).
268
Mediating these highly personal claims to religious rights with the wider
public interest is a task that has been assigned to the courts by legislatures
across the country. It is a well-accepted function carried out for decades by
human rights commissions under federal and provincial statutes and, for
years by judges under the Canadian Charter of Rights and Freedoms, to
ensure that members of the Canadian public are not arbitrarily disadvantaged by their religion.
269
270
The covered Muslim woman as a trope is not itself a new idea. In the
European imagination before and after the period of European colonialism in the Muslim world, the covered Muslim woman represented all that
was novel and mysterious about the lands east of Europe. The covered
Muslim woman represented the exotic, often by bearing it directly on
her body. Her hidden face creates for her onlooker a sense of curiosity
and enticement that is not lost on marketing agents seeking to increase
their market share for consumer goods. For instance, the food company
Presidents Choice uses the image of a covered Muslim woman to market
its line of couscous, a staple of North African diets. The covered Muslim
woman on the box wears a niqb made of luxurious fabric and vibrant
color. Her mysterious, smokey eyes beckon the consumer to ingest all she
represents. The consumer, captivated by what he sees (and does not see),
is beckoned to consume something at once exciting and mysterious.
In recent court decisions, the covered Muslim woman represents a
very dierent trope. Instead of being viewed as exotic, she has become
foreign. Far from being an enticement, she is a threat. Her mystery and
sensuality have disappeared, leaving courts to view her as a sign of an
ominousthough unde inedextremism that can have adverse and
unavoidable consequences on other, uncovered Muslim women that
the law must thereby protect. In fact, the image of the covered Muslim
woman as a threat to the well-being of the national polity was made
explicit in the Swiss campaign to constitutionally ban minarets in the
countrya campaign that ultimately succeeded. That campaign
utilized an image of an ominous looking covered Muslim woman, with
missile-like minarets emanating from a Swiss lag. The covered Muslim
Reasonable Accommodation, ed. Lori Beaman (Vancouver: University of British Columbia
Press,
).
Judy Mabro, Veiled Half-Truths: Western Travellers Perceptions of Middle Eastern
Women (London: I.B. Tauris,
).
On the constitutive relationship between culture and marketing for consumer
goods, see Grant McCracken, Culture and Consumption: A Theoretical Account of
the Structure and Movement of the Cultural Meaning of Consumer Goods, Journal of
Consumer Research (
):
.
Speci ically, the product is Presidents Choice Memories of Marrakech Whole
Wheat Couscous, which can be viewed at the following website: <http://reviews.presidentschoice.ca/
/F
/reviews.htm> (accessed January ,
).
Christopher Caldwell, No Minarets, Please, The Weekly Standard , no.
(December ,
); Bandung Nurrohman, A lesson to draw from the Swiss ban on
minarets, The Jakarta Post, December
, p. . See also, Daniel Moeckli, Of Minarets
and Foreign Criminals: Swiss Direct Democracy and Human Rights, Human Rights Law
Review , no. (
):
, which illustrates the adverse implication of direct democracy on the interests and welfare of minorities in Switzerland.
The image of the campaign posters went viral and can be found on various websites,
such as the following: <http://blogs.reuters.com/faithworld/
/ / /the-swissminaret-ban-and-other-trends-for-islam-in-europe/> (accessed January ,
).
271
272
273
The debate about core values, identity, and the nation is acute in the case
of Muslims in Europe, in particular those Muslims for whom veiling is
an important marker of their religious identity and expression. As Jos
Casanova writes,
The controversies over the Muslim veil in so many European societies and
the overwhelming support among the French citizenry, including apparently among the majority of French Muslims, for the restrictive legislation prohibiting the wearing of Muslim veils and other ostensibly religious
symbols in public schools, as a threat to national cohesion, may be an
extreme example of illiberal secularism. But in fact one sees similar trends
of restrictive legislation directed at immigrant Muslims in liberal Holland,
precisely in the name of protecting its liberal, tolerant traditions from the
threat of illiberal, fundamentalist, patriarchal customs . . . Anti-immigrant
xenophobic nativism, secularist antireligious prejudices, liberal-feminist
critiques of Muslim patriarchal fundamentalism, and the fear of Islamic
terrorist networks are being fused indiscriminately throughout Europe
into a uniform anti-Muslim discourse . . .
274
275
For a statement of the case, the relevant legislation, and the conclusions of the
government commissioner, see the decision of the Conseil dEtat, Case
, <http://
arianeinternet.conseil-etat.fr/arianeinternet/ViewRoot.asp?View=Html&DMode=Htm
l&PushDirectUrl= &Item= &fond=DCE&texte=
&Page= &querytype=simple&N
bEltPerPages= &Pluriels=True> (accessed March ,
, copy on ile with author).
Angelique Chrisa is, France rejects Muslim woman over radical practice of Islam,
The Guardian, July ,
, p. (quoting the Conseil dEtat). See also, Katrin Bennhold,
A Muslim woman too orthodox for France; It bars citizenship over her strict garb,
International Herald Tribune, July ,
, p. ; Ronald P. Sokol, Why France Cant See
Past the burqa, The Christian Science Monitor, July ,
, p. .
276
leads a life that is almost reclusive and removed from French society.
She does not have any visitors at her apartment; in the morning she
does her housework and goes for a walk with her baby or children,
and in the afternoon she goes to visit her father or father-in-law . . .
[S]he is able to go shopping on her own, but admits that usually she
goes to the supermarket with her husband.
From these facts, the government commissioner concluded that the
claimant had not adopted or otherwise acquiesced to the core values
of the French Republic, in particular the core value of gender equality.
Of particular interest is the way in which the commissioner used the
claimants veiling habit to characterize the quality and content of her
values: She lives in complete submission to the men of her family, which
is demonstrated by the clothing that she wears, the organization of her
daily life and the statements that she made . . . showing that she inds this
normal.
After reviewing the submissions and evidence, as well as taking into
account the European Convention of Human Rights and Fundamental
Freedoms, the Conseil dEtat upheld the governments decision to reject
Ms Silmis application for citizenship. The Conseil dEtat did not refer
to Ms Silmis veiling in its decision. In fact, it had held in prior cases
that wearing the veil is not, by itself, grounds for denying suf icient
assimilation into French society. But it nonetheless agreed with the
government that despite her French language abilities and her history
as a resident in France, her religious values were contrary to the core
values of the society and therefore were an obstacle to her application for
citizenship.
An analysis of this opinion reveals certain peculiarities about the
evidence garnered against the claimant and its interpretation by the
government commissioner. For instance, the commissioner noted that
while Ms Silmi could go shopping on her own, she usually went with her
husband. This particular evidence can be understood in di erent ways. It
may have been that Ms Silmi preferred to shop with her husband because
she enjoyed her husbands company, and might otherwise ind shopping
alone less enjoyable. Maybe he would help carry any merchandise or
groceries that she purchased. The government commissioner, on the other
hand, represented this piece of evidence with a singularly determinate
meaning, namely that Ms Silmi was not an emancipated woman, had not
Conseil dEtat, Case
277
278
279
280
281
religious beliefs required her to wear the niqb. She was convinced that
by asking her to take a full-face photo, the DMV was asking her to choose
between sacri icing her religious convictions or her drivers license. As
such, she iled a lawsuit alleging a violation of her religious freedom.
The court analyzed Ms Freemans claims under Floridas Religious
Freedom Restoration Act, which requires the state to show a compelling
interest in the event that a law, whether of general application or not,
substantially burdens an individuals religious freedom. As the court
stated: if Freeman can show a substantial burden on the free exercise
of her religion, the state must demonstrate a compelling governmental
interest and show that the law is the least restrictive means of furthering
its interest. Under this law, the initial legal burden was on the petitioner
(here, Ms Freeman) to show that the DMV requirement to reveal her face
for the drivers license photograph was a substantial burden on the free
exercise of her sincere religious beliefs. If Ms Freeman could satisfy her
legal burden of proof, the state would be required to show that, despite
the substantial burden on her freedom, the legal requirement nonetheless met a compelling state interest and also that the requirement was
the least restrictive means of achieving that interest. In other words,
the law would impose upon the government a burden of justi ication
only if its requirements substantially burden the petitioners religious
freedom. Put dierently, the state could incidentally burden ones
religious freedom rights, and may impose slight inconveniences without
having to justify them to the petitioner or to the court. The applicable
legal test in the Freeman case, therefore, delineated the boundary within
which the enterprise of governance could operate without having to
justify its actions. In de ining the zone of discretionary activity, the legal
test helped constitute the enterprise of governance in a manner akin to
how premodern Muslim jurists granted the ruler a zone of discretionary
authority through the doctrines of tazr and siysa shariyya. As it
turned out in the Freeman case, Ms Freeman did not satisfy her initial
legal burden of proof. The court found that she did not show that the new
requirement was a substantial burden on her religious belief. As such,
the state did not need to prove its actions were compelling or the least
restrictive. Rather, in the confrontation between the state authority and
the individual minority claimant, the court not only found against the
individual, but it did so in part by freeing the enterprise of governance
even from the task of justifying itself.
There was no real question about whether Ms Freeman sincerely
believed she must cover herself on religious grounds. The court found her
Freeman, .
282
belief sincere. The real question was whether the requirement to unveil
for the photograph was a substantial burden on her religious freedom.
Quoting the Florida Supreme Courts test for substantial burden, the
Freeman court wrote: a substantial burden on the free exercise of
religion is one that either compels the religious adherent to engage in
conduct that his religion forbids, or forbids him to engage in conduct that
his religion requires. The debate therefore centered on the debates in
Islam concerning the requirement of Muslim women to cover.
The court held that the states requirement for a full-face photograph
did not substantially burden Ms Freemans religious freedom. Rather, it
constituted a mere interference. To reach its conclusion, the court relied
on the testimony of expert witness Khaled Abou El Fadl, a professor of
Islamic law at UCLA School of Law:
Dr. El Fadl testi ied that in Islamic countries there are exceptions to the practice of veiling. Consistent with Islamic law, women are required to unveil
for medical needs and for certain photo ID cards. Examples include photo
ID cards to be displayed to police, to enter and take professional exams, and
for passports. The only quali ication is that the taking of the photograph
accommodate Freemans belief. Here, the Departments existing procedure
would accommodate Freemans veiling beliefs by using a female photographer with no other person present.
283
284
285
David J. Seipp, Our Law, Their Law, History, and the Citation of Foreign Law,
Boston University Law Review (
):
; Jeremy Waldron, Foreign Law and the
Modern Ius Gentium, Harvard Law Review
(
):
.
On the unconstitutionality of sentencing the mentally disabled to the death penalty, see Atkins v Virginia,
US
(
). On the unconstitutionality of juvenile death
penalty, see Roper v Simmons,
US
(
). On the unconstitutionality of anti-sodomy laws, see Lawrence v Texas,
S Ct
(
).
286
On and o the court, though, Kennedys stance has suered signi icant
criticism. In a dissenting opinion in Roper, Justice Antonin Scalia retorted:
The basic premise of the Courts argumentthat American law should
comport with the laws of the rest of the worldought to be rejected out of
hand . . . What these foreign sources af irm . . . is the Justices own notion
of how the world ought to be, and their diktat that it shall be so henceforth
in America. For Scalia, the use of foreign law to decide domestic
constitutional rights issues unduly extends the scope of judicial power
and is fundamentally anti-democratic. As Roger P. Alford states, [u]sing
global opinions as a means of constitutional interpretation dramatically
undermines sovereignty by utilizing the one vehicleconstitutional
supremacythat can trump the democratic will re lected in state and
federal legislative and executive pronouncements. Harold Koh, on the
other hand, criticizes the likes of Scalia and Alford by suggesting that
the citation to foreign law has been a notable feature of Supreme Court
decisions since the beginnings of the country, and contributes to the
legitimacy of the state in the global arena.
The Freeman court did not specify any particular Islamic country in
its opinion. Two states that could reasonably be considered Islamic
countries are Iran and Saudi Arabia. If the Freeman court was referring
implicitly to the practices of the Iranian and Saudi Arabian Governments,
which may very well allow women to remove their coverings for
identi ication photos, Scalia and Alford are right to worry about the
democratic de icit that can arise when citing foreign law indiscriminately.
Ms Freeman, a US citizen, was eectively held to rules and regulations
to which she neither acceded nor consented. These facts alone are not
necessarily dispositive. Indeed, Kohs response cautions against any
blanket antagonism against the use of foreign law. Yet given the analysis
of the post-colonial Muslim state in Chapter , the analysis in Freeman
Roper,
US
. See also, Je rey Toobin, Swing Shift: How Anthony Kennedys
Passion for Foreign Law Could Change the Supreme Court, The New Yorker, September
,
, .
Roper,
US
at
; Toobin, Swing Shift.
Roger P. Alford, Misusing International Sources to Interpret the Constitution,
American Journal of International Law , no. (
): , .
Harold Hongju Koh, International Law as Part of Our Law, American Journal of
International Law , no. (
): , .
287
288
These guidelines are meant to make certain that the foreign and
international law materials US courts rely upon re lect a democratic
commitment. They also ensure international law materials are used
consistently, and not so selectively as to nearly predispose the case to
certain outcomes over others that might prevail if domestic law alone
were considered. Importantly, the imperative to get the facts right
requires a commitment to serious empirical research. Ramsey
criticizes the Supreme Courts use of international law to deem
unconstitutional the application of the death penalty on the mentally
disabled in Atkins v Virginia, because the majority relied on advocates
briefs about international law without investigating the law for itself:
Surely the Court would never state a proposition of U.S. law and cite only
an advocates brief. That it could do so for a matter of international practice
displays a lack of commitment to the empirical project, and a lack of respect
for international sources. If we (and the Court) cannot bring ourselves to
do the empirical project right, that seems further evidence that we are in it
only for the results.
The debate about the use of foreign law in domestic rights cases should
raise concerns about the implication of the Freeman courts decision on
future cases that involve covered Muslim women. Although the Florida
case was not a constitutional case, it nonetheless subjected Ms Freemans
rights claim to Floridas statutory law. The situation is not strictly
analogous to the ones noted above that involve the Supreme Court
deciding cases under the Bill of Rights. But that does not change the fact
that by relying on foreign practices of unnamed Islamic countries, the
Freeman decision is vulnerable to similar criticisms of its decision.
Michael D. Ramsey, International Materials and Domestic Rights: Re lections
on Atkins and Lawrence, American Journal of International Law , no. (
): ,
.
Ramsey, International Materials, .
Ramsey, International Materials, .
289
290
291
; Thomas Linden and Tessa Hetherington, Schools and Human Rights, the Denbigh
High School Case, Education Law Journal , no. (
):
; Thomas Poole, Of
Headscarves and Heresies: The Denbigh High School Case and Public Authority DecisionMaking Under the Human Rights Act, Public Law (
):
; Mohammad Mazher
Idriss, The Defeat of Shabina Begum in the House of Lords, Liverpool Law Review
(
):
; Ian Ward, Shabina Begum and the Headscarf Girls, Journal of Gender
Studies , no. (
): ; John Mikhail, Dilemmas of Cultural Legality: A Comment
on Roger Cotterrells The Struggle for Law and a Criticism of the House of Lords
Opinions in Begum, International Journal of Law in Context , no. (
):
.
292
293
The lawsuit that ensued concerned the scope of both the schools
authority to demand compliance with a uniform requirement, and Ms
Begums right to manifest her religious beliefs. Ms Begum claimed that
the school had eectively expelled her for her refusal to conform to the
uniform requirement. The school argued that it never expelled Ms Begum;
it had the discretion to create and enforce a uniform requirement, which
is all it did. Ms Begum was free to return to school as long as she adhered
to the uniform requirement. After reviewing relevant statutory and
regulatory provisions concerning education and school uniform policies,
Justice Bennett of the High Court of Justice (Admin) held that the school
did not formally expel or exclude Ms Begum from school. She was at all
times free to attend her classes, as long as she adhered to the uniform
requirement. Certainly, the court recognized that if Ms Begum would not
violate her religious requirements, she could not attend classes. But as
the initial choice was hers, her restriction from attending classes could
not be construed as the school expelling her.
Ms Begum further claimed, however, that the schools actions violated
her religious freedom under Article of the European Convention of
Human Rights (ECHR). That Article reads as follows:
( ) Everyone has the right to freedom of thought, conscience and religion;
this right includes freedom to change his religion or belief and freedom,
either alone or in community with others and in public or private, to manifest his religion, or belief, in worship, teaching, practice, and observance.
( ) Freedom to manifest ones religion or beliefs shall be subject only to
such limitations as are prescribed by law and are necessary in a democratic
society in the interests of public safety, for the protection of public order,
health or morals, or for the protection of the rights and freedoms of others.
294
] EWHC
(Admin), para.
295
[I]t is clear from the evidence that there are a not insigni icant number
of Muslim female pupils at Denbigh High School who do not wish to wear
the jilbab and either do, or will, feel pressure on them either from inside or
outside the school. The present school uniform policy aims to protect their
rights and freedoms. Further, if the choice of two uniforms were permitted
for Muslim female pupils, it can be readily understood that other pupils of
dierent or no faiths might well see that as favoring a particular religion.
The court was convinced that the uniform upholds a sense of community
that the jilbb would undermine. The jilbb represented the onset of
extremism that had to be prevented from entering the school. If the jilbb,
and thus extremism, were to be permitted onto the school grounds, the
student community in general, and non-jilbb-wearing Muslim girls in
particular, would suer. Consequently, even if Ms Begums rights had
been infringed (which the court found was not the case), the uniform
requirement nonetheless would be justi ied in the interest of promoting
community values and protecting the rights of others.
On appeal, Bennett J.s ruling was overturned. Brooke L.J., writing
for the Court of Appeal, found that the uniform requirement infringed
Ms Begums religious freedom under Article and did not satisfy the
requirements of Article ( ) of the ECHR. The school pro ered two
principal arguments to justify its uniform requirement, namely that
it promoted community value and harmony and that it protected the
rights of others. Members of the school emphasized the pedagogical
importance of instilling in the student body the virtue of civic harmony
and responsibility. Brooke L.J. noted that a major learning objective on
the part of the curriculum concerned with citizenship was for pupils to
work together positively and cooperatively in a community that fosters
respect for all. Commenting on the statement by deputy head teacher
Mr Connor, Brooke L.J. wrote:
It was important in [Mr Connors] experience to recognise that many adolescents require a lot of support to understand the importance of inclusion, equal opportunities, mutual respect and social cohesion, such as was
fostered by the schools uniform policy. He attested to the same concerns
among a number of girls at the school as Mr. Moore had mentioned, and he
believed that the school had a duty to protect these pupils from inappropriate peer pressures, or pressures from outside extremist groups. There had
been an incident in February
when some young men who represented
an extremist Muslim group had picketed the school gates and distributed
lea lets to the pupils which exhorted Muslims not to send their children to
Begum [
] EWHC
(Admin), para. .
The Queen on the application of Shabina Begum v The Headteacher and Governors of
Denbigh High School [
] EWCA Civ
, para. .
296
297
Article ( ). Among the House of Lords, there were two justi ications
that were particularly prominent in their decision. One justi icatory
argument drew upon institutional arguments about court deference to
the enterprise of governance: the uniform requirement was justi ied
because of the deference courts owe to government administrators,
such as the heads and governors of schools, under doctrines such as the
margin of appreciation, to be discussed below. The second justi icatory
argument had to do with issues of public good and threats to it, namely
that the jilbb was a threat to the well-being of the school community at
large, and to the rights of Muslim girls to be free from religious coercion
concerning their attire. In other words, the arguments justifying the
uniform requirement adopted two tacks. The irst approach posited
the court in between the government agency (the school board) and the
minority claimant, and required the court to adopt a principle of judicial
deference to the enterprise of governance (i.e., the doctrine of margin of
appreciation). This endorsement of judicial deference illustrates that at
the discursive site of the minority claimant, the hegemonic capacity of
the law becomes especially apparent, if not poignantly so. The second
approach characterized the inal outcome as based on concerns for thirdparty rights and thereby positioned the school board in a more neutral,
umpire-like role. Notably, this approach introduced third parties into the
equation, but only by reference to the fears of extremism.
The second approach concerning third-party rights will be addressed
irst, whereas the irst approach will be analyzed in the subsequent
section. In his lead opinion, Lord Bingham relied on the head teacher,
Ms Bevans, view that the uniform requirement was a signi icant factor
in promoting the public good at the school. He wrote: The head teacher
believes that school uniform plays an integral part in securing high
and improving standards, serving the needs of a diverse community,
promoting a positive sense of communal identity and avoiding manifest
disparities of wealth and style. Prior to Mrs Bevans arrival, the school
had suered the ill eects of racial tension among the students. The
uniform requirement helped overcome those tensions. Now the school
was worried that with the jilbb would come undesirable dierentiation
between Muslim groups according to the strictness of their views.
The head teacher was especially concerned that the jilbb would create
ruptures in the school and undermine the purpose of the uniform
policy, namely to promote inclusion and social cohesion, as opposed to
fragmentation and dierence.
Begum [
Begum [
] UKHL
] UKHL
, para. .
, para. .
Begum [
] UKHL
, para.
298
Begum [
Begum [
] UKHL
] UKHL
, para.
, para.
.
.
Begum [
Begum [
] UKHL , para. .
] UKHL , para. .
299
growing up here face particularly dif icult choices: how far to adopt or to distance themselves from the dominant culture.
), para.
300
Tulkens objection on this point is signi icant because of the way in which
a fear of extremism in the polity led to the insertion of third-party rights
as part of the legal analysis.
Sahin, para.
.
Sahin, para. .
Sahin, para.
Sahin (dissent), para. .
Sahin (dissent) para. .
301
302
wished to do so to wear the hijab. This was indeed a thoughtful and proportionate response to reconciling the complexities of the situation. This is
demonstrated by the fact that girls have subsequently expressed their concern that if the jilbab were to be allowed they would face pressure to adopt
it even though they do not wish to do so. Here is the evidence to support the
justi ication which Judge Tulkens found lacking in the Sahin case.
Begum [
] UKHL , para. .
Davies, The House of Lords and Religious Clothing,
.
Notably, the concern about Muslim womens agency in these cases may be criticized
on the grounds of inadequately understanding the agency of women who are, at the same
time, members of religious communities. See Mahmood, Politics of Piety. The concern
for female agency in the Begum decision is evident by how the judges express concern
that Ms Begum speaks only through her brother, and not of her own accord. See Mikhail,
Dilemmas of Cultural Legality,
.
303
304
] EWHC
(Admin), paras
305
J. and the House of Lords noted this con lict but were unconcerned by
the contradictions by the expert witnesses. In fact, the internal debates
of Muslim scholars were of little consequence to either courts analysis
given the prevailing legal standards that looked to the petitioners
sincerity, cogency, and seriousness in belief. As Lord Bingham of the
House of Lords wrote: It is common ground in these proceedings that
at all material times the respondent [Begum] sincerely held the religious
belief which she professed to hold. It was not the less a religious belief
because her belief may have changed . . . or because it was a belief
shared by a small minority of people . . . [A]ny sincere religious belief
must command respect, particularly when derived from an ancient and
respected religion.
The subjective approach to religious belief is not an uncommon
approach utilized by democratic constitutional courts tasked with
exercising judicial review on grounds of religious freedom. On the one
hand, the subjective standard has the virtue of respecting a petitioners
conscientious assertion of his or her religious convictions. On the other
hand, it disregards the way in which beliefs are themselves embedded in
a tradition that gives beliefs and practices a thick or rich meaning.
In the Begum cases, Bennett J. and the House of Lords emphasized the
individual sincerity of the claimant. In doing so, though, they nonetheless
found that Ms Begum suered no infringement of her religious freedom.
They made this inding by invoking the judicial doctrine of the margin
of appreciation. That doctrine requires courts to defer to the decision
of local administrative bodies, here represented by their high esteem for
the eorts of Mrs Bevan and the governors of the high school. The school,
wrote Lord Bingham:
had taken immense pains to devise a uniform policy which respected
Muslim beliefs but did so in an inclusive, unthreatening, and uncompetitive
way . . . It was feared that acceding to [Ms. Begums] request would or might
have signi icant adverse repercussions. It would in my opinion be irresponsible of any court, lacking the experience, background and detailed knowledge of the head teacher, sta and governors, to overrule their judgment on
a matter as sensitive as this. The power of decision has been given to them
Begum [
] EWHC
(Admin), para. ; Begum [
] UKHL , para. .
Begum [
] UKHL , para. .
See for instance, the Canadian Supreme Court decision Syndicat Northcrest v
Amselem,
SCC ; [
] SCR
.
Benjamin Berger, Laws Religion: Rendering Culture, Osgoode Hall Law Journal
, no. (
):
; idem, The Cultural Limits of Legal Tolerance, in After
Pluralism: Reimagining Religious Engagement, eds Courtney Benderand Pamela Klassen
(New York: Columbia University Press,
), .
306
for the compelling reason that they are best placed to exercise it, and I see
no reason to disturb their decision.
Likewise, Lord Ho man held that the House of Lords owed the school a
degree of deference as to how it managed its operations. Referring to ECHR
jurisprudence on margin of appreciation, Lord Ho man wrote: In my
opinion a domestic court should accept the decision of Parliament to
allow individual schools to make their own decisions about uniforms . . .
[T]he justi ication must be sought at the local level and it is there that
an area of judgment, comparable to the margin of appreciation, must
be allowed to the school. By relying on the margin of appreciation,
the court employed legal doctrines that, given concerns about the limits
of judicial competence, eectively implied deference to the enterprise
of governance, here the governing school board. While courts must be
careful not to exceed their competence, this case nonetheless showcases
how the courts view of the range of its competence had the e ect of
enhancing the enterprise of governance.
Deferring to the schools decision was not only legally required of the
court, but also very much a testament to the courts trust in the leadership
of Mrs Bevan, the head teacher of Denbigh High School. In these cases,
Mrs Bevan eectively became the courts trustworthy resource on the
Islamic requirements of veiling, despite also being a party to the case.
Consistently, various opinions took note of Mrs Bevans unique position
as a Bengali Muslim woman, her local knowledge of di erent parts of the
Muslim world, her eorts to include the Muslim community in the design
of the uniform, and her success in turning Denbigh High School into a
high-performing school.
For instance, Bennett J. stated:
Mrs Bevan, the Headteacher, was born into a Bengali Muslim family and
grew up in India, Pakistan and Bangladesh before coming to this country. She has an understanding of the Islamic dress code and the practices
adopted by Muslim women.
307
in this country and abroad, and she says that she understands the Islamic
dress code and the practices adopted by Muslim women. She does not, however, purport to have a detailed knowledge of the theological issues which
surfaced in this dispute.
Lord Ho man:
Yasmin Bevan, who comes from a Muslim Bengali family, has been head
teacher since
. Under her leadership, standards of education and behavior at the school have greatly improved. She has consistently been supported
by the governors, among whom Muslims are strongly represented.
Lord Scott:
Moreover the head teacher, Mrs. Yasmin Bevan, who had been appointed
in
, was born into a Bengali Moslem family and brought up in the subcontinent before moving to this country . . . The head teachers background
con irms she well understands the Moslem dress code for women.
Begum [
Begum [
] EWCA Civ
, para. .
] UKHL , para. .
Begum [
] UKHL , para. .
Begum [
] UKHL , paras .
308
character. There is little doubt in the Islamic tradition that Abd Allh
b. Salm was venerated, respected, and trusted. He may have once been
Jewish, but by the time he appeared in the story of the two adulterous
Jews, he was a converted Muslim, native informant. Consequently, when
he caught the young Jewish reader covering part of the Torah, Abd Allh
b. Salm eectively excluded the Jewish readers own representation
of the law as unreliable and posited his own as authoritative and
trustworthy.
In the Begum case, the courts presented Mrs Bevan as assuming a
similar role. As an educator and successful school administrator, she
manifested commitment to the states programme of educating young
citizens. She utilized a democratically inspired process to develop the
uniform requirement, and she made every eort to be inclusive. She
was, in other words, one of Us, both in terms of shared values and
commitments to the institutions of the enterprise of governance. She
was especially well-positioned to decide on appropriate uniform styles in
large part because of her own background as a Bengali Muslim woman
who had lived throughout South Asia and was suitably familiar with the
Islamic traditions on veiling. In other words, she was also one of Them.
Only Lord Justice Brooke, in the Court of Appeal, was careful to limit the
scope of her knowledge and appreciation of the Islamic doctrinal debate
when he wrote: She does not, however, purport to have a detailed
knowledge of the theological issues which surfaced in this dispute.
At various points in the Begum case, Ms Bevan was made to be the native
informant who could be trusted to lead the school (and the courts) to a
suitable resolution.
By construing Mrs Bevan as a native informant, though, the courts
failed to account for a possible intra-Muslim community contest over
religious identity, fashion, and authenticity. The shalwar khameez is a
style of dress that is common among South Asians. The jilbb on the
other hand, is a style of dress more common in the Arab world. Mrs
Bevan, of South Asian descent, may very well have been familiar with
the requirements for appropriate Muslim attire, and so too may have
the Muslim members on Denbigh High Schools board of governors.
However, they may not have made the court aware of any intracommunity tension between South Asian Muslims and Arab Muslims
that may have lurked in the backdrop of this particular controversy.
J. Horovitz, Abd Allh b. Salm, Encyclopaedia of Islam, Second Edition. Eds
P. Bearman et al.
Begum [
] EWCA Civ
, para. .
This tension is anecdotally addressed in Manji, The Trouble With Islam Today,
309
Just as there was no indication about whether the Jews coming to the
Prophet were Rabbinic or schismatic, or whether Abd Allh b. Salam was
of the same or a dierent Jewish group, there was also no awareness by
the Begum courts of whether and to what extent any intra-community
con licts informed the views about Islamic dress that the courts heard.
Arguably, by inding against Ms Begum, in part because the jilbb is
a symbol of extremism, the court may have unwittingly perpetuated
stereotypes of Muslim Arabs as extremists.
310
311
312
313
Conclusion
Analyzing the dhimm rules in close detail has allowed us to leave behind
the competing tendencies to view these rules through the interpretive
lenses of harmony or persecution, tolerance or intolerance. As suggested
throughout this study, the language of tolerance and intolerance hides
more than it reveals about the intelligibility of the dhimm rules. Such
tolerance-talk disregards the ways in which the dhimm rules re lect
the challenge of governing amidst diversity, a challenge that is far from
unique to the Islamic tradition.
Additionally, framing Shara as Rule of Law reveals a dynamic that
goes beyond the rari ied notion of Shara as a repository of ancient
doctrines, and presents a complex image of Shara that de ies neat
dichotomies between law and morality, theory and practice, and
centralized and decentralized modes of legal ordering. Shara as Rule of
Law recognizes the contested nature of law and legal argument, thereby
rendering Shara as a claim space where the intelligibility of any claim
of justice is dependent upon the constitutive features of the boundaries
of that space. Rule of Law permits a consideration of Shara in general,
and the dhimm rules in particular, as embedded within a politico-legal
context. It informs and is informed by such factors as the curriculum and
institutions of legal education, the institutions of law and adjudication,
and of course the presumption of an enterprise of governance.
The analysis of the dhimm rules from a Rule of Law perspective
suggests that the speci ic terms of a given dhimm rule are less
interesting than is appreciating how the dhimm rules in the aggregate
are symptoms of the more general challenge of governing amidst
diversity. As shown throughout Part I, premodern Muslim jurists
resolved that challenge in a multitude of ways. For instance, they
debated whether the shared capacity to reason to the truth and to the
good could justify imposing Shara-based obligations upon the dhimm.
While they disagreed on the normative implications of human reason,
they generally recognized that something else was required to justify
the imposition of Qurnically based general rules upon non-Muslims, as
well as the exceptions from general rules of obligation. One particularly
powerful legal construct they developed was the contract of protection.
Conclusion
315
316
Conclusion
Conclusion
317
318
Conclusion
Conclusion
319
lives and property. But some (though not all) of those jurists held that
dhimms could not form charitable trusts that perpetuated values that
ran contrary to the polity. Nor could they be trusted to testify truthfully
and thereby contribute to the conditions of intelligibility in the claim
space of Shara.
Notably, Diefenbakers suspicion should also recall the more recent
eorts by American security policy experts, led by Lt Gen. William
Boykin (ret.) and Lt Gen. Harry Edward Soyster (ret.), to ban Shara in
various states across the United States out of concern for the countrys
security interests:
The enemy adheres to an all-encompassing Islamic political-militarylegal doctrine known as shariah. Shariah obliges them to engage in jihad
to achieve the triumph of Islam worldwide through the establishment of
a global Islamic State governed exclusively by shariah, under a restored
caliphate.
The good news is that millions of Muslims around the worldincluding
many in Americado not follow the directives of shariah, let alone engage
in jihad. The bad news is that this reality re lects the fact that the imposition of strict shariah doctrine is at di erent stages across Muslim-majority
and -minority countries.
320
Conclusion
For the language of the Bill and related documents, see the relevant National
Assembly website: Bill
, Societ: Interdiction de la dissimulation du visage dans
lespace public, th legislature (assented to May ,
), <http://www.assembleenationale.fr/ /dossiers/dissimulation_visage_espace_public.asp> (accessed, July ,
). As noted earlier, the Quebec version of the ban would make accommodations for
covered Muslim women, unless such accommodations pose security risks.
Scott, The Politics of the Veil, .
See the discussion on Ms Silmis case in Chapter .
See the discussion on the Shabina Begum case in Chapter .
See the discussion on the Freeman case in Chapter .
Conclusion
321
322
Conclusion
that legal arguments and doctrines can and do operate to the contrary,
especially in cases where minorities assert claims against the state.
Indeed, the mutually constitutive relation between the law and the
enterprise of governance is arguably most manifest when members of
minority groupswho are already in an asymmetrically disadvantaged
position of powermake claims upon the enterprise of governance. This
dynamic involving minority groups is not limited to the Islamic legal
tradition, but rather is characteristic of the challenges that arise when
governing amidst diversity.
Certainly some readers may be uneasy with the conclusions of this
study. Those committed to the myth of Islamic persecution may ind the
parallels drawn to legal traditions elsewhere in the world outrageous.
Those compelled to vindicate the myth of an Islamic harmony may
ind the treatment of the covered Muslim woman not only disgraceful,
but also a useful diversion from the often-negative attention paid to
the premodern Islamic tradition. At the beginning of the twenty- irst
century, there is no shortage of inger-pointing by those antagonistic to
the Muslim world, or by those who, out of post-colonial angst, are all too
happy to point out the hypocrisies and inconsistencies of Western-styled
democratic constitutional governance. In both cases, though, the ingerpointing only perpetuates the othering that has been identi ied in this
study as a veritable hallmark of human experience through the ages.
There is no reason to deny that factual di erences contribute to
boundaries that thereby create the conditions for othering. Such factual
dierences are part of everyday experience. For instance, to assert
a sense of community, family, or even of self often involves asserting a
boundary beyond which the Other lies. Communities might internally
divide amongst themselves, creating minorities within minorities, or
sects within a larger overarching label. The fact of di erence is not itself
suspect. Rather, the apprehension underlying this study is whether, when,
why, and under what circumstances a factual dierence should become
normatively relevant such as to justify and legitimate di erentiation
For instance, S.A. Zaidi recounts the various debates among northern Indian
Muslims concerning who is a Muslim. In doing so, he recounts the views of dierent
groupings of Muslims within the larger Muslim community, and shows how even the
seemingly fair, but general label of Muslim can hide considerable debate, dissent,
and fractiousness: S.A. Zaidi, Who is a Muslim? Identities of ExclusionNorth Indian
Muslims, c.
Conclusion
323
324
Conclusion
Conclusion
325
326
Conclusion
intentional. Those dynamics can and usually will dominate over and
against those who claim and demand space for their di erence. When a
minority member makes a claim against an enterprise of governance, a
discursive site appears that makes plain the hegemonic potential of the
law in the interests, quite often, of an enterprise of governance. At that
site, as the readers imagination takes light, it is hoped the reader might
also take account of, if not necessarily work against, the hegemony that
can and often does arise.
Bibliography
Note: Entries for the online version of the Encyclopaedia of Islam, Second Edition,
edited by P. Bearman, Th. Bianquis, C.E. Bosworth, E. van Donzel, and W.E.
Heinrichs (Leiden: Brill, 2009; Brill Online, University of Toronto, at <http://
www.brillonline.nl/subscriber/entry?entry-islam_SIM> are indicated by the
short form El2 , s.v.
Arabic Sources
Abd al-Jabbr, Al-Q. Shar al-Ul al-Khamsa. Beirut: Dr Iy al-Turth alArab, 2001.
Abduh, Muammad. Ikhtilf al-Qawnn bi Ikhtilf Awl al-Umam. In
al-Aml al-Kmila lil-Imm Muammad Abduh: al-Kitbt al-Siysiyy.
Ed. Muammad Imra. 30915. Beirut: al-Muassasa al-Arabiyya, 1972.
Al-ls, Ab al-Fal Mamd. R al-Man Tafsr al-Qurn al-Am wa alSab al-Mathn. Beirut: Dr al-Fikr, 1997.
Al-mid, Sayf al-Dn. Al-Ikm Ul al-Akm. Beirut: Dr al-Fikr, 1997.
Al-Asmand, Muammad. Badhl al-Naar al-Ul. Ed. Muammad Zak Abd
al-Barr. Cairo: Maktabat Dr al-Turth, 1992.
Al-Ayn, Badr al-Dn. Al-Binya Shar al-Hidya. Ed. Ayman li Shabn.
Beirut: Dr al-Kutub al-Ilmiyya, 2000.
.Umdat al-Qr Shar a al-Bukhr. Ed. Abd Allh Mamd Muammad
Umar. Beirut: Dr al-Kutub al-Ilmiyya, 2001.
Al-Azhar, li Abd al-Sam al-b. Jawhir al-Ikll. Ed. Muammad Abd
al-Azz al-Khlid. Beirut: Dr al-Kutub al-Ilmiyya, 1997.
Al-Baghaw, Ab Muammad al-usayn b. Masd. Al-Tahdhb Fiqh al-Imm
al-Sh i. Eds dil Amad Abd al-Mawjd and Al Muammad Muawwa.
Beirut: Dr al-Kutub al-Ilmiyya, 1997.
Al-Baht. Kashshf al-Qin an Matn al-Iqn. Beirut: Dr al-Kutub al-Ilmiyya,
1997.
Al-Baldhur, Amad b. Yay. Kitb Fut al-Buldn. Ed. M.J. de Goeje. Leiden:
Brill, 1966.
Al-Bqilln, Ab Bakr. Al-Taqrb wa al-Irshd al-aghr. Ed. Abd al-amd b. Al
Ab Zunayd. Beirut: Muassasat al-Risla, 1998.
Al-Bar, Ab al-usayn. Al-Mutamad Ul al-Fiqh. Beirut: Dr al-Kutub
al-Ilmiyya, n.d.
Al-Bayhaq, Ab Bakr. Al-Sunan al-Kubr. Ed. Muammad Abd al-Qdir A.
Beirut: Dr al-Kutub al-Ilmiyya, 1999.
Al-Bukhr, Abd al-Azz b. Amad. Kashf al-Asrr an Ul Fakhr al-Islm
al-Bazdaw. Ed. Muammad al-Mutaim bi Allh al-Baghdd. Beirut: Dr
al-Kitb al-Arab, 1997.
328
Bibliography
Al-Dr Qun. Sunan al-Dr Qun. Ed. Magd al-Shr. Beirut: Dr al-Kutub
al-Ilmiyya, 1996.
Al-Dhahab. Siyar Alm al-Nubal. 4th ed. Beirut: Muassasat al-Risla, 1986.
Al-Frb, Ab Nar. Ful Muntaaa. Ed. Fawz Najjr. Beirut: Dr al-Mashraq,
1971.
Al-Ghazl, Ab mid. Al-Musaf min Ilm al-Ul. Baghdad: Maktabat
al-Muthanna, n.d.
. Al-Tibr al-Masbk Naat al-Mulk. Ed. Muammad Damaj. Beirut:
Muassasat Izz al-Dn, 1996.
. Al-Wajz Fiqh al-Imm al-Sh i. Eds Al Muawwa and dil Abd
al-Mawjd. Beirut: Dr al-Arqam, 1997.
. Al-Was al-Madhhab. Ed. Ab Amr al-usayn. Beirut: Dr al-Kutub
al-Ilmiyya, 2001.
assn, usayn mid. Naariyyat al-Malaa al-Fiqh al-Islm. Cairo: Dr
al-Naha al-Arabiyya, 1971.
Al-ab. Mawhib al-Jall. Ed. Zakariyy Amrt. Beirut: Dr al-Kutub
al-Ilmiyya, 1995.
Al-ill, al-Muaqqiq. Shar al-Islm Masil al-all wa al-arm. Ed. diq
al-Shrz. 10th ed. Beirut: Markaz al-Rasl al-Aam, 1998.
Al-urr al-mil. Wasil al-Sha. Beirut: Dr Iy al-Turth al-Arab, n.d.
Ibn Ab al-Damm. Kitb Adab al-Qad. Ed. Muammad al-Qdir At. Beirut: Dr
al-Kutub al-Ilmiyya, 1987.
Ibn al-Arab, Ab Bakr. Kitb al-Qabas. Ed. Muammad Abd Allh Walad Karm.
Beirut: Dr al-Gharb al-Islm, 1992.
. riat al-Awadh b Shar a al-Tirmidh. Beirut: Dr al-Kutub
al-Ilmiyya, 1997.
Ibn Askir,Ali b. al-asan. Tarkh Madnat Damashq. Ed. Umar b. Gharma
al-Amraw. Beirut: Dr al-Fikr, 1995.
Ibn ajr al-Asqaln. Fat al-Br: Shar a al-Bukhr. Eds Muammad Abd
al-Bq and Muibb al-Dn al-Khab. Beirut: Dr al-Marifa, n.d.
Ibn anbal, Amad. Musnad al-Imm Amad b. anbal. Eds. Samr aha alMajzb et al. Beirut: al-Maktab al-Islm, 1993.
Ibn azm. Al-Muall bil-thr. Ed. Abd al-Gha r Sulaymn al-Bandr.
Beirut: Dr al-Kutub al-Ilmiyya, n.d.
Ibn Hishm. Al-Sra al-Nabawiyya. Eds Muaf al-Saq, Ibrhm al-Abyr and
Abd al-a Shalb. Beirut: Dr al-Marifa, n.d.
Ibn Imd. Shadhart al-Dhahab Akhbr man Dhahab. Beirut: Dr al-Kutub
al-Ilmiyya, n.d.
Ibn Isq, Khall. Mukhtaar Khall. Ed. Amad Al arakt. Beirut: Dr al-Fikr,
1995.
Ibn al-Jawz. al-Taqq Adth al-Khilf. Ed. Muammad Fris. Beirut: Dr
al-Kutub al-Ilmiyya, n.d.
Ibn Khallikn. Wafayt al-Ayn. Eds Ysuf Al wl and Maryam Qsim wl.
Beirut: Dr al-Kutub al-Ilmiyya, 1998.
Arabic Sources
329
Ibn Mjah. Al-Sunan. Eds Muammad Nir al-Dn al-Albn and Al al-alab
al-Athar. Riyadh: Maktabat al-Marif, 1998.
Ibn Manr. Lisn al-Arab. 3rd ed. Beirut: Dr dir, 1994.
Ibn Miskawayh. Tahdhb al-Akhlq wa Tahr al-Arf. Ed. Ibn al-Khab. N.p.:
Maktabat al-Thaqfa al-Dniyya, n.d.
Ibn Mu li, Ab Abd Allh. Al-Fur. Ed. Ab al-Zahr zim al-Q. Beirut:
Dr al-Kutub al-Ilmiyya, 1997.
Ibn Mu li, Ab Isq. Al-Mubdi Shar al-Muqni. Ed. Zahr Shawsh. Beirut:
al-Maktab al-Islm, 1974.
Ibn al-Najjr. Shar Kawkab al-Munr: Mukhtaar al-Tarr. Eds Muammad alZuayl and Nazr ammd. Riyadh: Maktabat al-Ubaykn, 1997.
Ibn Naqb al-Mir, Ahmad. Reliance of the Traveller: A Classic Manual of Islamic
Sacred Law. Trans. Nuh H.M. Keller. Rev. ed. Evanston, Illinois: Sunna Books,
1994.
Ibn Nujaym. Al-Shar al-Bar al-Riq. Beirut: Dr al-Kutub al-Ilmiyya, 1997.
Ibn Qayyim al-Jawziyya. Awn al-Mabd: Shar Sunan Ab Dwd. Beirut: Dr
al-Kutub al-Ilmiyya, 1998.
Ibn Qudma, Abd Allh b. Amad. Al-Mughn. Beirut: Dr Iy al-Turth
al-Arab, n.d.
Ibn Rushd al-a d. Bidyat al-Mujtahid wa Nihyat al-Muqtaid. Eds Al
Muawwa and dil Abd al-Mawjd. Beirut: Dr al-Kutub al-Ilmiyya, 1997.
.The Book of the Decisive Treatise Determining the Connection Between
the Law and Wisdom. In Decisive Treatise & Epistle Dedicatory. Trans. Charles
Butterworth. 137. Provo, Utah: Brigham Young University Press, 2001 (with
facing Arabic and English translation).
Ibn Rushd al-Jadd. Al-Bayn wa al-Tal. Beirut: Dr al-Gharb al-Islm, 1988.
. Al-Muqaddimt al-Mumahhidt. Ed. Muammad ajj. Beirut: Dr al-Gharb
al-Islm, 1988.
Ibn Taymiyya, Taq al-Dn. Al-Siysa al-Shariyya Ilh al-R wa al-Raiyya.
Beirut: Dr al-Kutub al-Ilmiyya, 1988.
Al-Ja, Ab Bakr. Akm al-Qurn. Ed. Abd al-Salm Muammad Al Shhn.
Beirut: Dr al-Kutub al-Ilmiyya, 1994.
. Al-Ful al-Ul. Ed. Muammad Muammad Tmir. Beirut: Dr al-Kutub
al-Ilmiyya, 2000.
Al-Juwayn, Ab al-Mal. Kitb al-Ijtihd min Kitb al-Talkh. Ed. Abd al-amd
Ab Zunayr. Damascus: Dr al-Qalam, 1987.
. Kitb al-Talkh Ul al-Fiqh. Eds Abd Allh al-Nibal and Shabbir Amad
al-Amr. Beirut: Dr al-Bashir al-Islmiyya, 1996.
. Al-Burhn Ul al-Fiqh. Beirut: Dr al-Kutub al-Ilmiyya, 1997.
Al-Ksn, Ab Bakr b. Masd. Badi al-ani Tartb al-Shari. Eds Al
Muammad Muawwa and dil Amad Abd al-Mawjd. Beirut: Dr
al-Kutub al-Ilmiyya, 1997.
Al-Khab al-Baghddi. Kitb al-Faqh wa al-Mutafaqqih. Cairo: Zakariyy Al
Ysuf, 1977.
330
Bibliography
English Sources
331
332
Bibliography
English Sources
333
334
Bibliography
Blankinship, Khalid Yahya. The End of the Jihad State: The Reign of Hisham Ibn
Abd al-Malik and the Collapse of the Umayyads. Albany: State University of
New York Press, 1994.
Bobbitt, Philip. Constitutional Fate: Theory of the Constitution. New York: Oxford
University Press, 1982.
Bosworth, C.E. The Concept of Dhimma in Early Islam. In Christian and Jews in the
Ottoman Empire: The Functioning of a Plural Society. Eds Benjamin Braude and
Bernard Lewis. 2 vols 1:3754. New York: Holmes & Meier Publishers, 1982.
Bosworth, C.E., Netton, I.R., and Vogel, F.E. El2, s.v., Siysa.
Bouchard, Grard and Taylor, Charles. Building The Future, A Time for
Reconciliation: Report. Quebec City: Commission de consultation sur le
pratiques daccomodement reliees aux dierence culture 2008.
Boudhiba, Abdelwahab. The Protection of Minorities. In The Different Aspects
of Islamic Culture: The Individual and Society in Islam. Ed. A. Boudhiba and
M. Maruf al-Dawalibi. 33146. Paris: UNESCO, 1998.
Boykin, William G. et al., Shariah: The Threat to America: An Exercise in Competitive
Analysis: Report of Team BII, Washington D.C.: Center for Security Policy, 2010.
(<http://shariahthethreat.org/wp-content/uploads/2011/04/Shariah-TheThreat-to-America-Team-B-Report-Web-09292010.pdf>) (accessed October
28, 2010).
Brandt, Michele and Kaplan, Je rey A. The Tension between Womens Rights
and Religious Rights: Reservations to CEDAW by Egypt, Bangladesh and
Tunisia. Journal of Law and Religion 12, no. 1 (199596): 10542.
Braude, Benjamin. Foundation Myths of the Millet System. In Christians and
Jews in the Ottoman Empire: The Functioning of a Plural Society. Eds Benjamin
Braude and Bernard Lewis. 2 vols. 1:6988, 6972. New York: Holmes &
Meier Publishers, 1982.
. The Strange History of the Millet System. In The Great OttomanTurkish
Civilization. Ed, Kemal Cicek. 2 vols. 2:40918. Ankara: Yeni Turkiye, 2000.
. and Lewis, Bernard, eds. Christian and Jews in the Ottoman Empire: The
Functioning of a Plural Society. 2 vols. New York: Holmes & Meier Publishers,
1982.
Breiner, Bert F. Shara and Religious Pluralism. In Religion, Law and Society:
A ChristianMuslim Discussion. Ed. Tarek Mitri. 5162. Geneva: WCC
Publications, 1995.
Breivik, Anders. 2083: A European Declaration of Independence. <http://
publicintelligence.net/anders-behring-breiviks-complete-manifesto-2083a-european-declaration-of-independence/> (accessed March 24, 2012).
Bremmer, Ian. The End of the Free Market: Who Wins the War Between States and
Corporations. New York: Portfolio, 2010.
Brinton, Jasper Y. The Mixed Courts of Egypt. Rev. ed. New Haven: Yale University
Press, 1968.
Brockelmann, C. El2, s.v., al- Mward Abu l-asan Al b. Muammad b. abb.
Brockopp, Jonathan E. The Essential Sharah: Teaching Islamic Law in the
Religious Studies Classroom. In Teaching Islam. Ed. Brannon M. Wheeler.
7793. New York: Oxford University Press, 2003.
English Sources
335
336
Bibliography
English Sources
337
338
Bibliography
Faruqi, Ismail R. The Rights of Non-Muslims under Islam: Social and Cultural
Aspects. In Muslim Communities in non-Muslim States, 4366. London: Islamic
Council of Europe, 1980.
Feldman, Noah. What We Owe Iraq: War and the Ethics of Nation Building.
Princeton: Princeton University Press, 2006.
Fenton, Paul. Book Review: Islam and Dhimmitude. Midstream 49, no. 2
(2003): 401.
Finnis, John. Nationality, Alienage and Constitutional Principle. Law Review
Quarterly 123 (July 2007): 41745.
. Endorsing Discrimination between Faiths: A Case of Extreme Speech?
Oxford Legal Studies Research Paper No. 09/2008; Notre Dame Legal
Studies Paper No. 0808; Islamic Law and Law of the Muslim World No.
0816. Available at SSRN: <http://ssrn.com/abstract=1101522> (accessed
December 19, 2011).
Forst, Rainer. The Limits of Toleration. Constellations 11, no. 3 (2004): 31225.
Fram, Edward. Two Cases of Adultery and the Halakhic Decision-Making
Process. AJS Review 26, no. 2 (2002): 277300.
Frank, Daniel and Leon Nemoy. Karaites. In Encyclopedia of Religion, Second
Edition. Ed. Lindsay Jones. 8: 50828. Detroit: Macmillan Reference, 2005.
Freedman, David Noel. The Nine Commandments: Uncovering the Hidden Pattern
of Crime and Punishment in the Hebrew Bible. New York: Doubleday, 2000.
Freidenreich, David M. Foreigners and Their Food: Constructing Otherness in
Jewish, Christian, and Islamic Law. Berkeley: University of California Press,
2011.
Friedmann, Yohanan. Classi ication of Unbelievers in Sunni Muslim Law and
Tradition. Jerusalem Studies in Arabic & Islam 22, (1998): 16395.
. Tolerance and Coercion in Islam. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
2003.
Frum, David. Whats Right. National Review 54, no. 24 (December 23, 2002):
60.
Fukuyama, Francis. The End of History and the Last Man. New York: Free Press,
1992.
. Re lections on The End of History: Five Years Later. History & Theory 34,
no. 2 (1995): 2743.
. There are No Short Cuts to The End of History. New Perspectives Quarterly
23, no. 2 (2006): 358.
Fuller, Lon L. The Morality of Law. Rev. ed. New Haven: Yale University Press,
1969.
Gauthier-Villars, David. France moves on ban of some Islamic veils. The Wall
Street Journal. July 14, 2010. A15.
Gerard, Jasper. Faith, the veil, shopping, and me. Sunday Times (March 26,
2006): 5.
Gervers, Michael and Ramzi J. Bikhazi, eds. Conversion and Continuity: Indigenous
Christian Communities in Islamic Lands, Eighth to Eighteenth Centuries.
Toronto: Ponti ical Institute of Medieval Studies, 1990.
English Sources
339
Gibb, H.A.R. Studies on the Civilization of Islam. Eds. Stanford Shaw and William
Polk. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1962.
Gilliot, Cl., Repp, R.C., Nizami, K.A., Hooker, M.B., Lin, Chang-Kuan, and Hunwick,
J.O. El2 , s.v., Ulam.
Goddard, Hugh. ChristianMuslim Relations: A Look Backward and a Look
Forwards. Islam and ChristianMuslim Relations 11, no. 2 (2000): 195212.
Goitein, S.D. A Turning Point in the History of the Muslim State. In Studies in
Islamic History and Institutions, 14967. Leiden: Brill, 1968.
Goldziher, Ignaz. Introduction to Islamic Theology and Law. Trans. Andras and
Ruth Hamori. Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1981.
Goodich, Michael, ed. Other Middle Ages: Witnesses at the Margins of Medieval
Society. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press, 1998.
Gottheil, Richard. Dhimmis and Moslems in Egypt. In Old Testament and
Semitic Studies. Eds Robert Francis Harber, Francis Brown and George Foot
Moore. 2 vols. 1:353414, 3824. Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
1908.
. A Fetwa on the Appointment of Dhimmis to Of ice. In Zeitschrift fur
Assyriologie und Verwandte Gebiete. Ed. Carol Bezold, 20314. Strassburg:
Verlag von Karl J. Trubner, 1912.
. An Answer to the Dhimmis. Journal of the American Oriental Society 41
(1921): 383457.
Green, Leslie. The Authority of the State. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1988.
. Pluralism, Social Con lict, and Tolerance. In Pluralism and Law. Ed. Arend
Soeteman, 85105. London: Kluwer Academic Publishers, 2001.
. On Being Tolerated. In The Legacy of H.L.A. Hart. 277298. Ed. M. Kramer
et al. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2008.
Glen, M. Fethullah. Toward a Global Civilization of Love and Tolerance. The
Light, Inc., 2004.
Haarmann, Ulrich. Mamluk Endowment Deeds as a Source for the History of
Education in Late Medieval Egypt. Al-Abhath 28 (1980): 3147.
Habermas, Jrgen. Religion in the Public Sphere. European Journal of Philosophy
14, no. 1 (2006): 125.
Hacker, Joseph R. Jewish Autonomy in the Ottoman Empire: Its Scope and
Limits. Jewish Courts from the Sixteenth to the Eighteenth Centuries. In The
Jews of the Ottoman Empire. Ed. Avigdor Levy, 153202. Princeton: Darwin
Press, 1994.
Haddad, Wadi Zaidan. Ahl al-Dhimma in an Islamic State: The Teaching of Abu
al-Hasan al-Mawardis al-Ahkam al-Sultaniyya. Islam and ChristianMuslim
Relations 7, no. 2 (1996): 16980.
Hallaq, Wael B. Was the Gate of Ijtihd Closed? International Journal of Middle
East Studies 16, no. 1 (1984): 341.
. Was al-Sha ii the Master Architect of Islamic Jurisprudence?
International Journal of Middle East Studies 25 (1993): 587605.
. A History of Islamic Legal Theories. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1997.
340
Bibliography
English Sources
341
342
Bibliography
English Sources
343
344
Bibliography
English Sources
345
Mernissi, Fatima. The Veil and the Male Elite: A Feminist Interpretation of Womens
Rights in Islam. Trans. Mary Jo Lakeland. New York: Basic Books, 1992.
Merry, Sally Engle. Law and Colonialism. Law and Society Review 25, no. 4
(1991): 89122.
Mikhail, John. Dilemmas of Cultural Legality: A Comment on Roger Cotterrells
The Struggle for Law and a Criticism of the House of Lords Opinions in
Begum. International Journal of Law in Context 4, no. 4 (2009): 38593.
Mir-Hosseini, Ziba. The Construction of Gender in Islamic Legal Thought and
Strategies for Reform. Hawwa 1, no. 1 (2003): 128.
. Muslim Womens Quest for Equality: Between Islamic Law and Feminism.
Critical Inquiry 32 (2006): 62945.
Miskawayh, Amad b. Muammad. The Re inement of Character. Trans.
Constantine K. Zurayk. Beirut: American University of Beirut, 1968.
Moad, Edward Omar. A Path to the Oasis: Sharah and Reason in Islamic Moral
Epistemology. International Journal for Philosophy and Religion 62, no. 3
(2007): 13548.
Moaddel, Mansoor. Islamic Modernism, Nationalism, and Fundamentalism:
Episode and Discourse. Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 2005.
Modarressi Tabtabi, Hussein. Kharj in Islamic Law. London: Anchor Press
Ltd, 1983.
. Some Recent Analysis of the Concept of majz in Islamic Jurisprudence.
Journal of the American Oriental Society 106, no. 4 (1986): 78791.
Moeckli, Daniel. Of Minarets and Foreign Criminals: Swiss Direct Democracy
and Human Rights. Human Rights Law Review 11, no. 4 (2011): 77494.
Mller, Jrgen and Skaaning, Svend-Erik. On the Limited Interchangeability of
rule of law measures. European Political Science Review 3, no. 3 (2011): 37194.
Molotch, Harvey. The Rest Room and Equal Opportunity. Sociological Forum
3, no. 1 (1988): 12832.
Morony, Michael G. Iraq after the Muslim Conquest. Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 1984.
. The Age of Conversions: A Reassessment. In Conversion and Continuity:
Indigenous Christian Communities in Islamic Lands, Eighth to Eighteenth
Centuries. Eds Michael Gervers and Ramzi J. Bikhazi, 13550. Toronto:
Ponti ical Institute of Medieval Studies, 1990.
Moss, Dana and Krieger, Zvika. Policing Religion. New Statesman, September
3, 2007, 1617, 17.
Mottahedeh, Roy. Loyalty and Leadership in an Early Islamic Society. Princeton:
Princeton University Press, 1980.
Motzki, Harald. The Origins of Islamic Jurisprudence: Meccan Fiqh Before the
Classical Schools. Trans. Marion H. Katz. Leiden: Brill, 2001.
Mumisa, Michael. Islamic Law: Theory & Interpretation. Beltsville, Maryland:
Amana Publications, 2002.
Murphy, Andrew R. Toleration and the Liberal Tradition. Polity 29, no. 4
(1997): 593623.
Muztar, A.D. Dhimmis in an Islamic State. Islamic Studies 18, no. 1 (1979):
6575.
346
Bibliography
Nasir, Jamal J. The Islamic Law of Personal Status. 3rd ed. London: Graham &
Trotman, 2002.
Nasr, Vali. International Relations of an Islamist Movement: The Case of the
Jamaat-i Islami of Pakistan. New York: Council on Foreign Relations, 2000.
Nemoy, L. and Zajaczkowski, W. Early Karaism. The Jewish Quarterly Review
40, no. 3 (1950): 30715.
. El2 , s.v., Karaites.
Nurrohman, Bandung. A lesson to draw from the Swiss ban on minarets. The
Jakarta Post. 15 December 2009. P. 7.
Nussbaum, Martha. Liberty of Conscience: In Defense of Americas Tradition of
Religious Equality. New York: Basic Books, 2008.
Ohnesorge, John K.M. The Rule of Law. Annual Review of Law and Social Science
3 (2007): 99114.
Pedersen, J., et al. and El2 , s.v., Madrasa.
Peerenboom, Randy. The Future of Rule of Law: Challenges and Prospects for
the Field. Hague Journal of the Rule of Law 1 (2009): 110.
Peirce, Leslie. Morality Tales: Law and Gender in the Ottoman Court of Aintab.
Berkeley: University of California Press, 2003.
Peri, Oded. The Muslim waqf and the Collection of jizya in Late Eighteenthcentury Jerusalem. In Ottoman Palestine, 18001914: Studies in Economic and
Social History. Ed. Gad G. Gilbar, 28797. Leiden: Brill, 1990.
Philliou, Christine M. Biography of an Empire: Governing Ottomans in an Age of
Revolution. Berkeley: University of California Press, 2011.
Polisi, Catherine E. Universal Rights and Cultural Relativism: Hinduism and
Islam Deconstructed. World Affairs 167, no. 1 (2004): 417.
Poole, Thomas. Of Headscarves and Heresies: The Denbigh High School Case
and Public Authority Decision-Making Under the Human Rights Act. Public
Law (2005): 68595.
Post, Robert S. The Social Foundations of Privacy: Community and Self in the
Common Law Tort. California Law Review 77, no. 5 (1989): 9571010.
Powers, David S. Studies in Quran and Hadith: The Formation of the Islamic Law
of Inheritance. Berkeley: University of California Press, 1986.
. Orientalism, Colonialism, and Legal History: The Attack on Muslim
Family Endowments in Algeria and India. Comparative Studies in Society and
History 31, no. 3 (1989): 53571.
. Law, Society and Culture in the Maghreb, 13001500. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2002.
Prakash, Gyan. Orientalism Now. History and Theory 34, no. 3 (1995): 199
212.
Al-Qattan, Najwa. Dhimmis in the Muslim Court: Legal Automony and
Religious. Discrimination. International Journal of Middle East Studies 31
(1999): 42944.
Qureshi, Aijaz Hassan. The Terms Kharaj and Jizya and Their Implications.
Journal of the Punjab University Historical Society 12 (1961): 2738.
Rahman, Fazlur. Islamic Methodology in History. Islamabad: Islamic Research
Institute, 1964.
English Sources
347
348
Bibliography
English Sources
349
Stilt, Kristen. The mutasib, law, and society in early Mamluk Cairo and Fustat
(648802/12501400). PhD dissertation. Harvard University, 2004.
. Islamic Law in Action: Authority, Discretion and Everyday Experiences in
Mamluk Egypt. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2012.
Stockett, Kathryn. The Help: A Novel. New York: Penguin, 2009.
Stone, Suzanne Last. The Intervention of American Law in Jewish Divorce: A
Pluralist Analysis. Israel Law Review, 34 (Summer 2000): 170210.
Suberu, Rotimi T. The Supreme Court and Federalism in Nigeria. Journal of
Modern African Studies 46, no. 3 (2008): 45185.
Sunstein, Cass R. and Vermeule, Adrian. Interpretation and Institutions.
Michigan Law Review 101, no. 4 (2003): 885951.
Tabtabi, Hossein Modarressi. Kharj in Islamic Law. London: Anchor Press,
Ltd., 1983.
Taha, Mahmoud Mohamed. The Second Message of Islam. Trans. Abdullahi
Ahmed An-Naim. Syracuse: Syracuse University Press, 1996.
Tamanaha, Brian. On the Rule of Law: History, Politics, Theory. Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 2004.
Taqi Usmani, Muhammad. The Islamization of Laws in Pakistan: The Case of
Hudud Ordinances. Muslim World 96, no. 2 (April 2006): 287304.
Taylor, Charles. Sources of the Self. Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1992.
. Modern Social Imaginaries. Durham, North Carolina: Duke University
Press, 2004.
Tibawi, A.L. Origin and Character of Al-Madrasah. Bulletin of the School of
Oriental and African Studies 25, no. 2 (1962): 22538.
Tibi, Bassam. The Crisis of Modern Islam: A Preindustrial Culture in the Scienti icTechnological Age. Trans. Judith von Sivers. Salt Lake City: University of Utah
Press, 1988.
Toobin, Je rey. Swing Shift: How Anthony Kennedy's Passion for Foreign Law
Could Change the Supreme Court. The New Yorker, September 12, 2005, P. 42.
Tritton, A.S. The Caliphs and their Non-Muslim Subjects: A Critical Study of the
Covenant of Umar. London: Frank Cass and Co., Ltd, 1970.
Tucker, Charles E. Cabbages and Kings: Bridging the Gap for More Eective
Capacity-Building. University of Pennsylvania Journal of International Law 32
(2011): 10125.
Tully, James. Public Philosophy in a New Key. 2 vols. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 2008.
Tyler, Aaron. Islam, the West and Tolerance: Conceiving Coexistence. New York:
Palgrave MacMillan, 2008.
Tyser, C.R., et al. Trans. The Mejelle: Being an English Translation of Majallah
El-Ahkam-I-Adliya and a Complete Code on Islamic Civil Law. Kuala Lumpur:
The Other Press, 2001.
Vajda, G. Ahl al- Kitb. Encyclopaedia of Islam. Eds P. Bearman, Th. Bianquis,
C.E. Bosworth, E. van Donzel and W.P. Heinrichs. Leiden: Brill, 2008. (Brill
Online, University of Toronto, accessed 04 September 2008.)
350
Bibliography
351
352
Bibliography
353
Index
Abd al-Jabbr, al-Q82, 84
Abd Allh Ibn Salm 150, 158, 1601,
3034, 3079
Abella, Rosalie 67, 279
Ab lib, Al ibn see Al ibn Ab lib
Abou El Fadl, Khaled 4, 1012, 1845,
282
Ab Bakr 501, 578
Ab anfa 116
Ab Ysuf 116, 238
Abu-Lughod, Lila 312
Abu-Odeh, Lama 171, 212
accommodation6, 236, 905,
10636, 25861, 268, 282, 292,
31112 see also humiliation;
subordination/submission
adulterers, stoning to death
of 14664, 256, 272, 3034, 3079
Afghanistan 62, 218
Agamben, Giorgio 124
Akasoy, Anna 356
Al-mid, Sayf al-Dn 80, 203
alcohol 10813, 136, 1423, 279
see also core values; property;
public drunkenness,
public good
Alford, Roger P 2867
Algeria, colonialism in 2089
Al ibn Ab lib 68, 90, 156, 240
Anderson, Benedict 21
Anghie, Antony 2468, 257
Annan, Ko i 1819
Anscombe, Frederick F 209
apostasy 289, 578, 103, 232, 2367,
24557 see also Malaysia; Lina Joy
case
aqd al-dhimma see contract of
protection
Arab Spring 623, 21819
Aristotle 324
Arnaldez, Roger 176
Arneil, Barbara 60
Arslan, Alp 193
assimilation 2756, 309
al-Aswad al-Kind, ibn al-Miqdd74
356
Index
Index
core values
alcohol 1423
contract of protection 126
covered Muslim women 272, 2759,
310, 31213, 320
dierence, regulation of 967
iqh 131
governance 96, 126, 1301, 1789,
258
insiders and outsiders, dhimms
as 131
jurists 126, 1423
marginalization 274
Other 967
property 1423
public good 1423
religious minorities 273, 27980
superiority/primacy of Islam 126,
130
universalism 131, 142
ul al- iqh 9
counter-majoritarianism 20, 285
covered Muslim women, regulation
of 260, 269313
assimilation 2756
authority 291
awra, de inition of 283
bans 31011, 31920
Belgium 310, 319
Canada 269, 279, 310
citizenship 2718, 31011
colonialism 270
core values 272, 2759, 310, 31213,
320
counter-majoritarianism 285
democracy 299300
dhimm, covered women as the
new 310, 312
drivers licences, photos on 2805,
288, 2901, 3201
Europe 96, 26972, 2759, 291311
European Convention on Human
Rights 275, 293310, 321
extremism 2948, 3002, 309
foreigners, covered women as 280
91
France 2712, 2759, 31011,
31920
gender equality 2778, 31112, 320,
323
governance 26971, 281, 284, 291,
297, 301, 30812, 3202
hegemony 234, 272, 275, 2789,
291, 30313, 320
357
358
Index
deterrence 106
dhimm rules see also contract of
protection; history of dhimm
rules; jizya
alcohol 10813, 136, 1423, 279
attire, restrictions on34, 1316,
229
dierence, regulation of 95144
discrimination 34, 367, 44
genealogy of rules 726
harmony, myth of 25, 3441, 74, 99,
135, 314, 322
hegemony 245, 317
home construction regulation34,
12631
imperialism 22, 609, 220
jurists 24
land tax liability 1212, 230
legal subject, the dhimm as 7794,
314
military service 34, 37
modern state 24, 28, 232
Other, the 42
Ottoman courts, use of 434
persecution, myth of 25, 34, 3845,
99, 135, 223, 272, 314, 322
pork 10813, 136
post-colonial Muslim states,
in 22359
reason and the obligation to
obey 7987
religion of dhimms in the public
sphere 667, 11926, 22930, 279
religious minorities 23, 260313
religious sites 11923, 22930, 279
Saudi Arabia, wrongful death
damages in 23245
Shara as Rule of Law 7, 1621, 24,
278, 16777, 31417
sources 726
termination of use of term
dhimm378
tolerance 25, 7, 24, 3346, 1412,
314
transport, modes of 1316, 229
universalism 27, 609, 96, 220
witnesses 13641, 31819
Diefenbaker, John 31819
difference847, 95144, 31718,
3226
diplomas 228 see also ijza
disabilities, persons with323
discretionary authority of
rulers 1534, 177, 17983
discrimination
dhimm rules 34, 367, 44
dierence 3224
disabilities, persons with 323
examples 34, 37
gender equality 216, 2678, 2778,
31112, 320, 323
harmony, myth of 34, 367
historical context 34, 367
historiography 25
Jim Crow laws 3234
jizya 367
natural dierences 3234
religious minorities 4, 21415,
2678
Saudi Arabia, wrongful death
damages in 23345
Shara as Rule of Law 21415
domination see subordination/
submission
Donner, Fred 535, 589
Doumato, Eleanor Abdella 2278,
232
dress, restrictions on 34, 1316, 229
see also covered Muslim women,
regulation of
drivers licences, photos on 2805,
288, 2901, 3201
educational institutions18995, 212
Egypt 62, 315, 20711, 219, 224, 2267
elections623 see also democracy
El-Mahdi, Rabab 21819
Ely, John Hart 20
empire see Islamic imperialism
Europe96, 171, 20711, 26979,
291311, 315 see also individual
countries
European Convention on Human
Rights3, 275, 293310, 321
expulsion 33, 46, 4850, 53, 55, 59, 76
extremism 2948, 3002, 309
Faiza Tamby Chik, Datuk 253
family law 21213, 216
Faruqi, Ismail 37
Fethullah Glen, M 4
iqh
authority 89
colonialism 210, 257
core values 131
customary code 212
discretionary authority of
rulers 180
Index
ijtihd 89, 196, 198, 200, 205
legal subject, the dhimm as 79
Malaysia, apostasy case in 2578
Other, the 248
post-colonialism 259
Saudi Arabia, wrongful death
damages in 2578
Shara as Rule of Law 7, 89, 169,
212
tolerance 142
food regulations 21, 136
foreign law in US courts 28390
forelocks, cutting 134
Forst, Rainer 6
France
Algeria, colonialism in 2089
assimilation 275
citizenship 2759
covered Muslim women 2712,
2759, 31011, 31920
Frankfurter, Felix 2613
freedom of religion26, 2514,
2617, 2817, 290303, 305,
3201
manifestation of religious
belief 2936, 300, 320
Freeman, Sultaana 28091, 310,
321
Friedenreich, David 21
Friedmann, Yohanan 667
Frum, David 3940
Fukuyama, Francis 612
Fuller, Lon 1314
funerary rites 1289
fur 9 see also interpretation
gay people, treatment of 31819
gender 216, 2678, 2778, 31112,
320, 323 see also covered Muslim
women, regulation of
general rules, exceptions to 106,
11013, 1301, 137, 140, 1489,
162
general welfare, rules of see
mumalt
Gentile, Patrizia318
ghalabat al-ann2045 see also
interpretation
Al-Ghazl, Ab mid 1078, 110,
1334, 1789, 1812, 205
globalization 29
Gobitis, Lillian and William 2614,
2667
Gottheil, Richard 74
359
360
Index
governance (cont.)
reason and the obligation to obey 79,
856
religion of dhimms in the public
sphere 11925
religious minorities 23, 225, 265,
309, 3202
Saudi Arabia, wrongful death
damages in 235, 2412, 2445
siysa shariyya 177, 180, 183; see
also discretionary authority of
rulers
sovereign states 28, 170, 172, 207,
211, 2245, 257, 31516
tazr 177, 1803; see also
discretionary authority of rulers
theft 107, 11112
tolerance 56, 245
treaty/tax model 33, 467, 569
universalism 609, 88, 1445, 168,
1845, 2201, 315
witnesses 1401
Green, Leslie 5
Grotius, Hugo 60
Haddad, Wadi 98
hadth 1912, 1969, 2023, 212, 2378
al-kim 133
Hale, Brenda 2989, 3012
Hamidullah, Muhammad 99
anbal, Amad ibn 120
harmony, myth of 25, 3441, 74, 99,
135, 314, 322
al-attb 103, 181
Hearn, Julie 61
hegemony of law
adulterers, stoning to death of 151,
1578, 162
colonialism 258
covered Muslim women 234, 272,
275, 2789, 291, 30313, 320
dhimm rules 245, 317
governance 235, 163, 2479, 259,
320, 326
human rights 28
liberal democracies 2930, 612
Malaysia, apostasy case in 256,
2589
religious minorities 235, 2639,
27980, 310, 320
Saudi Arabia, wrongful death
damages in 235
Shara as Rule of Law 235, 151,
31617
Hillenkoetter, Roscoe318
history of dhimm rules
cleansing model 33, 46, 4850, 53,
55, 59, 76
contract of protection 6972
discrimination 34, 367
existence, ensuring 4754
governance 33, 44, 46, 5869, 76,
325
harmony, myth of 25, 3441, 74, 99,
135, 314, 322
historiography 25, 33, 41
Iberian peninsula 356
imperialism 25, 33, 4470, 76,
1456, 1556, 325
inclusion 6972
Jewish tribes, battles with 4754,
155
jizya 367, 979
judicial autonomy 424
jurists 25, 325
lease/rent model33, 467, 556, 57,
59
madrasa 190
marginalization 6972
Medina, securing 4757
muan 1567
persecution, myth of 25, 34, 3845,
99, 135, 223, 272, 314, 322
post-colonialism 2234
Shara as Rule of Law 1722, 33, 45,
20619, 222, 31617
sources 25
tolerance 3446
treaty/tax model 33, 467, 569
universalism 6070
Hoffman, Leonard 298, 3067
Hoffman, Murad 37
home construction regulation34,
12631
human rights 1, 4, 28, 211, 21316,
218, 233, 2424, 275, 293310, 321
humiliation 26, 37, 75, 99100,
105 see also accommodation,
subordination/submission
Hunter, James Davison 60, 31718
Hunwick, John O 120
Iberian Peninsula, conquest of 356
Ibn Abbs, Abd Allah 1289
Ibn Ab al-Damm 187
Ibn azm 112
Ibn Hishm 50
Ibn Manr 147
Index
Ibn Masd 186
Ibn Nujaym 1023, 122, 240
Ibn Qayyim al-Jawziyya 202
Ibn Qudma 75, 1045, 125, 130, 182,
199
Ibn Rushd al-a d (Averroes) 36,
153, 1767, 199
Ibn Rushd al-Jadd 103
Ibn Taymiyya, Taq al-Dn 1801
identity 21617, 231, 269, 315
ijza1923, 228
ijtihd79, 1756, 195206, 217
imagined communities 21
immigration 97, 2724, 30910
imperialism see Islamic imperialism
Indonesia 215
inheritance 11718, 127, 129, 142, 290
International Covenant on Civil and
Political Rights243
international law2467
Internet 29
interpretation see also authority;
ijtihd; jurists
adulterers, stoning to death of 155,
15762
al-ashbah 8, 2012, 204
authority 1757, 196206, 217
colonialism 210
fur 9
ghalabat al-ann 2045
ijtihd79, 1756, 195206, 217
istidll 1756
mufts 220
qadhf 155
qs 220
Shara as Rule of Law 712, 17,
1757, 195206, 220, 31617
Iran 2868, 28990
Iraq 589, 62, 218
Isin, Engin 274
Islamic imperialism2468
conversion to Islam 646
dhimm rules 22, 609, 220
existence, ensuring 4754
governance 214, 29, 33, 4469, 76,
168, 2201, 224, 227, 235, 248,
315, 325
historical context 25, 33, 4470, 76,
1456, 1556, 325
ijtihd 205
jihd 64
jizya 659, 97105
jurists 212, 609, 2201, 315
muan 1567
361
362
Index
Jizya (cont.)
governance 99101, 1035, 118
harmony, myth of 99
historical context 367, 979
humiliation 26, 75, 99100, 105
imperialism 659, 97105
inclusion 97, 99
jurists 735, 83, 1005
legal role 97, 99100, 102
marginalization 99
obligation 83
Other, the 37, 97, 101, 103
People of the Book 735, 1012
persecution, myth of 99
political role 97, 99100, 102, 105
polytheists 1023
Qurn 97, 101, 103
reason 83
religious freedom 26
Shara as Rule of Law 101, 1045
social contract 26, 97
subservience/subordination 37, 74,
99101
superiority/primacy of Islam 127
universalism 659, 98, 1001, 1035
Jordan 623
Joy, Lina see Lina Joy case
judges 11, 424, 1858, 220
judicial review1920, 305
jurists
authority 10, 12, 1757
autonomy 28
core values 126, 1423
iqh 200
fur 9
ghalabat al-ann 2045
governance 202, 144, 154, 163,
17788, 220, 309, 316
imagined communities 21
ijtihd 195205
legitimacy 912
madrasa 1914
public good 143
q 1858
reason 7987, 175, 3234
Shara as Rule of Law 712, 17,
204, 146, 164, 1689, 1727, 220
justice 172, 1779
al-Juwayn, Ab al-Mal 1012,
1767, 1878, 205
Kahn, Paul 49
al-Ksn, Ab Bakr 10912, 1245,
1345, 181
Index
al-Mward, Ab al-asan 8890,
105, 111, 1234, 129, 1389, 153,
1789, 199, 2378, 258, 268
Mecca, battles with forces of 4757
Medina, securing 4757
Menocal, Maria Rosa 35
military service 34, 37
minorities see religious minorities
missionaries in Africa 601
modern state
centralization 170
citizenship 97, 244
colonialism 207, 212, 216, 221, 242
dhimm rules 24, 28, 232
equality of sovereign states 28, 170,
207, 2267 family law 212
governance 24, 207, 2212, 232, 242,
248, 256, 2834, 31516
human rights 211, 216
immigration 97
national identity 216
Shara as Rule of Law 278, 1702,
194, 20622, 248, 2568, 2834, 315
mosques 1902
mumalt, 79, 81
Muwiya 241
Mu li, Ab Abd Allh ibn 125
mufts 220
Muammed, the Prophet 4657, 63,
66, 69, 746, 99, 1026, 124, 1289,
147, 150, 15562, 176, 1867,
1912, 196, 238, 240, 243, 303
muan1469, 151, 153, 1557
al-Mulk, Nim 189
multiculturalism 1, 2930
Muslim states and Islamic law 22359
capitulation agreements with
Ottoman Sultan 224
Egypt, adoption of Napoleonic Code
in 224, 2267
governance 224, 227, 232, 2589
jurists 2234, 2578
Malaysia, apostasy case in 232,
24559
Saudi Arabia 2278, 23245, 2578
United Nations 2267
al-Mutawakkil 133
nationalism 21, 21617, 231, 233
natural law 60
Nussbaum, Martha 2712
obligation see legal subject, the
dhimm as
363
Ohnesorge, John 15
Othering
adulterers, stoning to death of 158,
161
core values 967
covered Muslim women 271, 279,
289, 31012
dhimm rules 42
dress, restrictions on 134, 136
iqh248
human rights 1
Jews 161
jizya 97, 100, 104
muan 156
multiculturalism 1
Other, the107, 139, 145, 158, 161,
164, 271, 275, 299, 30812
persecution, myth of 389
public sphere, dhimms in the 124,
125
Saudi Arabia, wrongful death
damages in 232
Shara as Rule of Law 164, 1678
sovereign exception 49
theft, liability for 1078
tolerance 154, 31718
United States 289, 31718
Ottoman Empire reform period
(Tanzimat) 20910
Pact of Umar 702
Pedersen, J 191
People of the Book 667, 735, 85,
1012, 138, 227
persecution, myth of 25, 34, 3845,
99, 135, 223, 272, 314, 322
poll tax see jizya
polytheists 66, 69, 734, 1023
pork 10813, 136
Powers, David 2089
precedential reasoning see qiys
property 10819, 1423, 279
proselytization 124
public drunkenness see alcohol;
public good
public good
charitable endowments 114, 11619
core values 1423
covered Muslim women 26971, 279,
291, 294302, 31012, 320
governance 136, 182
jurists 143
Malaysia, apostasy case in 2545
national unity 2613
364
Index
Index
separate-but-equal 1920
September11, 2001 967, 2801,
290, 302
sexual slander see qadhf
Al-Sh i, Muammad ibn
Idrs 120, 197
Shh, Mlik 193
Shara as Rule of Law
adulterers, stoning to death
of 14951, 155, 1614
authority 12, 278, 1727, 189, 216,
21920
centralization 170, 314
charitable endowments 11415, 117
claim space, Shara as 1317, 1678,
1723, 20619, 31417
colonialism 20711, 21617, 221,
259
constitutionalism 21216, 218
constitutive conditions of
Shara 2067
contract of protection 912, 95
covered Muslim women 271, 275,
279, 284, 31213
death of Shara 1702
decentralization 173, 314
de inition 710, 13, 21920
democracy 1920
dhimm rules 7, 1624, 278, 16777,
31417
dierence, regulation of 144
discrimination 21416
European law 171
family law 171, 21213, 216
iqh 7, 89, 169, 212
fur 9
governance 1702, 20721
adth 212
hegemony 235, 151, 31617
historical development 722, 33, 45,
20619, 222, 31617
historiography 33
home construction regulation 127,
1301
human rights 28, 211, 213, 216, 218
idealized, Shara as 169
ijtihd 79, 1756, 195206
imperialism 216, 669, 168
interpretation 712, 17, 1757, 195
206, 220, 31617
jizya 101, 1045
jurists 712, 17, 204, 146, 1689,
1727, 220
justice 172
365
366
Index
sources (cont.)
muan 157
public good, notions of 143
qadhf 1534, 155
Shara as Rule of Law 911, 171,
1747, 212, 214, 317
superiority/primacy of
Islam 12730
sovereign exception 489
sovereignty 170, 207
Soyster, Harry Edward 319
Spencer, Robert 5
Stone, Harlan F 2634
stoning14664, 256, 272, 3034,
3079
subordination/submission see also
accommodation; humiliation
adulterers, stoning to death of 157
contract of protection 90, 93
dress, restrictions on 1312, 1346
jizya 37, 74, 99101
persecution, myth of 389
qadhf 1534
Saudi Arabia, wrongful death
damages in 2367, 240
transport, modes of 131, 133, 1356
universalism 26
witnesses 140
Sunna 63, 726, 197
Switzerland, minarets in 96, 270
syllogism 176
al-abar, Muammad ibn Jarr 63, 71
Tanzimat20910
tax see jizya; land tax
tazr see discretionary authority of
rulers
terrorism 40, 62, 967, 2723, 2801,
290, 302, 31213
theft, liability for 1068, 11112, 136,
143, 198200
Tibawi, AL 1934
tolerance27
contract of protection 45, 95
culture of intolerance 28
de inition 5
dhimm rules 25, 7, 24, 3346,
1412, 314
dress, restrictions on 135
Europe 2734
iqh 142
governance 56, 245
harmony, myth of 25, 3441, 74, 99,
135, 314, 322
Index
drivers licences, photos on 2805,
288, 2901, 3201
lag salute 2618
foreign law in US courts 28390
gay people, treatment of 31819
Iran 2867, 28990
Jim Crow era 3234
judicial review 1920
Other, the 289, 31718
religious freedom 2617, 2817, 290,
3201
Saudi Arabia 2867, 28990
security 31819
separate-but-equal 1920
September 11, 2001 967, 2801,
290, 302
tolerance 3940, 31719, 3234
universalism 612
washrooms, access to 3234
Universal Declaration of Human
Rights2367
universalism
accommodation 6, 236, 905,
10636, 25861, 268, 282, 292,
31112
adulterers, stoning to death of 149,
157
charitable endowments 115, 119,
143
Christianity 601
contract of protection 6970
conversion to Islam 646
core values 131, 142
dhimm rules 27, 609, 96, 220
dress, restrictions on 136
ethics 267
governance 609, 88, 1445, 168,
1845, 2201, 315
historical context 6070
home construction
regulation 1267, 1301
imperialism 26, 6070, 96, 141,
2201, 315, 325
jihd ethic 64
jizya 659, 98, 1001, 1035
367