Sein Langiage

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 13

SEIN LANGUAGE

Being is said in many ways.


—Aristotle,
Met. 1003a33

1. To Be
Being is one of the most important philosophical notions, and the
behaviour of the verb to be has induced philosophical perplexities ever
since (at least) Plato’s Sophist. What follows is a contemporary examina-
tion of the matter. Discussions of the notion have always involved a
curious blend of logic, linguistics, and metaphysics. My discussion will be
no different.
I restrict my linguistic claims to contemporary English. To what
extent similar points apply to other languages, I leave to people with
better linguistic knowledge to determine. Ironically, though, it is the work
of three native German speakers that we will find most useful in the inves-
tigations: Frege, Heidegger, and Meinong.
For background to the whole enterprise, let me start with the follow-
ing distinctions. Names are a phrases which may refer to an object—or
objects; I will allow for plural reference.1 These include proper names
(Mary, John and Mary) and definite descriptions (the highest mountain,
the highest mountains). Predicate complements are phrases which
follow the copula to produce a verb phrase. These include adjectival
phrases (red), common nouns (a man), and participles, present (running)
and past (loved). Quantifier phrases are noun-phrases starting with a
quantifier (some person, no people, all persons). This trichotomy is essen-
tially, Frege’s. In his terms, the three categories are: names, (first-order)
concept expressions, and second-order concept expressions.
Against this background we may look at the verb to be. In the next
two sections of the essay, I will discuss the finite parts of the verb. Fol-
lowing that, we will turn to the nonfinite parts.
“Sein Language” by Graham Priest,
The Monist, vol. 97, no. 4, pp. 430–442. Copyright © 2014, THE MONIST, Peru, Illinois 61354.
SEIN LANGUAGE 431

2. The Finite Parts of the Verb


The finite present indicative parts of the verb are: am/is/are. The
finite past indicative parts are: was/were. The verb has finite subjunctive
parts: be (present) and were (past). It also has a finite imperative part: be
(2nd person present only). As far as I can see, the differences of tense and
mood, though crucial for many matters, are of little importance for the
present discussion. Hence I will restrict what I have to say explicitly to the
present indicative parts. Similar comments apply to other tenses and
moods.
Following standard logician’s practice—and therefore, of course,
Frege—we may classify the finite uses of the verb into three kinds that I
will call the predicative, equational, and existential.2 Let us see how
these work.

2.1 The predicative use


Let us start with contexts of the form: name + is/are + X. If X is a
predicative complement, the use of is is predicative. Paradigms are:

• John is happy.
• The man is running.
• The women are singing.

In predicative contexts, is/are expresses the relation of instantiation. In


Meinongian terms, it expresses the Sosein (being so) of an object.3 We can
write this form as: a is/are F (or in the notation of modern logic, simply
Fa).4 The name, a, if it refers at all, refers to an object (or objects); the
predicate complement refers to a property.5 And such a sentence is true if
the object(s) referred to by a instantiate the property referred to by F.
Thus, in the first example, John refers to an object, happy refers to a prop-
erty, and the sentence is true if John instantiates that property.

2.2 The equational use


Still in contexts of the form: name + is/are + X; if X is a name, then
the occurrence of is is equational. Paradigms are:
432 GRAHAM PRIEST

• George Elliot is Mary Ann Evans.


• George is the winner of the race.
• The members of the cabinet are the four oldest people.

In contexts such as this, is expresses the relation of identity. In the syntax


of modern logic, this form is standardly represented by: a=b. And such a
sentence is true if the object(s) referred to by a are identical with the
object(s) referred to by b.6 Thus, in the first example, Mary Ann Evans
refers to an object, George Elliot refers to an object, and is indicates that
the two object are the same.
Meinong has no special name for this kind of being, so I will coin
one: Identitätsein. This is a relation that each thing bears to itself, and to
only itself. Clearly, it is a particular case of Sosein.
The reason for distinguishing the equational use of the verb from the
predicative use is simple. From name1 is/are name2, we can infer name2
is/are name1. The relation is symmetric. From name is/are F we cannot
infer F is/are name. Indeed, this is not even grammatical—except as a
poetic way of re-expressing the original (Happy is John*).7

2.3 The existential use


Yet still in contexts of the form: name + is/are + X: if X is empty, we
have the existential use of is/are. Paradigms of this are:

• Homer is.
• The Hanging Gardens of Babylon are (no longer).

These are perfectly grammatical, but sound rather stretched and precious
in English.8 More colloquial is to use the verb exist, thus: Homer exists;
the Hanging Gardens of Babylon exist (no longer). The locution with is
is, in fact, perfectly commonplace in some languages, such as Ancient
Greek, which have no separate word for existence.
In Meinong’s terms, this is the is of Sein. (Meinong further divides
this into two kinds: existence [existieren] and subsistence [bestehen]. The
first applies to concrete objects; the second applies to abstract ones.) A
sentence of the form: name + is/are is true iff the object(s) named exist(s).
SEIN LANGUAGE 433

The existential use of is is clearly different from the other two uses, since
both of these are grammatical relations, while this is a monadic property.
We will write this, henceforth, as E.

2.4 Quantifier phrases


Matters are much the same in contexts of the form quantifier phrase
+is/are + X.9 If X is a predicative complement, the use of is is predicative:

• No men are running.


• Every woman is happy.
• Some dogs are allowed in.

The sentence is true iff no/every/some of the objects in question instanti-


ate(s) the property specified by the predicative complement.
If the X is a name, the use of is is equational:

• No man is Fido (He’s a dog).


• Every man (in the room) is John.
• Some man is the winner of the race.

The sentence is true iff no/every/some of the objects in question is/are


identical with the object(s) referred to by the name.
If X is empty, the use of is is existential:

• No unicorn is (or ever was).


• Every one who was there is (no longer).
• Some of those mentioned are (no longer).

The sentence is true iff no/every/some of the objects in question exist.


Let us use S for the particular quantifier (some), then some F is/are
G may be written as Sx(Fx∧Gx).10 The other two quantifiers mentioned
may be defined from this in the familiar fashion. Sentences of this form
bear further scrutiny. F can be the generic thing/object, Ox: some thing
434 GRAHAM PRIEST

(something) is G, some object is G. Expressions of the form something is


G are then of the form Sx(Ox∧Gx), or simply SxGx, since to be an object
is a property that all things have. In something is G, then, the is is the is
of predication.
In Sx(Fx∧Gx), the F can also be the existence predicate: Sx(Ex∧Gx).
This says that some existent thing is G, or simply there exists a G. If ∃ is
the existential quantifier, we may write this as ∃xGx. This is not equiva-
lent to some things are G. Witness: some things do not exist (e.g., Father
Christmas) versus there exist things that do not exist. Obviously, there
exist some Gs entails some things are G, but not vice versa. However, if
G is the kind of thing that is in space and time, then some things are G
implies there exists some Gs. Thus, some chairs are in the room implies
there exist chairs in the room. This is not because of the force of the is,
but because of the kind of thing that chairs are: if something is a chair, it
exists. More of there exists in a moment.

3. There
It is appropriate here to consider the use of is in the locution there is,
as in there is a church in the town. It should be noted, first, that this is
idiomatic in a certain sense: in other languages, different verbs are used
for the sentences with the same meaning. French: Il y a une église dans la
ville (avoir, to have); German: Es gibt eine Kirche in der Stadt (geben, to
give).
Next, though linguists disagree over the parsing of such sentences,11
one thing about which there is no disagreement is that there is is not a
quantifier. What to make of such locutions?

3.1 There is, I


Let us start with locutions of the form there is + X, where X is a
simple quantifier phrase, as in:

• There are no dinosaurs.


• There are some beautiful works of art.
• There is a man on the bus.
• There is everything described.
SEIN LANGUAGE 435

Perhaps the most natural understanding of the there in this context is


as a dummy subject, standing in for the quantifier phrase. This makes our
examples equivalent to:

• No dinosaurs are.
• Some beautiful works of art are.
• A man on the bus is.
• Everything described is.

(In the same way, it can be a dummy subject standing in for a noun phrase.
It is too difficult for me to get there means: for me to get there is too difficult.)
The is, in this case, is clearly the is of existence (since it is not com-
plemented), and can be replaced by the verb exists:

• There exist no dinosaurs [No dinosaurs exist].


• There exist some beautiful works of art [Some beautiful works of
art exist].
• There exists a man on the bus [A man on the bus exists].
• There exists everything described [Everything described exists].

So, in contexts such as these, the is is the is of existence.


I note that indefinite descriptions like a man on the bus can be (at
least) two different things. They can be common nouns, John is a man on
the bus; they can also be quantifier phrases, a man on the bus spoke to me
(i.e., some man on the bus spoke to me). On the current understanding, in
there is a man on the bus, the phrase is a quantifier phrase (the singular
form of there are some men on the bus). Given this, the inference: a is an
F, so there is (exists) an F is invalid (a might not exist); but the inference
a is an F, so something is an F is valid.

3.2 There is, II


Matters are somewhat different if the X in there is + X is a quantifier
phrase plus a predicative complement, as in:
436 GRAHAM PRIEST

• There are no women on the committee.


• There are some children running.
• There is a man in the church.
• There is every person one could wish for here.

Again, the most natural understanding of such a sentence has the there
standing in as a dummy subject of the quantifier phrase, giving:

• No women are on the committee.


• Some children are running.
• A man is in the church.
• Every person one could wish for is here.

So, e.g., there is a man in the church means Sx(Mx∧Cx). The sentence is
true if something satisfies Mx∧Cx, and the is here is the is of predication,
as I have already observed. Similarly, there is some thing (something) C
means some thing is C: Sx(Ox∧Cx)—or just SxCx: something satisfies C.
The something here, note, does not have to be an existent thing. Witness:
There are three non-existent objects mentioned on the page, as well as one
existent object (Anna Karenina, Sherlock Holmes, Zeus; Winston Churchill).
I note, however, that sentences of this form can sustain a reading
where the there stands for everything that follows the is. Thus, our four
examples could mean:

• No women on the committee are [exist].


• Some children running are [exist].
• A man in the church is [exists].
• Every person one could wish for here [exists].

This reading is much less natural in most contexts. However, strictly


speaking, sentences where what follows the is is a quantifier phrase plus
a predicate complement are ambiguous.
SEIN LANGUAGE 437

3.3 An idiom
There is one complicating factor to note. In some idiolects there
exists can be used just to mean some. Thus, in mathematical texts, in par-
ticular, one frequently finds locutions of the form there exists a prime
number greater than 10 (or prime numbers greater than 100 exist).
However, these mean neither more nor less than that something has a
certain property, such as prime number greater than 100. That the use of
the word exists in this context is an idiom is shown by the fact that there
are clearly contexts which resist this locution. Thus, again, some things do
not exist—e.g., Father Christmas—makes perfectly good sense; there
exist things which do not exist does not.
The idiomatic use of exists in mathematics is mirrored by an equally
idiomatic use of modal vocabulary. For example, mathematicians fre-
quently say that one mathematical structure can be embedded in another;
or that, given a certain lemma, one may prove such and such a theorem.
These locutions have nothing to do with possibility and necessity (much
less permission and obligation). They are simply ways of expressing the
fact that something satisfies a certain condition—a function (in the case of
the embedding) or a deduction (in the case of the proof). So it is with talk
of existence here.
The point that the use of the word exists in a mathematical context is
just an idiomatic way of saying that a concept is instantiated was made by
no less a person than Frege himself. Thus we have:12
I have called existence a property of a concept. How I mean this to be taken
is best made clear by an example. In the sentence ‘there is at least one square
root of 4,’ we have an assertion not about (say) the definite number 2, nor
about -2, but about a concept square root of 4; viz. that it is not empty.

But also:13
Existential sentences, beginning ‘there is’ (‘es gibt’), are closely related to
particular ones: compare the sentence ‘there are numbers which are prime’
with ‘some numbers are prime’. This existence is still too often confused
with reality and objectivity.

It might be suggested that by ‘reality’ here, Frege means physical reality,


rather than some platonic reality. However, this thought does not survive
long. The platonic reality of abstract objects—if Frege really does sub-
438 GRAHAM PRIEST

scribe to this—is objective if anything is. So this cannot be the contrast he


is drawing.

4. Nonfinite Parts of the Verb


Let us now turn to the nonfinite parts of the verb to be. These are
principally the infinitive and the participles.

4.1 Verb complements


Let us start with the infinitive: (to) be. The most common occurrence
of an infinitive in English is as a complement to a finite verb, especially
an auxiliary verb, e.g., will be, ought (to) be, may be. In each of these
cases, be can be used in the predicative, equational, and existential senses.
For example, we have, respectively:

• John will be happy.


• John will be the first person to pass the post.
• After I die, I will not be (any longer).

Similarly for the other verbs which the infinitive can complement. The
participles, being and been can also be used as verb complements. The
first of these complements be, used in its predicative sense; the second
complements have. Thus we have:

• Mary is being (has been) difficult.


• Mary is being (has been) the most difficult person.
• If I am thinking (have thought) then I am being (have been).

which display our three uses of the verb.

4.2 As a noun phrase


Perhaps the philosophically most significant use of the infinitive—
with or without an added complement—is as a noun phrase. Thus in:

• To be kind is a noble aim.


SEIN LANGUAGE 439

• To be the first man across the line is his aim.


• To be is to do.

The three infinitive clauses illustrate the predicative, equational, and exis-
tential uses of the infinitive verb.
Again, the infinitive can usually be replaced by a present participle,
used in a nominative sense—a gerund. Thus, we have equivalently:

• Being kind is a noble aim.


• Being the first man across the line is his aim.
• Being is doing.

In uses such as this, the infinitive or participle refers to a property—or,


possibly, a state of affairs or an event involving that property.

4.3 The ambiguity of being


But what property? To be is, as we have seen, ambiguous. It can
mean the property of existence, Sein. But it can also mean Sosein and
Identitätsein. There is another kind of “sein” to note here. Not every sen-
tence of the form name is/exists is true. The tallest mountain exists is true;
Father Christmas exists is not. In Meinongian terms, the tallest mountain
has Sein; Father Christmas has Nichtsein. An object, as such, may there-
fore have either Sein or Nichtsein. It itself is “beyond” the pair of
predicates. Again, in Meinongian terms, any object has Außersein. That is,
it is simply an object.
Now, Außersein, Sosein, and Identitätsein are equivalent. If some-
thing has Außersein (is an object), it has properties (Sosein)—if only the
property of being an object; and if it has properties, it is obviously an
object. Similarly, if something is an object (Außersein) it is self-identical
(Identitätsein) and vice versa. We may therefore take these three to be
essentially one notion, distinct from Sein.
To be or being, then, is ambiguous. It may mean either Außersein or
Sein. The first corresponds to the grammatically transitive use of is; the
second to the intransitive. I will refer to the first of these (Außersein) as
beingH, and the second (Sein) as beingM. Clearly, anything with beingM
has beingH, but not vice versa.
440 GRAHAM PRIEST

The subscript ‘M’ here stands for Meinong, since this is how he uses
the word, as I have noted. When Meinong speaks about being (Sein), he
means something (existieren/bestehen) which an object may have or lack.
The ‘H’ stands for Heidegger. For when Heidegger speaks of being he
speaks of what all objects have, whether or not they exist. Thus he says:14
Everything we talk about, mean, and are related to is in being in one way or
another. What and how we ourselves are is also a being. Being is found in
thatness and whatness, reality, the objective presence of things [Vorhanden-
heit], subsistence, validity, existence [Da-sein], and in the “there is” [es gibt].

And to make it clear that this is Sosein, that is, Außersein:15


Being is used in all knowledge and all predicating, in every relation to beings
and in every relation to oneself, and the expression is understandable without
“further ado.” Everyone understands “The sky is blue,” “I am happy,” and
similar statements.

4.4 Being and beings


The gerund being can function not only as a (proper) noun, but also
as a common noun. So one has: this is a being, these are beings. Beings
are the things that have the property of being (whichever of the two mean-
ings is at issue). As Heidegger is wont to say, everything has being (Sein),
and so is a being (Seiend). This use, note, is not normally available with
other gerunds. Thus, it makes no sense to say, e.g.: this is a running* One
has to say: this is a running thing. By contrast, this is a being thing*
makes no sense at all.
Finally, there is a bit of philosophical jargon concerning being worth
noting. As well as the property being, some writers, arguably following
Aristotle, have taken there to be property instances, tropes. Thus, for the
universal humanity, we have: the humanity of Socrates, the humanity of
Xantippe, etc. In logicians’ terms, humanity of, is a function symbol (cf.,
father of), rather than a predicate. Applying this to the universal being, we
then have: the being of Socrates, the being of Xantippe, etc.—and more
generally, the being of beings. Or as Heidegger puts it: das Sein des
Seinden.

5. This Be the End


This completes our overview of the behaviour of this most philo-
sophically important and troubling of verbs. Said Quine: to be is to be the
SEIN LANGUAGE 441

value of a bound variable.16 Things are slightly more complicated than


that.17

Graham Priest
City University of New York
University of Melbourne

NOTES

1. In nearly all cases, reference is context dependent; but this will play no role in what
follows.
2. See Priest (2008, xxi). Linguists themselves disagree about exactly how many dis-
tinct uses of the first two kinds there are (somewhere between one and four). See
Mikkelson (2011).
3. For Meinongian terminology, see Marek (2008).
4. If the terms are plural, it would be more normal to write this as Faa (see Linnebo
2008), but I simplify here and in what follows.
5. At least, an abundant one; there is no heavy-duty metaphysics going on yet. (For
the distinction between sparse and abundant properties, see Swoyer and Orilia [2011].)
6. In the plural case, each of the as is a b, and vice versa.
7. Actually, one may reduce the is of identity to the is of predication by supposing that
when it is used in this sense, it is actually elliptical for is identical to. So George Elliot is
Mary Anne Evans means George Eliot is identical to Mary Anne Evans. The symmetry of
the relation is then a fact about this particular predicate: cf., Mary is the same height as
George.
8. When my first child was born, I recall sending my parents a telegram saying
“Marcus Timon Priest is.”
9. It makes no sense for the left flank of the is to be a predicative phrase, for reasons
we have just noted. The only other permutations that make sense are: quantifier phrase +
is/are + name (every man is John); quantifier phrase + is/are + quantifier phrase (every
member is some man); quantifier phrase + is (uncomplemented) (every man in the room
is). In the first two cases the is must be the equational is. (For all men, x, x = John; for every
member, x, some man, y, is such that x=y.) In the third, it is obviously existential.
10. See Priest (2005).
11. See McNally (2013).
12. Geach and Black (1970, 48–9).
13. McGuiness (1984, 239).
14. Stambaugh (1996, 5).
15. Stambaugh (1996, 53).
16. Quine (1948).
17. Drafts of this paper were given in 2013 at the University of Göttingen, and at the
workshop Fiction/alism, at the University of Hamburg. Thanks go to the participants in the
ensuing discussions. Thanks, too, go to Friederike Moultmann for helpful discussions on
these matters.
442 GRAHAM PRIEST

REFERENCES

Geach, P., and Black, M., eds. and trans. 1970. Translations from the Philosophical Writ-
ings of Gottlob Frege, Oxford: Basil Blackwell.
Linnebo, Ø. 2008. “Plural Quantification,” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy,
http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/plural-quant/.
McGuinness, B., ed. 1984. “On Mr. Peano’s Conceptual Notation and My Own,” Col-
lected Papers on Mathematics, Logic, and Philosophy, Oxford: Basil Blackwell,
234–48.
McNally, L. 2011. “Existential Sentences,” in von Heusinger, K., Maienborn, C. and
Portner, P., eds., Semantics: An International Handbook of Natural Language
Meaning, v. 2, Berlin: de Gruyter, 1829–48.
Marek, J. 2008. “Alexius Meinong,” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy,
http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/meinong/.
Mikkelsen, L. 2011. “Copular Clauses,” in von Heusinger, K., Maienborn, C., and Portner,
P., eds., Semantics: An International Handbook of Natural Language Meaning, vol.
2, Berlin: de Gruyter, 1805–29.
Priest, G. 2005. Towards Non-Being, Oxford: Oxford University Press.
———. 2008. Introduction to Non-Classical Logic: From If to Is, Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Quine, W.V.O. 1948. “On What There is,” Review of Metaphysics 48: 21–38. Reprinted in
From a Logical Point of View, Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press, 1953.
Stambaugh, J., trans. 1996. Being and Time, Albany, NY: State University of New York
Press.
Swoyer, C., and Orilia, F. 2011. “Properties,” Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy,
http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/properties/.

You might also like