Aristotle - Categories
Aristotle - Categories
Aristotle - Categories
By Aristotle
Translated by E. M. Edghill
Section 1
Part 1
On the other hand, things are said to be named 'univocally' which have both
the name and the definition answering to the name in common. A man and an
ox are both 'animal', and these are univocally so named, inasmuch as not only
the name, but also the definition, is the same in both cases: for if a man
should state in what sense each is an animal, the statement in the one case
would be identical with that in the other.
Things are said to be named 'derivatively', which derive their name from some
other name, but differ from it in termination. Thus the grammarian derives his
name from the word 'grammar', and the courageous man from the word
'courage'.
Part 2
Some things, again, are present in a subject, but are never predicable of a
subject. For instance, a certain point of grammatical knowledge is present in
the mind, but is not predicable of any subject; or again, a certain whiteness
may be present in the body (for colour requires a material basis), yet it is
never predicable of anything.
Other things, again, are both predicable of a subject and present in a subject.
Thus while knowledge is present in the human mind, it is predicable of
grammar.
There is, lastly, a class of things which are neither present in a subject nor
predicable of a subject, such as the individual man or the individual horse.
But, to speak more generally, that which is individual and has the character of
a unit is never predicable of a subject. Yet in some cases there is nothing to
prevent such being present in a subject. Thus a certain point of grammatical
knowledge is present in a subject.
Part 3
When one thing is predicated of another, all that which is predicable of the
predicate will be predicable also of the subject. Thus, 'man' is predicated of
the individual man; but 'animal' is predicated of 'man'; it will, therefore, be
predicable of the individual man also: for the individual man is both 'man' and
'animal'.
Part 4
Expressions which are in no way composite signify substance, quantity, quality,
relation, place, time, position, state, action, or affection. To sketch my
meaning roughly, examples of substance are 'man' or 'the horse', of quantity,
such terms as 'two cubits long' or 'three cubits long', of quality, such attributes
as 'white', 'grammatical'. 'Double', 'half', 'greater', fall under the category of
relation; 'in a the market place', 'in the Lyceum', under that of place;
'yesterday', 'last year', under that of time. 'Lying', 'sitting', are terms indicating
position, 'shod', 'armed', state; 'to lance', 'to cauterize', action; 'to be lanced',
'to be cauterized', affection.
Part 5
Substance, in the truest and primary and most definite sense of the word, is
that which is neither predicable of a subject nor present in a subject; for
instance, the individual man or horse. But in a secondary sense those things
are called substances within which, as species, the primary substances are
included; also those which, as genera, include the species. For instance, the
individual man is included in the species 'man', and the genus to which the
species belongs is 'animal'; these, therefore-that is to say, the species 'man'
and the genus 'animal,-are termed secondary substances.
It is plain from what has been said that both the name and the definition of
the predicate must be predicable of the subject. For instance, 'man' is
predicted of the individual man. Now in this case the name of the species man'
is applied to the individual, for we use the term 'man' in describing the
individual; and the definition of 'man' will also be predicated of the individual
man, for the individual man is both man and animal. Thus, both the name and
the definition of the species are predicable of the individual.
With regard, on the other hand, to those things which are present in a subject,
it is generally the case that neither their name nor their definition is
predicable of that in which they are present. Though, however, the definition
is never predicable, there is nothing in certain cases to prevent the name
being used. For instance, 'white' being present in a body is predicated of that
in which it is present, for a body is called white: the definition, however, of
the colour white' is never predicable of the body.
Everything except primary substances is either predicable of a primary
substance or present in a primary substance. This becomes evident by
reference to particular instances which occur. 'Animal' is predicated of the
species 'man', therefore of the individual man, for if there were no individual
man of whom it could be predicated, it could not be predicated of the species
'man' at all. Again, colour is present in body, therefore in individual bodies, for
if there were no individual body in which it was present, it could not be
present in body at all. Thus everything except primary substances is either
predicated of primary substances, or is present in them, and if these last did
not exist, it would be impossible for anything else to exist.
It is, then, with good reason that of all that remains, when we exclude primary
substances, we concede to species and genera alone the name 'secondary
substance', for these alone of all the predicates convey a knowledge of
primary substance. For it is by stating the species or the genus that we
appropriately define any individual man; and we shall make our definition
more exact by stating the former than by stating the latter. All other things
that we state, such as that he is white, that he runs, and so on, are irrelevant
to the definition. Thus it is just that these alone, apart from primary
substances, should be called substances.
Yet this is not peculiar to substance, for it is also the case that differentiae
cannot be present in subjects. The characteristics 'terrestrial' and 'two-footed'
are predicated of the species 'man', but not present in it. For they are not in
man. Moreover, the definition of the differentia may be predicated of that of
which the differentia itself is predicated. For instance, if the characteristic
'terrestrial' is predicated of the species 'man', the definition also of that
characteristic may be used to form the predicate of the species 'man': for 'man'
is terrestrial.
Yet species and genus do not merely indicate quality, like the term 'white';
'white' indicates quality and nothing further, but species and genus determine
the quality with reference to a substance: they signify substance qualitatively
differentiated. The determinate qualification covers a larger field in the case
of the genus that in that of the species: he who uses the word 'animal' is
herein using a word of wider extension than he who uses the word 'man'.
If, then, a man should make this exception and contend that statements and
opinions are capable of admitting contrary qualities, his contention is
unsound. For statements and opinions are said to have this capacity, not
because they themselves undergo modification, but because this
modification occurs in the case of something else. The truth or falsity of a
statement depends on facts, and not on any power on the part of the
statement itself of admitting contrary qualities. In short, there is nothing
which can alter the nature of statements and opinions. As, then, no change
takes placein themselves, these cannot be said to be capable of admitting
contrary qualities.
Part 6
Space and time also belong to this class of quantities. Time, past, present, and
future, forms a continuous whole. Space, likewise, is a continuous quantity;
for the parts of a solid occupy a certain space, and these have a common
boundary; it follows that the parts of space also, which are occupied by the
parts of the solid, have the same common boundary as the parts of the solid.
Thus, not only time, but space also, is a continuous quantity, for its parts have
a common boundary.
Strictly speaking, only the things which I have mentioned belong to the
category of quantity: everything else that is called quantitative is a quantity in
a secondary sense. It is because we have in mind some one of these quantities,
properly so called, that we apply quantitative terms to other things. We speak
of what is white as large, because the surface over which the white extends is
large; we speak of an action or a process as lengthy, because the time covered
is long; these things cannot in their own right claim the quantitative epithet.
For instance, should any one explain how long an action was, his statement
would be made in terms of the time taken, to the effect that it lasted a year,
or something of that sort. In the same way, he would explain the size of a
white object in terms of surface, for he would state the area which it covered.
Thus the things already mentioned, and these alone, are in their intrinsic
nature quantities; nothing else can claim the name in its own right, but, if
at all, only in a secondary sense.
That which is not a quantity can by no means, it would seem, be termed equal
or unequal to anything else. One particular disposition or one particular
quality, such as whiteness, is by no means compared with another in terms of
equality and inequality but rather in terms of similarity. Thus it is the
distinctive mark of quantity that it can be called equal and unequal.