Research Paper On Philosophical Thought Experiments: Rafael Kieran M. Monday AB Philosophy II
Research Paper On Philosophical Thought Experiments: Rafael Kieran M. Monday AB Philosophy II
Research Paper On Philosophical Thought Experiments: Rafael Kieran M. Monday AB Philosophy II
On
Philosophical
Thought
experiments
Discussion
1. Zeno’s Arrow
In the arrow paradox (also known as the fletcher's paradox), Zeno
states that for motion to occur, an object must change the position which
it occupies. He gives an example of an arrow in flight. He states that in
any one (durationless) instant of time, the arrow is neither moving to
where it is, nor to where it is not. It cannot move to where it is not,
because no time elapses for it to move there; it cannot move to where it
is, because it is already there. In other words, at every instant of time
there is no motion occurring. If everything is motionless at every instant,
and time is entirely composed of instants, then motion is impossible.
Whereas the first two paradoxes divide space, this paradox starts by
dividing time and not into segments, but into points.
Searle argues that a good way to test a theory of mind, say a theory that
holds that understanding can be created by doing such and such, is to
imagine what it would be like to do what the theory says would create
understanding. Searle (1999) summarized the Chinese Room argument
concisely:
Imagine a native English speaker who knows no Chinese locked in a
room full of boxes of Chinese symbols (a data base) together with a
book of instructions for manipulating the symbols (the program).
Imagine that people outside the room send in other Chinese symbols
which, unknown to the person in the room, are questions in Chinese (the
input). And imagine that by following the instructions in the program the
man in the room is able to pass out Chinese symbols which are correct
answers to the questions (the output). The program enables the person in
the room to pass the Turing Test for understanding Chinese but he does
not understand a word of Chinese.
Searle goes on to say, “The point of the argument is this: if the man in
the room does not understand Chinese on the basis of implementing the
appropriate program for understanding Chinese then neither does any
other digital computer solely on that basis because no computer, qua
computer, has anything the man does not have.”
3. Galileo’s Balls
According to a biography by Galileo's pupil Vincenzo Viviani, in
1589 the Italian scientist Galileo had dropped two balls of different
masses from the Leaning Tower of Pisa to demonstrate that their time of
descent was independent of their mass.Via this method, he supposedly
discovered that the objects fell at the same acceleration, proving his
prediction true, while at the same time proving Aristotle's theory of
gravity (which states that objects fall at speed relative to their mass)
false. At the time when Viviani asserts that the experiment took place,
Galileo had not yet formulated the final version of his law of free fall.
He had, however, formulated an earlier version which predicted that
bodies of the same material falling through the same medium would fall
at the same speed.This was contrary to what Aristotle had taught: that
heavy objects fall faster than lighter ones, in direct proportion to weight.
While this story has been retold in popular accounts, there is no account
by Galileo himself of such an experiment, and it is accepted by most
historians that it was a thought experiment which did not actually take
place. An exception is Drake, who argues that the experiment did take
place, more or less as Viviani described it.
4. Twin Earth
Putnam’s Experiment:
We begin by supposing that elsewhere in the universe there is a planet
exactly like Earth in virtually all respects, which we refer to as ‘Twin
Earth’. (We should also suppose that the relevant surroundings [are
exactly the same as for] Earth; it revolves around a star that appears to
be exactly like our sun, and so on.) On Twin Earth, there is a Twin
equivalent of every person and thing here on Earth. The one difference
between the two planets is that there is no water on Twin Earth. In its
place there is a liquid that is superficially identical, but is chemically
different, being composed not of H2O, but rather of some more
complicated formula which we abbreviate as ‘XYZ’. The Twin
Earthlings who refer to their language as ‘English’ call XYZ ‘water’.
Finally, we set the date of our thought experiment to be several centuries
ago, when the residents of Earth and Twin Earth would have no means
of knowing that the liquids they called ‘water’ were H 2O and XYZ
respectively. The experience of people on Earth with water, and that of
those on Twin Earth with XYZ would be identical.
Now the question arises: when an Earthling (or Oscar for simplicity
sake) and his twin on Twin Earth say 'water' do they mean the same
thing? (The twin is also called 'Oscar' on his own planet, of course.
Indeed, the inhabitants of that planet call their own planet 'Earth'. For
convenience, we refer to this putative planet as 'Twin Earth', and extend
this naming convention to the objects and people that inhabit it, in this
case referring to Oscar's twin as Twin-Oscar, and Twin-Earth water as
water.) Ex hypothesi, their brains are molecule-for-molecule identical.
Yet, at least according to Putnam, when Oscar says 'water', the term
refers to H2O, whereas when Twin Oscar says 'water' it refers to XYZ.
The result of this is that the contents of a person's brain are not sufficient
to determine the reference of terms they use, as one must also examine
the causal history that led to this individual acquiring the term. (Oscar,
for instance, learned the word 'water' in a world filled with H 2O, whereas
Twin Oscar learned 'water' in a world filled with XYZ.)
This is the essential thesis of semantic externalism. Putnam famously
summarized this conclusion with the statement that "'meanings' just ain't
in the head."
7. Experience Machine
Nozick asks us to imagine a machine that could give us
whatever desirable or pleasurable experiences we could want.
Psychologists have figured out a way to stimulate a person's brain
to induce pleasurable experiences that the subject could not
distinguish from those he would have apart from the machine. He
then asks, if given the choice, would we prefer the machine to real
life?
Nozick also believes that if pleasure were the only intrinsic value,
people would have an overriding reason to be hooked up to an
"experience machine," which would produce favorable sensations.
9. Inverted Spectrum
The reason that the least well off member gets benefited is
that it is assumed that under the veil of ignorance, under original
position, people will be risk averse. This implies that everyone
is afraid of being part of the poor members of society, so the
social contract is constructed to help the least well off members.
The problem can be stated in brief, "if a man born blind can
feel the differences between shapes such as spheres and cubes,
could he similarly distinguish those objects by sight if given the
ability to see?"
14. N-universes
These properties are however not directly perceived through the senses
or imagination (the wax can be extended and moved in more ways than
can be imagined). Instead to grasp the essence of the wax, it must be
done through pure reason:
We must then grant that I could not even understand through the
imagination what this piece of wax is, and that it is my mind alone
which perceives it.
—René Descartes, 1911 edition of The Philosophical Works of
Descartes (Cambridge University Press), translated by Elizabeth S.
Haldane
16. Allegory of the Cave
The four models are arranged into a first pair for the visible
world, and a second pair for the purely intelligible world. The
models are described in succession as corresponding to increasing
levels of reality from common illusion, to belief, to reasoning, and
then to philosophical understanding.
The Analogy of the Divided Line immediately follows the
Metaphor of the Sun and is in turn followed by the Allegory of the
Cave.
Plato holds a very strict notion of knowledge. For example,
he does not accept expertise about a subject, nor direct perception
(the Theaetetus), nor true belief about the physical world (the
Meno) as knowledge. For knowledge, he also requires
philosophical understanding of the relevant Ideas (Forms), as a
basis for proper justification at all other levels of the Divided Line.
Thus, for this reason, in most of the 'earlier, Socratic' dialogues,
Socrates denies knowledge both to himself and others.
For the first level, "the world of becoming and passing
away," Plato expressly denies the possibility of knowledge.
Constant change never stays the same, therefore, properties of
objects must refer to different Ideas at different times. Note that for
knowledge to be possible, which Plato believed, the other three
levels must be unchanging. The third and fourth level, mathematics
and Ideas are already eternal and unchanging. However, to ensure
that the second level objective, physical world is also unchanging,
Plato, in the Republic, Book 4 introduces empirically derived
axiomatic restrictions that prohibit both motion and shifting
perspectives.
20. Swampman
The experiment runs as follows:
Suppose Davidson goes hiking in the swamp and is struck and killed by
a lightning bolt. At the same time, nearby in the swamp another
lightning bolt spontaneously rearranges a bunch of molecules such that,
entirely by coincidence, they take on exactly the same form that
Davidson's body had at the moment of his untimely death. This being,
whom Davidson terms "Swampman," has, of course, a brain which is
structurally identical to that which Davidson had, and will thus,
presumably, behave exactly as Davidson would have. He will walk out
of the swamp, return to Davidson's office at Berkeley, and write the
same essays he would have written; he will interact like an amicable
person with all of Davidson's friends and family, and so forth.
Davidson holds that there would nevertheless be a difference, though no
one would notice it. Swampman will appear to recognize Davidson's
friends, but it is impossible for him to actually recognize them, as he has
never seen them before. As Davidson puts it, "It can't recognize
anything, because it never cognized anything in the first place."
Amongst those who accept the force of this argument, there are two
distinct ways of viewing its consequences. On the one hand, many
philosophers have taken it to affect merely how we should evaluate
Swampman. The argument is believed to demonstrate that Swampman's
utterances and thoughts do not mean anything, and do not refer to
anything in particular. On this view, Swampman's subjectivity and
consciousness are considered to be unchanged. Others have argued that
this lack of a causal history renders incoherent the notion that
Swampman could have a mind at all, which in turn raises the question of
whether he is, in fact, a person. (Note that Davidson calls Swampman
"it" rather than "he.")