Psychoanalytic Film Theory and The Problem of The Missing Spectator, Stephen Prince
Psychoanalytic Film Theory and The Problem of The Missing Spectator, Stephen Prince
Psychoanalytic Film Theory and The Problem of The Missing Spectator, Stephen Prince
Psychoanalytic Film
Theory and the Problem of
the Missing Spectator
Stephen Prince
71
72 Part Two: Film Theory and Aesthetics
studies is that theories of spectatorship fly well beyond the data and in ways
that pay little or no attention to the evidence we do have about how people
watch and interpret films and television.
Contemporary theories of spectatorship are distinguished by a preference
for employing psychoanalysis as the primary modality for explaining film
viewing. Indeed, a recent review of theories of spectatorship warns that the
failure by cognitivists to take psychoanalysis seriously can only result in limited
and imperfect accounts. Accepting psychoanalysis as a given, the author as-
serts, somewhat dogmatically, that the spectator's activity "needs to be read
in relation to unconscious processes." 1 Contemporary theories of spectator-
ship are also characterized by a reluctance to engage empirical modes of in-
vestigation. I will be suggesting in this chapter, however, that questions about
how people process, interpret, and respond to cinematic images and narratives
are empirical questions, or, at the least, incorporate an empirical dimension,
which can be investigated by observing the behavior of real viewers. Theory
building can, and should, come from this. Research on real viewers will need
to be placed within a theoretical framework, but any theory of spectatorship
which fails to deal at some level with the empirical evidence on spectatorship
should be suspected of being insufficiently grounded. One result offilm stud-
ies' disdain for empirical methods has been the construction of theories that
deal with "subjects" but not real viewers, with ideal spectators who exist in
the theories but who have no flesh-and-blood counterparts. As Judith Mayne
explains:
One can understand the historical necessity for bracketing "real people" when
the only available way to talk about such viewers was in the language of socio-
logical or mass communications research-a language, that is, totally drenched
in the assumptions of a white, male, heterosexual norm and a belief in con-
scious, rational responses presumably untainted by contradiction or unconscious
desires. 2
psychoanalytic accounts, let us look at this difficulty in the Freud essay and
how it has failed to slow the launching of theoretical claims in film studies.
Typically, in the sciences, measures of quantitative data are evaluated in terms
of the issues of validity and reliability. Is the researcher really measuring the
phenomenon in question or some other unsuspected phenomenon? Are the
results consistent, assuming all conditions could be replicated? Freudian data,
of course, are qualitative, but one still wishes to know whether the linkages
between clinical data and the high -level theories (in the case of the essay on
beating, theories of sadism and masochism) spun from them are warranted.
Unfortunately, several characteristics of the Freud essay help produce a
weak foundation for theory, especially when trying to analogize Freud's dis-
cussions to the cinema. First is the extremely limited number of patients Freud
used as the basis for his discussion-six patients, of whom four were female
and two male. The bulk of the essay is confined to descriptions of the fantasies
of the four female patients. His findings, therefore, are based on an extremely
small sample, and, beyond the clinical diagnoses of obsessional neurosis or
hysteria, he provides no particulars on the patients. One cannot even tell if the
quotations Freud presents to summarize the content of the fantasies (for ex-
ample, "My father is beating the child") are his own words paraphrasing his
patients' reports or are actually the words of one of the patients. They seem
to be paraphrases because of the peculiar manner in which he presents them
and because they are meant to represent the common elements in the descrip-
tions of all four patients. This succeeds in further mystifying the particulars of
the patients since we do not even have their own words before us.
In light of this, I submit that it is extremely difficult for film theorists to
evaluate the validity of Freud's claims in this essay and, especially, to generalize
from this small sample in ways that permit the construction of grand theories
of cinema spectatorship sui generis. But extremely intelligent film scholars
have not been reluctant to generalize to a much larger population. Thus, in
film theory we can read confident announcements that "there are three basic
factors in common between the beating fantasies of men and women." 9
More troubling even than the extremely small sample upon which Freud
bases his macrotheories of sadomasochism is his own admission, clearly stated
in the essay, that phase two-"I am being beaten by my father"-is fictive, is
made up for the purposes of analysis. Freud writes:
This second phase is the most important and the most momentous of all. But we
may say of it in a certain sense that it has never had a real existence. It is never
remembered, it has never succeeded in becoming conscious. It is a construction
of analysis, but it is no less a necessity on that account. 10
struct theories of cinema spectatorship. Kaja Silverman points out Freud's fab-
rication of phase two and emphasizes the audacity behind it but decides,
nevertheless, that "I can find nothing to dispute in Freud's account of
phase 2 .... " I l
our research and theory more productive, I should point out that the move
toward a more cognitive and empirical orientation can help close a gap in our
understanding of film viewing which psychoanalysis has helped to produce.
Psychoanalytic film theory fails to deal with the complex role that perceptual
processes play in a viewer's understanding of visual media. Perception tends
to get conflated with sexual energy as a "scopic" drive, a sexually based urge
to view things voyeuristically. Metz claimed that "the practice of cinema is
only possible through the perceptual passions: the desire to see (= scopic
drive, scopophilia, voyeurism) .... " 12 For Metz, visual perception was under-
stood as a kind of sweeping searchlight mounted on top of the viewer's neck,
and psychoanalytically inclined theories of perception have not gained much
in sophistication since Metz's uninformed description. 13
Aside from psychoanalytic film theory's failure to model a sophisticated
perceptual process, the claims it does make ill fit the available evidence on how
viewers watch film and television. The problem with the "scopic drive" is that
it models viewing as a driven and reactive process during which the viewer's
passion for looking is cathected by particular formal cues (for example, "fe-
tishizing" close-ups). The scopic drive implies a unifocal fixation within the
viewer maintained by a match of formal features and inner fantasy.
Observations of real spectators furnish a rather different portrait of viewing
behavior. A great deal of research has studied the ways young children watch
television. Preschool children in a room furnished with toys and containing
other adults or children do not stare with steady fixation at the screen. In-
stead, the child will repeatedly glance away from the screen, averaging about
150 looks toward and away from the screen per hour. Furthermore, glances
at the screen are quite brief, and most last no longer than 15 seconds. 14 Ob-
servations of adult television behavior reveal a similar pattern: looks at the
screen are extremely brief and are punctuated by regular glances away from
the screen, with non-looking pauses averaging as high as 22 seconds. The
researchers conclude that "continuous episodes of visual attention as long as
60 seconds are relatively rare." 15
These data, of course, are derived from television viewing behavior. The
psychoanalytic film theorist could object that the conditions of film viewing,
in relation to which the scopic drive is discussed, are crucially different-the
film viewer sits before a huge screen in a theater free of the distractions that
typically accompany television viewing. However, most people now watch
their movies on television via the VCR, and the psychoanalytic theorist would
still need to be able to explain how a sexually driven "perceptual passion"
yields patterns of viewing behavior in which visual attention is intermittent,
subject to continual breaks and interruptions, and is discontinuous. While the
scopic drive might not rule out intermittent attention, scopic theory needs to
deal with this phenomenon, which the drive-based model of vision as fetish
has tended to downplay.
At the very least, theorists of the scopic drive should begin to specify those
78 Part Two: Film Theory and Aesthetics
factors that might produce the onset and cessation of glances at the screen.
Empirical research has already pointed toward a host of such factors, among
which are specific formal features. Not surprisingly, cuts and on-screen move-
ment tend to maintain visual attention, but so do auditory features, which are
especially effective in stimulating glances back to the screen since a viewer can
monitor audio changes while looking away from the screen, as signs that im-
portant changes are occurring in the show or film that bear attention. 16 Theo-
ries of the scopic drive say little about the role of auditory features as cues
regulating a viewer's levels of visual attention because attentiveness, an active
and conscious process, is not posed as a major variable by the theories.
Furthermore, empirical evidence suggests that visual attention to television
is a function of age and may have a developmental basis in terms of cognitive
growth and increasing sophistication of medium-specific skills,17 rather than
being something driven by a fixed current oflibidinal energy. Empirical evi-
dence, in other words, can deal with differences among spectators better than
can psychoanalysis. Levels of attention and comprehension will vary among
film and television viewers depending on such characteristics as age, degree of
cognitive development, and amount of prior experience with the medium.
The empirical research on factors affecting levels of attention and comprehen-
sion can give us a more nuanced portrait of spectatorship than does psycho-
analysis, and this, in turn, can help us to construct theories that are sensitive
to the differences, as well as the similarities, among viewers.
Rather than continuing to base theories on a concept of the scopically
driven, fixated (or "positioned") viewer, I suggest that we begin to derive our
theories and research from the constructs of "attention" and "attentiveness."
This will enable us to make a key advance in the way we model viewing be-
havior. It will enable us to conceptualize, and study, viewing processes in
terms of levels of information processing and emotional response. IS Concep-
tualizing attention as a multilevel process and researching spectatorship from
that angle, rather than in terms of a unifocal drive, can help bring our theories
more in line with the available empirical evidence on film viewing. 19 This is an
important step that film studies needs to take in order that our theories be
consistent with well-established evidence about media viewing. The con-
structs of "attention" and "attentiveness" can be usefully employed to build
flexible, multilevel models of how viewers of visual media process visual
narratives.
An example can be instructive here. Communication researcher Frank
Biocca has recently proposed a sophisticated model of semantic processing
which bears a close relationship to some of the stipulations of contemporary
film theory, yet it is inclined in a different, cognitively oriented direction. 20
Biocca's model rests upon the synthesis of a great deal of empirical research
from the fields of psychology and communication, as well as input from film
theory, and, by working at a high level of abstraction, it demonstrates how
theory both incorporates and transcends the empirical data from which it
draws.
P R INC E: Psychoanalytic Film Theory 79
Biocca points to the differences between the model viewer that filmmakers
and other communicators have in mind during production and the actual,
"instantiated" viewer who sees the program or film. He stresses, like reader-
response theories, variability of response across viewers, but he comes at these
issues from a cognitive context emphasizing multilevel semantic processing of
the message in terms of seven "schematic frames," so called because they ac-
cess the viewer's schemata or frameworks of interpretation. From the first sec-
onds of programming, Biocca points out, viewers begin to construct models
of the intended message and, during the course of the show or film, they are
continuously revising these models in accordance with the shifting formal and
semantic structures of the message. This interpretive work carried out by the
viewer is complex and ongoing and is informed by data -driven processing of
formal codes as well as by schema-driven inferences about meaning and val-
ues. Biocca suggests that viewers organize incoming information by assigning
it to, and evaluating it within, seven overall frameworks. The spectator judges
information with respect to its discursive topic, its membership in a "possible
world," the actors or agents in a causal sequence, point of view understood in
terms of both mode of address and position of sight, narrative structure, ideo-
logical organization, and the relation of all of these issues to the viewer's own
self-identity.
In the mind of the viewer, schematic frames organize information and inferences
about places and social situations (possible worlds); people, causes, and agents
(actants); topics (discursive frames); as well as inferences about ideologies and
how the programming relates to the viewer (ideological and self-schematic
frames).21
and "positioning" and, instead, place viewers within an altogether more ra-
tional, flexible, and multivalent context.
the people on television and their interactions present interpretive tasks which
are common to all presentations of social life, whatever the medium. They in-
clude such tasks as understanding that another person has his or her own per-
spective, inferring the other's perspective, and judging the morality of another's
actions. 31
form in daily life. Motion picture viewers are expert decoders of the gestural
and facial displays sanctioned in their culture and may even be sensitive to
certain displays across culturesY (In cases where facial and gestural cues
might be unfamiliar, filmmakers can always build redundant information into
the narrative and dramatic context of a scene to clarifY for viewers the appro-
priate responses, thus ensuring the general comprehensibility of their prod-
uct.) This reproduction by the cinema of culturally patterned streams of facial
and gestural expression provides an important incentive to viewers to measure
the content of the cinematic image against their horizon of extra-filmic life
experience.
Psychoanalytic film theory has tended to ignore these dimensions of iconic
and noniconic correspondence or has dealt with them in a negative fashion by
postulating viewers who are duped by "transparency effects" or the "illu-
sions" of realist, perspective-based imagery. It is clear, however, that these
correspondences facilitate the viewer's easy comprehension of cinematic im-
ages and encourage an entirely rational process whereby the viewer maps as-
pects of the cinematic display onto dimensions of his or her real-life visual and
social experience. Psychoanalytic film theory has had little to say about the
complex ways viewers seek correspondences between their experience and
what they see on screen-at least little to say that is truly researchable. Virtu-
ally all of the evidence cited in the foregoing discussion has come from the
disciplines of psychology and communication. Researchers in the disciplines
which have established traditions of empirical study, have looked carefully at
how viewers watch film and television, and they have gone some way toward
understanding that process. Film theorists, by contrast, with little tradition of
work in (and little respect for) empirical procedures, have constructed spec-
tators who exist in theory; they have taken almost no look at real viewers. We
are now in the unenviable position of having constructed theories of specta-
torship from which spectators are missing.
Spectators are absent from our accounts of spectatorship because psycho-
analysis has failed to furnish valid or reliable data that could be used to con-
struct or modifY theory. Our field's dilemma in this area is not that it needs to
engage in better "theorization" but that it needs to revise some of its basic
methodological procedures. As a field that encompasses the domains of his-
tory, theory, and criticism, film studies sprawls over a large area. Not all of the
questions it confronts are empirical ones, nor should they be approached us-
ing empirical methods. But some clearly are, and I submit that spectatorship
is an area for empirical inquiry. Two excellent avenues for approaching ques-
tions of spectatorship empirically would involve application of the concepts of
correspondence (both iconic and noniconic) and of attention and attentive-
ness. In this essay, we have seen how these concepts can produce fruitful in-
vestigations of spectatorship and, I hope, how nicely they fit as constructs with
the evidence that is available on the ways that people watch visual media and
infer meaning from visual displays. These concepts have already informed a
84 Part Two: Film Theory and Aesthetics
great deal of research elsewhere, and there is no reason why film studies can-
not further these lines of inquiry. Doing so, however, will involve a rethinking
of what spectatorship is and a recognition that theory is more than a set of
shared perspectives facilitating dialogue among adherents of the theory.
At a minimum, we should ask that our theories be capable of generating
researchable questions and be responsive to the evidence our studies furnish.
As this chapter has suggested, psychoanalytic film theory is flawed in both of
these areas. Once again, it is important to emphasize that the approach out-
lined here does not entail minimizing the richness of our philosophical or
conceptual frameworks. The results of our research always will need to be
integrated within a broad explanatory framework, that is, will need to be ac-
counted for theoretically. But our theories of spectatorship will also need to
be referenceable in terms of the available evidence on spectators. Above all,
we need to start our search for the missing spectator who has been lost to film
theory for several decades now. It will be a difficult search since film studies
has a long way to go. But iffilm scholars can undertake it, film studies will lay
claim to what should always have been an essential area of distinguished ac-
complishment-a sophisticated portrait of what it means to watch a film.
NOTES
1. Judith Mayne, Cinema and Spectatorship (New York: Routledge, 1993), p. 59.
2. Ibid., p. 37.
3. Kenneth Mark Colby and Robert J. Stoller, Cognitive Science and Psychoanalysis
(Hillsdale, N.J.: Lawrence Erlbaum, 1988), p. 3.
4. Ibid., p. 29.
5. See Laura Mulvey, "Visual Pleasure and Narrative Cinema," Screen 16, 3 (Au-
tumn 1975): 6-18, and her reconsideration of this essay in Visual and Other Pleasures
(Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1989).
6. See D. N. Rodowick, The Difficulty ofDifference (New York: Routledge, 1991);
Mary Ann Doane, "The 'Woman's Film': Possession and Address," in Re-Vision: Essays
in Feminist Film Criticism, eds. Mary Ann Doane, Patricia Mellencamp, and Linda
Williams (Frederick, Md.: AFIjUniversity Publications of America, 1984), pp. 67 - 80;
and Miriam Hansen, "Pleasure, Ambivalence, Identification: Valentino and Female
Spectatorship," Cinema Journal 25, 4 (1986): 6-32.
7. Christian Metz, The Imaginary Signifier: Psychoanalysis and the Cinema, trans.
Celia Britton, et al. (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1982), p. 64.
8. Rodowick, The Difficulty ofDifference, p. x.
9. Ibid.,p. 71.
10. Sigmund Freud, "A Child Is Being Beaten: A Contribution to the Study of the
Origin of Sexual Perversions," in Sigmund Freud, Collected Papers, 5 vols., trans. su-
pervised by Joan Riviere (New York: Basic Books, 1959),2: 179-80.
11. Kaja Silverman, "Masochism and Male Subjectivity," in Male Trouble, ed. Con-
stance Penley and Sharon Willis (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1993),
p.50.
12. Metz, The Imaginary Signifier, p. 58.
PRINCE: Psychoanalytic Film Theory 85
29. For a comprehensive review of this literature, see Patrick A. Cabe, "Picture Per-
ception in Nonhuman Subjects," in The Perception of Pictures, 2 vols., ed. Margaret A.
Hagen (New York: Academic Press, 1980),2: 305-43.
30. Elizabeth M. Perse and Rebecca B. Rubin, "Attribution in Social and Parasocial
Relationships," Communication Research 16,1 (February 1989): 73.
31. Aimee Dorr, "How Children Make Sense of Television," in Reader in Public
Opinion and Mass Communication, ed. Morris Janowitz and Paul M. Hirsch (New
York: Free Press, 1981), p. 374.
32. Paul Messaris and Larry Gross, "Interpretations of a Photographic Narrative by
Viewers in Four Age Groups," Studies in the Anthropology of Visual Communication 4
(1977): 99-111.
33. Thomas J. Berndt and Emily G. Berndt, "Children's Use of Motives and Inten-
tionality in Person Perception and Moral Judgement," Child Development 46 (1975):
904-12.
34. Austin S. Babrow, Barbara J. O'Keefe, David L. Swanson, Renee A. Meyers, and
Mary A. Murphy, "Person Perception and Children's Impression of Television and Real
Peers," Communication Research 15, 6 (December 1988): 680-98.
35. Cynthia Hoffner and Joanne Cantor, "Developmental Differences in Responses
to a Television Character's Appearance and Behavior," Developmental Psychology 21, 6
(1985): 1065-74.
36. Ray L. Birdwhistell, Kinesics and Context (Philadelphia: University ofPennsyl-
vania Press, 1970).
37. See Paul Ekman and Wallace V. Friesen, "Constants Across Culture in the Face
and Emotion," Journal ofPersonality and Social Psychology 17, 2 (1971): 124-29, and
Paul Ekman, "Expression and the Nature of Emotion" in Approaches to Emotion, ed.
Klaus R. Scherer and Paul Ekman pp. 319-43.