Murray Charles - Human Diversity PDF
Murray Charles - Human Diversity PDF
Murray Charles - Human Diversity PDF
Cover design by Jarrod Taylor. Cover copyright © 2020 by Hachette Book Group, Inc.
Hachette Book Group supports the right to free expression and the value of copyright.
The purpose of copyright is to encourage writers and artists to produce the creative
works that enrich our culture.
The scanning, uploading, and distribution of this book without permission is a theft of
the author’s intellectual property. If you would like permission to use material from the
book (other than for review purposes), please contact [email protected].
Thank you for your support of the author’s rights.
Twelve
Hachette Book Group
1290 Avenue of the Americas, New York, NY 10104
twelvebooks.com
twitter.com/twelvebooks
Twelve is an imprint of Grand Central Publishing. The Twelve name and logo are
trademarks of Hachette Book Group, Inc.
The publisher is not responsible for websites (or their content) that are not owned by
the publisher.
The Hachette Speakers Bureau provides a wide range of authors for speaking events.
To find out more, go to www.hachettespeakersbureau.com or call (866) 376-6591.
E3-20191205-JV-NF-ORI
Contents
Cover
Title Page
Copyright
Dedication
Epigraph
A Note on Presentation
Introduction
Part I
“Gender Is a Social Construct”
Part II
“Race Is a Social Construct”
Part III
“Class Is a Function of Privilege”
Part IV
Looking Ahead
Acknowledgments
Discover More
About the Author
Appendix 1: Statistics for People Who Are Sure They Can’t Learn Statistics
Appendix 2: Sexual Dimorphism in Humans
Appendix 3: Sex Differences in Brain Volumes and Variance
Notes
References
To Harlan Crow
Explore book giveaways, sneak peeks, deals, and more.
Now that we’re alone, let me tell you what Human Diversity is about and why I wrote
it.
The sciences form a hierarchy. “Physics rests on mathematics, chemistry on
physics, biology on chemistry, and, in principle, the social sciences on biology,” wrote
evolutionary biologist Robert Trivers.1 If so, this century should be an exhilarating time
to be a social scientist. Until now, we social scientists—for I am a member of that tribe
—have been second-class citizens of the scientific world, limited to data and methods
that cast doubt on our claim to be truly part of the scientific project. Now, new
possibilities are opening up.
Biology is not going to put us out of business. The new knowledge that geneticists
and neuroscientists are providing, conjoined with the kinds of analyses we do best, will
enable us to take giant strides in understanding how societies, polities, and economies
really function. We are like physicists at the outset of the nineteenth century, who were
poised at a moment in history that would produce Ampères and Faradays.
We ought to be excited, but we aren’t. Trivers again: “Yet discipline after discipline
—from economics to cultural anthropology—continues to resist growing connections to
the underlying science of biology, with devastating effects.”2
Why the resistance? Because the social sciences have been in the grip of an
orthodoxy that is scared stiff of biology.
The Orthodoxy
The core doctrine of the orthodoxy in the social sciences is a particular understanding
of human equality. I don’t mean equality in the sense of America’s traditional ideal—
all are equal in the eyes of God, have equal inherent dignity, and should be treated
equally under the law—but equality in the sense of sameness. Call it the sameness
premise: In a properly run society, people of all human groupings will have similar
life outcomes. Individuals might have differences in abilities, the orthodoxy (usually)
acknowledges, but groups do not have inborn differences in the distributions of those
abilities, except for undeniable ones such as height, upper body strength, and skin
color. Inside the cranium, all groups are the same.
The sameness premise theoretically applies to any method of grouping people, but
three of them have dominated the discussion for a long time: gender, race, and
socioeconomic class. Rephrased in terms of those groups, the sameness premise holds
that whatever their gender, race, or the class they are born into, people in every group
should become electrical engineers, nurture toddlers, win chess tournaments, and write
sci-fi novels in roughly equal proportions. They should have similar distributions of
family income, mental health, and life expectancy. Large group differences in these life
outcomes are prima facie evidence of social, cultural, and governmental defects that
can be corrected by appropriate public policy.
The intellectual origins of the orthodoxy go back more than three centuries to the
early days of the Enlightenment and the concept of humans as blank slates. The
explicit rejection of a role for biology in the social sciences occurred from the end of
the nineteenth through the beginning of the twentieth centuries, with the leading roles
played by Émile Durkheim in sociology, Franz Boas in anthropology, and John Watson
in psychology.3
The political expression of the orthodoxy had its origins in the mid-1960s with the
legal triumphs of the civil rights movement and the rise of feminism. In the beginning,
the orthodoxy consisted of specific allegations and solutions: Racism keeps black
unemployment high. Sexism stunts women’s careers. Affirmative action and
antidiscrimination laws are needed. But the orthodoxy soon began to incorporate an
intellectual movement that gained momentum in the mid-1960s with the publication of
The Social Construction of Reality by Peter L. Berger and Thomas Luckmann.
The authors were dealing with an ancient problem: Each of us thinks we know
what reality is, but different people have different perceptions of it. “The sociologist is
forced by the very logic of his discipline to ask, if nothing else, whether the difference
between the two ‘realities’ may not be understood in relation to various differences
between the two societies,” wrote Berger and Luckmann.4 This beginning, written in
plain English, perfectly sensible, morphed during the 1970s and 1980s into the
orthodox position that just about everything is a social construct, often argued in
postmodern prose that is incomprehensible to all but the elect.5 The sources of human
inequalities are artificial, made up, a reflection of the particular reality that a dominant
segment of society has decided is the one we must all live by.
As I write, three of the main tenets of the orthodoxy may be summarized as
follows:
Gender is a social construct. Physiological sex differences associated with
childbearing have been used to create artificial gender roles that are unjustified by
inborn characteristics of personality, abilities, or social behavior.
Race is a social construct. The concept of race has arisen from cosmetic
differences in appearance that are not accompanied by inborn differences in
personality, abilities, or social behavior.
Class is a function of privilege. People have historically been sorted into classes
by political, economic, and cultural institutions that privilege heterosexual white males
and oppress everyone else, with genes and human nature playing a trivial role if any.
People can be re-sorted in a socially just way by changing those institutions.
I have stated these tenets baldly. If you were to go onto a university campus and
chat privately with faculty members whose research touches on issues of gender, race,
or class, you would find that many of them, perhaps a majority, have a more nuanced
view than this. They accept that biology plays a role. Why then don’t they mention the
evidence for a biological role in their lectures? Their writings?
A common answer is that they fear that whatever they write will be misinterpreted
and misused. But it’s easy to write technical articles so that the mainstream media
never notice them. The real threat is not that the public will misuse a scholar’s findings,
but that certain fellow academicians will notice those findings and react harshly.
Therein lies the real barrier to incorporating biology into social science. It is possible
to survive on a university campus without subscribing to the orthodoxy. But you have
to be inconspicuous, because the simplistic version of the orthodoxy commands the
campus’s high ground. It is dangerous for a college faculty member to say openly in
articles, lectures, faculty meetings, or even in casual conversations that biology has a
significant role in creating differences between men and women, among races, or
among social classes. Doing so often carries a price. That price can be protests by
students, denial of tenure-track employment for postdocs, denial of tenure for assistant
professors, or reprimands from the university’s administrators.
The most common penalties are more subtle. University faculties are small
communities, with all the familiar kinds of social stigma for misfits. To be openly
critical of the orthodoxy guarantees that a vocal, influential element of your community
is going to come after you, socially and professionally. It guarantees that many others
will be reluctant to be identified with you. It guarantees that you will get a reputation
that varies from being an eccentric at best to a terrible human being at worst. It’s easier
to go along and get along.
The risks that face individual faculty members translate to much broader damage to
academia. We have gone from a shared telos for the university, exemplified by
Harvard’s motto, “Veritas,” to campuses where professors must be on guard against
committing thought crimes, students clamor for protection against troubling ideas,
codes limiting the free expression of ideas are routine, and ancient ideals of scholarly
excellence and human virtue are derided and denounced.6 On an individual level, social
scientists have valid rationales to avoid exploring the intersection of biology and society.
Collectively, their decisions have produced a form of de facto and widespread
intellectual corruption.
Archaeological Digs
The good news is that some scholars have been exploring the intersection of biology
and society despite the risks—so many that the orthodoxy is in the process of being
overthrown. The heavy lifting is being done not within the social sciences, but by
biologists and, more specifically, by geneticists and neuroscientists. They have been
accumulating data that will eventually pose the same problem for defenders of the
sameness premise that Aristotelian physicists faced when Galileo dropped objects from
heights. Everyone could see that they didn’t behave as Aristotle’s theory predicted. No
one could offer a counterargument. When our understanding of the genome and the
brain is sufficiently advanced—and it is approaching that point faster than most people
realize—the orthodox will be in the same position. Continuing to defend the sameness
premise will make them look silly. It is my belief that we are nearing inflection points
and that the triumph of the revolution will happen quickly. The key battles are likely to
be won within the 2020s. This book is a progress report.
In the course of writing Human Diversity, it became apparent to me that progress
is at strikingly different points for gender, race, and class. The analogy of an
archaeological dig of a buried city comes to mind.
The dig for gender is well along. Excavations have been extensive, the city’s layout
has been identified, and thousands of artifacts have been found. There’s lots yet to be
done, but the outlines of the city and its culture are coming into focus.
The dig for race is in its early stages. Topological analysis has identified a promising
site, initial clearing of the site has been completed, and the first probes have established
that there’s something down there worth investigating. Scientists are just beginning
excavation.
The dig for class had been largely completed by the end of the twentieth century,
and scholars in this century had until recently been kept busy analyzing the artifacts.
They are now returning to the site with newly developed tools.
Analogies aren’t precise, but this one explains the organization of the book. I begin
with gender differences and devote five substantial chapters to them. A lot has been
securely learned about gender differences. Race gets shorter chapters describing how
the site was located, how it has been cleared, and the evidence that there’s something
down there worth investigating. The chapters on class summarize findings that for the
most part have been known for decades.
Why Me?
I am neither a geneticist nor a neuroscientist. What business do I have writing this
book?
The answer is that specialists are seldom good at writing overviews of their
specialties for a general audience because they know too much—the forest and trees
problem. It’s often easier for an outsider to communicate the specialists’ main findings
to other outsiders. There are personal reasons as well. I think I’m skilled at making the
findings of technical literatures accessible to a broader audience, I enjoy doing it, and I
have been a fascinated observer of developments in genetics and neuroscience for
years. I’m also at a point in my career when I’m immune to many of the penalties that
a younger scholar would risk.
That career includes the firestorm that followed the publication of The Bell Curve
more than a quarter of a century ago, an experience that has been on my mind as I
have written Human Diversity. How can I avoid a repeat? Perhaps it’s impossible. The
background level of animosity and paranoia in today’s academia is much worse than it
was in 1994. But here is the reality: We are in the midst of a uniquely exciting period of
discoveries in genetics and neuroscience—that’s good news, not bad. My first goal is to
describe what is being learned as clearly as possible, without sensationalism. I hope you
will finish the book understanding that there are no monsters in the closet, no dread
doors that we must fear opening.
My second goal is to stick to the low-hanging fruit. Almost all of the findings I
report are ones that have broad acceptance within their disciplines. When a finding is
still tentative, I label it as such. I know this won’t deter critics from saying it’s all
pseudoscience, but I hope the experts will be yawning with boredom because they
know all this already. Having done my best to accomplish those two things, I will hope
for the best.
WHY THERE IS SO LITTLE ABOUT EVOLUTIONARY PSYCHOLOGY
IN HUMAN DIVERSITY
Hundreds of millions of years of evolution did more than shape human physiology. It shaped the
human brain as well. A comparatively new discipline, evolutionary psychology, seeks to understand
the links between evolutionary pressures and the way humans have turned out. Accordingly,
evolutionary psychology is at the heart of explanations for the differences that distinguish men from
women and human populations from each other. Ordinarily, it would be a central part of my
narrative. But the orthodoxy has been depressingly successful in demonizing evolutionary psychology
as just-so stories. I decided that incorporating its insights would make it too easy for critics to attack
the explanation and ignore the empirical reality.
I discuss some evolutionary material in my accounts of the peopling of the Earth and the source
of greater male variance. That’s it, however, ignoring the rest of the fascinating story. The note gives
you some sources for learning more.[7]
The 10 Propositions
The propositions that accompany most of the chapters are intended to exemplify low-
hanging fruit. I take on an extremely broad range of topics, but with the limited purpose
of clarifying a handful of bedrock issues.
I apologize for the wording of the 10 propositions—they are not as snappy as I
would prefer—but there’s a reason for their caution and caveats. On certain important
points, the clamor of genuine scientific dispute has abated and we don’t have to argue
about them anymore. But to meet that claim requires me to state the propositions
precisely. I am prepared to defend all of them as “things we don’t have to argue about
anymore”—but exactly as I worded them, not as others may paraphrase them.
Here they are:
On all 10, the empirical record is solid. The debate should move on to new findings
in the many areas where great uncertainty remains. That doesn’t mean I expect the 10
propositions to be immutable. On the contrary, I have had to keep in mind that Human
Diversity is appearing in the midst of a rushing stream, reporting on a rapidly changing
state of knowledge. Aspects of it are sure to be out of date by the time the book
appears. My goal is to have been so cautious in my wording of the propositions that
any outdated aspects of them will have been elaborated or made more precise, not
overturned.
How the Phrase Cognitive Repertoires Is Used Throughout the Rest of the Book
The 10 propositions repeatedly refer to “characteristics of personality, abilities, or
social behavior.” As I will occasionally put it, I am talking about the ways in which
human beings differ above the neck (a loose way of putting it, but serviceably
accurate).
I use personality and social behavior in their ordinary meanings. Abilities is a
catch-all term that includes not only intellectual abilities but interpersonal skills and the
clusters of qualities that have been described as emotional intelligence and grit. A good
way of thinking about the universe of abilities is through Howard Gardner’s famous
theory of multiple intelligences.[8]
From now on I will usually abbreviate personality, abilities, and social behavior
to cognitive repertoires. Cognitive means that it happens in the cranium or is at least
mediated there. Repertoires refers to different ways of doing things that need not be
ordered from “bad” at one extreme to “good” at the other. Some of them can be so
ordered, but few have bad-to-good extremes. If you’re an employer, where do you
want a job applicant to be on the continuum from “extremely passive” to “extremely
aggressive”? It depends on whether you’re recruiting Navy SEALs or care providers at
nursing homes, and in neither case is the most extreme position the ideal one. The
same is true even of something generally considered to be an unalloyed good, such as
high IQ. Google may be looking for the highest possible visuospatial skills among its
applicants for programmers, but the qualities that often accompany stratospheric
visuospatial skills would make many of them dreadful choices as SEALs or care
providers.
For most of the human qualities we will be discussing, “bad” and “good” don’t
capture human differences. How many kinds of lovable are there? How many kinds of
funny? How many kinds of annoying? Using the word repertoires allows for these
kinds of apples and oranges too. So take note: For the rest of the book, cognitive
repertoires = characteristics of personality, abilities, and social behavior.
From earliest recorded human history, everywhere and in all eras, women have borne
the children and have been the primary caregivers. Everywhere and in all eras, men
have dominated the positions of political, economic, and cultural power.1 From those
two universal characteristics have flowed a cascade of secondary and tertiary
distinctions in the status of men and women, many of which have nothing to do with
their actual capabilities. In today’s language, gender has indeed been partly a social
construct. Many of those distinctions were ruthlessly enforced.
The legal constraints on women in the modern West through the eighteenth century
were not much short of de facto slavery. Mary Astell, often regarded as the first
feminist (though she had precursors), made the point in response to John Locke’s
cramped endorsement of women’s equality in the Second Treatise.2 She italicized
phrases borrowed from Locke’s philosophical case for freedom: “If all men are born
free, how is it that all women are born slaves? As they must be if the being subjected to
the unconstant, uncertain, unknown, arbitrary will of men, be the perfect condition
of slavery?… And why is slavery so much condemned and strove against in one case,
and so highly applauded and held so necessary and so sacred in another?”3
If Astell’s language seems extreme, consider: An English woman at the time Astell
wrote and for more than a century thereafter rarely got any formal education and had
no access to university education, was prohibited from entering the professions, and
lost control of any property she owned when she married. She was obliged to take the
“honor and obey” marriage vow literally, with harsh penalties for falling short and only
the slightest legal protections if the husband took her punishment into his own hands.
Men were legally prohibited from actually killing their wives, but just about anything
less than that was likely to be overlooked. When the first wave of feminism in the
United States got its start at the Seneca Falls Convention of 1848, women were
rebelling not against mere inequality, but against near-total legal subservience to men.
Under those conditions, first-wave feminists were too busy to say much about
questions of inborn differences between men and women. An exception was Kate
Austin, who compared the plight of women to those of Chinese women with bound
feet: “We know that at birth the feet of the little baby girl were straight and beautiful
like her brothers, but a cruel and artificial custom restrained the growth. Likewise it is
just as foolish to assert that woman is mentally inferior to man, when it is plain to be
seen her brain in a majority of cases receives the same treatment accorded the feet of
Chinese girls.”4 As Helena Swanwick put it, “There does not seem much that can be
profitably said about [the alleged inferiority of women]… until the incubus of brute
force is removed.”5 Men joined in some of the strongest early statements on nature
versus nurture. John Stuart Mill coauthored “The Subjection of Women” with his
feminist wife, Harriet Taylor.6 George Bernard Shaw wrote, “If we have come to think
that the nursery and the kitchen are the natural sphere of a woman, we have done so
exactly as English children come to think that a cage is the natural sphere of a parrot—
because they have never seen one anywhere else.”[7]
After the great legal battles of first-wave feminism had been won during the first
two decades of the twentieth century, a new generation of feminists began to devote
more attention to questions of nature versus nurture. The result was second-wave
feminism, usually dated to the publication of Simone de Beauvoir’s Le Deuxième Sexe,
a massive two-volume work published in 1949. Its argument sprawled across
philosophy, history, sociology, economics, and psychology. The founding statement of
second-wave feminism opened the second volume: “On ne naît pas femme: on le
devient.” One is not born, but rather becomes, a woman.[8]
It was an assertion that required an explanation of how and why the change from
birth to adulthood takes place. The intuitive explanation of “how” is that little girls are
taught to be women—what is known now as socialization theory. It refers to the ways
that children are exposed to influences that shape their gender identities. The pressure
can come from parental interactions in infancy and toddlerhood, as girl babies are
dressed differently from boy babies and female toddlers are given dolls to play with
while boys are given trucks. The pressure may take the form of encouragement by
parents, teachers, or playmates to engage in sex-typed play and discouragement of
behaviors that go against type, as in the case of tomboy girls and effeminate boys.
Parents may teach different lessons about right behavior, emphasizing the importance
of being helpful and cooperative to daughters and the importance of standing up for
themselves and taking the initiative to sons. Children may be encouraged to model
themselves on the parent of their own sex. In these and many other ways, sometimes
subtle or unconscious, children are constantly getting signals that track with the
stereotypes of males and females.
This brief characterization of socialization theory skips over a number of intense
scholarly debates between learning theorists and cognitive theorists, but the debaters
differ about the mechanisms at work. All agree on the basic tenet that girls are taught
from infancy to be girls and boys are taught from infancy to be boys.9
Is socialization theory true? It’s natural to think so, if only because almost
everybody can think of something during their childhood that involved references to
what girls are supposed to be and what boys are supposed to be. Those of us who
have had children of both sexes know that our interactions with our daughters and our
sons have been somewhat different even if we tried hard to be gender-neutral in
encouraging their abilities and ambitions.
But it’s one thing to have such personal experiences and another to demonstrate
empirically that these differences in treatment as children produce the sex differences in
personality, abilities, and social behavior that we observe in adult women and men.
Little boys and little girls are treated differently, but how differently? “Several
theoretical models suggest mechanisms that are consistent with the differential
treatment of boys and girls,” wrote four Dutch scholars of childhood socialization.
“However, to date there is no consensus in the literature about the extent to which
parents do treat their sons and daughters differently, in which areas of parenting this
mostly occurs, and whether fathers and mothers differ in the extent of gender
differentiation.”10 [Emphasis in the original.]
The literature about differential socialization now consists of hundreds of titles. The
note gives an overview of what has been found.[11] The short answer is that while
there are lots of reasons to think that little girls and little boys are treated differently, it’s
surprisingly hard to prove that the differences are more than superficial.
Apart from its empirical problems, socialization theory standing alone is
unsatisfying. Yes, it provides a framework for exploring the how of the construction of
artificial sex differences, but it is silent on the why. Why should it be, everywhere and
throughout history, that certain differences between the sexes have been so consistent?
Isn’t it simpler to assume that we’re looking at innate sex differences produced by
millions of years of evolution? In 1987, psychologist Alice Eagly published Sex
Differences in Social Behavior: A Social-Role Interpretation, introducing a
comprehensive theory of sex differences that embraces evolution, sociology,
psychology, and biology, providing an answer to the why.12 She has continued to
develop the theory in the decades since, often in collaboration with psychologist Wendy
Wood. Reduced to its essentials, the argument goes like this:
In the beginning was evolution, which led to physical sex differences. Males were
larger, faster, and had greater upper body strength than females. Only females were
capable of gestation and lactation. Given such differences, certain divisions of labor
were natural. In hunter-gatherer societies, men’s greater upper body strength led
societies to funnel males into social roles involving physical strength—for example,
hunting and protection against predators—and to funnel women into social roles
involving childcare.
Over the millennia, social roles gave rise to gender roles as people associated the
behaviors of males and females with their dispositions. Women are associated with
childcare not just because of biology but because of a reflexive assumption that
women, more than men, have innate nurturing qualities. It is not just that men’s
physical attributes make them more efficient hunters than women; it is also reflexively
assumed that males have innate advantages—aggressiveness, perhaps, or initiative—
that make them better hunters. This conflation of social role and gender role persists
after the original physical justification for some social role has disappeared. These
beliefs about stable, inherent properties of men and women have solidified without a
biological foundation for them.
Enter socialization. If society has come to depend on women caring for children,
little girls need to be socialized into the personality traits and skills that facilitate
nurturance. If society has come to depend on men being providers and leaders, little
boys need to be socialized into the personality traits that facilitate acquiring resources
and status.
Social role theory includes a role for biology. “Men and women selectively recruit
hormones and other neurochemical processes for appropriate roles, in the context of
their gender identities and others’ expectations for role performance,” Eagly and Wood
write. “Testosterone is especially relevant when, due to personal identities and social
expectancies, people experience social interactions as dominance contests. Oxytocin is
relevant when, due to personal identities and social expectancies, people define social
interactions as involving bonding and affiliation with close others.”13 Biology interacts
with psychology in two ways. Men and women alike psychologically internalize their
gender roles as “self standards” for regulating their own behavior. They also regulate
their behavior according to the expectations that others in the community have of them.
“Biology thus works with psychology to facilitate role performance.”14
The interdisciplinary sweep of social role theory means that it calls upon a wide
variety of empirical observations about social roles across history and across cultures,
evidence from psychology about internalization of norms, social psychological
experiments, the nature of sex differences in personality, demographic trends, and
economics, among many others. There is no equivalent to the meta-analyses of
socialization studies that permits a short characterization of the state of knowledge
about the validity of social role theory. But social role theory does what socialization
theory does not: It provides a comprehensive explanation of why sex is a social
construct.
But is sex exclusively a social construct? That the woman in a heterosexual couple
does more housework than the man even when both have full-time jobs is at least
largely a gender difference—the product of culture. It may have biological roots
(perhaps men have evolved to be more tolerant of a messy living space than women
are). But the issue is whether differential effort in doing the housework is sustained
today by culture or genes. Think of it this way: How many women who can afford to
hire someone to clean the house do so? A lot.
But simple quickly becomes complicated. Is the difference between the time men
and women spend tending to young children artificially created by culture or driven by
inborn male-female differences? How about the attraction of girl toddlers to dolls and
boy toddlers to trucks? Male-female differences in college majors? Male-female
differences in attraction to casual sex? Are they sex differences or gender differences?
The sensible answer would seem to be “probably some of both,” with arguments
about how much of which. At one level, that’s actually how the academic debate is
conducted. The following chapters have hundreds of references to highly technical
articles, adhering to normal standards of scientific rigor, published in refereed journals,
arguing questions of nature and nurture, with male and female scholars making
contributions on all sides on all topics. The tone is usually civil, and the conclusions are
usually nuanced and caveated.
But the women and men who are engaged in this endeavor are a rarefied group of
neuroscientists and quantitative social scientists. Few of them seek publicity (many do
their work as unobtrusively as possible), and they do not set the mood on college
campuses. Since American second-wave feminism took off in the 1960s, the most
visible feminist academics have rejected the possibility that there are any significant sex
differences from the neck up. In my terminology, they have denied that men and
women have any inborn differences in cognitive repertoires. A person’s gender “is an
arbitrary, ever-changing socially constructed set of attributes that are culture-specific
and culturally generated, beginning with the appearance of the external genitals at
birth,” in the words of one of the most widely read feminist scientists in women’s
studies courses, Ruth Bleier.15 It’s not a position with a lot of nuance. Gender is a
social construct. End of story.
The most famous illustration of what happens to those who question the orthodoxy
is what befell economist Larry Summers. On January 14, 2005, Summers, then
president of Harvard University, spoke to a conference on diversifying the science and
engineering workforce.16 In his informal remarks, responding to the sponsors’
encouragement to speculate, he offered reasons for thinking that innate differences in
men and women might account for some of the underrepresentation of women in
science and engineering. He spoke undogmatically and collegially, talking about
possibilities, phrasing his speculations moderately. And all hell broke loose.
An MIT biologist, Nancy Hopkins, told reporters that she “felt I was going to be
sick,” that “my heart was pounding and my breath was shallow,” and that she had to
leave the room because otherwise “I would’ve either blacked out or thrown up.”17
Within a few days, Summers had been excoriated by the chairperson of Harvard’s
sociology department, Mary C. Waters, and received a harshly critical letter from
Harvard’s committee on faculty recruiting. One hundred and twenty Harvard
professors endorsed the letter. Some alumnae announced that they would suspend
donations.18 Summers retracted his remarks, with, in journalist Stuart Taylor Jr.’s
words, “groveling, Soviet-show-trial-style apologies.”19 As if to validate that image,
Lizabeth Cohen, a Harvard history professor, told reporters after attending the
Summers self-criticism session that “[h]e regrets what he said, and I hope that he will
prove that by taking constructive steps. We’re going to be in intense discussions with
him over the next week.”20
Since 2005, expanding knowledge about male-female differences has substantiated
Summers’s speculations. The next five chapters review that evidence. The basics have
been available to interested lay readers for years.[21] And yet elite gender studies
departments still refuse to acknowledge the biological side of gender differences.[22]
The degree to which the standard social science disciplines have also ignored this
literature is an intellectual scandal. Evolutionary biologist Robert Trivers, whom you
met in the introduction, has not held back:
Once you remove biology from human social life, what do you have? Words.
Not even language, which of course is deeply biological, but words alone that
then wield magical powers, capable of biasing your every thought, science itself
reduced to one of many arbitrary systems of thought.
And what has been the upshot of this? Thirty-five wasted years and
counting. Years wasted in not synthesizing social and physical anthropology.
Strong people welcome new ideas and make them their own. Weak people run
from new ideas, or so it seems, and then are driven into bizarre mind states,
such as believing that words have the power to dominate reality, that social
constructs such as gender are much stronger than the 300 million years of
genetic evolution that went into producing the two sexes—whose facts in any
case they remain resolutely ignorant of.23
Despite the orthodoxy’s devotion to “words that have the power to dominate
reality,” the state of knowledge about the observable differences in men and women
has advanced enormously in the last 20 years. During those same years, the state of
knowledge about sex differences in the brain has been transformed. The next five
chapters give you an overview of the most important developments.
1
A few decades from now, I expect we will have a widely accepted comprehensive
theory of sex differences that is grounded in neuroscience, genetics, and evolutionary
psychology. Progress has already been made in that regard, but it is still at the frontiers
of scholarship and bears no resemblance to low-hanging fruit. In any case, my
purposes don’t require that level of sophistication. A simple framework for thinking
about phenotypic sex differences is supported by a growing number of scholars. This
framework also links up with recent findings about sex differences in the brain.
A WORD ABOUT USAGE
From now on I will usually refer to “sex differences” instead of “gender differences.” “Gender” was
popularized in the 1960s to designate socially constructed differences.[1] But it turns out that there is
no clear division between biological and socially constructed differences and no point in trying to
pretend otherwise—which is what the widespread use of “gender” amounts to. In the technical
literature, many scholars who write on these topics have resumed the use of “sex” to apply to all
kinds of differences between males and females. So do I.
The People-Things Dimension
More than a century ago, Edward Thorndike, one of the founders of educational
psychology, asserted that the greatest cognitive difference between men and women is
“in the relative strength of the interest in things and their mechanisms (stronger in men)
and the interest in persons and their feelings (stronger in women).”2 In 1944, Hans
Asperger, for whom Asperger’s syndrome is named, hypothesized that the autistic
cognitive profile is an extreme variant of male intelligence, which is another way of
saying that normal males are more interested in things than people.3 On the female
side, the quantifiable existence of a female advantage in “sociability,” as it had come to
be called, was developed over the last half of the twentieth century among experts in
personality.
Putting these advances together with some discoveries in biology that I will discuss
in chapter 5, Simon Baron-Cohen, director of Cambridge University’s Autism Research
Centre, developed a theory of male-female differences that he described for a general
audience in The Essential Difference: Male and Female Brains and the Truth About
Autism, published in 2003. He coined the words systemizer and empathizer. In Baron-
Cohen’s formulation, men are driven to understand and build systems. The defining
features of a system are that it has rules and that it does something. It has inputs at one
end and outputs at the other. In between are specific operations that translate the inputs
into the outputs. “This definition,” Baron-Cohen wrote, “takes in systems beyond
machines such as math, physics, chemistry, astronomy, logic, music, military strategy,
the climate, sailing, horticulture, and computer programming. It also includes systems
like libraries, economics, companies, taxonomies, board games, or sports.”4 Whatever
the system may be, men are attracted to understanding what makes it tick.
Understanding what makes human beings tick? Not so much. “The baby is crying
because it’s hungry” is something men can recognize as well as women (ordinarily,
anyway). But entering into and responding to the state of someone else’s mind is a
different matter. Empathy is required for that. Most men can do it, but on average,
women are attracted to it more and do it better. It’s not just because women devote
more attention to it. Entering into someone else’s mind calls on a different set of mental
capabilities than the ones required for understanding a system.
Empathizer as Baron-Cohen uses the word is not confined to understanding what’s
going on inside the other person’s head. It also involves “the observer’s emotional
response to another person’s emotional state.”5 Sympathy might be one part of the
emotional response, but it can also be anger or concern. These responses may be used
for altruistic or self-interested purposes. Good empathizers can make effective
ministers to the grieving and effective therapists for the psychologically troubled—but,
using the same neurocognitive tools, they can also make effective arbitrators of
disputes, interrogators of criminal suspects, managers of people, or election-winning
politicians.
Other scholars of sex differences have been finding differences in academic
interests, careers, and life choices that break along the lines of systemizing and
empathizing but that also lend themselves to the broader and simpler difference that
Thorndike identified—in choice after choice, men are attracted to options that have
more to do with things while women are attracted to options that have more to do with
people. That’s the simple theory of the case I bring to the chapters on sex differences:
Women and men divide along the People-Things dimension.
Lest there be any misunderstanding: I am talking about statistical tendencies, not
binary divisions. Many men and women possess trait profiles more typical of the
other sex.[6] But these tendencies are strong enough to create distinctively different
distributions on important traits of personality, abilities, and social behavior.
First Interlude: Interpreting How Big a Sex Difference Is
The dotted vertical lines show the means for women and men. The gray horizontal
bar shows the difference between the two, which I call the “raw effect size.” Dividing
it by the pooled standard deviations of the two groups gives us a way to express
magnitude that can be compared across different traits.
An effect size is denoted as d. To calculate d for height, I subtracted the male mean
from the female mean, producing a difference of –5.4 inches. The pooled standard
deviation is 2.9 inches, so d equals –5.4 ÷ 2.9, which works out to an effect size of –
1.86. This is an extremely large effect size. Most sex differences are much smaller and
the distributions have much more overlap.
Note that the sign of d (negative or positive) is arbitrary. If I had subtracted the
female mean from the male mean, the effect size wouldn’t have changed, but the sign
would have been positive. Just so you know, in this book my default will be to
subtract the male mean from the female mean in calculating sex differences.
Therefore negative d values will always indicate that males are higher than females
on the trait in question, whether “higher” means something good, bad, or neutral.
Two questions are crucial to assessing the importance of sex differences: When is
an effect size big enough to be interesting? Should individual effect sizes be treated
individually or aggregated?
When Is an Effect Size Big Enough to Be Interesting?
Jacob Cohen, who originated Cohen’s d, inadvertently set the standard for interpreting
effect sizes (he had a different purpose in mind). His list was subsequently expanded
by Shlomo Sawilowsky. Under these guidelines, a d value of 0.01 = very small, 0.20 =
small, 0.50 = medium, 0.80 = large, 1.20 = very large, and 2.00 = huge.7
The guidelines were well-intended but have often proved to be pernicious in
practice. As Cohen himself took pains to point out, the importance of a given value of
Cohen’s d depends on the specific topic you are examining.[8] In 2019, psychologists
David Funder and Daniel Ozer took on what they called the “nonsensical” standard set
by Cohen, arguing that the interpretation of effect sizes should be guided by their
consequences. In the case of a drug for curing a deadly disease that has a relatively
small success rate, the effect of a success is a saved life—a consequence that can be
important even if the effect size is small. In the case of a small effect size that has
many repetitions, it’s the cumulative effect that’s important. For example, a study that
tracked two million financial transactions found that the correlation between a person’s
score on a measure of extraversion and the amount spent on holiday shopping is just
+.09. “Multiply the effect identified with this correlation by the number of people in a
department store the week before Christmas,” the authors wrote, “and it becomes
obvious why merchandisers should care deeply about the personalities of their
customers.”9 They offered a new set of guidelines based on the correlation coefficient
(r). In the summary that follows, I have replaced the value of r with the equivalent
value of Cohen’s d.
The authors argued that an effect size of .10 “is ‘very small’ for the explanations of
single events but potentially consequential in the not-very long run,” while an effect
size of .20 “is still ‘small’ at the level of single events but potentially more ultimately
consequential.”10 Other scholars have advocated similar guidelines for interpreting
small values of d.11 But their treatment of “small” collides with the position taken by
the most influential work arguing for small sex differences in cognitive repertoires—the
“gender similarities hypothesis” originated by psychologist Janet Shibley Hyde in the
September 1985 issue of American Psychologist, the flagship journal of the American
Psychological Association. Here is her statement of the hypothesis:
The gender similarities hypothesis holds that males and females are similar on
most, but not all, psychological variables. That is, men and women, as well as
boys and girls, are more alike than they are different. In terms of effect sizes,
the gender similarities hypothesis states that most psychological sex differences
are in the close-to-zero (d ≤ 0.10) or small (0.11 < d < 0.35) range, a few are in
the moderate range (0.36 < d < 0.65), and very few are large (d = 0.66–1.00)
or very large (d > 1.00).12
Describing precisely why those two faces are so obviously a female’s on the left
and a male’s on the right is daunting. The individual differences are almost
imperceptible. But one thing is sure: To average out all those tiny individual differences
and conclude that “male and female faces are virtually indistinguishable” would be
ridiculous. The estimate of overall sex difference in faces must be expressed as some
sort of aggregation. I submit that the same holds true for all sex differences comprised
of functionally distinctive but conceptually related traits.
2
Bimbo. Jock. Feminine. Macho. A great lady. A true gentleman. Males and females
have been stereotyping each other from time out of mind, positively and negatively.
Almost all of the stereotypes are about personality characteristics that are thought to
break along the lines of sex. Some do and some don’t. At the end of the review of the
evidence in this chapter, I defy anyone to conclude that either sex has a superior
personality profile. They’re just different. Some of the most coherent ways they’re
different correspond to the People-Things dimension.
Sex Differences in Psychiatric and Neurological Conditions
Source: Adapted from McCarthy, Nugent, and Lenz (2017): Table 2. The original table
includes references.
At this point, I just want to put the existence of these well-documented and
important sex differences on the table.2 Possible biological causes will be discussed in
chapter 5.
Sex Differences in Personality Within the Normal Range
Now I turn to adult personality profiles. We know from everyday experience that
personality characteristics tend to cluster. The person who is the life of the party tends
to enjoy being around other people elsewhere. The person who is a hypochondriac also
tends to fret about other things. In the 1940s, psychometricians led by Raymond
Cattell began to explore how personality “facets,” the detailed indicators of personality
characteristics, clustered into larger constructs—“factors.”[3] Over several years,
Cattell and his colleagues developed a model that had 16 factors and a self-report
personality test called the Sixteen Personality Factor Questionnaire, labeled 16PF. It is
now in its fifth edition and continues to be widely used.
By the 1980s, another personality model had gained wide currency. It is known
colloquially as the Big Five model, the label I will use.4 The factor that explains the
most variance is neuroticism, which I will relabel emotional stability (see the box
below). The other four, in descending order of the variance they explain, are
extraversion, openness, agreeableness, and conscientiousness. The first widely
accepted test was based on work by Paul Costa and Robert McCrae of the National
Institutes of Health. I will refer to it as the Five Factor Model (FFM) inventory.5
NEUROTICISM OR EMOTIONAL STABILITY?
Every personality characteristic has a continuum that goes from one extreme to the other, and neither
extreme is desirable. 6 For example, agreeableness at one extreme indicates an unquestioningly
acquiescent person; at the other extreme, it indicates a reflexively antagonistic person. Four of the
Big Five factors have labels that describe a moderately positive position on the continuum. One label,
neuroticism, is not only negative but, to most ears, extremely negative. In the technical literature,
scholars increasingly use a moderately positive label for this factor, emotional stability. I do so as
well.
Other personality models have been developed, but the 16PF and FFM inventories
continue to be the ones with the largest databases and the most cross-national
databases.7 I focus on three surveys of adults: the U.S. standardization sample of
Costa and McCrae’s FFM inventory in 1992 (n = 1,000), hereafter called the Costa
study; a 2018 replication using the open-access version of the FFM inventory by
psychologists Petri Kajonius and John Johnson (n = 320,128), hereafter called the
Kajonius study; and the analysis by psychologists Marco Del Giudice, Tom Booth, and
Paul Irwing of the U.S. standardization sample for the fifth edition of the 16PF
inventory (n = 10,261), hereafter called the Del Giudice study.
Personality Sex Differences in the United States
It is appropriate to begin by emphasizing that on many important personality traits, the
differences between men and women are quite small. These trivial differences apply to
many characteristics that are sometimes ascribed to men (e.g., “assertive or forceful in
expression,” “self-reliant, solitary, resourceful”) and ones that are sometimes ascribed
to women (e.g., “open to the inner world of imagination,” “lively, animated,
spontaneous”). The full list is given in the note.[8]
Among the traits on which men and women differ, some of the largest effect sizes
are consistent with the higher prevalence of depression among women. In the FFM
inventory, women experienced more free-floating anxiety than men (d = +0.40 and
+0.56 for the Costa and Kajonius studies respectively) and were more vulnerable to
stress (d = +0.44 and +0.54). In the 16PF inventory, women were more apprehensive,
self-doubting, and worried (d = +0.60 in the Del Giudice study).9
Some of the substantively significant sex differences correspond to traditional
stereotypes about feminine sensibility. In the FFM inventory, women were more
appreciative of art and beauty than were men (d = +0.34 and +0.33 for the Costa and
Kajonius studies respectively), were more open to inner feelings and emotions (d =
+0.28 and +0.64), were more modest in playing down their achievements (d = +0.38
and +0.45), and were more reactive, affected by feelings, and easily upset (d = +0.53).
In the 16PF inventory, several stereotypical characteristics were combined into one
factor, “sensitive, aesthetic, sentimental,” with a whopping d of +2.29.
The characteristics shown in the table below have a special bearing on the People-
Things dimension.
Measuring personality sex differences in infancy is tough, and the instruments for doing so are not
nearly as precise as instruments for older children. Different studies come up with different estimates
of some relationships, and almost all of the studies need replication. The most dramatic example of a
finding from infancy, which led to considerable publicity, was a 2002 study presenting evidence that
newborn girls no more than two days old after birth showed stronger interest in a human face while
the newborn boys showed stronger interest in a mechanical mobile. 14 It is a single, unreplicated
study with a sample of 102, not proof to take to the bank, but its finding was in line with many other
studies that have found personality sex differences in infants.
On average, infant girls cry longer than boys in response to recordings of another baby crying,
believed to be a primitive empathic reaction. 15
On average, infant girls hold eye contact with an adult human longer than boys do. 16
On average, infant girls show more expressions of joy than boys at the appearance of the
mother. 17
On average, infant girls are more responsive to maternal vocalizations than infant boys. 18
On average, infant girls are more distressed by maternal “still face” than infant boys. 19
On average, infant girls show visual preferences for objects with human attributes while boys
show more visual preferences for balls and vehicles. 20
On average, infant girls are more likely to initiate and respond to joint attention. 21
In Erin McClure’s meta-analysis of 20 studies of facial expression processing in infants, the six
studies for which effect sizes were reported or could be calculated had a weighted effect size of
+0.92 favoring girls.[22]
Sex Differences in Personality Worldwide
So far, I have presented nothing indicating that these personality differences are
hardwired. Maybe that’s just the way little girls and little boys are brought up in the
United States and other Western cultures. That’s where cross-national comparisons
come in. The legal and social status of women varies widely around the world. Some
Islamic cultures still keep women at a level of legal subservience little better than
Western women experienced until the twentieth century. Some sub-Saharan African
cultures still take the superiority and dominance of men for granted and organize daily
life accordingly. At the other extreme are countries in Western Europe and especially
Scandinavia that have erected elaborate structures to require gender parity in all
economic and social matters.
Cultures around the world have other deep differences that affect both women and
men—for example, the intensely family-oriented cultures of much of Asia compared to
the individualism of the Western tradition. And yet despite this extremely wide range of
environments in which children are raised, sex differences in personality are
remarkably similar around the world.
The same article that reported the results for American adults on the Costa-McCrae
inventory also reported them for 25 other countries.23 In 2005, McCrae and Antonio
Terracciano used observer reports from 50 cultures, 22 of which had not been included
in previous studies. The next table shows effect sizes for the same five traits from the
Costa-McCrae inventory shown in the previous table, adding the results from the
international samples.
The results show universally higher female means and similar effect sizes on the
individual traits. Even taken country by country, the number of anomalies was
remarkably small. The Costa study reported effect sizes for extraversion,
agreeableness, and openness for 26 populations in 25 countries—78 effect sizes in all.
The signs for 77 out of the 78 were positive (women scored higher).24 The McCrae
study of 50 cultures reported country-by-country effect sizes for 49 populations in 46
countries. Of the 147 effect sizes reported, 139 were positive. The largest of the
negative effect sizes (i.e., higher for males) was trivially small (d = –0.05).25
This consistency is all the more remarkable considering that the 50 nations included
ones from East Asia, South Asia, the Mideast, Africa, Europe, South America, and
North America, and nations that ranged from the most impoverished and traditional
(e.g., Uganda, Burkina Faso) to the wealthiest and most sex-egalitarian (e.g., Sweden,
Denmark). The great cultural and economic disparities across these countries make it
difficult to see how all of them could produce uniform socialization of girls to be more
warm, altruistic, sympathetic, sociable, and artistically sensitive than men.
Sex Differences in Personality and a Society’s Gender Egality
I use gender egality in preference to gender equality to signify not just progress toward
diminishing sex differences but also institutional, legal, and social changes intended to
put men and women on an equal footing. The question at hand is whether sex
differences in personality are smaller in countries that have made the most progress.
The theories of socialization and of social roles that I summarized in chapter 1
necessarily expect that the answer is yes. If sex differences in personality are artificial,
diminishing the causes of artificial differences must eventually lead to smaller
differences.26 The only question is how long it will take. This brings us to a
counterintuitive finding that seems to cut across a variety of sex differences: Many sex
differences in cognitive repertoires are wider rather than smaller in countries with
greater gender egality. Personality traits offers the first example.
The Evidence for Wider Personality Differences in Advanced Countries
The Costa study. The Costa study discovered this startling result as they examined the
scores for individual nations in their pioneering study. The wrong nations had the
largest sex differences: “Sex differences are most marked among European and
American cultures and most attenuated among African and Asian cultures,” they wrote.
[27]
To convey this finding more systematically, I employ the UN’s annual Gender
Inequality Index (GII). It is based on maternal mortality rate, adolescent birth rate,
women’s share of seats in parliament, percentage of women with at least some
secondary education, and women’s labor force participation.[28] A high score on the
GII indicates high inequality.
The results correspond to widespread impressions that Western Europe has the best
record for sex equality. Among the 70 nations with data on personality and a GII score,
the five nations with the best (meaning lowest) scores on the GII were Switzerland,
Denmark, the Netherlands, Sweden, and Iceland. The five nations with the worst
(highest) GII scores were Burkina Faso, Congo, Egypt, Pakistan, and Tanzania.
As noted, both socialization and social role theories of sex differences predict that
effect sizes should diminish as gender egality increases. Translated into a prediction
about the Costa data, this means that a correlation between the absolute size of the sex
difference and the GII should be positive (greater inequality is associated with greater
personality differences).29 In the Costa study, those correlations were not only negative
—the “wrong” sign—but substantially so: –.61 for emotional stability, –.57 for
extraversion, –.49 for openness to emotion, and –.42 for agreeableness.30 On average,
personality differences were wider in countries with greater gender egality.
The McCrae study. The McCrae study applied the same measures plus one for
conscientiousness to a larger sample of nations, using an observational measure of
personality traits rather than self-reports. It found the same thing as the Costa study.
The correlations between the Gender Inequality Index with the effect sizes for sex
differences were once again all in the “wrong” direction and all substantial: –.61 for
openness to emotion, –.57 for emotional stability, –.56 for extraversion, –.47 for
conscientiousness, and –.43 for agreeableness.[31]
The Schmitt study. In 2008, an international team of behavioral scientists consisting
of American David Schmitt, Austrian Martin Voracek, and two Estonians, Anu Realo
and Jüri Allik, drew on one of the largest cross-cultural studies of personality ever
conducted, part of the International Sexuality Description Project, with three aims in
mind.
First, the team wanted to see if the findings of the Costa and McCrae studies
generalized to another instrument for measuring personality. The Schmitt study used
the Big Five Inventory, consisting of 44 self-report items, rather than the FFM
inventory.
Second, the team wanted to increase the range of nations in the database. In all,
they obtained personality measures from 55 nations, including 14 that were not part of
either the Costa or McCrae studies.
Third, the Schmitt study undertook an elaborate set of tests to determine whether
artifacts explained the widening personality differences in advanced countries.
The short version of the answers presented at length in the Schmitt study is that (1)
the Big Five Inventory showed essentially the same cross-national patterns that the
FFM inventory had produced; (2) the addition of new nations allowed an extension of
the conclusions that the Costa and McCrae studies had reached; and (3) the arguments
for an artifactual explanation of the widening gap in advanced nations were not borne
out by the analyses.32
The Giolla study. In 2018, Erik Mac Giolla and Petri J. Kajonius published the
results for a database with a more extensive (120-item) version of the FFM for 22
countries with uniformly larger sample sizes per country (at least 1,000) than the
samples used by the other studies. Uniquely, this study also calculated Mahalanobis D
—the method for aggregating individual effect sizes that I described in chapter 1. The
index of gender egality used for the study was the Global Gender Gap Index (GGGI)
published by the World Economic Forum. The index is scored from 0 to 1, with 1
meaning gender equality (or better conditions for women) on all of the 14 indicators.33
In this case, the “right” correlation with the absolute size of the sex difference is
negative (a higher score on the GGGI is associated with smaller sex differences).
Instead, all of the correlations between personality differences and the GGGI were
positive, which means they were all in the “wrong” direction and all were substantial:
+.33 for emotional stability, +.33 for openness, +.48 for conscientiousness, +.49 for
agreeableness, and +.53 for extraversion. The correlation between the GGGI and the
aggregate statistic D was 0.69. The size of D was much larger than the average value
of the effect sizes. Mean D was 0.89 compared to a mean for Cohen’s d of 0.24—
further evidence of how much difference aggregating conceptually related indicators
makes.34
The Falk study. Also in 2018, economists Armin Falk and Johannes Hermle
published their analysis of the Global Preferences Survey conducted in 2012. The
indicators were not of personality traits per se, but of six preferences that in turn are
consistent with personality traits. Four of these preferences were in the social domain:
altruism, trust, positive reciprocity (a preference for rewarding positive behaviors), and
negative reciprocity (a preference for punishing negative behaviors). Two were
nonsocial and had more direct implications for economic behavior: risk-taking and time
discounting (preference for a future larger reward than an immediate smaller reward).
The sex differences on the four social preferences were all on the side of People-
oriented personality traits: On average, women preferred altruism, trust, and positive
reciprocity more than men and were more averse to negative reciprocity than men. In
the two nonsocial preferences, men preferred risk-taking and waiting for a larger
reward more than women. The analysis employed representative samples from 76
countries.
All of the sex differences on these traits became larger as countries became more
economically developed and more egalitarian in their social policies. The correlations of
preferences with the authors’ Gender Equality Index were all in the wrong direction:
+.51 for altruism, +.41 for trust, +.13 for positive reciprocity, +.40 for negative
reciprocity, +.34 for risk-taking and +.43 for patience.35 Greater equality was
associated with larger sex differences. The authors did not report an aggregated effect
size. However, they did create an index incorporating all six preferences. The
correlation between the size of the sex difference on the combined index and the
Gender Equality Index was +.56. The correlation was even larger (+.67) for a measure
of national wealth, per capita GDP. Or as the authors put it, “These findings imply that
both economic development and gender equality exhibited an independent and
significant association with gender differences in preferences.”36
Five different studies, based on different measures of personality and national gender
egality, analyzing data from dozens of countries, all found the same pattern: overall
consistency in male-female differences in personality, but larger differences in the most
advanced countries.[37]
Explaining Wider Personality Differences in Advanced Countries
Why haven’t the sex differences in personality gotten smaller in countries that have
aggressively adopted gender-egalitarian policies? Why instead, and contrary to all
expectations, have they tended to widen?
Costa and his coauthors hypothesized that in traditional societies with strong sex
roles, people see behavioral sex differences as socially mandatory, not the result of
personal dispositions, whereas people in advanced societies are more likely to see them
as evidence of personal dispositions.38 Another possibility is that people tend to
compare themselves to others of their own sex in traditional cultures, whereas in
advanced cultures people compare themselves to the whole population. For example, a
woman in a traditional culture may rank herself on kindness relative to other women.
She may be of the opinion that women tend to be kinder than men, but that doesn’t
enter into her self-report. In an advanced culture, perhaps a woman compares her
kindness to others of both sexes, and a sex difference emerges.39
It should be pointed out that these hypotheses do not argue that the wider sex
differences in personality in the more egalitarian countries are illusions. They de facto
acknowledge the reality of the large differences in advanced countries; it’s just that the
differences are masked in countries with strong sex roles. But the Schmitt study argues
that in fact the hypotheses cannot be sustained in the face of the patterns in the data.
Instead, the authors introduced an important new empirical perspective to explain the
phenomenon of widening sex differences: Perhaps we’re looking at a general
phenomenon that goes far beyond personality traits. For example, the Schmitt study
points out, sexual dimorphism in height increases with a country’s wealth. So too with
sexual dimorphism in blood pressure. So too with competitiveness in sports—as
opportunities and incentives increase for women to compete in sports, sex differences
in performance increase as well. So too with differences between advantaged and
disadvantaged groups in health and education when new opportunities are made
available to all. Two years after the Schmitt study made these points, another study led
by Richard Lippa found that sexual dimorphism in visuospatial abilities also increased
with gender equality.40
Another surprise from the Schmitt study was its finding that men do most of the
changing, in both the physiological and personality traits. When sexual dimorphism in
height increases, for example, it is primarily due to greater height among males. In the
case of personality, the Schmitt study found that the wider sex gap in emotional
stability in advanced countries is not the result of women becoming less emotionally
stable, but of men self-reporting higher levels of emotional stability, and also lower
levels of agreeableness and conscientiousness, than men in less advanced countries.
Whatever the explanation turns out to be, the evidence about personality profiles
around the world needs to be taken on board by orthodox academics. In 2016, David
Schmitt and colleagues returned to the body of evidence that had accumulated since
the turn of the twenty-first century, summarizing it this way:
Psychological sex differences—in Big Five traits, Dark Triad traits, self-esteem,
subjective well-being, depression, and values—are demonstrably the largest in
cultures with the lowest levels of bifurcated gender role socialization or
sociopolitical patriarchy. Ultimately, the view that men and women start from a
blank slate simply does not jibe with the current findings, and scholars who
continue to assert gender invariably starts from a psychological blank slate
should find these recurring cross-cultural patterns challenging to their
foundational assumptions.41 [Emphasis in the original.]
The core message of this chapter is that the personality profiles of males and females
are different in ways that break along the People-Things dimension worldwide.
Many of the differences conform to stereotypes of masculine and feminine
characteristics, which in turn prompts me to remind you once again that we are talking
about overlapping distributions. Many males are closer to the female profile than are
many females, and vice versa. But neither is it appropriate to minimize those
differences. Sometimes the effect size for a single aspect of the personality inventories
is huge, as in the effect size of +2.29 for the “sensitive, aesthetic, sentimental” factor in
the 16PF standardization sample. Sometimes separate but conceptually related facets
point to a large aggregated difference even when such aggregates have not been
calculated, as in the case of the facets in the FFM that are related to the People-Things
dimension.
The traits that differ along the People-Things dimension are not shocking. The
technical studies tell us that women are, on average, warmer, more sympathetic, more
altruistic, and more sensitive to others’ feelings than men are. I suggest that these
technical findings are face-valid. They match up with common human experience.
Why do many of these differences apparently become more pronounced in the
most gender-egalitarian nations? I will not try to adjudicate among the explanations that
others have advanced, but I will disclose my own, admitting that it is completely ex
post facto: The deprivations of freedom that women still suffer in traditional societies
sometimes suppress the expression of inborn personality traits. For example, whatever
genetic tendencies toward extraversion that women in a strict Muslim culture may
have, they are under enormous cultural pressure to modify their expression of those
tendencies to meet cultural norms. Perhaps such conditions also warp the expression of
male personality. Under this hypothesis, genetically-grounded personality differences
widen in the most gender-egalitarian societies for the simplest of reasons: Both sexes
become freer to do what comes naturally.
3
As groups, men and women have different cognitive profiles. Those differences
manifest themselves many different ways, leaving us with a lot of ground to cover in
this chapter. I begin with summaries of the state of knowledge about a variety of
specific abilities, then turn to cross-national data, and conclude with two syntheses that
help tie the pieces together.
Specific Skills and Aptitudes
For some of these summaries, I make use of Diane Halpern’s fourth edition of Sex
Differences in Cognitive Abilities (2012).1 I do not try to interweave the dozens of
references Halpern cites, giving instead a single endnote at the outset with the pages for
her book. I add endnotes for material that she did not use or that postdate the fourth
edition.
On Average, Females Have Better Sensory Perception Than Males2
When it comes to the five senses—taste, touch, smell, sound, vision—the story is
mostly one of small female advantages.
Most of these differences have small individual effect sizes consistent with the
stereotype that “women are more sensitive than men,” For taste, touch, smell, and
sound, women are (on average) more sensitive instruments than men are. They are not
a lot more sensitive on any single sense, but somewhat more sensitive on all of them.
Even when it comes to vision, the male advantage in detecting movement is
counterbalanced by a greater male disadvantage in color blindness.6
Women are also more sensitive to pain than men. It’s not that women aren’t as
tough as men; rather, the neurological experience of pain is more intense for women.7
Evidence for greater female sensitivity to pain is found even in infancy.8 Another
aspect of this greater sensitivity is a pronounced sex difference in “disgust,” whether in
response to exposure to pathogens (e.g., reactions to seeing a rat or to an oozing
wound) or with regard to sexual activity that involves risk of disease or decreases
reproductive fitness (e.g., incest). Effect sizes for sexual disgust can be large, ranging
from +0.60 to +1.54.9
On Average, Females Have Better Perceptual and Fine Motor Skills Than Males10
Females have an advantage on certain perceptual-motor tasks. On digit-symbol coding,
for example, where each symbol corresponds to a number (e.g., “substitute 2 for #”),
women code faster than men do. Sometimes these differences involve large effect
sizes, with d = +0.86 in one major study.
Females have an even larger advantage in a variety of fine motor skills involving
hand-eye coordination. Evidence for this advantage goes back to infancy.11 Diane
Halpern observes dryly that while such tests of fine motor skills “are sometimes labeled
‘clerical skills tests’… I note here that fine motor skills are also needed in a variety of
other professions such as brain surgery, dentistry, and the repair of small engines.”12 In
tests of motor skills, it sometimes happens that men are faster but women are more
accurate.
On Average, Males Have Better Throwing Skills Than Females13
Men have a substantial advantage in many large motor skills, but few of them have
much to do with cognition. The major exception is males’ pronounced advantage on
tasks that involve throwing objects accurately at stationary or moving targets, because
that accuracy is highly dependent on visuospatial processing in the brain. Effect sizes
have sometimes exceeded 1.0 and persist when right-handed subjects are throwing with
their left hands.14
On Average, Females Have Better Memory on Several but Not All Types of
Memory15
Memory comes in many forms—long-term and short-term, “autobiographical,”
“episodic,” and “semantic,” among others. Here are the main themes of the research,
mostly drawn from Diane Halpern:
I’ve just given the first of dozens of ratios that are reported in the book. Unless I specify otherwise,
all the ratios I report are produced by dividing the male value by the female value, which means the
base for all the numbers is 1, as in, for example, 3.3:1. I omit the base and report the ratio as 3.3,
which is easier to read.
Females Probably Retain an Advantage at the Extreme High End of Verbal Ability
Before Puberty and Probably Lose It Subsequently
At the beginning of adolescence, girls still have some advantage at the extreme high end
of verbal ability, but it does not seem to persist through high school for American
students. These are provisional conclusions awaiting further evidence.
Gifted 7th graders. Since 1981, Duke University has sponsored the Duke
University Talent Identification Program (Duke TIP), which now operates in a 16-state
region of the South and Midwest. Students are invited to participate if they have
previously scored in the top five percentiles for their grade level on the composite score
of a standardized test or a relevant subtest (usually math or verbal). It attracts more
than 100,000 students a year, accumulating more than 2.8 million participants since
1980. Upon entering TIP, participants take either the SAT or the ACT. Because they
are taking college entrance tests designed for 17-year-olds, SAT scores obtained in their
seventh year of schooling discriminate levels of ability among students in fractions of
the top percentile.
The female advantage in the top percentile persisted to the highest levels of verbal
ability. For the top 0.01 percent in the SAT (the largest female advantage), there were
1.4 girls for every boy.[21]
Gifted students as of grade 12. I’m still talking about verbal ability as measured by
the SAT and ACT, but no longer about 13-year-olds. Rather, I refer to students who
take it at the normal time. They are self-selected for academic ability. Stated
conservatively, the test-taking populations for both the SAT and ACT are still
concentrated in the upper half of the ability distribution.[22]
For the test pools as a whole, the young women who take the SAT have
consistently had fractionally lower scores than the young men. The opposite is true of
the ACT—the females have fractionally higher scores. The note gives the details.[23]
Sex ratios in the top few percentiles. What goes on in the top few percentiles of
verbal skills for adolescents ages 17–18? The only source I have been able to find that
casts light on the answer is the SAT data broken down not only by gender but by score
intervals (the ACT does not publish such information). The SAT data are internally
consistent in showing that the female advantage disappeared in the verbal reasoning test
and was trivially small in the writing test at the top levels of ability, but it’s a single set
of test batteries. The pattern needs to be replicated in other large databases before
making much of it.
Sex Differences in Math Ability in the Normal Range Are Inconsistent and Small24
Now we turn to mathematics, which has gotten most of the attention in the debate
about sex differences in test scores. It’s one of the rare cases in which the data are
plentiful and the story doesn’t vary, at least within the United States:
Females get higher classroom grades than males in math at all K–12 grade levels—
but, for that matter, females get higher grades than males in just about everything
during the K–12 years. On standardized tests, sex differences in mean scores on
mathematics tests usually favor males, but the effect sizes are quite small for
representative samples of students. A meta-analysis of the NAEP mathematics test
from 1990 to 2011 found effect sizes of –0.07, –0.04, and –0.10 (favoring boys) in
grades 4, 8, and 12 respectively.25 In the most recent test for grades 4 and 8, 2017, the
effect sizes were –0.06 and –0.03 respectively. The most recent math test for grade 12
was in 2015, when the effect size was –0.09.26
Halpern’s review of meta-analyses of differences in math scores includes many
other standardized tests showing similarly small effect sizes. To the question, “Is the
typical male better at math than the typical female?” the answer is close to settled: “If
yes, not enough to be noticeable,” with an open possibility that a small gap will close
altogether.
Males Have a Persisting Advantage in Math at the Extreme High End
“Sex differences in mathematics become progressively larger as the sample becomes
more selective and the type of math skill becomes more advanced,” writes Halpern,
and herein lies a major issue in the study of cognitive sex differences.27 The literature
has been extensive and aroused contentious reactions, but the dust has settled (as much
as any dispute about sex differences is allowed to settle) on a few basic points.28 We
once again have two major sources of data: scores of 12–13-year-olds who are tested
in 7th grade using a college entrance exam (SAT or ACT), and for 17–18-year-olds
who are tested in their senior year.
Gifted 7th graders. The last 60 years have seen major reductions in the male
advantage at the extreme high end for 7th graders. For those in the top two percentiles,
a ratio of about 2.0 in 1960 appears to have disappeared. For those in the top
percentile, a male ratio of about 7.0 has fallen to around 1.5. At the most stratospheric
level, the top 1 percent of the top 1 percent, a male advantage that was measured at
about 13 to 1 in the 1970s and the early 1980s has fallen to less than 3 to 1.29 In short,
what was once thought to be an overwhelming male advantage at high levels of math
achievement has been greatly reduced during the last six decades. But a second
statement is also true: The male advantage for 7th graders at the highest levels of ability
shrank mostly during the 1980s and has been relatively stable since the early 1990s.30
Gifted 12th graders. For college-bound seniors taking the SAT math, the gap at a
broadly defined high end—treating the entire SAT pool as a moderately gifted group—
has narrowed since the 1970s. The effect size of the male advantage on the SAT was –
0.38 in 1977, its largest since the first published scores in 1972, and stood at –0.25 in
2016, its smallest ever.31 The shrinkage in the size of the male advantage was relatively
steady throughout the period.
A WORD ABOUT THE SAT
The letters SAT originally stood for Scholastic Aptitude Test, which signaled the test’s purpose: to
identify high-IQ students regardless of their family circumstances or the quality of their schooling.
The College Board has ignored that history since IQ became politically incorrect in the 1960s, but the
SAT remained a good measure of IQ for high school graduates into the 1990s. 32 Since the SAT does
not release the needed psychometric information, there’s no way to be sure, but I surmise that the
SAT lost a little of its quality as a measure of IQ in the revision in 1994, more in the revision in 2005,
and still more in the revision in 2016. I should add that the SAT is not culturally biased against ethnic
minorities or the poor and, at least until the revisions of 2005 and 2016, was far less susceptible to
coaching than most parents think.[33]
For the American Mathematics Competitions, the male-female ratio remains quite
high. Which ratio you think is closer to correct depends on your judgment about the
population of test-takers. From 2009 to 2018, the population of AMC12 test-takers
averaged 59 percent male and 41 percent female. Your opinion about the reason for the
sex imbalance in test-takers should push you toward one choice or the other.
One possibility is that students self-select into the AMC testing pool if they think
they’re good enough at math to do well on the test and otherwise don’t bother to take
it. To the extent that there is a genuine sex imbalance of talent in the top percentiles of
ability, then more males than females will self-select into the pool. If you are attracted
by this explanation, you should focus on the raw ratios as the correct ones.
Another possibility is that the larger proportion of male test-takers is an artifact
having nothing to do with underlying math talent. Taking the AMC is exceptionally
nerdy. Perhaps that’s more off-putting to 17-year-old girls than to 17-year-old boys.
Perhaps there is a difference (whether biological or socialized doesn’t matter) in how
much boys and girls enjoy the kind of competition that the AMC represents. If you are
attracted by this explanation, you should focus on the adjusted ratios as the correct
ones.
I won’t try to spin out all the many ways in which the meaning of the ratios is
clouded by selection factors. Whichever ratio you think is closer to the truth, they point
to an empirical reality: The male-female ratios in the top percentiles of the AMC12 are
substantial and they grow larger at the 98th and especially the 99th percentile. In the
table, I counted perfect scores of 150 as being in the 99th percentile. When they are
broken out separately, it turns out that from 2009 to 2018, 97 males and 7 females got
perfect scores: a ratio of 13.9.
On Average, Males Have Substantially Better Visuospatial Skills Than Females36
Diane Halpern’s review of sex differences in visuospatial skills takes 17 pages. It is so
long partly because the concept is complicated (she divides visuospatial skills into five
components) and partly because, in her words, “sex differences in spatial tasks are
among the largest sex differences.”37 But another good reason for a lengthy discussion
is that a male advantage in visuospatial skills has specific implications for real-world sex
differences in vocations. In the Paleolithic period, they were useful for throwing spears
at edible mammals and finding one’s way back home after a long hunting trip. Now
they are useful because they seem to be an essential component of extraordinary
mathematical and programming skills. Other professions that make extensive use of
visuospatial abilities include engineering, architecture, chemistry, aviation, and the
building trades.
The first category of spatial aptitude is spatial perception. An example is the Piaget
water-level task:
The test-taker is asked to draw a line to show how the water line would look in the
tilted bottle. The correct answer is a horizontal line relative to the earth. Halpern
reports that the best estimate, summarizing results over many studies, is that about 40
percent of college women get it wrong.38 Effect sizes favoring males range from –0.44
to –0.66. In Halpern’s words, “It is difficult to understand why this should be such a
formidable task for college women.”39 And yet the result has been replicated many
times, has been confirmed internationally, and is just about impossible to explain as a
product of culture or socialization (if you doubt that, give it a try).40
“Mental rotation” refers to the ability to imagine how objects will look when rotated
in two-or three-dimensional space. Twenty-five years of research and several meta-
analyses have all confirmed a substantial male advantage throughout the age range,
with effect sizes ranging from –0.52 to –1.49.
Spatiotemporal ability is another conceptually distinct form of visuospatial skill that
calls for judgments about moving objects. For example, the subject of the test might be
asked to press a key when a moving object passes a specified point or asked to make
an estimate of “time of arrival” of a moving object at a specified destination. Effect
sizes have ranged from –0.37 to –0.93.41 In a large sample, with a carefully executed
experimental design, effect sizes ranged from –0.51 to –0.81.42
The fourth type of visuospatial skill calls upon participants to generate a visual
image from short-term or long-term memory and then use information in that image to
perform a task. The tests usually are scored for both speed and accuracy. In one of the
best studies, the effect sizes on speed for four different tasks ranged from –0.63 to –
0.77, all favoring males, with no sex differences in accuracy.[43]
The last type of visuospatial skill is called spatial visualization, which calls on
people to go through a multistep mental process to understand how an object will be
changed if something is done to it. For example, the paper-folding test asks: If you fold
a piece of paper in half and punch three holes through it, what will the piece of paper
look like when it is unfolded? Males usually show an advantage on spatial visualization,
but the effect sizes are generally small.
Halpern describes other types of visuospatial skills, all of which show a male
advantage.[44] An important outstanding question is how large the aggregate difference
in visuospatial skills might be. Many of the effect sizes for sex differences in
visuospatial skills are large even when taken individually. But given the parallel with
personality facets—conceptually related but distinct traits—a calculation of
Mahalanobis D for large samples of males and females who have taken a
comprehensive test battery would be instructive. Perhaps many of the different types
of skills are so intercorrelated that aggregating them would not add much to the largest
individual effect size. It is a question that I hope will be explored.
On Average, Women Have Better Social Cognition Than Men
We take for granted that we can infer what someone else is thinking, but this inference
is actually a theory—“theory of mind,” often abbreviated as ToM in the literature. It
refers to our belief that other people have minds of their own that operate in ways we
can understand. It is properly called a theory because the only mind we have direct
access to is our own and because we can make predictions based on our theory.[45]
Children acquire ToM as toddlers. As normal people mature, they employ ToM to
navigate the social world in increasingly complex ways. But not everybody has a
normal human consciousness. The severely autistic have trouble with ToM—one of
the features of autism that inspired Baron-Cohen’s empathizer-systemizer theory. Even
within the normal range, people vary widely in their ability to project themselves into
another person’s mind and correctly predict how that person will react. These are skills
that are encompassed by Howard Gardner’s interpersonal intelligence and that other
scholars refer to as cognitive empathy, mentalizing, mindreading, or the label I have
chosen to use, social cognition. In terms of Simon Baron-Cohen’s empathizing and
systemizing, social cognition is to empathizing as visuospatial skills are to systemizing.
In both cases, the topic is neurocognitive abilities that contribute to a broad difference
between the sexes.
The study of social cognition originated in one of the most durable sex stereotypes,
that women are more intuitive than men. Through the early 1970s, researchers were
dismissive of evidence that a sex difference existed. As late as 1974, the most
comprehensive review of sex differences yet undertaken concluded that “neither sex
has greater ability to judge the reactions and intentions of others in any generalized
sense.”46 Then in 1978, psychologist Judith Hall produced the first comprehensive
study of all the quantitative work that had been done. In “Gender Effects in Decoding
Nonverbal Cues,” published in Psychological Bulletin in 1978, Hall reported mean
effect sizes favoring females of +0.32 for visual cues, +0.18 for auditory cues, and a
large effect of +1.02 for the seven studies that combined visual and auditory cues.47
Six years later, Hall extended her meta-analysis to include nine countries around the
world. Subsequent work has yielded similar results.48
In 2014, psychologists Ashley Thompson and Daniel Voyer undertook a new meta-
analysis. Hall’s reviews had included studies of accuracy in interpersonal perception of
any kind. Thompson and Voyer focused on the ability to detect specific discrete
emotions. As in other studies, the results showed a female advantage, but with a
smaller effect size that had a lower bound effect size of +0.19 and an upper bound of
+0.27.49
The Thompson meta-analysis also corroborated Hall’s findings that effect sizes are
substantially increased when the subjects in the studies have access to a combination of
visual and audio information—that is, when they could see both face and body
language and also hear tone of voice. The lower bound effect sizes favoring women
were +0.17 for visual only, +0.16 for audio only, and +0.38 for a combination of the
two.[50]
The publication of Daniel Goleman’s bestselling Emotional Intelligence: Why It
Can Matter More than IQ in 1995 prompted the construction of tests to measure
emotional intelligence (EI). The most psychometrically successful and widely used one
has been the Mayer-Salovey-Caruso Emotional Intelligence Test (MSCEIT). Version 2
has eight subscales measuring four aspects of EI: perceiving emotion, assimilating
emotion in thought, understanding emotion, and reflectively regulating emotion. Of
these, the items that most directly measure social cognition as I have been using the
term are in the subtests for perceiving emotion. A 2010 meta-analysis found an effect
size favoring females of +0.49. On the overall score for performance EI, the female
advantage was +0.47.51
I will return to other evidence of sex differences in social cognition in chapter 5,
reporting the progress that neuroscientists have made in identifying sex differences in
brain function that relate to sex differences in social cognition. In the meantime, two
points about differences in social cognition need emphasis:
Social cognition consists of a set of abilities, not something that women do better
than men just because they are paying more attention to other people than men do.52
Those abilities often break along the People-Things dimension. For example, it has
been found that systemizing skills and empathizing skills are inversely related in men—
men who scored high on tests measuring systemizing tended to score low on tests
measuring empathizing. Males are rarely good at both systemizing and empathizing. In
contrast, these skill sets are largely independent in women. Women can be high in both,
low in both, or high in one and low in the other.53 The same study found evidence that
men apply systemizing skills to empathizing tasks. Put another way, even when men do
well in social cognition tasks, they are not using the cognitive tools most naturally
suited to that purpose.
It has also been established that the relationship of IQ to social cognition is different
for men and women. Subtests measuring memory are standard in a full-scale IQ test.
They wouldn’t be included if they did not correlate with the other subtests seeking to
measure g. But the correlation between IQ and certain kinds of memory is different for
men and women. In a Swedish study comparing IQ with three episodic memory tasks,
women outperformed men in all three—verbal memory, memory for pictures of things,
and memory for pictures of faces. The difference was that male performance was
substantially correlated with IQ for all three tasks while IQ was substantially less
important, especially at the lower levels, for women. Women with IQs of 60–80 had
verbal memory as high as men with IQs of 101–120. Women with IQs of 60–80 had
substantially higher scores on memory for faces than men with IQs of 101–120.54
Something’s going on with memory in females that calls on non-IQ skills that men do
not tap (or perhaps possess) to the same degree.
The aggregate sex difference in social cognition has yet to be estimated. Four
different clusters of sex differences are relevant to assessing the overall magnitude of
the sex difference in social cognition. The first consists of the direct measures that I
have reviewed in this section. The second consists of the female advantage in memory
for faces, which in turn is presumably related to the ability to discern visual clues about
emotional states. The third is the cluster of ways in which the female sensory apparatus
is more sensitive than the male’s. The fourth cluster has to do with male-female
differences in personality that bear on the reasoning aspect of social cognition.55 In the
technical literature, the effect sizes in all four of these categories have been treated
separately. The prudent expectation is that if these individual effect sizes, which have
usually been in the small to medium range, were aggregated appropriately, they would
reveal a much larger overall difference.
Is There a Sex Difference in g?
The most famous cognitive measure is the IQ test. The tests are designed to minimize
sex differences,[56] but minor sex differences in test scores do exist, and they have
usually, though not always, favored males.[57] The Wechsler Adult Intelligence Scale
(WAIS), one of the best-known IQ tests, provides a typical example. The U.S.
standardization samples for the first version, released in 1955, showed a 1.0-point
difference in full-scale IQ favoring males. WAIS-R, released in 1981, showed a 2.2-
point difference. WAIS-III, released in 1997, showed a 2.7-point difference. WAIS-IV,
released in 2008, showed a 2.3-point difference.58
But all of this evidence is based on IQ scores, not on the general mental factor g,
the thing that IQ tests are imperfectly measuring. The distinction between an IQ score
and g is crucial. An IQ score is based on a set of subtests. The simple sum or average
of scores depends on which tests have more representation in the test battery;
therefore, as Arthur Jensen wrote, “the simple sum or mean of various subtest scores is
a datum without scientific interest or generality.”59 The question of scientific interest
regarding a sex difference in intelligence is whether there is a sex difference on g.
Jensen’s conclusion after assessing g in five major test batteries—the WAIS, the
Wechsler Intelligence Scale for Children-Revised (WISC-R), the General Aptitude Test
Battery (GATB), the Armed Services Vocational Aptitude Battery (ASVAB), and the
British Ability Scales (BAS)—was that “the sex difference in psychometric g is either
totally nonexistent or is of uncertain direction and of inconsequential magnitude.”60
Jensen made this pronouncement in his magnum opus, The g Factor, published in
1998. The list of eminent scholars who have shared that view began with Cyril Burt
and Lewis Terman in the early part of the twentieth century and continued through the
rest of the century and into the twenty-first century with figures such as Raymond
Cattell, Nathan Brody, Hans Eysenck, John Loehlin, David Geary, Diane Halpern,
Thomas Bouchard, David Lubinski, and Camilla Benbow. I should add that Richard
Herrnstein and I took the same position in The Bell Curve.
This does not mean that everyone accepts that the question has been settled. A
lively and sometimes acrimonious debate has been ongoing in recent years that you
may follow by checking the sources in the note.[61] It is still technically unsettled. My
own sense—and it’s no more than that, from someone who is knowledgeable about IQ
but not expert in the abstruse technical issues that are being disputed—is that the
possibility of a trivial sex difference in g is still in play but the demonstration of a
meaningful one is not.
Do Sex Differences in Abilities Diminish in Countries with Greater Gender
Egality?
The question has different answers for academic abilities and measures of visuospatial
skills.
Academic Abilities
PISA test results from the early 2000s gave reason to believe that greater gender egality
had a meaningful relationship with academic test scores, but data since then have made
that case increasingly tough to make.62 The emerging story is both more complicated
and more interesting. It appears that all of the following are likely to be true:
Worldwide, overall sex differences in performance on math and science tests in
the normal range are trivially small. The 2015 PISA survey included 67 countries.
The overall mean effect size on the math test was –0.05—a tiny difference favoring
boys.[63] The overall mean effect size on the science test was +0.01—no difference.
The TIMSS survey of 2011 included 45 countries. The overall mean effect size on the
math test was +0.04—a tiny difference favoring girls. The overall mean effect size on
the science test was +0.05—a tiny difference again favoring girls.
The differences that do appear in some individual countries have a weak and
inconsistent relationship with gender egality. Some analyses of the PISA and TIMSS
survey in the early 2000s found a negative correlation between the size of the sex
difference in mathematics and the indexes of gender equality in the culture.64 When
Gijsbert Stoet and David Geary analyzed all four PISA administrations from 2000 to
2009, they concluded that the patterns in the early 2000s were not sustained:
The results of the most recent administrations of the PISA and TIMSS tests are
consistent with that finding.
When the standardized scores for the Gender Development Index (GDI), Gender
Inequality Index (GII), and Global Gap Index (GGI) are combined, the biggest effect
sizes favoring boys in math were Honduras, Austria, and Ghana. In science, they were
again Ghana and Honduras, plus Costa Rica. It’s hard to make much of that pattern
with regard to gender egality in political and social institutions. But it’s even harder
when you consider the biggest effect sizes favoring girls: Oman, Bahrain, and Jordan
for math; Jordan, Albania, and the United Arab Emirates for science—not countries
known for their enlightened gender policies. Taking the data from the last two decades
as a whole, cross-national academic test scores show no significant relationship to
measures of gender egality. Details are in the note.[66]
The most plausible explanation for the substantial effect sizes in math and science
that appear in some individual countries is cultural, not biological. Why should some
Arab countries that are notorious for legal and cultural discrimination against women
produce female high school students who perform better in math than their privileged
male classmates while nothing approaching the same gap favoring females is found
elsewhere, either in countries with high gender egality or in non-Arab countries with
low gender egality? It looks as if something about Arab socialization of children either
depresses male incentives to do well in math and science or increases female incentives
to do well in math and science.
The most plausible explanation for the consistent female advantage in verbal tests is
biological, not cultural. The story for reading achievement in the PISA test echoes the
consistent female advantage found in U.S. tests of verbal skills. Girls outscored boys in
reading in every single PISA country, with effect sizes that ranged from a low of +0.08
in Peru to a remarkable high of +0.83 in Jordan. Nor was Jordan alone among nations
with bad records on gender egality but large effect sizes favoring girl students. Other
nations in the bottom half of the gender egality index but with effect sizes of +0.40 or
higher were Algeria, the United Arab Emirates, Qatar, and Georgia. The mean effect
size across all 67 PISA nations was +0.32. The correlation of the effect size with the
egality index was –.11.67
It is difficult to reconcile the universal advantage of women in verbal tests with
socialization or social role theories, neither of which has ever appealed to the idea that
the oppression of women can enhance their cognitive ability. All the social-construct
argumentation is based on the proposition that discrimination has suppressed female
accomplishment. Nor can the argument be easily shifted by arguing that social roles
encourage women to be more social and verbal, which is then reflected in superior
verbal skills. The verbal test in PISA is not about sociability. It measures a cognitive
ability to assimilate and analyze language that is as cognitively demanding as
mathematics is in the nonverbal domain. There is no evidence that underlying verbal
ability can be taught, either deliberately or through socialization. The parsimonious
explanation for the international female advantage in verbal tests, across cultures that
cover the full range from openly oppressive to aggressively gender-equal, is that
women have a genetic advantage.
Measures of Visuospatial Skills
Some evidence indicates that sex differences in visuospatial skills are greater in
countries with greater gender egality. In 2005, the BBC conducted an Internet survey
of sex differences that included tests of mental rotation and line-angle judgment. Total
sample sizes were 90,433 and 95,364 respectively, with sample sizes large enough to
reliably explore sex differences for 53 countries. An analysis (first author was Richard
Lippa) found, “Sex differences in mental rotation and line angle judgment performance
were universally present across nations, with men’s mean scores always exceeding
women’s mean scores.”68 The mean national effect size was –0.47 for the mental
rotation task and –0.49 for the line-angle judgment task, both favoring men and
statistically significant at p < .001.69
“STATISTICALLY SIGNIFICANT AT P < .001”
The Lippa study then calculated the correlations between national effect sizes of
sex differences and four measures of national development: the UN Gender
Development Index, UN Gender Empowerment Index, per capita income, and life
expectancy. For all of these measures, “high” equals “good” (more gender egalitarian or
economically developed), so, according to social-construct theories, the correlations
with the size of the gender difference should be negative (the effect sizes should be
smaller for more egalitarian or developed societies). The table below shows the
correlation coefficients from the Lippa study after controlling for age and education.
The more advanced the country, the wider the sex differences in both visuospatial
tasks. The relationship was stronger on the line-angle judgment task—all four indices
were significantly correlated with the effect size, at the p < .01 level or better for three
of the four. For the mental rotation task, the correlations were significant at the p < .01
level for both the UN Gender Development Index and life expectancy. But the main
point of the table is that not a single correlation, large or small, is negative—a finding
directly at odds with expectations of the social-construct logic.
Why should these differences in visuospatial skills be wider in more developed
countries? Lippa offers potential explanations based on the greater effects of stereotype
threat in advanced countries and evolutionary theories that posit greater sensitivity of
males to environmental challenges, but these remain only hypotheses.70 Nobody
knows.
Recapitulation (and Integration)
I have bombarded you with a great many numbers about a great many different kinds
of male and female differences in neurocognitive functioning. Two integrative analyses,
conducted by leading scholars in their respective fields, help to see the broader picture.
Patterns on a Broad Neurocognitive Battery
First, consider the profiles of neurocognitive functioning found in a major recent study
of neurocognitive sex differences in children and young adults. It was led by
psychologists Ruben and Raquel Gur. They examined the largest and best-documented
sample of its kind, the Philadelphia Neurodevelopmental Cohort (PNC). It consists of
9,122 persons ages 8 to 21, divided between 4,405 males and 4,717 females.
The participants were administered the Computerized Neurocognitive Battery
(CNB). A neurocognitive battery of tests is not the same as an IQ test battery that is
being used to measure different aspects of g. Rather, neurocognitive refers to bits and
pieces of the way a person’s brain works, focusing on ones that can be linked to the
functioning of specific brain systems. The most common categories covered by the
major tests of neurocognitive functioning include executive function (such things as
mental flexibility, planning, and strategic decisions), memory, complex cognition (verbal
and visuospatial facility), social/emotional cognition, and sensorimotor function. A
neurocognitive battery commonly contains at least 10 subtests, and some contain a few
dozen.
The battery administered to the Philadelphia Neurodevelopmental Cohort consists
of 14 subtests designed to measure executive function, episodic memory, complex
cognition, social cognition, and sensorimotor and motor function. Twelve of the
subtests have two measures: the accuracy and speed of the participant’s performance.
The other two measure only the speed of motor and sensorimotor function. In all, the
test yielded 26 male-female comparisons. Twelve of them amounted to an absolute
effect size of less than 0.1. Women outscored men on six of the seven measures of
accuracy with an effect size greater than 0.1, and they outscored men on four of the
seven measures of speed with an effect size greater than 0.1.71 The highlights are
similar to findings you have already encountered:
Females had more accurate memory for items involving words and people.
On IQ-like items, women did better on the verbal ones; men did better on the
spatial ones.
On the three subtests measuring social cognition, females were both more
accurate and faster than males on all of them.
On the subtest measuring motor speed, males were faster than females.
The authors describe another pattern that did not involve specific subtests, but
rather an overall construct called within-individual variability (WIV), referring to the
evenness or unevenness of performance on the test battery. A participant with high
scores on some subtests and low ones on others has high WIV; a participant who is
near the same point on the distribution on all the tests has low WIV. In the technical
literature, high WIV is associated with cognitive specialization, while people with low
WIV are considered to be cognitive generalists.72 Males in the Philadelphia
Neurodevelopmental Cohort had higher WIV than females on both speed and accuracy
for almost all ages from 8 to 21, and the difference was most pronounced in the oldest
participants.73
The magnitude of the effect sizes ranged from small to medium. Given such large
sample sizes, all but two of the differences were statistically significant. Ruben and
Raquel Gur summarized their findings this way. The full citations for the references
they mention are included in the note:
We will get to the “sex differences in laterality” reference in chapter 5. For now, the
Gurs’ summary is a concise way of expressing the pattern of differences that the
individual sections of this chapter have described.
Male and Female Differences in Cognitive Toolboxes
Even when men and women get the same answers to their cognitive tasks, they often
get there by different routes. For example, people with high verbal skills often get the
right answer to mathematics problems, but by using verbal forms of logic rather than
mathematical symbols or spatial reasoning. Another well-documented example is how
people navigate from point A to point B. Women tend to identify and remember
landmarks—a strategy that taps into the female advantage in memory. Men tend to
construct a mental map of the route—a strategy that taps into the male advantage in
visuospatial skills.75 Both methods work equally well for a wide variety of navigation
tasks.76 People are just using different sets of tools to get the job done.
In the early 2000s, Wendy Johnson and Thomas Bouchard, senior psychologists at
the famed Minnesota Institute for the Study of Twins Raised Apart (MISTRA),
decided to extend the metaphor of cognitive tools.77 Using an analogy, they
hypothesized that everyone has an “intellectual toolbox,” but no two are exactly alike.
They are stocked with varying tools that people use with different frequencies,
different degrees of skill, and in different ways, and there are systematic toolbox
differences between men and women. On average, men and women can accomplish
most intellectual tasks equally well with their different choices and uses of tools. Hence
the similarity in overall g. “But some tasks can be accomplished much better with
certain tools than with others,” Johnson and Bouchard write, “and individual
performance on these tasks depends not only on skill in tool use, but also to some
degree on individual toolbox composition.… The analogy is incomplete, of course, but
it makes clear the question we address in this paper, namely, what are the differences
in specific tool use (mental abilities) of men and women when overall skill in tool
choice and use (g) is removed?”78
Johnson and Bouchard used the MISTRA sample, consisting of adult twins raised
apart along with many of their spouses, partners, adoptive and biological family
members, and friends. The sample was not representative, but its members came from
a wide range of backgrounds, and the researchers had extraordinarily thorough
information about them. All of them had gone through at least one weeklong
assessment of medical and physical traits plus psychological tests of cognitive abilities,
personality, interests, and attitudes.
Johnson and Bouchard used sophisticated quantitative methods. Describing them
would take us far afield (it was a combination of factor analysis and regression
analysis), but the result is simple enough to understand.
Imagine a man and woman with equal general intelligence (g). The woman uses her
elevated verbal skills to help her solve math problems while the man uses his elevated
visuospatial skills to help solve him math problems. They take two math tests. One
consists entirely of problems expressed in mathematical notation. The other consists of
math problems expressed in words. They both get most of the items right on both tests
—g goes a long way toward enabling people to solve math problems no matter what
their special skills might be. But the woman gets a slightly higher score than the man on
the word-problem test while the man gets a slightly higher score on the one using
mathematical notation. The net result is no sex difference. But actually there was a
difference in tools that the man and woman used. What Johnson and Bouchard did
was to strip away the role played by g and let us see the differences in tools. A more
precise description is given in the note.[79]
The Johnson study presented the results for all 42 tests, but calculated effect sizes
only for those that met a stricter than normal standard of statistical significance (p < .01
instead of p < .05) because of the large number of tests involved. Results for the
residual effects on 21 of the subtests that met that statistical standard are shown in the
following table. I omit the p values. All but two of the p values for the residual effects
were at the .001 level.80 The effect sizes stripped of g are ordered from the largest for
females (positive) to the largest for males (negative).
Assessment activity: Production of words beginning and ending with specified letters
Overall effect size: ns
Effect size stripped of g: +0.57
First, look at the column showing the overall effect size, calculated the same way
as all the other effect sizes you have seen. Among the effect sizes that were statistically
significant, four were “small” by the Cohen guidelines, eight were “medium,” one was
“large,” and one was “very large.” We can safely assume that most of those that did
not meet the p < .01 standard of statistical significance fell in the “small” range.
Now look at the right-hand column, showing the difference between males and
females on these subtests when the role of g has been extracted. As Johnson and
Bouchard anticipated, all of these effect sizes are larger than the overall effect size.
Furthermore, only one qualifies as “small” while 13 are “medium,” five are “large,”
and two are “very large.” (As you might predict, I think that if these conceptually
related effect sizes were aggregated, the value of Mahalonobis D would be huge.)
Johnson and Bouchard’s work tells us how much that apparent similarity in overall g is
illusory: End points are similar, but ways of getting to them are different. Hence the
title of their article: “Sex Differences in Mental Abilities: g Masks the Dimensions on
Which They Lie.”
Linking Sex Differences in Neurocognitive Functioning with the People-Things
Dimension
People generally enjoy the things they’re good at. They also like the experience of
being good at what they do—a fundamental truth about the nature of human
enjoyment that goes back to Aristotle. The sex differences in neurocognitive
functioning point to a tendency for men and women to enjoy different kinds of
activities. When I discussed visuospatial skills, I listed some of the vocations that, to
attain excellence, require high visuospatial skills—math, programming, engineering,
architecture, chemistry, the building trades. They’re all Things occupations. Excellence
in verbal skills almost by definition requires one to be able to engage with other people.
This is self-evidently true in occupations that require steady interaction with other
people—teaching, patient-oriented medicine, and helping professions of all kinds.
They’re all People occupations.
These days, everyone who has been paying attention knows that the Things and
People occupations I just listed are notorious for being disproportionately male and
female respectively. You can guess what’s coming next.
4
The third component of cognitive repertoires is social behavior, but there’s no point in
cataloging all the ways in which men and women differ in social behavior. They go
from the obvious and extreme (e.g., men commit the overwhelming majority of violent
crimes) to the obvious and everyday (e.g., women perform the overwhelming majority
of child-rearing tasks).1 I devote this chapter to an extended look at the People-Things
thesis regarding education and vocation. More than a century after legal restrictions on
women’s vocations were lifted and half a century since gender discrimination in hiring,
promoting, and firing was outlawed, large disparities continue in the university
educations that young men and women attain, the jobs they take, and how their careers
unfold. What to do about this is a major policy debate. Here, I lay out some reasons
for thinking that the persistence of these observable sex differences constitutes strong
circumstantial evidence for underlying biological causes.
The Women of SMPY
From January 2012 to February 2013, a team of Vanderbilt psychologists surveyed 322
men and 157 women in their late 40s about their work preferences and life values. The
men and women differed on many of their views. Limiting the list to ones with an
absolute effect size of 0.35 or higher, here were the things that men valued more or
agreed with more than women did.2 The effect sizes are shown in parentheses:
“The prospect of receiving criticism from others does not inhibit me from
expressing my thoughts.” (–0.54)
A merit-based pay system (–0.53)
Having a full-time career (–0.51)
Inventing or creating something that will have an impact (–0.45)
A salary that is well above the average person’s (–0.43)
“I believe that society should invest in my ideas because they are more
important than those of other people in my discipline.” (–0.42)
Being able to take risks on my job (–0.41)
Working with things (e.g., computers, tools, machines) as part of my job (–
0.41)
“The possibility of discomforting others does not deter me from stating the
facts.” (–0.40)
Having lots of money (–0.36)
Stereotypical men.
Meanwhile, here were the things that the women in the sample valued more than
the men did, again limiting the list to ones where the absolute effect size was 0.35 or
higher:3
Stereotypical women.
Why have I presented such predictable results? Because this chapter is about sex
differences in educational and vocational choices, and this particular sample lets me put
issues of sex differences in abilities aside. Every one of those middle-aged men and
women had an IQ of about 140 or higher.5 They were part of the Study of
Mathematically Precocious Youth—SMPY.
The Unique Advantages of the SMPY Samples
The results I just presented came from members of SMPY’s Cohort 2, born in 1964–
67, who at age 13 had tested in the top 0.5 percent of overall intellectual ability: the top
1 in 200. All of them were also in the top percentile specifically in math skills.6 All of
the respondents were intellectually qualified to have pursued any undergraduate major
they preferred and any cognitively demanding career.7
The SMPY sample has other advantages. Every girl in the sample knew she was
extremely talented in math by the time she entered her teens. Her mathematical talent
was part of her self-image from an early age.
SMPY
Johns Hopkins psychologist Julian Stanley began SMPY in 1971. He recruited large numbers of 12-
year-olds to take the SAT math test. The SAT is designed for high school juniors and seniors bound
for college. By administering it to 12-and 13-year-olds who had not yet taken high school math
courses, Stanley was able to identify students with exceptionally high aptitude for math. Over the
years, SMPY established four cohorts of mathematically precocious youth who became part of a
longitudinal study that continues as I write, jointly directed since 1991 by Camilla Benbow and David
Lubinski.[8] I focus on the results from the 35-year and 40-year follow-ups for Cohort 2 with some
supplemental findings regarding Cohort 3.
Virtually all of the parents of these girls were extremely supportive of their
daughters’ talent. SMPY parents responded positively to their child’s invitation to seek
admission to the program and then were willing to go through the time and effort to get
their child to the testing site, which often meant a significant journey. Apart from these
indicators, we also have the results of a study of the SMPY parents in that era. The
study found that “(a) parents were treating their children differently based not on their
child’s gender but apparently rather as a function of their child’s talent; (b) fathers did
not appear to be more involved with the mathematically talented students than with the
verbally talented; and (c) the majority of students, especially females, were not strongly
sex typed.”9
Despite their parents’ support, it might be argued that the girls who entered
SMPY’s Cohort 2 were still socialized to traditional pre-feminist norms. The modern
feminist movement was in its first decade when they were born in the mid-1960s. It
should be assumed that as little girls the SMPY women had gotten a full dose of
socialization to female roles in a country that was still traditional on matters regarding
gender roles.
If the girls who entered SMPY had typically come from small towns or from
middle-class suburban neighborhoods in the Midwest or South, that argument would
have merit. But instead they came from highly educated, upper-middle-class families
located in the Washington, Baltimore, and Philadelphia areas. By the early 1970s, these
families and neighborhoods were probably more explicitly and emphatically feminist
than comparable neighborhoods today. It may be hard for readers not old enough to
remember for themselves how long—50 years now—the upper-middle-class milieu has
been overwhelmingly feminist, so perhaps a few reminders are in order.
First, consider the timeline of legal reforms:
The girls of Cohort 2 were born into a world in which legal equality had been
established, but in some respects that was the least of it. Even by the time they were in
elementary school, the list of legal victories had been accompanied by a cultural sea
change that began in the 1960s and was at its height during the 1970s and early 1980s.
In the upper-middle-class schools and neighborhoods where most of the SMPY girls
grew up, courses in elementary school were filled with inspirational stories about
women scientists, political leaders, artists, and authors. High schools were putting boys
and girls in the same gym classes, and high school counselors were urging female
students to go into male-dominated careers. On campuses, young women were hearing
faculty and their fellow students urging them to forgo marriage and childbearing in
favor of a career. Gloria Steinem’s famous slogan “A woman needs a man like a fish
needs a bicycle” comes from the early 1970s, epitomizing a celebration of women that
found cultural expression in films, popular music, and television.10 When the girls of
Cohort 2 reached college age in 1982–85, they all knew that the most famous
universities in the nation were eager to add them to their student bodies and even more
eager for them to populate their majors in science, technology, engineering, and math,
familiarly known as STEM.
That’s the female sample we are able to follow through almost 50 years of their
lives: extraordinarily talented women who knew they were talented from an early age,
were urged to enter STEM fields, and were often urged not to let children and family
dictate their lives. Yet they reached their late 40s with a profile of stereotypical sex
differences in career and life priorities. What had they been doing in the meantime?
Even Among the Gifted, People Tend to Like Doing What They Do Best
Educationally, males and females in Cohort 2 were in a dead heat, with nearly the same
high proportions getting bachelor’s, master’s, and doctoral degrees.11 Yet the traditional
gender gap in STEM majors persisted. The SMPY women were about twice as likely
to take STEM majors as the general population of female undergraduates,12 but this
was true of the men also, and so the male-female ratio in STEM degrees among the
SMPY sample (1.6) was fractionally higher than the ratio in the general undergraduate
population (1.5).13 Meanwhile, twice as many of these gifted young women were
getting degrees in the social sciences, business, and the humanities as were the gifted
young men.14
Why the persistence of the tilt of men toward STEM and women toward the social
sciences and the humanities? The special nature of the SMPY sample enables a test of
this proposition: It doesn’t make any difference how extremely talented you are in one
field; you tend to gravitate toward the field in which you are the most talented.15 Even
though everyone in Cohort 2 was gifted in math skills, those whose verbal skills were
even higher than their math skills tended to end up in the social sciences, humanities,
business, and law, while those whose math skills were greater than their verbal skills
tended to end up in STEM fields. This pattern was true for both males and females.16
Much of the theoretical literature assumes that this tendency is driven by students’
and their parents’ knowledge of grades and test scores—that the numbers tell them
they are better at math than verbal or vice versa.17 But there is good reason to think
that the impulse runs deeper than conscious knowledge. This finding emerged first
from Project Talent, a 1960 study based on a nationally representative sample (total
sample size was about 400,000) of American high school students whose participants
were given tests of visuospatial skill to accompany their scores on verbal and
mathematics tests. Visuospatial skill is not ordinarily something that schools test or that
students think about. And yet it turned out that such skills played an important
independent role in shaping the students’ academic and vocational choices, strongly
reinforcing a tendency for students to go into STEM majors if those skills were high
and depressing the likelihood of going into STEM majors if they were low.18
Was the same true of students who were gifted in both math and verbal skills?
Members of SMPY Cohort 2 completed two visuospatial subtests of the Differential
Aptitude Tests.19 The results mirrored those from Project Talent. The students’
visuospatial skills interacted with their verbal and math scores, with high skills pushing
them toward STEM and low scores pushing them toward the humanities or social
science majors.20
What I’ve just reported applied to Cohort 2, who were in the top 0.5 percent in
intellectual ability. Surely (or so it would intuitively seem), this phenomenon has to fade
at some level of ability when it doesn’t make any difference which skill set is higher—
even your “weaker” skill is fabulously high. But apparently not, or so SMPY’s Cohort
3 seems to tell us.
SMPY’s Cohort 3 is the largest database of profoundly gifted persons ever
assembled for systematic longitudinal research: 253 males and 67 females who as 12-
year-olds were in the top 0.01 percent of intellectual ability, with an estimated mean IQ
of 186.21 The top 1 in 10,000. The phenomenon they had identified in Cohort 2—even
highly gifted people gravitate to the fields where they have the greatest comparative
advantage—also applied to Cohort 3. Among those whose SAT math scores were at
least a standard deviation above their SAT verbal scores (the “high-math” group”), 69
percent had an undergraduate major in math or an inorganic science, compared to 29
percent of those whose SAT verbal scores were at least a standard deviation above
their SAT math scores (the “high-verbal” group). Forty-two percent of the high-verbal
group had undergraduate degrees in the humanities or arts, compared to 23 percent of
the high-math group.22 The sample size of women is too small to draw strong
conclusions from Cohort 3 as a single study, but its consistency with the results for the
larger sample in Cohort 2 and the nationally representative Project Talent data make it
worth noting: The male-to-female disparity in attraction to STEM even among the
profoundly gifted suggests that we may be looking at nothing more complicated than
people’s attraction to doing what they do best no matter how extraordinarily gifted they
are in the things they don’t do best.
Even Among the Exceptionally Gifted Who Are Attracted to STEM, Males and
Females Gravitate to Different Types of STEM
Hidden within the overall figures is another intriguing story: Even gifted women who
are attracted to STEM gravitate toward the life sciences (People-oriented), not math
and the physical sciences (Things-oriented). It was not a subtle tendency.
Proportionally, males outnumbered females by almost two to one on the Things-
oriented sciences, and females outnumbered males by almost two to one on the
People-oriented sciences.[23] The implication: Women who are so gifted that they can
deal with any intellectually demanding field are not scared off by science per se. They
instead tend to prefer those fields that deal with living things rather than nonliving
things.
The results from the smaller sample of profoundly gifted woman in Cohort 3
indicate a similar sex difference in interests, except that the female tilt toward STEM
disciplines that deal with living things was even stronger among the women of the top
0.01 percent in math than it was for those who were “merely” in the top 1 percent—
and it’s definitely not because the women of Cohort 3 weren’t smart enough to do
physics or pure mathematics if they felt like it.24
Even Among the Exceptionally Gifted, Women Have Different Life Priorities and
Work Priorities Than Men That Affect Their Career Trajectories and Achievements
The SMPY women were similar to the general population of college-educated women
in matters of marriage and children. Among the SMPY women at ages 45–49, 75
percent were married, compared to 72 percent of all college-educated women of the
same age. Seventy-four percent of the SMPY women had borne children, compared to
80 percent of their college-educated peers. Fifty-seven percent of the SMPY women
had more than one child, compared to 61 percent of their college-educated peers.25
In light of this, it is not surprising that the list of sex differences in work preferences
and life values that began this chapter included several that directly or indirectly
involved children, particularly with regard to women’s markedly greater unwillingness
than men to work long hours. Long hours at work compete with that responsibility. But
motherhood doesn’t appear to be the whole story. Remember that the women of
Cohort 2 were ages 45–49 when they were surveyed in 2012–13. They weren’t being
asked about how many hours they were willing to work outside the home when they
had preschool children at home, but how much they were prepared to work in their late
40s and the years ahead. In that context, the results of one survey question were
especially intriguing. How much would they be willing to work, at most, if given their
ideal job? Thirty percent of these extraordinarily talented women, few of whom had
small children to care for, were unwilling to work more than 40 hours per week even if
they were given their ideal job, compared to only 7 percent of the men.26 Add in the
other responses indicating the priorities SMPY women put on community service,
having time to socialize, not working outside the home, having a meaningful spiritual
life, and being available for family and friends, and we are once again faced with a sex
difference in profiles. Individually, most of the effect sizes ranged from small to
medium. As in the case of personality differences, these effect sizes are found in
indicators that are conceptually related but functionally distinct, and I would argue that
aggregating them would give us a more accurate picture of the magnitude of the sex
differences involved. But, even lacking the data to calculate Mahalanobis D, it is safe
to conclude that in middle age the SMPY men and women had importantly different
life priorities—which makes the next set of results all the more interesting.
The SMPY Men and Women Saw Themselves as Having Equally Satisfying Lives
As part of their survey, the members of Cohort 2 were given some standard
instruments for measuring subjective well-being.27 As a group, their evaluations of their
lives as of their late 40s were extremely positive—in the top decile, according to the
norms for those instruments. The differences between women and men were
uniformly minuscule.28 The authors’ appraisal of these findings seems exactly right:
In short, marked sex differences in how participants allocated their time and
structured their lives were not accompanied by corresponding sex differences in
how they viewed their career accomplishments and close relationships, or in
their positive outlook on life. One interpretation of the lack of appreciable
differences between the sexes across these indicators is that there are multiple
ways to construct a meaningful, productive, and satisfying life.29
I have given so much space to the SMPY cohorts for two reasons. The first is to
emphasize that sex differences in ability profiles are not the whole explanation for
differences in educational and vocational choices. As I discussed in chapter 3, sex
differences exist in the male and female profiles of abilities, and they do indeed have
implications for performance in certain occupations. But the data from the SMPY
cohorts convincingly document that STEM sex differences persist at virtually the same
levels when women are easily capable of having successful STEM careers if they want
them.
Second, the SMPY results pose a challenge to which defenders of social-construct
explanations must respond: Suppose we grant that socialization discourages girls from
STEM fields. But socialization to avoid STEM fields is not something in the water that
all little girls drink in similar quantities. It is fostered by specific inputs from parents,
teachers, peers, and the media, among other agents. Different little girls get different
amounts.
As noted earlier, we have good reason to think that the SMPY women
disproportionately grew up with gender-neutral toys, had mothers who were in
professional careers, had parents both of whom proactively told their daughters to
transcend gender stereotypes, were educated in progressive upper-middle-class schools,
and had peer groups consisting of other girls raised in similar circumstances.
Vulnerability to socialization into traditional female roles also varies by a girl’s
personal characteristics. We know for sure that the SMPY girls were all extremely
smart and knew they were smart. It seems reasonable to assume that they were also
disproportionately confident, with keen critical faculties, and resistant to propaganda.
In short, the nature of the SMPY sample tells us that the SMPY females got a
smaller dose of socialization to traditional female roles than average and had higher
levels of resistance than average. If socialization is the whole explanation for
differences in attraction to STEM vocations, how is it possible that the girls of Cohort
2, in the top half percent of academic ability, show the same ratio to the SMPY men
that the general population of college-educated girls shows to the general population of
college-educated men? The SMPY results imply sex differences that transcend
socialization.
GOING BEHIND THE NUMBERS
For a three-dimensional understanding of the priorities of highly accomplished women, you should
read Susan Pinker’s The Sexual Paradox: Men, Women, and the Real Gender Gap (2008). In
addition to a still-relevant account of the science of sex differences, the book contains a number of
in-depth profiles of women who were extremely successful professionally but made choices in their
careers that were different from those men usually make. Pinker’s narrative is in effect the SMPY
results brought to life.
Any discussion of the trends in vocation and life choices among the general population
of women must begin with the transformed opportunities for women since 1960.
Sociologist Catherine Hakim has cast these in terms of five specific changes that
produced a qualitatively new reality for women:
The invention of new forms of contraception, especially the pill, gave women
reliable and independent control over their own fertility.
The equal opportunities revolution gave women better access to all careers and
positions.
White-collar occupations, the ones most attractive to women, expanded.
Jobs for secondary earners expanded, making it easier for women to combine
childcare and work outside the home.
Freedom of lifestyle choices in liberal modern societies increased.33
All of these changes began in a concentrated period of time during the 1960s.
Without hyperbole, the results have been revolutionary.
In 1960, a few years before second-wave feminism took off in the United States,
only 41 percent of women ages 25–54 were in the labor force. In 2018, that figure
stood at 75 percent.
By 2015, women had a presence in high-status jobs that was inconceivable in
1960. From 1960 to 2018, women went from 1 percent of civil engineers to 17
percent; from 5 percent of attorneys to 35 percent; from 8 percent of physicians to 42
percent.
Not a single woman was the CEO of a Fortune 500 company in 1960, nor would
there be any until 1972.34 In 2018, 25 women were Fortune 500 CEOs, among them
the chief executives of General Motors, IBM, PepsiCo, Lockheed Martin, Oracle, and
General Dynamics.
In 1960, there was one woman in the U.S. Senate. After the 2018 election, there
were 25. In the 1960 House of Representatives, there were 19 women. After the 2018
election, there were 102.
Female students from elementary school through college have long had higher
mean grade point averages than males in most subjects (including math).35 But in 1960
women were nonetheless a minority of entering college students (46 percent), and the
gap grew during the undergraduate years. Almost two males got a bachelor’s degree for
every woman who did. In 1982, the number of women getting bachelor’s degrees
surpassed the number of men. The gap continued to widen subsequently. By 2016,
1,082,669 women got bachelor’s degrees compared to 812,669 men—a 33 percent
difference.[36]
The change in professional degrees was even more dramatic. The figure below
shows the number of PhDs, medical degrees, law degrees, dental degrees, and others
ordinarily requiring at least three years of graduate work.
Source: National Center for Education Statistics, Digest of Education Statistics, 1995
edition: Table 236, and 2017 edition: Table 318.
In 1960, 20 men got a professional degree for every woman who did. By 1970, the
ratio was less than 10 to 1. By 1980, it was less than 3 to 1. In 2005, women caught
up with men. Since then, more women have gotten more professional degrees than
men in every year. As of 2016, 93,778 women got a professional degree compared to
84,089 men.[37]
Nothing about women’s abilities had changed in the interim. Opportunities formerly
denied them had opened up, and women were exercising talents and capacities they
had possessed all along. That is the overriding headline about gender and occupational
changes during second-wave feminism.
It is in this context of progress for women over the course of half a century that I
now show you the data on current sex differences in vocational interests and life.
Sex Differences in Vocational Interests and Life Choices in the General
Population
The argument here amounts to two mini-propositions: that the vocational preferences
of men and women as measured by tests differ in ways that correspond to differences
on the People-Things dimension, and that the job choices that people actually make
correspond to their preferences.
Men and Women Are Attracted to Different Vocations, and Those Differences
Correspond to Differences on the People-Things Dimension
In 1959, psychologist John Holland published an article titled “A Theory of Vocational
Choice” that has shaped vocational counseling ever since.38 At the heart of his theory,
which was created without regard to sex differences, was the premise that an adult
comes to a vocational choice with “a hierarchy of habitual or preferred methods for
dealing with environmental tasks.… The person making a vocational choice in a sense
‘searches’ for situations which satisfy his hierarchy of adjustive orientations.”39 In its
final form, Holland’s theory posited six clusters of these orientations:
The theory is often referred to as RIASEC, based on its combined initials. I should
add that two of the labels were poorly chosen. As the descriptions make clear,
“Enterprising” doesn’t refer to entrepreneurship or risk-taking. It’s about interacting
with other people in a leadership or managerial role. “Conventional” doesn’t mean
timid or boring or stuck with tradition. It refers to a preference for procedure,
systematic practices, and orderliness. These more accurate understandings also make it
clear why Enterprising is related to the People dimension and Conventional is related to
what Baron-Cohen calls systemizing—and, by extension, the Things dimension.
Subsequently, psychometrician Dale Prediger developed a two-dimensional way of
assessing the results of inventories testing Holland’s orientations. One dimension went
from Ideas at one extreme to Data at the other. The second dimension went from
Things at one extreme to People at the other. Prediger accompanied his analysis with
formulas for computing a People-Things index and an Ideas-Data index.41
Schematically, Holland’s and Prediger’s ideas look like this.
Source: ACT (2009): Fig. 1.1. 42
Source: Author’s analyses, CPS 2014–18 and Su, Rounds, and Armstrong (2009): Table
3.
It’s not often that two completely different databases produce such similar results.
The big sex differences on both interests and jobs were for the Realistic and Social
orientations—the conceptually clearest Things and People orientations—and on
Prediger’s overall index combining all the RIASEC data.
STEM occupations. The same thing happens within different kinds of STEM
occupations: In 2015, two of the same authors, Rong Su and James Rounds,
conducted another meta-analysis focusing on distinctions within scientific and technical
occupations. Again, their database of vocational preferences and a database of actual
jobs held by the U.S. working-age population produced almost interchangeable results.
In both cases, the biggest sex differences favoring men involved the most Things-
oriented jobs; the biggest sex differences favoring women involved the most People-
oriented jobs.[46] The degree of consistency of the sex differences in vocational
interests and occupations is quite remarkable. To draw the discussion together, consider
the table below.
The three columns draw on databases that are quite different in both measures and
samples, yet they tell a clear and consistent story.[47] Effect sizes on Realistic favoring
men were –0.84, –0.92, and –0.77 for the three sources; effect sizes on Social favoring
women were +0.68, +0.88, and +0.84 for the three sources.
Trends in Vocational Interests and Choices Since 1970
Everything I’ve given you so far is evidence for the existence of a phenomenon—sex
differences on the People-Things dimension—but no evidence for its cause. All these
effect sizes could simply mean that women and men alike continue to be socialized into
certain gender-typical interests as well as gender-typical jobs.
Let’s turn to evidence that I believe makes this interpretation difficult to defend. A
look back at what has happened to educational and job choices over the last 50 years
suggests that vocational doors really did open up for women during the 1970s, that
women took advantage of those new opportunities to the extent that they wanted to,
and that we fairly quickly reached a new equilibrium.
Women’s Undergraduate Majors Since 1970: A Brief Surge in Things-Oriented
STEM and Enduring Increases in People-Oriented STEM
Women’s undergraduate majors offer a case in point. In 1971, 38 percent of women’s
bachelor’s degrees were in education. That proportion had fallen by half by the early
1980s. Meanwhile, degrees in business grew from 3 percent in 1971 to 20 percent by
1982. Women were no longer limited to K–12 teaching as their major professional
option (besides nursing), and they quickly made other professional interests known.
There were also big changes in women’s bachelor of science degrees—but of a
particular kind. Consider first the most Things-oriented STEM careers—physics,
chemistry, earth sciences, computer science, mathematics, and engineering. The
percentage of women’s degrees obtained in those majors more than doubled from 1971
to 1986—but “more than doubled” meant going from 4 percent to 10 percent.48 And
1986 was the high point. By 1992, that number had dropped to 6 percent, where it has
remained, give or take a percentage point, ever since. It’s not that women were
unwilling to undertake majors that require courses in math and science. Women’s
degrees in People-oriented STEM—biology and health majors—doubled in just the
eight years from 1971 (9 percent) to 1979 (18 percent), remained at roughly that level
through the turn of the century, then surged again, standing at 27 percent of degrees in
2017. Rather, they wanted to use their math and science so that they could study topics
that dealt with living things, especially people, rather than topics restricted to inanimate
things and abstract concepts.
Occupations of College-Educated Women: Change in the 1970s and Early 1980s,
Stability Since the Late 1980s
I turn from trends over time in women’s vocational interests and choices of
undergraduate majors to trends over time in the jobs they hold as employed adults.[49]
To analyze the trends in the jobs that women hold, I took advantage of the
Department of Labor’s O*NET database that assigns RIASEC scores to every
occupation.50 I then used Prediger’s work to identify jobs that tilt toward the People
and Things ends of the spectrum. The specifics are given in the note.[51]
Analyzing women’s choices over the years since 1970 is complicated by three
contemporaneous trends: Women were rapidly entering the labor force through the
mid-1990s, concentrated among married women; the percentage of People jobs as a
proportion of all jobs was increasing as the service sector grew and manufacturing
declined; and fewer people were getting married. Furthermore, all of these trends
played out differently for college-educated women and women with no more than a
high school education, so I will present the results separately for those two categories.
All numbers refer to employed persons ages 25–54. I begin with the story for college-
educated women.
The pair of figures below shows how occupations for college-educated women
changed when categorized as People-oriented or Things-oriented.52 The figure on the
left shows percentages of employed women in People jobs versus Things job. The
figure on the right shows the sex ratios for the two types of jobs. The dotted lines
represent the average for 2014–18, giving you a way to see how long the current
situation has lasted.
Based on either perspective, observers in the late 1980s could be excused for
thinking that men and women would converge within a few decades. From 1970
through the mid-1980s, the percentage of women in Things jobs had risen and the
male-female ratio had plunged. If those slopes had been sustained, the percentages of
men and women in Things jobs would have intersected around 2001. The percentages
of men and women in People jobs would have intersected in the mid-1990s.
But convergence was already slowing by the late 1980s and had effectively stalled
by 1990. The percentage of women in Things jobs hit 30 percent in 1990 and never
subsequently surpassed it. Rounded to one decimal point, the male-female ratio in
Things jobs reached 1.4 in 1982 and remained in the narrow range of 1.4–1.6 through
2018.53
For college-educated women, the distribution of vocational choices along the
People-Things dimension changed substantially from the 1970s into the mid-1980s, but
little has changed since then. It looks as if women were indeed artificially constrained
from moving into a variety of Things occupations as of 1970, that those constraints
were largely removed, and that equilibrium was reached around 30 years ago.
For Women with No More Than a High School Education, Not Much Changed
Overall, the story for high-school-educated women is like the Sherlock Holmes story
with the dog that didn’t bark. In 1971, 30 percent of women were employed in People
jobs. By 2018, that figure had risen to 39 percent. During the same period, the
proportion of women employed in Things jobs moved in a narrow range from a high of
53 percent in 1971 to a low of 46 percent in 2004. As of 2018, the figure stood at 51
percent. Most of the rise in People jobs can be associated with the increased role of
People jobs in the economy, but not all.54 The effects of the feminist revolution in the
1970s and early 1980s that were so evident for college-educated women were missing
for women with no more than a high school education.
This finding surprised me. From the 1970s onward, well-paying jobs for women
without college educations were opening in manufacturing and a wide variety of
technical specialties that were formerly closed to them—not only opened up but
opened wide. From the 1970s through the mid-1990s, males with no more than a high
school education were dropping out of the labor force, working shorter hours, and
were more often unemployed, while women with no more than a high school education
were joining the labor force and working longer hours.55 A variety of evidence
indicates that during the same period working-class men were becoming more
unreliable employees.56 It appears that the time was right for women to enter these
jobs if only for economic reasons, independently of vocational preferences.
Some women took advantage of those new opportunities. For example, among
people ages 25–54 employed as mechanics or repairers, only 0.6 percent were women
in 1971–75. In 2014–18, 2.1 percent were women—a proportional increase of 350
percent. But seen as a percentage of all employed women with no more than a high
school degree, mechanics and repairers constituted 0.1 percent of employed women
ages 25–54 in 1971–75 and 0.2 percent of them in 2014–18—such a tiny number that
the increase in women mechanics had no effect on the trendline. In other blue-collar
jobs, there were remarkably small increases in the percentage of jobs held by women.
Among people ages 25–54 with no more than a high school degree employed in
manufacturing jobs in 1971–75, an average of 21 percent were women. In 2014–18,
that figure was 23 percent.
In sum: The effect of the feminist revolution on the vocations of college-educated
women was real but quickly reached a new equilibrium. For women with no more than
a high school education, it is as if the feminist revolution never happened.
Cross-National Sex Differences in Vocational Directions
As I discussed in chapter 3, the results of the 2015 administration of the PISA tests
were familiar from previous ones, showing a small math effect size (–0.05) favoring
boys and a moderate reading effect size (+0.32) favoring girls. In 2018, psychologists
Gijsbert Stoet and David Geary published an analysis of the 2015 round of PISA tests
that cast a new and informative light on what those results imply for the attraction of
males to Things occupations and of females to People occupations.
The authors created a measure of the individual 15-year-old’s personal strengths in
science, math, and reading scores relative to their overall ability. The details are given
in the note,[57] but it comes down to this: Suppose 100 students from a magnet school
for the gifted take the PISA tests, and so do 100 students from an ordinary high school.
Joan, from the magnet school, has raw science, math, and reading scores of 700, 650,
and 600 respectively, for an average of 650 points. Her science score is 50 points
above her personal average. Joe, from the ordinary high school, has raw science, math,
and reading scores of 400, 350, and 300 respectively, for an average of 350 points. His
science score is also 50 points above his personal average. So for both of them, despite
the great difference in their raw scores, science is their relative strength. But how can
we compare their respective relative strengths? The measure Stoet and Geary devised
is a statistically suitable way for doing so—what I will call relative-strength scores (the
authors called them intraindividual scores). We can then add up the 100 relative-
strength scores for each school and compare them by sex, making statements about sex
differences (if any) between the relative strengths of boys and girls in the two schools.
We can do the same thing comparing nations. The following table summarizes the
2015 PISA results for 62 countries showing mean scores by nation, relative-strength
scores, and correlations with the Global Gender Gap Index.58
Subject: Mathematics
Mean scores
Effect size (d): –0.05
Correlation with GGGI: –.18 (ns)
Relative-strength scores
Effect size (d): –0.55
Correlation with GGGI: –.04 (ns)
In the words of Proposition #3, “On average, women worldwide are more attracted to
vocations centered on people and men to vocations centered on things.” The
proposition is true with regard to the general population and to the gifted men and
women of SMPY. It is established by scores on tests of vocational interests and by the
revealed preferences of the jobs that people take. It applies to those with advanced
educations and those with high school educations. It has persisted over a half century
of second-wave feminism and has not diminished in the last three decades.
The subtext of this chapter has been that it’s not plausible to explain the entire
difference in educational and vocational interests as artifacts of gender roles and
socialization. If that were the case, the world shouldn’t look the way it does. In
contrast, a mixed model—it’s partly culture, partly innate preferences—works just fine.
In this narrative, females really were artificially deterred from STEM educations and
occupations through the 1950s and into the 1960s. One of the effects of the feminist
revolution was that new opportunities opened up for women and women took
advantage of them. The changes in women’s choices of college majors dramatically
reflect that, along with their movement into professions such as medicine, the law, and
business. But something has to explain how quickly those changes settled into a new
equilibrium of educational and occupational choices that has lasted for 30 to 40 years
now.
Is the patriarchy still to blame? One can try to defend that position, but it has to be
done with data. I hope the nationwide, enduring patterns of educational and vocational
choices across women of different interests and levels of ability have shown how hard
it is to make that case.
5
Twenty years ago, this chapter would have been able to discuss many sex differences
in rodent brains but not in human brains.1 Then, doing that kind of research on humans
could be a career-killer. “Be careful, it’s the third rail,” a senior colleague told
neurobiologist Larry Cahill in 2000. “Fortunately, times are changing,” Cahill wrote in
the introduction to a special double issue of the Journal of Neuroscience Research in
2017 devoted to sex differences in the brain:
This chapter is in no sense a survey of the state of knowledge about sex differences
in the brain. There’s too much going on, it’s far too complex, and too much still
consists of tentative findings for anything resembling a comprehensive discussion. My
first goal for this chapter is to present some of the most important known sex
differences in the brain. My second goal is to give you a sense of the exciting progress
that is being made in linking specific differences in the brain to specific behavioral sex
differences. Proposition #4 is accordingly modest. Stated informally, the proposition
amounts to, “What we see in observable differences between males and females on the
People-Things dimension hangs together with things that are being learned about
differences in male and female brains. The connections are still approximate, with
many unknowns remaining, but they are becoming clearer.”
Second Interlude: Things About Genetic Sex Differences and the Brain That You
Need to Know to Read the Rest of the Book
So much for the preliminaries. The next three sections describe some of the most
important and securely known biological sex differences in the brain: the activational
effects of the sex hormones, sex differentiation during fetal and neonatal brain
development, and the generally greater lateralization of the male brain. I then discuss
differences in emotional cognition and their links to specific regions of the brain.
I have consigned discussion of two other securely documented and substantial sex
differences to Appendix 3: “Sex Differences in Brain Volumes and Variance.” Both
types of difference will presumably play into the story of sex differences in cognitive
repertoires eventually, but as I write they represent important findings with
undetermined or uncertain effects on the phenotype.
The Activational Effects of Sex Hormones
Almost everyone has heard about sex hormones. Both sexes have all of the major sex
hormones to some degree, but androgens are the ones most identified with males
(testosterone being the most famous) and estrogens are the ones most identified with
females. Their effects on mood and behavior are part of the popular culture. Some of
the stereotypes are exaggerated, but not all of them. Journalist Andrew Sullivan once
underwent a medically prescribed regimen of testosterone injections. Here is his
description of what an injection did to him:
Within hours, and at most a day, I feel a deep surge of energy. It is less edgy
than a double espresso, but just as powerful. My attention span shortens. In the
two or three days after my shot, I find it harder to concentrate on writing and
feel the need to exercise more. My wit is quicker, my mind faster, but my
judgment is more impulsive. It is not unlike the kind of rush I get before talking
in front of a large audience, or going on a first date, or getting on an airplane,
but it suffuses me in a less abrupt and more consistent way. In a word, I feel
braced. For what? It scarcely seems to matter.22
Nor were those effects limited to Sullivan’s mood. When he began his series of
testosterone injections, he weighed 165 pounds.
I now weigh 185 pounds. My collar size went from a 15 to a 17 1/2 in a few
months; my chest went from 40 to 44. My appetite in every sense of that word
expanded beyond measure. Going from napping two hours a day, I now rarely
sleep in the daytime and have enough energy for daily workouts and a hefty
work schedule. I can squat more than 400 pounds. Depression, once a regular
feature of my life, is now a distant memory. I feel better able to recover from
life’s curveballs, more persistent, more alive. These are the long-term effects.
They are almost as striking as the short-term ones.23
These effects of hormones are akin to those of alcohol—powerful but varying with
their level in the bloodstream, which changes over time. The technical term for these
effects is activational. Hormones have many such effects on phenotypic differences
between males and females, and the hormones are not limited to estrogen and
testosterone. For example:
The female advantage in social cognition. A single administration of testosterone
in women significantly altered connectivity of the network in the brain (technically
known as the IFG-ACC-SMA network) that underlies the integration and selection of
sensory information during empathic behavior. This finding suggests a neural
mechanism by which testosterone can impair the recognition of emotions.24
In a double-blind, placebo-controlled study, testosterone administered to women
diminished their accuracy in inferring mental states. Estrogen administered to men
increased their emotional reactivity when watching a distressed person.25
In a placebo-controlled study, administration of oxytocin to males improved their
ability to infer the mental state of others from social cues. The effect was pronounced
for difficult items.26
The female advantage in prosocial behavior. In a double-blind and placebo-
controlled experiment, pharmacologically blocking dopaminergic transmission reduced
prosociality in women and selfishness in men. The authors concluded that in females
the dopaminergic reward system is more sensitive to shared rewards than to selfish
rewards, while the opposite is true for males. Their conclusion is supported both by
pharmacological and neuroimaging data.27
The higher male level of impulsive behavior. In a placebo-controlled experiment,
testosterone administered to males diminished their performance on the Cognitive
Reflection Test, which measures capacity to override intuitive judgments with
deliberated answers. The independent effect of the testosterone persisted after controls
for background variables and 14 other hormones.28
The higher female level of risk aversion. Variations in salivary concentrations of
testosterone were analyzed in MBA students. Higher levels of testosterone in women
were associated with lower levels of risk aversion, with collateral evidence suggesting
that testosterone has nonlinear effects on risk aversion. Persons high in testosterone
and low in risk aversion were also more likely to choose risky careers in finance.[29]
The higher female level of emotional arousal. Neuroimaging studies have shown
that measures of fear and arousal are associated with changes in estradiol levels across
the menstrual cycle and correlate with changes in the functional reactivity of the
amygdala and hippocampus.30
I will leave the discussion of the activational effects of hormones with these
examples. The even bigger story about hormones and sex differences is not their
temporary activational effects, but their permanent organizational effects on the fetal
and neonatal brain.
Sex Differentiation During Fetal and Neonatal Brain Development
The discovery that testosterone permanently changes brain tissue was made 60 years
ago but remains remarkably little known among the lay public. What follows is a
simplified description. A more complete description (for example, discussing important
changes that occur during and after puberty) would include yet other ways in which
brains develop differently in males and females.
By the end of week eight, a human embryo’s brain and central nervous system
already contain their rudimentary structures. By week 26, the primary ridges, folds,
and furrows of the human brain have emerged. Most of the 100 billion neurons in the
adult human brain have already been created.31 These basic changes happen for both
sexes, driven by processes that are believed to be unrelated (or nearly so) to the
embryo’s sex.32
But long before week 26, sex has entered the picture. Even at the end of the
embryonic phase, the embryo’s testicles or ovaries have been developing for two
weeks. By week 12, the differentiation of the sexual organs is settled, and the
differentiation of the brain begins. Specifically, testosterone surges in human males
occur twice before birth, during weeks 12–18 and again during weeks 34–41. Another
testosterone surge in males, often called mini-puberty , occurs in the first three months
after birth.33
The confirmation of this role for hormones dates to 1959 and a seminal article by
Charles Phoenix and his colleagues.34 Before then, biologists knew about the role of
the sex hormones in stimulating mating behavior. The Phoenix study presented the first
evidence that hormones also had organizational effects that permanently altered the
structure of the nervous system. “No other idea in behavioral neuroendocrinology has
so transformed how we think about the genesis of masculine and feminine behavior,”
wrote neuroendocrinologist Kim Wallen. “The notion that hormones at circumscribed
times in life predictably and permanently alter the function, and we now know, the
structure, of a living being to become phenotypically male, is one of the truly powerful
ideas of the twentieth century.”35
Since 1959, thousands of experiments have been conducted on nonhuman
mammals, primarily rodents and primates, in which the experimental animals are
exposed to hormone manipulations during critical periods of prenatal and neonatal
development.36 These experiments have established that certain regions of the brain
(but not others) have receptors (in different proportions) that accept chemical signals
from hormones. These signals can affect a cell’s survival, its anatomical connectivity,
and its neurochemicals.
It has been found that the default is female—in the absence of a spike in
testosterone at the appropriate times during gestation and neonatal life, the brain takes
on female characteristics. Feminization is not an entirely passive process, however. Just
as some receptors accept chemical signals from testosterone, others accept signals from
estrogen. But it is through the spike in testosterone that the brain is both masculinized
and defeminized (the testosterone prevents the development of female
characteristics).37 For both males and females, changes that develop during the fetal
and neonatal phases also have delayed effects. Some of the circuits that are already
formed by three months after birth are quiescent until activated by sex hormones at
puberty.38
What does masculinized mean? Neuroscientist Margaret McCarthy summarized
aspects of masculinization in rodents as follows:
The quote from Margaret McCarthy gives you only a glimpse of the many ways in which studies of
rodents and primates have documented that the mammalian brain is a highly sexed organ. My
approach is akin to going into a fight with one hand voluntarily tied behind my back. One of the
largest and most sophisticated bodies of knowledge about biological sex differences in the brain is
based on nonhuman mammals, primarily rodents and some species of monkey. I am ignoring it here
for the same reason I draw so little from evolutionary psychology. Like the accusation that
“Evolutionary psychology is nothing more than just-so stories,” the dismissive response that
“Knowing something about rats doesn’t mean humans work that way” is more effective than it
should be. The proper question is not “Why should we think humans are the same as rats?” but
rather “Why should we think that one mammalian brain was immune from the evolutionary forces
that produced highly sexed brains in other mammals?”
Exploring the Organizational Effects of Prenatal Hormones in Humans
A genetic disorder of the adrenal glands known as congenital adrenal hyperplasia
(CAH) has been recognized for more than a century. It can result in the production of
too little cortisol or aldosterone, with effects having nothing to do with sexual identity.
But it also can result in overproduction of androgens, especially testosterone. Starting
in the late 1960s, researchers began to explore the possibility that girls with CAH might
be more likely to engage in male sex-typed behavior in their choices of toys and
games.40 In the 1980s, researchers also began to explore the possibility that the
organizational effects of prenatal hormones in animal studies applied to humans as
well.41 In 1995, sociologist and demographer J. Richard Udry and his colleagues put
that possibility to the test and found that the model used for animal research did in fact
apply to humans: “It is concluded that gendered behavior is not entirely socially
constructed, but partly built on a biological foundation.”42 It was a landmark article in
the development of an alternative to the social-construction orthodoxy.
Also beginning in the late 1960s, neurologist Norman Geschwind had been studying
anatomical asymmetries in the brain. By the early 1980s, Geschwind had integrated
diverse empirical evidence to reach a specific hypothesis that would explain links
between maleness and the right hemisphere. Along with one of his students, Albert
Galaburda, he presented his hypothesis in another landmark article, “Cerebral
Lateralization,” in 1985:
It is the intent of this hypothesis to account for the following: (1) Left-
handedness is usually found to be more common in men than women. (2) The
developmental disorders of language, speech, cognition, and emotion, e.g.,
stuttering, dyslexia, and autism are strongly male predominant. (3) Women are
on the average superior in verbal talents while men tend on the average to be
better at spatial functions. (4) Left-handers of both sexes and those with
learning disabilities often exhibit superior right-hemisphere functions. (5) Left-
handedness and ambidexterity are more frequent in the developmental disorders
of childhood. (6) Certain diseases are more common in non-right-handers, e.g.,
immune disorders.43
We found that the toddlers (at twelve and twenty-four months of age) who we
had identified as having lower fetal testosterone, now had higher levels of eye
contact and a larger vocabulary; or, putting it the other way around, the higher
your levels of prenatal testosterone, the less eye contact you now make and the
smaller your vocabulary. This is exactly as Geschwind had predicted. When we
got those results, I had one of those strange feelings, like a shiver down the
spine. A few drops more of this little chemical could affect your sociability or
your language ability. I found it extraordinary.46
In the first two decades of the twenty-first century, these beginnings have been
augmented by an array of additional evidence for the role of androgens in masculinizing
the human brain.
Evidence from natural variation in prenatal testosterone. Baron-Cohen’s Autism
Research Centre has generated most of the studies documenting the relationships
between prenatal testosterone levels and various measures of male-typical and female-
typical behavior. These include visuospatial ability,47 autism,48 the empathy quotient,49
systemizing quotient,50 social relationships,51 and interest in children.52 The pattern of
results linking testosterone to the phenotype has been striking but not dispositive. A
2015 review of the literature on early androgen exposure and sex development (first
author was Melissa Hines) indicates that the underlying problem may be the use of
amniotic fluid: The within-sex variation in testosterone in amniotic fluid may not be
sufficient to serve as a reliable measure of natural variation in prenatal exposure to
testosterone.53 It can point research in the right direction, but seldom can conclusively
pin down relationships. Measures of neonatal testosterone (which can be tested
directly) and studies of people with sexual disorders are producing more robust
evidence.
DISSENTING VOICES
The best-known and most detailed critiques of the organizational role of testosterone in particular and
biological explanations of phenotypic sex differences in general are Rebecca Jordan-Young’s Brain
Storm (2010), Cordelia Fine’s pair of books, Delusions of Gender (2010) and Testosterone Rex
(2017), and Gina Rippon’s The Gendered Brain (2019). 54 All four books are directed at the general
reader and are entertainingly written. They draw attention to some problems that are indeed common
such as small samples, inconsistent results, and scarce replications.
The reviews in the mainstream press have been uniformly and sometimes gushingly enthusiastic.
[55] Testosterone Rex also won the 2017 Royal Society Insight Investment Science Book Prize,
awarded by the oldest scientific society in the world. 56 And yet none of these books has had a visible
effect on neuroscientists working on sex differences. There were a few critical reviews in the
technical literature, and other academics have had scathing things to say in blogs, but that’s it.[57] A
neuroscientist whom I asked about the lack of reaction to Testosterone Rex replied, “One reason you
don’t find many critiques of Fine’s book is that people in the field really don’t care. It’s so evidently
nonsense.” In their view, Jordan-Young, Fine, and Rippon are guilty of cherry-picking (they’re good
at attacking weak studies; they don’t come to grips with the strong ones), fail to acknowledge the
weaknesses of their favored studies, and set up straw men, demolishing positions that neuroscientists
working on sex differences don’t take (e.g., treating male and female brains as binary).[58]
If you want to compare the arguments side by side, I recommend a pair of articles easily
obtainable online. The first is by Cordelia Fine, Daphna Joel, and Gina Rippon: “Eight Things You
Need to Know About Sex, Gender, Brains, and Behavior: A Guide for Academics, Journalists,
Parents, Gender Diversity Advocates, Social Justice Warriors, Tweeters, Facebookers, and Everyone
Else.”59 The second is a response by Marco Del Giudice, David Puts, David Geary, and David
Schmitt: “Sex Differences in Brain and Behavior: Eight Counterpoints.”60
If you’re trying to compare the positions in Jordan-Young, Fine, and Rippon with mainstream
science on the crucial issue of masculinization of the male brain, I recommend two evenhanded
reviews of the literature on early androgen exposure written by acknowledged experts in the field.
One is “Early Androgen Exposure and Human Gender Development” by Melissa Hines, Mihaela
Constantinescu, and Debra Spencer. 61 Hines is director of the Gender Development Research Centre
at Cambridge University. The other is “Beyond Pink and Blue: The Complexity of Early Androgen
Effects on Gender Development” by Sheri A. Berenbaum, professor of psychology and pediatrics at
Penn State and member of the Penn State Neuroscience Institute. 62
A subsequent study specifically focused on how 125 women with CAH compared
to their unaffected siblings on the People-Things dimension. The researchers found
that females with CAH had more interest in Things versus People than did unaffected
females, and variations among females with CAH reflected variations in their degree of
androgen exposure. On Prediger’s Things-People dimension, the effect size comparing
women with and without CAH was –0.75 (indicating that women with CAH were
farther toward the Things end of the continuum).64
In terms of their self-defined sexual identity, almost all adult women with CAH self-
identify as women. Only about 1–2 percent choose to live as males, but that is far
higher than the one per thousands in women without CAH. About 5 percent experience
sex dysphoria, also far above the levels for women without CAH.65
The other sexual disorder is complete androgen insensitivity syndrome (CAIS).
Fetuses with CAIS are genetically male, carrying the XY chromosome pair. Their testes
produce prenatal testosterone in normal amounts at the proper times—but their
androgen receptors are not functional. The testosterone circulates, but it has no effect.
Persons with CAIS are born with externally normal female genitalia, reared as girls, are
usually indistinguishable from girls behaviorally, and are usually designated as females
in the technical literature despite their Y chromosome.66 It is also noteworthy that,
despite their Y chromosome, CAIS carriers apparently do not have elevated spatial
skills.67
A 2017 study by Swedish neuroscientists identified specific ways in which fetuses
with a Y chromosome but affected by CAIS develop brains that are a mix of
characteristically “male” and “female” patterns. Omitting the most abstruse results,
women with CAIS displayed a characteristically female pattern of thicker parietal and
occipital cortices and thinner left temporal cortex than male controls.68 On the other
hand, the CAIS women displayed a “male” pattern in cortical thickness with regard to a
thinner cortex in the precentral and postcentral gyrus. CAIS women were
characteristically “female” with regard to the hippocampus volumes and “male” with
regard to the caudate volumes. Add in the more abstruse findings, and the authors felt
able to conclude that “the results indeed show considerable support” for the hypotheses
they took into the study: The CAIS condition—no effect of testosterone on neural
tissue—explains the similarities in brain structure between CAIS women and female
controls, while the presence of the Y chromosome and its unique genes explains the
similarities between CAIS women and male controls.69
Exploring the Interplay of Biology and Socialization
Accepting the organizational role of hormones does not require that we reject a role for
socialization. Intuition tells us that both are probably involved, and scholars have made
progress in exploring the balance.
In 2000, Richard Udry used an elegant experimental design to initiate an
investigation of the nature-nurture balance. Udry took advantage of the natural
variation in androgen levels among women even in the absence of a genetic disorder
such as CAH. He assembled a sample of 163 adult women (ages 27–30 at the time of
analysis) who had measures of their testosterone and SHBG70 values taken in utero
(they were drawn from the Child Health and Development Study conducted in the
1960s). Udry’s researchers also obtained measures of the women’s adult levels of
testosterone and SHBG along with a variety of questionnaire information that enabled
Udry to assess the participants along four masculinity-femininity continua. The
continua involved the importance of home, interests, job status, and personality. The
results showed the predicted relationships of both prenatal and adult testosterone and
SHBG to adult gendered behavior—but also showed independent relationships of
childhood gender socialization to adult gendered behavior. The more interesting finding
involved an interaction term: The effects of childhood socialization were confined to
women who had low levels of prenatal androgen exposure. In Udry’s words, “if a
daughter has natural tendencies to be feminine, encouragement will enhance femininity;
but if she has below average femininity in childhood, encouraging her to be more
feminine will have no effect.”71 A second interesting finding involved scores on a
measure of the importance of spending time with one’s family. In adolescence, the
women in the study had been tightly bunched in the middle of the range regardless of
their level of prenatal androgen exposure. When interviewed at ages 27–30, those with
above-average prenatal androgen exposure had moved to the “not important” position,
while those with below-average prenatal androgen exposure had moved to the “very
important” position.
In 2015, Shannon Davis and Barbara Risman drew from the same Child Health
and Development Study that Udry used, but with a larger sample. In their article with
the main title “Feminists Wrestle with Testosterone,” they used an analogous set of
instruments, applied them to path analysis, and got complementary results. Their
analysis showed effects of both prenatal androgen exposure and childhood
socialization, with socialization playing the stronger role in terms of path coefficients.
[72] Their finding that the effect of hormones was stronger for masculinity than
femininity is consistent with Udry’s finding.
73
Male-Female Differences in Brain Lateralization and Connectivity
So far, I have discussed evidence that the prenatal and neonatal surges of testosterone
are causally linked to a variety of phenotypic sex differences, but I haven’t directly
addressed Geschwind’s hypothesis that the male brain is more lateralized than the
female brain because of the organizing effects of testosterone.
Lateralization
Lateralization refers to the relative localization of a function in one hemisphere or the
other. To apply it to the question we are discussing, Geschwind hypothesized that
males primarily use the left hemisphere for verbal tasks and the right hemisphere for
spatial tasks, whereas women use both hemispheres for both types of tasks. Another
way of expressing it is that males exhibit more functional asymmetry.
Even before Geschwind formulated his hypothesis about testosterone and the right
hemisphere, scholars had been considering the possibility that sex differences in test
scores might point to sex differences in the use of the left and right hemispheres of the
cerebrum. As early as 1980, a review of the evidence in Behavioral and Brain
Sciences cautiously concluded that the literature did not “overwhelmingly confirm”
greater functional asymmetry in males, but among those studies that did find a sex
difference, “the vast majority are compatible with [that] hypothesis.”74 A meta-analysis
in 1996 came to the somewhat more confident conclusion that “it appears that sex
differences in verbal and spatial abilities can be explained, at least in part, by the fact
that men tend to be more lateralized than women.”75
Recall that the default in brain development is female. In the case of language
processing, this means that the default is to use both hemispheres. The salient issue in
analyzing the effects of testosterone on language processing is that something about the
development of the male right brain is crowding out the use of the right hemisphere for
language processing (which, by default, would also ordinarily be used). The focus of
the right hemisphere on spatial processing, driven by the impact of testosterone on the
right hemisphere, is a plausible explanation.
Clinical evidence from brain injuries reinforces the probability of sex differences in
lateralization. When women suffer brain damage to the left hemisphere, they are less
likely than men to develop language difficulties. Women’s language test scores after
brain damage suffer the same effect whether the damage occurred in the left or right
hemisphere, whereas men are more affected by damage to the left hemisphere.76
Researchers are also able to investigate this difference by anesthetizing just one
hemisphere of the brain. Women lose language fluency no matter which hemisphere is
anesthetized; men do so only if it is the left hemisphere.77
Most of the evidence from brain injuries had been developed before the advent of
fMRI. Since then, neuroscientists have made major advances in understanding what’s
going on inside the brain that produces the circumstantial evidence for greater male
lateralization.
Evidence of Sex Differences in Structural Connectivity
Neurons in the brain produce thoughts and behaviors through their interconnections.
But there has to be an architecture to those connections, just as there must be an
architecture to any kind of network. That architecture is labeled structural
connectivity. The map of those connections is called the connectome. The word was
created to reflect its kinship to the map of the genome. There are many parallels. Maps
of both the genome and connectome don’t answer questions of functionality in
themselves, but they do provide a framework within which function can be studied.
Both consist of structural elements at different levels of scale—from genetic regulatory
networks to genes to base pairs in the genome; from brain regions to neuronal
populations to neurons in the connectome.78
Don’t expect to see a fully mapped human connectome anytime soon. Whereas the
genome has about 3 billion sites, the human brain has about 86 billion neurons.
Whereas the sites of the genome lie sequentially along a strip of DNA, neurons can
connect with many other neurons. The complexity of a connectome is such that, as I
write, neuroscientists are still struggling to complete the connectome of the fruit fly
larva, a brain that contains just 15,000 neurons.79
Neuroscientists are nonetheless able to construct connectomes using regions as the
unit of analysis instead of individual neurons. In the early 2000s, it was established that
the connectome follows a “small-world” topology.80 The phrase has a precise
mathematical description, but the easiest way to understand it is through the
popularized concept of “six degrees of separation,” referring to the assertion that you
can establish a path between yourself and any other person in the world through no
more than five intermediary links.81 The reason you can do it is that your personal
cluster of acquaintances includes at least a few people who have a direct connection
with some other distant cluster. That’s how the brain is organized: It is characterized by
a high degree of local clustering of neurons, forming nodes and hubs, supplemented
with random connections that permit direct pathways between distant nodes.
From the mid-1990s onward, new evidence from fMRI accumulated for greater
lateralization among males.82 A group of neuroscientists at Beijing Normal University
hypothesized that connectivity varies by brain size and by sex. They used DTI
tractography to analyze MRI images of 72 healthy, right-handed young adults. They
found no relationship between path length and either brain size or sex, which the
authors interpreted as suggesting that “the global efficiency of structural networks of
the brain is not affected by sex or brain size.”83 But their analysis of the efficiency of
local clusters told a strikingly different story: The smaller the brain, the higher the
efficiency of clusters—but only for women. The correlation between the authors’
clustering coefficient and brain size for women was a sizable –.53. For men, the
correlation was a trivially small –.09. It’s a finding that bears on the similarity of g in
males and females despite the larger male brain volumes that I discuss in Appendix 3.
In 2014, the state of knowledge saw a major advance through a study titled “Sex
Differences in the Structural Connectome of the Human Brain.” First author was
Madhura Ingalhalikar. She and her colleagues at the University of Pennsylvania and at
Children’s Hospital of Philadelphia used the same Philadelphia Neurodevelopmental
Cohort discussed in chapter 3. Their sample size was large: 428 males and 521
females. The 10 coauthors of the Ingalhalikar study parcellated the cerebrum into 95
regions, then used interregional probabilistic fiber tractography to compute the
connection probability between regions, expressed in a 95-network matrix. Analyses
were conducted by sex and by each of three age groups corresponding to the
developmental stages of childhood (8–13 years), adolescence (13–17 years), and young
adulthood (17–22 years).
Here are the main findings:
In this paper, it has been shown that on average, for pairs of female and male
subjects with equal brain sizes and similar ages, the CCA is larger in the female
by a few percent. Given that postmortem studies of callosal fibers in normal
subjects have either found no difference in fiber density between sexes or a
denser fiber packing in females, it can be inferred that for a given brain size, the
female cerebral hemispheres are more extensively interconnected.98
Once again, the effect size is modest; once again, it is consistent with other sex
differences in the brain indicating greater female symmetry in brain connectivity.
Sex Differences in Gray Matter
In 2012, a study of sex difference in gray matter provided triangulating evidence for the
role of fetal testosterone in changing the male right hemisphere. Michael Lombardo
was the first author of the resulting article, “Fetal Testosterone Influences Sexually
Dimorphic Gray Matter in the Human Brain.” Its findings should be treated as
provisional until replicated, but it gives a window into the research that is linking brain
structure and function to differences in neurocognitive test scores.
The Lombardo analysis was conducted in two phases. First, neuroimaging of 28
normally developing males ages 8–11 whose prenatal testosterone had been measured
through amniotic fluid established the relationship between fetal testosterone and the
volume of gray matter (adjusted for differences in brain size) in brain regions of
interest.99 Next, neuroimaging of 101 boys and 116 girls, also 8–11 years old, was used
to assess sexual dimorphism in the same regions of interest. Boiling down a highly
technical presentation, the three regions of interest showed significant sex dimorphism
in both gray matter volume and in the correlations of fetal testosterone with adult gray
matter volume.100
In a region of the brain in the right hemisphere that has been associated with social-
cognitive and social-perceptual abilities, including empathy, greater fetal testosterone
was predictive of larger gray matter volume, and the mean gray matter volume was
larger for boys than for girls. The correlation of +.45 for fetal testosterone and gray
matter volume fits in with collateral evidence that higher fetal testosterone correlates
negatively with eye contact among infants,101 attributions of intentionality at four years
of age,102 and empathy at eight years of age.103
In a region of the brain that overlaps with key language regions, including
Wernicke’s area, and extends into Geschwind’s territory, greater fetal testosterone was
predictive of smaller gray matter volume and girls had larger gray matter volume than
boys.104 The sizable negative correlation (–.47) of fetal testosterone with the volume of
gray matter is consistent with collateral evidence that higher fetal testosterone is
correlated with smaller vocabulary at ages 12 and 24 months and that girls have larger
vocabularies than boys at those ages.105
In all three regions of interest, the relationships of fetal testosterone to gray matter
volume were consistent with other studies involving autism, conduct disorder, and
developmental language problems that disproportionately affect males.106 “In sum,” the
authors concluded, “this study provides the first evidence that FT [fetal testosterone]
has an organizing effect on some sexually dimorphic areas of the human brain. Along
with prior work on how FT influences behavior, this work highlights FT as an
important developmental mechanism contributing to sex differences in
neuroanatomy.”107
There’s more on this topic that I will not try to cover (the note has some more sources
for the curious), nor will I try to cover the continuing debate about the details.108 My
limited point is that the debate is being conducted within a consensus among
neuroscientists that the male brain is more lateralized than the female brain. The
differences are consistent with observed phenotypic sex differences in visuospatial and
verbal skills.
Sex Differences in Emotional Cognition and Memory
I promised that I would give you a glimpse of the progress that is being made in
directly linking sex differences in the brain to sex differences in the phenotype. I chose
progress in understanding sex differences in emotional response because an extensive
technical literature has been accumulating and because of the intriguing links between
the female phenotypic advantage in certain kinds of memory and the greater female
vulnerability to depression.[109] The story that is emerging has not reached the level of
settled science, but progress has been remarkable.
Emotions and some types of memory have been identified with a set of regions
located deep in the temporal lobes. Five of the most important regions are the
amygdala, hippocampus, thalamus, hypothalamus, and cingulate gyrus. For
convenience, I will use a familiar label, “limbic system,” with the understanding that
the term has fallen out of favor among neuroscientists—it amounts to “brain regions
that do emotion,” with no satisfactory way of delineating what regions do and do not
qualify.
The amygdala plays an important role in evaluating the emotional valence of a
situation (it is famously involved in fight-or-flight decisions) and in learning through
reward and punishment. It also is involved in the consolidation of emotion-laden
memory.
The region most closely associated with memory is the hippocampus, located
immediately behind the amygdala. Specifically, the hippocampus is key to the
consolidation of long-term declarative memory—the inventory of events and facts that
we can consciously call to mind. The hippocampus is especially important to episodic
memory, based on events that we have observed or participated in.110
With the advent of neuroimaging, researchers soon started investigating what parts
of the brain were activated when samples of men and women were exposed to
emotionally loaded material. The most common stimuli were sets of pictures that evoke
negative or positive responses. Negative examples are photographs of a mutilated
corpse or of a prison cell. Positive examples are photographs of a child happily blowing
out birthday candles or of champagne glasses clinking against a setting sun. More
examples are available online.111
Male-Female Differences in Response to Sexual Stimuli
Before proceeding to other kinds of emotion, let’s get one of the obvious varieties out
of the way: sex differences in response to sexual stimuli. The overall conclusion,
expressed by one of the leading researchers on sex differences in emotional response,
will not come as a shock: “Numerous studies have demonstrated that men are more
psychologically and physiologically responsive to visual sexually arousing stimuli and
display a greater motivation to seek out and interact with such stimuli.”112 Science
marches on.
A biological substrate underlies that observed sex difference. It has been known for
some time, through clinical studies of rodents and by studying humans who have
suffered seizures near the amygdala, that both the amygdala and hypothalamus are
involved in sexual behavior.113 Neuroimaging studies have now established that the
amygdala and hypothalamus in humans also show significant sex differences.
The most obvious difference is that the male amygdala and hypothalamus are
significantly larger than the female amygdala and hypothalamus, even after controlling
for total brain size.[114] Two collateral findings indicate that size makes a difference.
First, the residual size of the amygdala after neurosurgery for epilepsy has been
correlated with residual sexual drive.115 Second, while many regions of the brain do not
differ in size after controlling for total brain size (see Appendix 3), the ones that do
differ tend to have high concentrations of sex hormone receptors.116 Brain size is most
dimorphic in regions where sex hormones have had the greatest organizational effect.
The results of neuroimaging studies are consistent with the proposition that men not
only react more strongly to sexual stimuli than women, but also that men and women
have different neurocognitive profiles. An initial neuroimaging study in 2002 established
a higher level of sexual arousal in neural activation among men, but it left open two
interpretations of the results: the arousal hypothesis and the processing mode
hypothesis.117 The arousal hypothesis is that men show greater brain activation
because there is a simple sex difference in the magnitude of response to equivalent
stimuli. The greater size of the amygdala and hypothalamus might help account for this
kind of sex difference.
The processing mode hypothesis, originated by psychologist Stephan Hamann, who
tested it, is that men and women use different neural pathways. If so, men and women
matched on level of arousal will exhibit different brain activation patterns. That’s what
Hamann found. Even after equating level of sexual arousal among the male and female
participants, both through fMRI data and self-ratings, the amygdala and hypothalamus
exhibited substantially more activation among males than among females.118 The
activation among the females was not just less than that of men in the amygdala and
hypothalamus, it was slight. As for the rest of the brain, there were no areas at all in
which females showed greater activation than males.
Sex Differences in Response to Nonsexual Emotional Stimuli
The larger question is whether men and women also respond differently to emotional
stimuli more broadly defined.
Emotional responses and sex differences in memory. It is a familiar conversational
event for long-married couples: The wife vividly remembers a family event from many
years ago that the husband has completely forgotten. Over the 1980s and 1990s,
evidence accumulated that this is not a baseless stereotype. On average, women are
better than men at what psychologists call “autobiographical memory.”119 It is not
limited to mothers remembering events involving their children; it applies generally.
Evidence also accumulated for another sex difference: Women tend to be better at
remembering the minutiae of an event (labeled peripheral detail), while men tended to
be better at identifying the core events (labeled gist).[120]
The advent of fMRI has enabled researchers to relate these phenotypic sex
differences to sex differences in the functioning of the brain. The basic technique is to
expose the subjects to pictures or films while they are undergoing fMRI. A few weeks
later, the subjects are tested on their memory for the scenes they saw. With the
successfully remembered scenes in hand, the investigators can then go back to the
fMRI results and see which brain areas were active.
In 2003, Larry Cahill and Anda van Stegeren drew on the accumulating evidence
for two relationships to make a prediction. The two bodies of evidence were, first, that
the right hemisphere (which tends to play a relatively larger role in males) is biased
toward the more global aspects of a scene, while the left hemisphere (which tends to
play a relatively larger role in women) is biased toward finer detail; and, second, that
the amygdala’s role in memory for emotional material is concentrated in its right
hemisphere for men and left hemisphere for women. The prediction was that
administration of a drug that impairs amygdala function for memory (propranolol)
should have opposite effects on men and women, impairing memory for gist in men
and memory for peripheral detail in women. The results confirmed the prediction.121
Repeated studies since then have elaborated on the sex differences in functioning of
the amygdala. The level of neural activity in the amygdala is consistently predictive of
later recall: The higher the level, the greater the probability that the scene will be
remembered.122 But for both sexes, this predictiveness holds for only one hemisphere:
the left amygdala in women, the right amygdala in men. An additional finding from one
study provides a possible explanation of women’s better recall: When asked to rate the
level of emotional arousal in the pictures they were shown, the subjects’ ratings of
emotional arousal correlated with the left amygdala in both men and women. In other
words, women use the same region—the left amygdala—both for emotional reactions
and for encoding memory. In men, the emotional reactions occur in one hemisphere
and the encoding of memory in the other. It could be part of the explanation for the
greater vividness and accuracy of women’s emotional memories.
The strength and persistence of emotional responses to negative stimuli. By 2012,
Jennifer Stevens and Stephan Hamann of Emory University could call upon 80
separate neuroimaging studies with a total of 1,217 participants for a meta-analysis of
sex differences in brain activation in response to emotional stimuli.123
The meta-analysis indicated that both sexes used all the major elements of the
limbic system along with other parts of the brain. But there were also statistically
significant differences in several regions, and they formed an intriguing pattern for
negative or positive emotions.
Men and women showed significant differences in their response to negative
images in a total of 17 regions. The intriguing pattern was that women showed
significantly greater activation than males in all of the major regions of the limbic
system: the left amygdala, hippocampus, thalamus, hypothalamus, and the medial
frontal and anterior cingulate gyri. The only region among the major components of the
limbic system with a disproportionately high male activation was the left putamen, a
part of the basal ganglia that is not known to have any relationship with emotion (it has
many functions, but mostly involving control of motor skills). To put it another way,
when it came to negative emotion, females had significantly stronger responses in those
parts of the brain that play the most important part in generating emotion; males had
significantly stronger responses in regions of the brain that are only peripherally
involved in generating emotion.
Now consider what happens when men and women are exposed to positive images.
Men showed significantly greater activation than women in the left amygdala, but, with
that single exception, neither sex had significantly greater activation in any component,
major or minor, of the limbic system traditionally defined. All of the other areas in
which there were significant sex differences were elsewhere in the brain. Thus a first
and potentially important sex difference: Women have a pronounced neurological
tendency to respond to negative stimuli; men have a pronounced neurological tendency
to respond to positive stimuli.
The Stevens meta-analysis is useful for establishing the reality of an overall
relationship—in this case between regional sex differences in the brain and emotional
response—but the best individual studies tell us more about what’s going on.
Rumination. In the psychological literature, rumination refers to thoughts, typically
autobiographical, that a person mentally rehearses over and over, usually not
productively. When they are negative thoughts, rumination amounts to brooding. Taken
to an extreme, rumination can become depression. In the 1990s, Susan Nolen-
Hoeksema led several studies establishing that women were more likely than men to
ruminate, particularly in response to negative events.124 In the early 2000s, two studies
using brain imaging established a biological basis for those findings. Instead of showing
participants pictures just once, participants saw them several times. The finding in both
studies was that males quickly became habituated to a stimulus—the response in the
amygdala decreased rapidly after the first few exposures—whereas it persisted among
women.125 In 2013, researchers at the Harvard Medical School (Joseph Andreano was
the first author) tested whether this pattern replicated for both positive and negative
stimuli. It did not. As in previous studies, men showed higher amygdala activity for
novel stimuli than women no matter whether the stimulus was negative, neutral, or
positive. For familiar positive stimuli, men again had a higher response than women.
But when it came to negative stimuli, men quickly habituated while women continued
to show substantial amygdala activity even after repeated exposure. The difference was
large enough that it reached statistical significance despite the small sample size.126
Now recall the table in chapter 2 that showed the prevalence of personality
disorders by sex. Men had higher incidence rates on the autism spectrum, conduct
disorders, ADHD, and schizophrenia, among others. Women had higher prevalence on
another set, including three that involve rumination: major depression, generalized
anxiety, and post-traumatic stress disorder. The findings I have just summarized point
to a sex difference both in the intensity of initial reaction to negative stimuli and in the
persistence of that reaction, which in turn point to a difference in rumination. In
discussing the meaning of its findings, the Andreano study put them into the context of
the literature on depression and the brain:
Persons at increased risk for both depression and anxiety disorders exhibit
amygdala activity in response to both novel and familiar faces, while controls
respond only to novel faces.127
Persons at increased risk for those disorders continue to show increased
amygdala response to faces even after extended habituation.128
Persons high in trait anxiety fail to habituate to previously threat-associated
stimuli, as these stimuli continue to evoke amygdala activity after extinction
training.129
Persons with post-traumatic stress disorder show decreased habituation in
amygdala signal to repeated fearful faces.130
Individuals with more persistent amygdala response to negativity in the Andreano
sample also self-reported more anxiety and depressive symptoms than those with
faster habituation.131
Spontaneous intrusive memories and mood-congruent recall have been related to
increased amygdala activity.132
Increased engagement of the amygdala during the encoding of emotions predicts
subsequent memory.133
Putting together the pieces, Andreano and his coauthors concluded that “a
resistance to habituation to negative material in women may represent a potential
vulnerability contributing to women’s higher rate of affective disorder.”134
I have given you a typical example of how progress is being made in linking
phenotypic sex differences—in this case, a conspicuous sex difference in depression
and related disorders—and their biological underpinnings. It comprises an intricate map
of related phenomena that have been observed and implications that have been
substantiated.
At the end of it, we still are looking at an incomplete picture. But this example is
also typical in the velocity of discovery that it represents. At the turn of the twenty-first
century, it was known that the incidence of depression was higher among women, that
women ruminate more than men, and that there was probably some relationship
between those facts. Two decades later, important components of the biological
processes of depression are understood and progress continues to be rapid. When the
full etiology of depression is known, it may well be that environmental influences
explain some of the sex differences in prevalence of depression. But even now,
convincing evidence indicates that biology is also part of the story.
Recapitulation
The takeaways from this chapter’s complicated discussion can be summarized quickly:
These topics barely scratch the surface. For example, I described sex differences in
memory as they are related to the amygdala. Researchers are now integrating the
findings on the phenotypic sex differences in memory, spatial abilities, and perceptual
processing (the temporal order in which a scene and its individual features are
recognized) into an explanation that invokes sex differences in the amygdala,
hippocampus, and lateralization, all mediated by the locus coeruleus in the brain stem
and the adrenal glands (more precisely, the catecholamine system).135 For those of you
who want to get a broader sense of how much has been done and is under way in
research on sex differences in the brain and are prepared to cope with some densely
technical material, I recommend a 2019 review article, “Sex Differences in the
Developing Brain.”136
Probably the takeaway with the most long-term importance is that it’s still early
days. The progress in understanding sex differences in the brain over the last two
decades has been spectacular, but you can expect it to be eclipsed by what will be
learned in the next twenty years.
A Personal Interpretation of the Material in Part I
I reserve an entire chapter at the end of the book for my own interpretation of larger
issues, but I also end Parts I, II, and III with personal statements of my reading of the
material.
Males and females are different. A lot different. The distinctions that show up in
the phenotypic evidence on personality, abilities, educational choices, vocational
choices, and career paths are interconnected both conceptually and empirically. The
links between these phenotypic differences and the sex differences in the brain are still
only partly understood, but what we have learned so far also hangs together. I expect
that the more we learn, the more closely phenotypic differences will match up with
genetic differences. I will also assert without trying to demonstrate it that this coherent
picture fits seamlessly within the context of evolutionary pressures over millions of
years that shaped Homo sapiens.
But this is also a good time to remind you that “a lot different” does not come close
to comprehensively different. On the contrary, those who would try to make the case
that one sex is superior to another should recall some of the personality traits described
in chapter 2 on which males and females do not appear to differ. Some of those
involve personality traits that many men like to associate with being male, such as
forcefulness in expression, self-reliance, and venturesomeness; others involve traits that
many women like to associate with being female, such as openness to the inner world
of the imagination, spontaneity, and openness to new experiences. In those instances
and many other important traits such as commitment to fulfilling moral obligations and
thinking things through before acting, males and females are indistinguishable.
As the discussion of abilities in chapter 3 should have made clear, males and
females do indeed differ in their profiles of abilities—but in such complicated ways that
claiming superiority for one sex or the other is ridiculous. Or I’ll put it another way:
Claiming superiority can be done only by attaching subjective weights to different
strengths. Revealing what those weights are exposes how subjective the claims are.
As for the differences in educational and vocational choices discussed in chapter 4,
decisions about what makes for a satisfying vocational life are intimately bound up with
personal preferences and priorities. Inborn sex differences in personality and abilities
contribute to different distributions of vocational preferences and priorities. Sex
differences in this domain will be with us forever. They are not to be deplored but
celebrated.
PART II
“RACE IS A SOCIAL CONSTRUCT”
Peoples of the world have probably had words that mean “people different from us”
as long as they have had language. A common practice in isolated tribes has been to
call one’s own tribe humans and everyone else nonhumans. By the end of the sixteenth
century, the word race had entered the English language, originally used loosely to
refer to people of common descent, identified with their common culture and
geographic place. Increasing contact with the peoples of Africa and Asia led to
distinctions based on differences in appearance. In popular usage, whites in Europe
began to group races based on skin color—white, black, yellow, brown, and red.
In the eighteenth century, science got involved. Naturalists Carl Linnaeus and
Johann Blumenbach proposed formal groupings of populations into races based on
distinctive morphological features. By the middle of the nineteenth century, scholars
had decided that the different races were not only cosmetically and morphologically
distinctive but also had different personality and intellectual characteristics. The
differences amounted to a racial hierarchy, they argued, with whites on top and blacks
at the bottom.
These scientific writings occurred in the context of the Europeans’ colonization of
the New World. In South and North America alike, the intruders displaced and in many
cases eradicated the indigenous peoples who already occupied the land. They enslaved
and imported African blacks and incorporated slavery into their social systems.
The consequences were devastating. In the opening to Part I, I described the legal
status of English women through the eighteenth century as not much short of de facto
slavery. The effects of actual slavery experienced by Africans in the New World went
far beyond legal constraints, and they were far worse on every dimension of life. The
freedom granted by emancipation in America was only marginally better in practice and
the situation improved only slowly through the first half of the twentieth century.
Meanwhile, all of the indigenous cultures of the New World had been devastated
beyond recognition by the end of the nineteenth century. For the United States,
founded on ideals of liberty and equality, that record was a fatal flaw that in my view
ensured the eventual unraveling of the American project.[1]
Among scholars, the opening of the twentieth century saw a scientific backlash not
only against the idea of a racial hierarchy but against the idea of race itself. Its most
prominent spokesman was Franz Boas, a pioneering anthropologist and a fierce
opponent of what he labeled “scientific racism.”2 A British anthropologist who studied
under Boas, Ashley Montagu, took his mentor’s position to new levels of passion
(“Race is the witchcraft, the demonology of our time”) and set the rhetorical tone for
today’s academic orthodoxy. The book from which that quote is taken, Man’s Most
Dangerous Myth: The Fallacy of Race, was originally published in 1942 and remained
in print throughout the rest of the century.3
In the 1970s and 1980s, the backlash against the concept of race got new
ammunition with two propositions: The genetic differences among human populations
are insignificant, and humans left Africa too recently for important differences to have
evolved. These arguments were most famously expressed by geneticist Richard
Lewontin and paleontologist Stephen Jay Gould, both of Harvard.
In 1972, Lewontin published an article titled “The Apportionment of Human
Diversity.” In it, he analyzed genetic diversity among the different races with the tools
available at the time and found that less than 15 percent of all genetic diversity is
accounted for by differences among groups. He concluded with a passage that has
since become canonical:
The canonical version of the orthodoxy’s second proposition appeared twelve years
later, written by Gould for his regular column in Natural History magazine. “Equality
[of the races] is not given a priori,” he wrote.
Gould argued for this conclusion along several lines, some of which echoed
Lewontin. But he also offered a new proposition that quickly became popular: “[T]he
division of humans into modern ‘racial’ groups is a product of our recent history. It
does not predate the origin of our own species, Homo sapiens, and probably occurred
during the last few tens (or at most hundreds) of thousands of years.” For Gould, the
implication was obvious:
As long as most scientists accepted the ancient division of races, they expected
important genetic differences. But the recent origin of races… squares well with
the minor genetic differences now measured. Human groups do vary strikingly
in a few highly visible characters (skin color, hair form)—and this may fool us
into thinking that overall differences must be great. But we now know that our
usual metaphor of superficiality—skin deep—is literally accurate.
And so, he concluded in his 1984 article, “Say it five times before breakfast
tomorrow; more important, understand it as the center of a network of implication:
‘Human equality is a contingent fact of history.’”5 Gould stuck to that position for the
rest of his life. In an interview in 2000, he made the blanket statement that “natural
selection has almost become irrelevant in human evolution. There’s been no biological
change in humans in 40,000 or 50,000 years. Everything we call culture and civilization
we’ve built with the same body and brain.”6
The implication was obvious: The concept of race has been made up—or, put more
academically, socially constructed. Sociologists Michael Omi and Howard Winant
supplied a theoretical framework for the social construction of race in 1986 with the
publication of Racial Formation in the United States: From the 1960s to the 1980s.
Racial formation, they wrote, refers “to the process by which social, economic, and
political forces determine the content and importance of racial categories.”7 Race, they
went on to argue, is an artificial way of assigning people to groups, consolidating the
power of the majority that sets the rules for racial assignment and enabling that
majority to control racial minorities.
The orthodox sometimes come surprisingly close (given the obvious cosmetic
differences across races) to asserting that biological race is a figment of our
imaginations. I’m not talking about people at the fringes of academia. An official
statement of the American Sociological Association in 2003 told its members to beware
“the danger of contributing to the popular conception of race as biological.”8 Nor am I
talking about attitudes that have softened in the face of all that has been learned since
the sequencing of the genome. Here is part of the official statement of the American
Association of Physical Anthropology on race that was adopted on March 27, 2019:
For Jared Diamond, author of the bestselling Guns, Germs, and Steel, “[t]he reality of
human races is another commonsense ‘truth’ destined to follow the flat Earth into
oblivion.”10
It is in this context that Part II sets out to convince you that the orthodoxy about
race is scientifically obsolete.
6
Readers of Human Diversity presumably span the range in their opinions on these issues, but I’m
writing for what I conceive to be the statistically modal type: reasonably open-minded but also
accepting the intellectual received wisdom. My sense of that received wisdom regarding sex
differences is that a strict view of “gender is a social construct” is seen as too extreme—it is
accepted that gender is largely a social construct, but not entirely so. My experience with race has
been different. The intellectual received wisdom seems to be that significant racial differences in
cognitive repertoires are known to be scientifically impossible.
It was discovered that human populations are genetically distinctive in ways that
correspond to self-identified race and ethnicity.
Advances in the ability to date evolutionary changes have revealed that
evolutionary selection pressure since humans left Africa has been extensive and
mostly local to the different continents.
Raw race differences in genetic material related to cognitive repertoires are
common, not exceptional.
As we set out, let me specify what the orthodoxy gets right. Franz Boas and Ashley
Montagu were right to say that many nineteenth-century conceptions of race were
caricatures divorced from biological reality. Richard Lewontin was right that race
differences account for only a small fraction of the biological variation existing among
humans. Stephen Jay Gould was right to reject the once widely held belief that humans
evolved independently in Europe, Asia, and Africa for hundreds of thousands of years.
The orthodoxy is not wrong altogether but goes too far when it concludes that race is
biologically meaningless. We have before us an exercise in modifying our understanding
of race, not resurrecting nineteenth-century conceptions.
The orthodoxy is also right in wanting to discard the word race. It’s not just the
politically correct who believe that. For example, I have found nothing in the genetics
technical literature during the last few decades that uses race except within quotation
marks. The reasons are legitimate, not political, and they are both historical and
scientific.
Historically, it is incontestably true that the word race has been freighted with
cultural baggage that has nothing to do with biological differences. The word carries
with it the legacy of nineteenth-century scientific racism combined with Europe’s
colonialism and America’s history of slavery and its aftermath.
Scientifically, it is an error to think of races as primordial. Part of the story I will tell
describes the repeated cycles of mixing, isolation, and remixing that have gone on
among the populations that left Africa. Such cycles have also gone on within the
populations that remained in Africa, not to mention remixing by populations that
revisited Africa. As you will see, the number of groups into which people can be sorted
genetically is fluid and depends on how much genetic information is brought to bear on
the sorting.
The combination of historical and scientific reasons makes a compelling case that
the word race has outlived its usefulness when discussing genetics. That’s why I adopt
contemporary practice in the technical literature, which uses ancestral population or
simply population instead of race or ethnicity, throughout the rest of Part II.
Third Interlude: Genetic Terms You Need to Know to Read the Rest of the Book
I cannot discuss any of the propositions of Part II without using technical terms
regarding genetics. Hence it’s time for another interlude, a refresher course in this area
of biology.
Genome. A genome consists of two strands of DNA (deoxyribonucleic acid),
intertwined in the famous double helix and found in the nucleus of almost every cell of
every organism. In humans, each strand of DNA consists of a string of more than three
billion occurrences of one of four chemicals: adenine, thymine, guanine, and cytosine,
usually referred to by their first letters, A, T, G, or C. Each occurrence in each strand
is lightly linked by hydrogen bonds to a corresponding occurrence in the other strand.
They are called base pairs. Stretched out, the three billion base pairs in the nucleus of
just a single cell would be about six feet long. But the strands are curled up into a space
about six microns across—six millionths of a meter.
Site is a synonym I will use for base pair. In the technical literature, locus is often
used for this purpose, but with the advent of genome-wide association studies, locus
also is often used to designate a larger stretch of the genome.2 I always use site to refer
to a single base pair and locus when both sites and regions are involved.
WHAT DOES “SEQUENCING OF THE HUMAN GENOME” MEAN?
DNA, like some other complex molecules, has a specific physical sequence of bits. DNA has a
sequence of nucleotides arranged in base pairs. To sequence a segment of DNA is to determine the
base pair residing at each address (which also requires that you have an exact address for the
beginning and end of the segment relative to the rest of the genome). It is like a map of New York’s
Broadway showing every building and its unique address, but not what any of the buildings are used
for. Sometimes you will read about “mapping” or “decoding” the genome. They are probably
referring to the same thing as “sequencing.”
In the early 1970s, British biochemist Frederick Sanger, who had already won a Nobel Prize for
sequencing insulin, joined another British biochemist, Alan Coulson, to invent a method for
sequencing up to 80 nucleotides at a time, far more than anyone had been able to do previously. In
1977, they published an improved, faster version that was the foundation for subsequent generations
of sequencing technology. 3
During the 1980s and 1990s, limited segments of the human genome were sequenced, but it was
left to the Human Genome Project, begun in 1990, to undertake the huge collaborative effort needed
to sequence and stitch together the identities of the three billion base pairs making up the human
genome.
Drafts of the complete genome were released starting in June 2000. On April 14, 2003, the
National Human Genome Research Institute announced that the Human Genome Project had been
successfully completed and published the full sequence. 4 In the rest of this book, I will sometimes
refer to 2003 as the date for the sequencing of the genome, with the understanding that work on the
human genome had already begun using the earlier drafts.
Enough background. It’s time to recount how human ancestral populations can be
defined not by the color of their skin or any other visible characteristic, but by the
profiles of their DNA.
7
You will be seeing references to these databases in the rest of Part II:
The HGDP-CEPH database. Predating the sequencing of the genome, this database consists of
lymphoblastoid cell lines from 1,050 individuals in 52 world populations. It was assembled by the
Human Genome Diversity Project at Stanford University under the direction of Luigi Luca Cavalli-
Sforza.
The Perlegen database: In 2005, researchers at Perlegen Sciences genotyped almost 1.6 million
SNPs in 71 Americans of European, African, and Asian ancestry.
The HapMap Project: The first large database of ancestral populations, Phase 1 of the HapMap
Project, released in 2005, genotyped a million SNPs in 269 individuals drawn from four populations
—Yoruban in Nigeria, Japanese in Tokyo, Han in Beijing, and Utah residents of northern and western
European ancestry.
1000 Genomes Project: This has been the most widely used database for analyzing ancestral
populations since the release of Phase 1 in 2012. It is described in detail here.
Among the one-third of the sites that meet the technical definition of SNP (the
minor allele frequency is at least .01), almost all will be present in at least one colonist,
but their existence will be precarious because they are carried by only a few. Thus the
genetic distinctiveness of the colonists will increase with each generation because, in
each generation, thousands of SNPs will cease to vary because so few members of the
crew carried the unusual variant and the coin flips went against those SNPs.
In addition to losing diversity through SNPs that have ceased to vary (and therefore
may no longer be called SNPs), genetic drift will produce different patterns among the
SNPs that remain. Suppose we split up our crew into two groups of 50. At the time of
the split, let’s say that a given SNP has a frequency of 50 percent in both groups.
Twenty generations later, suppose it has drifted downward to a percentage of 45
percent in one of the groups and upward to 55 percent in the other. It has been a
completely random event without adaptive implications in both cases, but the two
groups have nonetheless become genetically distinctive with regard to that particular
SNP.
I have described the process in terms of a spaceship crew centuries in the future,
but the relevant population genetics theory has been established for decades. In 1943,
Sewall Wright explored the mathematics of genetic transmission in a population
distributed uniformly over a large area.4 It had long been accepted that populations
separated by geographical barriers such as mountains or oceans would be genetically
distinctive (the “island model”). Wright’s equations demonstrated that even within an
area in which a population is evenly spread without geographic barriers, the parents of
any given individual are drawn from a small surrounding region (the “isolation by
distance model”). In 1948, Gustave Malécot demonstrated mathematically that
population differences in gene frequencies may be expected to increase as a function of
geographic distance.5 In 1964, population geneticists Motoo Kimura and George Weiss
integrated these findings into what they labeled the “stepping stone model of population
structure.”6 This model postulated that a population expands outward from a single
geographic center and that occasionally a band splits off from the larger group. The
result is a series of stepwise increases in genetic drift and decreases in genetic diversity
within each band. The process came to be called a “serial founder effect.”
The model also predicted that the cumulative magnitude of genetic distinctiveness
would tend to be associated with geographic distance from the original center, because
these migrations would tend to be driven by the subpopulation’s need to find
unoccupied territory. It may seem odd that such a need existed, given how few humans
were around during the Pleistocene, but hunter-gatherers take up a lot of space—
usually about 5,000 acres per person, although, depending on local conditions, a band
of just 25 could require more than 1,000 square miles.7 By moving away from
occupied territory, humans would also usually be moving farther geographically from
the original center.
How the Earth Was Peopled
This body of theoretical work became especially relevant as paleontologists and then
geneticists found compelling evidence for what is known as the Out-of-Africa
explanation of human expansion. It started out simple. It is now exceedingly complex
and becoming more so.
Around 6 million years ago, the first hominins diverged from chimpanzees,
becoming fully bipedal sometime more than 4 million years ago.8 Homo habilis, who
was bipedal and apparently used stone tools, appeared about 2.5 million years ago.
About 2 million years ago came our likely direct ancestor, Homo erectus. Hominins
first expanded out of Africa around 1.8 to 2.1 million years ago and eventually spread
throughout Eurasia.9
LABELS FOR OUR ANCESTORS
Hominins: Refers to all branches of the human family, modern and extinct. Another word, hominid,
formerly had this meaning, but in contemporary usage, hominid refers to all modern and extinct great
apes, including us. Mnemonic for keeping them straight: Human and hominin both end with an n.
Homo erectus: Simplifying, the hominin that immediately preceded Homo sapiens.[10]
Homo sapiens: Us. All humans on planet Earth.
Anatomically modern humans: This term, abbreviated AMH in the technical literature, refers to
archaic Homo sapiens who had globular brain cases and other physiological traits of Homo sapiens
but did not leave behind substantial evidence of cultural accouterments (art, burials, ornament,
musical instruments). 11
Until the late 1980s, three theories competed to explain where and how Homo
erectus became Homo sapiens.12 The oldest of these was Franz Weidenreich’s
multiregional hypothesis, dating back to the 1940s, arguing that evolution from Homo
erectus to anatomically modern humans happened contemporaneously throughout
Africa and Eurasia but with continual gene flow across regions during the process.13 In
the early 1960s, Carleton Coon countered with the “candelabra hypothesis,” arguing
that anatomically modern humans had evolved along separate lines in Africa, Europe,
and Asia.14 The third theory was the Out-of-Africa hypothesis. It emerged in the 1980s
as paleontologists realized that the oldest fossil remains of anatomically modern
humans were always being found in eastern Africa, not in Europe or Asia.
Genetics entered the debate in 1987 when geneticist Rebecca Cann used
mitochondrial DNA, which is inherited solely from the mother, to argue that all of
today’s humans are descended from a single female who lived sometime between
99,000 and 148,000 years ago.15 A year later, paleontologists Christopher Stringer and
Peter Andrews combined the genetic evidence with the growing paleontological record
to make the case that anatomically modern humans had evolved exclusively within
Africa and only thereafter expanded to the rest of the world.[16]
By the end of the 1980s, the circumstantial evidence for the Out-of-Africa model
had won over a majority of the scientists working on the problem, but definitive
evidence required more detailed access to the genome. In 1991, population geneticist
Luigi Luca Cavalli-Sforza of Stanford University initiated the Human Genome
Diversity Project (HGDP). Geneticists around the world had been collecting blood
samples and other data from different populations. Cavalli-Sforza’s idea was to
assemble and augment these disparate sources of information, combining them into an
integrated database. Eventually, the project brought together cultured lymphoblastoid
cell lines from 1,050 individuals in 52 world populations. Preliminary results were
included in Cavalli-Sforza’s magnum opus, 1,088 pages long, The History and
Geography of Human Genes, published in 1994.17 The HGDP data broadly
substantiated the theory that the human dispersal had indeed consisted of radiating
expansions from a single center somewhere in Africa.
The finishing touch came in 2005 when scholars from Stanford, the University of
Illinois, and the University of Michigan applied the newly acquired data from the
sequenced human genome to rigorous genetic tests of two key questions: Was Africa
the origin of the human dispersal? Was the peopling of the globe characterized by the
“serial founder effect” (the loss of genetic diversity that occurs when a subpopulation
breaks off from the main population)? The analyses were excruciatingly thorough. To
take just one example, the authors performed regressions of genetic distance on
geographic distance using each of 4,210 potential centers for human dispersal. By the
end of their work, they could conclude confidently that “no origin outside Africa had
the explanatory power of an origin anywhere in Africa” and that the geographic
patterns were “consistent with a model of a serial founder effect starting at a single
origin.”18
Since 2005, advances in genetics and new paleontological evidence have
transformed the state of knowledge about the dispersal out of Africa and have also
identified a number of new questions.19 Some uncertainty has emerged about exactly
where anatomically modern humans arose. The consensus answer has long been East
Africa, but now it is thought that other regions in the continent may have played a role.
Recent fossil evidence for anatomically modern humans comes from Morocco and
dates to 315,000 years ago, more than 100,000 years earlier than the previous oldest
fossils.20 A team of physical anthropologists, archaeologists, and geneticists have
argued that morphologically and technologically varied populations of Homo sapiens
lived throughout Africa, supporting a view of a “a highly structured African prehistory
that should be considered in human evolutionary inferences, prompting new
interpretations, questions, and interdisciplinary research directions.”21 But the core
tenet of the Out-of-Africa theory—that hominins became Homo sapiens exclusively in
Africa—remains uncontested.
The immediate consequence of the exodus was the spaceship effect. Within Africa,
interbreeding continued even across substantial geographic distance. The genetic
diversity that had already accumulated within Africa was largely conserved. The few
hundred people who left Africa carried with them only a fraction of the total genetic
diversity that existed there. In that sense, subsequent generations were guaranteed to be
distinct from those who remained in Africa, if only because their descendants could not
possibly carry the full range of traits that still occurred among the peoples who
remained.
Theories about the exodus from Africa have their own uncertainties. More than one
dispersal occurred, but by what routes? When? The archaeological record combined
with recent paleogenomic evidence strongly suggests that an early wave or waves
traveled from northern Egypt across the Sinai Peninsula and were probably present in
the Levant around 200,000 years ago—much earlier than had previously been
thought.22
Tens of thousands of years later, a southern exodus occurred, probably through the
Bab-el-Mandeb Strait at the mouth of the Red Sea.23 The date of the exodus was
formerly put at about 60,000 years ago, but emerging evidence points to an earlier
date, perhaps as early as 120,000–130,000 years ago.24
Until 2016, the evidence for multiple dispersals led naturally to the assumption that
at least some members of more than one wave survived. A plausible scenario was that
an initial southern wave peopled Southeast Asia and “Sahul,” the name that has been
given to the Pleistocene landmass that included today’s Australia, New Guinea, and
Tasmania. It is now usually called Oceania by students of human populations. It was
thought that a later northern wave spread through the Levant and peopled Europe,
Central Asia, East Asia, and eventually the Americas via the Siberian bridge.25
In 2016, a new whole-genome study based on 300 genomes from 142 diverse
populations provided evidence for a one-wave scenario, indicating that just one band of
anatomically modern emigrants from Africa has descendants among today’s humans.26
The individuals in the study represented a larger and more globally representative set of
populations than ever before, with genomes sequenced at a more precise level than
ever before. But, as usual, there were complications. The genomes of Papuans in the
study gave signs that about 2 percent of their genomes might have come from an
earlier population. That’s not much, but it suggests something more complicated than a
single band of emigrants.
One thing is sure: Homo sapiens was not spreading into an unpopulated continent.
Whenever they reached Eurasia, it is now accepted that at least two archaic hominins,
the Neanderthals and Denisovans, were already in residence and that the anatomically
modern newcomers interbred with both groups.27 The admixture with the Neanderthals
was until recently dated to 50,000–65,000 years ago.28 Other evidence now suggests
that introgression with Neanderthals began earlier, with one study finding that it could
date as far back as 270,000 years, which opens up still another set of possibilities.29 It
affected the genomes of both modern Europeans and East Asians.30 Admixture with
Denisovans is found in proportions as high as 5 percent in Papuans and the
Melanesians and Australian Aboriginals, and in far lower proportions in South,
Southeast, and East Asians.31
The complications don’t stop there. There are the Hobbits to deal with—fossils
from the three-foot hominins found on the Indonesian island of Flores.32 There are the
apparent migrations from Europe back into North Africa.33 There’s the unexpected
discovery that America was not peopled by a single migration across the Bering Strait
but more likely by four separate prehistoric migrations, one of which is a mysterious
population Y that has descendants in both the Amazon and in Australasia.34 In David
Reich’s words, “the evidence for many lineages and admixtures should have the effect
of shaking our confidence in what to many people is now an unquestioned assumption
that Africa has been the epicenter of all major events in human evolution.”35
Reich’s 2018 book, Who We Are and How We Got Here, also recounts one of the
most useful discoveries in modifying the traditional view of race. It is not the case that
Europe was settled by emigrants from Africa who then adapted over tens of thousands
of years to become the peoples we now identify as European whites. Europe was
repeopled several times, as groups from various points in Central Asia and the Middle
East displaced the existing populations. What we think of as European whites are
indeed an amalgam. So are today’s East Asians, South Asians, sub-Saharan Africans,
and Amerindians. Ancestral populations did not evolve quietly in isolation. Genetic
ancestry is endlessly fluid and dynamic.
The study of the peopling of the Earth has both powerful new analytic methods
and a mother lode of ancient DNA data that has barely been tapped. I won’t try to give
a sense of the mainstream on many open questions, because everything is in such flux.
Some accessible overviews are given in the note.[36] I should add that I have had to
revise this account several times during the time it took to write Human Diversity
because of new discoveries. There’s no reason to doubt that additional discoveries are
on the way over the next several years. Stay tuned.
The Correspondence Between Genetic Differentiation and Self-Identified Race
and Ethnicity
The maps in The History and Geography of Human Genes revealed for the first time
that genetic differentiation of populations showed a continental pattern. This should not
have been surprising—if humans began in Africa, population genetics theory predicted
that the differentiation would increase along with geographic distance from Africa. But
it was nonetheless jarring to see how closely the clusters corresponded with traditional
definitions of races at the continental level. The five continents in question were Africa,
Europe, East Asia, the Americas, and Oceania.
The First Cluster Analyses of Genetic Distinctiveness Across Populations
During the 1990s and 2000s, Stanford’s Human Genome Diversity Project produced a
series of cluster analyses that successively expanded on the patterns reported in The
History and Geography of Human Genes. The first was published the same year,
1994. Cavalli-Sforza collaborated with other scholars—Anne Bowcock was the first
author—to analyze a particular type of microsatellite at 30 places on the genome, using
a sample covering 14 populations. They used cluster analysis to explore the ways in
which the 14 populations fell into groups.
FOUR THINGS TO REMEMBER ABOUT CLUSTER ANALYSIS
Many kinds of statistical cluster analysis are routinely used by disciplines in both the hard and the
soft sciences. They all have the same generic purpose: to see whether the members of a sample can
appropriately be parsed into groups. The choice of how many groups is specified by the analyst. The
usual procedure is to instruct the statistical software to produce K clusters, beginning with K = 2 and
repeating it for incremental values of K as long as the clusters being produced continue to be
informative.
Geneticists use a variety of statistical techniques to assess clustering. They fall into two broad
categories: distance-based methods and model-based methods. 37 The ones I will be discussing are all
distance-based, bringing no preconceptions to the analysis. The statistical theory and the
computational algorithms for cluster analysis are complex, and trying to describe them here would be
overkill. 38 Just remember four things about all of the methods that pass methodological muster:
1. A distance-based cluster analysis does not artificially force clusters on the basis of some a
priori categorization. The software is trying to find the best statistical fit for the raw data;
that’s all.
2. The software will dutifully identify whatever number of “clusters” it is told to produce, but
the output of the software also usually makes it easy for the investigators to see that the
results aren’t really clusters in any substantive sense.
3. Cluster analysis is exploratory. It is standard procedure for the investigators to run the
cluster analysis several times, specifying incremental numbers of clusters and asking what
differences among the subjects correspond to the statistical clusters.
4. When dealing with human populations, the clusters do not define “racial purity.” That an
individual falls into a single cluster with no admixture indicates statistical coherence given the
value of K that happens to be in use for that run. Depending on the number of polymorphic
sites in the analysis and the value of K, an individual can fall into a single cluster with no
admixture with one value of K and yet show a membership in more than one cluster with
another value of K. The only consistent aspect of cluster analyses of human populations is
that the clusters do fall along geographical lines—which is not a product of the software but
is consistent with the population genetics theory that antedated the tools for conducting
cluster analyses.
The cluster analysis used by Cavalli-Sforza and Bowcock confirmed (as have all
subsequent analyses) that the great bulk of variation in humans is within populations,
not between them, just as Lewontin said. But even with the limited measures of genetic
variation available in the early 1990s, their clusters corresponded to the geographic
origin of the subjects at the continental level.39 In 1998, a similar analysis conducted by
geneticists at Yale produced similar results.40
The methods used for this pioneering work were primitive by later standards. In
2000, Stanford geneticists led by Jonathan Pritchard developed a more sophisticated
method that they implemented through a software program called Structure.41 Among
other things, the new method allowed for mixed ancestry—individuals could be
assigned to more than one cluster, with the percentages in the various clusters summing
to 100.
In 2002, a team of scholars with the Human Genome Diversity Project (first author
was Noah Rosenberg) applied the Structure software to a sample of 1,056 individuals
from 52 populations, using 377 autosomal microsatellites.42 The individuals were
deliberately chosen from so many populations to ensure that the software’s clustering
algorithms would not be constrained by artificially narrow groups (e.g., a European
sample drawn exclusively from Dutch individuals). Their results replicated and
expanded upon the 1994 and 1998 findings. The cleanest set of clusters was produced
when K was set to 5. The five clusters once again clustered according to continents:
Africa, Europe, East Asia, the Americas, and Oceania.
The First Cluster Analysis Using Hundreds of Thousands of SNPs
The sequencing of the genome changed everything. In 2008, a team of eleven scholars
affiliated with the Human Genome Diversity Project (first author was Jun Z. Li) used
the same sample as the Rosenberg study, reduced to 51 populations and 938 persons
for technical reasons. The big difference was that the Li study was analyzing 642,690
variants instead of 377.43 Here’s what they found as K went from two to seven:
At K = 2, two sets of the 51 populations in the Li study’s database had virtually no
overlap: populations in sub-Saharan Africa versus populations in East Asia plus a few
in the Americas. All the other populations were mixtures of the two clusters.
At K = 3, the people who showed virtually no admixture across clusters consisted
of individuals from sub-Saharan Africa, today’s Europe and Mideast, and the East
Asian–Americas group. Those from Central and South Asia had varying mixtures of
the European/Mideast and East Asian/Amerind clusters.
At K = 4, the Amerindians split off to form a separate cluster.
At K = 5, the Oceania populations split off.
At K = 6, the Central and South Asians split off.
At K = 7, the configuration that the authors assessed as the most informative, those
in the Mideast split off from the Europeans.
The figure below graphically shows the results for the analysis at K = 7.
It is a fascinating graphic. It combines 938 vertical lines, one for each person in the
sample. Each line is partitioned into segments with lengths that correspond to that
person’s “ancestry coefficients.” When only one pattern is represented, the individual
belongs entirely to that cluster—as in large portions of the lines for Africa, Europe,
East Asia, and the Americas. In contrast, look at the Mideast segment of the figure.
Interpreted colloquially (remember that the labels for the clusters were added only after
each individual’s ancestry had been estimated), most of the lines have a mix of
Mideastern, European, and Central or South Asian ancestry.44
What struck me most about the Li analysis is what happened when the number of
clusters went from five to seven. As in the 2002 study, the first five clusters
corresponded to the five continental ancestral populations. But the two new subsidiary
clusters that emerged when K = 7 corresponded to commonsense observation. When K
= 5, the Li study produced a cluster that corresponded to the classic definition of
Caucasian—an odd agglomeration of peoples from Europe, North Africa, the Mideast,
South Asia, and parts of Central Asia. There had been a reason why physical
anthropologists had once combined these disparate populations—all of them have
morphological features in common—but it had never made sense to people who
weren’t physical anthropologists.45 With K = 7, one of the new clusters split off the
peoples of the Mideast and North Africa and the other split off the peoples of Central
and South Asia—precisely the groups that had always been visibly distinctive from
Europeans and from each other in the Caucasian agglomeration.
The figure below shows another perspective on the separation of members of the
51 subpopulations. The note gives details of the analysis.[46] Highly simplified, you’re
looking at the genetic distance of each of the 938 people in the study from the other
937.
Source: Li, Absher, Tang et al. (2008): Fig. S3B. The authors computed a 938-by-938
Identity-by-State (IBS) matrix using the software package PLINK, which was then
factor analyzed for all samples and for seven regions separately.
As I close this discussion, it is time for another reminder that the genetic distinctiveness
of populations is minor compared to their commonalities and that all of the clusters and
genetic distances are based on SNPs that for the most part are not known to affect any
phenotype. The material here does not support the existence of the classically defined
races, nor does it deny the many ways in which race is a social construct. Rather, it
communicates a truth that geneticists expected theoretically more than half a century
ago and that has been confirmed by repeated empirical tests: Genetic differentiation
among populations is an inherent part of the process of peopling the Earth. It is what
happens when populations successively split off from parent populations and are
subsequently (mostly) separated geographically.
The inescapable next question is whether we’re looking at a phenomenon that has
been confined to SNPs that have no effect on the phenotype, or whether the same
thing has been happening to SNPs that do have such an effect. We will explore that
topic by looking at what has been learned about evolution since humans left Africa.
8
A pillar of the orthodox position is that humans left Africa so recently that they
haven’t had time to differentiate themselves genetically in ways that would affect
cognitive repertoires. That position is now known to be wrong, as indicated by
Proposition #6. Presenting the evidence for Proposition #6 involves a number of
technical issues regarding evolution, and so it’s time for another interlude.
Fourth Interlude: Evolutionary Terms You Must Know to Read the Rest of the
Book
Evolution refers to the process whereby the first primitive forms of life became the
biosphere we know today, a process independently understood in its modern form by
Charles Darwin and Alfred Russel Wallace in the 1830s and 1840s and famously
described in 1859 by Darwin in On the Origin of Species.
Mutation. The evolution of completely new traits—hearing or eyesight, for
example—requires mutations. Mutations have several causes. The chemicals that make
up the base pairs can decay or be damaged. The process for correcting those errors (a
capability for DNA repair is built into every cell) is pretty good, but it sometimes makes
mistakes. Similarly, errors can occur during DNA replication. Mutations can be caused
by different forms of radiation or exposure to certain chemicals. These and other
causes can affect the chemical in one letter of a base pair or the number of repetitions
in microsatellites. They can result in small insertions or deletions of bases (indels), and
structural variations in regions of DNA.1
An extensive literature debates the incidence of mutations and whether the rate has
increased or decreased over time. The rate is usually expressed in incomprehensibly
small numbers (e.g., 1.29 × 10–8 per position per generation). But the same study that
produced that estimate thankfully gives an intuitively useful way of thinking about it: It
implies that a newborn with 30-year-old parents will carry 75 new SNV mutations and
6 new short indel mutations.2
The process of mutation is a matter of chance. The great majority of mutations
have no effect or a negative effect—random changes are unlikely to add something
positive to highly evolved traits.3 “Negative effect” in evolutionary terms refers to a
reduction in reproductive fitness (often just fitness), the technical term for describing
reproductive success, measured in the simplest case by the number of offspring one
produces.4 Even when a mutation has a positive effect on fitness, it initially happens to
a single individual. For that mutation to spread from one individual throughout the
population requires a great deal of luck. Exactly how much luck was calculated almost
a century ago by British geneticist J. B. S. Haldane: If a given allele has a selective
advantage of s, the chance that it will sweep through a large population and become
fixed is 2s.5 For example, if the selective advantage conferred by an allele is 5 percent
(a large advantage for a single allele), it has only a 10 percent chance of eventually
becoming fixed. Even a highly favorable mutation has a precarious place in the genome
until it has successfully propagated to many people.
Allele frequency. The evolution of population differences in traits that already exist
is driven by changes in allele frequency. Suppose that some trait is determined by 100
SNPs and that the average allele frequency for the alleles that promote that trait is .20
among Bretons and .60 among the Hakka. The trait in question will probably be more
pronounced or more common among the Hakka than among Bretons, but the trait is
not exclusively Hakka. On the contrary, the luck of the draw means that some Bretons
will have a more pronounced expression of that trait than some Hakka.
CALCULATING AND EXPRESSING AN ALLELE FREQUENCY
The five main candidates driving evolution through either mutations or changes in
allele frequencies are natural selection, sexual selection, migration, introgression, and
genetic drift. You have already encountered genetic drift in chapter 6. Here are quick
summaries of the other four:
Natural selection. The most famous of the mechanisms for translating infusions of
new genetic variations into effects on traits is the principle of natural selection, the
momentous insight achieved independently by Charles Darwin and Alfred Russel
Wallace. Here is the way Darwin put it in On the Origin of Species: “If variations
useful to any organic being do occur, assuredly individuals thus characterized will have
the best chance of being preserved in the struggle for life; and from the strong principle
of inheritance they will tend to produce offspring similarly characterized. This principle
of preservation, I have called, for the sake of brevity, Natural Selection.”6
Both Darwin and Wallace were inspired by the same empirical observation: All
species are so fertile that their populations should increase exponentially, and yet the
sizes of populations are relatively stable. The necessary implication is that significant
numbers of any generation fail to reproduce.
Another empirical observation was that no two members of a species are exactly
alike. Furthermore, it was obvious to Darwin and Wallace that many of the variations
within a species are heritable. Hence Darwin’s and Wallace’s key inference: Some
variations facilitate the transmission of traits to the next generation; some variations
impede that transmission. Variations increase or diminish reproductive fitness.
Evolution selects for reproductive fitness.
Sexual selection. Sexual selection is a form of natural selection, but it doesn’t
necessarily have anything to do with an organism’s abilities to survive threats to life.
On the contrary, some signals that attract the opposite sex can reduce reproductive
fitness. For example, bright coloring in male birds makes them more attractive to
females but also makes them more visible to predators.
Sexual selection is all about finding someone to mate with and having offspring that
survive to the age of reproduction. Reproductive fitness is irrelevant. A frivolous
example, but one that makes the point: Whether someone is left-handed or right-
handed is genetically determined, with left-handers being in a small minority—about 10
percent of the population.7 There is no reason to think that left-handedness in and of
itself augments reproductive fitness. But if for some reason women were to develop a
strong sexual preference for left-handed men, it would not take long on an evolutionary
time scale for the proportion of left-handed men to increase drastically.
What’s your best chance of passing on your genes? It depends on your role in
mating versus parenting, which in turn depends on your sex, which in turn depends
(you may be surprised to learn) on the size of your gametes. Gamete refers to a germ
cell that is able to unite with another to sexually reproduce. By biological definition, the
male sex is the one that produces the smaller gametes (in human males, spermatozoa),
and the female sex is the one that produces the larger gametes (in human females,
eggs).8
Why is it that so many living things are characterized by two sexes that produce
gametes of very different size? Because as an empirical matter, that’s the arrangement
that gives the best odds that progeny will survive. The process can be modeled
mathematically. Assuming a positive correlation between the size of the fertilized cell
and its survival, a stable equilibrium is often a bifurcation of the population into two
types characterized by extremely different gamete sizes. The intuitive explanation of
this result is that any fertilized cell resulting from a large gamete begins the struggle for
life with the advantage of a stockpile of nourishment; the production of many small
gametes is advantageous because the number of fertilizations is maximized. Two
intermediate-sized gametes don’t work as well because neither is fully committed either
to nourishing the fertilized cell or maximizing the number of fertilizations, and this
mediocrity tends not to prosper.
Now comes the evolutionary kicker that is at the source of so much contemporary
argument about sex roles and child-rearing: Among almost all living things that
reproduce sexually, the sex with the smaller gametes (males) provides less care after
fertilization than the sex with the larger gametes (females).
It makes evolutionary sense. In most mammalian species, the most efficient way
for a male to ensure that his genes survive is to impregnate as many females as
possible.9 The most efficient way for a female to ensure that her genes survive is to
make the most of her limited opportunities to produce offspring, which means being
choosy about the quality of the male’s fitness and devoting a lot of effort to keeping the
offspring alive. In his book Male, Female, evolutionary psychologist David Geary
makes the point with an extreme case: A male elephant can impregnate several females
in a single day. A female elephant must carry a single offspring for 22 months before it
is even born, let alone weaned. Female elephants don’t get many chances to pass on
their genes. The female elephants who succeed tend to be the ones who are most adept
at mating with healthy males and who are devoted to the welfare of their babies.10
Homo sapiens is an outlier among mammals, with the male providing more paternal
care than is customarily observed—but it’s still not a lot compared to the burden
carried from fertilization onward by the female.
Migration. Different human populations have lived in contact with each other as
long as there have been humans, and occasionally their members have had sex with
each other and produced children. Over a long period of time, these offspring alter the
gene pool.
Such intermingling through migration has been going on for tens of thousands of
years. And yet contemporary human groups, including different ethnicities within the
same continental ancestral population, still have distinctive genetic signatures in cluster
analyses and are still visually distinguishable to a greater or lesser degree. Why haven’t
humans long since become a uniform shade of beige with a common set of
physiological features?
It’s not mysterious. Even though the interbreeding of populations has gone on for
so long, usually it has not happened on a large scale over many generations, which
means it is easily possible for populations to mingle some aspects of their gene pools
and yet remain visually distinct. Suppose that back in the thirteenth century a Chinese
woman had borne a child with a visitor from Italy, Marco Polo. That child was half
Italian and half Chinese and probably looked like a mix. But the second generation of
that initial union was only a quarter Italian, the third generation one-eighth, the fourth
generation one-sixteenth—and by that time none of Marco Polo’s descendants had the
slightest visible trace of their Italian ancestry.
This has been a common experience throughout history: Interbreeding produces a
visible blend in the first generation of progeny, but the heritage of one of the parents
wins out over the long run. It remains surprisingly true even today: America has one of
the most ethnically diverse populations in the world, with the most opportunities for
children of mixed parentage to mate with other children of mixed parentage, and yet,
for example, among American women who have a European American and a Chinese
American parent, 82 percent marry a European American husband, putting their
children (now only a quarter ethnically Chinese) on the road toward eventual
indistinguishability from fully European Americans.11
Even though encounters among human populations have not led to the degree of
visible blending one might intuitively expect, those encounters can nonetheless
introduce changes that persist in the gene pool forever after. Suppose, for example, that
Marco Polo had passed on an allele that conferred protection against a deadly pathogen
afflicting the Chinese. In this hypothetical case, it would still be true that several
generations later his descendants in China would look exactly like any other Chinese
and would carry few distinctively Italian alleles—but one of them could be that highly
valuable antipathogen allele, already in the process of spreading among the Chinese
population without leaving a visible trace.12
Introgression. The fastest way to introduce completely new genes into a species,
orders of magnitude faster than mutation, is interbreeding with another species
—introgression.13 It’s not common. A breeding wall usually prevents different species
from producing offspring. If they succeed, those offspring are often infertile (e.g.,
mules, produced by the interbreeding of horses and donkeys). But some species are
interfertile, meaning that introgression produces fertile offspring. Introgression is likely
to produce significant evolutionary results because of the sheer quantity of new genetic
variants introduced into both genomes.
The 1000 Genomes Project. In addition to the foregoing evolutionary terms, you
need to know something about the 1000 Genomes Project that will be referenced in the
rest of this chapter and will figure prominently in chapter 9.
The 1000 Genomes Project had its inception in September 2007, when an
international group of geneticists convened at Cambridge University to plan a collection
of sequenced genomes from individuals around the world. The goal was to find genetic
variants with allele frequencies of at least .01 in a broad range of populations. The
Phase 1 database for the 1000 Genomes Project assembled information on more than
39 million SNPs and other genetic variants for 1,094 persons grouped into 14 ancestral
subpopulations. Five of them came from Western and Northern Europe, three from
East Asia, three from sub-Saharan Africa, and three from the Americas. In the
subsequent discussion and the next chapter, I limit my use of the Phase 1 data to the
subpopulations representing the Big Three continental ancestral populations that are at
the center of discussions about race differences: sub-Saharan Africa (hereafter
“Africans”), Western and Northern Europe (“Europeans”), and East Asia (“Asians”).
The subpopulations for Africa are the Luhya in Western Kenya, Yoruba in Nigeria, and
African Americans in the American Southwest. The subpopulations for Europe are
British samples drawn from England and Scotland, Finns in Finland, Tuscans from
Italy, and Americans of Northern and Western European ancestry from Utah. The
subpopulations for East Asia are Han in South China, Han students in Beijing, and
Japanese in Tokyo. Details on the populations are given in the note.[14]
Rethinking the Nature of Recent Human Evolution
How much evolution took place after humans left Africa? Before the genome was
sequenced, geneticists had few tools for exploring that question. Some things looked as
if they must have evolved after the dispersal—most obviously light skin among
Europeans and Chinese and lactase persistence in Europeans. But otherwise the story
of recent evolution was inaccessible.
Then came the sequencing of the genome, “a turning point in the study of positive
selection in humans,” as evolutionary geneticist Pardis Sabeti put it.15 It changed just
about everything about the study of human evolution since humans left Africa: the type
of natural selection at the center of geneticists’ attention, the strategies they used to
identify the specific genes and SNPs involved, and the methods for implementing those
strategies.
Early on, a team of anthropologists and geneticists (first author was John Hawks)
took advantage of the newly sequenced genome to test the provocative hypothesis that
adaptive human evolution has recently accelerated. The transition to agriculture in
some populations about 10,000 years ago led to drastic changes in diet, population
density, technology, economics, and culture in general. Evolutionary biologists are still
trying to understand the many intense evolutionary pressures that were generated.
Among the most urgent was the need to adapt to the lethal epidemic diseases—
smallpox, malaria, yellow fever, typhus, and cholera—that followed the introduction of
agriculture. The Hawks study concluded that “the rapid cultural evolution during the
Late Pleistocene created vastly more opportunities for further genetic change, not
fewer, as new avenues emerged for communication, social interactions, and
creativity.”16 It was a radical departure from the conventional wisdom, but just the
beginning of a wholesale rethinking of recent evolution.
From Darwin’s Insights to the Modern Synthesis
The word genetics wasn’t even coined until 1905, soon after Gregor Mendel’s
pioneering work was rediscovered after having been ignored for almost half a century.
The first half of the twentieth century saw a series of landmark discoveries about the
biology of genetic transmission, led by Thomas Hunt Morgan in the early decades and
culminating in the discovery of the double-helix structure of DNA by James Watson
and Francis Crick in 1953.17
From the beginning, scientists were aware of the potential importance of genetics
for explaining how evolution worked at the molecular level. One of the earliest
theoretical findings was genetics’ equivalent to Newton’s first law of motion:
identification of the circumstances under which the frequencies of alleles at a given site
would remain stable.18 Discovered independently by Godfrey Hardy and Wilhelm
Weinberg, who both published in 1908, it became known as the Hardy-Weinberg
equilibrium. It provided the baseline against which to identify and measure disturbances
to the equilibrium—the process of evolution.
But there was a problem in reconciling Darwinian evolution and Mendelian
genetics. The Darwinian model posited excruciatingly slow and imperceptibly small
modifications in continuous phenotypic traits. In Mendelian genetics, the phenotype
changed abruptly depending on a few discrete alleles—for example, the alleles
determining the color or shape of the seeds among Mendel’s pea plants.
The tension was resolved by three giants born within three years of each other:
Ronald Aylmer Fisher (1890–1962), J. B. S. Haldane (1892–1964), and Sewall Wright
(1889–1988). From 1915 through the mid-1930s, they laid the mathematical
foundation for what has become known as the modern evolutionary synthesis, or,
within the field, simply “the modern synthesis.”
The first among equals was probably Fisher, an authentic genius (in the process of
making his seminal contributions to genetics, he also made seminal contributions to
modern statistics). His 1918 article “The Correlation Between Relatives on the
Supposition of Mendelian Inheritance” is foundational, demonstrating that gradual
variation in a trait could be the result of Mendelian inheritance.19 In so doing, he
incorporated the polygenic nature of traits and the importance of allele frequency
(though he did not use those terms). I have already mentioned J. B. S. Haldane’s
coefficient s for expressing the probability that a mutation will go to fixation and Sewall
Wright’s work in the theory of genetic differentiation among populations. But these are
just examples of a cascade of contributions that Fisher, Haldane, and Wright had made
by the mid-1930s. They built the theories of population and quantitative genetics that
still guide these disciplines today.
A Shift in Focus from Hypothesis-Driven Candidate Gene Studies to Hypothesis-
Generating Genome-Wide Studies
Candidate gene studies. From the 1930s through the rest of the century, the number
of things that geneticists could do with this magnificent body of theory was limited.
Perforce, geneticists had to adopt strategies that worked despite only fragmentary
knowledge of what was going on within the genome. One was the “candidate gene”
approach.20
It began with Anthony Allison’s observation back in the early 1950s that sickle cell
anemia was geographically limited within Africa to areas where malaria was endemic.
Why should people who survived in an environment afflicted by malaria be peculiarly
vulnerable to a blood disease unknown elsewhere? Allison hypothesized that a mutation
with a huge s value because it protected against malaria had swept through the
population even though it had the lesser deleterious effect of susceptibility to sickle cell
anemia. A mutation that did both of those things was probably in that part of the
genome involving blood. Allison picked the Hemoglobin-B gene as his candidate gene
and subsequently identified a specific mutation that had been the target of natural
selection.21
A more sophisticated way of identifying candidate genes, called linkage analysis,
enabled progress during the 1980s in understanding genetically based diseases such as
Huntington’s disease, Alzheimer’s disease, and some forms of cancer.22 But by the
mid-1990s, researchers working on diseases such as schizophrenia, bipolar disorder,
and diabetes were stymied. Linkage analysis was useful for diseases that were caused
by alleles with large effects, but it produced inconclusive and often contradictory
results for complex diseases that were caused by many alleles with small effects.
Evolutionary geneticists also used the candidate gene approach for exploring the
known adaptations that had occurred after the dispersal from Africa, such as lightened
skin. But such obvious examples of recent evolution were rare. As geneticist Joshua
Akey explained it, candidate gene studies have two major limitations.23 One is that they
require a priori hypotheses about which genes have been subject to selection, but few
traits lend themselves to a priori hypotheses. This is true of many physiological traits,
but especially of cognitive ones. The relevant alleles surely involve brain function and
might have something to do with hormones, but that’s not nearly specific enough to
identify a candidate gene. Ingenious attempts to do so failed. Perhaps the most
frustrating example was the search for the genetic basis of cognitive ability using the
candidate gene approach. Years of intensive effort in the late 1990s and early 2000s
failed to identify even a single replicable genetic locus affecting it.24
The second limitation of candidate gene studies was how to determine whether
natural selection was really involved even if a candidate gene seemed to be panning
out. Perhaps the alleles were under selection pressure. But perhaps genetic drift was at
work, or some other mechanism that had nothing to do with natural selection. The
available theoretical models weren’t good enough to yield precise predictions, and the
statistical tests were often inadequate for robust conclusions.
Genome-wide association study (GWAS), pronounced “g-wasp” without the “p.”
GWAS is an acronym now as ubiquitous in the technical literature as SNP. The
technique itself is usually abbreviated as GWA. The idea behind it was first expressed
in 1996 in an article in Science by Stanford geneticist Neil Risch and Yale
epidemiologist Kathleen Merikangas. “Has the genetic study of complex disorders
reached its limits?” they asked. Their answer put geneticists on course to a new and
productive technique:
We argue below that the method that has been used successfully (linkage
analysis) to find major genes has limited power to detect genes of modest
effect, but that a different approach (association studies) that utilizes candidate
genes has far greater power, even if one needs to test every gene in the
genome. Thus, the future of the genetics of complex diseases is likely to require
large-scale testing by association analysis.25
One of the unexpected findings since the sequencing of the genome has been how
much evolution has taken place in the recent past, continuing up to the present. Most
of it has occurred through changes in standing variation. Some of it has occurred
through introgression.
Evolution Through Selection Within Homo Sapiens
Evolutionary geneticists wasted no time in using the new tools that became available
after the sequencing of the genome. In a 2009 article, just six years after the final draft
was published, Joshua Akey could assemble the results of 21 studies that had already
used genome-wide scans for natural selection.46 Focusing on the seven studies that
used the largest samples at that time, the HapMap and Perlegen databases, he
constructed an integrated map of positive selection.47
The aggregate numbers from just those seven were startlingly large. A total of
5,110 distinct regions of the genome were identified by at least one study,
encompassing 14 percent of the genome and 23 percent of all genes. A total of 722
regions containing 2,465 genes were identified in two or more studies. His conclusion:
Since then, the number of loci believed to be under selection has continued to
grow. In 2012, a team predominantly from Stanford used a different method,
employing a measure called ROH (“runs of homozygosity”), applying it to the
combined data from the HGDP-CEPH and HapMap databases.49 They identified 69
regions that they labeled “ROH hotspots.” The top 10 included genes involving cell
function, connective tissue development, the brain, vision, the central nervous system,
and skin pigmentation. Five of the top 10 regions had not previously been identified as
sources of recent selection pressure.
In 2013, Sharon Grossman of the Broad Institute of Harvard and MIT and her
colleagues published the results for a method called CMS (Composite of Multiple
Signals) designed to pinpoint specific variants within the genetic regions under
selection.50 Initial applications of this method yielded an additional 86 regions showing
a high probability of selection pressure, along with hundreds of specific genes that
appear to have been under recent selection pressure. These include genes involving
hearing, immunity, infectious disease, metabolism, olfactory receptors, pigmentation,
hair and sweat, sensory perception, vision, and brain development.
In 2016, another international team made progress in identifying human adaptation
within the last 2,000 years. Using a new method, the Singleton Density Score, applied
to a sample of the ancestors of modern Britons, they found strong signals in favor of
selection for lactase persistence, blond hair, and blue eyes. Their conclusion: “Our
results suggest that selection on complex traits has been an important force in shaping
both genotypic and phenotypic variation within historical times.”51
Also in 2016, Daniel Schrider and Andrew Kern published a sophisticated new
machine-learning technique called Soft/Hard Inference through Classification. They
applied it to six populations that have low levels of historical admixture: three of sub-
Saharan Africans (two from West Africa, one from Kenya), one of non-Latino whites
in Utah, one of Japanese in Japan, and one of Amerindians in Peru. Their method
identified 1,927 “distinct selective sweeps,” of which 1,408 were ones not previously
identified.52 The work by Schrider and Kern also substantiated the importance of
changes in standing variation. Of the total 1,927 sweeps they identified, 92.2 percent
were soft, which accounts for the title of their article, “Soft Sweeps Are the Dominant
Mode of Adaptation in the Human Genome.” Geneticists Rajiv McCoy and Joshua
Akey summarized the implications this way:
I have restricted myself to a handful of the global and largest studies. The total
body of work is far greater. In 2009, Joshua Akey had 21 studies to work with. A 2016
review article titled “Fifteen Years of Genomewide Scans for Selection” included an
additional 52 studies.54
In response to such findings, a controversy has arisen. Are we really looking at
natural selection or at genetic drift due to purifying and background selection?55 A team
of researchers at the Max Planck Institute for Evolutionary Anthropology set out to
answer that question through an analysis of contemporary allele frequencies in the
1000 Genomes Project combined with evidence from a high-quality genome of a
45,000-year-old anatomically modern human from Ust’-Ishim in Siberia. Their answer,
published in 2016, was that many of the most strongly differentiated alleles between
Africans and Eurasians had not risen in frequency after the dispersal from Africa.
“Nevertheless, our results provide clear evidence that local adaptation contributed to
these allele frequency changes in European populations, as strongly differentiated
alleles in Europeans are enriched in likely functional variants.”56
“Evidence” is the correct word, not “proof.” Techniques for discriminating natural
selection from other sources of change in standing variation are still being refined. The
state of knowledge is still nowhere close to a firm number for specifying how much
total evolutionary change there has been, how much of that total has been an adaptive
response to natural selection, how much has been a nonadaptive response to selection
on correlated traits, and how much has occurred by genetic drift.57 What can be said
more confidently is that the regions under selective pressure since the dispersal from
Africa are in fact extensive; that the methods for identifying these regions have steadily
improved since the earliest studies at the beginning of the century; and that each new
compilation shows a new and substantial amount of the genome has been influenced—
both directly and indirectly—by selection.
Evolution Through Introgression
Descendants of those who left Africa experienced significant introgression of genes
from other hominins. Two hominins are definitely involved: Neanderthals and
Denisovans. Others might eventually be identified.58
Scientists have known since the 1860s that a race of advanced hominins other than
Homo sapiens once lived in Europe. More recently, they have established that
Neanderthals lived in Asia as well. They descended from Homo erectus along a
separate line from Homo sapiens. The timing of the split has been estimated as early as
800,000 and as late as 400,000 years ago. It is now established that anatomically
modern humans bred with both Neanderthals and another, recently discovered archaic
hominin, the Denisovans, whose discovery in a cave near southern Siberia’s Altai
Mountains was announced in 2010. Introgression between Denisovans and Homo
sapiens left traces in modern East Asians and in peoples from New Guinea and
elsewhere in the Pacific. It is argued that Denisovan gene variants may also account for
Tibetans’ ability to function at high altitudes.59
Interbreeding between Neanderthals and Homo sapiens occurred in several places
and times in Europe and at least to some extent in East Asia, leaving traces of
Neanderthal DNA in modern Europeans and East Asians amounting to about 1 to 2
percent of the genome. It appears that Neanderthal alleles may have helped humans
adapt to non-African environments; Neanderthals are argued to have been not only
cold-adapted but hyperarctic-adapted.60 Another study concluded that “the major
influence of Neandertal introgressed alleles is through their effects on gene
regulation.”61 The safest conclusion at the moment is that most of the story is yet to be
told. The balance of probability says that most of the variants picked up from the
Neanderthals were neutral or negative, but the Neanderthals had probably been
adapting to conditions and pathogens not found in Africa for hundreds of thousands of
years and are bound to have carried many variants that would have been advantageous
to the newcomers. Chances are good that humans picked up some of them.
The new findings about recent evolution from natural selection and introgression
have triggered a spirited debate that is of greater interest to population geneticists than
to us. The neutral theory of molecular evolution has been an intellectual centerpiece of
population genetics since the early 1980s. It continues to have vigorous defenders.
Responding to an attack, an international team of seven population geneticists (first
author was Jeffrey Jensen) concludes that “it is now abundantly clear that the
foundational ideas presented five decades ago by Kimura and Ohta are indeed
correct.”62 On the other side are geneticists who think that the debate is over. “We
argue that the neutral theory was supported by unreliable theoretical and empirical
evidence from the beginning, and that in light of modern, genome-scale data, we can
firmly reject its universality,” wrote geneticists Andrew Kern and Matthew Hahn in
2018. “The ubiquity of adaptive variation both within and between species means that
a more comprehensive theory of molecular evolution must be sought.”63 If history is a
guide, the best bet is that some sort of theoretical synthesis will arise from this dialectic.
Whatever form it takes, it will have to accommodate the evidence for far more recent
evolution than was anticipated before the genome was sequenced.
Recent Selection Pressure Has Been Mostly Local
From the dawn of the genomics era, studies of recent selection have also found that
“local adaptation” was widespread, with “local” meaning that the genes under selection
varied by continent. An early analysis of local adaptation using the HapHap database
was published in 2006 by a team of geneticists (first author was Benjamin Voight).
They examined regions of the genome under selection pressure for three populations:
Yoruba (a Nigerian tribe), Europeans from a mix of Northern and Western European
countries, and East Asians (a mix of Chinese and Japanese). Of the 579 regions, 76
percent were unique to one of the three populations, 22 percent were shared by two of
the three, and only 2 percent were shared by all three populations.64 In the authors’
judgment, the degree to which selection occurred independently is probably
underestimated by these percentages.[65] In any case, these events represent quite
recent selection—“average ages of ∼6,600 years and ∼10,800 years in the non-African
and African populations respectively,” in the authors’ judgment.66
The same pattern has been found repeatedly. In Joshua Akey’s literature review of
21 early studies of recent selection published in 2009, he found that “∼80% of the 722
loci observed in multiple scans show evidence of local adaptation.”67 In that same year,
an international team funded by the Max Planck Society and the German government
published results using the HGDP-CEPH database you encountered in chapter 7. This
study employed its own distinctive method of identifying regions under selection
pressure but got familiar results. Grouping the 51 populations into their continental
ancestral location (European, East Asian, Central/South Asian, Middle Eastern,
Oceanian, and Amerindian), 68 percent of the regions under selection were under
selection for a single population. Another 20 percent were under selection in just two of
the six. Only 1 percent were under selection in all six populations.68
The six ethnic African ethnicities had little overlap with any of the non-African
ethnicities.69 Of the 632 regions identified as under positive selection, at least one of
the African populations was represented in 146 of them. Of those 146 regions, 82
percent were represented by a single African ethnicity. Just one was shared by two
African populations. Only 18 percent were shared by an African population and one or
more non-African populations.70
Principal Component Analysis Revisited
Recall from chapter 7 the patterns shown when noncoding genetic markers were
analyzed using principal component analysis. There’s no reason why the same analysis
could not be applied to functional variants. In 2013, an international team of geneticists
(first author was Xuanyao Liu) did so, using yet another method of identifying
signatures of positive selection, applied to the 14 populations of Phase 3 of the 1000
Genomes Project, that identified 405 regions under selection. The figure below shows
the results.
Source: Adapted from Liu, Ong, Pillai et al. (2013): Fig. 5C.
The meaning of the abbreviations: LWK: Luhya in Kenya. YRI: Yoruba in Nigeria. ASW:
African Americans in the Southwest. MKK: Maasai in Kenya. JPT: Japanese in Tokyo.
CHB: Chinese in Beijing. CHS: Chinese in Singapore. CHD: Chinese in Denver. MAS:
Malays in Singapore. INS: Indians in Singapore. GIH: Gujarati Indians in Houston. MXL:
Mexicans in Los Angeles. CEU: Europeans in Utah. TSI: Tuscans in Italy. The Mexican
population is an unknown mix of European and Amerindian ancestry.
The specifics are different from the profiles in the principal component analysis
shown in chapter 7—to be expected, since the nature of the datum entered in each cell
of the matrix for the figure above is completely different from those entered in the
earlier figure. Some of the subpopulations are different as well.71 But the clusters
formed by the 14 populations are distinct and familiar. When geneticists use noncoding
genetic variation from multiple populations, those populations are genetically distinctive
in ways that broadly correspond to self-identified race and ethnicity. When geneticists
use genetic variation that is not only functional but has been under selection pressure
since the dispersal from Africa, the same correspondence usually appears.
Recapitulation
Much has changed since the 1980s when it was still possible for Stephen Jay Gould to
believe that evolution since humans left Africa couldn’t be more than skin deep. The
main events were the sequencing of the genome and then the advent of genome-wide
scans. Those analyses in turn shifted the center of attention from evolution through
mutation to evolution through changes in allele frequencies. The same analyses
uncovered unexpectedly large portions of the genome that have been under recent
selection. Like the results of the cluster analyses of noncoding SNPs discussed in
chapter 7, the new analyses showed that the regions of the genome under selection
varied by geography and population ancestry. Or to summarize it in the words of
Proposition #6, evolutionary selection pressure since humans left Africa has been
extensive and mostly local.
9
This chapter is about raw ancestral population differences in SNPs that are
statistically related to cognitive repertoires—“raw” meaning that a great deal of work
remains to be done before the significance of such differences is understood.
Until a few years ago, this topic was still terra incognita. Only a handful of
statistical relationships between specific SNPs and cognitive traits had been identified.
But the growth in that number has been phenomenal, paralleling the growth in the
number of SNPs associated with diseases and physiological traits. To illustrate what’s
been happening, consider the GWAS Catalog. It was begun in 2008 by the National
Human Genome Research Institute, part of the U.S. National Institutes of Health.1 The
first year with a published GWAS was 2005, when two studies reported a grand total of
two SNPs.2 In 2018 alone, the GWAS Catalog added 17,182 previously unidentified
SNPs. Here’s what the history looks like:
As of the end of May 2019, the catalog included 3,469 studies reporting 136,286
variants. The total number of unique variants was 89,544. And that’s just a fraction of
the total number of variants that have been associated with phenotypic traits at lesser
levels of statistical significance. That total is over a million, residing in databases
maintained by university and private sector research centers scattered around the
world.
Hardly any analyses of this burgeoning knowledge base have compared results for
different continental ancestral populations (which for readability I will subsequently
abbreviate to “continental populations”). Researchers have been wary of such
comparisons because the results can’t be trusted. Paradoxically, the reason they can’t
be trusted has indirectly become the reason that continental population differences will
soon be studied intensively.
Why Continental Population Differences Will Be Studied
For the last quarter century, medical researchers have been grappling with evidence
that what’s true about a disease for one ancestral population isn’t necessarily true for
another. It’s called population stratification.
The problem was first suspected in the mid-1990s. Medical researchers looking for
candidate genes routinely compared the genetics of a group with the disease being
studied with a comparison sample of people without the disease. In choosing those
samples, ancestry was initially not a consideration. But as researchers got access to
more genetic information, they began to worry that their results were being
contaminated because the ancestral populations in the samples had different genetic
profiles.3 A back-and-forth debate ensued in the technical literature. By 2004, the
weight of the evidence had become clear. As one of the early DNA-based studies
concluded, “Even small amounts of population admixture can undermine an association
study and lead to false positive results. These adverse effects increase markedly with
sample size. For the size of study required for many complex diseases, relatively
modest levels of structure within a population can have serious consequences.”4
POLYGENIC SCORES
Polygenic scores will be discussed in detail in chapter 14. For now, think of them as analogous to
test scores, but based on combined allele frequencies instead of combined answers to test questions.
A polygenic score for schizophrenia (for example) measures the genetic risk of schizophrenia.
A decade later, the first studies using polygenic scores verified an explanation for
population stratification that generalizes far beyond the study of diseases: Polygenic
scores for one continental population don’t work as well for other continental
populations no matter what the trait may be. In technical terms, the predictive validity
of a polygenic score deteriorates as the genetic distance between the test population
and the comparison population increases, consistent with population genetics theory.5
For example, a polygenic score based on a test population of English and Italians
usually generalizes accurately for French and Germans, not so accurately for Chinese
and Indians, and least accurately for the genetically most distant populations from sub-
Saharan Africa.[6]
Population differences in predictive validity could reflect natural selection, genetic
drift, or gene × environment interactions. Population geneticists have had strong
scientific motivation to learn more about those differences but have been frustrated
because the artifacts produced by population stratification are so common.7 Statistical
analysis can correct for some of population stratification’s effects, but the only full
solution is to have large samples from all the ancestral populations that are being
compared. The problem is that genomic data have typically been collected from people
who lived in the nations where geneticists worked, dominated by Europe and the
United States, which in turn meant that large genomic databases were overwhelmingly
people of European ancestry.
The collection of large samples from non-European populations was on the back
burner through the first half of the 2010s. It’s understandable—samples in the
hundreds of thousands are logistically demanding, and the foundations and government
agencies with deep enough pockets to fund such samples have not (until recently) put
them on their agendas. There also has been a lack of urgency: Geneticists have been
kept busy with an ample supply of GWA research projects that can be done with
European samples.
Then murmurings about underrepresentation of non-Europeans in genomic
databases began appearing. They reached a broad audience in 2018 when British
geneticist David Curtis charged that by using European samples, “UK medical science
stands at risk of being institutionally racist.”8 In 2019, an article by a team of American
geneticists in Cell, “The Missing Diversity in Human Genetic Studies,” widely picked
up by the media, detailed the many ways in which the bias toward European samples
“effectively translates into poorer disease prediction and treatment for individuals of
under-represented ancestries.”9
It now appears likely that large samples from underrepresented populations—
notably Africans and South Asians—will be available soon (China and Japan have been
building such databases on their own). When they come online, ancestral population
differences related to disease are going to be studied minutely.
Those same databases will potentially allow researchers to study genetic differences
in personality traits, abilities, and social behavior across continental populations. That
potential is likely to generate cross-cutting pressures. For highly charged topics such as
IQ, many people will continue to urge that studying population differences does more
harm than good. But what happens if findings from European samples about cognitive-
related traits such as depression, autism, or schizophrenia lead to more effective
treatments for Europeans but not for other populations? It will be ethically imperative
to study the genetics of mental disorders in other populations as well, which means
studying the ways in which they differ from Europeans. The idea that geneticists could
ignore ancestral population differences indefinitely was always implausible. It is now
out of the question.
Differences in Allele Frequencies Within and Across Continental Population
When SNPs cause differences in phenotypic traits, evidence for that role surfaces first
in differences in target allele frequencies. The target allele is usually defined as one
that is associated with an increase in the magnitude or intensity of a trait. If the topic is
diabetes, the target alleles are the ones associated with an increase in the risk or
severity of diabetes. If the topic is IQ, the target alleles are those associated with
increases in IQ scores. Other labels used in the literature include risk allele, effect
allele, and increasing allele. As in chapter 8, I express target allele frequencies
exclusively as proportions ranging from 0 to 1 rather than as percentages of
chromosomes.
My purpose in this discussion is limited to the wording of Proposition #7 as it
applies to common SNPs: Continental population differences in target allele frequencies
associated with personality, abilities, and social behavior are common. I am not
presenting proof that those differences cause phenotypic differences, but showing you
how different the situation actually facing geneticists is from the impression you may
have when you hear that “race is a social construct.” Virtually all traits, whether
physiological, related to disease, or related to cognitive repertoires, exhibit many large
differences in target allele frequencies across continental populations.
Comparing Subpopulations from the Same Continent
I’ll use a specific example, schizophrenia, as an entry point to the topic. First, consider
the landscape for subpopulations within the same continental population. The following
graphs show what happens when the target allele frequencies for two populations are
plotted against each other for three within-continent pairs: Kenyans and African
Americans, British and Italians, and Chinese and Japanese.
Source: Author’s analysis, GWAS Catalog, and Phase 1 of the 1000 Genomes Project. A
total of 962 SNPs in the GWAS Catalog are associated with schizophrenia. For this and
the subsequent graphs, I chose 500 to plot (962 in a small graph would produce too
many overlays, obscuring the pattern). 10
The diagonal line identifies SNPs for which the target allele difference is zero. As
you can see, the actual differences are closely bunched to either side of the diagonal on
all three graphs.
Scatter plots like these imply extremely high correlations between the two sets of
target allele frequencies, and indeed they are high: +.98 for the African and Asian pairs;
+.97 for the European pair. These results are typical. Taking all of the unique SNPs for
all traits that are part of both the GWAS Catalog and 1000 Genomes—a sample of
43,543 SNPs—the average correlations were +.98 for the three African pairs, +.98 for
the six European pairs, and +.99 for the three Asian pairs.11
Comparing Continental Populations
Now look what happens when we repeat the exercise, but comparing Africans with
Asians, Asians with Europeans, and Europeans with Africans.
Source: Author’s analysis, GWAS Catalog and Phase 1 of the 1000 Genomes Project.
The landscape is completely different. The cross-continent correlations are all high
by the standards of social science, but even correlations of +.70, +.81, and +.74 (which
are the ones represented in the figure) are associated with large differences between
target allele frequencies. Why did I choose schizophrenia for the example? Because the
three correlations for schizophrenia are nearly the same as the correlations for all SNPs
related to cognitive repertoires in the GWAS Catalog: +.71 for Africans and Asians,
+.76 for Africans and Europeans, and +.81 for Asians and Europeans. The
schizophrenia example is typical, not extreme.
And that’s the nut of what I am trying to convey with Proposition #7. We don’t
know what these differences mean yet (with a few exceptions to be taken up later), but
the image fostered by “race is a social construct” does not apply. The raw material for
investigating genetic sources of population differences in phenotypic traits consists of
differences in target allele frequencies. For subpopulations within continents, the raw
material is meager. For continental populations, the raw material is abundant.
An Operational Definition of “Large”
To demonstrate that abundance, I need a summary statistic for conveying how many
SNPs fall far from the diagonal in the scatter plots. I settled on an operational definition
of “large” that defines “large” relative to differences within continental subpopulations:
A difference in target allele frequencies is called “large” if it is bigger than 99
percent of the target allele frequency differences found within continental
subpopulations. To calculate that number, I used all 43,543 unique SNPs in the GWAS
Catalog that are also found in Phase 1 of the 1000 Genomes Project. Combining all of
the 12 pairs of within-continent subpopulations produced a sample of 522,516 pairs of
target allele frequencies. Twenty percent of the absolute differences in target allele
frequencies were less than .01, 63 percent were less than .05, and 88 percent were less
than .10.12 Ninety-nine percent were less than .19—to be more precise, less than .186.
Thus my operational definition says that the smallest between-continent difference that
is “large” is anything greater than .186. For convenience, I will round up and use .20 as
the criterion. It’s easier to remember.
In other words, if Asians have a target allele frequency of .45 for a certain SNP and
Europeans have a target allele frequency of .65 or higher on the same SNP, that
difference qualifies as “large.” If Europeans have a target allele frequency of .25 or
less, that difference also qualifies as “large.” What’s important is the absolute
difference between two populations.
How many SNPs show that large a difference? The following table shows the
results for 112 phenotypic traits grouped into three types of noncognitive traits and
three types of cognitive traits. The noncognitive traits are major diseases such as breast
cancer and Parkinson’s disease, physiological biomarkers such as height and weight,
and blood parameters such as red cell count and metabolite levels. The cognitive traits
are cognitive disorders such as depression, cognitive ability (both IQ and
neurocognitive functioning), and personality features such as risk-taking tolerance and
life satisfaction. The note gives details.[13]
Physiological Traits
No. of Unique SNPs: 13,431
Total: 33%
African-Asian: 37%
European-African: 33%
Asian-European: 30%
Diseases
No. of Unique SNPs: 3,718
Total: 33%
African-Asian: 38%
European-African: 33%
Asian-European: 30%
Biomarkers
No. of Unique SNPs: 5,298
Total: 35%
African-Asian: 39%
European-African: 35%
Asian-European: 31%
Blood parameters
No. of Unique SNPs: 4,415
Total: 31%
African-Asian: 35%
European-African: 31%
Asian-European: 28%
Cognitive Traits
No. of Unique SNPs: 9,628
Total: 36%
African-Asian: 39%
European-African: 37%
Asian-European: 32%
Cognitive disorders
No. of Unique SNPs: 2,594
Total: 35%
African-Asian: 38%
European-African: 37%
Asian-European: 31%
Mental abilities
No. of Unique SNPs: 5,715
Total: 36%
African-Asian: 39%
European-African: 36%
Asian-European: 32%
Personality features
No. of Unique SNPs: 1,319
Total: 38%
African-Asian: 42%
European-African: 38%
Asian-European: 35%
Source: Author’s analysis, GWAS Catalog and Phase 1 of the 1000 Genomes Project.
When comparing the three continental populations, about a third of all target allele
differences are at least .20.14 Note that .20 is the smallest difference that qualifies. The
mean difference among those that qualify is .33 for both the physiological and cognitive
traits.
The results for this subset of traits generalizes to all 2,147 traits in the GWAS
Catalog as of May 2019 that also had SNPs represented in Phase 1 of the 1000
Genome Project. For the combined noncognitive traits, 32 percent of target allele
differences across continental populations qualified as large. For the combined
cognitive traits, 34 percent qualified as large.
One other feature of the results generalizes: The three continental pairs are
consistently ordered. Africans and Asians have the highest proportion of large
differences, Asians and Europeans have the smallest proportion, and Africans and
Europeans are in between. This is consistent with the theoretically expected
relationship between geographic and genetic differences between populations discussed
in chapter 7.
The Traits Related to Cognitive Repertoires
The table here presents information on 22 traits related to personality, abilities, and
social behavior that have at least 100 SNPs associated with them. Unlike the previous
table, this one combines SNPs that are given different labels in the GWAS Catalog but
are associated with the same trait. For example, the trait labeled “well-being” in the
table combines SNPs from studies in the GWAS Catalog that were for traits labeled
“eudaimonic well-being” and “subjective well-being.” The note gives additional
information about the traits.[15]
The table provides more information than most readers need. Its purpose is to
enable skeptical readers to look at the results from a variety of perspectives. Suppose,
for example you think that an absolute difference of .20 is not sufficiently big. The
table also shows you the percentage of allele differences that met a threshold of .25,
which exceeds 99.9 percent of the within-continent differences. It also shows you the
between-continent correlations and the mean allele difference for those traits that met
the .20 threshold. Proposition #7 claims that “Continental population differences in
variants associated with personality, abilities, and social behavior are common.” In
effect, the table says that the data confirm that proposition no matter how you look at
them.
The Inevitability of Interesting Questions to Ask
Even though we don’t know what analyses of these data will show, the existence of so
many differences in target allele frequencies will raise interesting questions for a simple
reason: We already know that the target alleles for two populations seldom balance out.
Look again at the Asian-European scatter plot for schizophrenia.
Source: Author’s analysis, GWAS Catalog and Phase 1 of the 1000 Genomes Project.
DIFFERENCES IN TARGET ALLELE FREQUENCIES FOR TRAITS
RELATED TO COGNITIVE REPERTOIRES
If the investigator’s ambition is to identify a role for natural selection in creating
population differences, there’s no telling whether anything interesting lies in that plot.
Getting from raw differences in target allele frequencies to evidence of natural selection
is a long and torturous process, and even then the results should be treated
provisionally.16 For that matter, proof of the role of natural selection for many genetic
differences will remain unobtainable without methodological breakthroughs. Recall
from chapter 8 that one of the most commonly used tools doesn’t work for adaptations
that occurred more than 30,000 years ago.
But while proving natural selection is difficult, the differences in target allele
frequencies across populations can be analyzed without knowing what caused the
differences. Such analyses can’t be done now with any confidence because of the
problems of population stratification, but they will become feasible within a few years
when large databases from the major ancestral populations are available.
For purposes of illustration, let’s jump ahead to that time and suppose that the
schizophrenia scatter plot for Asians and Europeans is free of contamination by
population stratification and that target allele frequencies and the weights associated
with them can be taken at face value (very big suppositions). The 500 SNPs shown in
the scatter plot do not reveal an obvious imbalance between the target allele
frequencies above and below the diagonal, but it turns out a modest one does exist. In
the full sample of 962 SNPs associated with schizophrenia in the GWAS Catalog,
Asians have the higher target allele frequency for 513 SNPs compared to 449 for
Europeans. This opens the possibility—only a possibility—that Asians are genetically
more susceptible to schizophrenia than Europeans. Whether it is true depends on the
magnitude of the differences in target allele frequencies, the effect sizes associated with
the SNPs, and a variety of other considerations. Even if population stratification is no
longer a problem, the raw difference is useful only for deciding whether it is
worthwhile to curate the sample of SNPs to cleanse it of contaminating factors and to
analyze polygenic scores for Europeans and Asians. Perhaps the imbalance of 513 to
449 in the raw data will turn out to be meaningful; perhaps it won’t.
The imbalance of 513 to 449 for schizophrenia amounts to a 53:47 split per
hundred SNPs. The table of 22 traits related to cognitive repertoires presented above
has a total of 66 cross-continent pairs. The imbalance is at least 53:47 for 48 of those
66 pairs. It is 55:45 or greater for 33 of them. It is 60:40 or greater for 8 of them. No
matter what (reasonable) criterion for a large-enough imbalance you might adopt, many
imbalances qualify as large enough to warrant investigation. In time, they will in fact be
investigated. It is implausible to expect that none of the imbalances will yield evidence
of significant genetic differences related to phenotypic differences across continental
populations.
The results will often be complex. The same SNPs that affect the trait under
investigation will typically be correlated with many other traits as well, which may
sometimes mean that SNPs beneficial for a desirable trait also increase vulnerability to
undesirable ones, as in the case of the tradeoff between protection against malaria
versus the risk of sickle cell anemia. Some analyses may reveal that different
populations get to similar end points via different processes, as in the case of sex
differences in cognitive toolboxes discussed in chapter 3. But simple or complex, the
results are in my view bound to be interesting.
Whether my forecast is reasonable depends on the outcome of a larger debate
about establishing genetic causation. One side of that debate holds that my optimism is
dead wrong. The results cannot possibly be interesting, because causation cannot
possibly be established even after the problems of population stratification have been
solved. That debate is given a full discussion in chapter 14. It seems fair to say at least
this: It is fundamentally wrong to think of the study of genetic population differences as
an exercise in ranking populations from top to bottom. The questions to be explored
are far more interesting, complex, and potentially more rewarding than filling out an
ethnic scorecard.
WHAT ABOUT UNCOMMON AND RARE VARIANTS?
Most single nucleotide variants (SNVs) are found in fewer than 1 percent of chromosomes and
therefore do not qualify as common SNPs. The proportion of SNVs with allele frequencies of less
than .01 is currently estimated at 74 percent, but that’s going to increase as more rare variants are
discovered. 17 The closest to a complete inventory as I write is a 2016 sample based on 10,545
genomes that used deep sequencing techniques and identified 150 million variants in the human
genome. This is by no means the total. The study reported that each individual added to the sample
contributed 8,579 variants not previously identified, leading the authors to estimate that a sample of
100,000 genomes would identify 500 million variants. 18 How much additional variance rare variants
explain is still uncertain—a few articles have reported that they explain much of the missing
heritability in GWAS analysis, but most analyses show minor effects. 19
In addition to constituting the bulk of all variants, rare variants are also overwhelmingly confined
to a single continental population, on the order of 90 percent or more. 20 However, the importance of
rare variants to population differences is uncertain. By one line of argument, they should be minor. By
definition, a rare SNV has not spread widely through a population. It is either a new mutation or one
that has been only weakly selected if at all. Mutations are random events. They don’t happen because
there’s a need for them (e.g., a mutation giving protection against a disease does not occur because
the person was living where the disease was endemic). Thus there is no reason to believe that new
mutations occurring in two separated populations will be systematically different with regard to their
effects on a given trait. But the literature contains a variety of other perspectives on the role of rare
variants.[21] The short story is that comparatively little is known about the role of rare variants, both
generally and with regard to population differences. The action for now is with standing variation in
common SNPs.
Known Genetic Continental Population Differences
Our expectations for the future should take into account that many genetic population
differences are already established.
Hiding in Plain Sight
We have known for years that biologically complex differences in continental
populations have evolved since humans left Africa. It is an unlikely assertion on its face
—how can “race is a social construct” continue to be the received elite wisdom if such
differences are already known? But it’s true. Two examples of significant genetic
differences across populations have been sitting in plain sight for decades: lactase
persistence and susceptibility to sickle cell anemia. Details on both of these adaptations
are given in the note.[22] Both of these are major adaptations involving many biological
systems. For that matter, lightening of skin pigmentation, passed off as trivial because it
is only “skin deep,” is genetically more complicated than “skin deep” implies.[23] Why,
given these examples of complex adaptation that obviously occurred after the Africa
exodus, should it ever have been assumed that they were the only ones?
Continental Differences Discovered Through Genome-Wide Analysis
Even though the documentation of continental differences has had a low priority
among most genetics researchers, several have been found.
Susceptibility to inflammatory and immune-related diseases. In 2014, Jessica
Brinkworth and Luis Barreiro examined the GWA results for three chronic
inflammatory diseases (celiac disease, Crohn’s disease, and ulcerative colitis) and five
autoimmune diseases (type 1 diabetes, multiple sclerosis, rheumatoid arthritis, psoriasis,
and systemic lupus erythematosus). They found evidence “that at least some of the
present-day autoimmune risk loci have been adaptive and conferred some sort of
functional benefit to Europeans in the past.”24 The authors hypothesized that a large
sample of Africans would yield evidence that “the genetic determinants of susceptibility
to chronic inflammatory and autoimmune diseases in individuals of African descent are
distinct from those found among Europeans.”25 A 2016 study conducted by a large
international team (first author was Yohann Nédélec) found evidence that differences in
immune function arose from natural selection rather than genetic drift: “More
specifically,” the authors wrote, “our results suggest that a significant fraction of
population differences in transcriptional responses to infection are a direct consequence
of local adaptation driven by regulatory variants.”26
A study of psoriasis using samples of Europeans (called Caucasians in the study)
and Chinese identified European-specific loci that had a cumulative effect that “could
explain up to 82.83 percent of the prevalence difference of psoriasis between the
Caucasian and the Chinese populations.”27 Overall, the authors concluded, “This study
not only provides novel biological insights into the involvement of immune and
keratinocyte development mechanism, but also demonstrates a complex and
heterogeneous genetic architecture of psoriasis susceptibility across ethnic
populations.”28
Respiratory adaptation to high altitudes. Adaptation to high altitudes has occurred
among peoples living on the Qinghai Plateau in Tibet, the Andean Altiplano in Peru,
and the Semien Plateau in Ethiopia involving changes in pulmonary function, arterial
oxygen saturation, hemoglobin concentration, and maternal physiology during
pregnancy. The evolutionary routes taken by each population have involved different
genes and produced different responses.29 Resting ventilation among the Andeans is
normal for humans in general; among Tibetans, it is 50 percent higher. Arterial oxygen
saturation is elevated for Andeans and Ethiopians; not for Tibetans. Hemoglobin
concentration is elevated among Andeans, shows a minimal increase among Ethiopians,
and is actually lowered in Tibetans.30 An exotic complication in the case of the
Tibetans is that some of the mutations that helped adapt them to high altitude now
appear to have come from introgression with the mysterious Denisovans.31
Genetic disorders among Ashkenazi Jews. As early as the 1880s, it was noted that
Tay-Sachs disease occurred almost exclusively among Ashkenazi Jews. Over the years,
several other genetic disorders have been found to be far more prevalent among
Ashkenazi Jews than in any other population. The causes of the difference in
prevalence are still unresolved. One possibility is a population bottleneck around a
thousand years ago, as argued in a 2018 study that analyzed 5,685 Ashkenazi Jewish
exomes. The alleles in question included ones for Tay-Sachs.32
Another possibility is that natural selection has been at work. In 2009, before
access to GWA, Gregory Cochran and Henry Harpending argued that case, observing
that the Jewish genetic disorders are oddly grouped:
If a population bottleneck were the sole explanation, they calculated that the odds
of finding four disorders that affect sphingolipid metabolism would have been about 1
in 100,000.[34] The authors concluded instead that we are looking at recently evolved
differences across populations. While the explanation remains unclear, this much is
undisputed: The disorders are genetic, and so are population differences separating
Ashkenazi Jews from everyone else.
Prostate cancer. In 2018, a team of geneticists (first author was Joseph Lachance)
studied the genetic sources of the differential rates of prostate cancer in Europeans and
Africans. They used SNPs from the GWAS Catalog, Phase 3 of 1000 Genomes, and
the large database of African genomes assembled by Sarah Tishkoff of the University
of Pennsylvania. They found that a small proportion of SNPs with large target allele
frequency differences and large effect sizes make a disproportionate contribution to
population differences in the risk of prostate cancer. “Both neutral and selective
evolutionary mechanisms appear to have contributed to disparities in the genetic risk of
CaP. These mechanisms include founder effects due to the out-of-Africa migration and
genetic hitchhiking of disease susceptibility alleles with locally adaptive alleles.”35
Evidence of natural selection in height, schizophrenia, and body mass index. A
team of geneticists (first author was Jing Guo) examined height, body mass index,
waist-hip ratio adjusted for BMI, HDL cholesterol, LDL cholesterol, coronary artery
disease, type 2 diabetes, Alzheimer’s disease, schizophrenia, and educational
attainment for evidence of natural selection. The Guo study tapped a variety of
databases instead of limiting itself to the GWAS Catalog. The authors found evidence
that SNPs associated with height, schizophrenia, and waist-to-hip ratio have undergone
natural selection.36 They did not find such evidence for the other seven traits in the
study.
Blood pressure. A study by a team of Japanese geneticists (first author was
Fumihiko Takeuchi) used Europeans and East Asian samples to study continental
population differences in blood pressure. They found evidence for two remarkable
phenomena: “(1) the colocalization of distinct ancestry-specific variants that are not
rare and can exert mutually inverted genetic effects between the ethnic groups and (2)
the potential involvement of natural selection in the occurrence of ancestry-specific
association signals.”37 They argued that “we have discovered a new model in which
genetic effects for transethnic SNPs that form a shared haplotype at a locus are driven
by causal variants that are ancestry-specific but are not rare, which can be called a
common ancestry-specific variant association model.”38
And more. Greenlandic Inuits are genetically adapted to a marine diet rich in
omega-3 polyunsaturated fatty acids, increasing fitness in a cold and dark
environment.39 The population of San Antonio de los Cobres in Argentina has adapted
to high levels of arsenic in the groundwater through positive selection on SNPs
involved in the arsenic methylation pathway.40
It’s early days yet, but the results of the limited genome-wide analyses of
differences in continental populations to date point in the same direction: Many
continental population differences are out there.
Recapitulation
The story of the raw material for studying continental population differences applies to
SNPs related to physiological parameters, diseases, and cognitive repertoires.
Substantial between-continent differences in target allele frequencies are common.
Around a third of all differences meet a plausible definition of “large.” The limited
amount of sophisticated genetic analysis of between-continent differences done to date
suggests that these extensive differences observed in the raw material will frequently
yield productive results about genuine continental population differences.
A Personal Interpretation of the Material in Part II
Part II has described a parallel universe. In the universe inhabited by the elite media
and orthodox academia, it has been settled for decades that race is a social construct.
In that universe, the lessons taught by Richard Lewontin and Stephen Jay Gould back
in the 1970s and early 1980s still apply.
In the universe inhabited by geneticists who study human populations, the 1990s
saw glimpses of a new perspective, and the new century opened up fascinating stories
that had previously been closed.
The new understandings about the peopling of the Earth have been the most
dramatic. New roles in the evolution of Homo sapiens were discovered for
Neanderthals and previously unknown hominins. Access to ancient DNA enabled the
reconstruction of successive human migrations across Eurasia that have revolutionized
our knowledge of prehistory.
The understanding of recent evolution that prevailed as recently as the 1990s has
also been overturned. Human evolution does not always proceed at a glacial pace
dictated by random mutations. Sometimes changes in standing variation can occur
quickly in response to environmental selection pressures. Those environmental
pressures have typically been confined to populations in specific geographic areas.
Most recently, the task of assembling the genetic story for specific phenotypic traits
has begun. It is still in its early stages, but progress is accelerating nonlinearly. Hence
the nervousness that has prevented open discussion of what’s going on in the
geneticists’ parallel universe: the fear that we will discover scary population differences
in what I have called cognitive repertoires.
That fear accounts for the taboo that has been attached to discussions of genetics
and race. It’s no wonder. White Americans’ justified guilt about their history of
discrimination against blacks, native Americans, and immigrants from Latin America
and East Asia gives them reason to worry that white supremacists will use genetics to
rationalize that history.
Let me suggest an alternative way of thinking about ethnic differences. Many of the
people in elite circles who honor the taboo are also cosmopolitan. They have had
professional colleagues of many ethnicities and have traveled extensively, observing the
endless variety of ways in which people in different cultures think and behave. They
have no trouble believing from personal experience that Chinese think and behave
somewhat differently from Saudi Arabians. So do Saudi Arabians and Senegalese,
Senegalese and Norwegians, Norwegians and Italians, northern Italians and southern
Italians. Viewed from that perspective, ethnic differences in cognitive repertoires are
neither to be doubted nor feared. They exist, and everyone who has seen anything of
the world knows it. The mix of nature and nurture? That’s not the issue. The
differences themselves are facts. People around the world are similar in the basics and
different in the details. We connect through the basics. We live with and often enjoy the
differences.
The material in Part II does not foreshadow discovery of genetically-grounded
population differences in the basics. Rather, I hope I have persuaded you that
genetically-grounded differences in the details are to be expected. Some of these
genetic differences may consist of alternative routes for getting to similar ends, just as
has been found with many cognitive sex differences. Many others will be differences
that are neither better nor worse, but just differences. Probably some will lend
themselves to value judgments, but even those will cut both ways. No population is
free of defects nor possessed of all the virtues.
We can expect most of the genetic differences to range from small to moderate and
to explain just a portion of the phenotypic differences we already live with. Every
population will be represented from one extreme to the other on every trait. There will
be no moral or legal justification for treating individuals differently because of the
population to which they belong.
I doubt that these assurances will do much good. The prospect of genetic
differences across ancestral populations is still too sensitive for calm discussion. But
perhaps this will provide perspective:
We already know of a genetically-grounded population difference on a highly
sensitive trait that is far, far larger than any ancestral population difference we are going
to find. The populations in question are males and females. The highly sensitive trait is
the commission of physical violence against other humans. The undoubted genetic
source of the difference is the Y chromosome. How big is the difference? Judge it by
this: About 90 percent of all homicides are committed by males.41
If we can live with a population difference that huge on such an important
behavioral trait, we can easily live with the smaller differences in continental
populations that are likely to be found. The differences that will be documented during
the coming years should be greeted with “That’s interesting.” I fear that the
orthodoxy’s insistence that population differences in cognitive repertoires cannot exist
ensures that they initially won’t be greeted that way.[42] But they should be.
PART III
“CLASS IS A FUNCTION OF PRIVILEGE”
The system is rigged in favor of heterosexual white males. The privilege accorded
them accounts for who gets ahead in America and who is kept on the bottom. That’s
one sound-bite version of a core element of the orthodoxy. It began in academia in the
1960s, spilled over into American politics after the turn of the century, and by the 2016
election had become a common position among people who self-identify as
progressives. Its more nuanced version is that the system is not completely rigged, but
the dice are loaded in favor of whites, males, and heterosexuals—they don’t win all the
time, but they win far more often than they deserve.
Another sound-bite version of “class is a function of privilege” is that class is a
function of wealth: The system is rigged in favor of the rich, who pass their money to
the next generation, who in turn become the next generation of the upper class. The
more nuanced version is that social mobility has diminished in recent decades,
symptomatic of an entrenched upper class.
Meanwhile, those who self-identify as conservatives commonly believe that class is
a function of character, determination, and hard work. It draws from the traditional
American credo: In America, people can become anything they want to be if they try
hard enough. The more nuanced version is that people differ in their talents, but for
most occupations and roles in life, innate talent is not nearly as important as character,
determination, and hard work.
Part III is about a third narrative, not as dark as the orthodoxy’s nor as idealistic as
the traditional one. Class is a function of the genetic lottery plus character,
determination, hard work, and idiosyncratic circumstances. The sociological, economic,
and psychometric evidence for it has been available since at least the 1980s and on
some topics for longer. That’s why a quarter of a century ago, Richard Herrnstein and
I were able to write a book of 800-plus pages with the subtitle “Intelligence and Class
Structure in American Life.”1
The book’s main title was The Bell Curve. In many ways, it documents the ways in
which a segment of American society is a indeed morphing into a castelike upper class.
But inherited wealth is a tangential contributor. The bare bones of its argument are that
the last half of the twentieth century saw two developments of epochal importance:
First, technology, the economy, and the legal system became ever more complex,
making the value of the intellectual ability to deal with that complexity soar. Second,
the latter half of the twentieth century saw America’s system of higher education
become accessible to everyone with enough cognitive talent. The most prestigious
schools, formerly training grounds for children of the socioeconomic elite, began to be
populated by the students in the top few percentiles of IQ no matter what their family
background might be—an emerging cognitive elite. By 2012, what had been predictions
about the emerging cognitive elite as we were writing in the early 1990s had become
established social facts that I described in another book, Coming Apart.
The purpose of Part III is to bring the third narrative up to date, explicitly
addressing not just the role of IQ but of other abilities, the role of genes in determining
those other abilities, the distinctions among different kinds of environmental influences,
and the interactions between genes and environment.
But What About White Male Privilege and Intersectionality?
My proposition is that racism and sexism are no longer decisively important in determining who rises
to the top. To support that proposition, I am about to demonstrate that ethnic differences in two
major components of class—educational attainment and income—nearly disappear (or in some cases
favor ethnic minorities) for people at similar IQ levels. Let’s suppose that you think the exercise is
meaningless because you reject this use of IQ scores to make racial comparisons. You can
nonetheless read Part III profitably if you are willing to consider the evidence that class structure
within ethnic groups is shaped by the dynamics I describe—that, to take the most important example,
white class structure is shaped by these dynamics.
I will also mention, however, that defending your belief that ethnic differences in IQ are
meaningless is tough. The ways of defending it that first come to mind don’t work, for reasons
described in the note.[4]
I use two indicators, educational attainment and earned income, to make that case.
The data come from the 2018 Current Population Survey (CPS) and two cohorts of
the National Longitudinal Survey of Youth (NLSY). The details for each of the
following empirical claims are given in the notes.
Educational attainment by sex. Even without adjusting for anything, there’s no
female disadvantage to worry about when it comes to educational attainment. Women
now have higher mean years of education and a higher percentage of college degrees
than men and have enjoyed that advantage for many years. These advantages persist
over all IQ levels.[5]
Educational attainment by ethnicity. In terms of the raw numbers, Asians have
higher educational attainment than any other ethnic group. Blacks and Latinos have
substantially lower educational attainment than whites, but these discrepancies are
more than eliminated after adjusting for IQ.[6] Blacks have more mean years of
education and higher proportions of college degrees than whites at comparable IQ
levels. After taking IQ into account, Latino and white levels of educational attainment
are similar. Asians retain their advantage over whites after adjusting for IQ.[7]
Earned income by sex. A substantial female disadvantage in earned income exists,
but it is almost entirely explained by marriage or children in the household. Using
Current Population Survey data for 2018, earnings for women who were not married,
had no children living at home, and worked full-time were 93 percent of the earnings of
comparable men.[8] Married women with children in the house have considerably
lower earned income even after adjusting for IQ, but the main source of the income
discrepancy is not that married women in the labor force earn less than unmarried
women, but that married men earn more than unmarried men.[9]
Earned income by ethnicity. Using raw 2018 data from the CPS, Asians have
higher mean earned income than whites, while Blacks and Latinos have substantially
lower mean earned income than whites.[10] Once again, adjusting for IQ changes that
picture dramatically. The note reports multivariate results for two large, nationally
representative longitudinal surveys. In the earlier survey, adjusting for IQ wipes out the
ethnic income differential among whites, blacks, and Latinos (Asians were not included
in this survey). In the latter survey, whites and Latinos have effectively the same
earned income while the fitted mean for blacks is 84 percent of the fitted mean for
whites. The fitted mean for Asians is 57 percent higher than the fitted mean for whites.
[11]
Let me be clear: I am not using these numbers to say that women, blacks, and
Latinos do not still face problems because of sexism and racism. These numbers say
nothing about individuals being passed over for promotions because of their sex or
ethnicity, about glass ceilings, or about discriminatory or harassing interactions in the
workplace. But there can be many people who legitimately think they haven’t gotten
fair treatment without justifying the rhetoric that the orthodoxy uses about white male
privilege. If we’re comparing men and women with similar IQs or members of different
ethnicities with similar IQs, there’s only one American group that appears to be
privileged for mysterious reasons. Martian sociologists investigating us with an
unprejudiced eye would have no trouble identifying it: Americans of Asian ancestry.
There are a host of “Yes, but…” responses that different readers will have. The
leading one is probably that IQ is in itself a function of privilege produced by affluence
and good schools. And that brings us back to the topic of Part III.
Part III is about the role of genes in shaping this new class structure. Describing
that role involves three steps, each of which gets a chapter of its own:
But first you need to be familiar with the framework for disentangling the roles of
nature and nurture, to which I now turn.
10
We know a great deal about genes and class, far more than we know about genes
and gender or genes and race, and the basics have been known for decades—that’s
what I meant in the introduction when I said that the archaeological site for exploring
class had been effectively closed until the genome was sequenced.
It may sound odd to put it that way, because the orthodoxy still barely
acknowledges that genes play any role in human behavior, let alone shape
socioeconomic classes. On almost any campus in the country, you can find sociologists
who still assure their students that it’s all hereditarian pseudoscience.1 Class is driven
by white privilege and the oppression of the patriarchy. But among psychologists who
are familiar with the data, such views are exasperating without being an impediment to
their work. There are still a few holdouts, but psychologists’ debates about heritability
generally start from common understandings.2
Francis Galton was the first person to try to study heritability scientifically. His book
Hereditary Genius (1869) presented evidence from British history that people with
excellence in the same field—judges, parliamentarians, poets, scientists, even wrestlers
and oarsmen—tended to be related by blood.3 Twentieth-century scientists took up
where he left off. The intuitive thought here is that if genes are important, people who
are more closely related will resemble each other more—siblings will resemble each
other more than half siblings, for example.4 And so it has turned out in practice.
Let’s return to our running example, height. If you divide a perfectly random
assortment of people into two groups and correlate their heights, the correlation
coefficient will be around zero. If the assortment of people consists instead of pairs of
half siblings, the correlation will be around +.25. For full siblings it will be about +.50.
For identical twins it will approach +1.00.5 The rising correlation reflects the rising
percentage of genes that the pairs share. It forms the basis for a powerful research
methodology for calculating the heritability of a trait versus the contribution of the
environment: Compare the results for identical twins and fraternal twins—more
formally, monozygotic (MZ) twins, formed from a single egg that splits, and dizygotic
(DZ) twins, created by two fertilized eggs. But to explain why the method is so
powerful, first I need to unpack the meaning of heritability.
Heritability
Definition
People from time immemorial have noticed the resemblances of parents and children.
Languages around the world have adages reflecting them—in English, for example,
“the apple doesn’t fall far from the tree” and “a chip off the old block.”
The scientific definition of heritability is unrecognizably different. Expressed in
words, heritability is a ratio calculated as the variance attributable to genes divided by
total variance in the phenotype. Mathematically, the kind of heritability that I will be
discussing, narrow heritability, is denoted as h2.
A MINI-INTERLUDE
I don’t need to get into as many technicalities about heritability as were required for the discussions
of sex and population differences, but you need to be aware of the distinction between broad
heritability and narrow heritability. Broad heritability, denoted as H2, refers to the combination of
both additive and nonadditive sources of variation. Narrow heritability, denoted as h2, is limited to
additive variation.
To illustrate what “additive” means, consider a genetic site in a flower in which one allele codes
for red and the other codes for white. The flower is red if the two alleles in the SNP both code for
red, white if they both code for white, and pink if one codes for red and the other codes for white.
The color of the flower is the result of adding the effects of the pair of alleles in the person’s
genotype.
If an interaction between the two alleles is involved, the effects of the alleles don’t add up in the
same simple way. For example, suppose that one site codes for red or white and another site codes
for whether color pigment will be produced. To get a pink or red flower not only depends on the site
coding for color but also requires that the site coding for pigment production is a “yes.” That’s one
type of nonadditive heritability, called epistasis. The other main type of interaction is dominance,
involving alleles at the same site. Hemophilia is an example. It occurs only if both alleles code for
hemophilia. The allele coding for hemophilia is recessive while the “normal” allele is dominant.
Additive variation is the most prevalent form, as I will document. Standard practice has been to
fit a model based on additive variation and test to see how well it fits. If the fit is poor, the possibility
of nonadditive variance needs to be explored.
VP = A + C + E
In the technical literature, it is commonly referred to as the ACE model. The letter
A refers to additive genetic variance. The letter C originally referred to common
environment, now customarily called shared environment. Plausible candidates for the
shared environment are such things as parental income, occupation, education, age,
parenting practices, family structure, the quality of the neighborhood, and the quality of
the schools.[8] The letter E originally stood for error but now refers to a combination
of two things: measurement error and environmental influences that twins do not share
(and that make them different from one another), known as nonshared environment.
Both aspects of the nonshared environment need some explanation. Measurement
error bedevils all the sciences but is especially troublesome in the social sciences. The
error can consist not only of inaccurate measurement (e.g., family income is
misreported), but also of the gap that separates the construct (what the researcher
wants to measure) and the indicator (what the researcher is actually measuring). For
example, the number of books in the home is an indicator used to measure the
construct “environment for stimulating intellectual development.” But such an
environment is far more complicated than can be represented by a count of books.
Even if the count of books is technically accurate, the indicator will have a lot of error
as a representation of the construct. Because of this, the common practice of referring
to E as the nonshared environment without mentioning measurement error is seriously
misleading.
But some portion of the E component of the ACE model is likely to reflect
environmental influences that siblings do not share. In 1987, Robert Plomin, one of the
leading students of the nonshared environment, suggested five unshared sources of
such phenotypic differences.9 One is a catch-all nonsystematic category (e.g.,
accidents, illnesses, trauma). Four others are systematic: family composition (e.g., birth
order, sex differences), sibling interaction (e.g., differential sibling jealousy), parental
treatment (e.g., differential maternal affection), and extrafamilial networks (e.g., local
peer groups, teachers, social media).10 Actually demonstrating an important role for
these potential components of the nonshared environment has proved to be frustrating,
as I will discuss in chapter 13. For now, it is enough to recognize that the reality of the
nonshared environment is not surprising. If you have siblings, think of all the ways in
which you and they had different experiences growing up that were unrelated to your
parents’ socioeconomic status or to their common parenting practices. You are
probably thinking about differences generated by the nonshared environment.
The Analytic Power of Comparing MZ and DZ Twins
This brings us to the unique advantages of studying MZ twins and DZ twins:
Skipping the algebra that lies between, the first two of those advantages mean that
you can solve for A, C, and E in the ACE model. Geneticist Douglas Falconer
developed the equations for doing so. They look like this:
A = 2(RMZ − RDZ)
C = 2RDZ − RMZ
E = 1 – (A + C)
Put in words, narrow heritability equals twice the difference between the
correlations of the samples of MZ and DZ twins. The shared environmental
contribution equals twice the correlation among DZ twins minus the correlation among
the MZ twins. The nonshared environment equals 1 (the total variance) minus the sum
of heritability and the shared environment. The note gives an explanation of how this
bottom line is reached.[13] In the case of the height example, suppose that the
correlation for height of our sample of DZ twins is +.55 and the correlation for our
sample of MZ twins is +.95.
All full siblings share about 50 percent of their genes. The advantage of using DZ
twins instead of full siblings who are not twins is that twins are born at the same time.
Siblings born several years apart can be born into radically different environments
depending on what’s happened to the parents’ marital relationship, jobs, income, or the
location of their home in the meantime. None of those or many other important
environmental forces are likely to vary objectively for twins, even though the twins
may react to them differently.
TWINS RAISED APART
For many people, “twin studies” brings to mind the famous Minnesota Study of Twins Reared
Apart. 14 It got so much publicity because it produced so many dramatic examples of similarities in
adults who had never met each other. When the separated twin brothers who inspired the study were
reunited in their 30s, it was discovered that as children both had had a dog named Toy. As adults,
both had been married twice, first to wives named Linda and then to wives named Betty. They had
independently taken family vacations to the same three-block strip of Florida beach, both driving light
blue Chevrolets from their homes in the Midwest. Both smoked Salems, both had worked part-time
in law enforcement as sheriffs, and both had a habit of scattering love notes to their wives around the
house. 15
Studies of twins raised apart—the Minnesota study was one of several—produced valuable
information, but the method’s potential was limited. Separation of identical twins at birth happens so
seldom that large sample sizes are impossible. The range of environments in which separated twins
are raised is narrow—adoption agencies don’t knowingly place infants with impoverished or
dysfunctional parents. 16 In contrast, it is not difficult to assemble large samples of twins who have
been raised together. Their home environments span the range.
The Validity of Twin Studies
The ACE model makes a strong claim: It can disentangle the roles of nature and
nurture. You will not be surprised to learn that many challenges to the validity of that
model have been mounted.
The logic I have just presented entails five primary assumptions. Three of them,
discussed in the note, involve fewer problematic issues.[17] Two of the assumptions are
at center stage in the debate over the validity of twin studies:
To understand the causal dynamics that lead to financial and professional success for
some people and not for others, and thereby ultimately determine socioeconomic
classes, it is essential to understand the comparative roles of environment and genes.
Disentangling those roles with ordinary samples of people is extremely difficult and
subject to endless disputes. Even before the genome was sequenced, twins offered a
uniquely powerful solution. By comparing MZ twins and DZ twins, it is possible to
determine the proportional roles of genes and of the environmental conditions shared
by children in the same family. Armed with this method, scholars have conducted
thousands of twin studies. It’s time to look at what they have found.
11
This chapter has two purposes. The first is to establish that all cognitive repertoires
are heritable to some degree and that the ones most likely to affect success are
substantially heritable. You are free to apply your own definition of substantial to the
many numbers I present. My own interpretation is that substantially heritable doesn’t
have to mean more than half but it should be at least a third. My second purpose is to
ask you to think about environmental factors from a new perspective. The
conventional perspective is that the way parents raise a child makes a big difference for
all sorts of important qualities. Send children to really good schools, and it will make a
big difference in how well they perform intellectually. The right kind of parenting can
foster self-discipline and grit, or, for parents with different priorities, foster their
children’s creativity and free-spiritedness. Proposition #8 says “Not really.” The
environment in which a child grows up usually makes a difference, but seldom because
of the things that parents can control.
The Unexpected Story of the Shared Environment
In the decades since the ACE model was developed, thousands of twin studies have
been published. As early as 2000, the pattern of results had been so consistent and so
striking that behavior geneticist Eric Turkheimer was led to set out the three laws of
behavior genetics:
In the two decades since Turkheimer stated them, no one who accepts the validity
of twin studies has found reason to dispute them.
Turkheimer’s first law is the least interesting of the three. How many people are
really surprised to learn that all human traits are heritable to some degree? How can
anyone who has been a parent be surprised?2 The second law is the most provocative.
Turkheimer stated it circumspectly, but the typical finding is starker than his wording
indicates. It’s not just that the role of the shared environment is less than that of genes;
that role is usually small, especially with regard to the child’s eventual cognitive
repertoires as an adult.
This story has been known in broad outline within the behavior genetics
community since the 1980s. It was first exposed to a general audience in 1998 when
Judith Harris published The Nurture Assumption.3 It got wider attention in 2002 when
Steven Pinker recounted it in his bestseller The Blank Slate.4 It has subsequently been
referenced in many magazine and book-length discussions of parenting.5
At first glance, the claim that parental socialization doesn’t make much difference is
counterintuitive. The family environment, including socioeconomic status (SES), must
surely have a major influence on children’s outcomes. That’s why psychologists John
Loehlin and Robert Nichols of the University of Texas were bemused by the data on
850 twin pairs that they analyzed in the early 1970s. They unveiled their unexpected
finding in a book titled Heredity, Environment, and Personality, published in 1976.
In 1981, psychologists David Rowe and Robert Plomin named this mysterious
source of variation the nonshared environment, introduced in chapter 10.7 A year later,
psychologists Sandra Scarr and Susan Grajek put the expanding evidence into language
no one could fail to understand:
Lest the reader slip over these results, let us make explicit the implications of
these findings: Upper-middle-class brothers who attend the same school and
whose parents take them to the same plays, sporting events, music lessons, and
therapists, and use similar child rearing practices on them are little more similar
in personality measures than they are to working class or farm boys whose lives
are totally different. Now, perhaps this is an exaggeration of the known facts,
but not by much.8
The findings that Scarr and Grajek described in 1982 have subsequently been
confirmed and reconfirmed. The establishment of the truth—for truth it seems to be—
that the childhood family environment explains little about the cognitive repertoires of
the adult is one of the more important achievements of the social sciences in the last
four decades.9 Do not understand this truth too quickly, however. Three clarifications
need to be kept in mind.
First, I am using the word “explain” in its statistical sense, not an explicitly
causal sense. Proposition #8 says that even though you may think that your parenting
style and your family’s resources make a big difference in how your children turn out
as human beings, using a straightforward model for identifying that effect fails to turn
up evidence for it.
Second, parents can make a negative difference at the extremes. Really awful
parenting, involving severe deprivation and abuse, can damage children permanently.
[10] To raise children in really awful neighborhoods, where gangs run the streets and
the schools are dangerous and chaotic, increases the chances that your children will be
snared in peer groups (part of the nonshared environment) that damage their life
chances.[11] Proposition #8 should be understood to refer to parenting and
neighborhoods within a broad range but excluding the worst of the worst.
Third, the limited role of the family environment does not apply to life outcomes
that can be directly determined by money. It applies only to cognitive repertoires. If
you are wealthy you can give your children wealth, regardless of their personalities,
abilities, or social behaviors. Your socioeconomic class has a causal role in determining
your children’s material standard of living, but you cannot use your socioeconomic
status to make your children more than trivially “better” than they would have been
otherwise, whether “better” is defined in terms of personality, abilities, or social
behavior.
Can you use your money to make your children professionally more successful
than they would otherwise have been? It depends on the profession. The arena in
which family wealth can clearly make a huge difference is politics, because wealth can
influence nominating committees and finance campaigns, and the powers associated
with a political office automatically go to the winner of enough votes, regardless of
talent or character. If the parents own the corporation, they can bequeath the power of
ownership to the next generation (e.g, the Murdochs, Sulzbergers, and Kochs).
Parental wealth and influence can help a child get the appropriate degree and help
obtain the first job. It’s not so easy for parental influence to get the child promoted.
The more competitive the industry and the more cognitively demanding the job, the
less influence family wealth has.
The Polderman Meta-Analysis of Twin Studies
Personality
Specific personality disorders
Shared environment: 1%
Nonshared environment: 56%
Genes: 44%
Temperament and personality functions
Shared environment: 5%
Nonshared environment: 44%
Genes: 44%
Emotionally unstable personality
Shared environment: 19%
Nonshared environment: 46%
Genes: 35%
Abilities
Energy and drive functions
Shared environment: 0%
Nonshared environment: 43%
Genes: 57%
Experience of self and time functions
Shared environment: 0%
Nonshared environment: 44%
Genes: 56%
Psychomotor functions
Shared environment: 1%
Nonshared environment: 69%
Genes: 30%
Attention functions
Shared environment: 2%
Nonshared environment: 55%
Genes: 44%
Memory functions
Shared environment: 3%
Nonshared environment: 52%
Genes: 45%
Calculation functions
Shared environment: 13%
Nonshared environment: 32%
Genes: 56%
Higher-level cognitive functions
Shared environment: 18%
Nonshared environment: 27%
Genes: 55%
Language functions
Shared environment: 22%
Nonshared environment: 32%
Genes: 46%
Mild mental retardation
Shared environment: 22%
Nonshared environment: 45%
Genes: 33%
Social behavior
Work and employment
Shared environment: 0%
Nonshared environment: 63%
Genes: 37%
Intimate relationships
Shared environment: 0%
Nonshared environment: 65%
Genes: 35%
Attention functions
Shared environment: 2%
Nonshared environment: 55%
Genes: 44%
Family relationships
Shared environment: 6%
Nonshared environment: 66%
Genes: 28%
Informal social relationships
Shared environment: 10%
Nonshared environment: 59%
Genes: 32%
Global psychosocial functions
Shared environment: 11%
Nonshared environment: 41%
Genes: 48%
Societal attitudes
Shared environment: 12%
Nonshared environment: 50%
Genes: 37%
Looking after one’s health
Shared environment: 13%
Nonshared environment: 43%
Genes: 44%
Conduct disorders
Shared environment: 14%
Nonshared environment: 38%
Genes: 48%
Disorders due to tobacco use
Shared environment: 17%
Nonshared environment: 29%
Genes: 54%
Recreation and leisure
Shared environment: 18%
Nonshared environment: 27%
Genes: 55%
Disorders due to alcohol use
Shared environment: 19%
Nonshared environment: 38%
Genes: 44%
Religion and spirituality
Shared environment: 21%
Nonshared environment: 43%
Genes: 36%
Disorders due to cannabinoid use
Shared environment: 22%
Nonshared environment: 25%
Genes: 54%
Educational attainment
Shared environment: 25%
Nonshared environment: 26%
Genes: 50%
Disorders due to multiple drug use
Shared environment: 26%
Nonshared environment: 29%
Genes: 46%
Problems related to upbringing
Shared environment: 34%
Nonshared environment: 40%
Genes: 27%
Basic interpersonal interactions
Shared environment: 36%
Nonshared environment: 34%
Genes: 30%
Source: Polderman, Benyamin, de Leeuw et al. (2015): Supplementary Table 21. Statistics are reported for the
“best” model.
In interpreting the numbers, remember that the estimates for heritability are biased
downward by about 10 percent for reasons described in the note to the table. Also,
only a few of the categories discriminate by age. Thus, for example, the role of the
shared environment for “higher-level cognitive functions” is 18 percent—an estimate
that is too low if we are thinking about early childhood, too high if we are thinking
about adults.
Of the 30 traits in the table, 11 have shared-environment roles of less than 10
percent, 11 have roles of 10–19 percent, 6 have roles of 20–26 percent, and 2 have
more than 30 percent. The shared environment had its highest estimated values, 36
percent and 34 percent, for “basic personal interactions” and “problems related to
upbringing.” (Yes, these data seem to say, you can have some effect on your kids’
manners and you can also cause problems.) The 11 traits with a role for the shared
environment of less than 10 percent include specific personality disorders,
temperament and personality functions, work and employment, intimate relationships,
and family relationships.
The next table shows traits that involve serious psychological problems, all of
which affect cognitive repertoires in one way or another.
PSYCHOLOGICAL DISORDERS
Of the 15 traits in the table, only 2 have a role for the shared environment
exceeding 10 percent: bipolar disorder (14 percent) and emotional disorders with onset
specific to childhood (20 percent). The role of the shared environment for 12 of the 15
is less than 10 percent.
Can parents drive children to distraction? No doubt about it; just as children
routinely drive parents to distraction. But when it comes to severe mental disorders, the
parents’ genes are important while their parenting, by and large, is not.
Before leaving the estimates of heritability, I need to add more detail about two of
the most important cognitive repertoires, the general mental factor g and personality
characteristics.
The General Mental Factor g
The heritability of IQ scores (the best measures of g) was contested from the 1960s
through the 1990s, but the data-driven arguments had subsided even by the time
Herrnstein and I published The Bell Curve in 1994. At that time, we used a wide range
for characterizing heritability, saying that it was somewhere between 40 percent and 80
percent. Since then, the state of knowledge has advanced. Here are two findings for
which there was some evidence before the publication of The Bell Curve and that have
been solidly established since then:
The shared environment plays a large role in determining IQ during the first few
years of life, diminishing thereafter.
By the time people reach adolescence, almost all studies have found that the
shared environment has a negligible relationship to IQ.
Both findings are best documented in a review of the literature by Elliot Tucker-
Drob and his colleagues at the University of Texas. The graph below summarizes their
results.
Source: Adapted from Tucker-Drob, Briley, and Harden (2013): Fig. 1. Shaded areas
bound ± 1 standard error.
In other words, the value of C in the ACE model was zero. “It might seem odd,”
Plomin continued, “to report average correlations across a domain as diverse as
personality.” But, he added, there were hardly any exceptions. Whether the topic was a
Big Five characteristic such as extraversion or neuroticism or more specific
characteristics such as tolerance, sense of well-being, or alienation, twin studies of
heritability kept coming up with correlations for MZ twins that were more than twice
the correlations for DZ twins, leaving no role for the shared environment.16 He further
noted that studies of non-twin siblings and adoption studies were consistent with those
of the twin studies.17
In 2014, Turkheimer, with coauthors Erik Pettersson and Erin Horn, published a
long article in the Annual Review of Psychology that reviewed the history of the study
of personality. It’s worth quoting in full his summary of the role of the shared
environment:
The Second Law of Behavior Genetics, which states that the shared
environmental component of human individual differences is small, is usually
true for most traits, but the situation is somewhat starker for personality. It is
remarkable, in surveying the genetically informed personality literature in a very
wide context, how completely absent the shared environment is. In fact, it is
often the case that identical twins are more than twice as similar as fraternal
twins, a violation of the classical twin model that, if uncorrected, produces
negative estimates for shared environmental variance.18
The goal of this chapter is to present the case that Herrnstein’s syllogism is borne out
by the evidence and warrants a somewhat stronger statement when it comes to the role
of genes in shaping class structure. If individual success is based even modestly on
heritable traits, the aggregate effect on a society’s class structure will be important, as I
cautiously characterize it in Proposition #9. “Profound” is probably more accurate.
This goal should not obscure a larger truth. I’ll say it briefly but italicize it: The bulk
of the variance in success in life is unexplained by either nature or nurture.
Researchers are lucky if they explain half of the variance in educational attainment with
measures of abilities and socioeconomic background. They’re lucky if they can explain
even a quarter of the variance in earned income with such measures. The takeaway for
thinking about our futures as individuals is that we do not live in a deterministic world
ruled by either genes or social background, let alone by race or gender. But Proposition
#9 is about social classes, not individuals. The takeaway for thinking about the future
of modern Western societies is that the role of genes is important for shaping class
structure.
Heritable Traits and Success: The Primacy of g
The most important single heritable trait that explains socioeconomic success is the
general mental ability known as g, which in turn is best measured by a good IQ test.[2]
It is not only the most important, but typically far more important than any other single
heritable trait. On the other side of the picture, I will be showing you some evidence
that all other heritable traits have combined effects that are quite substantial—in some
circumstances and for some measures of success as important in combination as IQ.
Preliminaries
Many of the things that may concern you about IQ tests are not true. For a recent
accessible and accurate summary of the state of knowledge about IQ, I recommend
Stuart Ritchie’s Intelligence: All That Matters, a sprightly book that’s only 160 pages
long.3 But here are some of the main points that you need to know, along with
additional documentation.
IQ tests are not biased against minorities.4 Education does raise IQ, but within a
narrow range (you can’t become a genius by staying in school long enough).5 IQ scores
are usually stable, though not perfectly so, after around age six, when the first reliable
measures become available, until decline in old age.[6] IQ meets higher standards of
reliability and validity in measuring the construct it is intended to measure than any
psychological measure of personality or temperament.7
All of these statements have abundant, replicated evidence behind them and are not
subjects of controversy among specialists. This still leaves a list of “But what about…”
questions that people raise about IQ. This is not the place to deal with all of them, but
two misapprehensions are so widespread that I must at least briefly deal with them
here.
“IQ tests just measure how well you perform on IQ tests.” The proper description
of what g means for daily life goes far beyond performing well on tests. Sociologist
Linda Gottfredson’s description is the best I’ve found:
To put it another way, life is an IQ test.9 Compared to people with low IQs, people
who have high IQs are more likely to see that the tempting short-term payoff will be
costly in the long term. They are more likely to eat healthy foods, refrain from
smoking, and exercise regularly.10 They have fewer accidents.11 More broadly, think of
everyday life as a multitude of decisions. For some of those decisions, there’s no
objectively right or wrong choice; everything depends on personal priorities. That’s
why some people take up wingsuit gliding despite the mortality statistics—for them, the
reward is worth the risk. But many everyday decisions have an option that has an
objectively higher probability of producing an outcome that the individual does not
want. For those thousands of decisions over the course of a year, g is useful in
reducing the number of mistakes.12 The general mental factor g helps people navigate
the caprices and complications of everyday life.13
g HAS NOTHING TO DO WITH MERIT
I deliberately avoid the word meritocracy to describe a society in which able people rise to the top,
because the most important single ingredient, g, is a matter of luck. I’m willing to believe that people
have some control over their industriousness, perseverance, resilience, and other personal qualities
that have brought them success, even though those qualities are partly heritable. g is different. People
can make a little or a lot of what they were given; maybe they can even tweak their IQs by a couple
of points; but no one gets an IQ score of 130 by trying hard. Merit had nothing to do with it.
“The most successful people I know aren’t the ones with the highest IQs.” Two
separate issues are commonly confused.
First, the image of the intellectual genius who is a social klutz is overblown. It
happens—some people who have extremely high IQs have poor social skills and can be
successful only in certain occupations (some genius programmers come to mind).
Some people with high IQs seem to have oddly little common sense. They are
exceptions, however. The qualities besides IQ that contribute to success tend to be
correlated with IQ, and those correlations apply across the full range of IQ.
Second, there’s a good reason why people say, “The most successful people I
know aren’t the ones with the highest IQs.” They’re probably right. The reason they’re
right is what statisticians call restriction of range or truncation of range. Few people
these days live their lives in close daily contact with people who have a wide range of
IQs. Instead, people mostly hang out with others who are in their own IQ ballpark and
are thereby victimized by the illusion created by restriction of range.
More than 30 years ago, sociologist Steven Goldberg told me an analogy for
explaining it that I have been borrowing ever since: IQ has the same role for explaining
success in many professions as weight has in explaining the success of offensive
linemen in the NFL. The best offensive linemen in the NFL are not necessarily the
heaviest. The correlation between weight and productivity for all the offensive linemen
on the rosters of NFL teams is probably near zero. But you can’t get the job unless
you weigh at least 300 pounds.14 Similarly, CEOs of Fortune 500 companies, senior
partners in Park Avenue law firms, and tenured professors at Harvard may not be the
ones with the highest IQs among the potential occupants for such jobs. They
distinguished themselves from the others just as smart or smarter through other
personal assets. But restriction of range means that you are seeing what role those
other personal assets play when everyone figuratively weighs 300 pounds to begin
with.
The First Order Effects of g in Producing Success
Having a high level of g is a general resource for getting an advanced education and
being productive on the job—two of the most elemental building blocks of success.
Educational attainment. Over the last century, the gateway to economic success
has increasingly been defined by education, and the ability to take advantage of
education is g’s most obvious asset. In 2007, sociologist Tarmo Strenze published a
meta-analysis of 65 samples with information on IQ and educational attainment. IQ’s
correlation with eventual educational attainment for persons who had been tested at
ages 16–18, before the end of compulsory education, was +.58.15
The relationship between IQ and academic success is about as strong for graduate
school as for college. A 2010 meta-analysis of the literature on such tests found a
correlation between the SAT and first-year college GPA of +.51 and a correlation with
cumulative GPAs for the entire college career of +.53. The correlations between scores
on various graduate school admissions tests and subsequent graduate school GPAs
ranged between +.35 and +.46. The correlation between the Law School Admission
Test and scores on bar exams was +.46. The mean correlation of the Medical College
Admission Test and scores on medical licensing exams was +.64.16
Job productivity. One of the most common assertions about IQ is that it doesn’t
predict performance in the real world of work. The truth is the opposite. It’s not just
that IQ predicts job performance for people with cognitively demanding jobs; IQ
predicts job performance to some degree for people across the entire range of jobs.
People who are responsible for new hires at a workplace should know that an IQ score
is a better predictor of job performance than a résumé, evaluation through a job
interview, assessment centers, or work samples. The note has details.[17] How
important are the effects of IQ? Taking all jobs together, the predictive validity of IQ
scores for overall job performance is about +.50 (it’s higher than that for high-
complexity jobs). You can square that figure and point out that IQ explains only 25
percent of the variance in job performance. If you’re an employer, however, and are
told that a standard deviation increase in IQ is associated with half a standard deviation
increase in overall job performance, a predictive validity of +.50 is a big deal.18
Since we live in an age when the social sciences are suffering from a replication
crisis, I emphasize again that the generalizations I have made about the relationships of
g to educational attainment and job productivity are drawn from hundreds of studies.
Psychometric g Versus Other Personal Traits
The popular suspicion of IQ’s relationship to success has been tenacious, but for an
understandable reason. Anyone who has reached adulthood is aware of all the things
besides intelligence that matter in achieving success. The most obvious is simple hard
work. In any job setting with more than a few employees, we observe that some
people work long hours and others do as little as possible. But other traits also matter.
Some people are resilient while others give up when things go badly. Some people have
a knack for leading people and others do not. Some people are a pleasure to work with
and others are abrasive and off-putting. Industriousness, resilience, charisma,
cooperativeness, and many other traits are objectively valuable for productivity in most
kinds of jobs and rightly affect supervisors’ decisions about who gets ahead.
Since we know these other qualities are so important in everyday life, it seems that
good measures of them should explain at least as much about success as an IQ score.
People have in fact invested a great deal of effort in coming up with such measures.
The ones that have gotten the most public attention are Howard Gardner’s “multiple
intelligences” and two constellations of qualities that have been labeled “emotional
intelligence” and “grit.” All three talk about qualities other than g that are important to
success. I recommend Howard Gardner’s Frames of Mind: The Theory of Multiple
Intelligences (1983), Daniel Goleman’s Emotional Intelligence: Why It Can Matter
More Than IQ (1995), and Angela Duckworth’s more recent Grit: The Power of
Passion and Perseverance (2016) for nontechnical accounts of qualities that aren’t
directly measured by IQ tests and that are unequivocally important.
The technical validation of these three approaches is another matter. There’s a big
difference between persuasively arguing that something is important to success and
providing a measure of that “something” that is reliable, valid, and not already captured
by other measures. Tests of emotional intelligence or grit need to explain variance that
measures of IQ and personality traits don’t explain. That task has proved to be
daunting. Multiple intelligences, emotional intelligence, grit, and other ideas about the
causes of success were introduced into a world that already had measures of g and
personality traits that have passed repeated tests of reliability and construct validity.
The new kids on the block have had a hard time demonstrating that they could explain
additional variance.[19]
Progress has been made in understanding the role of traits other than IQ,
however.20 A technical literature documents the importance of self-control for success
in life independently of IQ.21 A related concept, locus of control (how much people
believe they are in control of what happens to them), has an independent role in
explaining both financial success and financial hardship.22 When it comes to academic
performance, simple self-confidence in one’s own ability was found to explain variance
in academic achievement in mathematics and English (but not in science) even after
controlling for IQ.23 Others have documented an independent role for the importance
of intellectual interest and curiosity.24
But the most extensive technical literature involves the Big Five personality factors
—emotional stability, extraversion, conscientiousness, openness, and agreeableness—
so much that a 2014 meta-analysis of the relationship of personality to academic
performance by psychologist Arthur Poropat had two dozen samples to work with.
Conscientiousness consistently played the most important role, with openness in
second place. Poropat reported effect sizes for them of +1.14 and +0.96 respectively,
far larger than those for agreeableness (+0.19), emotional stability (+0.36), or
extraversion (+0.23).25 In addition to its value for academic performance,
conscientiousness has also been found to predict job performance, salary, promotion,26
and occupational prestige.27 These findings make sense. The facets for measuring
conscientiousness—competence, orderliness, dutifulness, industriousness, self-
discipline, and deliberateness—come close to describing the ideal candidate for many
kinds of jobs that require solid day-by-day performance rather than flights of
creativity.28 Other studies have found that emotional stability, openness, and
agreeableness have independent associations with similar outcomes that contribute to
success. But while such effects have been found, they are quite small compared to the
role of g.
The effect sizes in the Poropat meta-analysis do not control for IQ—an important
omission. I have found three major studies that have analyzed the role of personality in
the presence of a good measure of childhood IQ.[29] One (first author was Rodica
Damian) is based on 81,075 persons from Project Talent, a subsample of a nationally
representative American sample tested in high school in 1961 who were followed up at
ages 28–30. Another (first author was Roger Staff) is based on a subset of 443 persons
drawn from the Aberdeen Birth Cohort of 1936 who were followed up at age 64. The
third study, by Helen Cheng and Adrian Furnham, is based on 4,808 persons from the
British National Child Development Study of 1958 who were followed up at age 50.
The following table shows what happened when IQ, parental SES, and the Big Five
personality traits were entered together in analyses of adult educational attainment and
occupational prestige.
Childhood IQ
Project Talent
Educational attainment: +0.41
Occupational prestige: +0.39
Aberdeen Birth Cohort
Adult reading: +0.65
Adult SES: +0.52
British NCDP
Educational attainment: +0.35
Occupational prestige: +0.14
Extraversion
Project Talent
Educational attainment: +0.08
Occupational prestige: +0.09
Aberdeen Birth Cohort
Adult reading: –0.05
Adult SES: +0.07
British NCDP
Educational attainment: –0.02
Occupational prestige: +0.07
Agreeableness
Project Talent
Educational attainment: +0.07
Occupational prestige: +0.08
Aberdeen Birth Cohort
Adult reading: +0.02
Adult SES: +0.05
British NCDP
Educational attainment: 0.00
Occupational prestige: 0.00
Conscientiousness
Project Talent
Educational attainment: +0.09
Occupational prestige: +0.09
Aberdeen Birth Cohort
Adult reading: +0.01
Adult SES: +0.07
British NCDP
Educational attainment: 0.00
Occupational prestige: +0.05
Emotional stability
Project Talent
Educational attainment: +0.05
Occupational prestige: +0.05
Aberdeen Birth Cohort
Adult reading: +0.04
Adult SES: +0.14
British NCDP
Educational attainment: +0.03
Occupational prestige: +0.01
Openness
Project Talent
Educational attainment: +0.09
Occupational prestige: +0.09
Aberdeen Birth Cohort
Adult reading: +0.15
Adult SES: +0.18
British NCDP
Educational attainment: +0.16
Occupational prestige: +0.05
Sources: Damian, Su, Shanahan et al. (2014): Tables 3, 6; Staff, Hogan, and Whalley (2017): Table 2; Cheng
and Furnham (2012): Fig. 2.
You can’t compare the size of the effects across the rows in the table. The metrics
are all related to standard deviations, but they are too different to make the numbers
comparable.[30] Rather, you should scan down the columns. None of the Big Five
personality factors has nearly the independent role that childhood IQ has. In fact, even
these modest effects are exaggerated, because the results for any one factor control
only for childhood IQ, not for the other four personality factors (that is, the
multivariate model was run five times, once for each model, not once with all five
factors entered as independent variables). The message of the information in the table
is not that other personal traits besides g are irrelevant after all. But each individual trait
plays a subordinate role.
Two ambitious attempts to measure the combined roles of a wide variety of
“heritable traits besides IQ” indicates that those other traits do play the significant role
in combination that intuition says they should.
The first was produced by an 11-person team of psychologists, mostly from
England, using 6,653 sets of twins in the UK Twins Early Development Study
(TEDS). The first author was Eva Krapohl.
The dependent variable was the participants’ scores on the national examination
administered at the end of compulsory education in the UK at age 16. It is known as
the GCSE (General Certificates of Secondary Education). The independent variables
involving heritable traits were IQ and eight other domains represented by composite
scores: personality (including the Big Five and grit), self-efficacy, well-being (e.g.,
happiness, hopefulness), parent-reported behavioral problems, and child-reported
behavioral problems, plus noncognitive scales for health, school environment, and
home environment.
In one sense, the Krapohl study is another example of the dominance of IQ. Unlike
the studies reported in the table above, the authors did conduct an analysis that entered
all nine of the domains in a single model. IQ alone explained 34 percent of the
phenotypic variance while the other eight combined explained 28 percent.31
What were the independent roles of the other eight? The published tables do not
answer that question directly. Twenty-eight percent divided by eight indicates that most
of the other roles must have been trivially small. Collateral evidence makes it clear that
the measure of self-efficacy was substantially more important than any of the others,
followed by the composite measure of personality.[32] As an estimate, IQ had an
independent role of about three and a half times that of self-efficacy and more than six
times the independent role of personality, the school environment, or parent-reported
behavior problems.33 IQ was much more important than self-efficacy in explaining
phenotypic variance, several times more important than personality, the school
environment, or parent-reported behavior problems. The independent roles of the
home environment, well-being, health, and child-reported behavior problems were
virtually zero.
The second study was conducted by a team of psychologists at the University of
Texas using a sample of 811 school-age twins from the Texas Twin Project. First
author was Elliot Tucker-Drob. The analysis combined several measures of cognitive
ability, the Big Five personality factors, and seven character traits that have featured
prominently in recent years: grit, intellectual curiosity, intellectual self-concept, mastery
orientation, educational value, intelligence mindset, and test motivation.
The seven character traits all loaded on a general character factor that seems to be
closely related to intellectual curiosity. The correlation of the general character factor to
a combined measure of knowledge and academic achievement (Ach) was +.47. With
regard to the Big Five personality factors, openness was as strongly correlated with
Ach (r = +.48) but, surprisingly to me, conscientiousness was not (r = +.16).34 The
general character factor contributed a lot to the measure of Ach, but not as much as the
measure of fluid intelligence. The same was true of openness.35
Which Comes First? Test Scores or SES?
How does the combined influence of heritable ability and personality traits stack up
against the influence of the socioeconomic circumstances into which a child is born?
Before turning to the results, I need to point out that any measure of parental SES
is not only a measure of the child’s environment; it is also partially a measure of the
parents’ talents (or lack of them) that produced the SES, which in turn are heritable—
in the case of IQ and personality, substantially heritable. It is amazing how seldom the
authors of technical articles that purport to assess the relative roles of IQ and parental
SES in producing adult outcomes mention this large and inescapable confound. Having
mentioned it here, I ignore it in the discussion of the following studies, because none of
them provides a way to estimate the degree of confounding between IQ and parental
SES. I return to the issue with some studies that do provide such estimates in chapter
12.
Performance in College
In the United States, the poster child for the indictment of tests is the relationship
between parental SES and performance on college admissions tests such as the SAT:
The higher the parental education and income, the higher the scores of the children.
How much of this relationship is causal? How much of it is a reflection of the
uncomfortable possibility that smart parents attain high SES and also produce smart
children?
The exhaustive analysis of this question, presented alongside a comprehensive
review of prior studies, was published in 2009 in the Psychological Bulletin by a team
of psychologists at the University of Minnesota (first author was Paul Sackett). The
authors presented results for a meta-analysis of College Board data, a meta-analysis of
other studies using a composite measure of parental SES, and a reanalysis of major
longitudinal datasets. A table summarizing the results is given in the note.[36] Boiling it
down:
After controlling for the admissions test score, the correlation of parental SES
and college grades dropped from +.22 to –.01 in the SAT meta-analysis, from
.09 to .00 in the meta-analysis of studies with composite SES measures, and
from a mean of .06 to .01 among the longitudinal studies.
After controlling for the measure of SES, the correlation between admission test
score and grades was reduced only fractionally: from +.53 to +.50 in the SAT
meta-analysis, from +.37 to +.36 in the meta-analysis of studies with composite
SES measures, and from a mean of +.313 to +.308 among the longitudinal
studies.
For practical purposes, parental SES explained nothing about the student’s college
grades after adjusting for test scores.
Educational Attainment, Income, and Occupation
Quantitative explorations of the comparative roles of IQ and parental SES in producing
economic success began with a pair of books in the 1970s for which sociologist
Christopher Jencks was the principal investigator and first author: Inequality, published
in 1972, and Who Gets Ahead, published in 1979.37 The results of subsequent studies
have not been consistent in their estimates of the magnitudes of the independent effects
of IQ and parental SES, but they have all found such effects.
The following table shows six databases with good pedigrees. Three of them—the
Aberdeen Birth Cohort, the National Child Development Study, and Project Talent—
were part of the preceding table on IQ and personality factors. The other three are a
sample drawn from the Scottish Mental Survey of 1932 (first author was Ian Deary)
who were followed up at ages 38–41, and the 1979 and 1997 cohorts of the
Longitudinal Survey of Youth project mentioned in the introduction to Part III.38 They
show results over a broad period, from the 1970s up to the present. The members of
the earliest cohort reached age 40 in 1972; the oldest members of the most recent
cohort are just turning 40 in 2020.
All of the metrics represent some form of standardized regression coefficient, but
once again there are too many differences across the studies to compare them. Rather,
focus on the relative sizes of the coefficients for childhood IQ and childhood SES. The
generalizations to be drawn are that all but two of the coefficients for childhood IQ are
larger than the coefficients for childhood SES and that in all but one case IQ has a
greater effect on educational attainment than it does on adult income or occupation.[40]
Not much should be made of specific magnitudes with a sample of six, but, to get a
sense of the table, the median ratio of the effects of childhood IQ to those of childhood
SES was 1.75. And of course, the putative effects of childhood SES were inescapably
partly genetic, as I noted earlier.
Recapitulation
Cognitive ability and personality strengths, both substantially heritable, are important to
achieving success in life—educationally, in earnings, and in professional achievement.
To that extent, class structure is, in the words of Proposition #9, importantly based on
differences in abilities that have a substantial genetic component. The relationship
between these abilities and success does not amount to genetic determinism for
individuals. It is, however, strong enough to decisively shape the social structure of
modern Western societies. Of the many abilities involved, the general mental factor g is
usually dominant. Proposition #9 is something that we haven’t had to argue about for
decades, despite all the furor that has accompanied the idea that success is affected by
genes. It’s demonstrably true.
But it is understandable why that truth still raises hackles for so many people. It
smacks of self-satisfaction with the way things are and indifference toward those who
were unlucky in the genetic lottery. It is also understandable that scholars and
policymakers alike have put a great deal of effort into attempts to use education and
other measures to help the unlucky. How well have they succeeded? What are the
constraints on helping? Those extremely sensitive issues are up next.
13
Outside interventions can change people profoundly. An inspiring teacher can fire the
imagination of a bored adolescent and change the trajectory of that student’s life.
Friends who intervene in an alcoholic’s life can change its trajectory. It happens all the
time. But Proposition #10 is not about individual successes. Rather, Proposition #10 is
about whether people can be changed by design in large numbers. That’s a more
ambitious objective, and it is made more ambitious yet by the material you have read in
the preceding three chapters. Those findings lend themselves to another syllogism:
In the Polderman meta-analysis discussed in chapter 11, there were exceptions to the
generalization that the role of the shared environment is trivially small. The shared
environment explained 36 percent of the variance for basic personal interactions, 24
percent for problems related to upbringing, 26 percent for disorders due to multiple
drug use, and 25 percent for educational attainment. If an outside intervention could
remediate a high proportion of the shared environmental influences that cause problems
in these areas, they would be meaningful accomplishments.
The Comparatively Minor Role of Outside Interventions
The question is whether that’s a reasonable expectation. The things that fall into the
shared and nonshared environment include all the effects of the family, school, and
neighborhood exerted during a young person’s waking hours. The usual kinds of
outside intervention—counseling, tutoring, mentoring, after-school activities, job
training—amount to a few hours per week. Even if the quality of those interventions is
excellent (a difficult thing to achieve in itself), we’re talking about a tiny fraction of a
youth’s waking hours. A teenager with a drug counselor might really like and listen to
his counselor. But he walks out of his meeting with the counselor into the same shared
home, school, and neighborhood environments that explain 26 percent of the variance
in drug use. If the shared environment explained 90 percent of the variance, then
maybe a few hours a week of an outside intervention might make some measurable
difference. If the shared environment explains just 26 percent of the variance, the
outside intervention has to be big—boarding school, for example, moving the family
out of the neighborhood, or adoption into a new family. Ordinary levels of outside
intervention are too small relative to the competing influences.
A similar logic applies to outside interventions that attempt to modify the behavior
of parents. Consider the outcome with the largest role for the shared environment (36
percent), basic personal interactions. That number says that parents can legitimately
think they’ve had a major role in raising sociable children. But if a 10-year-old is
exhibiting problems with basic personal interactions, a program that tries to change the
parents’ parenting practices has arrived far too late. Even if the program is successful,
the child is not going to turn on a dime just because his parents are behaving somewhat
more positively and effectually than they did for the preceding 10 years. If outcomes
that are primarily influenced by parenting are the problem, then solutions will have to
begin as close to birth as possible.
I will get to the empirical track record of outside interventions later. Now, I’m
drawing your attention to underlying realities that are too seldom made explicit. Outside
interventions of normal magnitude and intensity make sense for an extremely limited
set of problems that are analogous to health problems that can be cured by antibiotics
or surgery.
Problems that fit those criteria are rare, but they exist. Here’s an example: School
systems in large urban areas are notorious for tolerating chaotic classrooms in a handful
of schools in the most impoverished part of town. There’s no excuse for it. Children
who are eager to learn are prevented from doing so, with lifelong consequences, and
yet an outside intervention can completely cure that problem in a day: Install strict rules
of in-class conduct, and promptly and without exception eject disruptive students from
the classroom. Teachers will be able to teach and the remaining students will be able to
learn.
The difficulty, of course, is what to do with the students who have been ejected.
Solving their problems is a matter of changing their personalities, abilities, or social
behavior, or a combination of all three, and that’s what the first premise of the
syllogism says we don’t know how to do.
The underlying point of my example is why the solution works: We know how to
help people who already want to do something and are artificially prevented from doing
it. My solution doesn’t have to change the students who are already trying to learn. It
just needs to provide them with an environment in which they are enabled to do what
they already want to do. We are not constrained from helping with outside
interventions. We’re just constrained in whom we can help with what kinds of
problems.
If instead we try to change people who aren’t ready and able to change given the
opportunity, we’re back to a situation in which powerful competing forces, acting
through both genes and the nonshared environment, overwhelm the magnitude of the
intervention that seeks to produce change. Expecting to see a major impact from
outside interventions is usually unrealistic.
How Genes Shape Environment
Interventions intended to change the environment assume that if the environment
changes as planned, then, other things being equal, outcomes will be positively
affected. Suppose that parents use inconsistent discipline, for example, which is known
to be associated with negative outcomes for children. It is assumed that if the parents
can be taught to use a reasonable disciplinary style consistently, those negative
outcomes will be reduced. But that’s not the only way environmental effects work.
They can also be mediated by the correlation (r) between the genotype (G) and the
environment E, known in the trade as rGE. There are three types of rGE: passive,
evocative, and active.
Passive rGE can be illustrated with the case of aggressive behavior in a child who
was raised by a violent and abusive father. The child is likely to have gotten a double
dose of bad luck: the environmental effects of the parental abuse, and a father with a
genetic propensity for abusiveness, roughly half of which has also been passed down to
the child.1 Evocative rGE (sometimes called reactive rGE) occurs when the child’s
genetically influenced characteristics evoke a response from the environment (which
includes other people). Consider the case of parents who use physical punishment on
an aggressive child. It could be a case of evocative rGE, whereby parents are reacting
to the child’s violence by using physical punishment, which then only makes matters
worse. Active rGE occurs when children shape their environments—for example, by
choosing peer groups—for genetically influenced reasons. An adolescent boy who has
a genetic propensity for aggression is likely to be attracted to violent teenage gangs and
become a member. The environmental influences of the gang then reinforce, or even
amplify, the boy’s genetic propensity.
Now let’s make the example more complicated. In chapter 12, I referenced the
Krapohl study of a large sample of British twins. The objective was to identify the
causes of the differences among scores that the participants achieved on the General
Certificates of Secondary Education. You may recall that IQ explained more of the
variance in GCSE scores than any of the other individual measures, but the other
variables collectively explained about as much as IQ.2 This would suggest that even if
we don’t know how to raise IQ, outside interventions can do a lot to boost students on
the other contributions to school achievement. But the authors found that the
proportion of the covariance of these other factors with academic achievement was
extremely high. “To the extent that children’s traits predict educational achievement,
they do so largely for genetic reasons, for example, for personality (92%), behavior
problems (81% for parent-rated, 89% for child-rated), intelligence (75%), self-efficacy
(64%), and well-being (53%).”3 The authors went on to observe:
How does this affect the prospects for outside interventions? Correlations between
the genotype and the environment lend themselves to two quite different
interpretations.
One interpretation focuses on the ways in which genetic causes are mediated by
parental behavior. Yes, bad parenting practices are partly driven by parental genes, but
if it’s the parenting practices that are proximally causal, an outside intervention could
still have an effect if it could change the parenting practices.
The other interpretation focuses on the ways in which what we once thought was
an environmental cause turns out to be a partly genetic one. When an outside
intervention sets out to change bad parenting practices, the already difficult task of
changing a person’s behavior is fighting a genetic headwind. The behaviors that the
intervention is trying to change aren’t occurring just because of ignorance about good
parenting, but also because of genetic predispositions.
We have a natural experiment that lets us see how these competing forces work out
in practice—adoption at birth. Adoption studies routinely show that the correlation
between biological children’s IQ and the family’s socioeconomic status is around twice
the correlation between adoptive children’s IQ and the adoptive family’s socioeconomic
status.5 Can the benefits of competent parenting practices benefit the adopted child?
Yes. But adoption is as good as it gets. In effect, adoption at birth to competent parents
gives us a glimpse of what would happen if an outside intervention could magically be
successful at changing a wide variety of parenting behaviors from bad to good. An
outside intervention that makes modest improvements in a small proportion of
parenting problems will have a far smaller effect.
“The First Premise Is Wrong for the Early Stages of Life”
Everything we know about human development says that humans are most malleable
in the first years of life. The brain is still developing. Habits are not yet set in the child.
Some parenting practices can be changed for the better and still have time to work their
effects on the child. I fully share the view that if interventions are ever going to work,
they’re going to work in infancy and early childhood. But it’s one thing to believe that;
it’s another to confront the empirical findings about the difficulties and constraints that
have attended a half century of attempts to intervene early in life.
Heritability and Socioeconomic Status
Recall the figure in chapter 12 showing the role of the shared environment in IQ from
childhood to adulthood. It hit zero in adolescence, but the shared environment
explained more than half of the variance for the preschool years. That finding implies
that the second premise of my syllogism doesn’t necessarily apply to infants and young
children.
The proposition that heritability of IQ is lower for disadvantaged children than for
children from ordinary backgrounds was first advanced by psychologist Sandra Scarr in
1971, who found provisional evidence for it.[6] Subsequent studies in 1980 and 1999
provided stronger evidence, but the role of the shared environment remained small
even for disadvantaged children.[7]
In 2003, Eric Turkheimer published dramatic evidence that the opportunities for
intervening are not only higher at young ages, but that they are especially high for
disadvantaged children because of an interaction between heritability and SES.8 He and
his coauthors used 390 twin pairs with excellent data on zygosity drawn from the
National Collaborative Perinatal Project. The measure of IQ, administered at age
seven, was the Wechsler Intelligence Scale for Children, the most highly regarded test
of its kind. Their measure of the shared environment was an index of socioeconomic
status, expressed as a scale going from 0 to 100. The index was based not just on
parental education, but on a linear combination of information on parental education,
occupational status, and income, using a well-established method.9
It was close to a gold-standard study, and it produced unequivocal evidence for a
large gene × environment (hereafter G×E) interaction. In the best-fitting model, the
expected value of heritability (h2) when the measure of SES was set to zero (i.e., the
most impoverished, poorly educated families) was a tiny .02. When the measure of
SES was set to 100, the expected heritability was an exceptionally high .90. The even
more important finding was what happened to the role of the shared environment.
When the measure of SES was set to 100, representing the wealthiest and most highly
educated families, the expected value of the role of the shared environment (c2) was
only .09. When the measure of SES was set to 0, the expected value of c2 was .62—
almost three times greater than the role of the shared environment for the earlier
studies. Furthermore, a large role for the shared environment remained throughout the
bottom half of the SES distribution.10
SOME ADDITIONAL TECHNICAL TERMS
Set, as in “when the measure of SES was set to 100,” refers to the value assigned to an independent
variable, a definition easiest to understand by reading the following definition of expected value.
Expected value means a statistical best guess. All the results I discuss in this section are
produced by mathematical equations applied to large datasets. The models themselves are often
complicated, but the essence is simple. Suppose I have data for 1,000 adults on age, education, IQ,
and income. I want to know the best guess of family income (the dependent variable) of someone 30
years of age with 12 years of school and an IQ of 120 (the independent variables). Multivariate
statistical analysis can tell me the best guess for that dataset—the statistically expected value of the
family income when age is set to 30, years of education is set to 12, and IQ is set to 120. The
accuracy of the expected value depends on the magnitude of the correlations among the variables I’m
working with. For more on correlation and multivariate statistics, see Appendix 1.
Interaction effect. In social science analyses, an interaction effect has occurred when two things
acting in combination produce an effect in addition to their separate effects.
In the case of heritability and environment, here’s a simple example: Let’s assume that Alice and
Becky have high and low genetic endowment for IQ respectively (A in the ACE model) and that
reading during childhood raises IQ. Both children live in homes with many books (an element of C).
Alice reads all of the books while Becky reads only a few of them. In such a case, it is possible
(though not necessarily the case) that the effect that genes and books in the house have on IQ is not
just A + C but A + C + (A × C). This is an extremely simplified description. The note adds details.
[11]
Many subsequent studies have taken up the G×E interaction that Turkheimer’s
2003 study found. As I write, 11 of them are interpretable as attempts at replication.
[12] Add in the original Turkheimer study, and we have 12 studies of interest. Five of
them did not find a G×E interaction.13 The results for the seven that did are shown in
the table below. Details on how the percentages were determined are given in the note.
[14]
Why should the difference between the United States and the rest of the world be
so marked? Tucker-Drob and Bates ran through the options: cross-national differences
in the teaching of literacy and numeracy, educational quality, access to education and
medical care, social mobility, and income support, each of which has been argued by
sources they cite. But no one has done more than speculate about any of them. The
note describes some differences in the samples that might also be relevant.[17]
The Empirical Record for Early Childhood Interventions
Few topics in social policy have received more intense empirical scrutiny than the
effects of early childhood interventions. Unfortunately, few aspects of social policy
have also been as intensely politicized. In 2013, a leading specialist in pre-K programs,
economist Greg Duncan, and social policy scholar Katherine Magnuson published a
comprehensive review of the evidence up to that time. The authors found these
conclusions to be justified by the weight of the evidence:
Effect size at program exit. A meta-analysis of 84 evaluations of preschool
programs for disadvantaged students found that “the simple average effects size for
early childhood education on cognitive and achievement scores was .35 standard
deviations at the end of the treatment periods, an amount equal to nearly half of race
differences in the kindergarten achievement gap.”18 In other words, the average effect
size was worth noticing on the exit test. But…
Trend in effect sizes over time. The same meta-analysis found that the exit effect
sizes have been decreasing over time: “Programs beginning before 1980 produced
significantly larger effect sizes (.33 standard deviations) than those that began later (.16
standard deviations).”19 The authors attributed this to improved conditions for children
in the control group from the 1970s to the end of the century.
Fadeout. When participants in preschool programs are tracked after the end of the
intervention, programs that achieved an impact at exit consistently show fadeout
averaging about .03 standard deviations per year. “With end-of-treatment effect sizes
averaging around .30 standard deviations, this implies that positive effects persist for
roughly 10 years.”20
Head Start. From its beginning in 1965, Head Start generated many evaluations,
often done by a single school system and poorly designed. As part of the Head Start
reauthorization bill in 1998, Congress mandated a large and rigorously designed
evaluation that would provide dispositive evidence. The final report of the evaluation
was issued in 2010.21
After one academic year in the program, effect sizes in six language and literacy
areas ranged from .09 to .31, but there was negligible impact on math skills or on
children’s attention, antisocial, or mental health problems. The limited effects at exit
disappeared within two years. “By the end of first grade, both achievement levels and
behavioral ratings of treatment group children were essentially similar to achievement
levels of control-group children.”22
Delayed effects. Duncan and Magnuson cite evidence from the Perry Preschool
Project, the Abecedarian Project, and Head Start that some effects of the programs
emerge only in adolescence or later. For example, a study of siblings found that
children who attended Head Start were eight percentage points more likely to graduate
from high school. “Taken together, these studies suggest that despite the decline in
program impacts on achievement test scores as children progress through elementary
school, there may be measurable and important effects of Head Start on children’s life
chances.”23
Duncan and Magnuson accurately stated the results of the various programs and
were fair-minded in their interpretations of some of the inconsistencies and puzzles in
the data. They did not, however, emphasize the reasons why even the modest
successes warrant skepticism. In his review of the same programs, Grover Whitehurst,
former head of the Department of Education’s Institute of Education Sciences,
emphasized what Duncan and Magnuson did not:
Not one of the [pre-K] studies that has suggested long-term positive impacts of
center-based early childhood programs has been based on a well-implemented
and appropriately analyzed randomized trial, and nearly all have serious
limitations in external validity. In contrast, the only two studies in the list with
both high internal and external validity (Head Start Impact and Tennessee) find
null or negative impacts, and all of the studies that point to very small, null, or
negative effects have high external validity.[24]
In 2017, the Brookings Institution and the Duke Center for Child and Family Policy
put together a task force of 10 of the leading scholars in the field to provide a
consensus statement on the findings of the research to date. The specific consensus
statements included two that led with the words “Convincing evidence.” They can
serve as a summary for my account as well:
Convincing evidence shows that children attending a diverse array of state and
school district pre-K programs are more ready for school at the end of their
pre-K year than children who do not attend pre-K. Improvements in academic
areas such as literacy and numeracy are most common; the smaller number of
studies of social-emotional and self-regulatory development generally show
more modest improvements in those areas.
Convincing evidence on the longer-term impacts of scaled-up pre-K
programs on academic outcomes and school progress is sparse, precluding
broad conclusions. The evidence that does exist often shows that pre-K-
induced improvements in learning are detectable during elementary school, but
studies also reveal null or negative longer-term impacts for some programs.25
Whether the glass is half full or half empty is a matter of perspective. My own view
is that if a four-year-old who is experiencing pain or deprivation at home spends some
hours of the day in a warm and nurturing environment, that is a good in itself that does
not need to be justified by continued impact 20 years later. Pre-K can also be a positive
socializing experience for children who aren’t experiencing pain and deprivation at
home—that’s why pre-K programs are so popular with upper-middle-class parents for
their own children. On both counts, I do not oppose spending money on pre-K
programs that provide warm and nurturing environments for children in need.
However, ascertaining the proportion of programs that actually do provide warm and
nurturing environments for children in need is a neglected research topic.
The cautionary aspect of the two “consensus statements” is that they are consistent
with Proposition #10. Recall that the mean effect size for programs since 1980 was just
0.16 in the Duncan and Magnuson meta-analysis. That’s the effect on exit tests—
which then fades out. Teachers in those pre-K programs are using the same methods
they’ve used for the last 50 years, and nothing gives reason to expect some dramatic
new pedagogy is in our future. If the potential for helping children in early childhood is
to be realized, new tools will have to be found.
“The First Premise Is Wrong When It Comes to Self-Concept”
Over the last half century, psychologists and educators have spent immense effort
experimenting with ways in which achievement in life can be enhanced by changing the
way people think about their own abilities and potential—self-concept. The three major
manifestations of this effort have involved self-esteem, stereotype threat, and growth
mindset.
The Self-Esteem Movement
The self-esteem movement came first, with its origins often attributed to Nathaniel
Branden’s The Psychology of Self-Esteem, published in 1969.26 Branden himself, who
had first come to public attention as Ayn Rand’s principal disciple, treated self-esteem
as an internalized sense of self-responsibility and self-sufficiency. But the self-esteem
movement took on a life of its own. It soon discarded those core conditions of proper
self-esteem and instead focused instead on having a favorable opinion of oneself,
independently of objective justification for that favorable opinion. Children were to be
praised because praise fosters self-esteem. Criticism should be avoided because
criticism undermines self-esteem. Classroom competitions should be avoided because
they damage the self-esteem of the losers.
From the 1970s through the 1990s, low self-esteem took on the aura of a meta-
explanation for many of society’s major problems.27 And since low self-esteem was the
problem, high self-esteem was the solution. Psychological health, high educational
performance, earnings as an adult—whatever the desired outcome, higher self-esteem
would help produce it.
The empirical underpinnings of the self-esteem movement came crashing down in
the early 2000s. A team of scholars led by Roy Baumeister, formerly an advocate for
self-esteem interventions, reviewed 15,000 studies that had been written on the
relationship of self-esteem to the development of children and concluded that
improving self-esteem does not raise grades or career achievement, or have any other
positive effect.28 You can still find remnants of the enthusiasm for self-esteem in the
public schools (for example, in the persistence of the “everyone gets a trophy”
mindset), but the scholarly standing of simple self-esteem as a way to improve
childhood outcomes has declined precipitously.
Stereotype Threat
The label stereotype threat and the concept itself were introduced in a seminal article
by Claude Steele and Joshua Aronson in 1995.29 The authors administered the same
test to two sets of African American students. The test was described as a problem-
solving exercise (a neutral description) to one sample and as an IQ test (activating a
negative stereotype of the intelligence of African Americans) to the other. The authors
concluded that the threatening condition raised concerns about being judged by the
stereotype and thereby degraded the performance of the experimental sample. The
study got widespread publicity and the concept caught on. Soon stereotype threat was
extended to negative stereotypes about women. Its popularity as a concept rose as
rapidly as that of self-esteem had climbed a quarter of a century earlier. By 2003, only
eight years after the initial article, stereotype threat was covered in two-thirds of
introductory psychology textbooks.30
From the beginning, the effects of stereotype threat have been widely
misunderstood. The original paper by Steele and Aronson was interpreted in the media
as showing that once it had been removed, the ethnic difference in test scores
disappeared.31 What Steele and Aronson actually showed is that the ethnic gap can be
increased when stereotype threat is activated. That’s not the same as evidence that the
gap shrinks when it is removed.
The most commonly studied form of stereotype threat involves women and math,
using the hypothesis that activating the negative stereotype “women aren’t good at
math” depresses women’s math scores. Five meta-analyses of such studies were
published from 2008 through 2016. Despite a host of methodological issues that have
been treated differently by the different authors, the estimated effect sizes have
clustered within a fairly narrow range, as indicated below.
Given how closely the effect sizes are grouped, it is bemusing to read the authors’
perspectives on whether the glass is half full or half empty. The authors of three of the
studies treat their effect sizes more or less at face value and think they have practical
implications (Nguyen and Ryan, Picho et al., Doyle and Voyer). In contrast, Stoet and
Geary and Flore and Wicherts are both worried about the degree to which there is
evidence of publication bias (only studies that find stereotype threat reach publication),
a lack of control groups in many studies, and other methodological weaknesses.[32]
The studies of race-based stereotype threat do not have an equivalent body of
meta-analytic results, in large part because of the difficulty of assembling large sample
sizes. The Nguyen and Ryan meta-analysis reported an effect size for ethnic minorities
of –0.32.[33] Psychologists Gregory Walton and Steven Spencer combined three field
studies using African American participants to test race-based stereotype threat. Based
on the mean level of prior performance, they reported an effect size of –0.27.[34]
In interpreting these results, the overhanging problem is “researcher degrees of
freedom”—a phrase that refers to the many decisions researchers have to make in the
course of collecting and analyzing data combined with the tendency to make those
decisions in ways that favor the hypothesis they are testing.[35] The problem is most
acute for topics that have high political and emotional salience. Stereotype threat is a
classic example. Researcher degrees of freedom affect both the decisions during the
research and the decision whether to publish negative results. There are several
indications that such decisions have been a problem with stereotype threat research:
In 2019, scholars at the University of Minnesota dealt with these and other issues
in the most comprehensive meta-analysis of stereotype threat to date, focusing on the
high-stakes test settings in which stereotype threat should theoretically cause the most
problems. For the studies relevant to high-stakes settings, the effect size of stereotype
threat was –.14 (lowering test scores), a small effect that was further reduced to –.09
after correcting for publication bias. The authors summarized their findings as follows:
Based on the results of the focal analysis, operational and motivational subsets,
and publication bias analyses, we conclude that the burden of proof shifts back
to those that claim that stereotype threat exerts a substantial effect on
standardized test takers. Our best estimate of stereotype threat effects within
groups in settings with conditions most similar to operational testing is small and
inflated by publication bias.39
Given this assessment from the largest and most rigorous meta-analysis of a quarter
century of attempts to demonstrate stereotype threat, it seems unlikely that a significant
role for stereotype threat exists.
The Growth Mindset Movement
For many people, including me, the self-esteem movement as it developed in practice
was inherently problematic: Parents and teachers were encouraged to praise children
independently of their actual accomplishments. Shouldn’t parents and teachers be
encouraging earned self-esteem? In 1998, psychologists Carol Dweck and Claudia
Mueller put another spin on that concern: When we praise children for an
accomplishment, should we praise their intelligence or their effort? They conducted six
experiments using items from Standard Progressive Matrices (a widely used test of
nonverbal ability that involves no reading) as the task assigned to 5th graders.
Subsequently, some of the students were praised for their intelligence, others were
praised for the effort that they put into the test, and others received praise that didn’t
attribute the achievement to anything (e.g., “That’s a really high score”). The results
showed large and consistent effects. Children who had been praised for being intelligent
subsequently displayed less task persistence and less task enjoyment. They became
more concerned about getting a good score than about learning new things. They
became protective of their image as “smart” and reluctant to jeopardize it.40 The
article, bluntly titled “Praise for Intelligence Can Undermine Children’s Motivation and
Performance,” was especially jarring for a society in which many upper-middle-class
parents incessantly tell their children how smart they are.
Concluding the findings was this one: “Children praised for intelligence described it
as a fixed trait more than children praised for hard work, who believed it to be subject
to improvement.”41 That finding was the seed of the growth mindset movement, which
has had at least as much effect on public education in the United States as the self-
esteem movement did. It has given birth to nonprofit organizations such as PERTS
(Project for Education Research that Scales) and a for-profit company, MindsetWorks,
which sells curricula for teaching growth mindset.42 Advocates of growth mindset have
received millions of dollars in research grants from the Department of Education, the
Institute of Educational Sciences, and the Bill & Melinda Gates Foundation, among
others.43 “Growth mindset theory has had a profound impact on the ground,” wrote
educational scholar Carl Hendrick. “It is difficult to think of a school today that is not
in thrall to the idea that beliefs about one’s ability affect subsequent performance, and
that it’s crucial to teach students that failure is merely a stepping stone to success.”44
The essence of the theory is the distinction between fixed mindsets and growth
mindsets. Fixed mindsets see attributes such as intelligence as being fixed and are
accompanied by the student’s readiness to give up in the face of failure. Growth
mindsets see attributes such as intelligence as malleable and are accompanied by a
readiness to see failure as an opportunity to try again, try harder, and get better.45
Isn’t this tantamount to saying that g can be significantly increased—something that
runs counter to a large body of literature? Advocates of the growth mindset think of it
another way. Students’ beliefs can get in the way of realizing their cognitive potential.
An unwarranted belief in one’s own incompetence is an example. Removing that belief
may not increase cognitive potential, but it can increase achievement. Similarly, growth
mindset theory does not seek basic changes in personality, but a reorientation of the
way the student construes effort or setbacks in school.46
In 2018, a team of five psychologists published a meta-analysis (first author was
Victoria Sisk) of the effects of growth mindsets regarding two questions: Is there a
relationship between a growth mindset and academic achievement? Is there evidence
that growth mindset interventions produce improvements in academic achievement?
The relationship of growth mindset to academic achievement. This meta-analysis
analyzed the results of 273 studies with a combined sample of 365,915. The mean
correlation between growth mindset and academic achievement was .10. Corrected for
measurement unreliability, the estimated correlation was .12. The Sisk study analyzed
the results relative to a variety of moderators. Academic risk status and family SES did
not affect the relationship. There were statistically significant different effects for
children, adolescents, and adults, but the effect remained weak for all subgroups.
The effects of growth mindset interventions on academic achievement. The
second meta-analysis analyzed 43 studies with a combined sample of 57,155. Thirty-
seven of the 43 effect sizes were not significantly different from zero. One was
significantly different from zero but in the wrong direction. Only five of the effect sizes
were significant and positive. Overall, the effect size was negligible (d = +0.08).
The problem in interpreting the meta-analyses is that so few of the sources
provided large-sample direct tests of growth mindset theory or interventions (many
were conflated with stereotype threat). Among those that did provide direct tests, many
were unpublished master’s theses and doctoral dissertations of uncertain quality. The
advocates of growth mindset theory can point to direct tests of the theory in the
published literature that do show effect sizes, occasionally substantial, mixed in with
small or zero effect sizes.47 Most recently, a nationwide longitudinal, double-blind,
randomized trial with a sample of more than 12,000 found that a short online growth
mindset intervention in public high schools increased the grades of lower-achieving
students over the academic year and increased enrollment in advanced math courses in
the subsequent year. The overall effect size for students at risk for low achievement
was 0.11 overall and 0.17 for those in schools with positive peer norms. The findings
were robust.48 The 0.17 effect size is small by Cohen’s guidelines and potentially
consequential by Funder and Ozer’s guidelines.49 It is about the same as the mean for
pre-K interventions, few of which were subjected to comparably rigorous evaluations.
The validation of growth mindset theory is a work in progress. The key task is to
disentangle the effects of growth mindset interventions from preexisting personality
characteristics, chiefly openness and conscientiousness, and cognitive ability.50 The
advent of polygenic scores (see chapter 14) offers rich possibilities for such efforts.
“Some Aspects of the Nonshared Environment Can Be Affected by Outside
Interventions”
Rather than accepting this gloomy prospect at the outset, it made more sense
scientifically to look for possible systematic sources of non-shared
environmental effects. However, after thirty years of searching unsuccessfully
for systematic non-shared environmental influences, it’s time to accept the
gloomy prospect. Non-shared environmental influences are unsystematic,
idiosyncratic, serendipitous events without lasting effects.56
Raise the topic of genes’ role in affecting human behavior, and chances are good that
someone is going to tell you that you’re hopelessly behind the times. Epigenetics has
proved that alterations in the environment can change our genes, and therefore
traditional beliefs about inborn characteristics are outdated and irrelevant.
It’s no surprise that this view is so widespread. Respectable media have been
reporting it for years. Time magazine explained “Why Your DNA Isn’t Your Destiny”
back in 2010, with the subtitle “The new field of epigenetics is showing how your
environment and your choices can influence your genetic code—and that of your
kids.”57 In 2013, Discover magazine told us that “the genome has long been known as
the blueprint of life, but the epigenome is life’s Etch A Sketch: Shake it hard enough,
and you can wipe clean the family curse.”58 The New York Review of Books weighed
in with “Epigenetics: The Evolution Revolution” in its issue of June 7, 2018. Authors
Israel Rosenfield and Edward Ziff reported, “Epigenetics has also made clear that the
stress caused by war, prejudice, poverty, and other forms of childhood adversity may
have consequences both for the persons affected and for their future—unborn—
children, not only for social and economic reasons but also for biological ones.”59
It’s not just the big events like war that can change our brains. Jogging can do it
too. Here’s Tara Swart, holder of a PhD in neuropharmacology from King’s College
London, writing in Forbes:
The new and evolving science [of epigenetics] tells us that our gene expression
is malleable, influenced by external stressors and lifestyle choices, from running
outside to who you have your coffee break with. Rather than having a set
genetic blueprint, epigenetics demonstrates that although our genes themselves
are fixed, our genetic expression, much of which is heritable, is also
interconnected with a wide range of environmental factors.60
With rare exceptions, the mainstream media’s reporting on the science behind
epigenetics bears little resemblance to what’s actually been discovered.
The Basics
Your personal double helix of DNA resides in the nucleus of a cell. The rest of the cell
contains the proteins that enable it to perform its particular function, whether it be a
cell in a biceps or the brain. For a cell to do that, somehow the small number of
relevant genes in the DNA producing those proteins for that cell type must be identified
and their information transcribed. Then the transcription must be transferred to the
ribosome, the place in the cell where proteins are synthesized.
The steps in the process of getting the information to the ribosome are all part of
gene regulation, also called regulation of gene expression—turning genes off or on
and turning them up or down. Some of them involve a class of chemical modifications
to DNA or to components of the “packaging” of DNA (chromatin) that has led to what
is now called epigenetics.
The word epigenesis was first used in 1651 by William Harvey to describe the
developmental process that allows the homogeneous fertilized egg to become a
complex organism. In 1942, embryologist Conrad Waddington coined epigenetics,
which he defined as the “whole complex of developmental processes,” portraying an
“epigenetic landscape” of branching pathways that a cell might take.61
In 1958, just a few years after the discovery of the structure of DNA,
microbiologist David Nanney recast Waddington’s definition. Nanney described two
types of cellular control systems. One consisted of “genetics systems” that are involved
in transcription. The other consisted of “epigenetic systems” that were auxiliary
mechanisms for determining whether expression occurred, and if so, its intensity.62
Nanney’s article also drew attention to what would become a major aspect of
epigenetics: “persistent homeostasis,” referring to cellular memory that survives cell
division.63
What caused “persistent homeostasis”? Collapsing decades of research into a few
sentences and simplifying, the answer turned out to be epigenetic marks of two kinds:
those caused by DNA methylation and those caused by histone modifications. I will
concentrate on DNA methylation, which has been more commonly studied, and ignore
histone genetic marks in this short description.
THE DNA DOESN’T CHANGE
No one claims that the DNA code is modified by environmental events. All the scientific claims
involving epigenetics, correct and incorrect, are about changes in gene expression, not changes in
DNA.
For DNA methylation, the genetic mark can be thought of as a speck of a chemical
in the methyl group64 deposited onto a gene. The most common effect of methylation
is to turn off the gene—to suppress its expression by making it less accessible to the
transcription machinery—but in some circumstances it can turn on genes or modulate
their intensity.65
The task of methylating the genome begins early in life. At conception, a fertilized
egg contains not only DNA inherited from the parents but also the parents’ methylation
patterns. About a week after conception, almost all of those patterns are erased and
almost all of the genome is methylated de novo. This new genome-wide methylation
pattern paves the way for cell specialization by repressing DNA sequences that aren’t
supposed to be expressed in a given cell. During pregnancy, methylation and
demethylation continue at specific stages of the embryo’s development in a
programmed sequence until the tissue is fully developed, whereupon it has generated a
template that is extremely stable lifelong.
Extremely stable, but not completely so. Abnormal methylation events do occur
during the lifespan and have been implicated in various diseases, including some
cancers. This brings us to the heart of the excitement over epigenetics: the evidence
that changes in methylation can be induced by environmental events.
In the breathless accounts of the epigenetics revolution, a commonplace truth often
gets lost: Environmental events routinely change gene expression. If you break a bone
in your ankle, expressions of genes in that bone are going to change so that the bone
may heal. If you run a mile, a variety of changes in gene expression will have taken
place in your respiratory system. That the environment interacts with genes to change
the phenotype temporarily is not news. It happens all the time.
The distinctiveness of epigenetic change lies in the cellular memory of methylation
that survives cell duplication. Suppose that a negative environmental event early in
childhood not only caused temporary changes in gene expression (as in a broken
ankle), but changed the methylation patterns, thereby causing permanent genetic
changes that damage the phenotype. Suppose that a subsequent positive environmental
event could demethylate and thereby reactivate the genes that had been turned off by
the negative event. Suppose—and this was the most exciting possibility of all—that
cellular memory not only survived during the lifetime of the person who had
experienced these environmentally induced genetic changes, but could be passed on to
offspring.
That’s where the hype over epigenetics originated and why it has been so attractive
to the media. Epigenetics seems to promise release from genetic determinism. It seems
to offer new explanations for phenotypic differences and new possibilities for
remediation. At the extremes, it seems to offer hope for greater equality of capabilities
and outcomes across groups.
As these potential extensions of findings about gene expression sank in during the
2000s, the use of the term epigenetics expanded to include all forms of transmission of
the phenotype by mechanisms that did not involve changes in the DNA sequence—in
other words, to expand beyond Nanney’s emphasis on cellular memory and instead
treat the larger realm of transmission of the phenotype through RNA and transcription
factors as part of epigenetics.66 For John Greally, director of the Center for
Epigenomics at the Albert Einstein College of Medicine, this is too broad a definition,
conflating changes in transcription regulatory effects with cellular memory. This has
created pervasive problems of interpretation—among other reasons because a change
in DNA methylation can be an effect instead of a cause.67 But for better or worse, the
broad interpretation of epigenetics has taken hold and a correspondingly broad research
agenda based on it has been pursued for two decades. What has been found?
The Claims of the Advocates
The first significant claims for epigenetic change were tailor-made to feed into both the
optimism and the media excitement: They dealt with the effects of maternal love in
infancy. The article “Epigenetic Programming by Maternal Behavior,” published in
2004 (first author was Ian Weaver), reported that rat pups who received high levels of
arched-back nursing plus pup licking and grooming had differences in DNA methylation
of a specific glucocorticoid receptor in the hippocampus compared to pups who
received low levels of such nurturing.68 That particular receptor has been the focus of
attention because it regulates genes known to affect early development, especially
including the response to stress.
Media accounts immediately drew the obvious implication of the Weaver study’s
finding: If these effects occurred in rat pups, perhaps human children who are deprived
of such maternal care are permanently less able to cope with stress and more
vulnerable to psychological disorders for genetic reasons. The authors further
concluded that the effects on methylation were reversed with cross-fostering. “Thus
we show that an epigenomic state of a gene can be established through behavioral
programming, and it is potentially reversible.”69 The media also fastened on this
implication: Something can be done to undo the genetic damage experienced by
children who were deprived in infancy.
Since 2004, a flood of articles in technical journals has pursued the possibilities that
the Weaver study suggested. The ones that have received the most media attention
focus on “natural experiments” in the form of the Dutch famine of 1944–45, the
Chinese famine of 1959–61, and the children of Holocaust survivors. Most of these
studies are correlational. For example, studies have documented significant increases in
the incidence of schizophrenia among children born in both the Dutch and Chinese
families.70
In the case of the Dutch famine, a team of Dutch scholars compared methylation
60 years later of people who had been in utero during the worst of the famine with
siblings who were born before or after the famine. Their conclusion:
In other words, what happened to the children in utero probably affected DNA
methylation in ways similar to those of laboratory studies, but the data didn’t permit
the authors to determine whether it was the stress on the mother or the stress on the
fetus (or both) that caused those effects on methylation, nor could they tell whether the
changes were due to changes in DNA sequence variants or other factors.
In 2016, an article on Holocaust survivors and their children got widespread media
attention in the Guardian, New York Times, and Scientific American. Based on 32
Holocaust survivors and 22 of their adult offspring, the authors (first author was
Rachel Yehuda) reported, “This is the first demonstration of an association of
preconception parental trauma with epigenetic alterations that is evident in both
exposed parent and offspring, providing potential insight into how severe
psychophysiological trauma can have intergenerational effects.”72 The key adjective
for the parental trauma was preconception. Unlike the study of methylation in the
children of the Dutch famine, the Holocaust survivor study claimed to have evidence
of transgenerational epigenetic inheritance.
As I write, two systematic reviews of the epigenetics literature have been published.
The first, published in 2016, was written by psychiatrist Gustavo Turecki and
neurobiologist Michael Meaney. Their review of the literature identified 430 articles, of
which 40 met the authors’ criteria for inclusion.73 The other systematic review,
published in 2018, was prepared by a team supervised by developmental psychologist
Wendy Kliewer. The authors limited their review to studies of infants, using 20 out of
510 unique articles that their literature search had identified.
Neither review found support for epigenetic effects resembling the portrayal of
epigenetics in the media. Neither discussed transgenerational epigenetic change. You
may check out this characterization of the results for yourself. All of the major findings
are presented in the note.[74]
The Responses of the Critics
A familiar story in the history of science is that a paradigm-breaking discovery—the
heliocentric solar system, quantum mechanics—is made by Young Turks, resisted by
the older generation of scientists, and finally wins acceptance as the geezers die off
(“Science advances one funeral at a time”).75 But that’s not how the epigenetics debate
is being conducted within the profession. Epigeneticists who are still young themselves
and doing cutting-edge work see their discipline as the victim of a hijacking. In their
view, too many epigenetics enthusiasts are reaching conclusions and publishing them
without understanding the science that already exists. For John Greally, the Yehuda
study of Holocaust survivors “is pretty typical of all epigenetics studies today for being
uninterpretable.”76 Geneticist Graham Coop had a Twitter response to the New York
Review of Books article that began, “Utter nonsense.” And they have allies in the older
generation—the week that the New York Review of Books article came out,
evolutionary biologist Jerry Coyne’s blog began with “Another lousy article on
epigenetics.”
For those who want to pursue the debate, I can point you to an exchange that gives
you an overview of the issues and references many of the key sources. The
protagonists are neuroscientist Kevin Mitchell and Jill Escher, a well-known advocate
for autistic children.
Mitchell’s case against the popularized version of epigenetics began with two long
scholarly appraisals of the data posted on his blog, Wiring the Brain, in January
2013.77 In May 2018 he returned to the subject in the wake of the Yehuda study of
Holocaust victims. He was blunt. “You could be charitable and say the evidence is
weak, circumstantial, observational, and correlative, and that it warrants
circumspection and careful interpretation (and further research, of course!). I would go
further and say that nothing in any of those papers rises to the level of what should
properly be called a finding. There’s no there there.”78
A month later, Jill Escher responded on her blog, Germline Exposures, with a list of
49 references documenting her allegation that Mitchell cherry-picked studies to make
his case and ignored abundant evidence of epigenetic inheritance in mammals. She was
as blunt as Mitchell:
Sloppy overstatement and dogmatism from the Ivory Tower, such as Mitchell’s
blog post, can breed complacency precisely at a time when we should be deeply
alarmed about the intergenerational effects of past and current exposures. It
should be clear to all of us by now that molecular insults to the germline can
influence disease, behavior or physiology of offspring, perhaps in ways that are
staggeringly important for public health. While healthy skepticism is always
welcome, research does not progress by allowing outspoken academicians to
distort the state of the science, unchallenged.79
Four days later, Mitchell responded to Escher with another detailed methodological
critique of the epigenetics literature.80
If you’re wondering how an outsider is to form an opinion, I sympathize. Of the
many complex topics in this book, I found epigenetics to be the most impenetrable for
an amateur. I come away from the literature thinking of the controversy in terms of
two broad issues.
The first is whether events in early childhood change methylation patterns and
whether such patterns are reversible. I find Mitchell’s skepticism convincing, but this
aspect of the research is being conducted using methods that lend themselves to
rigorous examination. The more ambitious claims of the enthusiasts are currently
unwarranted, but if the enthusiasts are right they will eventually be able to make their
case via the scientific method.
The second issue is whether environmentally induced changes in methylation are
passed on to the next generation. The scientifically interpretable evidence for this is
mostly from work with C. elegans (a worm about one millimeter long) and D.
melanogaster (the fruit fly), which seems a long way from proving that it happens in
humans. But some evidence of intergenerational transmission has also come from
laboratory versions of the house mouse, a mammal, which strikes closer to home.81
The most widely publicized of these was the finding in the early 2000s that feeding
pregnant mice extra vitamins during pregnancy altered the coat color and disease
susceptibility of newborn mice and that the effects lasted for two generations.82 At the
end of 2018, a team of 10 geneticists, mostly at Cambridge University, published their
finding that the methylation marks on the transposable elements thought to be involved
were not transmitted to the next generation.83 In an interview with The Scientist, Dirk
Schübeler, a molecular geneticist who was not involved in the study, called the analysis
“an enormous technical tour de force.” Before it had been conducted, he continued,
the case of the changed coat color had been treated as the tip of an iceberg. “This
study shows there is no iceberg.”84
The case for intergenerational transmission isn’t fully resolved, but the proponents
face an uphill battle. The simplest reason it’s an uphill battle was explained by the
leader of the Cambridge study, Anne Ferguson-Smith. “There’s two rounds of
epigenetic programming that basically prevent any epigenetic marks from being
transmitted from one generation to the next,” she told The Scientist. “People don’t
seem to appreciate this.”85
Bernhard Horsthemke, director of the Institut für Humangenetik at the University
of Duisburg-Essen, has expressed the problems at greater length by putting together a
“roadmap to proving transgenerational epigenetic inheritance.” I’ve consigned it to a
note because it is long and technical—but that’s my point.[86] The accounts of the
transgenerational epigenetic effects of famines and the Holocaust that have gotten so
much press ignore all of these methodological problems.
This much seems uncontroversial: The study of methylation patterns and their
manipulability is at an extremely early stage. Even if one takes all of the conclusions in
the reviews of the literature at face value, their applications are far down the road. My
point with regard to Proposition #10 is limited. Epigenetics properly understood is a
vibrant field with findings that have important medical implications. But as far as I can
tell, no serious epigeneticist is prepared to defend the notion that we are on the verge of
learning how to turn genes on and off and thereby alter behavioral traits in
disadvantaged children (or anyone else).
Recapitulation
One of the signature issues dividing conservative and liberal policy analysts for the last
50 years has been the record of outside interventions on behalf of the poor and
disadvantaged. From my perch as one of those on the conservative side of the debate,
my appraisal is that the liberals have done well in arguing the benefits of income
transfers (their downsides notwithstanding) and the conservatives have done well in
documenting the overall failure of job training programs, preschool programs, and
elementary and secondary educational reforms (their short-term results
notwithstanding).
I will reserve my more speculative conclusions for the final chapter. For now, I
want to emphasize a few points that can form broadly shared common benchmarks in
assessing the ways in which Proposition #10 might be wrong.
We’ve already tried many, many strategies using the normal tools. For 50 years,
social and educational reformers have been coming up with new ideas for
interventions. A great many of them have received federal, state, or foundation
funding, sometimes lavish funding. As we survey the prospects for better results in the
future, it’s not as if there is a backlog of untested bright ideas awaiting their chance.
The modest role of the shared environment seems solidly established. As discussed
in chapter 10, the validity of twin studies has survived searching examination of its
underlying assumptions. Insofar as violations of those assumptions exist, they probably
tend to slightly understate the role of genes. The role of “genetic nurture” is greater
than we formerly knew, but that too is rooted in biology. The harder people have
looked for purely environmental causes, the more they have turned out to have genetic
underpinnings.
The gloomy prospect for systematically affecting the nonshared environment
seems vindicated. Nothing in the pipeline shows promise of overturning the negative
results to date.
Epigenetics as portrayed in the media has no relevance to Proposition #10 for the
foreseeable future. The widespread popular belief that environmental pressures
routinely and permanently alter gene expression in humans, that those alterations are
reversible, and that their effects are passed down through generations is wrong.
Proposition #10 will eventually be wrong. On the bright side, we can look at
recent developments and see reasons that Proposition #10 cannot be true forever. The
obvious example is the positive and even life-changing effects that pharmaceuticals
developed during the last few decades have had on some forms of depression and
other mental disorders. Who knows what role future drugs might play in enhancing
learning and positively affecting personality traits and social behavior? Their effects
might be dramatic. At some point, the promise of CRISPR for gene editing will be
realized, and all bets about the ability to change people by design in substantial
numbers will be outdated. If we’re looking at the long term, Proposition #10 will
certainly be wrong eventually. Not now.
A Personal Interpretation of the Material in Part III
We live in a world where certain kinds of abilities tend to be rewarded with affluence
and professional prestige. Those abilities have a substantial genetic component. That
genetic component is a matter of luck: We don’t choose our parents.
The genetic component tends to make social class “stickier,” because successful
parents pass along not only money but their talents to their offspring. The inheritance
of status is far from an ironclad certainty for any individual—on average, the child of
parents with very high IQs and outstanding interpersonal skills will have lower IQ and
lesser interpersonal skills than their parents.87 But if we step back and ask where the
people with exceptional intelligence and interpersonal skills in the next generation are
going to come from, the answer is that they will disproportionately come from high-
SES parents.
Putting these facts together—and I submit that the evidence is conclusive enough to
warrant treating them as facts—the implication is that advanced societies have replaced
one form of unfairness with another. The old form of unfairness was that talented
people were prevented from realizing their potential because of artificial barriers rooted
in powerlessness and lack of opportunity. The new form of unfairness is that talent is
largely a matter of luck, and the few who are so unusually talented that they rise to the
top are the beneficiaries of luck in the genetic lottery.
All of these statements apply to frequency distributions and their effects on society
as a whole. As individuals, most of our lives are not genetically determined except at
the extremes of success. We can’t all become rich and famous if we try hard enough,
but just about all of us can live satisfying lives, and we have many degrees of freedom
in reaching that goal.
Part IV
Looking Ahead
The future of the liberal arts lies, therefore, in addressing the fundamental
questions of human existence head on, without embarrassment or fear, taking
them from the top down in easily understood language, and progressively
rearranging them into domains of inquiry that unite the best of science and the
humanities at each level of organization in turn. That of course is a very
difficult task. But so are cardiac surgery and building space vehicles difficult
tasks. Competent people get on with them, because they need to be done.1
—Edward O. Wilson
That’s Edward O. Wilson writing in Consilience: The Unity of Knowledge, the book
that inspired this one. Twenty-two years after I first read it, the social sciences are on
the cusp of the future that Wilson foresaw. What next?
I should probably duck the question. Another Wilson, the eminent political scientist
James Q. Wilson, had a favorite story about his mentor, the equally eminent Edward C.
Banfield. “Stop trying to predict the future, Wilson,” Banfield would say to him.
“You’re having a hard enough time predicting the past.” Banfield’s excellent advice
weighs heavily on me, but I’ll give it a try.
Chapter 14 focuses on the problem of establishing causation with genomic material
and describes a great debate about the role of genomics in social science that is already
well under way. Its resolution will determine whether the social science revolution is
upon us or will be deferred indefinitely.
In chapter 15, I offer reflections and speculations about the material I have covered
in Human Diversity, unabashedly going beyond the data.
14
I began Human Diversity by asserting that advances in genetics and neuroscience will
enable social scientists to take giant strides in understanding how the world works—
that we social scientists are like physicists at the outset of the nineteenth century,
poised at a moment in history that will produce our own Ampères and Faradays. Can
anything more specific be said about how the coming revolution will unfold? The one
certainty is that it will be full of surprises. But I can describe a centrally important
debate that is already under way and try to tease out some of its implications.
The Difference Between the Genomic and Neuroscientific Revolutions
I focus on the genomics revolution in this chapter because it will have broader direct effects on
social science than will developments in neuroscience. To do quantitative neuroscience research, you
need to be a neuroscientist and have access to extremely expensive equipment such as MRI
machines. The results of the research will inform a variety of social science questions, but the work
won’t be done by social scientists. In contrast, the products of the genomics revolution, especially
polygenic scores, will be usable by social scientists with no training in genomics by the end of the
2020s in the same way that IQ scores are used by social scientists with no training in creating IQ
tests.
A Place to Stand
Two hallmarks of genuine science are proof of causation and the ability to predict.
Until the 1960s, the social sciences barely participated. Econometrics and
psychometrics were already established disciplines, but for the most part social
scientists wrote narratives with simple descriptive statistics. Some of those narratives
had deservedly become classics—for example, W. E. B. DuBois’s The Philadelphia
Negro, Robert and Helen Lynd’s Middletown, and Gunnar Myrdal’s An American
Dilemma—but social scientists were powerless to analyze causation or make
predictions in quantitative ways except with small samples in psychology laboratories
working with rats and pigeons. The multivariate statistical techniques for dealing with
larger and messier problems of human society had been invented, but the
computational burdens were too great.
In the early 1960s, computers began to arrive on university campuses. They were
slow, clumsy things—your smartphone has orders of magnitude more computing
power and storage than the most advanced university computers then.1 Getting access
to them was laden with bureaucracy. But they could perform statistical analyses that
were too laborious to be done by hand. For the first time, social scientists could explore
questions that required adjusting for multiple variables and make cautious quantitative
claims about causation. The changes that followed were dramatic and rapid. In 1960,
technical journals in sociology and political science were collections of essays. By
1980, they were collections of articles crammed with equations, tables, and graphs. In
the subsequent 40 years, the methods have become ever more sophisticated and the
statistical packages ever more powerful. The databases on which we work our analyses
are better designed, far larger and more numerous, and often downloadable with the
click of a mouse.
And yet in one sense we have been stuck where we were in 1960. Archimedes
famously promised to move the Earth if he had a long enough lever and a place to
stand. When it comes to analyses of human behavior, the social sciences have had a
lever for decades, but no secure, solid place to stand.
The debate about nature versus nurture is not just one of many issues in social
science. It is fundamental for everything involving human behavior. At the theoretical
level, consider economic behavior. To what extent does the assumption that humans
are rational actors explain how the market actually works? Answering that question
goes to core issues of how human beings function cognitively, which in turn depends
on the relative roles of environmental conditions and biologically grounded deviations
from rational calculations. On the practical level, almost every social policy analysis,
whether it measures the impact of interventions to deter juvenile crime or tries to
predict how a piece of legislation will affect the behavior of bankers, ultimately makes
sense or not based on scientific findings about human nature. It is a statement of fact:
Most of social science ultimately rests on biology.
But we have had no causally antecedent baseline for analyzing human behavior.
Twin studies are a case in point—a powerful method to determine when genes must be
involved, but unable to push our understanding beyond heritability estimates.
Everything more detailed that we try to say about the role of nature is open to
question. Triangulating data can make alternative explanations more or less plausible,
but ultimately social scientists have had no place to stand in tackling a central question
of their profession: What is innate?
Progress in genetics and neuroscience holds out the prospect—a hope for some, a
fear for others—that we can peer into the black box. An intense debate is under way
about whether that prospect is real or chimerical.
Interpreting Causation in an Omnigenic, Pleiotropic World
Genetic causation is far more complicated than earlier generations expected. It once
seemed straightforward: After the genome had been sequenced, geneticists would
slowly assemble a jigsaw puzzle. It would be a complicated one, but eventually they
would know which variants caused what outcomes.
As recently as 1999, geneticist Neil Risch, one of the originators of genome-wide
analysis, led a team of 31 geneticists trying to find loci affecting autism. They made
news by reporting that “the overall distribution of allele sharing was most consistent
with a model of ≥ 15 susceptibility loci.”2 They characterized 15 as a large number.
Eighteen years later, three of the team’s Stanford colleagues (first author was Evan
Boyle) published an article titled “An Expanded View of Complex Traits: From
Polygenic to Omnigenic.” In it, they used the Risch study to illustrate how much had
changed. A prediction of more than 15 loci for autism “was strikingly high at the time,
but seems quaintly low now,” they wrote.3 The intervening years had brought two
revolutionary surprises.
The first surprise was that most traits were associated with many, many loci. Effect
sizes for common variants were small, and the combined effects of those loci explained
only a fraction of predicted genetic variance. As genome-wide analyses became more
sophisticated, it was discovered that some loci did have sizable effects, but those loci
were usually rare variants—and it began to look as if there might be thousands of
them. Almost everything was highly polygenic.
And that’s just counting the SNPs that directly code for proteins. “A second
surprise,” the authors wrote, “was that, in contrast to Mendelian diseases—which are
largely caused by protein-coding changes—complex traits are mainly driven by
noncoding variants that presumably affect gene regulation.”4 Interpreting a statistical
association of a certain allele in a certain SNP with the expression of a trait was going
to be arduous.
The numbers of loci involved in a given trait could be staggering. Human height is
again a good example. The Boyle study estimated that 62 percent of all common SNPs
are statistically associated with a nonzero effect on height—millions of SNPs, in other
words. Not all of them are causal, but that’s not much comfort. “Under simplifying
assumptions,” the authors wrote, “the best-fit curve suggests that ∼3.8% of 1000
Genomes SNPs have causal effects on height.”5 About 100,000.6 The Boyle study
concluded that complex traits routinely follow a similar pattern, even if not quite so
extreme. This finding led them to propose what they called the “omnigenic” model of
complex traits, incorporating the evidence that tens of thousands of loci can causally
affect a single trait.
Another complexity is that a single SNP can affect many traits. This phenomenon is
called pleiotropy. Take, for example, a 2018 study that identified 148 loci affecting
general cognitive function. The authors tested the genetic correlations between general
cognitive function and 52 health-related traits. Thirty-six of them had statistically
significant correlations, including traits with no obvious relationship to cognitive
function, such as positive correlations with grip strength and negative correlations with
angina, lung cancer, osteoarthritis, and heart attack.7
Pleiotropy is ubiquitous. In 2016, Joseph Pickrell and his colleagues assembled
statistics for genome-wide studies of 42 traits or diseases ranging from anthropometric
traits such as height and nose size to neurological diseases (e.g., Alzheimer’s,
Parkinson’s) to susceptibility to infection (e.g., childhood ear infections, tonsillitis). The
number of associations ranged from a low of 5 for age at voice drop in men to over
500 for height.8 Such statistical associations could be coincidental or they could be
causal.
If they are causal, causality could work in one of two ways, sometimes called
“vertical” and “horizontal” pleiotropy. An example of vertical pleiotropy is a variant
that increases LDL cholesterol (bad cholesterol) and also shows an association with the
incidence of heart attack—the first causal relationship is direct, the second is
downstream from the first.9 Horizontal pleiotropy occurs when a variant has direct
causal effects on traits that are apparently not causally related to each other—for
example, when a variant seems to have an effect on both LDL cholesterol levels and
schizophrenia. A 2018 analysis limited to horizontal pleiotropy concluded that
“horizontal pleiotropy is pervasive and widely distributed across the genome” and that
“there are thousands of loci that exhibit extreme levels of horizontal pleiotropy.”10
Combining these and other discoveries, the task of translating the raw material I
described in chapter 9 into statements about causation is daunting. Geneticist Graham
Coop devised a vivid thought experiment that enumerates the difficulties.
Coop asks us to imagine that a genome-wide analysis using the UK Biobank has
revealed the British to have more alleles that are associated with tea consumption than
the French have. He imagines a protagonist named Bob who concludes that the
difference between the French and the British in their preference for tea is in part
genetic. Bob is judicious. “Bob would assure us that these alleles are polymorphic in
both countries, and that both environment and culture play a role. He would further
reassure us that there’ll be an overlapping distribution of tea drinking preferences in
both countries, so he’s not saying that all British people drink more tea for genetic
reasons. He’ll tell us he’s simply interested in showing that the average difference in tea
consumption is partly genetic.”11
Coop then turns to the difficulties that Bob has in drawing even that modest causal
inference. He begins with a core point: Genome-wide analyses “do not point to specific
alleles FOR tea preferences, only to alleles that happen to be associated with tea
preference in the current set of environments experienced by people in the UK
Biobank.” Coop does not argue that nothing causally informative can come from
GWAS. Some of the tea-drinking SNPs may be enriched near olfactory receptors.
Some may be associated with caffeine sensitivity. These are interesting from a causal
point of view. But daunting problems stand between these isolated findings and the
conclusion that the differential preference for tea among British and French is partly
genetic in origin.
First, there are G×E (gene × environment) interactions to contend with. Maybe
people who care about their weight are drawn to tea instead of soft drinks because tea
has fewer calories. It is found that alleles correlated with body mass index are also
correlated with tea preference. But that won’t necessarily permit causal inferences at a
national level. Perhaps, for example, what counts is not absolute BMI but one’s relative
BMI within a country, and the distributions of BMI in the UK and France are different.
A second problem is technical. Sometimes the SNP that shows up in a genome-
wide analysis is the one that actually does the work. However, it is often a “tag” SNP
that is physically near the functional SNP in the genome but doesn’t actually do the
work.
In comparing populations, this isn’t a big problem if the correlations between the
functional SNP and the tag SNP are the same in two populations. But recall from
chapter 9 the problems of population stratification. Coop describes how they might
affect the tea-drinking analysis. Pretend that British and French ancestral populations
have been geographically separated for a long time. The correlation between functional
and tag SNPs in one population is likely to have become different from the comparable
correlation in the other population if only because of genetic drift and recombination.
Let’s say that the allele frequencies of the functional SNP in the British and the French
are the same as they’ve always been, but the correlation between the tag SNP and the
functional SNP in the British is .90 while the comparable correlation among the French
has drifted down to .70. If, unbeknownst to us, our comparison of the two countries is
based on the tag SNP, we will wrongly fail to give a bump to French tea-drinking
preferences as often as we would if we were working with the functional SNP. Put
technically, the predictive validity of the analysis will be lower for the French than it is
for the British.
A variant on this problem is assortative mating. Suppose that people who are heavy
tea drinkers tend to mate with tall people. Over a few generations, height-increasing
alleles will be statistically associated with tea drinking even if there is no causal link.
This decreases the predictive validity of that population’s genetic score for tea drinking
relative to a population that does not falsely include height-increasing alleles in its
genetic score.
Coop also discusses another topic that I raised in chapter 9: A great deal of human
variation is concentrated in rare variants that the ordinary GWA won’t pick up, and
these rare variants are commonly private to a single ancestral population. Strong
conclusions about between-population comparisons will have to wait until we have far
more information about the effects of rare variants in different populations than we
have now. Coop concludes:
The tea-drinking example illustrates just how thoroughly the old jigsaw-puzzle
metaphor has been blown up. The process of mapping causal chains from genetic
variation to phenotypic trait is immensely more complicated than that.
The Great Debate
SNP 1
Target allele: T
Allele 1: A
Allele 2: T
Genotypic score: 1
Correlation with trait: 0.005
Weighted genotypic score: 0.005
SNP 2
Target allele: C
Allele 1: G
Allele 2: G
Genotypic score: 0
Correlation with trait: 0.004
Weighted genotypic score: 0.000
SNP 3
Target allele: A
Allele 1: A
Allele 2: A
Genotypic score: 2
Correlation with trait: 0.003
Weighted genotypic score: 0.006
SNP 4
Target allele: G
Allele 1: C
Allele 2: G
Genotypic score: 1
Correlation with trait: 0.003
Weighted genotypic score: 0.003
SNP 5
Target allele: G
Allele 1: C
Allele 2: C
Genotypic score: 0
Correlation with trait: 0.003
Weighted genotypic score: 0.000
SNP 6
Target allele: T
Allele 1: A
Allele 2: T
Genotypic score: 1
Correlation with trait: 0.002
Weighted genotypic score: 0.002
SNP 7
Target allele: C
Allele 1: C
Allele 2: G
Genotypic score: 1
Correlation with trait: 0.002
Weighted genotypic score: 0.002
SNP 8
Target allele: A
Allele 1: A
Allele 2: A
Genotypic score: 2
Correlation with trait: 0.002
Weighted genotypic score: 0.004
SNP 9
Target allele: A
Allele 1: T
Allele 2: T
Genotypic score: 0
Correlation with trait: 0.001
Weighted genotypic score: 0.000
SNP 10
Target allele: C
Allele 1: C
Allele 2: G
Genotypic score: 1
Correlation with trait: 0.001
Weighted genotypic score: 0.001
Polygenic score
Target allele:
Allele 1:
Allele 2:
Genotypic score: 9
Weighted genotypic score: 0.023
Source: Adapted from Plomin (2018): Table 12.1.
Suppose you are a person whose genome has been sequenced and the target alleles
for the ten SNPs in the table are associated with an increase in height. You want to
know your polygenic score for height. For SNP 1, you have one copy of the target
allele, so you enter 1 in the column labeled “Genotypic score.” For SNP 2, neither
copy of your two alleles is the target allele, so you enter 0. For SNP 3, both copies are
the target allele, so you enter 2. And so on. All told, you have 9 height-increasing
alleles out of a possible 20. That’s the simple version of a polygenic score. The more
sophisticated version is to multiply your score in the “Genotypic score” column by a
weight. Plomin uses the correlation of the SNP with the trait (regression weights are
also commonly used). Thus your “Weighted genotypic score” for SNP 1 is .005,
greater than the weighted score for SNP 8, even though you have only one copy of the
target allele in SNP 1 versus two copies for SNP 8. Add up all the weighted scores, and
the weighted polygenic score is 0.023.
As you can see, neither the unweighted nor the weighted polygenic scores has a
natural interpretation. The polygenic score can be interpreted only relative to a
population. Fortunately, polygenic scores are normally distributed. Eventually—this
achievement is probably some years down the road—we can hope for polygenic scores
with means and standard deviations that can be interpreted in the same way that they
are interpreted for IQ scores (which also have no natural interpretation in their raw
form).
Polygenic scores are not limited to SNPs that meet the stringent requirement for
genome-wide statistical significance. Plomin points out that the goal is the best
composite score. “The new approach to polygenic scores is to keep adding SNPs as
long as they add to the predictive power of the polygenic score in independent samples.
… Some false positives will be included in the polygenic score but that is acceptable as
long as the signal increases relative to the noise, in the sense that the polygenic score
predicts more variance.”15
Plomin sees polygenic scores as a game changer for three reasons:
Predictions from polygenic scores to psychological traits are causal in just one
direction (the trait cannot be a cause of the score).
Polygenic scores can predict from birth.
Polygenic scores can predict differences between family members, something
that twin studies cannot do.
We must start from recognition that all complex human traits result from a
combination of causes. If these causes interact, it is impossible to assign
quantitative values to the fraction of a trait due to each, just as we cannot say
how much of the area of a rectangle is due, separately, to each of its two
dimensions. Thus, in the analyses of complex human phenotypes, such as those
described above, we cannot actually find “the relative importance of genes and
environment in the determination of phenotype.”26
It is important to emphasize that Feldman, Turkheimer, and like-minded colleagues
are not merely repeating Graham Coop’s cautions about how many complications
remain unresolved. They aren’t just saying that it’s early days yet and that we
shouldn’t get ahead of the data. They are saying that when it comes to complex traits,
the GWA enterprise is futile. Turkheimer again: “Causal explanations of complex
differences among humans are therefore not going to be found in individual genes or
environments any more than explanations of plate tectonics can be found in the
chemical composition of individual rocks.”27
Predictions
On some purely technical issues, the Plomin and Turkheimer schools are not in
conflict. Plomin does not argue that polygenic scores are causal as Turkheimer defines
it. On the contrary, he acknowledges the disconnect: “The correlation between a
polygenic score and a psychological trait does not tell us about the brain, behavioral or
environmental pathways by which the polygenic score affects the trait.”28 For his part,
Turkheimer does not dispute the existence of the correlations between polygenic scores
and phenotypic traits that Plomin describes.
Yet these two schools nonetheless represent radically different understandings of
where genomics and neuroscience are going to take us. The great debate for which
they are exemplars is going to continue, informed by new developments in analytic
methods and results from the huge new genomic databases that are coming online. I
have speculative opinions about how the debate will go that I will reserve for the final
chapter. Here, I confine myself to some consequences that I think are close to
inevitable.
I should begin by stating my own assessment of the great debate, because it
undoubtedly affects my predictions: In my field, applied social science, predictive
validity trumps causal pathways. The Turkheimer position about our ignorance of
causal pathways is certainly correct now and may be correct for decades to come. But
applied social science has never been about causal pathways (until now, it’s never been
an option) and perhaps never will be. It’s about explaining enough variance to make
useful probabilistic statements.
Regarding the current limitations on predictive validity and the limited ways in
which the genomic analyses add anything to what we already know from twins studies,
I again think the Turkheimer position is correct about where we stand now. If you want
to know a six-year-old’s cognitive ability, an IQ score is still much more accurate than a
polygenic score. If you want to know the heritability of a trait, polygenic scores still
don’t tell us much that we don’t already know from twin studies. But we’re talking
about a field that sees methodological advances virtually every month. I think the
application of genomic data to social science questions is roughly where aviation was in
1908. Eric Turkheimer thinks the Wright Flyer design has unfixable performance limits
(and it does). Robert Plomin foresees the DC-3 (and it’s coming).
Polygenic Scores Will Be Useful No Matter What and Will Therefore Be Used
By the end of the 2020s, it will be widely accepted that quantitative studies of social
behavior that don’t use polygenic scores usually aren’t worth reading. More formally, it
will be widely accepted that the predictive validity of polygenic scores gives us useful
information about causes even though we still don’t understand the causal pathways.
It’s not an unusual situation in science, including the hard sciences. Look at the
discovery of laws in physics through the nineteenth century that were validated solely
by their predictive validity.
I will use a specific example to illustrate the situation facing applied social science.
Suppose it’s 2030 and researchers are exploring causes of juvenile crime. In addition to
the standard predictors as of 2020 (e.g., parental SES, education, IQ), researchers have
access to polygenic scores for various aspects of criminality. They analyze how the
phenotypic measures interact with the polygenic measures as predictors of criminal
behavior. In light of the Turkheimer school’s objections, can the researchers be sure
that the results for the polygenic scores are legitimately interpreted as causal? No. But
in an Occam’s-razor sense, the results of the analyses will make alternative hypotheses
more or less plausible and, as importantly, generate ideas for the next round of analyses
that will incrementally clarify what’s going on. In 2030, when large databases with
genomic information are easily available, I predict it will be akin to professional
malpractice to conduct an analysis of social behavior that does not include genomic
information. In any case, few quantitative social scientists are going to write such
analyses because they won’t get past peer review. The question, “Why didn’t you take
genetics into account?” will be universal and will have no good answer.
Broad Swaths of Social Science Will Be Affected
As I write, none of the social sciences have come to terms with genetics. My second
prediction is that by 2030 the holdouts will be confined to isolated pockets. The impact
of the genomic revolution will have importantly affected all of the traditional social
science disciplines.
“Affect” can mean several things. The most important will be the role of genomics
in creating novel research strategies that wouldn’t have occurred to a social scientist in
the pre-genomics era. In the study of genetic effects, twin studies are confining. They
require large, hard-to-assemble, expensive samples of twins. The Falconer equations
are a blunt tool that enables us to apportion roles to genes, shared environment, and
everything else, thereby answering the “how much” question. The new techniques will
open up new ways to explore the “how” questions. I’ve focused on polygenic scores,
but a variety of analytic tools are being developed—for example, Genome-Wide
Complex Trait Analysis (GCTA).29 Just as the advent of the university computer did in
the 1960s and 1970s, the advent of cheap genomic information will generate new
classes of studies that cannot be anticipated. Comparing the eventual power and
flexibility of genomic analyses with the ACE model is akin to comparing the power and
flexibility of multiple regression analysis with the analysis of a 2×2 contingency table.
With regard to the existing classes of studies, cheap genomic information will also
broadly affect studies that analyze a personality trait, ability, or social behavior as it
varies by sex, ethnicity, or class. The degree to which such studies are woven into
research agendas varies by discipline.
Psychology. The genomics revolution will affect just about everything in
psychology that involves the analysis of quantitative data. Psychology is about
understanding human personality, emotions, cognitive abilities, and behavior. All of
those topics include genetic sources. Plomin’s description of the possibilities that I
summarized earlier conveys the breadth of the potential effects on both clinical practice
and research.
Anthropology. Two of anthropology’s subfields, archaeology and physical
anthropology, deal in topics that can obviously be informed by ancient DNA, and
there’s no reason to think scholars in those fields won’t take advantage of it. The other
two subfields, cultural anthropology and linguistic anthropology, should be as
dramatically affected by genomic information as psychology will be, but they are now a
battleground between scholars who see their discipline as a science and those who see
it as a hybrid of investigation and social justice advocacy.[30] I assume that genomic
information will be incorporated to some degree into these latter two subfields, but it is
not clear to what extent.
Sociology. Some corners of sociology involve empirical topics that won’t be
affected, but they are the exception. To give you an idea, consider the 49 articles that
were published in America’s most prestigious sociological journal, the American
Sociological Review, in 2018 and the first issue of 2019. Of the 39 articles that
presented either survey data or quantitative experimental results, 33 were on topics for
which polygenic scores would be directly relevant. In almost half (18 of the 39), the
major topic of the article directly involved sex, ethnicity, or class.[31]
Economics and political science. The role of psychological factors in economics
goes back to Adam Smith’s Theory of Moral Sentiments. The work of Daniel
Kahneman, Amos Tversky, and Paul Slovic on decision making under conditions of
uncertainty and, more recently, the work of Cass Sunstein and Richard Thaler on
“nudge” theory, are both rich fields of study that will be informed by genomic data.32
They are only part of the growing field of behavioral economics. Similarly, questions
about how humans act as political agents are at the core of political science. Genomic
information is just as relevant to voting decisions as it is to economic decisions. The
finding from twin studies that political and ideological views are substantially heritable
opens up another set of possibilities.
Social policy. Perhaps the most visible impact of the genomics revolution will be
found in public policy analysis. This prediction obviously includes almost any issue
involving education, whether pre-K, K–12, or higher education, but it also includes
welfare policy, criminality and criminal justice, foster care and adoption, marriage and
family, poverty and unemployment—you name it. If it’s about social policy, it’s almost
certainly about topics that genomic data will inform.
We already have one specific example as I write. An international team led by
Kathryn Paige Harden and Benjamin Domingue used polygenic scores as a “molecular
tracer” to explore how the flow of students through the math pipeline in secondary
schools varied in socioeconomically advantaged and disadvantaged schools. Among
other things, the analysis revealed that advantaged schools did a better job than
disadvantaged schools of getting students with high polygenic scores into advanced
math classes and of buffering students with low polygenic scores from dropping out of
math. It also revealed that many students with exceptional polygenic scores were
unlikely to take the most advanced math classes.33 If these findings were to be
replicated and elaborated, they would have direct implications for better education
policy. It’s just the beginning.
Some Basics About the Role of the Environment Will Be Better Understood Soon
It will be a long time before the details are fully understood, but the introduction of
genomic data will answer some of the most basic questions about the respective roles
of genes and environment quickly, for two reasons.
First, genomic data can answer questions about genetic nurture (discussed in
chapter 13) that twin studies cannot. In twin studies, the shared environment is the
same for both twins, which raises difficult technical problems when there is no
variation around the family mean (for example, as in the case of divorce, which is by
definition completely shared by both MZ and DZ twins).34 Analyses using polygenic
scores or GCTA are not constrained to twins and thereby escape that problem.
The broader advantage of genomic analyses in this regard is that the complexities of
genetic nurture can be unraveled. “Although twin studies have reported for decades
that most environments are nearly as heritable as behaviors, this work has been limited
to twin-specific environments,” write Maciej Trzaskowski and Robert Plomin. “GCTA
opens up the possibility of investigating genetic influence on family-, neighborhood-, or
even country-wide environmental measures that cannot be studied using the twin
design because they are shared in common by members of a twin pair.”35 The same is
true of analyses using polygenic scores.
Second, genomic analyses using polygenic scores give us a usable baseline measure
of genetic potential. As matters stand, every measure of genetic potential that we use,
whether from cognitive tests or personality inventories, is contaminated by potential
environmental effects, and the contamination is rightly feared to be worst for people
who have come from the most disadvantaged environments. Correlations between
polygenic scores and phenotypes cannot be explained by backward causation, and that
alone is enough to give us important leverage, despite all the complications.36
Eric Turkheimer has used an analogy that illustrates what I mean, comparing
polygenic scores to a pile of raw building materials. Let’s say that you have many such
piles, each of which will be used to construct a building. If you carefully examine the
components of different piles, you can determine similarities among them—the
buildings’ starting places. “That similarity in starting place winds up being correlated
with how similar the eventual buildings are,” Turkheimer writes. “So pile-similarity is
correlated with similarity in how the buildings are used, or what color they are or how
big they are, or whatever. These correlations aren’t enormous, but they are striking,
often in the range of .4–.6. What’s more, it turns out that occasionally, there are
identical piles of materials, and although these identical piles don’t produce identical
buildings, the buildings they produce are damn similar, often in the range of .7–.9. This
is the heritability of building type.”37
Turkheimer’s point is that an individual’s genetic potential can lead to a widely
dispersed range of phenotypes, which is unquestionably true. My point is that the piles
are there at the beginning, constrain the range of possibilities, and are causal in just one
direction. By the same token, a polygenic score for IQ or any other trait is causally
antecedent, and that makes an enormous difference in the research questions we can
answer confidently.
To see how dramatically this will change matters, recall from chapter 12 the vexed
question of a G×E interaction between childhood SES and the heritability of IQ. The
reason that vexed question is so important is that low heritability for disadvantaged
children at young ages could mean an opening for interventions to have major effects.
One reason the results have been so equivocal is that measures of IQ before the age of
six are so unreliable. A reasonably good polygenic score for IQ fixes that.
Suppose that polygenic scores of children from disadvantaged backgrounds show
that their IQ scores as adolescents average 10 points lower than their polygenic scores
would have led us to expect. Confident new knowledge of that kind will energize the
search for effective interventions in ways that we can scarcely imagine. Conversely,
suppose it is found that the relationship of polygenic scores to phenotypic IQ scores in
adolescence is about the same regardless of the childhood environment. I realize that
many people dread such an outcome. In fact, that too will provide an incentive: to
redirect our attention to fostering human flourishing for people with a wide range of
ineradicable inequalities in gifts—a topic I take up in the concluding chapter. The most
likely scenario is that the results will be less dramatic in either direction but will
nonetheless teach us much about untapped potential.
The example generalizes to a wide variety of topics in which the underlying
question is the extent to which socioeconomic or cultural disadvantage has affected the
realization of a person’s potential. I will not spin out all the collateral analyses that
could be done or describe how the analytic complications could be dealt with. I do not
expect that such analyses will be free of controversy. Rather, I am asserting that many
such analyses are technically feasible, will be conducted within the relatively near
future, and will offer powerful tests of questions that have been argued for decades.
Eventually Environmental Influences Will Be Demystified
As matters stand, the environment is routinely treated by many social scientists as
almost mystically complicated.[38] I will have more speculative comments to make
about that assumption in the next chapter, but this much is not speculative: Being freed
from the restriction to samples of twins will enable this position to be explored as well,
though the process will take much longer than answering the basic questions.
Is socioeconomic environment in a specific culture the issue? We don’t need to go
out and assemble new longitudinal databases. We already have many large longitudinal
databases with detailed data on family structure, parenting practices, SES, education,
labor market experience, and just about every other interesting variable you can name.
The samples for many of these databases could easily be genotyped. Take, for
example, the 1979 and 1997 cohorts of the National Longitudinal Survey of Youth, two
of the most widely used American databases. Almost all of the members of those
samples are still alive and most of their whereabouts are known. Ask them for cheek
swabs in return for the kind of genomic information for which 23andMe charges a few
hundred dollars. We may be genotyping people at age 60, but in doing so we get
virtually the same baseline information that we would have gotten had we genotyped
them at birth.39 If we want to explore intergenerational effects, we can genotype the
parents and the offspring of the members of these samples.
Are we interested in G×E interactions for ancestral populations? Every major
ancestral population lives in every conceivable kind of environment. They live in
countries in different parts of the world. Within most of those countries, they have
varying socioeconomic status, varying numbers of generations of acculturation, and,
for that matter, varying degrees of admixture with other ancestral populations. They
live in countries that they rule and countries in which they are minorities. As minorities,
they live in countries where discrimination against their ethnic group is severe and
countries where it is negligible. Do ethnicity and environment interact in complex
ways? The natural variation in the environments where ancestral populations live is so
great that the raw material for answering that question is plentiful.
If the environment really is as pervasive and subtle a force as so many believe, the
comparisons of polygenic scores and phenotypic scores will reveal their complex
interactions and be a rich source of information for future research. But it’s also
possible that for some traits in some populations in some situations, the role of the
environment is not particularly complicated or important. That too would be an
important finding.
Recapitulation
The great debate will not end soon. The contending parties can continue to make their
respective cases on the core issues no matter what the other side says. If proving
causation at the molecular level is the goal, the Turkheimer school’s pessimism seems
well founded. If predictive validity is the goal, the Plomin school has good evidence
that usable polygenic scores for many traits are either already available or coming soon.
I will add, however, my own view that one important issue has already been
decided: There’s no longer any question whether the use of polygenic scores will be
widespread. This is already obvious in medical research. In 2010, two technical articles
in the U.S. National Library of Medicine contained the phrase “polygenic score” or
“polygenic risk score” in the title or abstract. By 2015, that number was up to 47. In
2018, it was 171. Publications during the first half of 2019 were on pace to increase by
another third.40 We can expect the same swift upsurge of publications in the social
sciences.
Beyond any of the specifics I have discussed, I share Plomin’s belief that we are in
the midst of an unfolding and historic revolution in the social sciences. As he put it in
Blueprint, “The most exciting aspect of polygenic scores is the potential they offer for
completely new and unexpected directions for research.”41 He gives examples from his
own research involving schools and social mobility, but his enthusiasm is properly
open-ended. When a scientific discipline gets a major new tool such as the microscope,
electrolysis, or spectroscopy, the eventual uses sprawl far beyond their original ones.
Polygenic scores will be a similarly multipurpose tool for expanding the questions that
social scientists can ask. Ultimately, the incorporation of genetic information into the
social sciences will be transformative.
15
The study of human diversity fascinates me, and I hope it has captured your interest
as well. Ongoing discoveries in genetics and neuroscience are going to change our
world in profound ways over the coming decades. I am optimistic that almost all of
them will be for the better.
The findings I have presented boil down to just three cautious conclusions:
Human beings can be biologically classified into groups by sex and by ancestral
population. Like most biological classifications, these groups have fuzzy edges.
This complicates things analytically, but no more than that.
Many phenotypic differences in personality, abilities, and social behavior that we
observe between the sexes, among ancestral populations, and among social
classes have a biological component.
Growing knowledge about human diversity will inevitably shape the future of the
social sciences.
I hope this long and winding account has also made it clear that we need not fear
talking about human differences. Nothing we are going to learn will diminish our
common humanity. Nothing we learn will justify rank-ordering human groups from
superior to inferior—the bundles of qualities that make us human are far too
complicated for that. Nothing we learn will lend itself to genetic determinism. We live
our lives with an abundance of unpredictability, both genetic and environmental.
Above all, nothing we learn will threaten human equality properly understood. I like
the way Steven Pinker put it: “Equality is not the empirical claim that all groups of
humans are interchangeable; it is the moral principle that individuals should not be
judged or constrained by the average properties of their group.”1
My conclusions are so cautious that they shouldn’t be controversial. If the
preceding chapters haven’t persuaded you of that, a summing up in this chapter is not
going to do the job.
I use this final chapter for another purpose. Writing Human Diversity has touched
on topics that I have been researching and thinking about for decades. The experience
has prompted many reactions on my part that don’t belong in the previous chapters
because they are based on the totality of my experience. I want to express them, but I
do so with trepidation. Remember that you are reading my personal and sometimes
idiosyncratic interpretations. They neither augment nor diminish the empirical case
for the ten propositions. The evidence that those propositions are true needs to be
confronted. Having done that, go ahead and form your own opinion of their
implications without regard to anything that follows. I am about to go beyond the data.
The Role of Genes in Explaining Human Differences Has Been Misconceived
I hope that the twenty-first century will see both social scientists and policymakers
come to peace with the reality of human nature. It’s about time.
The Eclipse of Human Nature
From antiquity through the Renaissance, most thinkers took it for granted that human
beings come into the world with preexisting characteristics. In the West, little was
written about how people could be changed except through Christian salvation. Then
toward the end of the seventeenth century came John Locke, intellectual father of the
Enlightenment, who popularized the theory of the mind as blank slate—tabula rasa.2
Locke himself was advocating empiricism and opposing the use of supposedly innate
ideas that justified the divine right of kings, hereditary aristocracies, and authoritarian
religious institutions.3 But the blank slate metaphor was powerful. It soon spread to the
assumption that human beings are malleable, molded by events and capable of being
molded by design.
In the eighteenth century, this position was most flamboyantly proclaimed by the
Enlightenment’s rock star, Jean-Jacques Rousseau, who was romantically optimistic
about education’s potential to do the molding by design. Even unromantic Adam Smith
believed in a partially blank slate: “The difference between the most dissimilar
characters, between a philosopher and a common street porter, for example, seems to
arise not so much from nature, as from habit, custom, and education.”4
But Smith also had a fully realized conception of an inborn human nature (see The
Theory of Moral Sentiments), and thereby represents a competing stream of
eighteenth-century thought in which he was joined by others in the Scottish
Enlightenment and by the American founders. Whereas the French First Republic
reified the belief that humans could be molded into any shape that rational planners
might devise, the American Constitution reified the belief that human nature must
shape the structure of government, not the other way around. Why did the founders
insist upon the checks and balances? “It may be a reflection on human nature,”
Madison famously wrote, “that such devices should be necessary to control the abuses
of government. But what is government itself, but the greatest of all reflections on
human nature?”5
During the nineteenth century, unsentimental realism about human nature lost
ground to a strange mix of idealism and rationalism that pursued extravagant goals. Karl
Marx outdid all the rest with his grand theoretical application of the scientific method
(as Marx saw it) to human malleability, blending history, sociology, economics, and
politics into a utopian vision of what could be accomplished given the right economic
and institutional structures.
The Communists who came to power in Russia didn’t think it was just theory; they
thought it would work miracles. “Communist life will not be formed blindly, like coral
islands, but will be built consciously, will be tested by thought, will be directed and
corrected,” Leon Trotsky wrote in 1924. “Man, who will learn how to move rivers and
mountains, how to build peoples’ palaces on the peaks of Mont Blanc and at the
bottom of the Atlantic, will not only be able to add to his own life richness, brilliancy
and intensity, but also a dynamic quality of the highest degree.”6
Elsewhere, the pioneers of the new discipline of sociology had less extreme
ambitions, but they drew from the same optimism about the power of the scientific
method applied to human behavior. “Our main objective,” Émile Durkheim wrote of
sociology, “is to extend the scope of scientific rationalism to cover human behavior.”
Causes and effects could be spelled out, he continued, and they in turn “can then be
transformed into rules of action for the future.”7 The constraints of inborn human
nature? “These individual natures are merely the indeterminate material that the social
factor molds and transforms.”8
At the beginning of the twentieth century, the application of the scientific method to
human malleability was extended to another new discipline, psychology. Behaviorism,
founded by John B. Watson, took the blank slate to its ultimate expression.9
By the 1940s, behaviorism had become a major field within academic psychology
departments, with B. F. Skinner acquiring considerable fame for, among other things,
his Skinner box for studying operant conditioning.11 Skinner was also convinced that
you often didn’t need to study humans to understand humans—pigeons and rats would
do. Or as one of his former students, Richard Herrnstein, answered, deadpan, when I
asked him why behaviorists used pigeons for research: “Given the right reinforcement
schedule, pigeons are indistinguishable from Harvard sophomores.”12
Eventually, the malleability assumption spilled over into policy. The social
democratic left in Europe and liberal thinkers in the United States did not aspire to
create a “new man” as the Communists had, but they were confident that many of
society’s problems of poverty, crime, and educational failure were waiting to be solved
by rational thinking scientifically applied to malleable human beings. The phrase “social
engineering” came into vogue—not used sarcastically as it usually is today, but as a
label for policies that would move society closer to utopia. The designers of those
programs did not spend time brooding over inborn, intractable characteristics of human
beings that might foil their plans.
The mid-1960s through the mid-1970s saw the apogee of American academic
optimism for using public policy to change behaviors on a grand scale. But as the
evaluations came in, it became apparent that the multibillion-dollar initiatives of the
Great Society in education, employment, and criminal justice had not worked out as
planned.13 Aspirations were scaled back. The emphasis changed from an upbeat
attitude that “smart social policy can fix that!” to the darker mentality of
intersectionality. By the 1990s, the problems of poverty, crime, and educational failure
were increasingly ascribed to an intractable, pervasive structure of oppression.
Meanwhile, the psychologists you met in Part III were using twin studies to explore
the heritability of human traits. But even those who were comfortable with a major role
for heritability of discrete traits were not necessarily comfortable with a role for human
nature.
Human nature refers to a coherent conception of the ways that human beings have
been shaped by evolution. My idea here goes all the way back to chapter 1 and my
reasons for wanting to aggregate effect sizes rather than treat them separately. What
makes the differences between male and female personalities interesting and important
is not an effect size of +0.24 on one facet in a personality inventory and –0.38 on
another, but the way that differences on a dozen facets fit together as a profile. So it is
with human nature: The important thing is not the heritabilities of specific traits but the
way that the heritability of a variety of linked traits forms an interpretable mosaic.
Even psychologists who are leading scholars of heritability shy away from putting
the pieces together or acknowledging that the pieces can be put together—such is the
shadow that has become associated with human nature. In Steven Pinker’s words, “To
acknowledge human nature, many think, is to endorse racism, sexism, war, greed,
genocide, nihilism, reactionary politics, and neglect of children and the disadvantaged.
Any claim that the mind has an innate organization strikes people not as a hypothesis
that might be incorrect but as a thought it is immoral to think.”14 That description,
written near the turn of the new century, still applies two decades later. Changing it
requires a rediscovery of human nature.
The Rediscovery of Human Nature
The rediscovery of human nature has been the province of evolutionary psychology.
One of my predictions about the genomics revolution, too speculative to be included in
chapter 14, is that evolutionary psychology will finally take its rightful role as a major
tool for understanding differences in cognitive repertoires across the sexes, ancestral
populations, and social classes. One of the ways it will do so is by tying the elements of
cognitive repertoires into a coherent description of human nature.
What we know as evolutionary psychology was anticipated in Darwin’s own work,
but it was not until 1964 and 1972 that seminal articles by William Hamilton and
Robert Trivers respectively provided a rich set of hypotheses for exploring how human
nature has been shaped through evolutionary processes.15 Biologist E. O. Wilson
expanded upon their work in Sociobiology (1975), and Richard Dawkins popularized
some of the key themes in The Selfish Gene a year later.16 Over the course of the
1980s, psychologist Leda Cosmides and anthropologist John Tooby wrote a series of
articles on evolutionary psychology that culminated in 1992 with “The Psychological
Foundations of Culture,” which proposed to replace what they called the Standard
Social Science Model (the intellectual version of the orthodoxy) with an Integrated
Causal Model that would bring biology into the picture.17
Even as evolutionary psychology matured as a discipline and developed ways of
dealing with the dangers of just-so storytelling, it was no secret that the underlying
objections to evolutionary psychology were political—the virulently hostile reaction to
E. O. Wilson’s Sociobiology left no doubt about it. A familiar figure from Part II,
Richard Lewontin, was joined by neurobiologist Steven Rose and psychologist Leon
Kamin as authors of a denunciation of evolutionary psychology titled Not in Our
Genes: Biology, Ideology, and Human Nature (1984).18 That hostility continues to this
day. It is an integral part of the orthodoxy.19
Evolutionary psychologists have been fighting back for decades and can claim to
have won on points many times over, but it has done little good.20 One of them, Steve
Stewart-Williams, has not repressed his frustration. “Critics who rail against status quo
bolstering, genetic determinism, and just-so story-telling are like the crazy person in the
bus shelter, fighting with a sparring partner who isn’t really there. They’ve invented
their own evolutionary psychology and are arguing loudly with that,” he wrote.21
“Fighting the evolutionary psychologists’ corner is like weeding a garden, or cutting the
head off a hydra. It’s like a Nietzschean eternal recurrence, or pushing Sisyphus’s rock
up the hill again and again, forever. And it’s also a pain in the butt.”22
I may sound naïve in predicting that the genomics revolution is going to finally get
the rock to the top of the hill. The orthodoxy has not had a problem brushing off hard
evidence in the past. Why should the genomics revolution pose a greater problem?
The reason goes back to the antiscientific bulwark that the orthodox are huddling
behind. Evolutionary psychology is about the reality of inborn human nature: the role
that biology has played in shaping human beings above the neck. The orthodox are
saying that it’s all socialization. They have felt able to continue to maintain this position
because there has not been an ironclad, you-can’t-get-around-this-one refutation of it.
Polygenic scores will eventually provide that.
Once again, look ahead to 2030. By that time, scientists will be able to make
predictions about personality characteristics, abilities, and social behavior of groups on
the basis of polygenic scores. If the orthodoxy is right, such statistical predictions
should be impossible. If everything is socialization, then DNA samples shouldn’t be
able to tell you anything about differences in personality characteristics, abilities, or
social behavior among adults.
“But they can just soften their position,” it may be argued. The orthodoxy can shift
to an “it’s almost but not entirely a matter of socialization” and carry on as before.
Perhaps that’s right, but I doubt it. We didn’t need to sequence the genome to
recognize that human beings have evolved underlying characteristics that are deeply
biological. In that sense, the orthodoxy on campuses has been hanging on inexplicably,
like a religious cult whose leader’s predictions have been contradicted by events time
and again. That amounts to a fragile situation. I don’t think the orthodoxy can tolerate
acknowledging openly that, for example, men and women are biologically different
above the neck even a little bit.
This explains my probably starry-eyed expectation: The ability to predict a wide
variety of human differences solely from baseline genetic measures will puncture the
center of the orthodoxy’s beleaguered defense. Evolutionary psychologists will be
liberated to make strides in describing human nature, not just individual heritable traits,
in an environment where the legitimacy and importance of their contributions is
accepted.
Reconciling Human Nature with Ideology
The insistence that only the environment shapes cognitive repertoires has been yet
another case, like “gender is a social construct” and “race is a social construct,” of
taking partial truths and running them into the ground. In the centuries when Locke and
Smith wrote, most people with the potential to be philosophers probably really were
living out their lives as street porters—and farmers and housewives. People in all eras
and places really are shaped to some degree by their environment. But the limits of
shaping are governed by hundreds of millions of years of evolution.
An apt example of the clash between utopian plans and human nature comes from
Israeli kibbutzes founded in the 1930s and 1940s. Infants and children were cared for
by full-time caretakers and lived in a centralized children’s quarter, spending only a few
hours per day with their parents. The intention was to replace the nuclear family with
the extended family of the community. The rationale for doing so was grounded in
ideals about human flourishing. The members of the early kibbutzes were themselves
idealistic and committed to their utopian goals. The kibbutzes were small enough (a
few hundred people) to permit intimate communities to form. The members shared
powerful bonds of a common ethnic and cultural heritage. If ever a socialist utopian
community could succeed, the kibbutzes had the best chance. For a while, it seemed to
work.23 Over the years, however, the nuclear family ineluctably reasserted itself.24 It
was inevitable. Societies must be made to fit human nature, because human nature
cannot be reshaped to fit theoretical utopias.
This brings us to the intersection of scientific findings and political ideology. I have
a problem finding the right words here, because the meanings of “conservative” and
“liberal” have shifted so radically in recent years. I’m using them as they were
popularly understood in the United States from the New Deal until 2016. With those
meanings in mind, this much is undeniable: The belief in constraints and limits on
government’s ability to change people is inherently conservative. The belief in open-
ended potential for changing people through the right policies is inherently liberal.
That doesn’t mean that liberals are forced into denying human nature; it just means
that they need to take it into account. In the case of sex differences, this can often be
done by adjusting policy to recognize differences in distributions between men and
women. Custody of children after divorce is a case in point. Until the last quarter of the
nineteenth century, men were automatically awarded custody of children. By the latter
part of the nineteenth century, and largely as a result of first-wave feminism, the
“tender years doctrine” automatically gave the mother custody of young children unless
there was clear evidence that the mother was unfit. In the 1970s, one effect of second-
wave feminism in many states was to remove the mother’s legal advantage in custody
disputes, substituting “the best interests of the child” as the basis for custody decisions
and encouraging joint custody.
What is likely to be in “the best interests of the child” when the child is of “tender
years”? By any measure of which sex is better at nurturing young children, there is a
big effect size favoring females and an overwhelming evolutionary case that the female
advantage is grounded in biology. If that is accepted as scientific reality, what is a
principled liberal position toward child custody? One option is to follow Pinker’s
principle that people should not be judged by the average properties of their group.
That’s clearly the right call when we’re talking about fairness in treating job applicants
or criminal defendants. But what about when a helpless third party’s “best interests”
are involved? In a world where judges in custody disputes often are faced with no clear
evidentiary basis for favoring one parent over another and a helpless third party’s
welfare is at stake, a principled liberal position can acknowledge an important innate
difference between men and women.
Similarly, Title IX of the Education Amendments of 1972 had a good rationale (if
you aren’t a libertarian) for requiring schools to provide equitable opportunity for
female students to participate in sports.25 Some girls love competitive sports, and they
weren’t being offered enough opportunities to play them. It’s also true that by any
measure of interest in team sports there’s a big effect size favoring males and there is
again an overwhelming evolutionary case that the greater male interest is grounded in
biology.26 Title IX should be administered with that difference in mind (it often hasn’t
been).
Women in combat? It’s not an issue of female courage. But from early childhood
into adulthood, males are far more attracted than females to physical contests,
including ones involving violence, and are more physically aggressive and risk-taking
than women. Once again there is an overwhelming case that the sex difference is
grounded in biology.27 Are women as enthusiastic as men about attacking and killing
total strangers if the proper institutional framework is provided (i.e., the military in
battle)? Are women as obsessively driven to win at all costs in contest situations as
men? Some women are, but what proportion? Can male soldiers be trained out of their
instinct to protect women? Probably some can—but what proportion? Men and
women have different distributions on these traits, with biology playing a major role.
The conclusion need not be that women shouldn’t be used in combat roles, but that the
relevant sex differences need to be taken into account. Women in combat as part of a
missile-firing team on a warship sidesteps the potential problems I just mentioned;
women in combat as part of a frontline infantry platoon triggers all of them.
Being realistic about human nature goes far beyond sex differences. An acceptance
of the constraints imposed by human nature should guide the administration of the civil
and criminal justice systems, the regulation of business, the powers granted to
bureaucrats—the operations of just about every social, cultural, economic, and political
institution. It can be done by conservatives and liberals alike without either side having
to abandon core principles. The challenge for conservatives is to accommodate their
historic advocacy of freedom and limited government with the role of the genetic
lottery in determining success. The challenge for liberals is to acknowledge the
constraints of human nature in ways they have historically resisted.
The Role of the Environment in Explaining Human Differences Has Been
Misconceived
It’s Not the Shared Environment Versus the Nonshared Environment. It’s the
Manipulable Environment Versus Happenstance and Milieu.
I cannot prove that the role of the environment in explaining human differences has
been misconceived, but I can describe why I think so.
Murray’s Conjecture
Analogies have been a popular way to describe the relative roles of genes and the
environment for 50 years. Richard Lewontin started it in 1970 with one that Richard
Herrnstein and I adapted for The Bell Curve: All of the kernels in a strain of hybrid
seed corn are genetically identical. But if two handfuls of that seed corn are planted in
Iowa and the Mojave Desert, there will be a huge difference in yield.28 Christopher
Jencks continued the tradition in 1979 with his analogy of red-haired children who are
denied education (hair color is highly heritable and will be correlated with a difference
in academic achievement, but it has nothing to do with genes).29 Eric Turkheimer used
piles of building materials to describe the limits of the genetic contribution in predicting
phenotypic traits. Graham Coop produced the most elaborate analogy, the one about
differences in French and English tea drinking that I recounted in chapter 14.
What these analogies have in common is that none of them would pose a problem
to a real analysis. That’s understandable; analogies need to employ simplistic situations
to make their point. But social scientists trying to figure out differences in corn yield,
educational achievement, the appearance of finished buildings, and tea drinking are not
going to spend a nanosecond puzzling over the environmental forces at work. They are
blindingly obvious. I think this is true far more often than most social scientists
concede, hence Murray’s Conjecture: When a difference really is environmental in
origin, it’s easy to prove it; when it’s hard to prove an environmental cause, it’s
because the role of the environment is minor.30
Why were there so proportionally few female physicians through the first half of
the twentieth century? Guess what: It was the environment. Proving that it was the
environment is trivially easy. Why has there been so little change in the vocational
choices of women for the last thirty years? It is now difficult to make an empirical case
that residual sexism is the culprit. The reason it’s so difficult, the conjecture says, is
because the environment no longer has much effect.
The conjecture applies to personality traits and abilities, but I must specify that it
often does not apply to much of social behavior. As I will explain subsequently, I think
milieu everywhere and always has pervasive effects on social behavior.
As an elaboration of Murray’s Conjecture, I propose a distinction among three
types of environmental forces: legal compulsion, hard custom, and soft custom.
Legal compulsion. In the hierarchy of ways in which some human beings can force
others to do their bidding, physical coercion is at the top. In a civilized society, that
means legal compulsion. Why was European Jewish achievement in the arts and
sciences so rare from the Middle Ages until the nineteenth century? Because Jews were
prohibited by law from entering universities or engaging in scientific professions. Within
two generations of their legal emancipation, Jews were disproportionately represented
among the leading figures in both the arts and sciences.31
Hard custom refers to means other than laws that entail coercion. An example of
physical coercion (and the threat of it) was the extralegal enforcement of segregation in
the South to supplement the Jim Crow laws until the Civil Rights Act of 1964 and
continuing to some degree thereafter. A nonviolent example of covert prohibition is the
de facto ceiling that many medical schools put on the number of women they would
admit until the law mandated equal access. Hard custom can persist for a long time
even though it is not underwritten by laws. Under some circumstances, legal
prohibition of discrimination can shorten its persistence.
Soft custom has no element of covert prohibition or the threat of physical coercion.
It consists instead of social incentives to refrain from engaging in a behavior—stigma or
social isolation. No one will beat you up, you won’t lose your job, nor will any other
tangible punishment be administered from on high. But you must bear social
punishment—the disapproval of your parents, teachers, or other people who matter to
you. Some of your friends become ex-friends. Your coworkers may shun you. For
example, if you were one of the first women hired as police patrol officers in the
1960s, you had to put up with a lot, even if you were treated correctly professionally
(which often didn’t happen). Maybe none of your male coworkers would eat lunch
with you and you would be subjected to endless derogatory comments about women’s
abilities.
My speculative proposition here is that once legal prohibitions and hard custom are
no longer an issue, soft custom has a short half-life. The arrival of even a second
policewoman on the force is a big relief to the pioneer. Then there are three, five, and
10 women. Many male police officers who were initially hostile see that the women are
pretty good cops after all and begin to accept them as equals. I am not saying that soft
custom goes away entirely, but that its power to intimidate diminishes nonlinearly, just
as the half-life of radioactivity diminishes nonlinearly. Further, I would argue that the
half-life is often a matter of years, sometimes a decade or so, but seldom many
decades.
Translated into the way I see the role of the environment as it is usually construed,
I think that much of the remaining discrimination against women, ethnic minorities, and
LGBT people in the United States consists of soft custom and is well into or past its
first half-life, albeit to varying degrees in different geographic and socioeconomic
settings. That’s why proving a large independent role for the environment in differential
outcomes is often becoming difficult.
Happenstance, Milieu, and the Manipulable Environment
None of the above means that the environment is unimportant in determining how
people’s lives turn out. But in conceptualizing the environment, we shouldn’t divide it
into the shared environment and the nonshared environment. Rather, we should divide
it into happenstance, milieu, and the manipulable environment.
Happenstance. Happenstance is equivalent to the nonshared environment seen
from a different perspective.
Surely everyone who has reached middle age occasionally stops to muse on how
differently life would have turned out except for random events. Certainly it is true of
people who are lucky enough to be in happy marriages. Meeting that right person is
almost always the result of a series of capricious events, and it’s scary to think how
your life would have been different if any one of the pieces hadn’t fallen into place.
With regard to one’s children, happenstance amounts to one-in-millions chances that
they turned out to be who they uniquely are. And of course, so was the union of egg
and sperm that created you. The role of randomness is huge.
But do you feel the same way about the kind of person you have become? Your
abilities? Your personality strengths and weaknesses? Speaking for myself, I know that
my circles of friends, the places I’ve lived, the books I have written, and all sorts of
other ways in which my personality traits and abilities have been expressed in behavior
have been hugely affected by happenstance. So has my happiness. I can easily imagine
having reached old age sad and lonely because of happenstance. But I sense that my
personality traits and abilities are close to what they would have been no matter what,
short of some extreme psychological or physical trauma.
I would argue that happenstance explains why people discover as they get older
that they are becoming more like their parents—a common personal experience that is
reflected in the technical literature demonstrating that heritability of many traits rises
with age. My logic goes like this: In adolescence and young adulthood, people act
inconsistently with their genetic predispositions for many reasons. Sometimes they are
consciously rebelling against their parents. The broader generic reason is that
adolescents and young adults are immature and prone to spectacularly poor judgment.
That’s why most of us recall things we did in adolescence and into our 20s and say to
ourselves, “What could I have been thinking?”
THE REAL MEANING OF CLASS PRIVILEGE
During those same years, we get bounced around by happenstance. Some random
influences push us to do foolish things; other random influences push us toward
maturity. For most people, this multitude of random events balances out, and we
emerge into adulthood less likely to do things that run against genetic predisposition.
Whether that’s good, bad, or indifferent depends on what genetic predispositions we’re
talking about. But the nonshared environment has had its heyday. It may have played
havoc with our lives for a time, but those effects were temporary (recall evidence to
that effect from chapter 13).
Milieu refers to the world into which we are born in its cultural, social, and
economic totality—the water in which we swim. Milieu often exerts itself most
powerfully on a national scale, but it has many variations. The Amish have managed to
preserve a comprehensive milieu in the face of a competitive national milieu. The
typical college or university has a milieu that transcends socioeconomic status. So does
a black neighborhood in Harlem or a Korean neighborhood in Los Angeles. In
America’s current polarized state, many of the politically committed of both extremes
live in separate milieus. In my view, the current biggest American division is the milieu
of small towns and small cities versus the milieu of the megalopolises and their
suburbs.
Milieu is pervasively causal. It doesn’t just influence the ways we behave. It
entirely rules out many possibilities and makes others almost inevitable. A thought
experiment may make the point. Imagine that Michelangelo, Mozart, and Shakespeare
are all cloned in the twenty-first century as babies with exactly the same DNA as the
originals. Let us suppose that as adults they respectively become an artist, a composer,
and a writer. It is easily imaginable that they will rise to the top of their professions in
our time—their talents would be prodigious in any century. But it is inconceivable that
their masterpieces will be anything like the Pietà, the Jupiter Symphony, or King Lear.
Expressions of genius are decisively shaped by the milieu into which geniuses are born.
Thinking of the distinction between milieu and environment in this way makes it
easy for me to understand why the shared environment explains so little. Go back to
our clone of Mozart. Let’s say that you and your spouse are the cloned boy’s adoptive
parents. You know about his talent, and you think classical music would be the highest
expression of his talent. What are you going to do that will channel that genius into
composing some new string quartets in the classical style? You can try all sorts of
things to manipulate the family environment, but you can’t affect the milieu. Every
moment that the cloned Mozart is not directly under your control, he will be swimming
in the milieu—in comparison to which parents are nearly powerless. He may compose
some mind-bendingly wonderful popular music or even wonderful atonal music. Not
the Jupiter.
The milieu exerts a similar influence over everyone’s life decisions. The
occupations that are in vogue. The age at which people marry and the number of
children they have. Sexual mores. Conceptions of virtue. Religiosity. The milieu
changes continually, usually in the way that an ocean liner changes course—visibly, but
seldom abruptly.32 Government can affect milieu, but, sadly, the best examples of
“successfully” doing so are the regimes of Hitler, Stalin, and Mao. In democratic
regimes, changes in the milieu are commonly driven by broad changes in the culture
that then prompt expression in public policy. The civil rights movement followed by the
Civil Rights Act of 1964 is a recent example in American history—it is inconceivable
that the Civil Rights Act would have been passed in any earlier administration no
matter how hard a president or party fought for it. The milieu wasn’t yet right.
The manipulable environment refers to discrete aspects of our world that are at
least theoretically possible to manipulate. It includes parenting practices, parental SES,
the school, and most other aspects of what twin studies call the shared environment.
Even if you share my belief that the milieu is a far more powerful influence, doesn’t
the fact that these influences are manipulable mean that we ought to try to manipulate
them for the benefit of those who need help? That brings us to a question that policy
analysts have been pondering for many years:
Why Is It So Hard for Outside Interventions to Work?
Of the 10 propositions that I defend in Human Diversity, the one that might attract the
most vehement criticism is the final one, #10: “Outside interventions are inherently
constrained in the effects they can have on personality, abilities, and social behavior.” I
almost refrained from spelling it out. What’s the point, since the amount of money now
being spent on such programs is rounding error in the federal budget? I included
Proposition #10 nonetheless because among the truths that need to be understood is
how incredibly difficult it is to get people to change permanently if they don’t already
want to—and sometimes even if they do.
One way or another, I have spent more than half a century around programs that
were trying to get people to change the way they behave, whether as a “change agent”
(how quaint that label sounds now) in the Peace Corps in the 1960s, an evaluator of
social programs in the field in the 1970s, or a policy analyst reading the technical
literature on social programs from the 1980s onward. These have been experiences that
would make a cynic of a far saintlier person than I, and I suppose they account for my
instinctive reaction to reports of success: “Oh yeah?” I have indeed grown cynical
listening to glowing descriptions of programs that turned out to bear no resemblance to
what was happening on the ground. I grew cynical because of technical articles in
which the upbeat “Conclusions” section about a program’s accomplishments didn’t
match up with the numbers in the “Results” section.
But those were not the experiences that most affected me. I alluded to my most
dispiriting ones in the acknowledgments for Losing Ground, written soon after I had
stopped evaluating social programs. My first debt, I wrote, was to the people who had
run the social programs I had observed:
I am under the impression that I now know some answers to that question that I
did not know in 1984.
The Fragility of Induced Effects
Effects of outside intervention are fragile. In a scientific sense, this is most apparent in
the hundreds of attempts since the 1960s to positively affect the capabilities and
behavior of disadvantaged populations, such as the pre-K programs I discussed in
chapter 13. This is not the place to hash out the contentious literature on other types of
interventions, but I think that four generalizations drawn from that literature are easily
defended.
The first one is positive: Programs for people who self-select into the program can
work.
Alcoholics Anonymous is the most famous example, but there are others. KIPP and
Success Academy are charter schools that have had success in educating students who
include many minority children from low-income households.34 The parents self-select
on behalf of their children and the children themselves also have to buy into KIPP’s
and Success Academy’s rigorous expectations. This is not to say that programs with
self-selected clients are universally successful. But we do know how to help people
who consciously want to help themselves and are prepared to try hard.
The other three generalizations apply to programs that try to help people without
self-selection, and they are pessimistic:
Substantively significant short-term effects have been observed, but even these
have been comparatively rare.
Fadeout of those immediate effects over a period of a few years has been nearly
universal.
Over the last six decades, not a single major improvement in the education or
socialization of the disadvantaged has been scaled up to the state or national
level.
What makes this dismal experience puzzling is that everyone who has spent time
with these efforts has seen anecdotal cases of not just “substantively significant” but
what looked like dramatic change. I remember observing classes in an inner-city school
in Atlanta where an experimental method of teaching math was being used. The same
kids who had been somnolent or sullen in other classes were on the edge of their seats,
completely engaged in an extremely fast-paced, intensive instruction in honest-to-god
math. This was in the late 1970s. The method was never scaled up, and I can
understand why. It required teachers to expend an enormous amount of nervous
energy over the entire class period. I can’t imagine being able to summon that kind of
energy for more than two periods a day at most. I can’t imagine that more than a small
fraction of teachers have the skillset required to do it successfully even for two periods
a day. Is it possible to take a class of ordinary students in a school in a
socioeconomically deprived neighborhood and make them excited about math? Yes,
I’ve seen it done. Do I have the remotest practical idea for how to do it on a large
scale? No.
There are success stories of all kinds out there, but they seldom last. The school
dropout whose mentor convinced her to return to school is enthusiastic for a few
months and then drops out again. The drug user relapses. The student who got special
tutoring in reading and whose grades went up in the first semester flunks the second
semester. If failure to follow up the initial success were the explanation, then the
solution would be simple: Provide follow-up support. But this leads to a second theme
regarding the fragility of environmentally induced change:
The Relapse Syndrome
It is striking and even mysterious how hard it is to sustain a good effect. I’m not talking
about disadvantaged children, but about you and me.
Does the word “diet” come to mind? Losing weight is something that large numbers
of Americans have successfully accomplished—temporarily. But the number of people
who are able to maintain their new, lower weight is minuscule compared to the number
who gain all the weight back within a few months.
What makes this especially odd is that the experience of the diet is often positive.
After a few days, you find that you aren’t suffering from terrible hunger after all, and
you have more energy. As you lose weight, you like the way you look in the mirror and
like the compliments you get from friends. You are getting exactly the positive
reinforcement that you hoped to get. And yet a few months later you are off the diet
and have gained back all the weight. Why? Different people have different answers,
but it comes down to this: You theoretically should be able to manipulate the
environment to produce a change in your phenotype, but it’s as if there were an
ineluctable gravitational force pulling you back to a genetic baseline, whether that
genetic baseline is grounded in your metabolism, your self-discipline, or some other
complicated set of personal tendencies over which you don’t seem to have enough
control.
The same may be said of other self-initiated attempts at improvement, whether it’s
a resolution to stick to an exercise regime or to keep your desk tidy. It’s not that we
fail, nor that we find we don’t like being fit or having a tidy desk. We succeed for a
while and enjoy the results. But it all fades away.
I will use another personal example, because it involves an achievement that has
eluded educators despite their most strenuous attempts: dramatically raising cognitive
function—not an effect size of +0.35 or +0.50, but of two or three standard deviations.
One summer while I was in graduate school, I enrolled in the Evelyn Wood speed-
reading course. When I entered the course, a pretest revealed that I read at about 500
words per minute—okay but nothing special. At the end of the course (as I recall, it
was about six weeks) I was reading at around 2,500 words per minute. It is hard to
convey what a phenomenal experience it is to be turning the pages of a book every few
seconds with full comprehension. Furthermore, the change was not as straightforward
as losing weight. The program had drastically raised my ability on a complex cognitive
task. As a graduate student with a crushing reading load, it seemed too good to be true.
And it was. There was a catch, and my Evelyn Wood teacher was stern about it:
You’ve got to read everything using the Evelyn Wood technique. You can’t decide to
pick up a detective novel and read it slowly just for fun. If you do, you’ll lose your
speed. I can’t complain that I wasn’t warned. And of course, I didn’t follow through,
and within a few months I was back at baseline. The experience often comes to mind
when people ask me if there’s any way to raise IQ and I have to answer that there’s no
way to raise it dramatically. Then some corner of my mind goes back to that brief,
shining moment when one of my own cognitive abilities shot upward like a rocket, and
I add, “not permanently.”
Nutritionists have a phrase for what happens with diets. Each person has a “set
point” (or “settling point”): a weight range that the body will defend if weight falls
below or above that range. I’m not going to get into the science of diets, but the
concept applies to a wide variety of traits that technically can be changed by
environmental stimuli, but seldom are permanently changed by those stimuli. A
heritability of, say, 50 percent means that half of the expression of that trait is
environmental, but it does not necessarily mean that any nontrivial proportion of that
environment can be manipulated to achieve a preferable expression of that trait over
the long term. It’s another reason I think the environmental role assigned to traits by
twin studies overestimates the plasticity of human beings. We are not made of soft
plastic that can be molded and then hardens into place. We are balls of Silly Putty. We
can be molded into interesting shapes—temporarily. Leave us alone for a while and
we’re flat again.
Toward the Best of All Possible Worlds
Custom dictates that policy analysts finish books by presenting politically realistic
policy recommendations. But despite being a policy analyst by profession, I have never
done so. I can’t think of any that I believe would make a difference. Instead, I have
advocated changes that I think would work if they were implemented but that I know
are politically impossible—replacing all welfare and income transfer programs with a
universal basic income, legal defense funds to support systematic civil disobedience to
the federal government, and universal education vouchers, among others.
Valued Places and the Four Wellsprings for Human Flourishing
However, I do have beliefs about policy implications more sweepingly defined. Readers
who don’t know what they are have an ample choice of sources. I’ve touched on them
in all but a few of the books I’ve written from Losing Ground on, most
comprehensively in In Pursuit (1988). I’m not going to write another full-scale
description here. But since the broad policy implications I have in mind bear intimately
on what motivated me to write Human Diversity, a few paragraphs are appropriate.
DOCUMENTATION
I am about to level a series of sweeping criticisms of public policy and the new upper class without
documentation. For those who are curious, here are the past discussions I am drawing on.
On the proper dependent variable for assessing public policy: In Pursuit, chapters 1, 2, and 8.
On valued places and the four wellsprings for human flourishing: In Pursuit, chapter 12; The
Bell Curve, chapter 22; In Our Hands, chapters 8, 9, 10, and 11; Coming Apart, chapter 15.
On the forces creating the new upper class: The Bell Curve, chapters 1, 2, 3, and 4; Coming
Apart, chapters 1 and 2.
On the segregation of the new upper class: The Bell Curve, chapter 21, and Coming Apart,
chapters 3 and 4.
On elites changing the rules in ways that they approve but which make life difficult for ordinary
Americans: Losing Ground, chapters 1, 2, 3, 12, 13, 14; In Pursuit, chapters 5 and 12; The Bell
Curve, chapters 21 and 22; Real Education, chapters 3 and 5; Coming Apart, chapters 14, 15, and
17; By the People, chapters 2, 3, and 4.
My argument begins with two apparently unrelated propositions. First, the ultimate
goal of public policy is not to do things like raise incomes or increase college graduation
rates but to enable people to flourish and to achieve deep satisfactions in life—to
pursue happiness in the Aristotelian sense of that word. Second, recent decades have
seen the development of the new upper class that I described in Coming Apart—not
just influential and affluent, but smart, highly educated, with its own distinctive culture,
significantly cut off from mainstream American society. It is the same group, no longer
emergent but having come to power, that Richard Herrnstein and I called the “cognitive
elite” in The Bell Curve. The new upper class includes (though is not limited to) the
people who have the leading roles in shaping the nation’s economy, culture, and
politics.
As individuals, most members of the new upper class are fine people, personally
and professionally. As a group, however, I think they have much to answer for. They
have created a world that is ideal for them, filled with the kind of complexity that they
are able to navigate and through which they can extract both money and power. At the
same time, they have abdicated their role as stewards of the culture. The new upper
class has been attentive to issues of economic inequality and inequality of opportunity
but has refused to take seriously other questions that invoke human flourishing—the
ways in which all human beings, not just those with IQs of 130-plus, can reach old age
satisfied with who they have been and what they have done. For me, what matters
most is not material equality, but access to the wellsprings of human flourishing, which
in turn requires that society be structured so that people across a wide range of
personal qualities and abilities are able to find valued places.
My definition of valued place is the same now as when Richard Herrnstein and I
coined the term in The Bell Curve: “You occupy a valued place if other people would
miss you if you were gone.”35 The central valued places are located in four domains
that I have argued are the wellsprings of human flourishing: family, community,
vocation, and faith. The valued places those wellsprings offer for adults are spouse,
parent, relative, friend, neighbor, congregant, and colleague. It is my view that social
policies since the mid-twentieth century, continuing to the present, have inadvertently
stripped ordinary people of valued places while leaving intact the ones enjoyed by the
new upper class.
I accept a role for economics. Hunger and homelessness are not conducive to
human flourishing. The government can provide resources that enable people to be not
homeless and not hungry. My own favored solution is a universal basic income that
replaces the existing system of transfers. I have written at length about why I think that
such a system would eliminate involuntary poverty and revitalize civil society.36 But
this is not the place to make the case for a specific solution. Rather, I want to stress
that satisfactions and dignity both arise from occupying valued places, and valued
places have to be formed gradually by the people who occupy them. What the new
upper class can do is honor the wellsprings. That means, for example, celebrating
marriage not just as one of many options, but as the institution that gives the most
people the best chance of creating a deep and fulfilling intimate relationship with
another adult. It means celebrating Tocquevillian community, whether it is found in a
small town or a neighborhood in a megalopolis. It means celebrating productive work
of all kinds. It means celebrating the fulfillment that people of faith derive from their
faith.
“Celebrating” does not mean passing laws. It means that the people who sit at the
apex of the nation’s politics, economics, and culture need to be advocates for marriage,
community, productive work, and, at the least, to treat religion with respect. Large
numbers of them fail that test and have failed it for decades. The members of the new
upper class avail themselves of the wellsprings. They marry, raise children, live in
communities they find satisfying, work hard, and some of them are religious. But they
don’t even acknowledge that they are tapping into the traditional sources of human
flourishing, let alone celebrate ordinary Americans who do. Instead, their attitude
toward ordinary Americans is too often covertly condescending if they are people of
color and openly disparaging if they are white. What are the policy implications of
Human Diversity? They don’t constitute a policy agenda. They involve the human
heart, not legislation or regulations. The first step is to reconstruct a moral vocabulary
for discussing human differences.
Reconstructing a Moral Vocabulary for Discussing Human Differences
A century ago, Walter Lippmann, then one of the nation’s most influential public
intellectuals, wrote of IQ tests, “I hate the impudence of a claim that in fifty minutes
you can judge and classify a human being’s predestined fitness in life. I hate the
pretentiousness of that claim. I hate the abuse of scientific method which it involves. I
hate the sense of superiority which it creates, and the sense of inferiority that it
imposes.”37 Among many people, polygenic scores prompt the same anger and
revulsion. They foresee dystopian futures in which polygenic scores are used to judge
and classify a human being’s predestined fitness in life according not just to IQ but
other cognitive traits as well. Personality traits. Potential for mental illness. Potential for
criminality.
The dystopian dangers are real, but so are wonderful opportunities to use our new
knowledge to do good. We won’t avoid the dangers and take advantage of the
opportunities until we are able to talk easily and realistically about human differences.
And yet so few try to do it. The conversation today within the new upper class seems
always to be about the ways in which individual differences are created by
environmental conditions that we must fix. It is seldom about how to deal with
differences that can’t be fixed.
Why? I think at the root is the new upper class’s conflation of intellectual ability
and the professions it enables with human worth. Few admit it, of course. But the
evolving zeitgeist of the new upper class has led to a misbegotten hierarchy whereby
being a surgeon is better in some sense of human worth than being an insurance
salesman, being an executive in a high-tech firm is better than being a housewife, and a
neighborhood of people with advanced degrees is better than a neighborhood of high
school graduates. To put it so baldly makes it obvious how senseless it is. There
shouldn’t be any relationship between these things and human worth. And yet, among
too many in the new upper class, there is.
The conflation of intellectual ability with human worth helps to explain the new
upper class’s insistence that inequalities of intellectual ability must be the product of
environmental disadvantage. Many people with high IQs really do feel sorry for people
with low IQs. If the environment is to blame, then those unfortunates can be helped,
and that makes people who want to help them feel good. If genes are to blame, it
makes people who want to help them feel bad. People prefer feeling good to feeling
bad, so they engage in confirmation bias when it comes to the evidence about the
causes of human differences.
I expect the genomics and neuroscientific revolutions to give us undeniable
evidence that differences in personality, abilities, and social behavior exist across
individuals and groups alike and that those differences cannot be much reduced by the
kinds of public policy changes that are available to us. For America, the old way of
dealing with that reality was the moral vocabulary of Christianity. We are all deeply
flawed—sinners—and we are all the beneficiaries of God’s unearned love and grace.
We are all equal in God’s eyes. That theological foundation, combined with America’s
devotion to individual freedom, underwrote a signature feature of American
exceptionalism: our egalitarianism. One of our proudest boasts was that in the United
States, people aren’t better than anyone else just because they have more money or a
higher position. We didn’t live by that ideal perfectly, but we did much better than
many people realize. In living memory, it was considered un-American to be a snob, to
look down on other Americans, and to think you were better than anyone else.
The moral vocabulary we must reconstruct for twenty-first century America cannot
be Christian nor even ecumenically religious. Society in general and the new upper
class in particular are too secular for that. The only choice left to us is a secular
understanding of the truth behind the old formulation, “We are all equal in God’s eyes.”
That secular understanding begins with the recognition that personality humility is not
optional but compulsory. If you possess unusual beauty, charm, intellect, or talent of
any sort, pride is inappropriate. Go ahead and take satisfaction in the use you have
made of your gifts (with a mental caveat that some of the resources you called on are
partly heritable too), but live with the consciousness of how incredibly lucky you were
to have been born that way and try to be worthy of it.
Humility is the first step in coming to grips with a secular version of “we are all
equal in God’s eyes,” but the fullness and depth of that truth cannot be apprehended
abstractly. It needs to be understood through experience. That starts with realizing that
most people are good, competent, and likeable, including those who don’t have much
in common with you—even, amazingly, people who don’t share your politics. The
more kinds of people you know and the better you know them, the easier it is to
recognize that “equality of human worth” isn’t just rhetoric. You will also find it is easy
to talk about the reality of human differences if you know in your gut how unimportant
those differences are in deciding whether the person next to you is someone you
respect. My prescription for the new upper class: Get out more.
When we are able once again to talk easily about human differences, a difficult and
elusive next step remains. The wellsprings of human flourishing have been going dry
for many Americans, and the damage done by the new upper class—however
inadvertently—has been importantly to blame. Replenishing and revitalizing those
wellsprings should be our first priority. But developing policies that replenish and
revitalize them must begin with a drastic shift in the thinking of most of the people who
run the nation’s economy, culture, and politics. It is time for America’s elites to try
living with inequality of talents, understanding that each human being has strengths
and weaknesses, qualities we admire and qualities we do not admire, and that our good
opinion seldom turns on a person’s talents, but rather on a person’s character. We need
a new species of public policy that accepts differences and works with people as they
are, not as we want to shape them. I hope this book contributes to that process.
Acknowledgments
I began work on Human Diversity with curiosity but only an informed amateur’s
knowledge about either genetics or neuroscience. As I always have done when taking
on an unfamiliar discipline, my first step was to find recent technical articles on topics
of interest and use the literature reviews to start tunneling into the subject matter.
The difference between this time and all the previous times was the breathtaking
complexity of the articles I was reading. The nomenclature alone was daunting, but that
was nothing compared to the substance. The processes required to go from a SNP to a
synthesized protein and then from proteins to effects on the phenotype were not only
stranger than I knew, but stranger than I could have imagined. Neuroscience was no
easier, with nomenclature as unfamiliar and brain structure and function as
complicated.
As I promised in the introduction, I stuck to the low-hanging fruit, but it was
obvious that I would need experts to save me from blunders. I adopted two strategies.
First, I emailed drafts of my work to the lead authors of the technical articles that I
discussed at length, asking them to tell me what I’d gotten wrong. Second, I asked
geneticists, neuroscientists, and behavior geneticists who were most well versed in
these topics to read long sections of text and vet them for errors of fact or
interpretation.
I am a controversial figure. The last thing a geneticist or neuroscientist working on
a college campus needs is to be thanked publicly by me. I therefore added a promise to
all my requests for review: “Your response will not be used in any way except to
improve the accuracy of the text. You will not be listed in the acknowledgments nor
will I disclose in any forum that you saw the draft.” That’s why I’m not going to give
you a single name of the many who responded to my requests (many did not) and to
whom I am so indebted. I hope they understand how grateful I am. I have a special
soft spot for those who responded to drafts that contained criticism of their work. In
return, I did my best to revise the text until they saw the presentation as fair, even
though residual disagreements remained.
I can safely thank a few people by name. E. O. Wilson, the pioneer of
sociobiology, planted the seeds of Human Diversity by writing Consilience: The Unity
of Knowledge, which I read when it first appeared in 1998. I was immediately
convinced that Wilson was right, and my excitement about the integration of the social
sciences with biology has stuck with me ever since. Arthur Brooks, AEI’s president,
and Karlyn Bowman and Ryan Streeter, successively the directors of social and
political studies at AEI as I worked on Human Diversity, were wholly supportive. Sean
Desmond, editor of two of my earlier books, returned to lend his wise editorial counsel
and to make the text much more readable. Roland Ottewell, my official copy editor,
and Miles Hoffman, my unofficial one and friend of 35 years, meticulously scrutinized
a late draft of the complete text. My agent, Amanda Urban, operated as she has since
she took me on in 1984: the good shepherd making sure her author is treated right,
morphing into a lioness as needed. None of this help means that no errors remain. An
anxious aspect of publishing a complicated book is knowing that mistakes must still be
hiding in there.
My wife and editor, Catherine, who has featured in so many acknowledgments,
initially tried to talk me out of writing Human Diversity. When I began work in the fall
of 2016, the nastiness associated with the reaction to The Bell Curve was a distant
memory. Did I really want to go through that again? I didn’t think it would be a big
deal one way or the other, but I was concerned that she was concerned. Then came
the radicalization of the campuses, when we learned that the bad old days were back
no matter what. “Confound it!” said Catherine, or two syllables to that effect, on the
day I returned from the riot at Middlebury. “If they’re going to do this kind of thing
anyway, go ahead and write it.” Human Diversity appears with her blessing, which
was absolutely essential. She is the coauthor of my life.
Charles Murray
Burkittsville, Maryland
July 29, 2019
Discover Your Next Great Read
Get sneak peeks, book recommendations, and news about your favorite authors.
The following is aimed at the liberal arts graduate who has not taken a math course
since high school and knows nothing whatsoever about statistics but wants to
understand the statistical concepts used in the text.
Distributions and Standard Deviations
This is a frequency distribution. What good is it? Looking at your high school
classmates standing around in a mob, you can tell little about their height. Looking at
those same classmates arranged into a frequency distribution, you can tell a lot, quickly
and memorably.
How Is the Distribution Related to the Standard Deviation?
We still lack a convenient way of expressing where people are in that distribution. What
does it mean to say that two different students are, say, six inches different in height?
How “big” is a six-inch difference? That brings us back to the standard deviation.
When it comes to high school students, you have a good idea of how big a six-inch
difference is. But what does a six-inch difference mean if you are talking about the
height of elephants? About the height of cats? It depends. And the things it depends on
are the average height and how much height varies among the things you are
measuring. A standard deviation gives you a way of taking both the average and that
variability into account, so that “six inches” can be expressed in a way that means
the same thing for high school students relative to other high school students,
elephants relative to other elephants, and cats relative to other cats.
How Do You Compute a Standard Deviation?
Suppose that your high school class consisted of just two people, who were 66 inches
and 70 inches tall. Obviously, the average is 68 inches. Just as obviously, one person is
2 inches shorter than average, one person is 2 inches taller than average. The standard
deviation is a kind of average of the differences from the mean—2 inches, in this
example. Suppose you add two more people to the class, one who is 64 inches and the
other who is 72 inches. The mean hasn’t changed (the two new people balance each
other off exactly). But the newcomers are each 4 inches different from the average
height of 68 inches. So the standard deviation, which measures the spread, has gotten
bigger as well. Now two people are 4 inches different from the average and two people
are 2 inches different from the average. That adds up to a total of 12 inches, divided
among four persons. The simple average of these differences from the mean is 3
inches, which is almost (but not quite) what the standard deviation is. To be precise,
the standard deviation is calculated by squaring the deviations from the mean, then
summing them, then finding their average, then taking the square root of the result. In
this example, two people are 4 inches from the mean and two are 2 inches from the
mean. The sum of the squared deviations is 40 (i.e., 16 + 16 + 4 + 4). Their average is
10 (40 ÷ 4). The square root of 10 is 3.16, which is the standard deviation for this
example. The technical reasons for using the standard deviation instead of the simple
average of the deviations from the mean are not necessary to go into, except that in
normal distributions, the standard deviation has wonderfully convenient properties. If
you are looking for a short, easy way to think of a standard deviation, “the average
difference from the mean” is close enough.
As an example of how a standard deviation can be used to compare apples and
oranges, suppose we are looking at members of the Olympic women’s gymnastics team
and professional basketball players. You notice a woman who is 5 feet 6 inches and a
man who is 7 feet. You know from watching gymnastics on television that 5 feet 6
inches is tall for a woman gymnast and 7 feet is tall even for a basketball player. But
you want to do better than a general impression. Just how unusual is the woman,
compared to the average gymnast on the U.S. women’s team, and how unusual is the
man, compared to the average professional basketball player?
We gather data on height among the women gymnasts and determine that the mean
is 5 feet 1 inch with a standard deviation (SD) of 2 inches (made-up numbers for this
example). For professional basketball players, we find that the mean is 6 feet 6 inches
and the SD is 4 inches. Thus the woman who is 5 feet 6 inches is 2.5 standard
deviations taller than the average; the seven-foot man is only 1.5 standard deviations
taller than the average. These numbers—2.5 for the woman and 1.5 for the man—are
also the basis for effect sizes introduced in chapter 1. Now we have an explicit
numerical way to compare how different the two people are from their respective
averages, and we have a basis for concluding that the woman who is 5 feet 6 inches is
a lot taller relative to other female Olympic gymnasts than a 7-foot man is relative to
other professional basketball players.
How Much More Different? Enter the Normal Distribution
Everyone has heard the phrase normal distribution or bell-shaped curve, or, as in the
title of a controversial book, bell curve. They all refer to a common way that natural
phenomena arrange themselves approximately (the true normal distribution is a
mathematical abstraction that is never perfectly observed in nature). If you look again
at the distribution of high school boys that opened the discussion, you will see the
makings of a bell curve. If we added several thousand more boys to it, the kinks and
irregularities would smooth out, and it would actually get close to a normal distribution.
A perfect one looks like the one in the figure below.
It makes sense that most things will be arranged in bell-shaped curves. Extremes
tend to be rarer than the average. If that sounds like a tautology, it is only because bell
curves are so common. Consider height again. Seven feet is “extreme” for humans.
But if human height were distributed so that equal proportions of people were five feet,
six feet, and seven feet tall, the extreme would not be rarer than the average. It just so
happens that the world hardly ever works that way.
Bell curves (or close approximations to them) are not only common in nature, they
have a close mathematical affinity to the meaning of the standard deviation. In any true
normal distribution, no matter whether the elements are the heights of basketball
players, the diameters of screw heads, or the milk production of cows, 68.3 percent of
all the cases fall in the interval between one standard deviation above the mean and one
standard deviation below it.
In its mathematical form, the normal distribution extends to infinity in both
directions, never quite reaching the horizontal axis. But for all practical purposes, when
we are talking about populations of people, a normal distribution is about six standard
deviations wide. The numbers below the axis in the figure above designate the number
of standard deviations above and below the mean. As you can see, the line has virtually
touched the surface at ±3 standard deviations.
A person who is one standard deviation above the mean in IQ is at the 84th
percentile. Two standard deviations above the mean puts him at the 98th percentile.
Three standard deviations above the mean puts him at the 99.9th percentile. A person
who is one standard deviation below the mean is at the 16th percentile. Two standard
deviations below the mean puts him at the 2nd percentile. Three standard deviations
below the mean puts him at the 0.1th percentile.
Why Not Just Use Percentiles to Begin With?
Why go to all the trouble of computing standard scores? Most people understand
percentiles already. Tell them that someone is at the 84th percentile, and they know
right away what you mean. Tell them that he’s at the 99th percentile, and they know
what that means. Aren’t we just introducing an unnecessary complication by talking
about “standard scores”?
Thinking in terms of percentiles is convenient and has its legitimate uses. I often
speak in terms of percentiles in the text. But they can also be highly misleading,
because they are artificially compressed at the tails of the distributions. It is a longer
way from, say, the 98th percentile to the 99th than from the 50th to the 51st. In a true
normal distribution, the distance from the 99th percentile to the 100th (or, similarly,
from zero to the 1st) is infinite.
Consider two people who are at the 50th and 55th percentiles in height. Using a
large representative sample from the National Longitudinal Study of Youth (NLSY) as
our estimate of the national American distribution of height, their actual height
difference is only half an inch. Consider another two people who are at the 94th and
99th percentiles on height—the identical gap in terms of percentiles. Their height
difference is 3.1 inches, six times the height difference of those at the 50th and 55th
percentiles. The farther out on the tail of the distribution you move, the more
misleading percentiles become.
Standard scores reflect these real differences much more accurately than do
percentiles. The people at the 50th and 55th percentiles, only half an inch apart in real
height, have standard scores of 0.0 and 0.13. Compare that difference of 0.13 standard
deviation units to the standard scores of those at the 94th and 99th percentiles: 1.55
and 2.33 respectively. In standard scores, their difference—which is 0.78 standard
deviation units, equivalent to an effect size of 0.78—is six times as large, reflecting the
sixfold difference in inches.
Correlation and Regression
Some sort of relationship between height and weight is immediately obvious. The
heaviest boys tend to be the tallest, the lightest ones the shortest, and most of them are
intermediate in both height and weight. Equally obvious are the deviations from the
trend that link height and weight. The stocky boys appear as points above the mass,
the skinny ones as points below it. What we need now is some way to quantify both
the trend and the exceptions.
Correlations and regressions accomplish this in different ways. But before we go
on to discuss these terms, be assured that they are simple. Look at the scatter plot. You
can see just by looking at the dots that as height increases, so does weight, in an
irregular way. Take a pencil (literally or imaginarily) and draw a straight, sloping line
through the dots in a way that seems to you to best reflect this upward-sloping trend.
Now continue to read and see how well you have intuitively produced the basis for a
correlation coefficient and a regression coefficient.
The Correlation Coefficient
Modern statistics provide more than one method for measuring correlation, but we
confine ourselves to the one that is most important in both use and generality: the
Pearson product-moment correlation coefficient (named after Karl Pearson, the English
mathematician and biometrician). To get at this coefficient, let us first replot the graph
of the class, replacing inches and pounds with standard scores. The variables are now
expressed in general terms. Remember: Any set of measurements can be transformed
similarly.
The next step on our way to the correlation coefficient is to apply a formula that
finds the best possible straight line passing through the cloud of points—the
mathematically “best” version of the line you just drew by intuition.
What makes it the “best”? Any line is going to be wrong for most of the points.
Take, for example, the boys who are 64 inches tall and look at their weights. Any
sloping straight line is going to cross somewhere in the middle of those weights and will
probably not cross any of the dots exactly. For boys 64 inches tall, you want the line to
cross at the point where the total amount of the error is as small as possible. Taken
over all the boys at all the heights, you want a straight line that makes the sum of all
the errors for all the heights as small as possible. This “best fit” is shown in the new
version of the scatter plot shown below, where both height and weight are expressed in
standard scores and the mathematical best-fitting line has been superimposed.
This scatter plot has (partly by serendipity) many lessons to teach about how
statistics relate to the real world. Here are a few of the main ones:
1. Notice the many exceptions. There is a statistically substantial relationship
between height and weight, but, visually, the exceptions seem to dominate. So
too with virtually all statistical relationships in the social sciences, most of
which are much weaker than this one.
2. Linear relationships don’t always seem to fit very well. The best-fit line looks
as if it is too shallow—notice the tall boys and see how consistently the line
underpredicts how much they weigh. Given the information in the diagram,
this might be an optical illusion—many of the dots in the dense part of the
range are on top of each other, as it were, and thus it is impossible to grasp
visually how the errors are adding up—but it could also be that the relationship
between height and weight is not linear.
3. Small samples have individual anomalies. Before we jump to the conclusion
that the straight line is not a good representation of the relationship, we must
remember that the sample consists of only 250 boys. An anomaly of this
particular small sample is that one of the boys in the sample of 250 weighed
250 pounds. Eighteen-year-old boys are rarely that heavy, judging from the
entire NLSY sample, only one or two per 10,000. And yet one of those
rarities happened to be picked up in a sample of 250. That’s the way samples
work.
4. But small samples are also surprisingly accurate, despite their individual
anomalies. The relationship between height and weight shown by the sample
of 250 18-year-old males is identical to the third decimal place with the
relationship among all 6,068 males in the NLSY sample (the correlation
coefficient is .501 in both cases). This is closer than we have any right to
expect, but other random samples of only 250 generally produce correlations
that are within a few points of the one produced by the larger sample. (There
are mathematics for figuring out what “generally” and “within a few points”
mean, but we needn’t worry about them here.)
Bearing these basics in mind, let us go back to the sloping line in the figure above. Out
of mathematical necessity, we know several things about it. First of all, it must pass
through the intersection of the zeros (which, in standard scores, correspond to the
averages) for both height and weight. Secondly, the line would have had exactly the
same slope had height been the vertical axis and weight the horizontal one.
Finally, and most significant, the slope of the best-fitting line cannot be steeper than
1.0. The steepest possible best-fitting line, in other words, is one along which one unit
of change in height is exactly matched by one unit of change in weight, clearly not the
case in these data. Real data in the social sciences never yield a slope that steep. Note
that while the line in the graph above goes uphill to the right, it would go downhill for
pairs of variables that are negatively correlated.
We focus on the slope of the best-fitting line because it is the correlation coefficient
—in this case, equal to .50, which is quite large by the standards of variables used by
social scientists. The closer it gets to ±1.0, the stronger is the linear relationship
between the standardized variables (the variables expressed as standard scores). When
the two variables are mutually independent, the best-fitting line is horizontal; hence its
slope is 0. Anything other than 0 signifies a relationship, albeit possibly a very weak
one.
Whatever the correlation coefficient of a pair of variables is, squaring it yields
another notable number. Squaring .50, for example, gives .25. The significance of the
squared correlation is that it tells us how much the variation in weight would decrease if
we could make everyone the same height, or vice versa. If all the boys in the class
were the same height, the variation in their weights would decline by 25 percent.
Perhaps you have heard the phrase “explains the variance,” as in, for example,
“Education explains 20 percent of the variance in income.” That figure comes from the
squared correlation.
In general, the squared correlation is a measure of the mutual redundancy in a pair
of variables. If they are highly correlated, they are highly redundant in the sense that
knowing the value of one of them places a narrow range of possibilities for the value of
the other. If they are uncorrelated or only slightly correlated, knowing the value of one
tells us nothing or little about the value of the other.
Regression Coefficients
Correlation assesses the strength of a relationship between variables. But we may want
to know more about a relationship than merely its strength. We may want to know
what it is. We may want to know how much of an increase in weight, for example, we
should anticipate if we compare 66-inch boys with 73-inch boys. Such questions arise
naturally if we are trying to explain a particular variable (e.g., annual income) in terms
of the effects of another variable (e.g., educational level). “How much income is
another year of schooling worth?” is just the sort of question that social scientists are
always trying to answer.
The standard method for answering it is regression analysis, which has an intimate
mathematical association with correlational analysis. If we had left the scatter plot with
its original axes—inches and pounds—instead of standardizing them, the slope of the
best-fitting line would have been a regression coefficient, rather than a correlation
coefficient. For example, the regression coefficient for weight regressed on height tells
us that for each additional inch in height, we can expect an increase of 3.9 pounds. Or
we could regress height on weight and discover that each additional pound of weight is
associated with an increase of .065 inches in height.
Multivariate Statistics
Multiple regression analysis is the main way that social science deals with the multiple
relationships that are the rule in social science. To get a fix on multiple regression, let us
return to the high school gym for the last time. Your classmates are still scattered about
the floor. Now imagine a pole, erected at the intersection of 60 inches and 80 pounds,
marked in inches from 18 inches to 50 inches. For some inscrutable reason, you would
like to know the impact of both height and weight on a boy’s waist size. Since
imagination can defy gravity, you ask each boy to levitate until the soles of his shoes
are at the elevation that reads on the pole at the waist size of his trousers. In general,
the taller and heavier boys must rise the most, the shorter and slighter ones the least,
and most boys, middling in height and weight, will have middling waist sizes as well.
Multiple regression is a mathematical procedure for finding that plane, slicing through
the space in the gym, that minimizes the aggregated distances (in this instance, along
the waist size axis) between the bottoms of the boys’ shoes and the plane.
The best-fitting plane will tilt upward toward heavy weights and tall heights. But it
may tilt more along the pounds axis than along the inches axis or vice versa. It may tilt
equally for each. The slope of the tilt along each of these axes is again a regression
coefficient. With two variables predicting a third, as in this example, there are two
coefficients. One of them tells us how much of an increase in trouser waist size is
associated with a given increase in weight, holding height constant; the other, how
much of an increase in trouser waist size is associated with a given increase in height,
holding weight constant.
With two variables predicting a third, we reach the limit of visual imagination. But
the principle of multiple regression can be extended to any number of variables.
Income, for example, may be related not just to education, but also to age, family
background, IQ, personality, business conditions, region of the country, and so on. The
mathematical procedures will yield coefficients for each of them, indicating again how
much of a change in income can be anticipated for a given change in any particular
variable, with all the others held constant.
Adapted from The Bell Curve: Intelligence and Class Structure in American Life by Richard J. Herrnstein and
Charles Murray. Copyright © 1994 by Richard J. Herrnstein and Charles Murray. Reprinted with permission of
The Free Press, a Division of Simon & Schuster Trade Publishing Group. I have made a few minor changes to
the original text, eliminating some material specific to issues in The Bell Curve and rewording a few sentences
to fit the context of Human Diversity.
Appendix 2
Before genetics got into the picture, the definition of biological sex was based on
physiological differences in the genitalia, leaving one option for identifying intersex
persons: people whose genitalia had some of the characteristics of both males and
females, known as hermaphrodites. Once the sex distinction in chromosomes was
discovered early in the twentieth century—females have the XX pair and males have
the XY pair—cleaner definitions of three types of intersexuals were possible: true
hermaphrodites (persons born with both testicular and ovarian tissue), people with the
XX chromosome pair but significant components of male sexual anatomy, and people
with the XY chromosome pair but with significant components of female sexual
anatomy.4
The three conditions that are consensually accepted as evidence that a person is
intersex are as follows:
True hermaphrodites. Individuals born with both testicular and ovarian tissue.5
Some of the people with the other two conditions appear to have the characteristics of
both male and female genitalia, but they don’t meet the technical definition.
Classic congenital adrenal hyperplasia (CAH) among females, discussed in
chapter 5. Classic CAH is the result of prenatal exposure to abnormally high levels of
male hormones (androgens). In female infants, CAH usually presents as ambiguous
genitalia. In children and adults, it is associated with masculinization of features, facial
hair, menstrual problems, and male-typical personality characteristics. In males, sexual
ambiguity is rarely involved nor are there usually any symptoms at birth.6 Classic CAH
in males is accompanied by abnormally rapid growth in childhood, early signs of
puberty, and shorter than expected height as an adult.
Androgen insensitivity syndrome (AIS), also discussed in chapter 5. AIS affects
only genetically male (XY) fetuses. The condition impairs masculinization of male
genitalia. In its mild form, the external genitalia at birth are those of a normal male; in
its extreme form, “complete” AIS (CAIS), the external genitalia are those of a normal
female.
The table below summarizes incidence of the three conditions. The note gives the
source and additional information about the numbers.[7]
True hermaphrodites
Percent: 0.0012
Total
Percent: 0.0173
Limited to the three conditions that are consensually accepted as evidence of an
intersex individual (including all levels of AIS), the proportion of intersex persons is
0.0173 percent—less than two-hundredths of a percentage point, or about one in 5,800
persons. That number is slightly inflated because the estimate for CAH includes males
as well as females.
In 2000, this core definition was broadened by a team of scholars (first author was
Melanie Blackless).8 Their criteria for a “typical” male or female were, in the authors’
own words, “exacting”:
Turner syndrome
Percent: 0.0369
Klinefelter syndrome
Percent: 0.0922
Vaginal agenesis
Percent: 0.0169
Total
Percent: 1.7108
Perhaps the most important point about all the above departures from a “Platonic
ideal of sexual dimorphism” is that none of the sources I have listed discuss sexual
ambiguity as among the presenting symptoms. Is it appropriate to define these people
as “intersexuals”?
I leave it as a question. The answer doesn’t matter in any practical sense for
establishing that humans consist of two sexes with a small number of exceptions.
Depending on what you think of the additional departures from the Platonic ideal—and
especially what you think of late-onset CAH—either 98.3 percent or 99.8 percent of
the population are unambiguously male or female in the biological sense. Either figure
makes my point.
I should add, however, that the answer does matter from the clinician’s point of
view. The total proportion of people considered intersexual in the Blackless study is
1.728 percent, which is almost exactly 100 times the total proportion of people—
0.0173 percent—considered intersexual based on the three core categories of
intersexuality. One clinician (also a psychologist and physician), Leonard Sax, observed
that the total for the three core categories “suggests that there are currently [2002]
about 50,000 true intersexuals living in the United States. These individuals are of
course entitled to the same expert care and consideration that all patients deserve.
Nothing is gained, however, by pretending that there are 5,000,000 such individuals.”20
Self-Identified Sexual Orientation
I begin with the ways in which people describe their sexual orientation independently of
measures of sexual behavior or attraction.
In 2011, Gary Gates of the Williams Institute published a synthesis of the major
studies up to that time that had asked adults to identify their orientation as
heterosexual, gay, lesbian, or bisexual. The Gates study combined the results from five
American surveys conducted from 2004 through 2009 to reach overall estimates. For
males, the results were estimates of 2.2 percent gay and 1.4 percent bisexual. For
females, the numbers were 1.1 percent lesbian and 2.2 percent bisexual. Overall, Gates
put self-identified lesbian, gay, and bisexual (LGB) individuals at 3.5 percent of the
population.21
READING INTO THE STATE OF KNOWLEDGE ABOUT SEXUAL IDENTITY
Standing apart from the rhetoric about gender fluidity and the existence of multiple genders is a body
of empirical work that still includes many controversies, but ones that are being argued out in the
technical literature the old-fashioned way, with actual data. For an overview of where things stand on
the major issues, including reviews of the literature on definitions, measurement issues, prevalence,
sex differences in expression of sexual orientation, sex differences in category-specific sexual
arousal, sexual fluidity, developmental and psychological correlates of sexual orientation, bisexuality,
and the environmental and genetic causes of sexual orientation, I recommend a 56-page article,
“Sexual Orientation, Controversy, and Science,” published in 2016 by a team of the field’s leading
scholars of varying perspectives (Michael Bailey, Paul Vasey, Lisa Diamond, Marc Breedlove, Eric
Vilain, and Marc Epprecht). 22
One of those sources was the General Social Survey, which had asked the question
for the first time in 2008 and has continued to ask it through 2016. We also have
subsequent data from an annual poll question about sexual identity that Gallup
introduced in 2012 and estimates from the National Health Interview Survey (NHIS).
The latest published percentages as I write are as follows:23
Both the Gallup data and the General Social Survey show steady though small
increases over time. An unweighted average of the three is 4.3 percent; an average
weighted by sample size is 4.0 percent.
These estimates of the LGB population may strike you as absurdly low (recall that
in polls, Americans estimate that about 23 percent of the population is gay or lesbian).
But they are actually higher than the estimates that have been found in the other
Western countries that have reported on self-identified sexual orientation for nationally
representative samples.[24] Here are the results of the most recent major studies
conducted outside America that I have been able to find:
There may well be some degree of undercount. But there has been a revolution in
openness about homosexuality in all of these countries that is now several decades old.
Homosexuality has even acquired cachet among some circles in all of these countries.
The answers to all of these surveys were anonymous. It is hard to come up with a
scenario whereby all of the reported results are radical undercounts of authentic
proportions of self-identified gays, lesbians, and bisexuals.
Prevalence of Same-Sex Attraction or Behavior
For example, an 18-year old New England girl identified as mostly heterosexual
because “I sort of like that it doesn’t just have a completely or just a bisexual,
but it has in between… there isn’t always that black and white picture.” A boy
in the same study explained, “I’m basically attracted to girls, but I’ve felt like
kind of attracted to guys before, but not to like some great extent.… I’ve never
felt I was attracted enough to a guy to like go out with them or something like
that or like having a relationship with a guy.”29
The authors presented data on 60 studies published from 1994 to 2012 with
samples from the United States, Canada, the United Kingdom, Norway, Australia, and
New Zealand and including a wide range of age groups. The authors of the Bailey
survey article used a subset of these studies that comprised 71,190 adult males and
117,717 adult females. Here are the results by sex:30
Completely heterosexual
Women: 86.8%
Men: 93.2%
Mostly heterosexual
Women: 10.1%
Men: 3.9%
Bisexual
Women: 1.4%
Men: 0.6%
Mostly homosexual
Women: 0.5%
Men: 0.7%
Completely homosexual
Women: 0.6%
Men: 1.4%
The results reinforce the point made earlier: The estimates of homosexuality for the
United States from the Gallup polls and the General Social Survey are much higher
than those from other studies. For current purposes, the main point of the results is the
small proportion of people who self-identify as “mostly heterosexual” and the
extremely small proportion who self-identify as bisexual.31 Are bisexuals undercounted
by these studies? Ritch Savin-Williams and Kenneth Cohen argue that the answer is
yes, giving a “best estimate” (the authors’ phrase) of male bisexual prevalence of about
10–20 percent.32
It’s partly a technical issue: The two “mostly” categories actually identify bisexuals.
If the table above had done that, the male bisexual figure would have been 5.2 percent
instead of 0.6 percent. The figure would be augmented by the small percentages of
men who do not answer “bisexual” but identify as pansexual, transgender, fluid,
questioning, or kink-oriented. In most cases these individuals are deleted from the
calculations of prevalence rates. Savin-Williams also argues that some men who don’t
answer the question are actually bisexual, and points to nonresponse rates in national
studies that sometimes reach 10 percent.
The problem ranked first on Savin-Williams’s list is definitional. He argues that a
major contributor to the undercount is the failure of many assessments to include
“nonsexual domains such as romantic attractions, infatuations, and relationships.”33
But should romantic but nonsexual attraction be classified as evidence of bisexuality?
For example, consider a man who had a one-time crush on another man as a teenager
but never was sexually aroused by him and has had enthusiastic sex exclusively with
women all his subsequent life. In trying to characterize the sexual orientation of the
population, it doesn’t seem realistic to categorize him as bisexual. On the other hand,
one may argue that a man who has had many such crushes on men throughout his life
but never acted upon them is psychologically bisexual.
No matter how detailed the data collection becomes, people with different
perspectives will make different judgments about such cases. A common assumption in
the technical literature is that to move someone off the “completely heterosexual” end
of the continuum, “attraction” needs to include actual sexual arousal by someone of the
same sex. If there’s no arousal, it doesn’t count. I share that position. A same-sex
attraction without any desire for sex is too easily confused with the genuine but
nonerotic love that heterosexual women can have for other women and heterosexual
men can have for other men.
The Transgender Phenomenon
Transgendered identity has become a major issue in academia and the media. In the
popular understanding, transgender people see themselves as trapped in the body of the
other sex. It’s more complicated than that.34
Childhood-onset gender dysphoria. This comes closest to the popular
understanding, and it occurs in both girls and boys. It is characterized by behavior
typical of the opposite sex from an early age. In the published literature, findings are
that the majority (60–90 percent) of children with this kind of gender dysphoria have
become comfortable with their sex of birth by adulthood, and thus have avoided the
need for a sex change.35 Adults whose childhood-onset gender dysphoria persists
typically do report that they have felt more like the other sex from their earliest
memories. Childhood-onset gender dysphoria is highly correlated with adult sexual
attraction to one’s birth sex, especially in males.
Autogynephilic gender dysphoria. This form occurs only in males. Autogynephilia
taken alone refers to sexual arousal at the idea of having a female body or behaving like
a female. It is usually a gradual process that begins in adolescence or later. Many men
with autogynephilia live their lives as heterosexual men with wives and children while
often engaging in practices such as cross-dressing in private. Males with autogynephilic
gender dysphoria (as distinct from autogynephilia alone) are more likely to live as
homosexuals and often possess a strong desire to obtain sex reassignment surgery, after
which they often identify as lesbian.36
Rapid-onset gender dysphoria (ROGD). This is a newly documented phenomenon
that might not even have existed a decade ago. It is characterized by adolescents,
mostly female, who showed no signs of gender dysphoria as children and apparently
abruptly decide they are transgender as teenagers.
As I write, only one systematic study of the ROGD phenomenon is available, based
on 256 surveys from parents who had reported that their teenage and young adult
children had exhibited rapid onsets of gender dysphoria.[37] The author, Lisa Littman,
a gynecologist specializing in gender dysphoria, reported that none of the parents’
children in the study (83 percent were girls) would have been likely to have met
diagnostic criteria for gender dysphoria in childhood. They did have a variety of
psychiatric problems, however. Many (48 percent) had experienced a traumatic event
prior to their declaration of gender dysphoria, and 63 percent had one or more
diagnoses of a psychiatric or neurodevelopmental disability.
The results implicated an important role for social influences. Sixty-seven percent
of the adolescents had one or more friends who declared they were transgender at
about the same time. Increased time on social media was common, and 69 percent of
the parents believed (for reasons they explained) that their children were using language
that they had found online. “Within friendship groups,” Littman writes, “the average
number of individuals who became transgender-identified was 3.5 per group. In 36.8%
of the friend groups described, the majority of individuals in the group became
transgender-identified.… Parents described intense group dynamics where friend
groups praised and supported people who were transgender-identified and ridiculed and
maligned non-transgender people. Where popularity status and activities were known,
60.7% of the [children] experienced an increased popularity within their friend group
when they announced a transgender-identification and 60.0% of the friend groups were
known to mock people who were not transgender or LGBTIA (lesbian, gay, bisexual,
transgender, intersex, or asexual).”38
Littman’s is the only systematic study, but two leading scholars of LGBTIA issues,
Michael Bailey and Ray Blanchard, have expressed some preliminary thoughts based
on interviews with mothers of ROGD children and clinicians who work with ROGD
children and parents, case studies, and the limited quantitative data. They surmise that
“ROGD is a socially contagious phenomenon in which a young person—typically a
natal female—comes to believe that she has a condition that she does not have. ROGD
is not about discovering gender dysphoria that was there all along; rather, it is about
falsely coming to believe that one’s problems have been due to gender dysphoria
previously hidden (from the self and others).”39
One thing seems clear: The rise in ROGD is concentrated among adolescent
females. Historically and internationally, males have had higher rates of gender
dysphoria than females. For childhood-onset gender dysphoria, this continues to be
true in data from Canada, the Netherlands, and the UK.40 But these same sources also
found that the ratio reversed itself among adolescents during the period 2006–10.41 In
the UK, which operates the largest child and adolescent gender services in the world,
the Gender Identity Development Service (GIDS), the sex ratio has become rapidly
more disproportionate. In 2010, 52 percent of adolescent referrals were female; by
2016, that figure had risen to 72 percent.42 The UK data also show a steep rise in
referrals of adolescents, from 92 in 2010 to 1,497 in 2016, but it is difficult to
disentangle how this growth is divided among increases in incidence, awareness of the
existence of the service, and GIDS’s area of coverage.
Taken together, how many people qualify as transgender? The fifth (2013) edition
of the Diagnostic and Statistical Manual of Mental Disorders of the American
Psychiatric Association put the incidence rate at 0.5–1.4 percent for males and 0.2–0.3
percent for women. A 2015 meta-analysis of prevalence studies reached much smaller
estimates of 0.0068 percent for women and 0.0026 percent for men.43 Kenneth
Zucker pulled together the available epidemiological data in a 2017 article and reached
an overall estimate of 0.5–1.3 percent.44 Whichever of these numbers is closest to the
truth, only a small proportion of such people have undergone the major sex
reassignment surgery that is popularly associated with transgender identity.45
I have left many aspects of sexual identity unaddressed not because they are
intrinsically unimportant but because of my limited objective: The first five chapters of
Human Diversity discuss sex differences, making it important to establish that those
chapters are not ignoring large proportions of people who do not fit the ordinary
definition of male or female. The evidence is incomplete in many respects, but not the
basics. Homo sapiens is a typically dimorphic species with regard to sexuality. It
consists of two sexes with an extremely small proportion of biological anomalies. Self-
identified homosexuality or bisexualism in the United States is somewhere around 5
percent and usually less than that elsewhere. There is room for disagreement about the
precise percentages, but not about the truth that humans are a normally dimorphic
species.
Appendix 3
This appendix deals with two important ways in which males and females differ
biologically: larger male brain volumes and generally greater male variance in a wide
variety of physiological and cognitive traits.
Brain Volumes
The biological reality of larger male brain volumes has been established, but no
consensus has been reached on what they mean.
Human Males Have Much Larger Mean Brain Volume Than Human Females
In the 1990s, the first studies of sex differences in brain volume using MRI scans
began to be published.1 By 2014, the literature had grown so large that an international
team of neuroscientists drawn primarily from Cambridge University (first author was
Amber Ruigrok) could publish “A Meta-analysis of Sex Differences in Human Brain
Structure” that combined 77 different studies involving 14,597 individuals.
The table below shows the results for the basic volume measures.
Volume: Cerebrum
Studies: 22
Sample size: 1,851
Mean difference (ml): 51.1
Percentage difference: 9.8
Effect size (d): –3.35
Volume: Cerebellum
Studies: 19
Sample size: 1,842
Mean difference (ml): 7.8
Percentage difference: 8.6
Effect size (d): –1.68
Source: Ruigrok, Salimi-Khorshidi, Lai et al. (2014): Table 3.
The effect sizes for two of the measured volumes qualify as “very large” by
Cohen’s guidelines, while the other five of them are “huge.”
Sex Differences in Brain Volume Extend to the Subcortical Regions
Good information on volumes of the regions of the brain in vivo had to wait for MRI
technology. The last half of the 1990s saw more than a dozen early studies showing
that a variety of subcortical volumes were larger in males, but small sample sizes left
uncertainty about the consistency and magnitude of the differences.2 That problem
continued into the 2000s. In the Ruigrok meta-analysis of 2014, the median sample
size of the 25 studies that examined sex differences in specific regions was just 86 and
only 10 of them had samples of more than 100.3
In 2018, many of the uncertainties of earlier work were put to rest by a team of
British scholars (first author was Stuart Ritchie) who analyzed subcortical regional
means and variances based on a sample of 5,216 persons from the UK Biobank data.4
The average male total brain volume was 1,234 cm3 compared to 1,116 cm3 for
females, which amounts to a difference of 118 cm3, representing an effect size of –
1.41, smaller than the –2.10 effect size in the Ruigrok meta-analysis.
The Ritchie study reported volume estimates for the 68 subcortical regions in the
Desikan-Killiany neuroanatomical atlas.5 Males had larger volumes in all 68. The
smallest effect size was –0.24 and the largest was –1.03, with a mean of –0.67. All
were highly statistically significant. The table below shows the Ritchie results for some
of the most important subcortical regions. Highly statistically significant effect sizes are
shown in boldface.
Total brain
Raw: –1.41
Adjusted for…
Height: –0.42
Total volume:
Gray matter
Raw: –1.28
Adjusted for…
Height: –0.31
Total volume: *
White matter
Raw: –1.49
Adjusted for…
Height: –0.47
Total volume: *
Left hippocampus
Raw: –0.55
Adjusted for…
Height: –0.17
Total volume: –0.02
Right hippocampus
Raw: –0.54
Adjusted for…
Height: –0.18
Total volume: –0.01
Left accumbens
Raw: –0.39
Adjusted for…
Height: –0.06
Total volume: +0.08
Right accumbens
Raw: –0.31
Adjusted for…
Height: –0.05
Total volume: +0.10
Left amygdala
Raw: –0.59
Adjusted for…
Height: –0.21
Total volume: –0.18
Right amygdala
Raw: –0.51
Adjusted for…
Height: –0.18
Total volume: –0.18
Left caudate
Raw: –0.66
Adjusted for…
Height: –0.20
Total volume: –0.01
Right caudate
Raw: –0.65
Adjusted for…
Height: –0.19
Total volume: 0.00
Left pallidum
Raw: –0.77
Adjusted for…
Height: –0.24
Total volume: –0.16
Right pallidum
Raw: –0.78
Adjusted for…
Height: –0.24
Total volume: –0.12
Left putamen
Raw: –1.01
Adjusted for…
Height: –0.30
Total volume: –0.22
Right putamen
Raw: –1.08
Adjusted for…
Height: –0.35
Total volume: –0.25
Left thalamus
Raw: –0.98
Adjusted for…
Height: –0.26
Total volume: +0.01
Right thalamus
Raw: –1.03
Adjusted for…
Height: –0.27
Total volume: –0.02
Source: Adapted from Ritchie, Cox, Shen et al. (2018): Tables 1 and S1. Figures in bold indicate that p < 10–4.
*Adjustments for gray and white matter for total brain volume were not performed because of collinearity.
The effect sizes in the “Raw” column represent the expected magnitudes of
difference in brain volumes in a randomly chosen man and a randomly chosen woman.
The effect sizes in the “Height” column represent the expected differences in brain
volumes of a man and woman of the same height. The effect sizes in the “Adjusted for
total volume” column represent the expected differences in regional brain volumes for a
man and a woman with the same total brain volume.
The raw effect sizes for the subcortical volumes ranged from –0.31 to –1.08, with
a median of –0.660. Adjusted for height, the effect sizes ranged from –0.05 to –0.35,
with a median of –0.24. The “Adjusted for total volume” column shows men retaining
larger volumes in all but two regions, but with effect sizes that are no larger than –0.25
and a median of –0.12.
Which of these three ways of looking at differences in brain volume should we
use? This question only raises more questions. It makes sense that we should adjust for
body size for some traits. A plausible reason that elephants have brains twice the
weight of human brains is that it takes a lot more neurons to control large muscular
structures and nervous systems than to control small ones. But the logic of adjusting
for body size is not obvious when it comes to the intellect and emotions. It’s all
happening in the brain. Why should it take more neurons to solve a quadratic equation
in a person who is 5 foot 8 than in a person who is 5 foot 4?
According to neuroscientists whom I have asked, there is oddly little in the
technical literature that systematically explores when it is appropriate to adjust for
differences in body size. But there is a clear reason to adjust for total brain size for
certain purposes: It is the appropriate method for finding interesting sex differences in
the relative sizes of different regions. The question that must still be at the back of the
investigator’s mind is the extent to which adjusting for total brain size produces another
kind of artifact, removing variance that does in fact contribute to sex differences in
overt traits. That brings us to the fraught question of brain size and how smart people
are.
Brain Size and g
The progress of hominids from chimpanzees to anatomically modern humans has been
marked by increases in skull volume.6 Paleontologists, physical anthropologists,
evolutionary biologists, and neuroscientists have broadly agreed that greater skull
volume means greater brain volume, and greater brain volume across species is
associated with greater cognitive capacity.7
It is also established that brain volume in humans is correlated with IQ scores, and
hence with g. That knowledge has been hard-won in the face of controversy. The early
correlations were based on indirect measures of brain size—for example, measuring
head circumference—that left much room for doubt.8 Then MRI technology made it
possible to determine in vivo volume of the brain with precision—and not just total
brain volume, but the volumes of the dozens of subcortical regions.
The size of the correlation of overall brain volume with IQ has varied from sample
to sample. Two meta-analyses of all such studies concluded respectively that the
correlation is +.33 and +.24.9 Subsequently, a reanalysis of the literature argued that
the scientifically most rigorous studies show an average correlation of +.39.10
Furthermore, this relationship holds within sexes. On average, men with larger brains
have higher IQ than men with smaller brains, and women with larger brains have
higher IQ than women with smaller brains.11
Is the relationship causal? After all, bigger brains mean more neurons. But what
counts for cognitive functioning in mammals is the number of neurons in the cerebral
cortex and the subcortical regions.12 On this score, humans stand apart from all other
mammals. The human cerebral cortex contains about 16 billion neurons. The next
largest, found in gorillas and orangutans, is just 9 billion.13
Several studies have found evidence for this causal link in humans. Cerebellar brain
volume has been found to explain variance in g in older adults, even after controlling
for frontal lobe volume (which tends to atrophy with age).14 In 2018, neuroscientists
reinforced the evidence for a causal link through a study with a large sample (n =
2,904) of brain development in youths and young adults (first author was Kirk
Reardon).15 The cortical surface area expands threefold between infancy and
adulthood. A priori, one might expect that human brains of different sizes scale
uniformly—a brain with larger total volume also has a linearly larger hippocampus,
amygdala, and so forth. But that’s not what the Reardon study found. “Rather,” as
David Van Essen summarized it, “larger brains show greater expansion in regions
associated with higher cognition and less expansion in regions associated with sensory,
motor, and limbic (emotion-and affect-related) functions.”16 The Reardon study also
found that overall cortical surface area correlated significantly with IQ after factoring
out age and sex.17 Thus there is good reason to expect a causal relationship not only
between brain volume and IQ, but between brain volume in specific regions and IQ.
Other things being equal, more neurons are a good thing for cognitive functioning.[18]
But other things are not equal.
Sexual Dimorphism in Brain Volumes Does Not Necessarily Mean Dimorphism in
Cognitive Function
Chapter 5 describes sex differences in connectivity that make female brains more
efficient. There’s much more work being done in this area. Sex differences in receptor
density could be at work independently of regional brain size or overall brain size.
Furthermore, volume isn’t the only relevant measure of size. Two other measures that
were considered in the Ritchie study were the convoluted cortical surface areas and
cortical thickness. Those two features have been found to be independent of each
other, both globally and regionally.19 The male-female differences in surface area for all
68 subcortical regions were even larger than those found for overall volume, with
effect sizes ranging from –0.43 to –1.20 and a mean of –0.83.20 This was not true of
cortical thickness, however. Consistent with an earlier study of sex differences in
cortical thickness,21 females had significantly thicker cortex across most of the brain
(47 of the 68 areas). Males had significantly thicker cortex in just 1 of the 68. The
differences in the remaining 20 areas did not reach statistical significance. The effect
sizes in the 47 ranged from +0.07 to +0.45, with a mean of +0.22 (a positive d
indicates greater cortical thickness among females). These differences remained
significant after adjusting for total brain size.
Other brain parameters can and do vary by sex; among them, cerebral blood flow,
glucose metabolism in the limbic system, dopamine transporter availability, the
percentage of gray matter tissue in some parts of the brain, and the percentage of white
matter tissue in other parts. The links between these parameters and behavior were
summarized by Ruben and Raquel Gur in a review article. “For example,” the Gurs
write, “differences in gray and white matter volumes have been related to performance
on verbal and spatial tasks, sex differences in hippocampal volume and in dopamine
availability have been linked to memory performance, and sex differences in limbic
activity and orbitofrontal volume have been associated with differences in emotion
regulation.”22 What all this shows, the Gurs conclude, is a set of differences that
cannot be ranked from good to bad, but that tend to be complementary.
Neuroendocrinologist Geert de Vries has argued that sex differences in brain
structure may work to prevent phenotypic differences. “Intuition tells us that sex
differences in brain structure beget sex differences in brain function,” he wrote in 2005.
“There is nothing wrong with that. If, for example, a brain area has three times more
cells that produce a specific neurotransmitter in one sex vs. the other, and if these cells
send, accordingly, three times denser projections to target neurons in another area,
stimulation of these cells will probably cause sex-specific responses in the target
neurons.”23 But researchers have drawn their hypothesis too narrowly, de Vries argues.
Sex differences in brain structure “may indeed generate differences in overt functions
and behavior, but they may just as well do the exact opposite, that is, they may prevent
sex differences in overt functions and behavior by compensating for sex differences in
physiology”—hence the subtitle to his article, “Compensation, Compensation,
Compensation.”24 In 2015, de Vries and Nancy Forger elaborated on such
compensatory mechanisms. Every organ in the body is sexually differentiated to some
degree, the authors argue, and they present a variety of examples whereby sexual
differentiation in organs and tissues throughout the body eventually affect neural
function or morphology.25
These are just some of the many reasons for caution. The reality of sex differences
in brain volumes is firmly established. Collateral evidence indicates that these myriad
differences must have implications at many levels of brain function. But our
understanding of the specifics, and what those differences mean for phenotypic traits,
is still rudimentary.
Generally Greater Male Variance
If you followed the furor about James Damore’s internal memo at Google that got him
fired in 2017, or if you’re old enough to have followed the furor over Larry Summers’s
comments about male-female differences in attraction to STEM back in 2005, you’ve
encountered the phrase “greater male variance hypothesis.” The reason the hypothesis
has gotten so much attention is its implication for explaining male dominance at the
highest levels of achievement in the arts and sciences throughout recorded history.26 If
general cognitive ability g is normally distributed, then even if males and females have
the same mean g, greater variation in males will mean that men are overrepresented at
the tails of the normal distribution.
A lot of “ifs” lie between the existence of greater male variance and the explanation
for male dominance at the highest levels of achievement. That’s why I am not prepared
to defend a statement that begins, “Greater male variance in measures of abilities
explains…” That’s a leap too far. But this less ambitious statement is no longer
controversial: Greater male variance in a wide variety of traits is a fundamental
biological characteristic of humans and of dimorphic species more generally. It doesn’t
happen with every trait for which data are available, but with a substantial majority of
them. The greater male variance hypothesis isn’t a hypothesis anymore.27 It is now
known to be generally true.
The Evolutionary Context for Greater Male Variance
I will break my own rule for this book and introduce a little evolutionary biology into
the conversation, because the reasons for greater male variance go so extremely deep
into the evolutionary dynamics that have been operating for hundreds of millions of
years among all species that reproduce sexually.
The simple observation that the males of many species show more visible variation
goes back to the 1700s and was remarked upon by Darwin in The Descent of Man.28 It
has an elemental evolutionary driver: the necessity of having progeny if one’s genes are
to be passed on. In 1948, A. J. Bateman, a botanist, presented the first hard evidence
for what became known as Bateman’s principle: In most species, variability in
reproductive success is greater in males than in females. He used that staple of genetic
research, the fruit fly, for his evidence.29 Through a series of experiments, Bateman
established three important sex differences in reproductive success:
The sex that provides more than his or her share of parental investment is an
important reproductive resource for members of the opposite sex. The result is
competition among members of the lower-investing sex (typically males) over
the parental investment of members of the higher-investing sex (typically
females). Competition for parental investment creates demand for the higher-
investing sex that in turn allows them to be choosey when it comes to mates.32
In more than 95 percent of mammalian species, males make extremely small
parental investments and females make huge ones.33 This imbalance can produce
greater male variability via different routes that have been the subject of an extensive
literature.34
Reviewing that literature here would take us far afield. Think of it this way: To pass
on your genes, you must mate. If you are a male and females are choosy, you need to
have traits that attract females in the first place and other traits that enable you to fight
off, figuratively or literally, other members of your own sex. If you are a female and
the males of your species will copulate with anything that moves, you do not face any
of those sources of evolutionary pressure.35 On the contrary, deviations from the
normal range may exact fitness costs.
If we are talking about modern human males and females, the dynamic I just
described may now be weak. Contemporary human males typically make far higher
parental investment than most mammals. Humans have been an example of what Steve
Stewart-Williams and Andrew Thomas call the “mutual mate choice” model, in
contrast to the “males-compete/females-choose” model.36 But the role that evolution is
argued to have played in generating greater male variability is not something that started
with Homo sapiens. It has been going on since sexual dimorphism began. In all cases
of greater choosiness in one sex, wider variability of traits improves your odds of
passing on your genes if you are a member of the less choosy sex. In the overwhelming
majority of cases, the less choosy sex has been male. When the process involves
unimaginable trillions of reproductive events over millions of years, the fractional
fitness advantages of greater variability add up.
A ROLE FOR THE SEX CHROMOSOMES IN PRODUCING GREATER MALE VARIABILITY
The fact that females have two X chromosomes while the male has only one suggests a
straightforward explanation for traits that are influenced by genes in the X chromosome. The
explanation is based on elementary arithmetic: Women can average, males can’t. Here’s the more
precise statement by evolutionary biologists Klaus Reinhold and Leif Engqvist: “Binomial sampling of
the large X chromosomes leads to the intuitive prediction that males should show larger variation. In
females, the traits that are influenced by X-chromosomal genes will be under the average influence of
the two parental copies, whereas in males, the effect of the single X-chromosome will not be
averaged. As a result, male mammals are expected to show larger variability than females in all traits
that are, at least to some extent, influenced by X-chromosomal alleles,” given certain conditions
described in the note.[37] The overall effect of the sex chromosomes on greater male variability is
limited to traits affected by the X chromosome, which means that greater male variability in most
traits must be driven by other forces.
So much for the evolutionary explanation of greater male variability. You’re free to
ignore it. The topic here is not an explanation of greater male variability, but the
empirical evidence for it. Nowhere is that biological truth more unequivocal than in
greater male variance in the brain.
Males Have Greater Variance Than Females at Both the Whole Brain and the
Regional Levels
The table below shows the variance ratios for the same three versions—raw, adjusted
for height, and adjusted for total brain volume—that I reported for effect sizes in
regional volumes. Variance ratio (VR) is computed as the variance of one population.
In the case of the following table and all other references to VRs in this discussion,
male variance is divided by female variance. Therefore a VR greater than 1.0 signifies
greater male variance.
Total brain
Raw: 1.22
Adjusted for…
Height
Total volume
Gray matter
Raw: 1.23
Adjusted for…
Height: *
Total volume: *
White matter
Raw: 1.22
Adjusted for…
Height: *
Total volume: *
Left hippocampus
Raw: 1.16
Adjusted for…
Height: 1.15
Total volume: 1.16
Right hippocampus
Raw: 1.30
Adjusted for…
Height: 1.28
Total volume: 1.35
Left accumbens
Raw: 1.23
Adjusted for…
Height: 1.23
Total volume: 1.22
Right accumbens
Raw: 1.20
Adjusted for…
Height: 1.20
Total volume: 1.20
Left amygdala
Raw: 1.35
Adjusted for…
Height: 1.35
Total volume: 1.37
Right amygdala
Raw: 1.27
Adjusted for…
Height: 1.28
Total volume: 1.27
Left caudate
Raw: 1.18
Adjusted for…
Height: 1.18
Total volume: 1.16
Right caudate
Raw: 1.19
Adjusted for…
Height: 1.19
Total volume: 1.20
Left pallidum
Raw: 1.14
Adjusted for…
Height: 1.10
Total volume: 1.09
Right pallidum
Raw: 1.19
Adjusted for…
Height: 1.16
Total volume: 1.15
Left putamen
Raw: 1.20
Adjusted for…
Height: 1.22
Total volume: 1.20
Right putamen
Raw: 1.23
Adjusted for…
Height: 1.23
Total volume: 1.23
Left thalamus
Raw: 1.22
Adjusted for…
Height: 1.18
Total volume: 1.33
Right thalamus
Raw: 1.20
Adjusted for…
Height: 1.18
Total volume: 1.30
Source: All ratios are implicitly compared to 1.0. For example, the entry of 1.22 for Total brain volume
represents a male-to-female ratio of 1.22. Adapted from Ritchie, Cox, Shen et al. (2018): Tables 1 and S1. For
all variance ratios, p < .001 (all but the variance ratio for the left hippocampus adjusted for height had p < 10–
4). All variables are adjusted for age and ethnicity. Ratios greater than 1.0 indicate greater male variance.
*Adjustments for gray and white matter for total brain volume were not performed because of collinearity.
The remarkable aspect of the table is how little the VRs are affected by controlling
for height or total brain volume, unlike the story for regional brain volumes presented
earlier. The mean of the 28 differences was a trivial 0.0014. The largest of all 28 of the
differences between the adjusted ratios and the raw ratio was just 0.04.
The table shows the results for only 14 subcortical regions. The full analysis in the
Ritchie study included 68 regions, with measures not just of volume but for surface
area and cortical thickness. Males had greater variance in all 68 regions, and those
differences were significant for 64 out of the 68. The surface area variance ratio was
significant in 66 of the 68 regions. The exception was the measure of cortical thickness,
where women had a thicker cortex than men across almost the entire brain. The
variance ratios for cortical thickness were nonsignificant with a single exception.38
Greater Male Variance in Other Biological Traits
Greater male variance is found in a wide variety of physiological traits. I won’t try to
list them all, but these examples will give you a sense of the prevalence of greater male
variance.
The U.S. National Health and Nutrition Examination Survey (NHANES) for 2015–
16 included 10 basic physiological measures. The variance results for adults ages 20–
39 (936 males, 1,017 females) are shown below: 39
Weight
Effect size (d): –0.62
Variance ratio: 1.15
Height
Effect size (d): –1.91
Variance ratio: 1.25
Waist circumference
Effect size (d): –0.24
Variance ratio: 0.99
Pulse
Effect size (d): +0.35
Variance ratio: 1.08
Of the 10 parameters in the NHANES data, seven show greater male variability,
two show effectively equal male and female variability, and only one, BMI, shows
clearly greater female variability.40 The mean variance ratio was 1.10.[41]
In 1988, the U.S. Army conducted an anthropometric survey of its uniformed
personnel, taking 132 measurements of length, breadth, and circumference of various
portions of the body plus a measure of overall weight using a sample of 1,774 men and
2,208 women balanced to reflect the racial/ethnic and age groups in the active-service
Army.42 The measures ranged from the basic (height, weight) to the arcane (bitragion
coronal arc, bispinous breadth). Of the 132, 3 percent had variance ratios of 1.0, 14
percent had variance ratios less than 1.0 (women had greater variance), and 83 percent
had ratios greater than 1.0 (men had greater variance). The average VR for the 132
anthropometric measures was 1.12.
A team of British scholars analyzed grip strength across the lifespan, combining 12
British studies with 49,964 subjects. From the ages of 5 to 9, girls had slightly higher
grip strength than boys (d = +.10) and slightly greater variability (VR = 0.88).
Thereafter, males had higher grip strength and greater variability. By the age of 20 and
for each 5-year age group through the oldest group (90–94), both the effect sizes and
the VRs were at least 1.8.43
MRI was used by Canadian and U.S. scholars to measure skeletal muscle mass in
200 women and 268 men ages 18–88 and of varied adiposity.44 The results are shown
below.
SM relative to BMI
d: –1.47
VR: 0.86
Lower body SM
d: –2.10
VR: 1.54
Upper body SM
d: –2.55
VR: 2.09
The effect sizes not adjusted for BMI are so large that there was virtually no
overlap between the males and females. The variance ratios were large as well. When
adjusted for BMI, the effect size remained large, but women were more variable than
men.[45]
This is just a sampling. The generalization seems secure: In childhood, the sex
differences in variability are scattered and small. Male variability increases after
puberty. As adults, greater male variability extends from the regions of the brain
throughout the body—not on every parameter, but on a large majority of them.
Greater Male Variance in Sexually Selected Attributes
In 1989, psychologist David Buss conducted a study of sex differences in human mate
preferences across 37 cultures worldwide. Using parental investment and sexual
selection theory, he predicted the results for five target attributes: In choosing mates,
males would value youth, physical attractiveness, and chastity more than females do;
females would value good providers (operationally defined as “good financial
prospects” and ambition/industriousness) more than men do. All of the five predictions
were empirically supported, though to different degrees.46
Fourteen years later, psychologists John Archer and Mani Mehdikhani returned to
Buss’s data with an additional hypothesis, based on Trivers’s theory of parental
investment but also on the prevalence of men who make high parental investment.
Some men behave as if they are pursuing the primordial male reproductive strategy of
impregnating as many females as possible; others behave as if they are pursuing a
strategy of attracting women through the promise of being good fathers. “If there are
alternative reproductive strategies among men but not among women, we would
predict greater variability among males than among females in psychological
characteristics associated with sexual selection,” the authors hypothesized, and used
Buss’s database to test the hypothesis. They also used meta-analyses of sex differences
in physical aggression, another trait predicted to be sexually selected.47
The weighted means for effect size and variance ratio are shown below:48
Physical aggression
Effect size (d): –0.70
VR: 2.04
Good looks
Effect size (d): –0.59
VR: 0.95
Chastity
Effect size (d): –0.30
VR: 1.82
Age difference
Effect size (d): 2.00
VR: 2.09
“Good looks” was the exception, with a VR slightly under 1.0. Males showed
substantially more variability than females on the other five, with ratios ranging from
1.41 to 2.09, consistent with their hypothesis.[49]
Greater Male Variance in Personality
The database used for the McCrae cross-national study in personality described in
chapter 2, based on observations rather than self-reports, has also been analyzed for
variability. In the United States, males had greater variability than females on all five
factors of the Five Factor Model, with VRs 1.05 for neuroticism, 1.21 for extraversion,
1.14 for openness, 1.08 for agreeableness, and 1.20 for conscientiousness. The mean
for all five was 1.13.50
This pattern applied to Anglophone and European countries generally. Excluding
the United States, the mean VR for 24 other Anglophone and European countries was
1.08. Those 24 countries did not show a higher male variance on neuroticism (mean
VR = 0.97). The mean VRs for the other factors were 1.08 for extraversion, 1.13 for
openness, 1.11 for agreeableness, and 1.13 for conscientiousness.51
The results also differed markedly by personality factor. Males had greater
variability in conscientiousness (84 percent of the countries), openness (75 percent),
and agreeableness (69 percent), but a majority of countries had greater female
variability in neuroticism (59 percent) and extraversion (53 percent). Overall, greater
male variability in personality is not nearly as consistent as for the other topics I cover.
Greater Male Variance in Mental Tests
In the early 1990s, testing experts Larry Hedges and Amy Nowell set out to conduct a
comprehensive study of sex differences in mental test scores, variability, and high-
scoring individuals in the United States for all of the large and nationally representative
datasets over the period from 1960 to 1992.52 Their article, published in Science in
1995, was the definitive statement of where things stood when they wrote. They
presented variability ratios for 37 different mental test measures. Male variance was
higher in 35 of the 37.53 The exceptions were a test of word memory and one of
coding speed—and, the authors noted, “In both cases, measures of the same constructs
in other surveys showed greater male variability.”54 Overall, Hedges and Nowell
concluded, “These data demonstrate that in U.S. populations, the test scores of males
are indeed more variable than those of females, at least for the abilities measured
during the 32-year period covered by the six national surveys. Moreover, there is little
indication that variance ratios are changing over time.”55
The National Assessment of Educational Progress (NAEP) now provides an even
longer trendline—44 years for reading and 37 years for math. From the first test in
1971 to the most recent one in 2015, 12th-grade boys have had higher variance than
girls on all 13 tests for which I have data, with ratios ranging from 1.07 to 1.20, with a
mean of 1.12. The trendline is absolutely flat. And yet in all of those tests, girls
outscored boys at the mean.56 On the nine math tests for which I have data, all showed
greater male variance, with ratios also ranging from 1.07 to 1.20 and a mean of 1.13.
The SAT shows even more consistent but quite small variance ratios. From 1996 to
2016, the variance ratio on the math test was never smaller than 1.03 and never larger
than 1.09. For the reading test, variance was almost but not quite equal, ranging from
1.02 to 1.05. There has been no trend in either test.
VARIABILITY IN MENTAL TESTS DURING CHILDHOOD
I concentrate on test scores in adolescents and older because so many sex differences, physiological
and mental, change during adolescence and persist thereafter. But greater male variability on mental
tests emerges early as well. Psychologists Rosalind Arden and Robert Plomin explored variance in g
in large British samples at ages 2, 3, 4, 7, 9, and 10. They found significantly greater variance among
boys at every age except 2. 57
Anglosphere
Mean variance ratio
Reading: 1.15
Math: 1.14
Science: 1.18
East Asia
Mean variance ratio
Reading: 1.12
Math: 1.18
Science: 1.18
Eastern Europe
Mean variance ratio
Reading: 1.12
Math: 1.12
Science: 1.14
Latin Am./Caribbean
Mean variance ratio
Reading: 1.09
Math: 1.12
Science: 1.13
Mideast/No. Africa
Mean variance ratio
Reading: 1.17
Math: 1.16
Science: 1.14
Scandinavia
Mean variance ratio
Reading: 1.19
Math: 1.14
Science: 1.18
SE Asia
Mean variance ratio
Reading: 1.12
Math: 1.10
Science: 1.07
Western Europe
Mean variance ratio
Reading: 1.12
Math: 1.14
Science: 1.15
The table shows remarkably consistent greater male variability in regions that are
culturally, socioeconomically, and educationally diverse. Furthermore, this uniformity
of greater male variability existed across three tests that showed quite different effect
sizes by sex. Averaged across countries, boys slightly outscored girls on the math test
(d = –0.05) while girls fractionally outscored boys on the science test (d = +0.01). Girls
substantially outscored boys on the reading test (d = +0.32). And yet the mean VRs for
those countries were –1.14, –1.14, and –1.15 for reading, math, and science
respectively.
How Big Does a Variance Ratio Have to Be Before It Becomes Important?
In his 1994 review of greater male variance in mental tests, Alan Feingold pronounced
that a VR between 0.9 and 1.1 was “negligible,”62 and thereby established a guideline
that others who discuss variance ratios have often followed. I consider this to be an
important error. VRs between 0.9 and 1.1 can be socially and culturally important for
any trait for which performance at the extremes has consequences.
Consider the implications for a normally distributed trait if the VR is just 1.09.
Assume that male and female means are equal, so that the only source of a disparity is
the greater male variance. With a VR of 1.09, we can expect males to outnumber
females by 31 percent in the 99th percentile, 38 percent in the top half of the top
percentile, and 57 percent in the top tenth of the top percentile. Those are noteworthy
disproportions in the abstract, but even more noteworthy when we consider the
consequences. The social consequences of this seemingly small disparity can be great.
In a population of 250 million adults—roughly the number of Americans ages 20
and older—the top 0.1 percent amounts to 250,000 people. Think about the 250,000
people with the nation’s highest visuospatial and math skills. They constitute some
substantial proportion of the top programmers and hardware designers in Silicon Valley,
the staffs of quantitative hedge funds, and the nation’s most eminent mathematicians,
physicists, chemists, biologists, and engineers. Apply the same logic to other fields
requiring different abilities—the 250,000 most gifted attorneys, the 250,000 most gifted
managers, the 250,000 most gifted in the performing arts. America is far from having
tapped the talents of all 250,000 of the most gifted in any field, but it is probable that a
large proportion of the most important accomplishments in all fields are done by those
who are in the top 0.1 percent, three standard deviations above the mean. Add in the
accomplishments and positions of the much larger numbers of people in the entire 99th
percentile—2.5 million people—and even the 31 percent disparity at that level, given a
VR of only 1.09, will have a large aggregated impact.
Once I leave behind a minimal case—equal means and VR of only 1.09—the
disproportions produced by normal distributions increase rapidly. For equal means and
a VR favoring males of 1.15, there will be 54 percent more males in the 99th percentile
and more than twice as many males in the 99.9th percentile. Start to combine a VR
with an effect size favoring males, and the sex imbalance increases even more. Given a
VR of 1.15 and an effect size of just d = –0.10 favoring males—“very small” by
Cohen’s definition—and you can expect twice as many males as females in the 99th
percentile and almost three times as many in the 99.9th percentile.
Do Statistical Expectations for the Tails Correspond to Actual Distributions?
The key issue here is the assumption that the distribution of the trait is perfectly normal
all the way out through three standard deviations. The only way to be sure what the
male-to-female ratios are at the extremes is to have such a large and representative
sample that you can see the actual numbers, not the theoretically predicted ones. But
this means extremely large samples. For example, if you are interested in knowing the
male-to-female ratio of people with IQs of 145 and higher, you are talking about the
ratio for the 99.865th percentile. With a mean of 100 and a standard deviation of 15,
even a sample of 10,000 people can be expected to produce only about 13 people with
IQs that high, far short of the number you need to have any confidence in the male-
female ratio. Many national assessments such as the NAEP in America and the
Cognitive Abilities Test in Great Britain have samples with hundreds of thousands or
even millions of scores, but to my knowledge they have not published breakdowns by
gender within the top five percentiles. We do have two solid pieces of evidence bearing
on the question, however.
The Early Childhood Longitudinal Study. The first comes from a test of the
common assertion that more people are in the gifted range of intelligence than the
statistics of the normal distribution would predict. The study of 10 large, nationally
representative samples (first author was Russell Warne) indicated that the numbers of
people in the top percentiles are generally about what they should be—somewhat more
for some tests, somewhat less for others, but overall close to expectations.63
For the question I’m asking—does greater male variance really predict
disproportionate numbers of males at the extremes?—the Warne study was valuable
because one of the studies it used, the Early Childhood Longitudinal Study, had a
nationally representative sample that was large enough (18,000) to assess disparities up
to the top half of the 99th percentile and information broken down by sex. They were
given standardized cognitive tests at six points during their observation from
kindergarten through 8th grade.
The effect sizes were typical: small female advantages on the reading tests, small
male advantages on the math and science tests, and trivial effect sizes on the general
knowledge test. The largest effect size was –0.24 on the science test; none of the rest
reached an absolute value of 0.17. But VRs for all of the tests were greater than 1.0,
ranging from 1.01 on the science test to 1.32 on one of the math tests. First, here are
the actual results—the ratios of boys to girls in various high-end categories ranging
from the top five percentiles to the top half of the top percentile.
Test: C4 Reading
Top 5%: 0.93
Top 2%: 0.97
Top 1%: 0.95
Top 0.5%: 1.07
Test: C4 Math
Top 5%: 1.84
Top 2%: 2.22
Top 1%: 2.91
Top 0.5%: 2.72
Test: C5 Reading
Top 5%: 0.95
Top 2%: 1.10
Top 1%: 1.16
Test: C5 Math
Top 5%: 2.09
Top 2%: 2.79
Top 1%: 4.35
Top 0.5%: 3.90
Test: C5 Science
Top 5%: 2.10
Top 2%: 2.68
Top 1%: 2.64
Top 0.5%: 4.38
Test: C6 Science
Top 5%: 2.28
Top 2%: 2.55
Top 1%: 1.77
Source: Data from Warne, Godwin, and Smith (2013), provided by Russell Warne, personal communication.
The numbering of the tests reflects the increasing ages at which they were
administered. To interpret the table, look at the top row, left-hand column—“1.44”
indicates that there were 44 percent more boys than girls in the top five percentiles for
the initial test of general knowledge. The two blank cells for the right-hand column
indicate that no more than a few students scored in that range.
The table shows two broad trends: Throughout elementary and middle school,
more boys than girls were represented in the top percentiles in general knowledge and
math, with roughly equal proportions for the reading test; and the ratios favoring boys
tended to increase as the criteria got more restrictive. Taking the mean for all the tests,
the ratios increased from 1.57 for the top five percentiles to 3.15 for the top half
percentile.
Next, how did the predictions for those categories based on the assumption of a
normal distribution work out? The graph below shows a scatter plot of the predicted
ratios and the actual ratios.
In this article, we reviewed the history of the hypothesis that general intelligence
is more biologically variable in males than in females and presented data from
two samples consisting of almost entire populations that test this hypothesis.
These data, which in many ways are the most complete that have ever been
compiled, substantially support the hypothesis.68
Many of the books I used for Human Diversity were e-book editions, few of which let
the reader know the page numbers of the print version. Most of the technical articles,
magazine articles, reports, and databases I cite were found on the Internet. In both
cases, standards for citations are still evolving. I have followed the Chicago style with
a few simplifying adaptations. For e-books, I give the chapter from which my material
was drawn, and the figure or table number when appropriate. For sources taken from
the Internet, I give the website’s name and the URL for the home page. I do not give
the specific web page because websites change their indexes so frequently, nor do I
include the date when I accessed the website.
The full citations of articles in newspapers, magazines, and websites are given in
the notes. The references section is reserved for books, journal articles, and other
scholarly works.
Introduction
1. Trivers (2011): chapter 13. For a full-scale exposition of the proposition that social
science must rest on biology, see Rosenberg (2017). Throughout the book, I use
an inclusive definition of social sciences, treating psychology as a social science
along with anthropology, sociology, economics, and political science.
2. Trivers (2011): chapter 13.
3. For the roots of the orthodoxy, see Tooby and Cosmides (1992) and Pinker
(2002): Part I. I give a fuller account of this story in chapter 15.
4. Berger and Luckmann (1966): 2.
5. For a sympathetic account of the subsequent development of social
constructionism, see Lock and Strong (2010).
6. This case was memorably made first in Bloom (1987) and brought up to date in
Lukianoff and Haidt (2018).
7. Two classics that introduced the field now called evolutionary psychology are E.
O. Wilson’s Sociobiology (1975) and Richard Dawkins’s The Selfish Gene
(1976). For those who are prepared for deep dives, there’s David Geary’s The
Origin of Mind: Evolution of Brain, Cognition, and General Intelligence (2004)
and the sixth edition of David Buss’s classic Evolutionary Psychology: The New
Science of the Mind (2019). A shorter and breezier account (but still scientifically
serious) is Steve Stewart-Williams’s The Ape That Understood the Universe: How
the Mind and Culture Evolve (2018).
8. Gardner (1983) and Gardner (2008). Gardner has nine intelligences in the most
recent version: visual-spatial, verbal-linguistic, logical-mathematical, interpersonal,
intrapersonal, musical, bodily-kinesthetic, naturalistic, and existential. The labels
for the last two are not intuitively understandable. Naturalistic refers to relating to
one’s natural surroundings and making accurate judgments, as in hunting, farming,
and Charles Darwin’s genius. Existential encompasses what others have called
spiritual intelligence. Bodily-kinesthetic intelligence is outside the purview of this
book. It has a significant cognitive component, involving a sense of timing,
understanding the goal of the physical action, and the mental qualities that go into
training the physical abilities. But the core of bodily-kinesthetic ability involves
capabilities below the neck. Otherwise, I discuss all of the intelligences (or talents;
call them what you will) represented by Gardner’s theory insofar as they have
entered the technical literature.
Part I: “Gender Is a Social Construct”
1. For the universality of male social and political dominance, see Goldberg (1993b).
The original version, titled The Inevitability of Patriarchy: Why the Biological
Difference Between Men and Women Always Produces Male Domination,
inspired a variety of attacks claiming to identify tribes or societies in which men
did not rule. Goldberg addressed all of them in the 1993 revision, making an
empirical case for the universality of male domination that has not subsequently
been challenged with data.
2. Locke’s case was limited to arguments that a woman is not the property of the
husband, she retains power over her children in the absence of the father, and a
woman has as much right as a man to dissolve the marriage compact. Locke
(1960).
3. Astell (1700): Preface to the third edition.
4. Kate Austin, “Woman,” unpublished MS, 1901. en.wikisource.org.
5. Swanwick (1913): 28.
6. Mill (1869).
7. Shaw (1891): 42. The advent of evolutionary theory in the mid-nineteenth
century provided ammunition for those who saw biologically grounded
differences. In 1875, Antoinette Blackwell published The Sexes Throughout
Nature, based on Darwin, concluding that men and women were importantly
different emotionally and intellectually, but equal. Blackwell (1875). The
Evolution of Sex, by Patrick Geddes and Arthur Thomson (1889), concluded that
men and women were primordially different: “We have seen that a deep
difference in constitution expresses itself in the distinctions between male and
female, whether these be physical or mental. The differences may be exaggerated
or lessened, but to obliterate them it would be necessary to have all the evolution
over again on a new basis. What was decided among the prehistoric Protozoa
cannot be annulled by Act of Parliament.” Geddes and Thomson (1889): 247.
8. “On ne naît pas femme: on le devient.” de Beauvoir (2009): 283. The sentence
comes at the opening of the first chapter of volume 2. The 2009 translation by
Constance Borde and Sheila Malovany-Chevallier reads, “One is not born, but
rather becomes, woman,” which I prefer. I have given the customary translation
in the text because it is so widely accepted.
9. Martin, Ruble, and Szkrybalo (2002) has a nice account of the different strands of
social role theory.
10. Endendijk, Groeneveld, Bakermans-Kranenburg et al. (2016): 1 of 33.
11. The meta-analyses that combine the studies of socialization have found only
modest evidence for differential treatment from the second half of the twentieth
century onward. The first assessment of the literature was Maccoby and Jacklin
(1974). They documented the reality of what are called sex-typed activities (e.g.,
little girls are given dolls, little boys are encouraged to play sports), but found that
otherwise “the reinforcement contingencies for the two sexes appear to be
remarkably similar.” (p. 342). A spirited debate ensued, led by Jeanne Block, who
argued in a series of articles that Maccoby and Jacklin had underestimated the role
of differential socialization (e.g., Block (1978), Block (1983)).
Lytton and Romney (1991), a subsequent meta-analysis of 172 studies of
gender socialization, examined socialization regarding eight topics: amount of
interaction, achievement encouragement, warmth, nurturance, responsiveness
(including praise), encouragement of dependency, restrictiveness/low
encouragement of independence, disciplinary strictness, encouragement of sex-
typed activities, sex-typed perception, and clarity of communication/use of
reasoning. The meta-analysis found few differences on any of them. “The effect
sizes for most socialization areas are nonsignificant and generally very small,
fluctuating in direction across studies,” the authors wrote in their conclusion. In
the North American studies, the one exception was moderately more
encouragement of sex-typed activities in boys. In the studies from other Western
countries, parents use moderately more physical punishment for boys than for
girls. Lytton and Romney (1991): 286 and Tables 4 and 5. The term effect size is
explained in chapter 1. The effect size for sex-typed activities was –0.43 (boys got
more encouragement) and the effect size for physical punishment was –0.37
(boys got more physical punishment).
Seven years later, another meta-analysis, Leaper, Anderson, and Sanders
(1998), focused specifically on studies that observed the language that parents use
with their children. There were sex differences in the types of speech that parents
employed (e.g., supportive speech, directive speech, informative speech). Not
surprisingly, mothers tend to talk more to their children than fathers do. But
fathers used the same patterns of language with daughters and sons alike. So did
mothers, with just two exceptions: Mothers talked somewhat more to daughters
than to sons and used somewhat more supportive speech with daughters than with
sons. The effect sizes were +0.29 and +0.22 respectively. This was not the stuff
of pervasive socialization through language.
Since 1998, one of the major areas in which researchers continue to look for
socialization effects has been differences in the ways parents exert parental control
over daughters and sons. In the theoretical literature there is a good strategy
(autonomy-supportive ) and a bad one (controlling). Autonomy-supportive
strategies combine an appropriate amount of control with an appropriate amount
of choice, take the child’s perspective into account, and explain the reasons when
the parent’s decision overrules the child’s preference. Endendijk, Groeneveld,
Bakermans-Kranenburg et al. (2016): 2 of 33. An extensive literature provides
evidence that autonomy-supportive strategies are associated with lower levels of
oppositional, aggressive, and hyperactive child behaviors. E.g., Kawabata, Alink,
Tseng et al. (2011); Karreman, van Tuijl, van Aken et al. (2006); Stormshak,
Bierman, McMahon et al. (2000).
The bad strategy is controlling. As the label implies, it is a “You will do it
because I tell you to do it” approach to child-rearing. The two chief ways in which
parents can be controlling are harsh physical control and psychological pressure or
manipulation (examples are shaming, inducing feelings of guilt, or withdrawing
affection). An extensive literature documents a variety of negative consequences
of controlling strategies, especially during adolescence. E.g., Karreman, van Tuijl,
van Aken et al. (2006); Rothbaum and Weisz (1994); Kawabata, Alink, Tseng et
al. (2011).
In 2016, the Dutch scholars cited earlier published a meta-analysis of the
literature on gender-differentiating parenting regarding control strategies. Their
conclusion was generically similar to those of the other meta-analyses: The
evidence showed little difference in the way parents treat daughters and sons.
Parents were slightly more controlling with sons, but the effect was negligible (d =
–0.08). The difference was even smaller regarding autonomy-supportive behavior
(d = –0.03). The analysis showed an effect over time, with boys receiving more
autonomy-supportive parenting in studies from the 1970s and 1980s, while girls
received more autonomy-supportive parenting in studies published from 1990 on.
But the fitted effect sizes remained small throughout, with an absolute d of no
more than about 0.10. Endendijk, Groeneveld, Bakermans-Kranenburg et al.
(2016): Fig. 2.
The authors’ conclusion resembles those of others who have studied gender
differentiation in parenting:
12. Eagly (1987). This abbreviated description is drawn from Eagly and Wood (2011).
For a detailed description of social role theory, see Wood and Eagly (2012).
13. Eagly and Wood (2011): 468.
14. Eagly and Wood (2011): 459.
15. Bleier (1991) quoted in Halpern (2012): 178.
16. Summers’s remarks were subsequently transcribed and released by the Office of
the President at Harvard. Summers (2005).
17. Stuart Taylor Jr., “Why Feminist Careerists Neutered Larry Summers,” Atlantic,
February 2005.
18. Sam Dillon and Sara Rimer, “No Break in the Storm over Harvard President’s
Words,” New York Times, January 19, 2005.
19. Taylor, “Why Feminist Careerists Neutered Larry Summers.”
20. Sam Dillon and Sara Rimer, “President of Harvard Tells Women’s Panel He’s
Sorry,” New York Times, January 21, 2005; Dillon and Rimer, “No Break in the
Storm over Harvard President’s Words.”
21. For those who want to look into sex differences more thoroughly, here’s a brief
reading list.
The book that for me best integrates the findings from the technical literature
with compelling narratives about real cases is Susan Pinker’s The Sexual
Paradox: Men, Women, and the Real Gender Gap. Much has been learned since
she published it in 2008, but none of her technical positions have been discredited
and many have been reinforced by subsequent work.
Simon Baron-Cohen’s The Essential Difference: Male and Female Brains
and the Truth About Autism (2003) is that rarity, a book that is both scientifically
seminal and readable.
A new edition of David Geary’s magisterial Male, Female: The Evolution of
Human Sex Differences is in press as I write. I expect it to be, like the earlier
editions in 1998 and 2010, the definitive statement of the existing state of
knowledge.
Diane Halpern’s Sex Differences in Cognitive Ability (2012) is focused on a
narrower topic and is somewhat denser than the others, but she tells you all you
need to know about her topic in one source.
If you want to work your way into a broader discussion of sex differences in
smaller chunks, I recommend a series of columns that David Schmitt wrote for
Psychology Today from 2013 to 2016, easily accessible online at
www.psychologytoday.com. Engagingly written, they are also fully documented
and accompanied by bibliographies.
22. As of early 2017, the Women’s Studies Online Resources webpage listed 673
American institutions of higher education that have women’s studies programs,
departments, or research centers. I didn’t try to review the course offerings for all
of them, but I did examine the course catalogs during the 2016–17 school year for
the women’s studies programs at 13 of the most prestigious universities in the
country—the eight Ivy League schools plus MIT, Stanford, Duke, the University
of Chicago, and the University of California at Berkeley. I was searching for
courses in women’s studies programs that provided systematic discussions of
biological evidence for sex differences in cognitive repertoires. I found a single
example: Cornell University’s course FGSS 3210, “Gender and the Brain,” cross-
listed as biology course BIONB 3215, which tells prospective enrollees, “Reading
the original scientific papers and related critical texts, we will ask whether we can
find measurable physical differences in male and female brains, and what these
differences might be.” I can’t guarantee that the online course listings were
complete. And while I found no courses dealing with hormones or other
genetically-grounded sources of male-female differences, I presume that these
topics, along with differences in the brain, are sometimes raised in courses not
specifically devoted to them. But compare what I found with what should be the
norm. At a reputable university—and these 13 are at the top of the heap—to get a
degree in women’s studies should include as an obvious requirement a solid
foundation in evolutionary biology and in the differential biology of the two sexes,
including biology above the neck. None of these 13 prestigious schools did.
23. Trivers (2011): 314–15.
1: A Framework for Thinking About Sex Differences
1. In the 1971 edition of the Oxford English Dictionary, the only definition of
gender as a noun applied to the sexes was as a jocular transfer of the linguistic use
of gender (masculine and feminine genders) to apply to humans. By the 1989
edition, it had added a new meaning: “In modern (especially feminist) use, a
euphemism for the sex of a human being, often intended to emphasize the social
and cultural, as opposed to the biological, distinctions between the sexes.” The
OED dated the earliest known example of that meaning to 1963, but the rationale
for using gender instead of sex was first introduced a decade earlier in Money
(1952).
2. Thorndike (1911): 32.
3. Quoted in Baron-Cohen (2002): 251.
4. Baron-Cohen (2003): 61.
5. Baron-Cohen (2003): 26.
6. Baron-Cohen and his colleagues devised tests for measuring systemizing and
empathizing, with scores labeled SQ and EQ respectively. In the largest sample of
people (5,186 total) who were administered both tests, the effect sizes (a term
explained later in this chapter) were +0.63 (females had a higher mean) for EQ
and –0.47 (males had a higher mean) for SQ. Wright and Skagerberg (2012).
Effect sizes in the samples used by Baron-Cohen and his colleagues have been
+0.50 and +0.76 for EQ and –0.59 for SQ. Baron-Cohen, Richler, Bisarya et al.
(2003): Table 1; Baron-Cohen and Wheelwright (2004): Table II.
7. Sawilowsky (2009).
8. Cohen used the descriptors to guide researchers in characterizing an expected d
value when there was no prior research available. He repeatedly told his readers
not to make too much of them. For example: “The terms ‘small,’ ‘medium,’ and
‘large’ are relative, not only to each other, but to the area of behavioral science or
even more particularly to the specific content and research method being
employed in any given investigation.” Cohen (1988): 25. And “A reader who finds
that what is here defined as ‘large’ is too small (or too large) to meet what his area
of behavioral science would consider appropriate standards is urged to make more
suitable operational definitions.” Cohen (1988): 79.
9. Funder and Ozer (2019).
10. Funder and Ozer (2019).
11. See Rosnow and Rosenthal (2003) for a critique of Cohen’s guidelines antedating
Hyde (2005). See Gignac and Szodorai (2016) for suggested guidelines
corresponding to those proposed by Funder and Ozer (2019).
12. Hyde (2005): 581. I have reproduced the inequality symbols as they appear in the
article, which apparently treats “<” as equivalent to “≤.”
13. Hyde (2005): 585–86.
14. Hyde (2005): 587.
15. Hyde (2005): 587.
16. Hyde (2005): 590.
17. In his technical discussion of this issue, Del Giudice put it this way: “When
measuring a multidimensional construct, the overall difference between two
groups is not the average of the effects measured on each dimension, but a
combination of those effects in the multidimensional space: Many small
differences, each of them on a different dimension, can create an impressive
effect when all the dimensions are considered simultaneously. Crucially, such
overall differences are likely to matter more than their individual components,
both in shaping people’s perceptions and in affecting social interaction.” Del
Giudice (2009): 268.
18. See Del Giudice (2009). He augmented the discussion in Del Giudice, Booth, and
Irwing (2012). Janet Hyde responded in the comments to Del Giudice (2009) with
“The Distance Between North Dakota and South Dakota.” Stewart-Williams and
Thomas (2013) critiques the use of Mahalanobis D in its appendix.
2: Sex Differences in Personality
1. Adapted from McCarthy, Nugent, and Lenz (2017): Table 2. I have omitted
neurological and neurodegenerative diseases that were included in the table:
migraine, stroke, multiple sclerosis, Alzheimer’s disease, Parkinson’s disease,
amyotrophic lateral sclerosis, and myasthenia gravis.
2. As with almost all sex differences, a minority literature disputes the magnitude of
differences. In the case of depression, for example, see Martin, Neighbors, and
Griffith (2013).
3. In statistics, factor has a technical meaning. In its most basic form, the statistical
procedure (factor analysis) creates a first component—a factor—that explains as
much of the variation among the observations as possible. The algorithms then
create a second factor that explains as much of the remaining variation as it can,
and so on through successive iterations, each of which produces a new factor,
until all of the variation has been assigned to a factor.
4. Lewis Goldberg, who had been instrumental in resuscitating interest in personality
studies after a lull in the 1960s and 1970s, coined the phrase “Big Five.” See his
review of the development of the Big Five model in Goldberg (1993a).
5. Costa and McCrae (1985). The 1985 version had measures of neuroticism,
extraversion, and openness. Agreeableness and conscientiousness were added
later. The official name of the current version is NEO-PI-3.
6. For a full discussion of this issue, see Pettersson, Mendle, Turkheimer et al.
(2014).
7. Other personality models include HEXACO, which adds an honesty-humility
factor to the Big Five, and a model focused on three problematic aspects of the
personality: narcissism, Machiavellianism, and sadism. It’s called variously the
Dark Triad or the Dark Tetrad model. For a review of the literature, see Furnham,
Richards, and Paulhus (2013).
8. Among the 30 FFM facets (the detailed characteristics that make up the five
factors), here are the ones that showed absolute effect sizes of less than 0.20 in
both the Costa and Kajonius studies: experiences anger or bitterness, assertive or
forceful in expression, open to the inner world of imagination, open to new
experiences in life, open to reexamining one’s own values, trust in others’ sincerity
or intentions, values orderliness, believes in fulfilling moral obligations, uses self-
discipline in fulfilling tasks, and thinks things through before acting. In the Del
Giudice study using the 16PF, these were the factors showing an absolute
difference of less than 0.20: Self-reliant, solitary, resourceful, lively, animated,
spontaneous, abstracted, imaginative, absentminded, organized, perfectionistic,
compulsive private, discreet, nondisclosing, socially bold, venturesome, and thick-
skinned.
9. Effect sizes are reported for latent variables corrected for specific variance and
measurement error. See the discussion in Del Giudice, Booth, and Irwing (2012).
10. Del Giudice, Booth, and Irwing (2012).
11. Del Giudice, Booth, and Irwing (2012).
12. Noftle and Shaver (2006). Averages of d are computed using the absolute value.
In this case, the values were corrected for attenuation due to scale unreliability.
13. Del Giudice (2009): Table 1.
14. Connellan, Baron-Cohen, Wheelwright et al. (2000): Table 1.
15. Sagi and Hoffman (1976); Simner (1971); Hoffman (1973). This and subsequent
citations in the list are drawn from Alexander and Wilcox (2012).
16. Hittelman and Dickes (1979); Leeb and Rejskind (2004); Lutchmaya, Baron-
Cohen, and Raggatt (2001).
17. Cossette, Pomerleau, Malcuit et al. (1996).
18. Gunnar and Donahue (1980).
19. Mayes and Carter (1990).
20. Alexander, Wilcox, and Woods (2009); Benenson, Duggan, and Markovits (2004);
Campbell, Shirley, and Heywood (2000). The doll-truck contrast shows up in
nonhuman primates as well: Male vervet and rhesus monkeys prefer trucks while
female ones prefer dolls. Alexander and Hines (2002); Hassett, Siebert, and
Wallen (2008).
21. Mundy, Block, Delgado et al. (2007); Olafsen, Ronning, Kaaresen et al. (2006).
22. McClure (2000). Another 14 studies simply reported that the results were
“nonsignificant” without including the information necessary to calculate effect
sizes. Half of those studies had samples of 48 or fewer. Large effect sizes can be
statistically insignificant with sample sizes that small. McClure calculated a lower
bound effect size of +0.26 if all of the nonsignificant results had an effect size of
zero—unrealistically low. The true value is somewhere between +0.26 and +0.92,
probably well toward the +0.92 end of the range. Even the lower bound of 0.26
was statistically significant.
23. Costa, Terracciano, and McCrae (2001).
24. Costa, Terracciano, and McCrae (2001): Table 3. The only exception was
agreeableness in Zimbabwe, which was a trivial –0.02.
25. McCrae and Terracciano (2005): Table 5. The inconsistent effect sizes, all of
them only fractionally different from zero, were for Nigeria (N = 0, A = 0, E = –
0.04, O = 0, C = 0), India (E = –0.05, O = +0.03), Botswana (E = –0.01),
Ethiopia (A = –0.02), Russia (A = –0.02), and Uganda (O = 0).
26. The prediction is necessary, but it has also been explicitly acknowledged. See
Eagly, Wood, and Johannessen-Schmidt (2004), quoted in Schmitt, Long,
McPhearson et al. (2016).
27. Costa, Terracciano, and McCrae (2001): 327. For the sake of consistency in the
interpretation of results, the countries in this and the subsequent discussion are
limited to those for which the UN has calculated a score on the Gender Inequality
Index. The median effect sizes for emotional stability, agreeableness, openness to
emotion, and extraversion for adults across 21 countries were –0.51, +0.45,
+0.26, and +0.23 respectively. The Costa study omitted the fifth factor,
conscientiousness, because none of its facets showed consistent sex differences.
The Costa study also addressed a problem with the facets for measuring
extraversion and openness. The facets for measuring extraversion included
warmth/affiliation, which is higher in females, and dominance/venturesomeness,
which is higher in males. Behaviorally, these traits are completely different, but
they more or less cancel each other out in the combined measure of extraversion.
A similar problem occurs with openness to experience (women are higher on
measures of openness to emotion and males are higher on openness to ideas). The
Costa study dealt with this problem by creating measures of extraversion and
openness that specifically focused on the warmth/affiliation aspect of extraversion
and the emotional aspect of openness. The discussion in Del Giudice, Booth, and
Irwing (2012) of these masking tendencies when traits are aggregated into the Big
Five includes citations of the relevant sources.
28. Indicators are given in Jahan et al. (2016): Statistical Annex, Tables 4 and 5. The
UN also has a Gender Development Index based on women’s life expectancy,
years of schooling, and women’s per capita gross national income. The correlation
between the Inequality and Development indexes is –.66 (“high” means “bad” on
the Inequality Index, “good” on the Development Index). Both indexes capture
measures of health (maternal mortality rate versus life expectancy) and education
(percent with at least some secondary education versus years of education). In
deciding whether to combine the two indexes, the issue is how much is added by
the measure unique to the Development Index, per capita gross national product. I
judged that to be minor, outweighed by the potentially distorting effects of double-
counting education and health. Data were downloaded from the Human
Development Reports website, www.hdr.undp.org.
29. Absolute size, because it doesn’t make any difference whether females or males
score higher on a personality trait—theoretically, sex differences on all personality
traits should be diminishing.
30. Author’s analysis using GII scores and Costa, Terracciano, and McCrae (2001):
Table 3.
31. For a more concrete sense of how these correlations translate into scores for
nations at the extremes, compare the nations in the McCrae sample with the five
lowest GII scores (Switzerland, Denmark, Iceland, Germany, Denmark) with the
nations with the five highest GII scores (Burkina Faso, India, Uganda, Ethiopia,
and Morocco). On all five factors, the mean effect sizes for the most gender-
egalitarian countries ranged from two times to more than three times the effect
size for the least gender-egalitarian countries: +0.46 compared to +0.22 for
agreeableness, +0.18 compared to +0.09 for conscientiousness, +0.27 compared
to +0.13 for extraversion, +0.36 compared to +0.12 for openness to emotion, and
–0.58 compared to –0.26 for emotional stability. Author’s analysis using GII
scores and McCrae and Terracciano (2005): Table 5.
32. Schmitt, Realo, Voracek et al. (2008).
33. A description of the index and the annual scores may be found at the World
Economic Forum’s website, www.weforum.org.
34. The countries with the five largest values of D, indicating the largest sex
differences in personality, were the Netherlands (1.17), Norway (1.13), Sweden
(1.11), Canada (1.07), and the UK (1.06). The countries with the five smallest
values of D, indicating the smallest sex differences in personality, were China
(0.47), Malaysia (0.58), Japan (0.59), South Korea (0.59), and India (0.70).
Author’s analysis of Mac Giolla and Kajonius (2018): Appendix B.
35. Falk and Hermle (2018): 3 of 6. The author’s Gender Equality Index is an
inversion of the UN’s Gender Inequality Index.
36. Falk and Hermle (2018): 3 of 6.
37. A cross-national study conducted two years after the Schmitt study, Lippa (2010),
provides additional evidence for these patterns but poses problems in
interpretation. Psychologist Richard Lippa used a BBC Internet survey conducted
in 2005 that attracted 255,114 people who responded to at least some items in
each of six modules. From these data, Lippa compared 53 nations on measures he
constructed for extraversion, agreeableness, and emotional stability using
indicators from the Cattell inventory. The effect sizes for the three were +0.18,
+0.61, and –0.41 respectively. The effect sizes in Lippa’s data showed significant
widening of the difference in agreeableness (r = –.41 for agreeableness and the
Gender Inequality Index), minor widening for emotional stability (r = –.14), and
no significant effect for extraversion (r = +.04). Lippa (2010): Table 1. The
difficulty with interpreting the Lippa findings arises from the nature of the sample.
The Internet survey was conducted exclusively in English. This means that the
sample is self-selected for people who speak English and use the BBC and the
Internet. Among those for whom English is a second language, there are problems
of misunderstanding the questions. Despite the reasons for expecting that Lippa’s
sample could produce quite different results from the other cross-national studies
(and there were indeed some differences), the same pattern of results was found:
“In summary, the current results strongly supported Costa et al.’s (2001) and
Schmitt et al.’s (2008) findings that sex differences in personality are highly
replicable across cultures. However, they were sometimes inconsistent with Costa
et al.’s conclusion that sex differences in personality are necessarily ‘modest in
magnitude’ (p. 328). The mean effect sizes for sex differences in agreeableness
and emotional stability, although moderate in magnitude, were still well within the
range of effect sizes for many classic person and situation effects in psychology
(Eagly, 1995; Lipsey & Wilson, 1993). More dramatically, when analyzed at the
aggregated level of men’s and women’s national means, sex accounted for 93% of
the variance in MF-Occ means, 75% of the variance in agreeableness means, 68%
of the variance in emotional stability means, and 23% of the variance in
extraversion, and in each case, sex accounted for much greater amounts of
variance than did either UN gender equality or the interaction of sex and gender
equality.” Lippa (2010): 634.
38. Costa, Terracciano, and McCrae (2001): 329.
39. Costa, Terracciano, and McCrae (2001). A more elaborate version of this
argument is given in Guimond, Branscombe, Brunot et al. (2007).
40. Lippa, Collaer, and Peters (2010).
41. Schmitt, Long, McPhearson et al. (2016): 6.
3: Sex Differences in Neurocognitive Functioning
1. The subsequent list of findings is taken from Halpern (2012): 104–8.
2. Halpern (2012): 104–8.
3. Binaural beats are an auditory phenomenon that occurs when two slightly
different frequencies of sound are played into each ear. Otoacoustic emissions are
caused by the motion of the cochlea’s sensory hair cells.
4. Halpern (2012): 106. In childhood, part of the sex difference may be explained by
girls’ superior verbal skills, but other studies have found the female advantage in
identifying smells in adult samples as well.
5. Halpern (2012): 109.
6. Females are not noticeably better at judging the passage of time, but there is a
systematic sex difference in direction of error. Men tend to overestimate a time
interval while women tend to underestimate it. Halpern (2012): 107–8.
7. Fillingim, King, Ribeiro-Dasilva et al. (2009); Rosen, Ham, and Mogil (2017).
8. Fuller (2002).
9. Fleischman (2014); Al-Shawaf, Lewis, and Buss (2017).
10. Halpern (2012): 108–10.
11. Nagy, Kompagne, Orvos et al. (2007); Piek (2002).
12. Halpern (2012): 109.
13. Halpern (2012): 110.
14. Watson and Kimura (1991).
15. Halpern (2012): 115–18.
16. Heuer and Reisberg (1990); Cahill, Haier, White et al. (2001).
17. Geary (2010).
18. Halpern (2012): 118–28.
19. Verbal reasoning. The Cognitive Abilities Test (CogAT) is a test of three types of
reasoning: verbal, quantitative, and nonverbal. Since it was first published in 1984,
it has undergone three revisions, in 1992, 2000, and 2011. In the four
standardization samples, girls performed better than boys in virtually all grades in
all standardizations (out of 28 combinations of grade level and standardization, the
difference favored girls in 24). Lakin (2013): Table 3. Effect sizes were uniformly
small, averaging +0.07 over all grades and standardizations. Only one of the 28
grade/standardization combinations reached an effect size of +0.20. A British
sample of 320,000 students ages 11–12 who took the CogAT in 2001–3 showed a
larger female advantage (d = +0.15).
Reading. America’s National Assessment of Educational Progress (NAEP) is
administered periodically to large, nationally representative samples, in grades 4,
8, and 12. In the reading test, girls outperformed boys in every grade and every
assessment from 1988 to 2015, with an overall effect size of +0.27. Reilly,
Neumann, and Andrews (2018), which was also the source of subsequent reading
and writing NAEP statistics. Twelfth-grade girls have had an advantage in the
reading test that goes back to the first administration of the test in 1971. Effect
sizes from 1971 to 1992 were in the +0.21 to +0.30 range. Hedges and Nowell
(1995): Table 3. There was no trend across the years in the size of the difference,
but grade level had a marked effect, with d rising from +0.19 in grade 4 to +0.30
in grade 8 and +0.32 in grade 12. The +0.19 effect size for grade 4 is consistent
with an analysis of 2015 performance on the federally required Reading/Language
Arts assessments, which found an effect size for reading of +0.19, combining
scores from grades 3 through 6. Peterson (2018): Table 1. These effect sizes
translate into substantial differences in the number of boys who failed to reach the
minimum standard of literacy by grade 12 (1.5 times as many boys as girls) and
the number of girls reaching the advanced literacy standard (1.9 times as many
girls as boys).
Writing. The female advantage in writing tests is larger than in reading tests.
In NAEP writing tests from 1988 to 2011, the overall effect size was +0.54. As in
the case of the reading test, there was no significant trend over the years but there
was a significant change in effect size from grade 4 to grade 8, when it rose from
+0.42 to +0.62. It stood at +0.55 in grade 12. Reilly, Neumann, and Andrews
(2018). Once again, the results from the Reading/Language Arts assessment in
2015 correspond with the NAEP results. The same study that found a female
advantage of just +0.19 on the reading test for grade 3 to grade 6 found an effect
size of +0.45 on the writing test. Peterson (2018): Table 1. These effect sizes
translated into even larger disparities at the low and high ends, with 2.2 times as
many boys failing to meet the minimum writing standard and 2.5 times as many
girls reaching the advanced standard. For additional evidence of a larger effect size
for writing than for reading and literature reviews, see Reynolds, Scheiber,
Hajovsky et al. (2015) and Scheiber, Reynolds, Hajovsky et al. (2015).
20. Arnett, Pennington, Peterson et al. (2017).
21. In the most recent follow-up, combining 320,000 TIP students from 2011 to
2015, the male-female ratio for the top percentile was 0.88 for the SAT verbal,
0.79 for the ACT English test, and 1.09 for the ACT reading test. For the top 0.5
percent, the corresponding ratios were 0.96, 0.94, and 0.88. For the top 0.01
percent, the corresponding ratios were 0.73, 0.86, and 0.95. Makel, Wai, Peairs et
al. (2016): Table 6. For tests administered until 1994, SAT scores could be
interpreted relative to the national population because the Educational Testing
Service conducted periodic norm samples explicitly designed for that purpose. But
then the SAT was “recentered” in 1995 so that the mean was once again set at
500 (it had fallen to 428 on the verbal test and 482 on the math test). The
substance of the test was revised in 2005 and again in 2017. Whether these
changes were good or bad is debated (for the record, I think mostly bad), but
without question those changes have made trends over time impossible to interpret
relative to the general population.
Data from the standardizations of the CogAT, representing tests of children
from grades 4 to 7, show virtual equality in the top five percentiles and the top
percentile of the verbal/reading domain from 1992. In the original 1984
standardization, the male-female ratios were 1.15 and 1.25 for the top five
percentiles and the top percentile respectively. Girls had a fractional advantage for
both categories in the 1992 and 2000 standardizations, while boys had a fractional
advantage for both categories in the 2011 standardization. Lakin (2013): Table 4.
22. The statement is based on information from the last national norm study
conducted by the Educational Testing Service in the mid-1980s. Braun, Centra,
and King (1987) combined with College Board (2016). I used the 2016 scores
because the College Board introduced major changes in the test in 2017, making
scores from 2017 onward incomparable with previous administrations. The table
showing scores from 1972 to 2016 used a correction for the recentering of the test
in 1995. Standard deviations were retrieved from the individual annual reports for
college-bound seniors. The two sources together indicate that about 67 percent of
the SAT pool had scores above the mean that would have been obtained if all
juniors took the SAT. Extrapolating that 1983 number to recent decades involves
some guesstimates (25 percent of 17-year-olds took the SAT in 1983 compared to
40 percent in recent years), but that the test-taking population is still concentrated
in the upper half of the ability distribution seems incontestable.
23. In terms of effect sizes, the SAT and ACT tell the same story—small—but they
have inconsistent signs. For the 45 years from 1972 to 2016, females have always
had slightly lower SAT verbal scores than males—a surprising contrast to the
universal female advantage for verbal tests of nationally representative samples.
The effect size moved in a narrow range from –0.02 to –0.12 during those
decades, with a mean of –0.06. College Board (2016): 2. The table showing
scores from 1972 to 2016 used a correction for the recentering of the test in 1995.
Standard deviations were retrieved from the individual annual reports for college-
bound seniors.
On the SAT writing test introduced in 2006 and discontinued as of 2017,
females had a small advantage that was never less than +0.10 and never larger
than +0.12. There was no trend over time on either test. But for the ACT from
1995 to 2016, females have maintained an advantage in both the reading and the
English tests. Effect sizes for the reading test moved in a range from +0.02 to
+0.09, with a mean of +0.06. Effect sizes for the English test moved in a range
from +0.11 to +0.17, with a mean of +0.14. Tables from the Digest of
Educational Statistics for 2009 (Table 147) and 2016 (Table 226.50),
downloadable from the National Center for Education Statistics website,
nces.ed.gov/programs/digest.
One of the imponderables about SAT scores is the growing imbalance in the
numbers of males and females taking the test. In 1981, about 22 percent of male
17-year-olds took the SAT compared to 25 percent of female 17-year-olds. (More
precisely, that percentage represents the number of test-takers divided by the
number of 17-year-olds. Some test-takers are older or younger than 17, but the
percentage would change only fractionally if broken down by age at testing.) The
gap first hit four percentage points in 1987, five percentage points in 1992, six
percentage points in 1996, and seven percentage points in 2000. The difference is
large enough that it must be assumed to deflate the female mean because the
female test-taking pool dips deeper into the cognitive distribution than does the
male pool. The effect is unlikely to be much, but it should be kept in mind. My
wordings of the conclusions I draw are intended to tolerate such a bias.
This inconsistency in the results from the SAT and ACT mirrors the earlier
data reported in a major review of the nationally representative populations from
1960 to 1995. Larry Hedges and Amy Nowell reported the male-female ratio
among top scorers in reading comprehension for two major surveys of high school
seniors: the National Longitudinal Study of the High School Class of 1972 and the
1980 High School and Beyond dataset. For scores in the 90th percentile and
higher, the ratios were 0.94 and 1.03—meaning females retained a small
advantage in one of the two. For those in the 95th percentile and higher, the ratios
were 0.81 and 1.06 respectively, thereby showing the same inconsistency. It
appears that for 17–18-year-olds from the upper half of the distribution to the
95th percentile, results can go both ways, depending on the test, sometimes
favoring females and sometimes favoring males, always by small margins. The
minimal conclusion is that the extremely consistent female advantage in the
normal range of verbal ability becomes less dependable as the ability level rises.
24. Halpern (2012): 146–50.
25. Reilly, Neumann, and Andrews (2015): Table 1. The effect sizes for the 2015
NAEP in grades 4, 8, and 12 were –0.07, 0.00, and –0.08 respectively. Author’s
analysis of data downloaded using the NAEP Explorer tool of a National Center
for Education Statistics website, www.nationsreportcard.gov.
26. Author’s analysis of data downloaded using the NAEP Explorer tool.
27. Halpern (2012): 146.
28. For literature reviews, see Penner (2003) and Wai, Cacchio, Putallaz et al. (2010).
29. The Study of Mathematically Precocious Youth, which figures prominently in the
next chapter, found ratios of about 13 favoring males in this range. Benbow and
Stanley (1980), as did Wai, Cacchio, Putallaz et al. (2010) for TIP students in
1981–85.
30. The earliest reliable estimates of differentials at the extremes of mathematical
ability come from Project Talent, a study based on a nationally representative
sample of American 15-year-olds conducted in 1960. The male-female sex ratio
was 1.3 for scores in the top 10 percent, 1.5 in the top 5 percent, 2.1 in the top 3
percent, and 7.0 in the top 1 percent. Hedges and Nowell (1995): 44. The best
longitudinal data since then come from Duke’s TIP program. Makel, Wai, Peairs
et al. (2016): Table 5.
31. 2016 College-Bound Seniors: Total Group Profile Report, College Board: 2,
downloadable from a College Board website, reports.collegeboard.org. Halpern
does not report ACT results by gender for the math test, and the ACT does not
publish those data.
32. For a history of the SAT, see Lemann (1999). For a presentation of the
psychometric properties of the test that tacitly confirm its measurement of the
general mental factor known as g, see Donlon (1984).
33. For the technical debate about test bias, see Mattern and Patterson (2013) and
Aguinis, Culpepper, and Pierce (2016). Insofar as there is bias (it is minor), it
favors blacks—SAT scores slightly overpredict college grades for blacks. Aguinis,
Culpepper, and Pierce (2016) provide evidence that there is differential predictive
validity at the level of individual institutions, but even that differential prediction
does not systematically favor whites or males. For a nontechnical discussion of
the SAT, including issues about what it measures and how much good coaching
does, see my article “Abolish the SAT,” available at the AEI website,
www.aei.org.
34. AMC tests are given in over 3,000 high schools. I focus on AMC12, the test that
is taken by 11th and 12th graders. From 2009 to 2018 (the years for which
detailed data are available), the AMC12 has been taken by 59,000 to 115,000
students per year. This is a small number compared to the million-plus students
who took the SAT during the same period, but the schools that give the test are
concentrated among the top high schools in major urban areas, which in turn, for
demographic reasons, probably contain most of the extremely talented math
students in the country. Furthermore, talented math students who are applying to
elite colleges have a strong incentive to take the AMC12—it’s a much more
difficult test than either the SAT or ACT math tests, and a high score on the AMC
can set their applications apart from the many applicants to elite colleges who
have an 800 on the SAT.
The test has a score range of 0 to 150. In their analysis of the AMC
competitions, Ellison and Swanson (2010) concluded that a score of 100 on the
AMC12 is equivalent to a score of 780–800 on the SAT math. I conducted the
analysis of the 2009–18 administrations of AMC12, using data downloaded from
the AMC website. Depending on the year, a score of 100 put a student at
anywhere from the 94th to the 98th percentile among those who took the AMC.
Thus the AMC12 gives us a glimpse into sex differences deep into the top
percentile of the total population.
35. The percentiles are based on the distribution for the entire population of test-
takers in a given year. The ratio divides the percentage of male test-takers who
scored within that percentile that year by the percentage of female test-takers who
scored within that percentile that year.
36. Halpern (2012): 128–45.
37. Halpern (2012): 138.
38. Halpern (2012): 130.
39. Halpern (2012): 130.
40. For a literature review, see Vasta and Liben (1996). For international results, see
de Lisi, Parameswaran, and McGillicuddy-de Lisi (1989).
41. Law, Pellegrino, and Hunt (1993).
42. Contreras, Rubio, Peña et al. (2007).
43. Huguet and Régner (2007) found that girls performed worse than boys at such a
memory task when it was described as testing memory for geometry but better
than boys when it was described as testing memory for drawing. The more recent
literature on stereotype threat and math and visuospatial skills more commonly
has found little or no effect and also found evidence of publication bias; e.g.,
Pennington, Litchfield, McLatchie et al. (2018); Stoet and Geary (2012); Ganley,
Mingle, Ryan et al. (2013). For more on stereotype threat, see chapter 13.
44. Men also have an advantage in visuospatial knowledge and memory. For example,
they learn a route from a two-dimensional map in fewer trials and with fewer
errors than females. This does not seem to be a function of greater male driving
experience. Rather, men and women tend to use different strategies in finding their
way from point A to point B, with women likely to use landmarks (“turn right at
the bank”), while men are more likely to use points of the compass (“turn north”)
and distances (“turn after three miles”), and to create mental maps. Boone, Gong,
and Hegarty (2018). In this regard, Halpern describes at length the curious story
of the National Geography Bee—a competition similar to the National Spelling
Bee, except that it asks questions about geographical features. An article by Lynn
Liben in 1995 pointed to what she described as “a shocking gender disparity
among winners at every level.” In 1993, about 14,000 of 18,000 school winners
had been boys, as were 55 of the 57 winners in states and territories. That
disparity has persisted undiminished in the quarter century since Liben’s article.
Through 2018, 27 of the 29 winners were male. What makes this especially
intriguing is the contrast with the National Spelling Bee. Both competitions require
extraordinary memorization. Neither geography nor spelling plays to stereotypical
male or female interests. And yet while 27 of 29 National Geography Bee winners
have been male, the 95 winners of the Spelling Bee have been split almost equally
between girls and boys, with girls holding a 49-to-47 advantage as of 2018.
Furthermore, girls have more than held their own since the earliest years—girls
won 7 of the first 10 contests.
45. The classic test for ToM is called a “false-belief task.” For example, a child is
given pictures of another child (Bill), a playground, and a classroom. The child is
told that Bill is going to look for his lunch bag. Bill’s lunch bag is really on the
playground, but Bill thinks his lunch bag is in the classroom. “Where do you think
Bill will look for his lunch bag?” Until they’re about three, children expect Bill to
look for it where the child knows it is—on the playground. Around age four,
children are able to predict Bill’s behavior on the basis of Bill’s false belief, not
their own true belief. See Premack and Woodruff (1978).
46. Maccoby and Jacklin (1974): 214.
47. Hall (1978): Table 4.
48. E.g., Rosip and Hall (2004); Schmid, Schmid Mast, Bombari et al. (2011).
49. Thompson and Voyer (2014): 1175. The authors followed a common practice of
establishing a lower bound by assigning an effect size of zero to any study
reporting that the effect size was statistically insignificant but without reporting its
magnitude. This amounted to 147 out of 551 effect sizes in the meta-analysis.
When they were excluded, the mean effect size was +0.27.
50. Thompson and Voyer (2014): Table 2. I cannot resist noting a detail of the
analyses reported in Table 2. Almost all of the 551 effect sizes in the studies used
for the meta-analysis had a mix of male and female subjects, and they showed a
lower-bound female advantage of +0.17. Thirty-one studies had only female
subjects, and the female advantage was +0.18. Just eight of the studies had
exclusively male subjects. The female advantage was +0.61. To put it another
way, women may be only modestly better than men at figuring out the emotions
that women are feeling, but they are definitely better than men at figuring out the
emotions that men are feeling.
Another interesting finding in the Thompson meta-analysis involved variations
in effect size depending on the kind of emotion involved. In the most widely used
classification, the six basic emotions are happiness, anger, sadness, fear, surprise,
and disgust. Ekman (1999). Past research has established that negative emotions
are more difficult to identify than positive ones—and that’s where women’s
advantage over men was concentrated. The lower bound effect sizes were +0.24
for negative emotions, compared to +0.19 for positive emotions. Thompson and
Voyer (2014): Table 2.
51. Joseph and Newman (2010): Table 6.
52. There is intriguing experimental evidence on this point. In one set of experiments,
participants were given a variety of incentives that would encourage them to “try
harder” to understand the emotional states of others. It didn’t seem to make any
difference, just as “trying harder” doesn’t make any difference in being able to
mentally rotate objects in three dimensions. Hall, Blanch, Horgan et al. (2009).
53. Valla, Ganzel, Yoder et al. (2010).
54. Herlitz and Yonker (2010): 112.
55. Allen, Rueter, Abram et al. (2017).
56. Full-scale IQ tests such as the Wechsler or Stanford-Binet are designed to
minimize sex differences. From the earliest versions of such tests, each item in
each subtest has been examined to see whether it is easier for one sex than the
other. If so, either a counterbalancing item favoring the other sex has been
included in that subtest or the item has been removed altogether. For a discussion
of the methods for eliminating gender differences in IQ subtests (which extends to
a citation of a book written in 1914), see Matarazzo (1972): 352–58. This practice
cannot altogether remove gender differences in the final published test, because
the sample used for the item analysis and the sample used for establishing the
national norms are different, but the process introduces a heavy thumb on the
scale that prevents large gender differences from emerging.
57. The standardization sample for the 1988 revision of the Woodcock-Johnson
battery of cognitive tests showed a female advantage of 2.4 points in the 1988
revision (author’s analysis, data provided courtesy of the Woodcock-Johnson
Foundation). The results apply to test-takers ages 18 through 65. In one of the
largest surveys ever conducted, the nearly universal Scottish Mental Survey of
1947, females had a mean that was 1.7 points higher than the male mean.
Johnson, Carothers, and Deary (2008): 521. In the large British sample of children
ages 11–12 who took CogAT in 2001–3, the total score slightly favored girls, with
an effect size of +0.05. Strand, Deary, and Smith (2006): Table 3.
58. Data are taken from the WAIS technical manuals published with each
standardization.
59. Jensen (1998): 536.
60. Jensen (1998): 538. Colom, Juan-Espinosa, Abad et al. (2000); Colom, García,
Juan-Espinosa et al. (2002); and Deary, Thorpe, Wilson et al. (2003) conducted
analyses of the issue and came to the same conclusion.
61. Lynn and Irwing (2004) reopened the debate, arguing that there are no sex
differences or a slight female advantage in early adolescence, but a nontrivial male
advantage opens by late adolescence. Lynn has continued to compile additional
data supporting the existence of a nontrivial sex difference in g, most recently in
Lynn (2017), a target article that attracted 11 detailed commentaries. Taken
together, they will give you a good overview of the state of the debate. Other
articles for the affirmative since the question was reopened in 1994 are Lynn
(1999); Irwing and Lynn (2005); Jackson and Rushton (2006); and Irwing (2012).
Others for the negative are Colom, Juan-Espinosa, Abad et al. (2000); Halpern
and LaMay (2000); Blinkhorn (2005); van der Sluis, Posthuma, Dolan et al.
(2006); and Iliescu, Ilie, Ispas et al. (2016). For a recent article with new data and
an overview of previous research, see Arribas-Aguila, Abad, and Colom (2019).
62. The most widely publicized study that made the case for a relationship between
test scores and gender egality, Else-Quest, Hyde, and Linn (2010), analyzed data
from the 2003 round of the Trends in International Mathematics and Science
Study (TIMSS) and the 2004 PISA round.
63. Author’s analysis, 2015 PISA scores downloaded from the OECD website,
www.oecd.org/pisa/. That database includes the standard deviation for each
country, enabling effect sizes to be based country-specific in both their means and
standard deviations. The means given in the text are calculated as the mean of the
individual effect sizes for the 67 countries. If instead the effect size is calculated
from the mean male and female test scores and the standard deviations of those
means, the female advantage is not +0.32, as given in the text, but +0.62. The
effect sizes for math and science are –0.09 and +0.01 respectively, not much
different from those reported in the text.
64. Guiso, Monte, Sapienza et al. (2008); Marks (2008); Else-Quest, Hyde, and Linn
(2010).
65. Stoet and Geary (2013). See also Stoet and Geary (2015).
66. The sign for the GII was reversed to make it correspond to the sign of the other
two (so that “high” = “good” on all three). The correlations among the three
separate indexes for 2015 are +.64 for the GDI and GII, +.64 for the GDI and
GGI, and +.52 for the GII and GGI. The face validity for the combined indexes is
good. The top-fifteen-ranked nations in gender egality are, in order, Iceland,
Finland, Norway, Sweden, Slovenia, Switzerland, Ireland, Estonia, Lithuania,
Latvia, Denmark, Germany, France, Belarus, and Belgium. The bottom fifteen,
starting with the last-ranked, were Yemen, Pakistan, Chad, Mali, Côte d’Ivoire,
Syria, Mauritania, Morocco, Liberia, Iran, Benin, Jordan, Burkina Faso, Gambia,
and Swaziland.
In some individual countries, the effect sizes of the PISA or TIMSS surveys
were nontrivial. Here are the countries with an absolute difference on the math
test of d ≥ 0.20 on either the PISA or the TIMSS surveys:
Male advantage
Honduras (–0.31)
Austria (–0.29)
Ghana (–0.28)
Argentina (–0.24)
Costa Rica (–0.24)
Tunisia (–0.22)
Chile (–0.22)
Lebanon (–0.22)
Italy (–0.21)
Ireland (–0.21)
Female advantage
Oman (+0.60)
Bahrain (+0.44)
Jordan (+0.29)
Thailand (+0.21)
The greatest female advantage was in Oman, ranked 104 out of 134 countries
on a combined index of gender egality. Jordan was ranked 123rd, Bahrain 86th,
and Thailand 60th. Meanwhile, the countries with a male advantage were evenly
split among nations in the top and bottom half of the rankings. This explains the
weak correlations between the index of gender egality and the effect size on the
math test: just –.17 for the PISA dataset and –.05 for the TIMSS dataset.
Now for the science test, again showing the countries with an absolute
difference of d ≥ 0.20.
Male advantage
Ghana (–0.27)
Honduras (–0.26)
Costa Rica (–0.26)
Tunisia (–0.25)
New Zealand (–0.24)
Hungary (–0.22)
Chile (–0.21)
Italy (–0.20)
Female advantage
Jordan (+0.47)
Albania (+0.31)
United Arab Emirates (+0.25)
Qatar (+0.23)
Trinidad (+0.23)
Finland (+0.21)
Algeria (+0.20)
Countries far down the list on the egality index—Jordan (123rd), Qatar
(102nd), United Arab Emirates (78th)—were associated with a female advantage
on science, while two of the countries where males had an advantage were well
into the upper half—New Zealand (16th) and Italy (28th). The correlation of the
egality index with the effect size in science was –.31 in the PISA dataset and –.22
in the TIMSS dataset.
67. Author’s analysis of the 2015 PISA results.
68. Lippa, Collaer, and Peters (2010): 993.
69. Lippa, Collaer, and Peters (2010): 993.
70. The problems in interpreting the Lippa findings for personality traits (see note 37
for chapter 2) were less problematic for interpreting the results for visuospatial
skills. It remains true that the test was effectively restricted to English speakers,
but the instructions for completing the visuospatial questions were insensitive to
level of English ability (unlike questions about personality that used vocabulary
with subtle distinctions in meaning).
71. Gur and Gur (2017): Fig. 2.
72. Roalf, Gur, Ruparel et al. (2014).
73. Roalf, Gur, Ruparel et al. (2014).
74. Gur and Gur (2017): 191. The references are Linn and Peterson (1985); Thomas
and French (1985); Voyer, Voyer, and Bryden (1995); Halpern, Benbow, Geary et
al. (2007); Williams, Mathersul, Palmer et al. (2008); Hines (2010); and Moreno-
Briseño, Diaz, Campos-Romo et al. (2010).
75. Boone, Gong, and Hegarty (2018).
76. Men and women perform equally on many navigational tasks, but Nazareth,
Huang, Voyer et al. (2019), a meta-analysis of human navigation literature
covering 694 effect sizes from 266 studies, found an overall d of –.34 to –.38
(favoring males).
77. Johnson and Bouchard (2007). See also Johnson and Bouchard (2005).
78. Johnson and Bouchard (2007): 24.
79. By using factor analysis and regression analysis in tandem, Johnson and Bouchard
were able to calculate residual effect sizes. Johnson/Bouchard’s hypothesis about
different toolboxes posited two conditions: First, g makes use of a problem-solving
toolbox that differs from individual to individual. Second, the overall usefulness of
the tools and skill in their use are evenly distributed between men and women. “In
the presence of these conditions,” the authors wrote, “g should tend to mask sex
differences in the specialized tools that contribute to more specialized abilities.
Thus, its removal from the scores on a battery of tests through statistical
regression should reveal greater sex differences in the residual scores than in the
original full scores, and the sex differences in the scores on the residual factor
scores should also be larger than commonly observed sex differences in mental
ability test scores.” They also hypothesized that, given these conditions, it would
be possible to understand more clearly the dimensions on which cognitive abilities
tend to differ between men and women—that is, differences either in the tools
that tend to be in their boxes or the ways they use them, or both. Johnson and
Bouchard (2007): 25.
80. The exceptions were picture arrangement (p < .009) and WAIS information (p <
.002).
4: Sex Differences in Educational and Vocational Choices
1. In the United States, males account for about 80 percent of arrests for violent
crime. Federal Bureau of Investigation, Uniform Crime Report for 2017: Table
33. For broader evidence on predominantly male antisocial behavior, see
Heidensohn and Silvestri (2012) and Del Giudice (2015).
2. Lubinski, Benbow, and Kell (2014): Figs. 4–5. The numbers for the effect sizes
depicted in the bar chart were provided by David Lubinski, personal
communication.
3. None of the statements in quotes with which respondents agreed or disagreed
reached an effect size of +0.35 for Cohort 2. Lubinski, Benbow, and Kell (2014):
Fig. 5.
4. There were also questions about working no more than 50 and 60 hours a week,
which women also answered affirmatively more than men (effect sizes were
+0.53 and +0.44 respectively).
5. “IQs of about 140 or higher” is an estimate, since the SMPY youngsters weren’t
given IQ tests. The cutoff for percentile 99.5 for full-scale IQ tests, which are
normed to a mean of 100 and a standard deviation of 15, is 139.
6. A student could qualify for SMPY by getting an SAT verbal score of at least 430
regardless of SAT math score, but all of the students chosen for the follow-up had
SAT math scores of at least 390, putting them in the top percentile on math
among 7th graders. Lubinski, Benbow, Shea et al. (2001): 310.
7. A caveat: SMPY students who were toward the bottom of the top percentile in
math (equivalent to an IQ of 135) might have struggled with a mathematics or
physics major at a demanding school like MIT or Caltech. But that’s a pretty
small caveat.
8. Cohort 1 was recruited in 1972–74 (n = 2,188) from those who scored in the top
1 percent on the SAT math. Beginning with the second wave of Cohort 1 and
continuing for the rest of the cohorts, students could qualify via either the SAT
math or the SAT verbal. Technically, a student with an extremely high verbal
score could be selected without being in the top 1 percent on the SAT math. In
practice, almost all of those in Cohorts 2 and 3 who qualified via the SAT verbal
were in the top 1 percent on math as well. Cohort 2 was recruited in 1976–79 (n
= 778) from the top 0.5 percent. Cohort 3 was recruited in 1980–83 (n =501)
from the top 0.01 percent. Cohort 4 was recruited in 1992–97 (n =1,130) and
consisted of students who were in the top 3 percent of students in academic
ability, with a large majority qualifying for the top 0.5 percent. Cohort 5, a form
of control group, was recruited in 1992 (n = 714) from graduate students ages 23–
25 enrolled in a STEM field at the 15 top-ranked graduate programs in
engineering, math, or science. Lubinski and Benbow (2006): Table 1.
Full disclosure: One of my daughters was part of the Talent Search program
that generated the SMPY (though not part of any of the follow-up cohorts) in the
late 1980s. My description of SMPY parents in the text matches the way her
parents were proud of her math talent and urged her to consider STEM fields.
She listened attentively. She reached Harvard in the early 1990s while Richard
Herrnstein and I were working on The Bell Curve. Herrnstein, who had become
her friend, urged her to major in applied math. She listened attentively. And
decided on Renaissance history and literature. Why? “It’s complicated,” she says.
9. Raymond and Benbow (1986): 816.
10. The slogan was made famous by Steinem, but she confirmed in a letter to Time
magazine (September 16, 2000) that the saying was originated in 1970 by Irina
Dunn, an Australian educator.
11. Twenty-five percent of the men and 29 percent of the women had stopped at the
bachelor’s degree. The same proportion (32 percent) of men and women had
completed master’s degrees. Forty percent of the men and 38 percent of the
women had completed PhDs.
12. Almost half (46 percent) of the Cohort 2 of SMPY women got their degrees in
STEM fields, nearly twice the proportion among all female undergraduates during
1986–89 (the years when Cohort 2 students graduated from college). Lubinski
and Benbow (2006): Table 2; Digest of Education Statistics: Online tables
supplementing section 322. The categories classified as STEM in the Digest of
Education Statistics tables were mathematics, engineering, architecture, computer
science, physical sciences, biology, and health.
13. Lubinski and Benbow (2006): Table 2. The statistic for the general population is
based on college majors for all American undergraduates during 1986–89. Digest
of Education Statistics: Online tables supplementing section 322, downloadable at
nces.ed.gov/programs/digest.
14. Lubinski and Benbow (2006): Table 2.
15. A technical literature exists on this topic. It goes under the label of “expectancy-
value theory.” Eccles (1983).
16. Lubinski and Benbow (2006).
17. E.g., Eccles, Vida, and Barber (2004).
18. Humphreys, Lubinski, and Yao (1993).
19. A total of 563 out of the 778 members of Cohort 2 completed two subtests of the
Differential Aptitude Tests (DAT): Mechanical Reasoning and Space Relations.
Shea, Lubinski, and Benbow (2001).
20. Shea, Lubinski, and Benbow (2001): Fig. 3.
21. Lubinski, Webb, Morelock et al. (2001). The male-female ratio in Cohort 3 was
11.2. This is not the result of randomized testing of a nationally representative
sample, but of a talent search that may have been unrepresentative for a variety of
reasons. But there is also no reason to think that the search was drastically tilted in
favor of boys. It represents evidence for a large male-female disproportion at the
extreme right-hand tail of the IQ distribution, but 11.2 should be treated as a
ballpark figure.
22. Lubinski, Webb, Morelock et al. (2001).
23. More precisely: For math, engineering, computer science, and the physical
sciences, the male-to-female ratio for Cohort 2 was 1.88. For biology, health, and
medicine, the female-to-male ratio was 1.84. The disparity in the most Things-
oriented STEM fields was far greater yet for PhDs and professional degrees.
Among the men who got PhDs, 42 percent got them in the most Things-oriented
STEM disciplines, compared to 7 percent of the women—a ratio of 6.0. But the
disparity reversed for the life sciences. Among SMPY men who got either a PhD
or a professional degree, 23 percent got it in either medicine or biology. For
women, the comparable statistic was 36 percent. Lubinski and Benbow (2006):
Table 2.
24. The male-to-female ratio of young women in Cohort 3 who got undergraduate
degrees in the most Things-oriented STEM majors was 1.8, almost identical to the
ratio of 1.9 for Cohort 2. Meanwhile, the female-to-male ratio in the life sciences
for Cohort 3 was 3.7, double the 1.8 ratio for Cohort 2. Lubinski and Benbow
(2006): Table 2.
25. Data for college-educated women ages 45–49: Author’s analysis, fertility samples
for the CPS, combined 2012 and 2014 surveys. Data for SMPY Cohort 2: David
Lubinski, personal communication.
26. Lubinski, Benbow, and Kell (2014): 2224.
27. Diener, Emmons, and Griffin (1985); Diener, Wirtz, Tov et al. (2010).
28. The SMPY women were fractionally lower than the men on satisfaction with their
success in their professional career but fractionally higher regarding the current
direction of their professional career. The women were also fractionally higher
than the men on their psychological flourishing, positive feelings, and overall
satisfaction with life. The men and women were equally satisfied with their
relationships. Lubinski, Benbow, and Kell (2014): Fig. 7.
29. Lubinski, Benbow, and Kell (2014): 2229.
30. Lubinski and Benbow (2006): 316.
31. Wang, Eccles, and Kenny (2013).
32. Valla and Ceci (2014): 220.
33. The wording is adapted from Hakim (2002): 433–34.
34. Katharine Graham broke that barrier by becoming CEO of the Washington Post’s
parent company upon the death of her husband.
35. Voyer and Voyer (2014).
36. Author’s analysis, CPS. The trendline in bachelor’s degrees is remarkable not
only for the steep upward climb in women’s degrees that had yet to level off as of
2015 but also for a sudden turnaround for men, from a steep increase through
1973 to the beginning of a long secular decline in 1975. The advent of the drop is
not an artifact of a drop in the population of men eligible for college (defined as
ages 18–23). The number in that age cohort increased slightly through 1983. And
although it decreased from 1983 to 1993, it is hard to blame the drop on a
shortage of males when the number of women getting BAs continued to increase
during the same period. Were women crowding out men? It might have been true
for private colleges that have unchanging undergraduate enrollments, but
undergraduate enrollment in public universities is more flexible, and new schools
continued to open throughout the period in question.
37. The male decline in graduate programs mirrors a similar phenomenon in male
undergraduate enrollment, but it was proportionately larger and lasted even longer
—30 years—than among undergraduates. In part, this may represent a crowding-
out effect. Many graduate programs are relatively inflexible in size, and schools
everywhere were eager to increase the number of women both for ideological
reasons and in response to the passage in 1972 of Title IX of the Education
Amendments, which prohibited discrimination by sex in any school receiving
federal funds. But while crowding out may explain part of the change in the male
trendline, this remarkable development is a rich subject for study.
38. For an account of the magnitude of Holland’s influence, see Nauta (2010).
39. Holland (1959): 35.
40. Wording for the six categories is taken from the technical manual for a widely
used RIASEC test, UNIACT: ACT (2009).
41. Prediger (1982). The People-Things and Data-Ideas dimensions have worked as
tools for vocational counseling, but there is continuing debate from a statistical
standpoint about whether they should be conceived as bipolar dimensions. See
Tay, Su, and Rounds (2011).
42. I took this version of the hexagon from the manual describing ACT’s version of
Holland’s Vocational Preference Inventory with the labels that ACT prefers.
Holland’s own labels are in parentheses. Holland (1977).
43. Holland’s Vocational Preference Inventory does not predict actual majors and
occupations well—too many competing considerations can override preferences.
Su (2018).
44. The effect size was +0.10, with women slightly closer than men to the Data end
of the spectrum. This might seem surprising because the word data is so closely
associated with the kinds of analysis done in STEM fields, but that’s the result of
semantics. The research chemist may do extensive analysis of data, but typically
for the purpose of testing a hypothesis grounded in theory—Ideas. Successful real
estate agents are good with people, but their work is grounded in numbers—Data.
45. The O*NET database can be accessed at www.onetcenter.org. In the O*NET
system, a job is classified according to the orientation that has the highest rating.
46. The Su study’s effect sizes showed the biggest sex differences in vocational
interests favoring men to be (in order from high to low) mechanical and electronic
repairers, engineering technicians, engineers, physical scientists, computer
scientists, and mathematicians. From 2014 to 2018, among employed Americans
ages 25–54 with BAs, the biggest ratios favoring males were, in the same
descending order, mechanical and electronic repairers, engineers, computer
scientists, engineering technicians, applied mathematicians, and physical scientists.
The Su study’s only three effect sizes favoring women were, in descending order,
medical services (primarily nurses and other assistants to physicians and dentists),
social scientists, and medical scientists. For employed Americans, the ratios
favoring women were, in descending order, medical services, social scientists, and
medical scientists. Overall the correlation of sex differences in vocational interests
and employment ratios for 12 STEM job categories was +.79. Su and Rounds
(2015): Table 4; author’s analysis, Current Population Survey combined for the
2014–18 surveys.
The ratios take into account sex differences in the total number of employed
people. Rather than using the raw numbers of employed males and females for
calculating the ratio, I use the proportions of employed males and females—e.g.,
the percentage of employed males who are engineers divided by the percentage of
employed females who are engineers.
47. The first column shows a meta-analysis of more than half a million scores on
interests. The second column shows the scores of the exceptionally talented
members of the four SMPY samples. The third column shows the RIASEC
ratings for the jobs actually held by Americans in the combined American
Community Surveys of 2011–15, consisting of a cross section of American adults
based on a sample of more than five million. The first two columns use the same
type of measures for two widely divergent populations. The third column uses a
different measure (scores for occupations instead of scores for interests). The
only cells that show a notable discrepancy are the Enterprising and Artistic cells
for the SMPY sample, in which the sex differences were larger than for either of
the two results based on the general population. For that matter, note that the
effect sizes for all six RIASEC dimensions were largest for the SMPY sample.
Men and women who are exceptionally intellectually talented have greater sex
differences on this topic than do men and women in the population as a whole.
48. The percentages are based on professional and academic majors. These consist of
agriculture, architecture, behavioral sciences, biology, business,
communications/journalism, computer science, education, engineering,
humanities, health sciences, mathematics, physical sciences, public administration,
and social sciences. The numbers are drawn from the relevant table in the Digest
of Education Statistics published annually by the National Center for Education
Statistics.
49. I limit the discussion to descriptive statistics. For a multivariate examination of
these issues see Lippa, Preston, and Penner (2014), which examined employment
in 60 specific jobs from 1972 to 2010. The study analyzed two issues. One was
the extent to which the best jobs go to men, with women excluded or hindered
from access to high-status jobs. On this score, the news was good. The link
between job status and occupational sex segregation as of 2010 was weak, with
women entering high-status occupations in large numbers. Furthermore, the link
had been weakening since 1972.
The same study also explored trends in the People-Things orientation that
accounted for so much of the sex segregation in occupations. In this regard, they
found that little had changed: “Thus, one factor—job status—has led to a
reduction in occupational sex segregation over the past 40 years (i.e., increasing
numbers of women have entered many formerly male-dominated high-status
occupations), whereas another factor—jobs’ people-things orientation—has
served to maintain occupational sex segregation (women continue to be found
more in people-oriented than in things-oriented occupations at all job status
levels).” Lippa, Preston, and Penner (2014): 8. Both models also revealed an
increase over time in the probability that women were employed in people-
oriented jobs, but the statistic in question did not reach statistical significance.
(Tables 2 and 3).
50. The data files may be found and downloaded at www.onetonline.org.
51. The following table gives an overview of the types of jobs that fell into each
category in the CPS over the period 1971–2015. The percentages refer to the
number of people in jobs in that category divided by the total number of people in
jobs classified as People or Things respectively.
Source: Author’s analysis, CPS 1970–2015. “Procedural health care” refers to occupations such as
surgeon, pathologist, radiologist, health technician, or low-skill hospital service staff, in contrast to
health care occupations that center on direct delivery through personal interaction between health care
worker and patient.
Annie Murphy Paul, “Not from Venus, Not from Mars: What We Believe
About Gender and Why It’s Often Wrong,” New York Times, February 23,
2017, nytimes.com/2017/02/23/books/review/testosterone-rex-myths-of-sex-
science-and-society-cordelia-fine.html.
Antonia Macaro, “Testosterone Rex by Cordelia Fine—Men, Women and
Myths,” Financial Times, February 17, 2017, ft.com/content/946956e6-f2df-
11e6-95ee-f14e55513608.
Sarah Ditum, “Testosterone Rex by Cordelia Fine Review—The Question
of Men’s and Women’s Brains,” Guardian, January 18, 2017,
www.theguardian.com/books/2017/jan/18/testosterone-rex-review-cordelia-
fine.
Sheri Berenbaum, “A Spirited Polemic Takes Aim at Biological Sex
Differences but Misses Opportunities to Highlight Relevant Science, Science
blog Books, Et Al., January 18, 2017,
blogs.sciencemag.org/books/2017/01/18/723/.
Rachel Cooke, “The Gendered Brain by Gina Rippon Review—
Demolition of a Sexist Myth,” Guardian, March 5, 2019,
www.theguardian.com/books/2019/mar/05/the-gendered-brain-gina-rippon-
review.
The view that humans comprise only two types of beings, women and men, a
framework that is sometimes referred to as the “gender binary,” played a
profound role in shaping the history of psychological science. In recent years,
serious challenges to the gender binary have arisen from both academic
research and social activism. This review describes 5 sets of empirical
findings, spanning multiple disciplines, that fundamentally undermine the
gender binary. These sources of evidence include neuroscience findings that
refute sexual dimorphism of the human brain; behavioral neuroendocrinology
findings that challenge the notion of genetically fixed, nonoverlapping,
sexually dimorphic hormonal systems; psychological findings that highlight the
similarities between men and women; psychological research on transgender
and nonbinary individuals’ identities and experiences; and developmental
research suggesting that the tendency to view gender/sex as a meaningful,
binary category is culturally determined and malleable. Costs associated with
reliance on the gender binary and recommendations for future research, as
well as clinical practice, are outlined. (Hyde, Joel, Bigler et al. (2018): 171).
Several considerations suggest that this cannot be the whole explanation. For
one thing, the Black/White differential in test scores is not eliminated when
groups or individuals are matched for SES. Moreover, the data reviewed in
Section 4 suggest that if we exclude extreme conditions, nutrition and other
biological factors that may vary with SES account for relatively little of the
variance in such scores. Finally, the (relatively weak) relationship between test
scores and income is much more complex than a simple SES hypothesis
would suggest. The living conditions of children result in part from the
accomplishments of their parents: If the skills measured by psychometric tests
actually matter for those accomplishments, intelligence is affecting SES rather
than the other way around. We do not know the magnitude of these various
effects in various populations, but it is clear that no model in which “SES”
directly determines “IQ” will do. (Neisser, Boodoo, Bouchard et al. (1996):
94).
Another obvious way to discount the value of adjusting for IQ is that the tests
are biased against blacks. This is the Task Force’s statement regarding cultural
bias because of language:
The language of testing is a standard form of English with which some Blacks
may not be familiar; specific vocabulary items are often unfamiliar to Black
children; the tests are often given by White examiners rather than by more
familiar Black teachers; African Americans may not be motivated to work
hard on tests that so clearly reflect White values; the time demands of some
tests may be alien to Black culture. (Similar suggestions have been made in
connection with the test performance of Hispanic Americans.) Many of these
suggestions are plausible, and such mechanisms may play a role in particular
cases. Controlled studies have shown, however, that none of them contributes
substantially to the Black/White differential under discussion here. Moreover,
efforts to devise reliable and valid tests that would minimize disadvantages of
this kind have been unsuccessful. (Neisser, Boodoo, Bouchard et al. (1996):
93–94).
With regard to cultural bias in predictive validity, the Task Force wrote:
Postdating the Task Force’s report, Fagan and Holland (2007) presented
experimental evidence that score differences between black and white students
were effectively eliminated when they were tested on the basis of newly learned
information, and argued that the black/white difference was the result of
differences in specific previous knowledge, which in turn reflected test bias. A
similar strategy was also used in the Siena Reasoning Test. Goldstein (2008);
Scherbaum, Hanges, Yusko et al. (2012). The problem with such tests is that
answering these kinds of questions relies in part on short-term memory, a much
less g-loaded cognitive skill than those captured by other test batteries. Michael
McDaniel analyzed the Siena Reasoning Test data (he did not have access to the
data necessary to analyze the Fagan test) and found that the “findings are
consistent with the inference that the reported lower mean racial differences in the
Siena Reasoning Test are due to its lower g saturation relative to other g tests. If
this inference is correct, one could also infer that the apparent lower g saturation
of the Siena Reasoning Test would be associated with lower validity and larger
prediction errors.” McDaniel and Kepes (2014): 339. In a 2018 presentation to the
Personnel Testing Council of Metropolitan Washington based on his research
conducted for the U.S. Army to evaluate alternative g tests, McDaniel
summarized “Ways to build a g test with low mean group differences” as “1. Use
easy items in the test. 2. Use items with low g saturation in the test. 3. Reduce the
reliability of the test so it measures g less well.” McDaniel (2018): 7.
Suppose you posit a broader role for bias, one that cannot be captured by
assessments of language and predictive validity. Call it the “background radiation”
theory of racism’s effect on IQ. This position holds that the United States is so
steeped in the conditions that produce the B/W difference that it affects every
performance measure, not just IQ scores. If this position is true, it is useless to
look for evidence of test bias. We have no criterion measure that is independent of
this culture and its history. The bias pervades everything.
If you take that position, I can’t argue you out of it with data. None can
conceivably exist. But you should understand the implications of that position.
The background radiation hypothesis implies that the performance yardsticks in
our society are not only biased but so similar in the degree to which they distort
the truth—in every type of educational institution from kindergarten through
graduate school, at every level of every occupation, for every performance
measure—that no differential distortion is picked up by the data. Is this plausible?
Everyday experience suggests that the environment confronting blacks in different
sectors of American life is not uniformly hostile. Assuming that the background
radiation hypothesis is true represents a considerably longer leap of faith than the
limited assumption that racism is still a factor in American life.
5. Source: the Census Bureau’s 2018 Annual Social and Economic Supplement of
the Current Population Survey, hereafter referred to as CPS-2018. The data were
downloaded from cps.ipums.org. The numbers for sex differences in educational
attainment refer to persons ages 25–54 after applying the CPS sample weights.
The means for highest grade completed in 2018 were 14.5 for women and 14.1
for men. Women have had a higher mean every year from 1997 through 2018.
The means for the percentages of persons with college degrees in 2018 were 41.0
percent for women and 35.7 percent for men. Women have had a higher
percentage than men every year from 2003 through 2018.
The sources for analyses that control for IQ are the 1979 and 1997 cohorts of
the National Longitudinal Survey of Youth, hereafter referred to as NLSY79 and
NLSY97. The surveys are sponsored by the Bureau of Labor Statistics of the
U.S. Department of Labor. Data were downloaded from the NLS Investigator
(nlsinfo.org/investigator/pages/search.jsp). They represent two of the handful of
large American datasets that have a full-scale measure of cognitive ability and a
long follow-up period, combined with detailed data on education, marital status,
fertility, income, and labor market experience. The application of sample weights
permits nationally representative estimates.
The measure of cognitive ability is the score on the Armed Forces
Qualification Test (AFQT). For a detailed description of the NLSY79, see
Herrnstein and Murray (1994): Appendix 2. For a detailed discussion of technical
issues regarding the AFQT as a measure of IQ, see Herrnstein and Murray
(1994): Appendix 3. The short story is that the AFQT is one of the most highly g-
loaded paper-and-pencil tests. By way of comparison, the median factor g-loading
for the subtests of the AFQT is .85, compared to a median of .69 for the subtests
of the most widely used IQ test for adults, the Wechsler Adult Intelligence Scale
(WAIS). The first factor, g, accounts for over 70 percent of the variance in the
AFQT compared to 53 percent in the WAIS. Herrnstein and Murray (1994): 607.
AFQT scores were normalized by year of age at testing and converted to the IQ
metric, with a range of 55–145. They are hereafter referred to as IQ scores.
The analyses adjusting for IQ are ordinary least squares regressions for years
of education and earned income, and logit analyses for the probability of getting a
college degree. All of the analyses were replicated with and without interaction
terms. Few of the interaction terms even approached statistical significance, and
the fitted values for the analyses including interaction terms were extremely close
to the fitted values for those that were restricted to main effects. I therefore report
the analyses based on main effects.
To facilitate comparisons of the results for the two NLSY cohorts, I limited
the samples to comparable age ranges at the date of the follow-up I report. At the
date of the most recent interview for the NLSY97 in 2015, 99 percent of the
cohort were ages 30–35, with a small number (69) who were 36. The sample for
analysis was limited to ages 30–35. I selected 1994 as the follow-up survey for the
NLSY79 cohort and limited the analysis for both cohorts to those who were ages
30–35 on the date of the interview (the NLSY79 cohort was chosen from a wider
range of birth years, 1957–64, than the NLSY97 cohort, who were born from
1980 to 1984). Income figures for both cohorts were converted to 2018 dollars.
The table below shows results for years of education and percentage of
persons with a college degree for both of the NLSY cohorts. For both indicators,
the dependent variable was regressed on IQ and a binary variable denoting sex.
The first table shows the fitted values for years of education when IQ is set to 80,
100, and 120, which correspond approximately to the 10th, 50th, and 90th
percentiles of IQ in a normal distribution.
IQ: 100
Men: 13.3
Women: 13.6
IQ: 120
Men: 15.3
Women: 15.5
IQ: 100
Men: 13.9
Women: 14.6
IQ: 120
Men: 16.1
Women: 16.8
Females had higher values for years of education than males for every IQ
category in both NLSY samples. Consistent with the story for sex differences in
educational attainment in chapter 4, the female advantage in fitted values for years
of education is greater for the NLSY97, whose members were born in 1980–84,
than for the NLSY79, whose members were born in 1957–64.
The next table shows the results for achievement of a college degree. Since
college degrees are rare among people with measured IQs of less than 100, I show
the results for fitted values of IQ set to 100, 110, and 120.
IQ: 100
Men: 15%
Women: 19%
IQ: 110
Men: 35%
Women: 42%
IQ: 120
Men: 61%
Women: 68%
IQ: 100
Men: 24%
Women: 35%
IQ: 110
Men: 44%
Women: 57%
IQ: 120
Men: 66%
Women: 77%
Women had an advantage for all three fitted values in both cohorts. As in the
case of years of education, the female advantage increased from the NLSY79
cohort to the NLSY97 cohort.
6. Since 2003, the Census Bureau has used a set of options for self-identified
ethnicity that permits combinations of two or three ethnicities. The numbers that
follow are based on those who self-identified as white only, black only, or Asian
only, and also reported that they were not Latino. The Latino number is based on
all those who self-identified with a specific Latino population (e.g., Puerto Rican,
Cuban, Chicano, Mexican American), regardless of their self-identified race. Mean
years of education for 2018 are shown below:
CPS 2018
White
Years of education: 14.8
College degree: 44.1%
Black
Years of education: 14.1
College degree: 28.3%
Latino
Years of education: 12.6
College degree: 19.4%
Asian
Years of education: 15.4
College degree: 64.6%
Other
Years of education: 14.2
College degree: 28.8%
Before adjusting for IQ, Asians have advantages in both years of education
and the percentage with college degrees.
7. The table below shows IQ by ethnicity for the two cohorts of the NLSY and, to
demonstrate how typical these results are, ethnic means for the three
standardizations of the WAIS over the last 40 years. Asians are not reported for
NLSY79 because that survey was limited to whites, blacks, and Latinos. The
ethnic designations for NLSY79 use the Sample ID variable (variable no.
R0173600). The ethnic designations for NLSY97 combine information from the
Key!Race and Key!Race_Ethnicity variables (nos. R538700 and R1482600) and
follow the pattern for the CPS: non-Latino whites, blacks, and Asians; and
Latinos of any self-identified race.
Mean IQ by ethnicity
NLSY (1979)
White: 103.1
Black: 86.7
Latino: 90.5
NLSY (1997)
White: 103.2
Black: 89.6
Latino: 94.0
Asian: 105.9
WAIS-R (1981)
White: 101.4
Black: 86.9
WAIS-III (1995)
White: 101.4
Black: 86.8
WAIS-IV (2008)
White: 103.2
Black: 88.7
Latino: 91.6
Asian: 106.1
Sources: Reynolds, Chastain, Kaufman et al. (1987): Table 1; Dickens and Flynn (2006): Supplemental
data provided by the authors.
The table below shows the results, expressed in years of education, when the
number of years of education is regressed on IQ and ethnicity. The sample was
limited to persons whose age at the most recent measure of years of education
was 30 or above.
IQ: 80
White: 11.0
Black: 12.0
Latino: 11.2
IQ: 100
White: 13.2
Black: 14.2
Latino: 13.4
IQ: 120
White: 15.4
Black: 16.4
Latino: 15.6
IQ: 80
White:11.7
Black: 12.3
Latino: 11.8
Asian: 12.9
IQ: 100
White:14.0
Black: 14.6
Latino: 14.2
Asian: 15.2
IQ: 120
White:16.4
Black: 17.0
Latino: 16.5
Asian: 17.6
For the NLSY79, blacks had an advantage of 1.1 years of education over
whites after adjusting for IQ, and Latinos had an advantage of 0.2 years over
whites. For the NLSY97, the black advantage was 0.6 years of education and the
Latino advantage was 0.1 years.
The next table shows the results of a logit regression of achievement of a
college degree (yes or no) on the same independent variables. The table shows the
percentages of each group obtaining a college degree. The fitted values of IQ
shown in the table are 100, 110, and 120, corresponding approximately to the
50th, 75th, and 90th percentiles.
IQ: 100
White: 15%
Black: 26%
Latino: 13%
IQ: 110
White: 36%
Black: 53%
Latino: 33%
IQ: 120
White: 65%
Black: 78%
Latino: 61%
IQ: 80
White: 28%
Black: 34%
Latino: 26%
Asian: 54%
IQ: 100
White: 49%
Black: 56%
Latino: 47%
Asian: 75%
IQ: 120
White: 71%
Black: 76%
Latino: 69%
Asian: 88%
Blacks got more college degrees than whites in both of the NLSY cohorts for
comparable IQs. So did Asians in the NLSY97. Latinos and whites with
comparable IQs have close to the same percentage of college graduates in both
NLSY cohorts, with a slight advantage for whites.
8. The indispensable source for understanding the nature of the remaining male-
female income disparities is Goldin (2014). I limit this presentation to the basics
provided by the CPS and the NLSY. The table below shows median earned
income (combined wages or salary, income from business, income from farm)
from the 2018 CPS for men and women ages 25–54 with various combinations of
marital status, children in the home, and labor force status. The results use the
CPS sample weights for persons.
CPS 2018
Unmarried women without children. The cohort of women in their early 30s
in 1994 earned as much as men at comparable IQ levels. For the cohort of
women in their early 30s in 2015, that held true for high-IQ women. Judging from
these results, there was a meaningful male advantage only for quite low levels of
IQ (e.g., the fitted value for earned income when IQ was set at 80 was 87 percent
of income for unmarried males with no children in the home).
Married women with at least one child in the home. Compare the earned
income for unmarried and married women. Married women in the labor force
earned noticeably less than unmarried women. But the larger factor that drove
down the ratio of female to male earnings was that married men earned much
more than unmarried men.
Family income. I show family income in addition to earned income to make a
point that will come as no surprise. Married women with children are, on average,
much more prosperous than unmarried women at comparable IQ levels. For the
NLS79 cohort, married women with children had more than double the fitted
family income of unmarried women without children (115 percent). That marriage
premium had dropped for the NLSY97 cohort but was still a substantial 49
percent.
10. The raw differences in earned income in the 2018 CPS are shown for two groups:
those who were in the labor force at the time of the interview (not necessarily
employed) and those who reported working for 52 weeks at 40 hours per week
during the year.
White
In the labor force: $48
Employed full-time year-round: $50
Black
In the labor force: $35
Employed full-time year-round: $40
Latino
In the labor force: $30
Employed full-time year-round: $35
Asian
In the labor force: $54
Employed full-time year-round: $65
The ethnic differences are substantial, with fully employed blacks and Latinos
earning only 80 percent and 70 percent of the white median respectively. Fully
employed Asians made 30 percent more than the white median.
11. The next table shows the fitted values of earned income expressed in 2018 dollars
for IQ set at 80, 100, and 120 for the two cohorts of the NLSY. Logged earned
income was regressed on IQ and ethnicity. The sample was limited to persons
ages 30–35 who reported being in the labor force (though not necessarily
employed) throughout the previous calendar year and reported working at least
one hour.
IQ: 80
White: $28,632
Black: $28,519
Latino: $26,973
IQ: 100
White: $40,514
Black: $40,355
Latino: $38,166
IQ: 120
White: $57,327
Black: $57,101
Latino: $54,005
IQ: 80
White: $29,883
Black: $25,144
Latino: $30,596
Asian: $46,975
IQ: 100
White: $40,584
Black: $34,147
Latino: $41,553
Asian: $63,796
IQ: 120
White: $55,117
Black: $46,375
Latino: $56,432
Asian: $86,641
For NLSY79, blacks and whites with comparable IQs had effectively identical
fitted earned incomes, with Latinos only fractionally behind. For NLSY97, blacks
had a fitted mean that was 84 percent of the white mean, Latinos and whites were
effectively equal, and the fitted Asian mean was 57 percent higher than the white
mean.
10: A Framework for Thinking About Heritability and Class
1. See Horowitz, Haynor, and Kickham (2018) for a survey of the ideological
positions of 479 sociologists in U.S. colleges and universities.
2. For exceptions, see Moore and Shenk (2017) and Burt and Simons (2014).
3. Galton (1869). I am drawing from the account in Herrnstein (1973): chapter 4,
which contains an excellent discussion of the history of scholarship about
heritability of IQ as of the early 1970s.
4. Sewall Wright wrote the classic papers on measuring degrees of relatedness in
1921. For an accessible discussion of them, see Hill (1995).
5. For a nice illustration of correlations on phenotypic outcomes for different degrees
of relatedness, see Cesarini and Visscher (2017): Fig. 1.
6. I adapted this example from Turkheimer, Pettersson, and Horn (2014): 519. “A
heritability coefficient represents the proportion of phenotypic variability that is
associated with variability in genotype. As such, it is an effect size, a variance
ratio, an R2 coefficient; and like any variance ratio it is sensitive to characteristics
of the population in ways that means are not. In particular, variance ratios depend
crucially on the variability of both the predictor and the outcome. For example,
the question, ‘How much of the variance in college performance is explained by
differences in SAT scores?’ has no meaningful answer, other than, ‘It depends on
the variability of SAT scores and other factors at the institutions where the study
is conducted.’” Turkheimer, Pettersson, and Horn (2014): 519.
7. Tucker-Drob, Briley, and Harden (2013).
8. Technically, these influences are obvious potential components of the shared
environment. They do not qualify as part of the shared environment unless they
do in fact make persons raised together more similar. At an anecdotal level,
consider the school that two siblings attend some years apart. It is “shared” in the
sense that both siblings walked into the same building every day. But the siblings
necessarily had different peer groups. Suppose also that the siblings shared none
of the same teachers. Those elements of the school are not shared. There’s no a
priori reason to assume that other elements of the school experience made
“school” meaningfully shared between the two siblings born even a year or two
apart. Now suppose that the solution to the ACE equation for large MZ and DZ
twins’ samples indicates no role for the shared environment and a substantial role
for the nonshared environment. It could well be that the effects of schooling were
real, but they were part of the effect attributed to the nonshared environment.
9. Plomin (2011): Table 1. It is adapted from Rowe and Plomin (1981).
10. Of these, different peer groups appear to be especially important, as documented
by Harris (1998).
11. The 100 percent figure for MZ twins is accurate when rounded to within half a
dozen decimal places. A study of SNPs in 66 adult twins found differences that
amount to one SNP per 1.2 × 10–7 nucleotides—an exceedingly small fraction. Li,
Montpetit, Rousseau et al. (2013). MZ twins can also fail to share 100 percent of
their genes because of rare conditions.
12. DZ twins share only approximately 50 percent because the coin flips that decide
the blocks of DNA donated by the mother and father don’t always produce
exactly equal totals from each.
13. To see the logic, start by thinking about a trait that is 100 percent heritable and
perfectly measured. The correlation of that trait among a sample of MZ twins,
who share 100 percent of their genes, has to converge on +1.0. What is going to
be the correlation among samples of DZ twins who share 50 percent of their
genes? It will just as inevitably converge on +.5. That difference in shared genes
in MZ and DZ twins gives the mathematical leverage for disentangling genes from
the shared environment.
Let’s say that we want to understand the heritability of obsessive-compulsive
disorder. Among a large sample of MZ twins raised together, we find the
correlation of the diagnosis of obsessive-compulsive disorder to be +.53. If one
MZ twin has obsessive-compulsive disorder, the other is much more likely than
chance to exhibit the disorder as well. Next, we assemble a large sample of same-
sex DZ twins raised together and discover that the correlation of their rate of
obsessive-compulsive disorder is +.28. (These percentages are taken from
Polderman, Benyamin, de Leeuw et al. (2015): Supplementary Table 21.) If
obsessive-compulsive disorder were caused entirely by environmental influences,
then the correlations for the samples of MZ and DZ twins would be the same.
The larger correlation for the MZ twins must be caused by their additional shared
genes.
This is a classic example of the distinction between specific people and large
samples. For the sake of argument, assume that it is possible for parenting to
produce obsessive-compulsive disorder. You observe that MZ twins both have
obsessive-compulsive disorder. There is no way to tell whether it came about
through shared genes or shared parents. But if you have 1,000 randomly chosen
pairs of MZ twins and another 1,000 pairs of DZ twins, and you find that twice as
many MZ twins as DZ twins have obsessive-compulsive disorder, then that
difference (with an ascertainable margin of error) can be explained only by their
additional shared genes. There’s no other possibility except that your samples
weren’t really random after all.
The equations for implementing this logic that I give in the text are called the
Falconer formulas after their originator, Douglas Falconer. What I’ve just given
you is the most basic treatment of Falconer’s formulas. Falconer (1960). The
results from the technical literature that I report in chapter 11 are usually based on
fitted models that use more complicated statistics. This is necessary because, apart
from any other reason, the basic ACE model must be elaborated whenever the
correlation among MZ twins is more than twice the correlation among DZ twins—
i.e., whenever solving for Falconer’s equations leads to a negative value for C.
But these refinements generally tweak the results of the basic Falconer formulas
by only a few percentage points.
14. Bouchard, Lykken, McGue et al. (1990). This is the study that you are likely to
have heard about. In fact, the first scientific study of twins goes back to 1937.
Newman, Freeman, and Holzinger (1937).
15. Segal (1999): 117–18.
16. The Minnesota study attracted charges that the heritability measures were
radically too high (e.g., Taylor (1980), Farber (1981)). Bouchard and his
colleagues responded with additional analyses that confirmed their main findings.
See Bouchard (1982) and Bouchard (1983).
17. The three other assumptions are: (1) Either nonadditive genetic effects (D and I)
or shared environmental effects (C) are zero; (2) there are no gene × environment
(G×E) interactions and no gene-environment correlations (rGE); and (3) twins are
representative of the non-twin population. For a discussion specifically of number
3, see Barnes and Boutwell (2013). For general discussion of these assumptions
with additional references, see Verweij, Mosing, Zietsch et al. (2012) and
Appendix A of Barnes, Wright, Boutwell et al. (2014).
18. Genetic assortative mating needs to be discriminated from cultural transmission,
which also tends to inflate the estimate of shared environmental effects. For a
discussion of the assumptions of the classical twin model and an empirical
assessment of assortative mating for intelligence, see Vinkhuyzen, van der Sluis,
Maes et al. (2012).
19. A separate issue is the genome-wide genetic similarity of mates (e.g., see
Domingue, Fletcher, Conley et al. (2014)). Here I am reporting evidence for
phenotypic assortative mating on discrete traits that are known to be substantially
heritable.
20. For citations, see the literature review in Barnes, Wright, Boutwell et al. (2014): 7.
21. Loehlin (1978): 72.
22. LoParo and Waldman (2014): 606.
23. E.g., Fosse, Joseph, and Richardson (2015); Hettema, Neale, and Kendler (1995);
Kaprio, Koskenvuo, and Rose (1990).
24. For citations on each of these outcomes, see LoParo and Waldman (2014): 606–
7. For a comprehensive list of studies of EEA as of 2014, see Barnes, Wright,
Boutwell et al. (2014): Appendix D. The authors summarize the table as follows:
Intelligence test scores are fairly stable during development. When Jones and
Bayley (1941) tested a sample of children annually throughout childhood and
adolescence, for example, scores obtained at age 18 were correlated r = +.77
with scores that had been obtained at age 6 and r = +.89 with scores from age
12. When scores were averaged across several successive tests to remove
short-term fluctuations, the correlations were even higher. The mean for ages
17 and 18 was correlated r = +.86 with the mean for ages 5, 6, and 7, and r =
+.96 with the mean for ages 11, 12, and 13. (Neisser, Boodoo, Bouchard et
al. (1996): 81).
Police
Operational validity of the IQ score: .24
Drivers
Operational validity of the IQ score: .45
Salespeople
Operational validity of the IQ score: .46
Clerical jobs
Operational validity of the IQ score: .54
Engineers
Operational validity of the IQ score: .63
Managers
Operational validity of the IQ score: .67
Computer programmers
Operational validity of the IQ score: .73
1. Choose your EI measure carefully. There are two, distinct definitions of the
term “Emotional Intelligence”: (a) ability to perform emotional tasks, and (b) a
grab-bag of everything that is not cognitive ability. It is critical to distinguish
these two, because measures based on the two EI definitions do not have the
same content, predictive validity, or subgroup differences.
2. Exercise extreme caution when using mixed EI measures. Grab-bag measures
of EI (i.e., self-report mixed measures) appear to exhibit some incremental
validity over cognitive ability and personality measures on average (based on
nine studies), but it is not clear why. As such, use of these measures for
personnel decisions may be difficult to defend, without extensive local
validation.
3. Know that ability EI measures may add little to the selection system. Ability-
based measures of EI (performance-based and self-report) exhibit little
incremental validity over cognitive ability and personality, on average.
4. Base the decision to use an EI measure on the job type (i.e., consider the
emotional labor content of the job). When dealing with high emotional labor
jobs (jobs that require positive emotional displays), all types of EI measures
exhibit meaningful validity and incremental validity over cognitive ability and
personality. In contrast, for low emotional labor jobs, EI validities are weaker
or can even be negative.
5. Be aware of subgroup differences on EI. Although more data are needed,
preliminary evidence suggests that performance-based EI measures favor
women and Whites, which may produce adverse impact against men and
African Americans. (Joseph and Newman (2010): 72).
Grit. Labels can be effective, and “grit” is a great one. It captures a human
quality that we recognize in some people and not in others and it has an obvious
and persuasive relationship to success in all sorts of human endeavors. But grit as
a psychological construct overlaps substantially with one of the Big Five factors,
conscientiousness. There are other psychometric issues as well. Marcus Credé has
published an excellent review of the literature and presentation of the major
issues. He sums up as follows:
For all its intuitive appeal, the grit literature is currently characterized by a
number of serious theoretical and empirical challenges ranging from a lack of
construct validity, discriminant validity, and predictive validity. At present
there is no empirical support for the idea that grit is the combination of
perseverance and passion or for the claim that grit adds to our understanding
of success and performance. Indeed, the best available evidence strongly
suggests that grit is largely a repackaging of conscientiousness—a widely
studied personality trait. If grit is to represent a meaningful contribution to our
understanding of success, researchers should focus on three broad areas.
First, future work will have to pay particularly close attention to whether the
combination of perseverance and passion into a single construct can be
theoretically or empirically justified or whether the two facets are best studied
individually. Second, future work should consider whether grit or grit facets
interact with ability to predict success or whether grit facets represent
necessary-but-not-sufficient conditions for success. Third, efforts should be
made to improve the measurement of grit and grit facets because any
empirical investigation of the role of grit requires that grit be measured better
than current scales allow. (Credé (2018): 611).
20. For a systematic discussion of the criteria for establishing that a noncognitive
factor in academic achievement is involved in gene-environment transactions, see
Tucker-Drob and Harden (2017).
21. Gottfredson and Hirschi (1990); Moffitt, Poulton, and Caspi (2013); Moffitt,
Arseneault, Belsky et al. (2011); Duckworth and Carlson (2013).
22. von Stumm, Gale, Batty et al. (2009); Lim, Teo, and Loo (2003); Furnham and
Cheng (2017).
23. Chamorro-Premuzic, Harlaar, Greven et al. (2010); Spinath, Spinath, Harlaar et
al. (2006); Stankov (2013).
24. von Stumm, Hell, and Chamorro-Premuzic (2011).
25. Poropat (2014): Table 2. In addition to Poropat (2014), Shanahan, Bauldry,
Roberts et al. (2014) has an excellent literature review in addition to making its
independent contribution. Important subsequent studies include Lechner, Danner,
and Rammstedt (2017) and Damian, Su, Shanahan et al. (2014).
26. Borghans, ter Weel, and Weinberg (2008).
27. Cheng and Furnham (2012).
28. These facets and the facets for neuroticism are taken from Costa, Terracciano,
and McCrae (2001): Table 2.
29. A fourth study, Borghans, Golsteyn, Heckman et al. (2016), found too late to
include in the main text, reports the independent and joint effects of personality
and IQ on academic outcomes without a measure of childhood SES.
In a sample of 298 from a Dutch high school, conscientiousness explained
more of the variance for grades than any other personality trait or IQ. For scores
on the Differential Aptitude Test, which the authors classified as an achievement
test, IQ was the most important predictor, but openness was also highly significant
(supplemental tables 7.1 and 7.2).
A study of a sample of 8,501 from the British Cohort Study had 11 dependent
variables representing test scores and grades. Locus of control consistently had a
positive effect on test scores while disorganization consistently had a negative
effect. The roles of IQ and the combined personality traits were roughly equal on
five of the dependent variables, while IQ and the combined personality traits each
had a somewhat larger role on three of the remaining dependent variables
(supplemental tables 7.3–7.7).
An analysis of 638 members of the NLSY79 found a dominant role for IQ
over measures of locus of control and self-esteem for scores on the Armed Forces
Qualification Test (which the authors treated as an achievement test) and grades.
On other dependent variables, neither IQ nor the personality inventories explained
more than trivial amounts of the variance (supplemental tables 7.8 and 8.1–8.6).
An analysis of 1,561 members of the National Survey of Midlife Development
(US) found that the Big Five personality traits explained more of the variance than
IQ on dependent variables measuring adult wages, physical health, mental health,
and depression (supplemental tables 8.7–8.11).
30. The Project Talent variables for intelligence, personality traits, and parental SES
were standardized prior to the analysis while the measures of educational
attainment, log of earned income, and occupational prestige were not. The tables
in the article reported unstandardized regression coefficients. I express them in the
table here as quasi effect sizes (the unstandardized regression coefficient divided
by the sample standard deviation) to make them more easily interpretable relative
to the standardized total effects in a structural equation model for the Aberdeen
Birth Cohort, and path coefficients for the British NCDP.
Both the Project Talent and Aberdeen cohort analyses used structural models
that were run five times, once for each of the Big Five factors. The total effects
for childhood IQ and parental SES given in the table represent the median of the
main effects for IQ and parental SES for the five coefficients (which with few
exceptions were within .01 of each other in all five runs).
31. Krapohl, Rimfeld, Shakeshaft et al. (2014): Table S7.
32. Given the results of the bivariate analyses showing the extent to which the
heritability of GCSE scores can be explained by each of the nine predictors
without considering any of the other eight, the contributions of well-being, child-
reported behavior problems, health, and the home environment after controlling
for the other predictors cannot have been more than a percent or so, and those of
personality, parent-reported behavior problems, and the school environment
cannot have been much more than 5 percent. Self-efficacy was the domain that
accounted for perhaps half of the 28 percent explained by eight non-IQ predictors.
Based on the implications of Krapohl, Rimfeld, Shakeshaft et al. (2014): Table
S6.
33. Krapohl, Rimfeld, Shakeshaft et al. (2014): The distribution of loadings in Table
S6 applied to the estimate of the total contribution to phenotypic variance of the
eight domains other than IQ of 28 percent in Table S7.
34. Tucker-Drob, Briley, Engelhardt et al. (2016): 800.
35. These statements are drawn from Tucker-Drob, Briley, Engelhardt et al. (2016):
Figs. 3 and 5. The figures report decomposed standardized path coefficients that
do not lend themselves to intuitive interpretation.
36. The table below is adapted from Sackett, Kuncel, Arneson et al. (2009): Table 4.
The figures for the SAT meta-analysis are corrected for national population range
restriction.
1. Rule out genetic, ecological and cultural inheritance. For studies in mice and
rats, inbred strains and strictly controlled environments need to be used. When
a pregnant female animal is exposed to a specific environmental stimulus, F3
offspring and subsequent generations must be studied in order to exclude a
direct effect of the stimulus on the embryos’ somatic cells and germ cells.
Even more desirable is the use of in vitro fertilization (IVF), embryo transfer
and foster mothers. When a male animal is exposed to an environmental
stimulus, F2 offspring must be studied in order to exclude transient effects on
germ cells. To ensure that any phenotype is exclusively transmitted via
gametes, IVF must be used, controlling for possible artifacts relating to IVF. In
contrast with laboratory animals, it is impossible to rule out ecological and
cultural inheritance in humans, but genetic effects should and can be excluded.
If an epimutation apparently follows Mendelian inheritance patterns, be
cautious: you are more likely looking at a secondary epimutation and genetic
inheritance. Study the haplotype background of the epimutation: if in a given
family it is always on the same haplotype, you are again most likely dealing
with a secondary epimutation. Do whole genome sequencing… to search for a
genetic variant that might have caused the epimutation and be aware that this
variant might be distantly located. Good spots to start looking are the two
neighboring genes, where a mutation might cause transcriptional read-through
in sense or antisense orientation into the locus under investigation.
Unfortunately, if you don’t find anything, you still cannot be 100% sure that a
genetic variant does not exist.
2. Identify the responsible epigenetic factor in the germ cells. Admittedly, this is
easier said than done, especially in female germ cells, which are scarce or
unavailable. Be aware that germ cell preparations may be contaminated with
somatic cells or somatic DNA. Use swim-up (sperm) or micromanipulation
techniques to purify germ cells to the highest purity. Exclude the presence of
somatic cells and somatic DNA by molecular testing, for example by
methylation analysis of imprinted genes, which are fully methylated or fully
unmethylated only in germ cells.
3. Demonstrate that the epigenetic factor in the germ cells is responsible for the
phenotypic effect in the next generation. If possible, remove the factor from
the affected germ cells and demonstrate that the effect is lost. Add the factor
to control germ cells and demonstrate that the effect is gained.… In light of
[the problems of doing such experiments in humans], this might currently be
too much to ask for to prove transgenerational epigenetic inheritance in
humans, but should, nevertheless, be kept in mind and discussed.
ACT. 2009. Act Interest Inventory Technical Manual. Iowa City, IA: ACT.
Aguinis, Herman, Steven A. Culpepper, and Charles A. Pierce. 2016. “Differential
Prediction Generalization in College Admissions Testing.” Journal of Educational
Psychology 108 (7): 1045–59.
Akey, Joshua M. 2009. “Constructing Genomic Maps of Positive Selection in Humans:
Where Do We Go from Here?” Genome Research 19 (5): 711–22.
Alcala, Nicolas, and Noah A. Rosenberg. 2016. “Mathematical Constraints on FST:
Biallelic Markers in Arbitrarily Many Populations.” Genetics 206 (3): 1581–600.
Alcock, John. 2001. The Triumph of Sociobiology. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Alexander, Gerianne M., and Melissa Hines. 2002. “Sex Differences in Response to
Children’s Toys in Nonhuman Primates.” Evolution of Human Behavior 23: 467–
79.
Alexander, Gerianne M., and Teresa Wilcox. 2012. “Sex Differences in Early Infancy.”
Child Development Perspectives 6 (4): 400–406.
Alexander, Gerianne M., Teresa Wilcox, and Rebecca Woods. 2009. “Sex Differences
in Infants’ Visual Interest in Toys.” Archives of Sexual Behavior 38 (23): 427–33.
Allegrini, Andrea, Saskia Selzam, Kaili Rimfeld et al. 2018. “Genomic Prediction of
Cognitive Traits in Childhood and Adolescence.” bioRxiv.
Allen, Timothy A., Amanda R. Rueter, Samantha V. Abram et al. 2017. “Personality
and Neural Correlates of Mentalizing Ability.” European Journal of Personality 31
(6): 599–613.
Al-Shawaf, Laith, David M. G. Lewis, and David M. Buss. 2017. “Sex Differences in
Disgust: Why Are Women More Easily Disgusted Than Men?” Emotion Review 10
(2): 149–60.
American Sociological Association. 2003. The Importance of Collecting Data and
Doing Social Scientific Research on Race. Washington, DC: American Sociological
Association.
Andersen, Margaret L., and Patricia H. Collins, eds. 2019. Race, Class, Gender:
Intersections and Inequalities. 10th ed. Boston: Cengage Learning.
Anderson, Edgar, and G. Ledyard Stebbins. 1954. “Hybridization as an Evolutionary
Stimulus.” Evolution 8: 378–88.
Anderson, Nathaniel E., Keith A. Harenski, Carla L. Harenski et al. 2018. “Machine
Learning of Brain Gray Matter Differentiates Sex in a Large Forensic Sample.”
Human Brain Mapping 40 (5): 1496–506.
Andreano, Joseph M., Bradford C. Dickerson, and Lisa Feldman Barrett. 2014. “Sex
Differences in the Persistence of the Amygdala Response to Negative Material.”
Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience 9: 1388–94.
Angel-Ajani, Asale, and Aldo Civico, eds. 2006. Engaged Observer: Anthropology,
Advocacy, and Activism. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press.
Angrist, Joshua D., Susan M. Dynarski, Thomas J. Kane et al. 2012. “Who Benefits
from KIPP?” Journal of Policy Analysis and Management 31 (4): 837–60.
Arcelus, Jon, Walter Bouman, Wim Van Den Noortgate et al. 2015. “Systematic
Review and Meta-analysis of Prevalence Studies in Transsexualism.” European
Psychiatry 30 (6): 807–15.
Archer, John. 2019. “The Reality and Evolutionary Significance of Human
Psychological Sex Differences.” Biological Reviews. Advance online publication.
Archer, John, and Mani Mehdikhani. 2003. “Variability Among Males in Sexually
Selected Attributes.” Review of General Psychology 7 (3): 219–36.
Ardekani, Babak A., Khadija Figarsky, and John J. Sidtis. 2013. “Sexual Dimorphism
in the Human Corpus Callosum: An MRI Study Using the Oasis Brain Database.”
Cerebral Cortex 23: 2514–20.
Arden, Rosalind, and Robert Plomin. 2006. “Sex Differences in Variance of
Intelligence Across Childhood.” Personality and Individual Differences 41: 39–48.
Argue, Debbie, Denise Donlon, Colin Groves et al. 2006. “Homo Floresiensis:
Microcephalic, Pygmoid, Australopithecus, or Homo?” Journal of Human Evolution
51 (4): 360–74.
Arnett, Anne B., Bruce F. Pennington, Robin L. Peterson et al. 2017. “Explaining the
Sex Difference in Dyslexia.” Journal of Child Psychology and Psychiatry, and
Allied Disciplines 58 (6): 719–27.
Arnold, Arthur P. 2017. “A General Theory of Sexual Differentiation.” Journal of
Neuroscience Research 95 (1–2): 291–300.
Arnold, M. L. 1997. Natural Hybridization and Evolution. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Aronson, Joshua, Carrie B. Fried, and Catherine Good. 2002. “Reducing the Effects of
Stereotype Threat on African American College Students by Shaping Theories of
Intelligence.” Journal of Experimental Social Psychology 38 (2): 113–25.
Arribas-Aguila, David, Francisco J. Abad, and Roberto Colom. 2019. “Testing the
Developmental Theory of Sex Differences in Intelligence Using Latent Modeling:
Evidence from the Tea Ability Battery (Bat-7).” Personality and Individual
Differences 138: 212–18.
Asbury, Kathryn, Theodore D. Wachs, and Robert Plomin. 2005. “Environmental
Moderators of Genetic Influence on Verbal and Nonverbal Abilities in Early
Childhood.” Intelligence 33 (6): 643–61.
Astell, Mary. 1700. Some Reflections upon Marriage. London: John Nutt.
Auer, P. L., and G. Lettre. (2015). “Rare Variant Association Studies: Considerations,
Challenges and Opportunities.” Genome Medicine 7 (1): 16.
Auyeung, B., Aneesha Ahluwalia, L. Thomson et al. 2012. “Prenatal Versus Postnatal
Sex Steroid Hormone Effects on Autistic Traits in Children at 18 to 24 Months of
Age.” Molecular Autism 3 (17): 1–5.
Auyeung, B., S. Baron-Cohen, E. Ashwin et al. 2009. “Fetal Testosterone and Autistic
Traits.” British Journal of Psychology 100 (Pt. 1): 1–22.
Auyeung, B., S. Baron-Cohen, Emma Chapman et al. 2006. “Foetal Testosterone and
the Child Systemizing Quotient.” European Journal of Endocrinology 155: 123–30.
Auyeung, B., R. Knickmeyer, E. Ashwin et al. 2012. “Effects of Fetal Testosterone on
Visuospatial Ability.” Archives of Sexual Behavior 41: 571–81.
Avise, John C. 2014. Conceptual Breakthroughs in Evolutionary Genetics: A Brief
History of Shifting Paradigms. New York: Elsevier.
Azziz, Ricardo, Enrico Carmina, Didier Dewailly et al. 2009. “The Androgen Excess
and PCOS Society Criteria for the Polycystic Ovary Syndrome: The Complete Task
Force Report.” Fertility and Sterility 91 (2): 456–88.
Bae, Christopher J., Katerina Douka, and Michael D. Petraglia. 2017. “On the Origin
of Modern Humans: Asian Perspectives.” Science 358 (6368).
Bailey, J. Michael. 2009. “What Is Sexual Orientation and Do Women Have One?” In
Contemporary Perspectives on Lesbian, Gay, and Bisexual Identities, edited by D.
A. Hope, 43–64. New York: Springer.
Bailey, J. Michael, Paul L. Vasey, Lisa M. Diamond et al. 2016. “Sexual Orientation,
Controversy, and Science.” Psychological Science in the Public Interest 17 (2): 45–
101.
Baird, A. D., S. J. Wilson, P. F. Bladin et al. 2004. “The Amygdala and Sexual Drive:
Insights from Temporal Lobe Epilepsy Surgery.” Annals of Neurology 55: 87–96.
Balaton, Bradley P., and Carolyn J. Brown. 2016. “Escape Artists of the X
Chromosome.” Trends in Genetics 32 (6): 348–59.
Barkow, J. H., L. Cosmides, and J. Tooby, eds. 1992. The Adapted Mind:
Evolutionary Psychology and the Generation of Culture. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Barnes, J. C., and Brian Boutwell. 2013. “A Demonstration of the Generalizability of
Twin-Based Research on Antisocial Behavior.” Behavior Genetics 43 (2): 120–31.
Barnes, J. C., John Paul Wright, Brian B. Boutwell et al. 2014. “Demonstrating the
Validity of Twin Research in Criminology.” Criminology 52 (4): 588–626.
Baron-Cohen, Simon. 2002. “The Extreme Male Brain Theory of Autism.” Trends in
Cognitive Sciences 6 (6): 248–54.
. 2003. The Essential Difference: Male and Female Brains and the Truth About
Autism. New York: Basic Books.
Baron-Cohen, Simon, Jennifer Richler, Dheraj Bisarya et al. 2003. “The Systemizing
Quotient: An Investigation of Adults with Asperger Syndrome or High–Functioning
Autism, and Normal Sex Differences.” Philosophical Transactions of the Royal
Society B: Biological Sciences 358 (1430): 361–74.
Baron-Cohen, Simon, and Sally Wheelwright. 2004. “The Empathy Quotient: An
Investigation of Adults with Asperger Syndrome or High Functioning Autism, and
Normal Sex Differences.” Journal of Autism and Developmental Disorders 34 (2):
163–75.
Barrett, J., and J. L. Armony. 2009. “Influence of Trait Anxiety on Brain Activity
During the Acquisition and Extinction of Aversive Conditioning.” Psychological
Medicine 39 (2): 255–65.
Bartels, M., C. E. M. van Beijsterveldt, and D. I. Boomsma. 2009. “Breastfeeding,
Maternal Education and Cognitive Function: A Prospective Study in Twins.”
Behavior Genetics 39: 616–22.
Bartz, J. A., J. Zaki, N. Bolger et al. 2011. “Social Effects of Oxytocin in Humans:
Context and Person Matter.” Trends in Cognitive Sciences 15 (7): 301–9.
Bateman, A. J. 1948. “Intra-sexual Selection in Drosophila.” Heredity 2: 349.
Bates, Timothy C., Narelle K. Hansell, Nicholas G. Martin et al. 2016. “When Does
Socioeconomic Status (SES) Moderate the Heritability of IQ? No Evidence for G ×
SES Interaction for IQ in a Representative Sample of 1176 Australian Adolescent
Twin Pairs.” Intelligence 56: 10–15.
Bates, Timothy C., Gary J. Lewis, and Alexander Weiss. 2013. “Childhood
Socioeconomic Status Amplifies Genetic Effects on Adult Intelligence.”
Psychological Science 24 (10): 2111–16.
Batty, G. David, K. M. Wennerstad, George D. Smith et al. 2008. “IQ in Early
Adulthood and Mortality by Middle Age: Cohort Study of One Million Swedish
Men.” Epidemiology 20 (1): 100–109.
Baumeister, Roy F., Jennifer D. Campbell, Joachim I. Kreuger et al. 2003. “Does High
Self-Esteem Cause Better Performance, Interpersonal Success, Happiness, or
Healthier Lifestyles?” Psychological Science in the Public Interest 7 (4): 1–44.
Beit-Hallahmi, Benjamin. 1981. “The Kibbutz Family: Revival or Survival.” Journal of
Family Issues 2 (3): 259–74.
Beltz, Adriene, Jane Swanson, and Sheri Berenbaum. 2011. “Gendered Occupational
Interests: Prenatal Androgen Effects on Psychological Orientation to Things Versus
People.” Hormones and Behavior 60 (4): 313–17.
Benbow, Camilla P., and Julian C. Stanley. 1980. “Sex Differences in Mathematical
Ability: Fact or Artifact?” Science 210: 1262–64.
. 1983. “Sex Differences in Mathematical Reasoning Ability: More Facts.”
Science 222: 1029–31.
Benenson, J. F., V. Duggan, and H. Markovits. 2004. “Sex Differences in Infants’
Attraction to Group Versus Individual Stimuli.” Infant Behavior and Development
27: 173–80.
Berenbaum, Sheri. 2017. “Born This Way?” Science 355 (6322): 254.
. 2018. “Beyond Pink and Blue: The Complexity of Early Androgen Effects on
Gender Development.” Child Development Perspectives 12 (1): 58–64.
Berenbaum, Sheri, and Melissa Hines. 1992. “Early Androgens Are Related to
Childhood Sex-Typed Toy Preferences.” Psychological Science 3 (3): 203–6.
Berg, Jeremy J., and Graham Coop. 2014. “A Population Genetic Signal of Polygenic
Adaptation.” PLoS Genetics 10 (8): e1004412.
Berg, Jeremy J., Arbel Harpak, Nicholas Sinnott-Armstrong et al. 2018. “Reduced
Signal for Polygenic Adaptation of Height in UK Biobank.” bioRxiv.
Berg, Jeremy J., Xinjun Zhang, and Graham Coop. 2017. “Polygenic Adaptation Has
Impacted Multiple Anthropometric Traits.” bioRxiv.
Berger, Peter L., and Thomas Luckmann. 1966. The Social Construction of Reality:
A Treatise in the Sociology of Knowledge. New York: Doubleday.
Berglund, Agnethe, Trine H. Johannsen, Kirstine Stochholm et al. 2016. “Incidence,
Prevalence, Diagnostic Delay, and Clinical Presentation of Female 46,XY Disorders
of Sex Development.” Journal of Clinical Endocrinology and Metabolism 101
(12): 4532–40.
Bermúdez de Castro, José María, María Martinón-Torres, Jordi Rosell et al. 2016.
“Continuity Versus Discontinuity of the Human Settlement of Europe Between the
Late Early Pleistocene and the Early Middle Pleistocene. The Mandibular
Evidence.” Quaternary Science Reviews 153: 51–62.
Besenbacher, Søren, Patrick Sulem, Agnar Helgason et al. 2016. “Multi-nucleotide de
novo Mutations in Humans.” PLoS Genetics (November 15).
Bigham, Abigail W. 2016. “Genetics of Human Origin and Evolution: High-Altitude
Adaptations.” Current Opinion in Genetics and Development 41: 8–13.
Blackford, J. U., A. H. Allen, R. L. Cowan et al. 2012. “Amygdala and Hippocampus
Fail to Habituate to Faces in Individuals with an Inhibited Temperament.” Social
Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience 8 (2): 143–50.
Blackford, J. U., S. N. Avery, R. L. Cowan et al. 2011. “Sustained Amygdala
Response to Both Novel and Newly Familiar Faces Characterizes Inhibited
Temperament.” Social Cognitive and Affective Neuroscience 6 (5): 621–29.
Blackless, Melanie, Anthony Charuvastra, Amanda Derryck et al. 2000. “How
Sexually Dimorphic Are We? Review and Synthesis.” American Journal of Human
Biology 12 (2): 151–66.
Blackwell, Antoinette. 1875. The Sexes Throughout Nature. New York: G. P. Putnam’s
Sons.
Blackwell, Lisa S., Kali H. Trzesniewski, and Carol Sorich Dweck. 2007. “Implicit
Theories of Intelligence Predict Achievement Across an Adolescent Transition: A
Longitudinal Study and an Intervention.” Child Development 78 (1): 246–63.
Blanchard, R. 2008. “Deconstructing the Feminine Essence Narrative.” Archives of
Sexual Behavior 37 (3): 434–38.
Bleier, Ruth. 1991. Gender Ideology and the Brain: Sex Differences Research.
Washington, DC: American Psychiatric Press.
Blinkhorn, Steve. 1982. “What Skullduggery?” Nature 296 (April 8): 506.
. 2005. “Intelligence: A Gender Bender.” Nature 438 (November 3): 31–32.
Block, Jeanne H. 1978. “Another Look at Sex Differentiation in the Socialization
Behaviors of Mothers and Fathers.” In The Psychology of Women: Future
Directions in Research, edited by J. A. Sherman and F. L. Denmark, 29–87. New
York: Psychological Dimensions.
. 1983. “Differential Premises Arising from Differential Socialization of the
Sexes: Some Conjectures.” Child Development 54 (6): 1335–54.
Bloom, Allan. 1987. The Closing of the American Mind: How Higher Education Has
Failed Democracy and Impoverished the Souls of Today’s Students. New York:
Simon & Schuster.
Boehmer, Annemie L. M., Hennie Brüggenwirth, Cissy van Assendelft et al. 2001.
“Genotype Versus Phenotype in Families with Androgen Insensitivity Syndrome.”
Journal of Clinical Endocrinology and Metabolism 86 (9): 4151–60.
Bolnick, Deborah A. 2008. “Individual Ancestry Inference and the Reification of Race
as a Biological Phenomenon.” In Revisiting Race in a Genomic Age, edited by
Barbara A. Koenig, Sandra Soo-Jin Lee, and Sarah S. Richardson, 4–85. New
Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press.
Bomba, L., K. Walter, and N. Soranzo (2017). “The Impact of Rare and Low-
Frequency Genetic Variants in Common Disease.” Genome Biology 18 (1): 77.
Boone, Alexander P., Xinyi Gong, and Mary Hegarty. 2018. “Sex Differences in
Navigation Strategy and Efficiency.” Memory and Cognition 46 (6): 909–22.
Borghans, Lex, Bart H. H. Golsteyn, James J. Heckman, et al. 2016. “What Grades
and Achievement Tests Measure.” Proceedings of the National Academy of
Sciences 113 (47): 13354.
Borghans, Lex, Bas ter Weel, and Bruce A. Weinberg. 2008. “Interpersonal Styles and
Labor Market Outcomes.” Journal of Human Resources 43 (4): 815–58.
Borkenau, Peter, Robert R. McCrae, and Antonio Terracciano. 2013. “Do Men Vary
More Than Women in Personality? A Study in 51 Cultures.” Journal of Research in
Personality 47 (2): 135–44.
Bos, Peter A., Dennis Hofman, Erno J. Hermans et al. 2016. “Testosterone Reduces
Functional Connectivity During the ‘Reading the Mind in the Eyes’ Test.”
Psychoneuroendocrinology 68: 194–201.
Bouchard, Thomas J., Jr. 1982. “Identical Twins Reared Apart: Reanalysis or Pseudo-
analysis?” Contemporary Psychology 27: 190–91.
. 1983. “Do Environmental Similarities Explain the Similarity in Intelligence of
Identical Twins Reared Apart?” Intelligence 7 (2): 175.
Bouchard, Thomas J., Jr., David T. Lykken, Matthew McGue et al. 1990. “Sources of
Human Psychological Differences: The Minnesota Study of Twins Reared Apart.”
Science 250 (October 12): 223–28.
Bowcock, A. M., A. Ruiz-Linares, J. Tomfohrde et al. 1994. “High Resolution of
Human Evolutionary Trees with Polymorphic Microsatellites.” Nature 368 (6470):
455–57.
Boyle, Evan A., Yang I. Li, and Jonathan K. Pritchard. 2017. “An Expanded View of
Complex Traits: From Polygenic to Omnigenic.” Cell 169 (7): 1177–86.
Braitenberg, Valentino. 2001. “Brain Size and Number of Neurons: An Exercise in
Synthetic Neuroanatomy.” Journal of Computational Neuroscience 10 (1): 71–77.
Branden, Nathaniel. 1969. The Psychology of Self-Esteem: A New Concept of Man’s
Psychological Nature. Los Angeles: Nash Publishing.
Braun, Henry I., John Centra, and Benjamin F. King. 1987. Verbal and Mathematical
Ability of High School Juniors and Seniors in 1983: A Norm Study of the
PSAT/NMSQT and the SAT. Princeton, NJ: Educational Testing Service.
Brinkworth, J. F., and L. B. Barreiro. 2014. “The Contribution of Natural Selection to
Present-Day Susceptibility to Chronic Inflammatory and Autoimmune Disease.”
Current Opinion in Immunology 31 (December): 66–78.
Brohawn, K. H., R. Offringa, D. L. Pfaff et al. 2010. “The Neural Correlates of
Emotional Memory in Posttraumatic Stress Disorder.” Biological Psychiatry 68
(11): 1023–30.
Brown, Gillian R. 2017. “Book Review: The Dangerous Battles over Sex and Gender.”
Trends in Ecology and Evolution 32 (12): 881–82.
Brown, P., T. Sutikna, M. J. Morwood et al. 2004. “A New Small-Bodied Hominin
from the Late Pleistocene of Flores, Indonesia.” Nature 431 (7012): 1055–61.
Browning, Sharon R., Brian L. Browning, Ying Zhou et al. 2018. “Analysis of Human
Sequence Data Reveals Two Pulses of Archaic Denisovan Admixture.” Cell 173 (1):
53–61.
Bryc, Katarzyna, Eric Y. Durand, J. Michael Macpherson et al. 2015. “The Genetic
Ancestry of African Americans, Latinos, and European Americans Across the United
States.” American Journal of Human Genetics 96 (1): 37–53.
Buckner, Randy L. 2013. “The Cerebellum and Cognitive Function: 25 Years of
Insight from Anatomy and Neuroimaging.” Neuron 80 (3): 807–15.
Burt, Callie H., and Ronald L. Simons. 2014. “Pulling Back the Curtain on Heritability
Studies: Biosocial Criminology in the Postgenomic Era.” Criminology 52 (2): 223–
62.
. 2015. “Heritability Studies in the Postgenomic Era: The Fatal Flaw Is
Conceptual.” Criminology 53 (1): 103–12.
Burt, S. Alexandra, Ashlea M. Klahr, and Kelly L. Klump. 2015. “Do Non-shared
Environmental Influences Persist over Time? An Examination of Days and
Minutes.” Behavior Genetics 45 (1): 24–34.
Buss, David M. 1984. “Evolutionary Biology and Personality Psychology: Toward a
Conception of Human Nature and Individual Differences.” American Psychologist
39 (10): 1135–47.
. 1989. “Sex Differences in Human Mate Preferences: Evolutionary Hypotheses
Tested in 37 Cultures.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 12: 1–49.
. 2019. Evolutionary Psychology: The New Science of the Mind. 6th ed. New
York: Routledge.
Bustamante, Carlos D., Esteban González Burchard, and Francisco M. De la Vega.
2011. “Genomics for the World.” Nature 475 (7355): 163–65.
Byrnes, J. P., D. C. Miller, and W. D. Schafer. 1997. “Gender Differences in Risk-
Taking: A Meta-analysis.” Psychological Bulletin 125: 367–83.
Cahill, Larry. 2017. “An Issue Whose Time Has Come.” Journal of Neuroscience
Research 95: 12–13.
Cahill, Larry, Richard J. Haier, Nathan S. White et al. 2001. “Sex-Related Difference
in Amygdala Activity During Emotionally Influenced Memory Storage.”
Neurobiology of Learning and Memory 75 (1): 1–9.
Cahill, Larry, Melina Uncapher, Lisa Kilpatrick et al. 2004. “Sex-Related Hemispheric
Lateralization of Amygdala Function in Emotionally Influenced Memory: An fMRI
Investigation.” Learning and Memory 11 (3): 261–66.
Cahill, Larry, and Anda van Stegeren. 2003. “Sex-Related Impairment of Memory for
Emotional Events with B-Adrenergic Blockade.” Neurobiology of Learning and
Memory 79 (1): 81–88.
Calafell, F., A. Shuster, W. C. Speed et al. 1998. “Short Tandem Repeat
Polymorphism Evolution in Humans.” European Journal of Human Genetics 6 (1):
38–49.
Callaway, Ewen. 2016. “Evidence Mounts for Interbreeding Bonanza in Ancient
Human Species.” Nature News (February 17).
. 2017. “Oldest Homo Sapiens Fossil Claim Rewrites Our Species’ History.”
Nature News (June 7).
Calvin, Catherine M., G. David Batty, Geoff Der et al. 2017. “Childhood Intelligence
in Relation to Major Causes of Death in 68 Year Follow-Up: Prospective Population
Study.” BMJ 357 (j2708).
Campbell, A., L. Shirley, and C. Heywood. 2000. “Infants’ Visual Preference for Sex-
Congruent Babies, Children, Toys and Activities: A Longitudinal Study.” British
Journal of Developmental Psychology 18: 479–98.
Campbell, Michael C., and Sarah A. Tishkoff. 2008. “African Genetic Diversity:
Implications for Human Demographic History, Modern Human Origins, and
Complex Disease Mapping.” Annual Review of Genomics and Human Genetics 9:
403–33.
Caplan, Bryan. 2011. Selfish Reasons to Have More Kids: Why Being a Great Parent
Is Less Work and More Fun Than You Think. New York: Basic Books.
Card, N. A., B. D. Stucky, G. M. Sawalani et al. 2008. “Direct and Indirect Aggression
During Childhood and Adolescence: A Meta-analytic Review of Gender Differences,
Intercorrelations, and Relations to Maladjustment.” Child Development 79: 1185–
229.
Carmina, Enrico, Didier Dewailly, Héctor F. Escobar-Morreale et al. 2017. “Non-
classic Congenital Adrenal Hyperplasia Due to 21-Hydroxylase Deficiency Revisited:
An Update with a Special Focus on Adolescent and Adult Women.” Human
Reproduction Update 23 (5): 580–99.
Carroll, John B. 1995. “Reflections on Stephen Jay Gould’s The Mismeasure of Man
(1981): A Retrospective Review.” Intelligence 21: 121–34.
Caspari, Ernst W. 1979. “Evolutionary Theory and the Evolution of the Human
Brain.” In Development and Evolution of Brain Size, edited by Craig Jensen and
Bruce C. Dudek, 9–28. New York: Academic Press.
Catani, Marco, Derek K. Jones, and Dominic H. Ffytche. 2005. “Perisylvan Language
Networks of the Human Brain.” Annals of Neurology 57: 8–16.
Cavalli-Sforza, Luigi Luca, Paolo Menozzi, and Alberto Piazza. 1994. The History and
Geography of Human Genes. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Cesarini, David, and Peter M. Visscher. 2017. “Genetics and Educational Attainment.”
npj Science of Learning 2.
Chalabaev, Aïna, Brenda Major, Philippe Sarrazin et al. 2012. “When Avoiding Failure
Improves Performance: Stereotype Threat and the Impact of Performance Goals.”
Motivation and Emotion 36 (2): 130–42.
Chamorro-Premuzic, Tomas, Nicole Harlaar, Corina Greven et al. 2010. “More Than
Just IQ: A Longitudinal Examination of Self-Perceived Abilities as Predictors of
Academic Performance in a Large Sample of UK Twins.” Intelligence 38 (4): 385–
92.
Chapman, Emma, Simon Baron-Cohen, Bonnie Auyeung et al. 2006. “Fetal
Testosterone and Empathy: Evidence from the Empathy Quotient (EQ) and
‘Reading the Mind in the Eyes’ Test.” Social Neuroscience 1 (2): 135–48.
Chekroud, Adam M., Emily J. Ward, Monica D. Rosenberg et al. 2016. “Patterns in
the Human Brain Mosaic Discriminate Males from Females.” Proceedings of the
National Academy of Sciences 113 (14): E1968.
Cheng, Helen, and Adrian Furnham. 2012. “Childhood Cognitive Ability, Education,
and Personality Traits Predict Attainment in Adult Occupational Prestige over 17
Years.” Journal of Vocational Behavior 81 (2): 218–26.
Cheverud, James M. 1984. “Quantitative Genetics and Developmental Constraints on
Evolution by Selection.” Journal of Theoretical Biology 110 (2): 155–71.
. 1988. “A Comparison of Genetic and Phenotypic Correlations.” Evolution 42
(5): 958–68.
Ciarrochi, Joseph V., Amy Y. C. Chan, and Peter Caputi. 2000. “A Critical Evaluation
of the Emotional Intelligence Construct.” Personality and Individual Differences 28
(3): 539–61.
Clarke, Geraldine M., Carl A. Anderson, Fredrik H. Pettersson et al. 2011. “Basic
Statistical Analysis in Genetic Case-Control Studies.” Nature Protocols 6 (2): 121–
33.
Clements, A. M., S. L. Rimrodt, J. R. Abel et al. 2006. “Sex Differences in Cerebral
Laterality of Language and Visuospatial Processing.” Brain and Language 98 (2):
150–58.
Clutten-Brock, T. H. 1989. “Mammalian Mating Systems.” Proceedings of the Royal
Society of London B 236: 339–72.
Cochran, Gregory, and Henry Harpending. 2009. The 10,000 Year Explosion: How
Civilization Accelerated Human Evolution. New York: Basic Books.
Cohen, Jacob. 1988. Statistical Power Analysis for the Behavioral Sciences.
Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Cohen-Bendahan, Celina C. C., Cornelieke van de Beek, and Sheri A. Berenbaum.
2005. “Prenatal Sex Hormone Effects on Child and Adult Sex-Typed Behavior:
Methods and Findings.” Neuroscience and Biobehavioral Reviews 29: 353–84.
Coleman, James S. et al. 1966. Equality of Educational Opportunity. Washington,
DC: U.S. Office of Education.
College Board. 2016. College-Bound Seniors: Total Group Profile Report. New York:
College Board.
Colom, Roberto, Luis F. García, Manuel Juan-Espinosa et al. 2002. “Null Sex
Differences in General Intelligence: Evidence from the WAIS-III.” Spanish Journal
of Psychology 5 (1): 29–35.
Colom, Roberto, Manuel Juan-Espinosa, Francisco Abad et al. 2000. “Negligible Sex
Differences in General Intelligence.” Intelligence 28 (1): 57–68.
Connellan, Jennifer, S. Baron-Cohen, Sally Wheelwright et al. 2000. “Sex Differences
in Human Neonatal Social Perception.” Infant Behavior and Development 23: 113–
18.
Constantinescu, Mihaela, David S. Moore, Scott P. Johnson et al. 2018. “Early
Contributions to Infants’ Mental Rotation Abilities.” Developmental Science 21 (4):
e12613.
Contreras, María José, Víctor J. Rubio, Daniel Peña et al. 2007. “Sex Differences in
Dynamic Spatial Ability: The Unsolved Question of Performance Factors.” Memory
and Cognition 35 (2): 297–303.
Coon, Carleton S. 1962. The Origins of Races. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.
Coop, G., J. K. Pickrell, J. Novembre et al. 2009. “The Role of Geography in Human
Adaptation.” PLoS Genetics 5.
Cossette, Louise, Andrée Pomerleau, Gérard Malcuit et al. 1996. “Emotional
Expressions of Female and Male Infants in a Social and a Nonsocial Context.” Sex
Roles 35 (11): 693–709.
Costa, Paul T., and Robert R. McCrae. 1985. The Neo Personality Inventory Manual.
Odessa, FL: PAR.
Costa, Paul T., Jr., A. Terracciano, and Robert R. McCrae. 2001. “Gender Differences
in Personality Traits Across Cultures: Robust and Surprising Findings.” Journal of
Personality and Social Psychology 81 (2): 322–31.
Cox, D. R. 1984. “Interaction.” International Statistical Review 52 (1): 1–24.
Credé, Marcus. 2018. “What Shall We Do About Grit? A Critical Review of What We
Know and What We Don’t Know.” Educational Researcher 47 (9): 606–11.
Crenshaw, Kimberlé. 1989. “Demarginalizing the Intersection of Race and Sex: A
Black Feminist Critique of Antidiscrimination Doctrine, Feminist Theory and
Antiracist Politics.” University of Chicago Legal Forum 140: 139–67.
Damian, Rodica, Rong Su, Michael Shanahan et al. 2014. “Can Personality Traits and
Intelligence Compensate for Background Disadvantage? Predicting Status
Attainment in Adulthood.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 109 (3):
473–89.
Dannemann, Michael, Kay Prüfer, and Janet Kelso. 2017. “Functional Implications of
Neandertal Introgression in Modern Humans.” Genome Biology 18 (1): 61.
Darwin, Charles. 1859. On the Origin of Species by Means of Natural Selection.
London: John Murray.
. 1900. The Descent of Man and Selection in Relation to Sex (A Library of
Universal Literature). New York: P. F. Collier and Son. Original edition 1871.
Davies, Gail, Max Lam, Sarah E. Harris et al. 2018. “Study of 300,486 Individuals
Identifies 148 Independent Genetic Loci Influencing General Cognitive Function.”
Nature Communications 9 (1): 2098.
Davies, William, and Lawrence S. Wilkinson. 2006. “It Is Not All Hormones:
Alternative Explanations for Sexual Differentiation of the Brain.” Brain Research
1126 (1): 36–45.
Davis, Bernard D. 1983. “Neo-Lysenkoism, IQ, and the Press.” The Public Interest
no. 73: 41–59.
Davis, Shannon N., and Barbara J. Risman. 2015. “Feminists Wrestle with
Testosterone: Hormones, Socialization and Cultural Interactionism as Predictors of
Women’s Gendered Selves.” Social Science Research 49: 110–25.
Dawkins, Richard. 1976. The Selfish Gene. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Deary, Ian J., Michelle D. Taylor, Carole L. Hart et al. 2005. “Intergenerational Social
Mobility and Mid-life Status Attainment: Influences of Childhood Intelligence,
Childhood Social Factors, and Education.” Intelligence 33 (5): 455–72.
Deary, Ian J., Graham Thorpe, Valerie Wilson et al. 2003. “Population Sex Differences
in IQ at Age 11: The Scottish Mental Survey 1932.” Intelligence 31 (6): 533–42.
de Beauvoir, Simone. 2009. Le Deuxième Sexe. Translated by Constance Borde and
Sheila Malovany-Chevallier. New York: Vintage. Original edition 1949.
Degler, Carl N. 1991. In Search of Human Nature: The Decline and Revival of
Darwinism in American Social Thought. New York: Oxford University Press.
de Graaf, Nastasja M., Guido Giovanardi, Claudia Zitz et al. 2018. “Sex Ratio in
Children and Adolescents Referred to the Gender Identity Development Service in
the UK (2009–2016).” Archives of Sexual Behavior 47: 1301–4.
Deichmann, Ute. 2016. “Epigenetics: The Origins and Evolution of a Fashionable
Topic.” Developmental Biology 416: 249–54.
de LaCoste-Utamsing, Christine, and Ralph L. Holloway. 1982. “Sexual Dimorphism
in the Human Corpus Callosum.” Science 216: 1431–32.
Del Giudice, Marco. 2009. “On the Real Magnitude of Psychological Sex Differences.”
Evolutionary Psychology 7 (2): 264–79.
. 2015. “Gender Differences in Personality and Social Behavior.” In
International Encyclopedia of the Social and Behavioral Sciences, edited by J. D.
Wright. New York: Elsevier.
Del Giudice, Marco, Emily S. Barrett, Jay Belsky et al. 2018. “Individual Differences
in Developmental Plasticity: A Role for Early Androgens?”
Psychoneuroendocrinology 90: 165–73.
Del Giudice, Marco, Tom Booth, and Paul Irwing. 2012. “The Distance Between Mars
and Venus: Measuring Global Sex Differences in Personality.” PLoS ONE 7 (1):
e29265.
Del Giudice, Marco, Richard A. Lippa, David A. Puts et al. 2016. “Joel et al.’s Method
Systematically Fails to Detect Large, Consistent Sex Differences.” Proceedings of
the National Academy of Sciences 113 (14): E1965.
de Lisi, Richard, Gowri Parameswaran, and Ann V. McGillicuddy-de Lisi. 1989. “Age
and Sex Differences in Representation of Horizontality Among Children in India.”
Perceptual and Motor Skills 68 (3, Pt. 1): 739–46.
Delwiche, Charles F. 2004. “The Genomic Palimpsest: Genomics in Evolution and
Ecology.” BioScience 54 (11): 991–1001.
Denworth, Lydia. 2017. “Is There a ‘Female’ Brain?” Scientific American
(September).
de Schotten, Michel Thiebaut, Flavio Dell’Acqua, Stephanie J. Forkel et al. 2011. “A
Lateralized Brain Network for Visuospatial Attention.” Nature Neuroscience 14:
1245.
Desikan, Rahul S., Florent Ségonne, Bruce Fischl et al. 2006. “An Automated Labeling
System for Subdividing the Human Cerebral Cortex on MRI Scans into Gyral Based
Regions of Interest.” NeuroImage 31 (3): 968–80.
Dessens, Arianne B., Froukje M. E. Slijper, and Stenvert L. S. Drop. 2005. “Gender
Dysphoria and Gender Change in Chromosomal Females with Congenital Adrenal
Hyperplasia.” Archives of Sexual Behavior 34 (4): 389–97.
Détroit, Florent, Armand Salvador Mijares, Julien Corny, et al. 2019. “A New Species
of Homo from the Late Pleistocene of the Philippines.” Nature 568 (7751): 181–86.
de Vries, Geert J. 2004. “Sex Differences in Adult and Developing Brains:
Compensation, Compensation, Compensation.” Endocrinology 145 (3): 1063–68.
de Vries, Geert J., and Nancy G. Forger. 2015. “Sex Differences in the Brain: A Whole
Body Perspective.” Biology of Sex Differences 6 (1): 15.
de Vries, Geert J., and Per Södersten. 2009. “Sex Differences in the Brain: The
Relation Between Structure and Function.” Hormones and Behavior 55 (5): 589–96.
Dewing, P., T. Shi, S. Horvath et al. 2003. “Sexually Dimorphic Gene Expression in
Mouse Brain Precedes Gonadal Differentiation.” Brain Research 118 (1–2): 82–90.
Diamond, Jared. 1994. “Race Without Color.” Discover Magazine (November).
Dick, Danielle M., Arpana Agrawal, Matthew C. Keller et al. 2015. “Candidate Gene-
Environment Interaction Research: Reflections and Recommendations.”
Perspectives on Psychological Science 10 (1): 37–59.
Dickens, William T., and James R. Flynn. 2006. “Black Americans Reduce the Racial
IQ Gap: Evidence from Standardization Samples.” Psychological Science 17 (10):
913–20.
Diener, Edward F., R. A. Emmons, and S. Griffin. 1985. “The Satisfaction with Life
Scale.” Journal of Personality Assessment 49: 71–75.
Diener, E., D. Wirtz, W. Tov et al. 2010. “New Well-Being Measures: Short Scales to
Assess Flourishing and Positive and Negative Feelings.” Social Indicators Research
97: 143–56.
Di Pietro, Janet A. 1981. “Rough and Tumble Play: A Function of Gender.”
Developmental Psychology 17 (1): 50–58.
Dittmann, Ralf W., Michael H. Kappes, Marianne E. Kappes et al. 1990. “Congenital
Adrenal Hyperplasia I: Gender-Related Behavior and Attitudes in Female Patients
and Sisters.” Psychoneuroendocrinology 15 (5): 401–20.
Dochtermann, Ned A. 2011. “Testing Cheverud’s Conjecture for Behavioral
Correlations and Behavioral Syndromes.” Evolution 65 (6): 1814–20.
Dodds, Richard M., Holly E. Syddall, Rachel Cooper et al. 2014. “Grip Strength
Across the Life Course: Normative Data from Twelve British Studies.” PLoS ONE 9
(12): e113637.
Domes, Gregor, Markus Heinrichs, Andre Michel et al. 2007. “Oxytocin Improves
‘Mind-Reading’ in Humans.” Biological Psychiatry 61: 731–33.
Domingue, Benjamin W., Jason Fletcher, Dalton Conley et al. 2014. “Genetic and
Educational Assortative Mating Among US Adults.” Proceedings of the National
Academy of Sciences 111 (22): 7996–8000.
Donlon, Thomas F., ed. 1984. The College Board Technical Handbook for the
Scholastic Aptitude Test and Achievement Tests. New York: College Entrance
Examination Board.
Dor, Yuval, and Howard Cedar. 2018. “Principles of DNA Methylation and Their
Implications for Biology and Medicine.” Lancet 392 (10149): 777–86.
Doyle, Randi A., and Daniel Voyer. 2016. “Stereotype Manipulation Effects on Math
and Spatial Test Performance: A Meta-Analysis.” Learning and Individual
Differences 47: 103–16.
Duckworth, Angela Lee, and Stephanie M. Carlson. 2013. “Self-Regulation and School
Success.” In Self-Regulation and Autonomy: Social and Developmental
Dimensions of Human Conduct, edited by Bryan W. Sokol, Frederick M. E.
Grouzet, and Ulrich Müller, 208–30. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Duff, Dawna, J. Bruce Tomblin, and Hugh Catts. 2015. “The Influence of Reading on
Vocabulary Growth: A Case for a Matthew Effect.” Journal of Speech, Language,
and Hearing Research 58 (3): 853–64.
Duncan, Greg J., and Katherine Magnuson. 2013. “Investing in Preschool Programs.”
Journal of Economic Perspectives 27 (2): 109–32.
Duncan, Laramie, Hanyang Shen, Bizu Gelaye et al. 2018. “Analysis of Polygenic
Score Usage and Performance Across Diverse Human Populations.” bioRxiv.
Durkheim, Émile. 1982. The Rules of the Sociological Method. Translated by W. D.
Halls. New York: Free Press. Original edition 1895.
Dweck, Carol S. 2006. Mindset: The New Psychology of Success. New York: Random
House.
Dweck, Carol S., and David S. Yeager. 2019. “Mindsets: A View from Two Eras.”
Perspectives on Psychological Science 14 (3): 1745691618804166.
Eagly, Alice H. 1987. Sex Differences in Social Behavior: A Social-Role
Interpretation. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Eagly, Alice H., and Wendy Wood. 2011. “Social Role Theory.” In Handbook of
Theories in Social Psychology, edited by P. van Lange, A. Kruglanski, and E. T.
Higgins, 458–76. Thousand Oaks, CA: Sage Publications.
Eagly, Alice H., Wendy Wood, and M. C. Johannessen-Schmidt. 2004. “Social Role
Theory of Sex Differences and Similarities: Implications for the Partner Preferences
of Women and Men.” In The Psychology of Gender, edited by Alice H. Eagly, A. E.
Beall, and Robert J. Sternberg, 269–95. New York: Guilford Press.
Eberstadt, Nicholas. 2016. Men Without Work: America’s Invisible Crisis. West
Conshohocken, PA: Templeton Press.
Eccles, Jacquelynne S. 1983. “Expectancies, Values, and Academic Behaviors.” In
Achievement and Achievement Motives: Psychological and Sociological
Approaches, edited by J. T. Spence, 75–146. San Francisco: W. H. Freeman.
Eccles, Jacquelynne S., Mina N. Vida, and Bonnie Barber. 2004. “The Relation of
Early Adolescents’ College Plans and Both Academic Ability and Task-Value Beliefs
to Subsequent College Enrollment.” Journal of Early Adolescence 24 (1): 63–77.
Edwards, A. W. F. 2003. “Human Genetic Diversity: Lewontin’s Fallacy.” BioEssays
25: 798–801.
Ehrhardt, A. A., and H. F. Meyer-Bahlburg. 1981. “Effects of Prenatal Sex Hormones
on Gender-Related Behavior.” Science 211 (4488): 1312.
Ekman, Paul. 1999. “Basic Emotions.” In Handbook of Cognition and Emotion,
edited by T. Dalgleish and M. Power, 45–60. New York: John Wiley & Sons.
Elhaik, Eran, Tatiana Tatarinova, Dmitri Chebotarev et al. 2014. “Geographic
Population Structure Analysis of Worldwide Human Populations Infers Their
Biogeographical Origins.” Nature Communications 5 (3513).
Ellison, Glenn, and Ashley Swanson. 2010. “The Gender Gap in Secondary School
Mathematics at High Achievement Levels: Evidence from the American
Mathematics Competitions.” Journal of Economic Perspectives 24 (2): 109–28.
Else-Quest, N. M., J. S. Hyde, and M. C. Linn. 2010. “Cross-National Patterns of
Gender Differences in Mathematics: A Meta-Analysis.” Psychological Bulletin 136
(1): 103–27.
Endendijk, Joyce J., Marleen G. Groeneveld, Marian J. Bakermans-Kranenburg et al.
2016. “Gender-Differentiated Parenting Revisited: Meta-analysis Reveals Very Few
Differences in Parental Control of Boys and Girls.” PLoS ONE 11 (7): e0159193.
Epstein, Herman T. 1979. “Correlated Brain and Intelligence Development in
Humans.” In Development and Evolution of Brain Size, edited by Craig Jensen and
Bruce C. Dudek, 111–31. New York: Academic Press.
Escaramís, Geòrgia, Elisa Docampo, and Raquel Rabionet. 2015. “A Decade of
Structural Variants: Description, History and Methods to Detect Structural
Variation.” Briefings in Functional Genomics: 14 (5): 305–14.
Fagan, Joseph F., and Cynthia R. Holland. 2007. “Racial Equality in Intelligence:
Predictions from a Theory of Intelligence as Processing.” Intelligence 35 (4): 319–
34.
Fairbairn, D. J. 2016. “Sexual Dimorphism.” In Encyclopedia of Evolutionary
Biology, edited by Richard M. Kliman, 105–13. Oxford: Academic Press.
Falconer, Douglas S. 1960. Introduction to Quantitative Genetics. London: Oliver &
Boyd.
Falk, Armin, and Johannes Hermle. 2018. “Relationship of Gender Differences in
Preferences to Economic Development and Gender Equality.” Science 362 (6412).
Fan, Shaohua, Matthew E. B. Hansen, Yancy Lo et al. 2016. “Going Global by
Adapting Local: A Review of Recent Human Adaptation.” Science 354 (6308): 54–
58.
Farber, S. L. 1981. Identical Twins Raised Apart: A Reanalysis. New York: Basic
Books.
Fausto-Sterling, Anne. 2000. Sexing the Body: Gender Politics and the Construction
of Sexuality. New York: Basic Books.
Feingold, Alan. 1994. “Gender Differences in Variability in Intellectual Abilities: A
Cross-Cultural Perspective.” Sex Roles 30 (1): 81–92.
Feldman, Marcus W. 2010. “The Biology of Ancestry: DNA, Genomic Variation, and
Race.” In Doing Race: 21 Essays for the 21st Century, edited by Hazel Rose
Markus and Paula M. L. Moya, 136–59. New York: W. W. Norton.
Feldman, Marcus W., and Richard C. Lewontin. 2008. “Race, Ancestry, and
Medicine.” In Revisiting Race in a Genomic Age, edited by Barbara A. Koenig,
Sandra Soo-Jin Lee, and Sarah S. Richardson, 89–101. New Brunswick, NJ:
Rutgers University Press.
Feldman, Marcus W., and Sohini Ramachandran. 2018. “Missing Compared to What?
Revisiting Heritability, Genes and Culture.” Philosophical Transactions of the Royal
Society B: Biological Sciences 373 (1743): 20170064.
Felson, Jacob. 2014. “What Can We Learn from Twin Studies? A Comprehensive
Evaluation of the Equal Environments Assumption.” Social Science Research 43:
184–99.
Fenstermaker, Sarah, and Candace West, eds. 2002. Doing Gender, Doing Difference.
New York: Routledge.
Field, Yair, Evan A. Boyle, Natalie Telis et al. 2016. “Detection of Human Adaptation
During the Past 2000 Years.” Science 354 (6313): 760–64.
Filkowski, M. M., R. M. Olsen, B. Duda et al. 2017. “Sex Differences in Emotional
Perception: Meta-analysis of Divergent Activation.” NeuroImage 147: 925–33.
Fillingim, R. B., C. D. King, M. C. Ribeiro-Dasilva et al. 2009. “Sex, Gender, and
Pain: A Review of Recent Clinical and Experimental Findings.” Journal of Pain 10
(5): 447–85.
Finnigan, Katherine M., and Katherine S. Corker. 2016. “Do Performance Avoidance
Goals Moderate the Effect of Different Types of Stereotype Threat on Women’s
Math Performance?” Journal of Research in Personality 63: 36–43.
Firkowska-Mankiewicz, A. 2002. Intelligence and Success in Life. Warsaw: IFiS.
Fischbein, Siv. 1980. “IQ and Social Class.” Intelligence 4: 51–63.
Fishbain, David A., and Adolfo Vilasuso. 1980. “Exclusive Adult Lesbianism
Associated with Turner’s Syndrome Mosaicism.” Archives of Sexual Behavior 9 (4):
349.
Fisher, Ronald Aylmer. 1918. “The Correlation Between Relatives on the Supposition
of Mendelian Inheritance.” Transactions of the Royal Society of Edinburgh 52:
399–433.
Fleischman, Diana Santos. 2014. “Women’s Disgust Adaptations.” In Evolutionary
Perspectives on Human Sexual Psychology and Behavior, edited by V. A. Weekes-
Shackelford and Todd K. Shackelford, 277–96. New York: Springer Science +
Business Media.
Flore, Paulette C., and Jelte M. Wicherts. 2015. “Does Stereotype Threat Influence
Performance of Girls in Stereotyped Domains? A Meta-analysis.” Journal of School
Psychology 53 (1): 25–44.
Foley, Sallie, and George W. Morley. 1992. “Care and Counseling of the Patient with
Vaginal Agenesis.” The Female Patient 17 (October): 73–80.
Fosse, Roar, Jay Joseph, and Ken Richardson. 2015. “A Critical Assessment of the
Equal-Environment Assumption of the Twin Method for Schizophrenia.” Frontiers
in Psychiatry 6: 62.
Freedman, Matthew L., David Reich, Kathryn L. Penney et al. 2004. “Assessing the
Impact of Population Stratification on Genetic Association Studies.” Nature Genetics
36: 388.
Fregel, Rosa, Fernando L. Méndez, Youssef Bokbot et al. 2018. “Ancient Genomes
from North Africa Evidence Prehistoric Migrations to the Maghreb from Both the
Levant and Europe.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 115 (26):
6774–79.
Fryer, C. D., Q. Gu, C. L. Ogden, et al. 2016. “Anthropometric Reference Data for
Children and Adults: United States, 2011–2014.” Vital Statistics (39).
Fuller, Barbara F. 2002. “Infant Gender Differences Regarding Acute Established
Pain.” Clinical Nursing Research 11 (2): 190–203.
Fumagalli, Matteo, Ida Moltke, Niels Grarup, et al. 2015. “Greenlandic Inuit Show
Genetic Signatures of Diet and Climate Adaptation.” Science 349 (6254): 1343.
Funder, David C., and Daniel J. Ozer. 2019. “Evaluating Effect Size in Psychological
Research.” Advances in Methods and Practices in Psychological Science. Advance
online publication.
Furnham, Adrian, and Helen Cheng. 2017. “Socio-demographic Indicators,
Intelligence, and Locus of Control as Predictors of Adult Financial Well-Being.”
Journal of Intelligence 5 (2).
Furnham, Adrian, Steven C. Richards, and Delroy L. Paulhus. 2013. “The Dark Triad
of Personality: A 10 Year Review.” Social and Personality Psychology Compass 7:
199–216.
Galton, Francis. 1869. Hereditary Genius: An Inquiry into Its Laws and
Consequences. 1892 ed. London: Macmillan.
Gamble, Clive, John Gowlett, and Robin Dunbar. 2014. Thinking Big: How the
Evolution of Social Life Shaped the Human Mind. London: Thames & Hudson.
Ganley, Colleen M., Leigh A. Mingle, Allison M. Ryan et al. 2013. “An Examination of
Stereotype Threat Effects on Girls’ Mathematics Performance.” Developmental
Psychology 49 (10): 1886–97.
Gardner, Howard. 1983. Frames of Mind: The Theory of Multiple Intelligences. 1985
ed. New York: Basic Books.
. 2006. “On Failing to Grasp the Core of MI Theory: A Response to Visser et
al.” Intelligence 34 (5): 503–5.
. 2008. Multiple Intelligences: New Horizons. New York: Basic Books.
. 2016. “Multiple Intelligences: Prelude, Theory, and Aftermath.” In Scientists
Making a Difference: One Hundred Eminent Behavioral and Brain Scientists Talk
About Their Most Important Contributions, edited by Robert J. Sternberg, Susan T.
Fiske, and Donald J. Foss, 167–70. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Gates, Gary J. 2011. How Many People Are Lesbian, Gay, Bisexual, and
Transgender? Los Angeles: Williams Institute.
Geary, David. 2004. The Origin of Mind: Evolution of Brain, Cognition, and
General Intelligence. Washington: American Psychological Association.
. 2010. Male, Female: The Evolution of Human Sex Differences. 2nd ed.
Washington, DC: American Psychological Association. Original edition 1998.
. 2017. “Evolutionary Framework for Identifying Sex-and Species-Specific
Vulnerabilities in Brain Development and Functions.” Journal of Neuroscience
Research 95 (1–2): 355–61.
Geddes, Patrick, and J. Arthur Thomson. 1889. The Evolution of Sex. New York:
Humboldt Publishing.
Gelman, Andrew. 2018. “You Need 16 Times the Sample Size to Estimate an
Interaction Than to Estimate a Main Effect.” Statistical Modeling, Causal
Inference, and Social Science (March 15).
Geschwind, Norman, and Albert M. Galaburda. 1985. “Cerebral Lateralization,
Biological Mechanisms, Associations, and Pathology: I. A Hypothesis and a Program
for Research.” Archive of Neurology 42 (5): 428–59.
Giedd, Jay N., Armin Raznahan, Aaron Alexander-Bloch et al. 2014. “Child Psychiatry
Branch of the National Institute of Mental Health Longitudinal Structural Magnetic
Resonance Imaging Study of Human Brain Development.”
Neuropsychopharmacology 40: 43.
Gignac, Gilles E., and Timothy C. Bates. 2017. “Brain Volume and Intelligence: The
Moderating Role of Intelligence Measurement Quality.” Intelligence 64: 18–29.
Gignac, Gilles E., and Eva T. Szodorai. 2016. “Effect Size Guidelines for Individual
Differences Researchers.” Personality and Individual Differences 102: 74–78.
Gilly, A., D. Suveges, K. Kuchenbaecker et al. (2018). “Cohort-wide Deep Whole
Genome Sequencing and the Allelic Architecture of Complex Traits.” Nature
Communications 9 (1): 4674.
Gladwell, Malcolm. 2008. Outliers: The Story of Success. Boston: Little, Brown.
Glazko, G. V., and M. Nei. 2003. “Estimation of Divergence Times for Major Lineages
of Primate Species.” Molecular Biology and Evolution 20 (3): 424–34.
Glezerman, Marek. 2016. “Yes, There Is a Female and a Male Brain: Morphology
Versus Functionality.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 113 (14):
E1971.
Goldberg, Lewis R. 1993a. “The Structure of Phenotypic Personality Traits.”
American Psychologist 48 (1): 26–34.
Goldberg, Steven. 1974. The Inevitability of Patriarchy: Why the Biological
Difference Between Men and Women Always Produces Male Domination. New
York: Morrow.
. 1993b. Why Men Rule: A Theory of Male Dominance. Chicago: Open Court.
Goldin, Claudia. 2014. “A Grand Gender Convergence: Its Last Chapter.” American
Economic Review 104 (4): 1091–119.
Goldstein, H. 2008. “Building Cognitive Ability Tests with Reduced Adverse Impact.”
Paper presented at Mid-Atlantic Personnel Assessment Consortium, New York.
Goldstein, Jill M., M. Jerram, R. A. Poldrack et al. 2005. “Hormonal Cycle Modulates
Arousal Circuitry in Women Using Functional Magnetic Resonance Imaging.”
Journal of Neuroscience 25: 9309–16.
Goldstein, Jill M., Larry J. Seidman, Nicholas J. Horton et al. 2001. “Normal Sexual
Dimorphism of the Adult Human Brain Assessed by in vivo Magnetic Resonance
Imaging.” Cerebral Cortex 11 (6): 490–97.
Goodman, Alan H., Yolanda T. Moses, and Joseph L. Jones. 2012. Race: Are We So
Different? Arlington, VA: American Anthropological Association.
Gordon, Claire C., Thomas Churchill, Charles E. Clauser et al. 1989. 1988
Anthropometric Survey of U.S. Army Personnel: Summary Statistics; Interim
Report. Natick, MA: United States Army.
Gordon, Robert A. 1997. “Everyday Life as an Intelligence Test: Effects of Intelligence
and Intelligence Context.” Intelligence 24 (1): 203–320.
Gottfredson, Linda S. 1997a. “Mainstream Science on Intelligence: An Editorial with
52 Signatories, History, and Bibliography.” Intelligence 24 (1): 13–23.
. 1997b. “Why g Matters: The Complexity of Everyday Life.” Intelligence 24
(1): 79–132.
. 2003. “g, Jobs, and Life.” In The Scientific Study of General Intelligence: A
Tribute to Arthur R. Jensen, 293–342. Oxford: Pergamon.
Gottfredson, Michael R., and Travis Hirschi. 1990. A General Theory of Crime.
Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Gould, Stephen J. 1981. The Mismeasure of Man. New York: W. W. Norton.
Grant, Michael D., William S. Kremen, Kristen C. Jacobson et al. 2010. “Does
Parental Education Have a Moderating Effect on the Genetic and Environmental
Influences of General Cognitive Ability in Early Adulthood?” Behavior Genetics 40
(4): 438–46.
Gravel, Simon, Brenna M. Henn, Ryan N. Gutenkunst et al. 2011. “Demographic
History and Rare Allele Sharing Among Human Populations.” Proceedings of the
National Academy of Sciences 108 (29): 11983.
Greally, John M. 2015. “Over-interpreted Epigenetics Study of the Week.”
EpgntxEinstein (August 23).
. 2018. “A User’s Guide to the Ambiguous Word ‘Epigenetics.’” Nature Reviews
Molecular Cell Biology 19: 207–8.
Greaves, Lara M., Fiona Kate Barlow, Carol H. J. Lee et al. 2017. “The Diversity and
Prevalence of Sexual Orientation Self-Labels in a New Zealand National Sample.”
Archives of Sexual Behavior 46 (5): 1325–36.
Grissom, Nicola M., and Teresa M. Reyes. 2019. “Let’s Call the Whole Thing Off:
Evaluating Gender and Sex Differences in Executive Function.”
Neuropsychopharmacology 44 (1): 86–96.
Grossman, Sharon R., Kristian G. Andersen, Ilya Shlyakhter et al. 2013. “Identifying
Recent Adaptations in Large-Scale Genomic Data.” Cell 152 (4): 703–13.
Groucutt, Huw S., Michael D. Petraglia, Geoff Bailey et al. 2015. “Rethinking the
Dispersal of Homo Sapiens out of Africa.” Evolutionary Anthropology: Issues,
News, and Reviews 24 (4): 149–64.
Guimond, S., N. R. Branscombe, S. Brunot et al. 2007. “Culture, Gender, and the
Self: Variations and Impact of Social Comparison Processes.” Journal of Personality
and Social Psychology 92: 1118–34.
Guiso, L., F. Monte, P. Sapienza et al. 2008. “Culture, Gender, and Math.” Science
320: 1164–65.
Gunnar, M. R., and M. Donahue. 1980. “Sex Differences in Social Responsiveness
Between Six Months and Twelve Months.” Child Development 51: 262–65.
Günther, Torsten, and Mattias Jakobsson. 2016. “Genes Mirror Migrations and
Cultures in Prehistoric Europe—a Population Genomic Perspective.” Current
Opinion in Genetics and Development 41: 115–23.
Guo, Jing, Yang Wu, Zhihong Zhu et al. 2018. “Global Genetic Differentiation of
Complex Traits Shaped by Natural Selection in Humans.” Nature Communications
9 (1): 1865.
Gur, Ruben C., D. Alsop, David C. Glahn et al. 2000. “An fMRI Study of Sex
Differences in Regional Activation to a Verbal and a Spatial Task.” Brain and
Language 74 (2): 157–70.
Gur, Ruben C., and Raquel E. Gur. 2017. “Complementarity of Sex Differences in
Brain and Behavior: From Laterality to Multimodal Neuroimaging.” Journal of
Neuroscience Research 95 (1–2): 189–99.
Haasle, Ryan J., and Bret A. Payseur. 2016. “Fifteen Years of Genomewide Scans for
Selection: Trends, Lessons and Unaddressed Genetic Sources of Complication.”
Molecular Ecology 25: 5–23.
Haier, Richard J. 2016. The Neuroscience of Intelligence. New York: Cambridge
University Press.
Hakim, Catherine. 2002. “Lifestyle Preferences as Determinants of Women’s
Differentiated Labor Market Careers.” Work and Occupations 29 (4): 428–59.
Haldane, J. B. S. 1927. “A Mathematical Theory of Natural and Artificial Selection,
Part V: Selection and Mutation.” Proceedings of the Cambridge Philosophical
Society 23: 838–44.
Hall, Judith A. 1978. “Gender Effects in Decoding Nonverbal Cues.” Psychological
Bulletin 85 (4): 845–57.
Hall, Judith A., Danielle C. Blanch, Terrence G. Horgan et al. 2009. “Motivation and
Interpersonal Sensitivity: Does It Matter How Hard You Try?” Motivation and
Emotion 33 (3): 291.
Halpern, Diane F. 2010. “How Neuromythologies Support Sex Role Stereotypes.”
Science 330 (6009): 1320.
. 2012. Sex Differences in Cognitive Ability. 4th ed. New York: Psychology
Press. Original edition 1986.
Halpern, Diane F., Camilla P. Benbow, David C. Geary et al. 2007. “The Science of
Sex Differences in Science and Mathematics.” Psychological Science in the Public
Interest 8: 1–51.
Halpern, Diane F., and Mary L. LaMay. 2000. “The Smarter Sex: A Critical Review of
Sex Differences in Intelligence.” Educational Psychology Review 12 (2): 229–46.
Hamann, Stephan. 2005. “Sex Differences in the Responses of the Human Amygdala.”
Neuroscientist 11 (4): 288–93.
Hamann, Stephan, Rebecca A. Herman, Carla L. Nolan et al. 2004. “Men and Women
Differ in Amygdala Response to Visual Sexual Stimuli.” Nature Neuroscience 7:
411–16.
Hamilton, Alexander, James Madison, and John Jay. 1982. The Federalist Papers.
New York: New American Library. Original edition 1787.
Hamilton, W. D. 1964. “The Genetical Evolution of Social Behaviour.” Journal of
Theoretical Biology 7 (1): 1–52.
Hänggi, Jürgen, Laszlo Fövenyi, Franziskus Liem et al. 2014. “The Hypothesis of
Neuronal Interconnectivity as a Function of Brain Size—a General Organization
Principle of the Human Connectome.” Frontiers in Human Neuroscience 8: 915.
Hanscombe, Ken B., Maciej Trzaskowski, Claire M. A. Haworth et al. 2012.
“Socioeconomic Status (SES) and Children’s Intelligence (IQ): In a UK-
Representative Sample SES Moderates the Environmental, Not Genetic, Effect on
IQ.” PLoS ONE 7 (2): e30320.
Hanselman, Paul, Christopher S. Rozek, Jeffrey Grigg et al. 2017. “New Evidence on
Self-Affirmation Effects and Theorized Sources of Heterogeneity from Large-Scale
Replications.” Journal of Educational Psychology 109 (3): 405–24.
Harden, Kathryn Paige, Benjamin W. Domingue, Daniel W. Belsky et al. 2019.
“Genetic Associations with Mathematics Tracking and Persistence in Secondary
School.” bioRxiv: 598532.
Harden, Kathryn Paige, Eric Turkheimer, and John C. Loehlin. 2007. “Genotype by
Environment Interaction in Adolescents’ Cognitive Aptitude.” Behavior Genetics 37:
273–83.
Hardyck, Curtis, and Lewis F. Petrinovich. 1977. “Left-Handedness.” Psychological
Bulletin 84 (3): 385–404.
Harris, Judith R. 1998. The Nurture Assumption: Why Children Turn Out the Way
They Do. New York: Free Press.
Hassett, Janice M., Erin R. Siebert, and Kim Wallen. 2008. “Sex Differences in Rhesus
Monkey Toy Preferences Parallel Those of Children.” Hormones and Behavior 54
(3): 359–64.
Hawks, John, Eric T. Wang, Gregory M. Cochran et al. 2007. “Recent Acceleration of
Human Adaptive Evolution.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 104
(52): 20753.
He, Y., Z. J. Chen, and A. C. Evans. 2007. “Small-World Anatomical Networks in the
Human Brain Revealed by Cortical Thickness from MRI.” Cerebral Cortex 17:
2407–19.
Hedges, L. V., and A. Nowell. 1995. “Sex Differences in Mental Test Scores,
Variability, and Numbers of High-Scoring Individuals.” Science 269: 41–45.
Hedges, S. Blair. 2000. “Human Evolution: A Start for Population Genomics.” Nature
408: 652–53.
Heidensohn, F., and M. Silvestri. 2012. “Gender and Crime.” In The Oxford Handbook
of Criminology, edited by M. Maguire, R. Morgan, and R. Reiner. Oxford: Oxford
University Press.
Henn, B. M., L. R. Botigue, S. Peischl et al. 2016. “Distance from Sub-Saharan Africa
Predicts Mutational Load in Diverse Human Genomes.” Proceedings of the
National Academy of Science 113 (4): E440–49.
Herculano-Houzel, Suzana. 2017. “Numbers of Neurons as Biological Correlates of
Cognitive Capability.” Current Opinion in Behavioral Sciences 16: 1–7.
Herlitz, Agneta, and Julie E. Yonker. 2010. “Sex Differences in Episodic Memory: The
Influence of Intelligence.” Journal of Clinical and Experimental Neuropsychology
24 (1): 107–14.
Hermisson, Joachim, and Pleuni S. Pennings. 2005. “Soft Sweeps: Molecular
Population Genetics of Adaptation from Standing Genetic Variation.” Genetics 169
(April): 2335–52.
Herráez, David L., Marc Bauchet, Kun Tang et al. 2009. “Genetic Variation and
Recent Positive Selection in Worldwide Human Populations: Evidence from Nearly 1
Million SNPs.” PLoS ONE 4 (11): e7888.
Herrera, Alexandra Ycaza, Jiaxi Wang, and Mara Mather. 2018. “The Gist and Details
of Sex Differences in Cognition and the Brain: How Parallels in Sex Differences
Across Domains Are Shaped by the Locus Coeruleus and Catecholamine Systems.”
Progress in Neurobiology. Advance online publication.
Herrnstein, Richard J. 1973. I.Q. in the Meritocracy. Boston: Little, Brown.
Herrnstein, Richard J., and Charles Murray. 1994. The Bell Curve: Intelligence and
Class Structure in American Life. 1996 ed. New York: Free Press.
Hershkovitz, Israel, Gerhard W. Weber, Rolf Quam et al. 2018. “The Earliest Modern
Humans Outside Africa.” Science 359 (6374): 456–59.
Hettema, J. M., Michael C. Neale, and Kenneth S. Kendler. 1995. “Physical Similarity
and the Equal-Environment Assumption in Twin Studies of Psychiatric Disorders.”
Behavior Genetics 25 (4): 327–35.
Heuer, Friderike, and Daniel Reisberg. 1990. “Vivid Memories of Emotional Events:
The Accuracy of Remembered Minutiae.” Memory and Cognition 18 (5): 496–506.
Hill, Carolyn J., Howard S. Bloom, Alison R. Black et al. 2008. “Empirical
Benchmarks for Interpreting Effect Sizes in Research.” Child Development
Perspectives 2 (3): 172–77.
Hill, William G. 1995. “Sewall Wright’s ‘Systems of Mating.’” Genetics 143: 1499–
506.
Hines, Melissa. 2010. “Sex-Related Variation in Human Behavior and the Brain.”
Trends in Cognitive Sciences 14: 448–56.
Hines, Melissa, Mihaela Constantinescu, and Debra Spencer. 2015. “Early Androgen
Exposure and Human Gender Development.” Biology of Sex Differences 6 (3): 1–
10.
Hines, Melissa, and Francine R. Kaufman. 1994. “Androgen and the Development of
Human Sex-Typical Behavior: Rough-and-Tumble Play and Sex of Preferred
Playmates in Children with Congenital Adrenal Hyperplasia (Cah).” Child
Development 65 (4): 1042–53.
Hines, Melissa, V. Pasterski, D. Spencer et al. 2016. “Prenatal Androgen Exposure
Alters Girls’ Responses to Information Indicating Gender-Appropriate Behaviour.”
Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 371
(1688): 20150125.
Hittelman, J. H., and R. Dickes. 1979. “Sex Differences in Neonatal Eye Contact
Time.” Merill-Palmer Quarterly 25: 171–84.
Hoffman, M. L. 1973. “Developmental Synthesis of Affect and Cognition and Its
Implications for Altruistic Motivation.” Developmental Psychology 11: 607–22.
Hoffmann, T. J., N. J. Marini, and J. S. Witte. 2010. “Comprehensive Approach to
Analyzing Rare Genetic Variants.” PLoS ONE 5 (11): e13584.
Hogan, Michael J., Roger T. Staff, Brendan P. Bunting et al. 2011. “Cerebellar Brain
Volume Accounts for Variance in Cognitive Performance in Older Adults.” Cortex 47
(4): 441–50.
Holland, John L. 1959. “A Theory of Vocational Choice.” Journal of Counseling
Psychology 6 (1): 35–44.
. 1977. Manual for the Vocational Preference Inventory (7th Rev.). Palo Alto,
CA: Consulting Psychological Press.
Holloway, Ralph L. 1979. “Brain Size, Allometry, and Reorganization: Toward a
Synthesis.” In Development and Evolution of Brain Size, edited by Craig Jensen
and Bruce C. Dudek, 59–88. New York: Academic Press.
. 2017. “In the Trenches with the Corpus Callosum: Some Redux of Redux.”
Journal of Neuroscience Research 95 (1–2): 21–23.
Horn, Joseph M., John C. Loehlin, and Lee Willerman. 1979. “Intellectual
Resemblance Among Adoptive and Biological Relatives: The Texas Adoption
Project.” Behavior Genetics 9 (3): 177–207.
Horowitz, Mark, Anthony Haynor, and Kenneth Kickham. 2018. “Sociology’s Sacred
Victims and the Politics of Knowledge: Moral Foundations Theory and Disciplinary
Controversies.” American Sociologist 49 (4): 459–95.
Horsthemke, Bernhard. 2018. “A Critical View on Transgenerational Epigenetic
Inheritance in Humans.” Nature Communications 9 (1): 2973.
Huerta-Sanchez, Emilia, Xin Jin, Asan et al. 2014. “Altitude Adaptation in Tibetans
Caused by Introgression of Denisovan-Like DNA.” Nature 512: 194–97.
Huguet, Pascal, and Isabelle Régner. 2007. “Stereotype Threat Among Schoolgirls in
Quasi-Ordinary Classroom Circumstances.” Journal of Educational Psychology 99
(3): 545–60.
Humphreys, Lloyd G. 1978. “To Understand Regression from Parent to Offspring,
Think Statistically.” Psychological Bulletin 85 (6): 1317–22.
. 1983. “Review of The Mismeasure of Man by Stephen Jay Gould.” American
Journal of Psychology 96: 407–15.
Humphreys, Lloyd G., David Lubinski, and Grace Yao. 1993. “Utility of Predicting
Group Membership and the Role of Spatial Visualization in Becoming an Engineer,
Physical Scientist, or Artist.” Journal of Applied Psychology 78 (2): 250–61.
Hyde, Janet Shibley. 2005. “The Gender Similarities Hypothesis.” American
Psychologist 60 (6): 581–92.
Hyde, Janet Shibley, Daphna Joel, Rebecca S. Bigler et al. 2018. “The Future of Sex
and Gender in Psychology: Five Challenges to the Gender Binary.” American
Psychologist 74 (2): 171–93.
Iliescu, D., A. Ilie, D. Ispas et al. 2016. “Sex Differences in Intelligence: A Multi-
measure Approach Using Nationally Representative Samples from Romania.”
Intelligence 58: 54–61.
Imperato-McGinley, J., M. Pichardo, T. Gautier et al. 1991. “Cognitive Abilities in
Androgen-Insensitive Subjects: Comparison with Control Males and Females from
the Same Kindred.” Clinical Endocrinology (Oxford) 34: 341–47.
Ingalhalikar, Madhura, Alex Smith, Drew Parker et al. 2014. “Sex Differences in the
Structural Connectome of the Human Brain.” Proceedings of the National Academy
of Sciences 111 (2): 823–28.
Irwing, Paul. 2012. “Sex Differences in g: An Analysis of the US Standardization
Sample of the WAIS-III.” Personality and Individual Differences 53 (2): 126–31.
Irwing, Paul, and Richard Lynn. 2005. “Sex Differences in Means and Variability on
the Progressive Matrices in University Students: A Meta-analysis.” British Journal
of Psychology 96: 505–24.
Jablonsky, N. G., and G. Chaplin. 2010. “Human Skin Pigmentation as an Adaptation
to UV Radiation.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 107 (suppl. 2):
8962–68.
Jackson, Douglas N., and J. Philippe Rushton. 2006. “Males Have Greater g: Sex
Differences in General Mental Ability from 100,000 17-to 18-Year-Olds on the
Scholastic Assessment Test.” Intelligence 34 (5): 479–86.
Jacobson, Kristen C., and Terrie Vasilopoulos. 2012. “Developmental Changes in
Moderating Effects of Parental Education on Individual Differences in Vocabulary
IQ from Adolescence to Young Adulthood.” Behavior Genetics 42: 941.
Jahan, Selim et al. 2016. Human Development Report 2016. New York: United
Nations Development Programme.
Jahanshad, Neda, and Paul M. Thompson. 2017. “Multimodal Neuroimaging of Male
and Female Brain Structure in Health and Disease Across the Life Span.” Journal of
Neuroscience Research 95 (1–2): 371–79.
Jannot, Anne-Sophie, Georg Ehret, and Thomas Perneger. 2015. “P < 5 × 10−8 Has
Emerged as a Standard of Statistical Significance for Genome-Wide Association
Studies.” Journal of Clinical Epidemiology 68 (4): 460–65.
Janssen, Ian, Steven B. Heymsfield, Zimian Wang et al. 2000. “Skeletal Muscle Mass
and Distribution in 468 Men and Women Aged 18–88 Yr.” Journal of Applied
Physiology 89 (1): 81–88.
Jencks, Christopher. 1979. Who Gets Ahead? The Determinants of Economic Success
in America. New York: Basic Books.
Jencks, Christopher, Marshall Smith, Henry Acland et al. 1972. Inequality: A
Reassessment of the Effect of Family and Schooling in America. New York: Basic
Books.
Jensen, Arthur R. 1998. The g Factor: The Science of Mental Ability. Westport, CT:
Praeger.
Jensen, Jeffrey D., Bret A. Payseur, Wolfgang Stephan et al. 2018. “The Importance
of the Neutral Theory in 1968 and 50 Years On: A Response to Kern and Hahn
2018.” Evolution 73 (1): 111–14.
Joel, Daphna, Zohar Berman, Ido Tavor et al. 2015. “Sex Beyond the Genitalia: The
Human Brain Mosaic.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 112 (50):
15468–73.
Joel, Daphna, Ariel Persico, Jürgen Hänggi et al. 2016. “Reply to Del Giudice et al.,
Chekroud et al., and Rosenblatt: Do Brains of Females and Males Belong to Two
Distinct Populations?” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 113 (14):
E1969–70.
Johnson, Wendy, and Thomas J. Bouchard Jr. 2005. “The Structure of Human
Intelligence: It Is Verbal, Perceptual, and Image Rotation (Vpr), Not Fluid and
Crystallized.” Intelligence 33: 393–416.
. 2007. “Sex Differences in Mental Abilities: g Masks the Dimensions on Which
They Lie.” Intelligence 35: 23–39.
Johnson, Wendy, Andrew Carothers, and Ian J. Deary. 2008. “Sex Differences in
Variability in General Intelligence: A New Look at an Old Question.” Perspectives in
Psychological Science 3 (6): 518–31.
Johnson, Wendy, Matt McGue, Robert F. Krueger et al. 2004. “Marriage and
Personality: A Genetic Analysis.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 86
(2): 285–94.
Jordan, Daniel M., Marie Verbanck, and Ron Do. 2018. “The Landscape of Pervasive
Horizontal Pleiotropy in Human Genetic Variation Is Driven by Extreme Polygenicity
of Human Traits and Diseases.” bioRxiv.
Joseph, Dana L., and Daniel A. Newman. 2010. “Emotional Intelligence: An
Integrative Meta-analysis and Cascading Model.” Journal of Applied Psychology 95
(1): 54–78.
Kaczkurkin, Antonia N., Armin Raznahan, and Theodore D. Satterthwaite. 2019. “Sex
Differences in the Developing Brain: Insights from Multimodal Neuroimaging.”
Neuropsychopharmacology 44 (1): 71–85.
Kahneman, D., P. Slovic, and A. Tversky, eds. (1982). Judgment Under Uncertainty:
Heuristics and Biases. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Kajonius, Petri, and Erik Mac Giolla. 2017. “Personality Traits Across Countries:
Support for Similarities Rather Than Differences.” PLoS ONE 12 (6): e0179646.
Kansaku, K., A. Yamaura, and S. Kitazawa. 2000. “Sex Differences in Lateralization
Revealed in the Posterior Language Areas.” Cerebral Cortex 10 (9): 866–72.
Kaprio, Jaakko, M. Koskenvuo, and R. J. Rose. 1990. “Change in Cohabitation and
Intrapair Similarity of Monozygotic (MZ) Cotwins for Alcohol Use, Extraversion,
and Neuroticism.” Behavior Genetics 20 (2): 265–76.
Karama, S. M., A. R. Lecours, J. M. Leroux et al. 2002. “Areas of Brain Activation in
Males and Females During Viewing of Erotic Film Excerpts.” Human Brain
Mapping 16: 1–13.
Karreman, Annemiek, Cathy van Tuijl, Marcel A. G. van Aken et al. 2006. “Parenting
and Self-Regulation in Preschoolers: A Meta-analysis.” Infant and Child
Development 15 (6): 561–79.
Katzman, Steven, and George M. Alliger. 1992. “Averaging Untransformed Variance
Ratios Can Be Misleading: A Comment on Feingold.” Review of Educational
Research 62 (4): 427–28.
Kawabata, Y., L. R. A. Alink, W.-L. Tseng et al. 2011. “Maternal and Paternal
Parenting Styles Associated with Relational Aggression in Children and Adolescents:
A Conceptual Analysis and Meta-analytic Review.” Developmental Review 31 (4):
240–78.
Kazachenka, Anastasiya, Tessa M. Bertozzi, Marcela K. Sjoberg-Herrera et al. 2018.
“Identification, Characterization, and Heritability of Murine Metastable Epialleles:
Implications for Non-genetic Inheritance.” Cell 175 (5): 1259–71.e13.
Kerminen, Sini, Alicia R. Martin, Jukka Koskela et al. 2018. “Geographic Variation and
Bias in Polygenic Scores of Complex Diseases and Traits in Finland.” bioRxiv.
Kern, Andrew D., and Matthew W. Hahn. 2018. “The Neutral Theory in Light of
Natural Selection.” Molecular Biology and Evolution 35 (6): 1366–71.
Kettlewell, H. B. D. 1955. “Selection Experiments on Industrial Melanism in the
Lepidoptera.” Heredity 9: 323–42.
. 1956. “Further Selection Experiments on Industrial Melanism in the
Lepidoptera.” Heredity 10 (3): 287–301.
Key, Felix M., Qiaomei Fu, Frédéric Romagné et al. 2016. “Human Adaptation and
Population Differentiation in the Light of Ancient Genomes.” Nature
Communications 7 (10775).
Khalid, Javaria Mona, Juliet M. Oerton, Carol Dezateux et al. 2012. “Incidence and
Clinical Features of Congenital Adrenal Hyperplasia in Great Britain.” Archives of
Disease in Childhood 97 (2): 101.
Kimura, Motoo. 1968. “Evolutionary Rate at the Molecular Level.” Nature 217: 624–
26.
. 1983. The Neutral Theory of Molecular Evolution. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press.
Kimura, Motoo, and George H. Weiss. 1964. “The Stepping Stone Model of
Population Structure and the Decrease of Genetic Correlation with Distance.”
Genetics 49: 561–76.
King, Jack L., and Thomas H. Jukes. 1969. “Non-Darwinian Evolution.” Science 164:
788–97.
Kirkpatrick, Robert M., Matt McGue, and William G. Iacono. 2015. “Replication of a
Gene-Environment Interaction Via Multimodel Inference: Additive-Genetic Variance
in Adolescents’ General Cognitive Ability Increases with Family-of-Origin
Socioeconomic Status.” Behavior Genetics 45 (2): 200–214.
Kliman, Richard. 2008. “The EvolGenius Population Genetics Computer Simulation:
How It Works.” Nature Education 1 (3): 7.
Knickmeyer, R., S. Baron-Cohen, P. Raggatt et al. 2005. “Foetal Testosterone, Social
Relationships, and Restricted Interests in Children.” Journal of Child Psychology
and Psychiatry 45 (1): 1–13.
. 2006. “Fetal Testosterone and Empathy.” Hormones and Behavior 49: 282–
92.
Kodric-Brown, Astrid, and James H. Brown. 1987. “Anisogamy, Sexual Selection, and
the Evolution and Maintenance of Sex “ Evolutionary Ecology 1 (2): 95–105.
Kong, Augustine, Gudmar Thorleifsson, Michael L. Frigge et al. 2018. “The Nature of
Nurture: Effects of Parental Genotypes.” Science 359 (6374): 424.
Korenman, Sanders, and David Neumark. 1991. “Does Marriage Really Make Men
More Productive?” Journal of Human Resources 26 (2): 282–307.
Korenman, Sanders, and Christopher Winship. 2000. “A Reanalysis of the Bell Curve:
Intelligence, Family Background, and Schooling.” In Meritocracy and Economic
Inequality, edited by Kenneth Arrow, Samuel Bowles, and Steven Durlauf.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Koscik, Tim, Dan O’Leary, David J. Moser et al. 2009. “Sex Differences in Parietal
Lobe Morphology: Relationship to Mental Rotation Performance.” Brain and
Cognition 69 (3): 451–59.
Krapohl, Eva, Kaili Rimfeld, Nicholas G. Shakeshaft et al. 2014. “The High
Heritability of Educational Achievement Reflects Many Genetically Influenced
Traits, Not Just Intelligence.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 111
(42): 15273–78.
Kuhn, Thomas S. 2012. The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. 4th ed. Chicago:
University of Chicago Press. Original edition 1962.
Kuncel, Nathan R., and Sarah A. Hezlett. 2010. “Fact and Fiction in Cognitive Ability
Testing for Admissions and Hiring Decisions.” Current Directions in Psychological
Science 19 (6): 339–45.
Kuncel, Nathan R., Deniz S. Ones, and Paul R. Sackett. 2010. “Individual Differences
as Predictors of Work, Educational, and Broad Life Outcomes.” Personality and
Individual Differences 49 (4): 331–36.
Kurdi, Benedek, Shayn Lozano, and Mahzarin R. Banaji. 2016. “Introducing the Open
Affective Standardized Image Set (OASIS).” Behavior Research Methods 49 (2):
457–70.
LaBar, K. S., and R. Cabeza. 2006. “Cognitive Neuroscience of Emotional Memory.”
Nature Reviews Neuroscience 7 (1): 54–64.
Lachance, Joseph, Ali J. Berens, Matthew E. B. Hansen et al. 2018. “Genetic
Hitchhiking and Population Bottlenecks Contribute to Prostate Cancer Disparities in
Men of African Descent.” Cancer Research 78 (9): 2432–43.
Lakin, Joni M. 2013. “Sex Differences in Reasoning Abilities: Surprising Evidence That
Male–Female Ratios in the Tails of the Quantitative Reasoning Distribution Have
Increased.” Intelligence 41 (4): 263–74.
Lander, E. S., and N. J. Schork. 1994. “Genetic Dissection of Complex Traits.”
Science 265 (5181): 2037.
Landy, Frank J. 2005. “Some Historical and Scientific Issues Related to Research on
Emotional Intelligence.” Journal of Organizational Behavior 26 (4): 411–24.
Law, David J., James W. Pellegrino, and Earl B. Hunt. 1993. “Comparing the Tortoise
and the Hare: Gender Differences and Experience in Dynamic Spatial Reasoning
Tasks.” Psychological Science 4 (1): 35–40.
Lawson, Daniel John, Neil Martin Davies, Simon Haworth et al. 2019. “Is Population
Structure in the Genetic Biobank Era Irrelevant, a Challenge, or an Opportunity?”
Human Genetics. Published online April 27, 2019.
Lawson, Daniel John, Lucy van Dorp, and Daniel Falush. 2018. “A Tutorial on How
Not to Over-interpret Structure and Admixture Bar Plots.” Nature Communications
9 (1): 3258.
Leaper, Campbell, Kristin J. Anderson, and Paul Sanders. 1998. “Moderators of
Gender Effects on Parents’ Talk to Their Children: A Meta-analysis.”
Developmental Psychology 34 (1): 3–27.
Lechner, Clemens, Daniel Danner, and Beatrice Rammstedt. 2017. “How Is
Personality Related to Intelligence and Achievement? A Replication and Extension of
Borghans et al. and Salkever.” Personality and Individual Differences 111: 86–91.
Leeb, R. T., and F. G. Rejskind. 2004. “Here’s Looking at You, Kid! A Longitudinal
Study of Perceived Gender Differences in Mutual Gaze Behavior in Young Infants.”
Sex Roles 50 (1–2): 1–14.
Lehre, Anne-Catherine, Knut P. Lehre, Petter Laake et al. 2009. “Greater Intrasex
Phenotype Variability in Males Than in Females Is a Fundamental Aspect of the
Gender Differences in Humans.” Developmental Psychobiology 51 (2): 198–206.
Lemann, Nicholas. 1999. The Big Test: The Secret History of the American
Meritocracy. New York: Farrar, Straus, and Giroux.
Lever, J. 1978. “Sex Differences in the Complexity of Children’s Play and Games.”
American Sociological Review 43: 471–83.
Lewis, Neil A., and Nicholas M. Michalak. 2019. “Has Stereotype Threat Dissipated
over Time? A Cross-Temporal Meta-analysis.” PsyArXiv Preprints.
Lewontin, Richard C. 1970. “Race and Intelligence.” Bulletin of the Atomic Scientists
26 (3): 2–8.
. 1972. “The Apportionment of Human Diversity.” Evolutionary Biology 6:
381–98.
. 1974. “The Analysis of Variance and the Analysis of Causes.” American
Journal of Human Genetics 26: 400–411.
Li, Jun Z., Devin M. Absher, Hua Tang et al. 2008. “Worldwide Human Relationships
Inferred from Genome-Wide Patterns of Variation.” Science 319 (5866): 1100–1104.
. 2008. Supporting Online Material for “Worldwide Human Relationships
Inferred from Genome-Wide Patterns of Variation.”
Li, Rui, Alexandre Montpetit, Marylène Rousseau et al. 2013. “Somatic Point
Mutations Occurring Early in Development: A Monozygotic Twin Study.” Journal of
Medical Genetics 51 (1): 28.
Lim, Vivien K. G., Thompson S. H. Teo, and Geok Leng Loo. 2003. “Sex, Financial
Hardship and Locus of Control: An Empirical Study of Attitudes Towards Money
Among Singaporean Chinese.” Personality and Individual Differences 34 (3): 411–
29.
Linn, M. C., and A. C. Peterson. 1985. “Emergence and Characterization of Sex
Differences in Spatial Ability: A Meta-analysis.” Child Development 56: 1479–98.
Lippa, Richard A. 2010. “Sex Differences in Personality Traits and Gender-Related
Occupational Preferences Across 53 Nations: Testing Evolutionary and Social-
Environmental Theories.” Archives of Sexual Behavior 39 (3): 619–36.
Lippa, Richard A., Marcia L. Collaer, and Michael Peters. 2010. “Sex Differences in
Mental Rotation and Line Angle Judgments Are Positively Associated with Gender
Equality and Economic Development Across 53 Nations.” Archives of Sexual
Behavior 39 (4): 990–97.
Lippa, Richard A., Kathleen Preston, and John Penner. 2014. “Women’s
Representation in 60 Occupations from 1972 to 2010: More Women in High-Status
Jobs, Few Women in Things-Oriented Jobs.” PLoS ONE 9 (5): e95960.
Littman, Lisa. 2018. “Rapid-Onset Gender Dysphoria in Adolescents and Young
Adults: A Study of Parental Reports.” PLoS ONE 13 (8): e202330.
. 2019. “Correction: Parent Reports of Adolescents and Young Adults Perceived
to Show Signs of a Rapid Onset of Gender Dysphoria.” PLoS ONE 14 (3):
e0214157.
Liu, X., R. T. Ong, E. N. Pillai et al. 2013. “Detecting and Characterizing Genomic
Signatures of Positive Selection in Global Populations.” American Journal of
Human Genetics 92 (6): 866–81.
Lock, Andrew, and Thomas Strong. 2010. Social Constructionism: Sources and
Stirrings in Theory and Practice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Locke, John. 1960. Two Treatises of Government. Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press. Original edition 1689.
Loehlin, John C. 1978. “Identical Twins Reared Apart and Other Routes to the Same
Direction.” In Twin Research, Part A: Psychology and Methodology, edited by W.
Nance, G. Allen, and P. Parisi, 69–77. New York: Allan R. Liss.
Loehlin, John C., and Robert C. Nichols. 1976. Heredity, Environment, and
Personality: A Study of 850 Sets of Twins. Austin: University of Texas Press.
Lombardo, Michael V., Emma Ashwin, Bonnie Auyeung et al. 2012. “Fetal
Testosterone Influences Sexually Dimorphic Gray Matter in the Human Brain.”
Journal of Neuroscience 32 (2): 674.
Lombardo, Michael V., B. Chakrabarti, Edward T. Bullmore et al. 2011.
“Specialization of Right Temporo-Parietal Junction for Mentalizing and Its
Association with Social Impairments in Autism.” NeuroImage 56: 1832–38.
Long, Jeffrey C., Jie Li, and Meghan E. Healy. 2009. “Human DNA Sequences: More
Variation and Less Race.” American Journal of Physical Anthropology 139 (1): 23–
34.
LoParo, Devon, and Irwin Waldman. 2014. “Twins’ Rearing Environment Similarity
and Childhood Externalizing Disorders: A Test of the Equal Environments
Assumption.” Behavior Genetics 44 (6): 606–13.
Lopez, Saioa, Lucy van Dorp, and Garrett Hallenthal. 2016. “Human Dispersal out of
Africa: A Lasting Debate.” Evolutionary Bioinformatics 11 (S2): 57–68.
Low, Bobbi S. 2015. Why Sex Matters: A Darwinian Look at Human Behavior.
Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Lubinski, David, and Camilla P. Benbow. 2006. “Study of Mathematically Precocious
Youth After 35 Years: Uncovering Antecedents for the Development of Math-
Science Expertise.” Psychological Science 1 (4): 316–45.
Lubinski, David, Camilla P. Benbow, and Harrison J. Kell. 2014. “Life Paths and
Accomplishments of Mathematically Precocious Males and Females Four Decades
Later.” Psychological Science 25 (12): 2217–32.
Lubinski, David, Camilla P. Benbow, Daniel L. Shea et al. 2001. “Men and Women at
Promise for Scientific Excellence: Similarity Not Dissimilarity.” Psychological
Science 12 (4): 309–17.
Lubinski, David, Rose Mary Webb, Martha J. Morelock et al. 2001. “Top 1 in 10,000:
A 10-Year Follow-up of the Profoundly Gifted.” Journal of Applied Psychology 86
(4): 718–29.
Luders, Eileen, Arthur W. Toga, and Paul M. Thompson. 2014. “Why Size Matters:
Differences in Brain Volume Account for Apparent Sex Differences in Callosal
Anatomy.” NeuroImage 84: 820–24.
Ludwig, Volker, and Josef Brüderl. 2018. “Is There a Male Marital Wage Premium?
New Evidence from the United States.” American Sociological Review 83 (4): 744–
70.
Lukianoff, Greg, and Jonathan Haidt. 2018. The Coddling of the American Mind:
How Good Intentions and Bad Ideas Are Setting Up a Generation for Failure. New
York: Penguin.
Luo, Yang, Xinyi Li, Xin Wang et al. 2018. “Estimating Heritability of Complex Traits
in Admixed Populations with Summary Statistics.” bioRxiv: 503144.
Lutchmaya, Svetlana, S. Baron-Cohen, and Peter Raggatt. 2001. “Foetal Testosterone
and Vocabulary Size in 18-and 24-Month-Old Infants.” Infant Behavior and
Development 24: 418–24.
. 2002. “Foetal Testosterone and Eye Contact in 12-Month-Old Human
Infants.” Infant Behavior and Development 25: 327–35.
Lynn, Richard. 1999. “Sex Differences in Intelligence and Brain Size: A Developmental
Theory.” Intelligence 27 (1): 1–12.
. 2017. “Sex Differences in Intelligence: The Developmental Theory.” Mankind
Quarterly 58 (1): 9–43.
Lynn, Richard, and Paul Irwing. 2004. “Sex Differences on the Progressive Matrices:
A Meta-analysis.” Intelligence 32: 481–98.
Lytton, Hugh, and David M. Romney. 1991. “Parents’ Differential Socialization of
Boys and Girls: A Meta-analysis.” Psychological Bulletin 109 (2): 267–96.
Maccoby, Eleanor E., and Carol N. Jacklin. 1974. The Psychology of Sex Differences.
Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press.
Mac Giolla, Erik, and Petri J. Kajonius. 2018. “Sex Differences in Personality Are
Larger in Gender Equal Countries: Replicating and Extending a Surprising Finding.”
International Journal of Psychology. www.ncbi.nlm.nih.gov/pubmed/30206941.
Machin, Stephen, and Tuomas Pekkarinen. 2008. “Global Sex Differences in Test
Score Variability.” Science 322 (5906): 1331.
Madsen, B. E., and S. R. Browning. 2009. “A Groupwise Association Test for Rare
Mutations Using a Weighted Sum Statistic.” PLoS Genetics 5: e1000384.
Makel, Matthew C., Jonathan Wai, Kristen Peairs et al. 2016. “Sex Differences in the
Right Tail of Cognitive Abilities: An Update and Cross Cultural Extension.”
Intelligence 59: 8–15.
Malaspinas, Anna-Sapfo, Michael C. Westaway, Craig Muller et al. 2016. “A Genomic
History of Aboriginal Australia.” Nature 538: 207–14.
Malécot, Gustave. 1948. Les Mathématiques de l’Hérédité. Paris: Masson.
Mallick, Swapan, Heng Li, Mark Lipson et al. 2016. “The Simons Genome Diversity
Project: 300 Genomes from 142 Diverse Populations.” Nature 538: 201–6.
Mancuso, N., N. Rohland, K. A. Rand et al. 2015. “The Contribution of Rare
Variation to Prostate Cancer Heritability. ” Nature Genetics 48: 30.
Marchini, Jonathan, Lon R. Cardon, Michael S. Phillips et al. 2004. “The Effects of
Human Population Structure on Large Genetic Association Studies.” Nature
Genetics 36: 512.
Mardis, E. R. 2008. “Next-Generation DNA Sequencing Methods.” Annual Review of
Genomics and Human Genetics 9: 387–402.
Marigorta, U. M., and A. Navarro. 2013. “High Trans-Ethnic Replicability of GWAS
Results Implies Common Causal Variants.” PLoS Genet 9 (6): e1003566.
Marks, G. N. 2008. “Accounting for the Gender Gaps in Student Performance in
Reading and Mathematics: Evidence from 31 Countries.” Oxford Review of
Education 34: 89–109.
Marth, Gabor T., Fuli Yu, Amit R. Indap et al. 2011. “The Functional Spectrum of
Low-Frequency Coding Variation.” Genome Biology 12 (9): R84.
Martin, C. L., D. N. Ruble, and J. Szkrybalo. 2002. “Cognitive Theories of Early
Gender Development.” Psychological Bulletin 128: 903–33.
Martin, L. A., H. W. Neighbors, and D. M. Griffith. 2013. “The Experience of
Symptoms of Depression in Men vs Women: Analysis of the National Comorbidity
Survey Replication.” JAMA Psychiatry 70 (10): 1100–1106.
Marwha, D., M. Halari, and L. Eliot. 2017. “Meta-analysis Reveals a Lack of Sexual
Dimorphism in Human Amygdala Volume.” NeuroImage 147: 282–94.
Matarazzo, Joseph D. 1972. Wechsler’s Measurement and Appraisal of Adult
Intelligence. New York: Oxford University Press.
Mattern, Krista D., and Brian F. Patterson. 2013. “Test of Slope and Intercept Bias in
College Admissions: A Response to Aguinis, Culpepper, and Pierce (2010).” Journal
of Applied Psychology 98 (1): 134–47.
Matthews, Gerald, Moshe Zeidner, and Richard D. Roberts, eds. 2007. The Science of
Emotional Intelligence: Knowns and Unknowns. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Mayer, John D., David R. Caruso, and Peter Salovey. 1999. “Emotional Intelligence
Meets Traditional Standards for an Intelligence.” Intelligence 27 (4): 267–98.
Mayes, L. C., and A. S. Carter. 1990. “Emerging Social Regulatory Capacities as Seen
in the Still-Face Situation.” Child Development 61: 754–63.
McCarthy, Margaret M. 2015. “Sex Differences in the Brain.” The Scientist (October
1).
McCarthy, Margaret M., and Arthur P. Arnold. 2011. “Reframing Sexual
Differentiation of the Brain.” Nature Neuroscience 14 (6): 677–83.
McCarthy, Margaret M., and Gregory F. Ball. 2011. “Tempests and Tales: Challenges
to the Study of Sex Differences in the Brain.” Biology of Sex Differences 2 (1): 4.
McCarthy, Margaret M., Bridget M. Nugent, and Kathryn M. Lenz. 2017.
“Neuroimmunology and Neuroepigenetics in the Establishment of Sex Differences in
the Brain.” Nature Reviews Neuroscience 18 (8): 471–84.
McClure, Erin B. 2000. “A Meta-analytic Review of Sex Differences in Facial
Expression Processing and Their Development in Infants, Children, and
Adolescents.” Psychological Bulletin 126 (3): 424–53.
McCoy, Rajiv C., and Joshua M. Akey. 2017. “Selection Plays the Hand It Was Dealt:
Evidence That Human Adaptation Commonly Targets Standing Genetic Variation.”
Genome Biology 18 (1): 139.
McCrae, Robert R., and A. Terracciano. 2005. “Universal Features of Personality
Traits from the Observer’s Perspective: Data from 50 Cultures.” Journal of
Personality and Social Psychology 88 (3): 547–61.
McDaniel, Michael A. 2005. “Big-Brained People Are Smarter: A Meta-analysis of the
Relationship Between in vivo Brain Volume and Intelligence.” Intelligence 33: 337–
46.
. 2018. How to Build a Cognitive Ability Test with Reduced Group Mean
Differences. Presentation to Personnel Testing Council of Metropolitan Washington
(February 21).
McDaniel, Michael A., and Sven Kepes. 2014. “An Evaluation of Spearman’s
Hypothesis by Manipulating G Saturation.” International Journal of Selection and
Assessment 22 (4): 333–42.
McGlone, Jeannette. 1980. “Sex Differences in Human Brain Asymmetry: A Critical
Survey.” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 3 (2): 215–27.
McGue, Matt, and David T. Lykken. 1992. “Genetic Influence on Risk of Divorce.”
Psychological Science 3: 368–73.
McHenry, H. M. 2012. “Origin and Diversity of Early Hominin Bipedalism.” In
African Genesis: Perspectives on Hominin Evolution, edited by S. C. Reynolds,
205–22. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Mecca, Andrew, Neil J. Smelser, and John Vasconcellos, eds. 1989. The Social
Importance of Self-Esteem. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Merton, Robert K. 1968. “The Matthew Effect in Science.” Science 159: 56–63.
Migeon, Barbara R. 2017. “Choosing the Active X: The Human Version of X
Inactivation.” Trends in Genetics 33 (12): 899–909.
Mill, John Stuart. 1869. The Subjection of Women. London: Longmans, Green, Reader
& Dyer.
Miller, Gregory A., and Jean P. Chapman. 2001. “Misunderstanding Analysis of
Covariance.” Journal of Abnormal Psychology 110 (1): 40–48.
Moffitt, Terrie E., Louise Arseneault, Daniel Belsky et al. 2011. “A Gradient of
Childhood Self-Control Predicts Health, Wealth, and Public Safety.” Proceedings of
the National Academy of Sciences 108 (7): 2693–98.
Moffitt, Terrie E., Avshalom Caspi, and Michael Rutter. 2005. “Strategy for
Investigating Interactions Between Measured Genes and Measured Environments.”
Archives of General Psychiatry 62 (5): 473–81.
Moffitt, Terrie E., Richie Poulton, and Avshalom Caspi. 2013. “The Lifelong Impact
of Early Self-Control.” American Scientist 101 (5): 352–59.
Money, John Williams. 1952. “Hermaphroditism: An Inquiry into the Nature of a
Human Paradox.” PhD dissertation, Harvard University.
Montagu, Ashley. 1997. Man’s Most Dangerous Myth: The Fallacy of Race. 6th ed.
Walnut Creek, CA: Altamira Press. Original edition 1942.
Moore, Carrie B., John R. Wallace, Daniel J. Wolfe et al. 2013. “Low Frequency
Variants, Collapsed Based on Biological Knowledge, Uncover Complexity of
Population Stratification in 1000 Genomes Project Data.” PLoS Genetics 9 (12):
e1003959.
Moore, D. S., and D. Shenk. 2017. “The Heritability Fallacy.” Wiley Interdisciplinary
Reviews: Cognitive Science 8 (1–2).
Moran, Carlos, Ricardo Azziz, Enrico Carmina et al. 2000. “21-Hydroxylase-Deficient
Nonclassic Adrenal Hyperplasia Is a Progressive Disorder: A Multicenter Study.”
American Journal of Obstetrics and Gynecology 183 (6): 1468–74.
Moreno-Briseño, P., R. Diaz, A. Campos-Romo et al. 2010. “Sex-Related Differences
in Motor Learning and Performance.” Behavioral and Brain Functions 6: 74.
Morrongiello, Barbara A., and Tess Dawber. 2004. “Identifying Factors That Relate to
Children’s Risk-Taking Decisions.” Canadian Journal of Behavioural Science 36
(4): 255–66.
Mueller, Claudia M., and Carol S. Dweck. 1998. “Praise for Intelligence Can
Undermine Children’s Motivation and Performance.” Journal of Personality and
Social Psychology 75 (1): 33–52.
Mundy, P., J. A. Block, C. Delgado et al. 2007. “Individual Differences in the
Development of Joint Attention in Infancy.” Child Development 78: 938–54.
Murray, Charles. 1984. Losing Ground: American Social Policy, 1950–1980. New
York: Basic Books.
. 1988. In Pursuit: Of Happiness and Good Government. New York: Simon and
Schuster.
. 1997. What It Means to Be a Libertarian: A Personal Interpretation. New
York: Broadway Books.
. 2003. Human Accomplishment: The Pursuit of Excellence in the Arts and
Sciences, 800 B.C. to 1950. New York: HarperCollins.
. 2006. In Our Hands: A Plan to Replace the Welfare State. Washington: AEI
Press.
. 2012. Coming Apart: The State of White America, 1960–2010. New York:
Crown Forum.
. 2015. By the People: Rebuilding Liberty Without Permission. New York:
Crown Forum.
Myrianthopoulos, N. C., and K. S. French. 1968. “An Application of the U.S. Bureau
of Census Socioeconomic Index to a Large Diversified Population.” Social Science
and Medicine 2: 283–99.
Nagel, Mats, Philip R. Jansen, Sven Stringer et al. 2018. “Gwas Meta-Analysis of
Neuroticism (N=449,484) Identifies Novel Genetic Loci and Pathways.” Nature 50
(7): 920–27.
Nagy, Emese, Hajnalka Kompagne, Hajnalka Orvos et al. 2007. “Gender-Related
Differences in Neonatal Imitation.” Infant and Child Development 16 (3): 267–76.
Nanney, D. L. 1958. “Epigenetic Control Systems.” Proceedings of the National
Academy of Sciences 44 (7): 712.
Narasimhan, Vagheesh M., Raheleh Rahbari, Aylwyn Scally et al. 2017. “Estimating
the Human Mutation Rate from Autozygous Segments Reveals Population
Differences in Human Mutational Processes.” Nature Communications 8 (1): 303.
Nauta, Margaret M. 2010. “The Development, Evolution, and Status of Holland’s
Theory of Vocational Personalities: Reflections and Future Directions for Counseling
Psychology.” Journal of Counseling Psychology 57 (1): 11–22.
Nave, Gideon, Amos Nadler, David Zava et al. 2017. “Single-Dose Testosterone
Administration Impairs Cognitive Reflection in Men.” Psychological Science 28
(10): 1398–407.
Nazareth, Alina, Xing Huang, Daniel Voyer, et al. 2019. “A Meta-Analysis of Sex
Differences in Human Navigation Skills.” Psychonomic Bulletin & Review.
Published online July 3, 2019.
Nédélec, Yohann, Joaquín Sanz, Golshid Baharian et al. 2016. “Genetic Ancestry and
Natural Selection Drive Population Differences in Immune Responses to
Pathogens.” Cell 167 (3): 657–69.e21.
Neisser, Ulric, Gwyneth Boodoo, T. J. Bouchard Jr. et al. 1996. “Intelligence: Knowns
and Unknowns.” American Psychologist 51 (2): 77–101.
Neves, Kleber, Gerson D. Guercio, Yuri Anjos-Travassos et al. 2018. “Lack of
Correlation Between Number of Neurons and Behavioral Performance in Swiss
Mice.” bioRxiv.
Newman, H. H., F. N. Freeman, and K. J. Holzinger. 1937. Twins: A Study of
Heredity and Environment. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Nguyen, Hannah-Hanh D., and Ann Marie Ryan. 2008. “Does Stereotype Threat
Affect Test Performance of Minorities and Women? A Meta-analysis of
Experimental Evidence.” Journal of Applied Psychology 93 (6): 1314–34.
Nielsen, Rasmus, Joshua M. Akey, Mattias Jakobsson et al. 2017. “Tracing the
Peopling of the World Through Genomics.” Nature 541 (7637): 302–10.
Noftle, Erik E., and Phillip R. Shaver. 2006. “Attachment Dimensions and the Big Five
Personality Traits: Associations and Comparative Ability to Predict Relationship
Quality.” Journal of Research in Personality 40 (2): 179–208.
Nolen-Hoeksema, S., J. Morrow, and B. L. Fredrickson. 1993. “Response Styles and
the Duration of Episodes of Depressed Mood.” Journal of Abnormal Psychology
102: 20–28.
Nolen-Hoeksema, S., L. E. Parker, and J. Larson. 1994. “Ruminative Coping with
Depressed Mood Following Loss.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology
67: 92–104.
Novembre, John, and Nicholas H. Barton. 2018. “Tread Lightly Interpreting Polygenic
Tests of Selection.” Genetics 208 (4): 1351–55.
Novembre, John, and Anna DiRienzo. 2009. “Spatial Patterns of Variation Due to
Natural Selection in Humans.” Nature Reviews Genetics 10: 745–55.
Novembre, John, and Benjamin M. Peter. 2016. “Recent Advances in the Study of
Fine-Scale Population Structure in Humans.” Current Opinion in Genetics and
Development (41): 98–105.
Okbay, Aysu, Jonathan P. Beauchamp, Mark Alan Fontana et al. 2016.
“Supplementary Information: Genome-Wide Association Study Identifies 74 Loci
Associated with Educational Attainment.” Nature 533 (7604).
Olafsen, K. S., J. A. Ronning, P. I. Kaaresen et al. 2006. “Joint Attention in Term and
Preterm Infants at 12 Months of Age: The Significant of Gender and Intervention
Based on Randomized Controlled Trial.” Infant Behavior and Development 29:
554–63.
Olalde, Iñigo, and Carles Lalueza-Fox. 2015. “Modern Humans’ Paleogenomics and
the New Evidences on the European Prehistory.” Science and Technology of
Archaeological Research 1 (1): 1–9.
Oleksyk, Taras K., Vladimir Brukhin, and Stephen J. O’Brien. 2015. “The Genome
Russia Project: Closing the Largest Remaining Omission on the World Genome
Map.” GigaScience 4 (1): 53.
Olsson, Andreas, Eleni Kopsida, Sorjonen Kimmo et al. 2016. “Testosterone and
Estrogen Impact Social Evaluations and Vicarious Emotions: A Double-Blind
Placebo-Controlled Study.” Emotion 16 (4): 515–23.
Omi, Michael, and Howard Winant. 1986. Racial Formation in the United States:
From the 1960s to the 1980s. New York: Routledge.
Ones, Deniz, S. Dilchert, and Chockalingam Viswesvaran. 2014. “Cognitive Abilities.”
In The Oxford Handbook of Personnel Assessment and Selection, edited by Neil
Schmitt, 179–224. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
1000 Genomes Project Consortium. 2012. “An Integrated Map of Genetic Variation
from 1,092 Human Genomes.” Nature 491 (7422): 56–65.
Otter, Maarten, Constance T. R. M. Schrander-Stumpel, and Leopold M. G. Curfs.
2010. “Triple X Syndrome: A Review of the Literature.” European Journal of
Human Genetics 18 (3): 265–71.
Pagani, Luca, Daniel John Lawson, Evelyn Jagoda et al. 2016. “Genomic Analyses
Inform on Migration Events During the Peopling of Eurasia.” Nature 538: 238–42.
Palmer, Benjamin R., Gilles Gignac, Ramesh Manocha et al. 2005. “A Psychometric
Evaluation of the Mayer–Salovey–Caruso Emotional Intelligence Test Version 2.0.”
Intelligence 33 (3): 285–305.
Papagianni, Dimitra, and Michael A. Morse. 2015. The Neanderthals Rediscovered:
How Modern Science Is Rewriting Their Story. New York: Thames & Hudson.
Parra, Esteban J. 2007. “Human Pigmentation Variation: Evolution, Genetic Basis, and
Implications for Public Health.” Yearbook of Physical Anthropology 50: 85–105.
Paunesku, David, Gregory M. Walton, Carissa Romero et al. 2015. “Mind-Set
Interventions Are a Scalable Treatment for Academic Underachievement.”
Psychological Science 26 (6): 784–93.
Pellegrini, Anthony D. 2007. “The Development and Function of Rough-and-Tumble
Play in Childhood and Adolescence: A Sexual Selection Theory Perspective.” In
Play and Development: Evolutionary, Sociocultural, and Functional Perspectives,
edited by Artin Göncü and Suzanne Gaskins, 77–98. New York: Erlbaum.
Pelphry, K. A., J. P. Morris, and G. McCarthy. 2005. “Neural Basis of Eye Gaze
Processing Deficits in Autism.” Brain 128 (Pt. 5): 1038–48.
Penner, Andrew M. 2003. “International Gender X Item Difficulty Interactions in
Mathematics and Science Achievement Tests.” Journal of Educational Psychology
95 (3): 650–55.
Pennington, Charlotte R., Damien Litchfield, Neil McLatchie et al. 2018. “Stereotype
Threat May Not Impact Women’s Inhibitory Control or Mathematical Performance:
Providing Support for the Null Hypothesis.” European Journal of Social Psychology
49 (4): 717–34.
Perez, Marcos Francisco, and Ben Lehner. 2019. “Intergenerational and
Transgenerational Epigenetic Inheritance in Animals.” Nature Cell Biology 21: 143–
51.
Peterson, Jennifer. 2018. “Gender Differences in Verbal Performance: A Meta-analysis
of United States State Performance Assessments.” Educational Psychology Review.
Published online September 3, 2018.
Pettersson, Erik, Jane Mendle, Eric Turkheimer et al. 2014. “Do Maladaptive
Behaviors Exist at One or Both Ends of Personality Traits?” Psychological
Assessment 26 (2): 433–66.
Phillips, Deborah A., Mark W. Lipsey, Kenneth A. Dodge et al. 2017. Puzzling It Out:
The Current State of Scientific Knowledge on Pre-kindergarten Effects: A
Consensus Statement. Washington, DC: Brookings Institution.
Phoenix, Charles H., Robert W. Goy, Arnold A. Gerall et al. 1959. “Organizing Action
of Prenatally Administered Testosterone Propionate on the Tissues Mediating Mating
Behavior in the Female Guinea Pig.” Endocrinology 65 (3): 369–82.
Picho, Katherine, Ariel Rodriguez, and Lauren Finnie. 2013. “Exploring the
Moderating Role of Context on the Mathematics Performance of Females Under
Stereotype Threat: A Meta-Analysis.” The Journal of Social Psychology 153 (3):
299–333.
Pickrell, Joseph K., Tomaz Berisa, Jimmy Z. Liu et al. 2016. “Detection and
Interpretation of Shared Genetic Influences on 42 Human Traits.” Nature Genetics
48: 709.
Pickrell, Joseph K., Graham Coop, John Novembre et al. 2009. “Signals of Recent
Positive Selection in a Worldwide Sample of Human Populations.” Genome
Research 19 (5): 826–37.
Pietschnig, Jakob, Lars Penke, Jelte M. Wicherts et al. 2015. “Meta-analysis of
Associations Between Human Brain Volume and Intelligence Differences: How
Strong Are They and What Do They Mean?” Neuroscience and Biobehavioral
Reviews 57: 411–32.
Pike, Alison, Shirley McGuire, E. Mavis Hetherington et al. 1996. “Family
Environment and Adolescent Depressive Symptoms and Antisocial Behavior: A
Multivariate Genetic Analysis.” Developmental Psychology 32 (4): 590–604.
Pinker, Steven. 2002. The Blank Slate: The Modern Denial of Human Nature. New
York: Viking Penguin.
Plomin, Robert. 2011. “Commentary: Why Are Children in the Same Family So
Different? Non-shared Environment Three Decades Later.” International Journal of
Epidemiology 40 (3): 582–92.
. 2018. Blueprint: How DNA Makes Us Who We Are. Cambridge, MA: MIT
Press.
Plomin, Robert, and Denise Daniels. 1987. “Why Are Children in the Same Family So
Different from One Another?” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 10: 1–60.
Plomin, Robert, and J. C. DeFries. 1983. “The Colorado Adoption Project.” Child
Development 54 (2): 276–89.
Plomin, Robert, G. E. McClearn, D. L. Smith et al. 1994. “DNA Markers Associated
with High Versus Low IQ: The IQ Quantitative Trait Loci (QTL) Project.” Behavior
Genetics 24 (2): 107–18.
Plomin, Robert, and Frank M. Spinath. 2004. “Intelligence: Genetics, Genes, and
Genomics.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 86 (1): 112–29.
Polderman, Tinca J. C., Beben Benyamin, Christiaan A. de Leeuw et al. 2015. “Meta-
analysis of the Heritability of Human Traits Based on Fifty Years of Twin Studies.”
Nature Genetics 47: 702–9.
Poldrack, Russell A., J. A. Mumford, and Thomas E. Nichols. 2011. Handbook of
fMRI Data Analysis. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Pomiankowski, Andrew, and A. P. Møller. 1995. “A Resolution of the Lek Paradox.”
Proceedings of the Royal Society B 260: 21–29.
Poropat, Arthur E. 2014. “A Meta-analysis of Adult-Rated Child Personality and
Academic Performance in Primary Education.” British Journal of Educational
Psychology 84 (2): 239–52.
Posth, Cosimo, Christoph Wiβing, Keiko Kitagawa et al. 2017. “Deeply Divergent
Archaic Mitochondrial Genome Provides Lower Time Boundary for African Gene
Flow into Neanderthals.” Nature Communications 8: 16046.
Poznik, G. David, Brenna M. Henn, Muh-Ching Yee et al. 2013. “Sequencing Y
Chromosomes Resolves Discrepancy in Time to Common Ancestor of Males Versus
Females.” Science 341 (6145): 562.
Prediger, Dale J. 1982. “Dimensions Underlying Holland’s Hexagon: Missing Link
Between Interests and Occupations?” Journal of Vocational Behavior 21 (3): 259–
87.
Premack, David, and Guy Woodruff. 1978. “Does the Chimpanzee Have a Theory of
Mind?” Behavioral and Brain Sciences 1 (4): 515–26.
Pritchard, Jonathan K., Matthew Stephens, and Peter Donnelly. 2000. “Inference of
Population Structure Using Multilocus Genotype Data.” Genetics 155 (2): 945.
Protzko, John, and Joshua Aronson. 2016. “Context Moderates Affirmation Effects on
the Ethnic Achievement Gap.” Social Psychological and Personality Science 7 (6):
500–507.
Ramachandran, Sohini, Omkar Deshpande, Charles C. Roseman et al. 2005. “Support
from the Relationship of Genetic and Geographic Distance in Human Populations for
a Serial Founder Effect Originating in Africa.” Proceedings of the National Academy
of Sciences 102 (44): 15942–47.
Ramel, W., P. R. Goldin, L. T. Eyler et al. 2007. “Amygdala Reactivity and Mood-
Congruent Memory in Individuals at Risk for Depressive Relapse.” Biological
Psychiatry 61 (2): 231–39.
Ranke, M. B., and P. Saenger. 2001. “Turner’s Syndrome.” Lancet 358: 309–14.
Raymond, Cindy L., and Camilla P. Benbow. 1986. “Gender Differences in
Mathematics: A Function of Parental Support and Student Sex Typing?”
Developmental Psychology 22 (6): 808–19.
Reardon, P. K., Jakob Seidlitz, Simon Vandekar et al. 2018. “Normative Brain Size
Variation and Brain Shape Diversity in Humans.” Science 360 (6394): 1222.
Reich, David. 2018. Who We Are and How We Got Here: Ancient DNA and the New
Science of the Human Past. New York: Pantheon.
Reilly, David, David L. Neumann, and Glenda Andrews. 2015. “Sex Differences in
Mathematics and Science Achievement: A Meta-analysis of National Assessment of
Educational Progress Assessments.” Journal of Educational Psychology 107 (3):
645–62.
. 2018. “Gender Differences in Reading and Writing Achievement: Evidence
from the National Assessment of Educational Progress (NAEP).” American
Psychologist 74 (4): 445–58.
Reinhold, Klaus, and Leif Engqvist. 2013. “The Variability Is in the Sex
Chromosomes.” Evolution 67 (12): 3662–68.
Reisberg, Sulev, Tatjana Iljasenko, Kristi Läll et al. 2017. “Comparing Distributions of
Polygenic Risk Scores of Type 2 Diabetes and Coronary Heart Disease Within
Different Populations.” PLoS ONE 12 (7): e0179238.
Reynolds, Cecil R., Robert L. Chastain, Alan S. Kaufman et al. 1987. “Demographic
Characteristics and IQ Among Adults: Analysis of the WAIS-R Standardization
Sample as a Function of the Stratification Variables.” Journal of School Psychology
25: 323–42.
Reynolds, Matthew R., Caroline Scheiber, Daniel B. Hajovsky et al. 2015. “Gender
Differences in Academic Achievement: Is Writing an Exception to the Gender
Similarities Hypothesis?” Journal of Genetic Psychology 176 (4): 211–34.
Rhemtulla, Mijke, and Elliot M. Tucker-Drob. 2012. “Gene-by-Socioeconomic Status
Interaction on School Readiness.” Behavior Genetics 42: 549–58.
Rhodes, Gillian, Linda Jeffery, Tamara L. Watson et al. 2004. “Orientation-Contingent
Face Aftereffects and Implications for Face-Coding Mechanisms.” Current Biology
14 (23): 2119–23.
Richards, M., and A. Sacker. 2003. “Lifetime Antecedents of Cognitive Reserve.”
Journal of Clinical and Experimental Psychology 25: 614–24.
Richardson, Ken, and Sarah H. Norgate. 2015. “Does IQ Really Predict Job
Performance?” Applied Developmental Science 19 (3): 153–69.
Richter, Daniel, Rainer Grün, Renaud Joannes-Boyau et al. 2017. “The Age of the
Hominin Fossils from Jebel Irhoud, Morocco, and the Origins of the Middle Stone
Age.” Nature 546: 293.
Richters, Juliet, Dennis Altman, Paul B. Badcock et al. 2014. “Sexual Identity, Sexual
Attraction and Sexual Experience: The Second Australian Study of Health and
Relationships.” Sexual Health 11 (5): 451–60.
Riès, Stéphanie K., Nina F. Dronkers, and Robert T. Knight. 2016. “Choosing Words:
Left Hemisphere, Right Hemisphere, or Both? Perspective on the Lateralization of
Word Retrieval.” Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences 1369 (1): 111–31.
Risch, Neil, and Kathleen Merikangas. 1996. “The Future of Genetic Studies of
Complex Human Diseases.” Science 273 (September 13): 1516–17.
Risch, Neil, Donna Spiker, Linda Lotspeich et al. 1999. “A Genomic Screen of Autism:
Evidence for a Multilocus Etiology.” American Journal of Human Genetics 65 (2):
493–507.
Ritchie, Stuart J. 2015. Intelligence: All That Matters. London: Hodder & Stoughton.
Ritchie, Stuart J., Simon R. Cox, Xueyi Shen et al. 2018. “Sex Differences in the Adult
Human Brain: Evidence from 5216 UK Biobank Participants.” Cerebral Cortex 28
(8): 2959–75.
Ritchie, Stuart J., and Elliot M. Tucker-Drob. 2018. “How Much Does Education
Improve Intelligence? A Meta-analysis.” Psychological Science 29 (8): 1358–69.
Rivas, Manuel A., Brandon E. Avila, Jukka Koskela et al. 2018. “Insights into the
Genetic Epidemiology of Crohn’s and Rare Diseases in the Ashkenazi Jewish
Population.” PLoS Genetics 14 (5): e1007329.
Roalf, David R., Raquel E. Gur, Kosha Ruparel et al. 2014. “Within-Individual
Variability in Neurocognitive Performance: Age-and Sex-Related Differences in
Children and Youths from Ages 8 to 21.” Neuropsychology 28 (4): 506–18.
Rojas, D. C., S. D. Bawn, T. L. Benkers et al. 2002. “Smaller Left Hemisphere
Planum Temporale in Adults with Autistic Disorder.” Neuroscience Letters 328:
237–40.
Ronald, James, and Joshua M. Akey. 2005. “Genome-Wide Scans for Loci Under
Selection in Humans.” Human Genomics 2 (2): 113–25.
Rosen, Sarah, Boram Ham, and Jeffrey S. Mogil. 2017. “Sex Differences in
Neuroimmunity and Pain.” Journal of Neuroscience Research 95 (1–2): 500–508.
Rosenberg, Alex. 2017. “Why Social Science Is Biological Science.” Journal for
General Philosophy of Science 48 (3): 341–69.
Rosenberg, Noah A. 2018. “Variance-Partitioning and Classification in Human
Population Genetics.” In Phylogenetic Inference, Selection Theory, and History of
Science: Selected Papers of A. W. F. Edwards with Commentaries, edited by
Rasmus Grønfeldt Winther, 399–402. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Rosenberg, Noah A., Saurabh Mahajan, Sohini Ramachandran et al. 2005. “Clines,
Clusters, and the Effect of Study Design on the Inference of Human Population
Structure.” PLoS Genetics 1 (6): e70.
Rosenberg, Noah A., J. K. Pritchard, J. L. Weber et al. 2002. “Genetic Structure of
Human Populations.” Science 298 (5602): 2381–85.
Rosenblatt, Jonathan D. 2016. “Multivariate Revisit to ‘Sex Beyond the Genitalia.’”
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 113 (14): E1966–67.
Rosenthal, Robert, and Donald B. Rubin. 1982. “Further Meta-analytic Procedures for
Assessing Cognitive Gender Differences.” Journal of Educational Psychology 74:
708–12.
Rosip, J. C., and Judith A. Hall. 2004. “Knowledge of Nonverbal Cues, Gender, and
Nonverbal Decoding Accuracy.” Journal of Nonverbal Behavior 28 (4): 276–86.
Rosnow, Ralph L., and Robert Rosenthal. 2003. “Effect Sizes for Experimenting
Psychologists.” Canadian Journal of Experimental Psychology 57 (3): 221–37.
Rothbaum, Fred, and John R. Weisz. 1994. “Parental Caregiving and Child
Externalizing Behavior in Nonclinical Samples: A Meta-analysis.” Psychological
Bulletin 116 (1): 55–74.
Rowe, David C., Kristen C. Jacobson, and Edwin J. C. G. Van den Oord. 1999.
“Genetic and Environmental Influences on Vocabulary IQ: Parental Education Level
as Moderator.” Child Development 70 (5): 1151–62.
Rowe, David C., and Robert Plomin. 1981. “The Importance of Nonshared (E1)
Environmental Influences on Behavioral Development.” Developmental Psychology
17: 517–31.
Rubin, Leah H., Li Yao, Sarah K. Keedy et al. 2017. “Sex Differences in Associations
of Arginine Vasopressin and Oxytocin with Resting-State Functional Brain
Connectivity.” Journal of Neuroscience Research 95 (1–2): 576–86.
Ruigrok, Amber N. V., Gholamreza Salimi-Khorshidi, Meng-Chuan Lai et al. 2014. “A
Meta-analysis of Sex Differences in Human Brain Structure.” Neuroscience and
Biobehavioral Reviews 39: 34–50.
Sabeti, Pardis C., Stephen F. Schaffner, Ben Fry et al. 2006. “Positive Natural
Selection in the Human Lineage.” Science 312 (June 16).
Sackett, Paul R., Chaitra M. Hardison, and Michael J. Cullen. 2004. “On Interpreting
Stereotype Threat as Accounting for African American–White Differences on
Cognitive Tests.” American Psychologist 59 (1): 7–13.
Sackett, Paul R., Nathan R. Kuncel, Justin J. Arneson et al. 2009. “Does
Socioeconomic Status Explain the Relationship Between Admissions Tests and Post-
secondary Academic Performance?” Psychological Bulletin 135 (1): 1–22.
Sagi, A., and M. L. Hoffman. 1976. “Empathic Distress in the Newborn.”
Developmental Psychology 12: 175–76.
Sahakian, Barbara J., and Julia Gottwald. 2017. Sex, Lies, and Brain Scans: How
fMRI Reveals What Really Goes On in Our Minds. Oxford: Oxford University
Press.
Sandberg, D. E., and H. F. L. Meyer-Bahlburg. 1994. “Variability in Middle Childhood
Play Behavior: Effects of Gender, Age, and Family Background.” Archives of
Sexual Behavior 23: 645–63.
Sandler, L., and E. Novitski. 1957. “Meiotic Drive as an Evolutionary Force.”
American Naturalist 91 (857): 105–10.
Sankararaman, Sriram, Swapan Mallick, Michael Dannemann et al. 2014. “The
Genomic Landscape of Neanderthal Ancestry in Present-Day Humans.” Nature 507:
354–57.
Sapienza, Paola, Luigi Zingales, and Dario Maestripieri. 2009. “Gender Differences in
Financial Risk Aversion and Career Choices Are Affected by Testosterone.”
Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 106 (36): 15268–73.
Satel, Sally, and Scott O. Lilienfeld. 2015. Brainwashed: The Seductive Appeal of
Mindless Neuroscience. New York: Basic Books.
Satterthwaite, Theodore D., Daniel H. Wolf, David R. Roalf et al. 2015. “Linked Sex
Differences in Cognition and Functional Connectivity in Youth.” Cerebral Cortex 25:
2383–94.
Sauce, Bruno, and Louis Matzel. 2018. “The Paradox of Intelligence: Heritability and
Malleability Coexist in Hidden Gene-Environment Interplay.” Psychological Bulletin
144.
Savic, Ivanka, Louise Frisen, Amirhossein Manzouri et al. 2017. “Role of Testosterone
and Y Chromosome Genes for the Masculinization of the Human Brain.” Human
Brain Mapping 38 (4): 1801–14.
Savic, Ivanka, Alicia Garcia-Falgueras, and Dick F. Swaab. 2010. “Sexual
Differentiation of the Human Brain in Relation to Gender Identity and Sexual
Orientation.” Progress in Brain Research 186: 41–62.
Savin-Williams, Ritch C., and Kenneth M. Cohen. 2018. “Prevalence, Mental Health,
and Heterogeneity of Bisexual Men.” Current Sexual Health Reports 10 (3): 196–
202.
Savin-Williams, Ritch C., and Zhana Vrangalova. 2013. “Mostly Heterosexual as a
Distinct Sexual Orientation Group: A Systematic Review of the Empirical Evidence.”
Developmental Review 33 (1): 58–88.
Sawilowsky, Shlomo S. 2009. “New Effect Size Rules of Thumb.” Journal of Modern
Applied Statistical Methods 8 (2): 597–99.
Sax, Leonard. 2002. “How Common Is Intersex? A Response to Anne Fausto-
Sterling.” Journal of Sex Research 39 (3): 174–78.
Sayre, Anne. 2000. Rosalind Franklin and DNA. New York: W. W. Norton.
Scarr, Sandra, and Susan Grajek. 1982. “Similarities and Differences Among Siblings.”
In Sibling Relationships: Their Nature and Significance Across the Lifespan,
edited by M. E. Lamb and B. Sutton-Smith. Hillsdale, NJ: Erlbaum.
Scarr-Salapatek, Sandra. 1971. “Race, Social Class, and IQ.” Science 4: 1285–95.
Scerri, Eleanor M. L., Mark G. Thomas, Andrea Manica et al. 2018. “Did Our Species
Evolve in Subdivided Populations Across Africa, and Why Does It Matter?” Trends
in Ecology and Evolution 33 (8): 582–94.
Scheiber, Caroline, Matthew R. Reynolds, Daniel B. Hajovsky et al. 2015. “Gender
Differences in Achievement in a Large, Nationally Representative Sample of
Children and Adolescents.” Psychology in the Schools 52 (4): 335–48.
Scheper-Hughes, Nancy. 1995. “The Primacy of the Ethical: Propositions for a
Militant Anthropology.” Current Anthropology 36 (3): 409–40.
Scherbaum, C. A., P. J. Hanges, K. Yusko et al. 2012. “The Spearman Hypothesis
Cannot Explain All Racial Score Differences.” Annual Meeting of the Society for
Industrial and Organizational Psychology.
Schiffels, Stephan, and Richard Durbin. 2014. “Inferring Human Population Size and
Separation History from Multiple Genome Sequences.” Nature Genetics 46 (8):
919–25.
Schmid, P. C., M. Schmid Mast, D. Bombari et al. 2011. “Gender Effects in
Information Processing on a Nonverbal Decoding Task.” Sex Roles 65: 102–7.
Schmitt, David P., A. E. Long, A. McPhearson et al. 2016. “Personality and Gender
Differences in Global Perspective.” International Journal of Psychology 52 (51):
45–56.
Schmitt, David P., A. Realo, M. Voracek et al. 2008. “Why Can’t a Man Be More Like
a Woman? Sex Differences in Big Five Personality Traits Across 55 Cultures.”
Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 94 (1): 168–82.
Schraiber, Joshua G., and Joshua M. Akey. 2015. “Methods and Models for
Unravelling Human Evolutionary History.” Nature Reviews Genetics 16 (12): 727–
40.
Schrider, Daniel R., and Andrew D. Kern. 2017. “Soft Sweeps Are the Dominant
Mode of Adaptation in the Human Genome.” Molecular Biology and Evolution 34
(8): 1863–77.
Schwartz, C. E., C. I. Wright, L. M. Shin et al. 2003. “Inhibited and Uninhibited
Infants ‘Grown Up’: Adult Amygdalar Response to Novelty.” Science 300 (5627):
1952–53.
Scutari, Marco, Ian Mackay, and David Balding. 2016. “Using Genetic Distance to
Infer the Accuracy of Genomic Prediction.” PLoS Genetics 12 (9): e1006288.
Segerstråle, Ullica. 2000. Defenders of the Truth: The Sociobiology Debate. Oxford:
Oxford University Press.
Seguin-Orlando, Andaine, Thorfinn S. Korneliussen, Martin Sikora et al. 2014.
“Genomic Structure in Europeans Dating Back at Least 36,200 Years.” Science 346
(6213): 1113.
Sehlmeyer, C., U. Dannlowski, S. Schöning et al. 2011. “Neural Correlates of Trait
Anxiety in Fear Extinction.” Psychological Medicine 41 (4): 789–98.
Seidlitz, Larry, and Ed Diener. 1998. “Sex Differences in the Recall of Affective
Experiences.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 74 (1): 262–71.
Sela, Yael, and Nicole Barbaro. 2018. “Evolutionary Perspectives on Personality and
Individual Differences.” In The Sage Handbook of Personality and Individual
Differences, edited by Virgil Zeigler-Hill and Todd K. Shackelford, 203–28. London:
Sage Publications.
Selzam, Saskia, Stuart J. Ritchie, Jean-Baptiste Pingault et al. 2019. “Comparing
Within-and Between-Family Polygenic Score Prediction.” bioRxiv: 605006.
Serre, David, and Svante Pääbo. 2004. “Evidence for Gradients of Human Genetic
Diversity Within and Among Continents.” Genome Research 14 (9): 1679–85.
Shanahan, Michael J., Shawn Bauldry, Brent W. Roberts et al. 2014. “Personality and
the Reproduction of Social Class.” Social Forces 93 (1): 209–40.
Shaw, George Bernard. 1891. The Quintessence of Ibsenism. London: Walter Scott.
Shaywitz, S. E., B. A. Shaywitz, K. R. Pugh et al. 1998. “Functional Disruption in the
Organization of the Brain for Reading in Dyslexia.” Proceedings of the National
Academy of Sciences 95: 2636–41.
Shea, Daniel L., David Lubinski, and Camilla P. Benbow. 2001. “Importance of
Assessing Spatial Ability in Intellectually Talented Young Adolescents: A 20-Year
Longitudinal Study.” Journal of Educational Psychology 93: 604–14.
Shewach, Oren R., Paul R. Sackett, and Sander Quint. 2019. “Stereotype Threat
Effects in Settings with Features Likely Versus Unlikely in Operational Test Settings:
A Meta-Analysis.” Journal of Applied Psychology. In press.
Shiao, Jiannbin Lee, Thomas Bode, Amber Beyer et al. 2012. “The Genomic
Challenge to the Social Construction of Race.” Sociological Theory 30 (2): 67–88.
Shin, L. M., C. I. Wright, P. A. Cannistraro et al. 2005. “A Functional Magnetic
Resonance Imaging Study of Amygdala and Medial Prefrontal Cortex Responses to
Overtly Presented Fearful Faces in Posttraumatic Stress Disorder.” Archives of
General Psychiatry 62 (3): 273–81.
Simmons, Joseph P., Leif D. Nelson, and Uri Simonsohn. 2011. “False-Positive
Psychology: Undisclosed Flexibility in Data Collection and Analysis Allows
Presenting Anything as Significant.” Psychological Science 22 (11): 1359–66.
Simner, Marvin. 1971. “Newborn’s Response to the Cry of Another Infant.”
Developmental Psychology 5 (1): 136–50.
Sirugo, Giorgio, Scott M. Williams, and Sarah A. Tishkoff. 2019. “The Missing
Diversity in Human Genetic Studies.” Cell 177 (March 21): 26–31.
Sisk, Victoria F., Alexander P. Burgoyne, Jingze Sun et al. 2018. “To What Extent and
Under Which Circumstances Are Growth Mind-Sets Important to Academic
Achievement? Two Meta-analyses.” Psychological Science 29 (4): 549–71.
Skinner, B. F. 1938. The Behavior of Organisms: An Experimental Analysis. New
York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.
Smith, Adam. 1776. An Inquiry in the Nature and Causes of the Wealth of Nations.
London: W. Strahan.
. 1979. The Theory of Moral Sentiments. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Original edition 1759.
Smith, Kerri. 2017. “The Brain Circuit Challenge.” Nature 548: 150–52.
Smouse, Peter E., Richard S. Spielman, and Myoung H. Park. 1982. “Multiple-Locus
Allocation of Individuals to Groups as a Function of the Genetic Variation Within and
Differences Among Human Populations.” American Naturalist 119 (4): 445–63.
Soden-Hensler, Brooke. 2012. “An Examination of Gene × Socioeconomic Status
Interactions for Reading Achievement.” PhD dissertation, Florida State University.
Sodini, Sebastian M., Kathryn E. Kemper, Naomi R. Wray et al. 2018. “Comparison
of Genotypic and Phenotypic Correlations: Cheverud’s Conjecture in Humans.”
Genetics 209 (3): 941–48.
Sohail, Mashaal, Robert M. Maier, Andrea Ganna et al. 2018. “Signals of Polygenic
Adaptation on Height Have Been Overestimated Due to Uncorrected Population
Structure in Genome-Wide Association Studies.” bioRxiv.
Sosnowski, David W., Carolyn Booth, Timothy P. York et al. 2018. “Maternal Prenatal
Stress and Infant DNA Methylation: A Systematic Review.” Developmental
Psychobiology 60 (2): 127–39.
Soutschek, Alexander, Christopher J. Burke, Anjali Raja Beharelle et al. 2017. “The
Dopaminergic Reward System Underpins Gender Differences in Social
Preferences.” Nature Human Behaviour 1 (11): 819–27.
Sowell, Elizabeth R., Bradley S. Peterson, Eric Kan et al. 2007. “Sex Differences in
Cortical Thickness Mapped in 176 Healthy Individuals Between 7 and 87 Years of
Age.” Cerebral Cortex 17 (7): 1550–60.
Speiser, Phyllis W., Eric S. Knochenhauer, Didier Dewailly et al. 2000. “A Multicenter
Study of Women with Nonclassical Congenital Adrenal Hyperplasia: Relationship
Between Genotype and Phenotype.” Molecular Genetics and Metabolism 71: 527–
34.
Spengler, Marion, Juliana Gottschling, Elisabeth Hahn et al. 2018. “Does the
Heritability of Cognitive Abilities Vary as a Function of Parental Education?
Evidence from a German Twin Sample.” PLoS ONE 13 (5): e0196597.
Spinath, Birgit, Frank M. Spinath, Nicole Harlaar et al. 2006. “Predicting School
Achievement from General Cognitive Ability, Self-Perceived Ability, and Intrinsic
Value.” Intelligence 34 (4): 363–74.
Spiro, Melford E. 1954. “Is the Family Universal?” American Anthropologist 56: 839–
46.
Sporns, Olaf. 2006. “Small-World Connectivity, Motif Composition, and Complexity of
Fractal Neuronal Connections.” Biosystems 85: 55–64.
. 2011. “The Human Connectome: A Complex Network.” Annals of the New
York Academy of Sciences 1224 (1): 109–25.
Staff, R. T., M. J. Hogan, and L. J. Whalley. 2017. “Childhood Intelligence and
Personality Traits Neuroticism and Openness Contributes to Social Mobility: A Study
in the Aberdeen 1936 Birth Cohort.” Personality and Individual Differences 114:
206–12.
Stankov, Lazar. 2013. “Noncognitive Predictors of Intelligence and Academic
Achievement: An Important Role of Confidence.” Personality and Individual
Differences 55 (7): 727–32.
Stanovich, Keith E. 1986. “Matthew Effects in Reading: Some Consequences of
Individual Differences in the Acquisition of Literacy.” Reading Research Quarterly
16: 32–71.
St. Clair, D., M. Xu, P. Wang et al. 2005. “Rates of Adult Schizophrenia Following
Prenatal Exposure to the Chinese Famine of 1959–1961.” JAMA 294 (5): 557–62.
Steele, Claude M., and Joshua Aronson. 1995. “Stereotype Threat and the Intellectual
Test Performance of African Americans.” Journal of Personality and Social
Psychology 69: 797–811.
Stevens, Jennifer S., and Stephan Hamann. 2012. “Sex Differences in Brain Activation
to Emotional Stimuli: A Meta-analysis of Neuroimaging Studies.” Neuropsychologia
50 (7): 1578–93.
Stewart, J. R., and C. B. Stringer. 2012. “Human Evolution out of Africa: The Role of
Refugia and Climate Change.” Science 335 (March 16).
Stewart-Williams, Steve. 2018. The Ape That Understood the Universe: How the
Mind and Culture Evolve. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Stewart-Williams, Steve, and Andrew G. Thomas. 2013. “The Ape That Thought It
Was a Peacock: Does Evolutionary Psychology Exaggerate Human Sex
Differences?” Psychological Inquiry 24 (3): 137–68.
Stiles, Joan, and Terry L. Jernigan. 2010. “The Basics of Brain Development.”
Neuropsychological Review 20: 327–48.
Stoet, Gijsbert, and David C. Geary. 2012. “Can Stereotype Threat Explain the Gender
Gap in Mathematics Performance and Achievement?” Review of General
Psychology 16 (1): 93–102.
. 2013. “Sex Differences in Mathematics and Reading Achievement Are
Inversely Related: Within-and Across-Nation Assessment of 10 Years of Pisa Data.”
PLoS ONE 8 (3): e57988.
. 2015. “Sex Differences in Academic Achievement Are Not Related to Political,
Economic, or Social Equality.” Intelligence 48: 137–51.
. 2018. “The Gender-Equality Paradox in Science, Technology, Engineering, and
Mathematics Education.” Psychological Science 29 (4): 0956797617741719.
Stormshak, Elizabeth A., Karen L. Bierman, Robert J. McMahon et al. 2000.
“Parenting Practices and Child Disruptive Behavior Problems in Early Elementary
School.” Journal of Clinical Child Psychology 29 (1): 17–29.
Strand, Steve, Ian J. Deary, and Pauline Smith. 2006. “Sex Differences in Cognitive
Abilities Test Scores: A UK National Picture.” British Journal of Educational
Psychology 76: 463–80.
Strenze, Tarmo. 2007. “Intelligence and Socioeconomic Success: A Meta-analytic
Review of Longitudinal Research.” Intelligence 35 (5): 401–26.
Stringer, C. B., and P. Andrews. 1988. “The Origin of Modern Humans.” Science 239:
1263–68.
Su, Rong. 2018. “The Three Faces of Interests: An Integrative Review of Interest
Research in Vocational, Organizational, and Educational Psychology.” Journal of
Vocational Behavior.
Su, Rong, and James Rounds. 2015. “All STEM Fields Are Not Created Equal: People
and Things Interests Explain Gender Disparities Across STEM Fields.” Frontiers in
Psychology 6: 189.
Su, Rong, James Rounds, and P. I. Armstrong. 2009. “Men and Things, Women and
People: A Meta-analysis of Sex Differences in Interests.” Psychological Bulletin
135 (6): 859–84.
Summers, Lawrence H. 2005. “Remarks at NBER Conference on Diversifying the
Science & Engineering Workforce.” NBER Conference on Diversifying the Science
& Engineering Workforce, Cambridge, MA.
Susser, E., and S. P. Lin. 1992. “Schizophrenia After Prenatal Exposure to the Dutch
Hunger Winter of 1944–1945.” Archives of General Psychiatry 49: 983–88.
Swanwick, Helena Maria. 1913. The Future of the Women’s Movement. London: G.
Bell & Sons.
Tang, Hua, Jie Peng, Pei Wang et al. 2005. “Estimation of Individual Admixture:
Analytical and Study Design Considerations.” Genetic Epidemiology 28: 289–301.
Takeuchi, Fumihiko, Masato Akiyama, Nana Matoba et al. 2018. “Interethnic Analyses
of Blood Pressure Loci in Populations of East Asian and European Descent.” Nature
Communications 9 (1): 5052.
Tang, Hua, T. Quertermous, Beatriz Rodriguez et al. 2005. “Genetic Structure, Self-
Identified Race/Ethnicity, and Confounding in Case-Control Association Studies.”
American Journal of Human Genetics 76: 268–75.
Tay, Louis, Rong Su, and James Rounds. 2011. “People-Things and Data-Ideas:
Bipolar Dimensions?” Journal of Counseling Psychology 58 (3): 424–40.
Taylor, Howard Francis. 1980. The IQ Game: A Methodological Inquiry into the
Heredity-Environment Controversy. New Brunswick, NJ: Rutgers University Press.
Telenti, Amalio, Levi C. T. Pierce, William H. Biggs et al. 2016. “Deep Sequencing of
10,000 Human Genomes.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 113
(42): 11901.
Tennessen, Jacob A., Abigail W. Bigham, Timothy D. O’Connor et al. 2012.
“Evolution and Functional Impact of Rare Coding Variation from Deep Sequencing
of Human Exomes.” Science 337 (6090): 64.
Thaler, R. H., and C. Sunstein (2008). Nudge: Improving Decisions About Health,
Wealth, and Happiness. New York: Penguin.
Thomas, Duncan C., and John S. Witte. 2002. “Point: Population Stratification: A
Problem for Case-Control Studies of Candidate-Gene Associations?” Cancer
Epidemiology Biomarkers and Prevention 11 (6): 505–12.
Thomas, J. R., and K. E. French. 1985. “Gender Differences Across Age in Motor
Performance: A Meta-analysis.” Psychological Bulletin 98: 260–82.
Thomas, K. M., W. C. Drevets, P. J. Whalen et al. 2001. “Amygdala Response to
Facial Expressions in Children and Adults.” Biological Psychiatry 49 (4): 309–16.
Thompson, Ashley, and Daniel Voyer. 2014. “Sex Differences in the Ability to
Recognise Non-verbal Displays of Emotion: A Meta-analysis.” Cognition and
Emotion 28 (7): 1164–95.
Thorndike, Edward L. 1911. Individuality. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.
Timmermann, Axel, and Tobias Friedrich. 2016. “Late Pleistocene Climate Drivers of
Early Human Migration.” Nature 538 (7623): 92–95.
Tobi, Elmar W., Roderick C. Slieker, René Luijk et al. 2018. “DNA Methylation as a
Mediator of the Association Between Prenatal Adversity and Risk Factors for
Metabolic Disease in Adulthood.” Science Advances 4 (1).
Tooby, John, and Leda Cosmides. 1992. “The Psychological Foundations of Culture.”
In The Adapted Mind: Evolutionary Psychology and the Generation of Culture,
edited by Jerome H. Barkow, John Tooby, and Leda Cosmides, 19–136. New York:
Oxford University Press.
Trivers, Robert. 1972. “Parental Investment and Sexual Selection.” In Sexual Selection
and the Descent of Man, edited by B. B. Campbell, 136–79. Chicago: Aldine.
. 2011. The Folly of Fools: The Logic of Deceit and Self-Deception in Human
Life. New York: Basic Books.
Trut, Lyudmila. 1999. “Early Canid Domestication: The Farm-Fox Experiment.”
American Scientist 87 (March–April): 160–69.
Trzaskowski, M., N. Harlaar, R. Arden et al. 2014. “Genetic Influence on Family
Socioeconomic Status and Children’s Intelligence.” Intelligence 42 (100): 83–88.
Tucci, Serena, and Joshua M. Akey. 2016. “A Map of Human Wanderlust.” Nature
538: 179–80.
Tucker-Drob, Elliot M., and Timothy C. Bates. 2015. “Large Cross-National
Differences in Gene × Socioeconomic Status Interaction on Intelligence.”
Psychological Science 27 (2): 138–49.
Tucker-Drob, Elliot M., Daniel A. Briley, Laura Engelhardt et al. 2016. “Genetically-
Mediated Associations Between Measures of Childhood Character and Academic
Achievement.” Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 111 (5): 790–815.
Tucker-Drob, Elliot M., Daniel A. Briley, and K. Paige Harden. 2013. “Genetic and
Environmental Influences on Cognition Across Development and Context.” Current
Directions in Psychological Science 22 (5): 349–55.
Tucker-Drob, Elliot M., and K. Paige Harden. 2017. “A Behavioral Genetic
Perspective on Non-cognitive Factors and Academic Achievement.” In Genetics,
Ethics, and Education, edited by Susan Bouregy, Elena L. Grigorenko, Stephen R.
Latham et al., 134–58. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Tucker-Drob, Elliot M., Mijke Rhemtulla, K. Paige Harden et al. 2011. “Emergence of
a Gene × Socioeconomic Status Interaction on Infant Mental Ability Between 10
Months and 2 Years.” Psychological Science 22 (1): 125–33.
Tunç, Birkan, Berkan Solmaz, Drew Parker et al. 2016. “Establishing a Link Between
Sex-Related Differences in the Structural Connectome and Behaviour.”
Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 371
(1688): 20150111.
Turecki, Gustavo, and Michael J. Meaney. 2016. “Effects of the Social Environment
and Stress on Glucocorticoid Receptor Gene Methylation: A Systematic Review.”
Biological Psychiatry 79 (2): 87–96.
Turkheimer, Eric. 2000. “Three Laws of Behavior Genetics and What They Mean.”
Current Directions in Psychological Science 5: 160–64.
. 2011. “Commentary: Variation and Causation in the Environment and
Genome.” International Journal of Epidemiology 40 (3): 598–601.
. 2019. “Genetics and Human Agency: The Philosophy of Behavior Genetics
Introduction to the Special Issue.” Behavior Genetics 49 (2): 123–27.
Turkheimer, Eric, Brian M. D’Onofrio, Hermine H. Maes et al. 2005. “Analysis and
Interpretation of Twin Studies Including Measures of the Shared Environment.”
Child Development 76 (6): 1217–33.
Turkheimer, Eric, Andreana Haley, Mary Waldron et al. 2003. “Socioeconomic Status
Modifies Heritability of IQ in Young Children.” Psychological Science 14 (6): 623–
28.
Turkheimer, Eric, Erik Pettersson, and Erin E. Horn. 2014. “A Phenotypic Null
Hypothesis for the Genetics of Personality.” Annual Review of Psychology 65 (1):
515–40.
Turkheimer, Eric, and Mary Waldron. 2000. “Nonshared Environment: A Theoretical,
Methodological, and Quantitative Review.” Psychological Bulletin 126 (1): 78–108.
Twenge, Jean M. 2006. Generation Me: Why Today’s Young Americans Are More
Confident, Assertive, Entitled—and More Miserable Than Ever Before. New York:
Free Press.
Udry, J. Richard. 2000. “Biological Limits of Gender Construction.” American
Sociological Review 65: 443–57.
Udry, J. Richard, Naomi M. Morris, and Judith Kovenock. 1995. “Androgen Effects
on Women’s Gendered Behaviour.” Journal of Biosocial Science 27 (3): 359–68.
UKK Consortium. 2015. “The UK10K Project Identifies Rare Variants in Health and
Disease.” Nature 526: 82–90.
Unterman, Rebecca. 2017. An Early Look at the Effects of Success Academy Charter
Schools. New York: MDRC.
U.S. Department of Health and Human Services, Administration for Children and
Families. 2010. Head Start Impact Study: Final Report. Washington, DC.
Valla, Jeffrey M., and Stephen J. Ceci. 2014. “Breadth-Based Models of Women’s
Underrepresentation in STEM Fields: An Integrative Commentary on Schmidt
(2011) and Nye et al. (2012).” Perspectives on Psychological Science 9 (2): 219–
24.
Valla, Jeffrey M., Barbara L. Ganzel, Keith J. Yoder et al. 2010. “More Than Maths
and Mindreading: Sex Differences in Empathizing/Systemizing Covariance.” Autism
Research 3 (4): 174–84.
van der Linden, Dimitri, Curtis S. Dunkel, and Guy Madison. 2017. “Sex Differences
in Brain Size and General Intelligence (g).” Intelligence 63: 78–88.
van der Sluis, Sophie, Danielle Posthuma, Conor V. Dolan et al. 2006. “Sex
Differences on the Dutch WAIS-III.” Intelligence 34 (3): 273–89.
van der Sluis, Sophie, Gonneke Willemsen, Eco J. C. de Geus et al. 2008. “Gene-
Environment Interaction in Adults’ IQ Scores: Measures of Past and Present
Environment.” Behavior Genetics 38 (4): 348–60.
Van Essen, David C. 2018. “Scaling of Human Brain Size.” Science 360 (6394): 1184.
van Honk, Jack, Dennis J. L. G. Schutter, Erno J. Hermans et al. 2004. “Testosterone
Shifts the Balance Between Sensitivity for Punishment and Reward in Healthy
Young Women.” Psychoneuroendocrinology 29 (7): 937–43.
Van Rooy, D. L., and Chockalingam Viswesvaran. 2004. “Emotional Intelligence: A
Meta-analytic Investigation of Predictive Validity and Nomological Net.” Journal of
Vocational Behavior (65): 71–95.
Vasta, Ross, and Lynn S. Liben. 1996. “The Water-Level Task: An Intriguing Puzzle.”
Current Directions in Psychological Science 5 (6): 171–77.
Verweij, Karin J. H., Miriam A. Mosing, Brendan P. Zietsch et al. 2012. “Estimating
Heritability from Twin Studies.” In Statistical Human Genetics: Methods and
Protocols, edited by R. Elston, J. Satagopan, and S. Sun. Totowa, NJ: Humana
Press.
Vinkhuyzen, A. A., S. van der Sluis, H. H. Maes et al. 2012. “Reconsidering the
Heritability of Intelligence in Adulthood: Taking Assortative Mating and Cultural
Transmission into Account.” Behavior Genetics 42 (2): 187–98.
Visser, Beth A., Michael C. Ashton, and Philip A. Vernon. 2006a. “Beyond g: Putting
Multiple Intelligences Theory to the Test.” Intelligence 34 (5): 487–502.
. 2006b. “g and the Measurement of Multiple Intelligences: A Response to
Gardner.” Intelligence 34 (5): 507–10.
Voight, Benjamin F., Sridhar Kudaravalli, Xiaoquan Wen et al. 2006. “A Map of Recent
Positive Selection in the Human Genome.” PLOS Biology 4 (3): e72.
von Hippel, William, and David M. Buss. 2017. “Do Ideologically Driven Scientific
Agendas Impede the Understanding and Acceptance of Evolutionary Principles in
Social Psychology?” In The Politics of Social Psychology, edited by J. T. Crawford
and Lee Jussim, 7–25. New York: Psychology Press.
von Stumm, Sophie, Catharine R. Gale, G. David Batty et al. 2009. “Childhood
Intelligence, Locus of Control and Behaviour Disturbance as Determinants of
Intergenerational Social Mobility: British Cohort Study 1970.” Intelligence 37 (4):
329–40.
von Stumm, Sophie, Benedikt Hell, and Tomas Chamorro-Premuzic. 2011. “The
Hungry Mind: Intellectual Curiosity Is the Third Pillar of Academic Performance.”
Perspectives on Psychological Science 6 (6): 574–88.
von Stumm, Sophie, Emily Smith-Woolley, Ziada Ayorech et al. 2019. “Predicting
Educational Achievement from Genomic Measures and Socioeconomic Status.”
bioRxiv: 538108.
Voyer, Daniel. 1996. “On the Magnitude of Laterality Effects and Sex Differences in
Functional Lateralities.” Laterality 1 (1): 51–83.
Voyer, Daniel, and Susan D. Voyer. 2014. “Gender Differences in Scholastic
Achievement: A Meta-analysis.” Psychological Bulletin 140 (4): 1174–204.
Voyer, Daniel, Susan D. Voyer, and M. P. Bryden. 1995. “Magnitude of Sex
Differences in Spatial Abilities: A Meta-analysis and Consideration of Critical
Variables.” Psychological Bulletin 117: 250–70.
Waddington, John. 1942. “The Epigenotype.” Endeavor 1: 18–20.
Wade, Nicholas. 2014. A Troublesome Inheritance: Genes, Race and Human History.
New York: Penguin.
Wai, Jonathan, Megan Cacchio, Martha Putallaz et al. 2010. “Sex Differences in the
Right Tail of Cognitive Abilities: A 30-Year Examination.” Intelligence 38 (4): 412–
23.
Wainschtein, Pierrick, Deepti P. Jain, Loic Yengo et al. 2019. “Recovery of Trait
Heritability from Whole Genome Sequence Data.” bioRxiv: 588020.
Wallen, Kim. 2009. “The Organizational Hypothesis: Reflections on the 50th
Anniversary of the Publication of Phoenix, Goy, Gerall, and Young (1959).”
Hormones and Behavior 55 (5): 561–65.
Walton, Gregory M., and Steven J. Spencer. 2009. “Latent Ability: Grades and Test
Scores Systematically Underestimate the Intellectual Ability of Negatively
Stereotyped Students.” Psychological Science 20 (9): 1132–39.
Wang, B., and J. Degol. 2013. “Motivational Pathways to STEM Career Choices:
Using Expectancy-Value Perspective to Understand Individual and Gender
Differences in STEM Fields.” Developmental Review 33: 304–40.
Wang, M. T., J. S. Eccles, and S. Kenny. 2013. “Not Lack of Ability but More Choice:
Individual and Gender Differences in Choice of Careers in Science, Technology,
Engineering, and Mathematics.” Psychological Science 24 (5): 770–75.
Warne, Russell T. 2019. “The Mismeasurements of Stephen Jay Gould.” Quillette
(March 19).
Warne, Russell T., Lindsey R. Godwin, and Kyle V. Smith. 2013. “Are There More
Gifted People Than Would Be Expected in a Normal Distribution? An Investigation
of the Overabundance Hypothesis.” Journal of Advanced Academics 24 (4): 224–
41.
Waterhouse, Lynn. 2006. “Multiple Intelligences, the Mozart Effect, and Emotional
Intelligence: A Critical Review.” Educational Psychologist 41 (4): 207–25.
Waterland, Robert A., and Randy L. Jirtle. 2003. “Transposable Elements: Targets for
Early Nutritional Effects on Epigenetic Gene Regulation.” Molecular and Cellular
Biology 23 (15): 5293.
Watson, John Broadus. 1914. Behavior: An Introduction to Comparative Psychology.
New York: H. Holt.
. 1924. Behaviorism. New Brunswick, NJ: Transaction.
Watson, Neil, and Doreen Kimura. 1991. “Nontrivial Sex Differences in Throwing and
Intercepting: Relation to Psychometrically-Defined Spatial Functions.” Personality
and Individual Differences 12 (5): 375–85.
Watts, D. J., and S. H. Strogatz. 1998. “Collective Dynamics of ‘Small-World’
Networks.” Nature 393: 440–42.
Weaver, Ian C. G., Nadia Cervoni, Frances A. Champagne et al. 2004. “Epigenetic
Programming by Maternal Behavior.” Nature Neuroscience 7: 847.
Weidenreich, F. 1946. Apes, Giants, and Man. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Weiner, Jonathan. 1994. The Beak of the Finch: A Story of Evolution in Our Time.
New York: Random House.
Wellman, Henry M., and David Liu. 2004. “Scaling of Theory-of-Mind Tasks.” Child
Development 75 (2): 523–41.
Whitehurst, Grover J. 2013. “New Evidence Raises Doubts on Obama’s Preschool for
All.” In Brown Center Chalkboard Series Archive. Washington, DC: Brookings
Institution.
Wicherts, Jelte M., Conor V. Dolan, and Han L. J. van der Maas. 2010. “A Systematic
Literature Review of the Average IQ of Sub-Saharan Africans.” Intelligence 38 (1):
1–20.
Wilde, Sandra, Adrian Timpson, Karola Kirsanow et al. 2013. “Direct Evidence for
Positive Selection of Skin, Hair, and Eye Pigmentation in Europeans During the Last
5,000 Years.” Proceedings of the National Academy of Sciences 111 (13): 4832–37.
Willerman, Lee, Robert Schultz, J. Neal Rutledge et al. 1991. “In vivo Brain Size and
Intelligence.” Intelligence 15 (2): 223–28.
Williams, G. C. 1966. Adaptation and Natural Selection: A Critique of Some Current
Evolutionary Thought. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Williams, L. M., M. J. Barton, and A. H. Kemp. 2005. “Distinct Amygdala-Autonomic
Arousal Profiles in Response to Fear Signals in Healthy Males and Females.”
NeuroImage 28 (3): 618–26.
Williams, L. M., D. Mathersul, D. M. Palmer et al. 2008. “Explicit Identification and
Implicit Recognition of Facial Emotions: I. Age Effects in Males and Females Across
10 Decades.” Journal of Clinical and Experimental Neuropsychology 19: 1–21.
Willoughby, Emily, Alan Love, Matt McGue et al. 2018. “Free Will, Determinism, and
Intuitive Judgments About the Heritability of Behavior.” Behavior Genetics 49 (2):
136–53.
Wilson, Edward O. 1975. Sociobiology. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
. 1998. Consilience: The Unity of Knowledge. New York: Alfred A. Knopf.
Winegard, Bo, Benjamin Winegard, and Brian Boutwell. 2017. “Human Biological and
Psychological Diversity.” Evolutionary Psychological Science 3 (2): 159–80.
Winkler, Anderson M., Peter Kochunov, John Blangero et al. 2010. “Cortical
Thickness or Grey Matter Volume? The Importance of Selecting the Phenotype for
Imaging Genetics Studies.” NeuroImage 53 (3): 1135–46.
Witchel, Selma Feldman, and Ricardo Azziz. 2010. “Nonclassic Congenital Adrenal
Hyperplasia.” International Journal of Pediatric Endocrinology 2010: 625105.
Wolf, Aaron B., and Joshua M. Akey. 2018. “Outstanding Questions in the Study of
Archaic Hominin Admixture.” PLoS Genetics 14 (5): e1007349.
Wood, Wendy, and Alice H. Eagly. 2012. “Biosocial Construction of Sex Differences
and Similarities in Behavior.” Advances in Experimental Social Psychology 46: 56–
123.
Wright, Daniel B., and Elin M. Skagerberg. 2012. “Measuring Empathizing and
Systemizing with a Large US Sample.” PLoS ONE 7 (2): e31661.
Wright, John Paul, J. C. Barnes, Brian B. Boutwell et al. 2015. “Mathematical Proof Is
Not Minutiae and Irreducible Complexity Is Not a Theory: A Final Response to Burt
and Simons and a Call to Criminologists.” Criminology 53 (1): 113–20.
Wright, Sewall. 1943. “Isolation by Distance.” Genetics 28: 114–38.
. 1978. Evolution and the Genetics of Populations: Variability Within and
Among Natural Populations. Chicago: University of Chicago Press.
Xing, Jinchuan, W. Scott Watkins, Adam Shlien et al. 2010. “Toward a More Uniform
Sampling of Human Genetic Diversity: A Survey of Worldwide Populations by High-
Density Genotyping.” Genomics 96 (4): 199–210.
Yan, C., G. Gong, J. Wang et al. 2011. “Sex-and Brain Size-Related Small-World
Structural Cortical Networks in Young Adults: A DTI Tractography Study.” Cerebral
Cortex 21 (2): 449–58.
Yeager, Ashley. 2019. “Classic Mechanism of Epigenetic Inheritance Is Rare, Not the
Rule.” The Scientist (March 1).
Yeager, David S., P. Hanselman, G. M. Walton et al. 2019. “Where Does a Scalable
Growth-Mindset Intervention Improve Adolescents’ Educational Trajectories.” In
press.
Yeager, David S., Rebecca Johnson, Brian James Spitzer et al. 2014. “The Far-
Reaching Effects of Believing People Can Change: Implicit Theories of Personality
Shape Stress, Health, and Achievement During Adolescence.” Journal of
Personality and Social Psychology 106 (6): 867–84.
Yeager, David S., Hae Yeon Lee, and Jeremy P. Jamieson. 2016. “How to Improve
Adolescent Stress Responses: Insights from Integrating Implicit Theories of
Personality and Biopsychosocial Models.” Psychological Science 27 (8): 1078–91.
Yehuda, Rachel, Nikolaos P. Daskalakis, Linda M. Bierer et al. 2016. “Holocaust
Exposure Induced Intergenerational Effects on FKBP5 Methylation.” Biological
Psychiatry 80 (5): 372–80.
Yeo, B. T. Thomas, Fenna M. Krienen, Jorge Sepulcre et al. 2011. “The Organization
of the Human Cerebral Cortex Estimated by Intrinsic Functional Connectivity.”
Journal of Neurophysiology 106: 1125–65.
Zhu, Zhaoyu, Robin Dennell, Weiwen Huang et al. 2018. “Hominin Occupation of the
Chinese Loess Plateau Since About 2.1 Million Years Ago.” Nature 559 (7715):
608–12.
Zigerell, L. J. 2017. “Potential Publication Bias in the Stereotype Threat Literature:
Comment on Nguyen and Ryan (2008).” Journal of Applied Psychology 102 (8):
1159–68.
Zucker, Kenneth J. 2017. “Epidemiology of Gender Dysphoria and Transgender
Identity.” Sexual Health 14: 404–11.
Zuckerman, Marvin, and D. Michael Kuhlman. 2000. “Personality and Risk-Taking:
Common Biosocial Factors.” Journal of Personality 68 (6): 999–1029.