Bram, Charles Olson and A.N. Whitehead
Bram, Charles Olson and A.N. Whitehead
Bram, Charles Olson and A.N. Whitehead
Shahar Bram
Lewisburg
Bucknell University Press
Contents
Acknowledgments 7
Introduction: An Opening 11
1. The Battlefield 18
2. Whitehead vs. Descartes 24
3. Experience 30
4. Concrescence 42
5. Fluency 67
6. Story, History, Myth 91
7. Stance 111
8. Failure? 133
Epilogue 143
Notes 144
Bibliography 156
Index of Poetic Units 159
Index 161
Acknowledgments
The author is grateful to the following for the permission to quote from their
books:
7
ACKNOWLEDGMENTS 8
Simon & Schuster, Inc.: Whitehead, Alfred North. Process and Real-
ity. Edited by D. R. Griffin and D. W. Sher-
burne. 1929. Reprint, New York: Free
Press, 1978.
A Later Note on
Letter # 15
In English the poetics became meubles—furniture—
thereafter (after 1630
as against what we know went on, the dream: the dream being
self-action with Whitehead’s important corollary: that no event
11
12 CHARLES OLSON AND ALFRED NORTH WHITEHEAD
In retrospect, we can infer from his manifesto, from its wording and from
the continued search for the correct poetics, even after the first part of the
poem had already been published, that Olson approached poetry as a process
and an ongoing search continuously actualized in each poetic unit that is part
of one long poem. Beginning as an optional poetic genre, the long poem is
transformed into the poetics of poetry. “Long” thus means process, the search
and continuity of the poem, as opposed to the perception of the poem as an
object, with defined borders, closed, “short.” For Olson, poetry is not a poem:
the name of an object, a finished aesthetic product, the outcome of a process
in itself minor or negligible. Rather, the poem is poesis; the process of creation
and the poem are, at most, two names or two perspectives for contemplating
the same activity, the creativity of a human being in the world.
The poetics that Olson develops expresses a total Weltanschauung, which
was influenced by two major sources. The first and most crucial is the phi-
losophy and cosmology of Alfred North Whitehead, mainly as presented in
Process and Reality, Whitehead’s main philosophical work, but also in several
of his other writings.1 Whitehead’s conception functions as a net through
which modern science and its discoveries enter the work of Olson, who kept
close track of developments in this realm. The mythopoeia of an ancient,
“primitive” world, as manifest in various texts from different cultures, times,
and places, known to Olson from his readings, blends with ways of thinking
that he fashioned with the aid of Whitehead’s theories. At crucially decisive
points, Olson found a close affinity between these two approaches, seemingly
representing two opposite poles; in fact, Olson argues that Whitehead “only
refines and corrects the most ancient myth-cosmos.”2 In his long poem,
Olson preserves and applies the principles of a worldview growing from and
with these two sources. The long poem as process, as the act of an organism
and as an organism per se, as a real event in the world, as ritual and story, as
creation and construction, as multiplicity within unity—all these terms rely
on foundations anchored in Whitehead’s philosophy and in mythopoeic
patterns of thinking. Olson was also aware of the affinity between these two
conceptions of the world because, in his view, they both rely on assumptions
opposed to those characterizing canonic Western culture. In this sense,
Olson’s poetic act constitutes a critique of prevailing norms and a proposal for
an alternative ethos, which he actualized as a poetics. The poem is an act and a
call to act, the building of a new (re-newed) identity for the individual and the
community.
“A Later Note on Letter # 15” is a convenient opening place for presenting
the long poem woven by Olson. Olson wrote “A Later Note on Letter # 15”
in 1962. At the time, he was about halfway through the process of writing The
Maximus Poems, a project that had begun as a vague idea in the late 1940s.
INTRODUCTION 13
The first poetic unit, “Letter # 1,” was written in 1950, and the poem was
truncated by his death in 1970. Since the poem began as a real letter, Olson
referred to the different units of the poem in progress as “letters.” This
terminology, however, was not sustained as the writing progressed. My term,
“poetic units,” will replace the term “letter,” thus applying also to those units
he himself does not entitle letters. The term “poetic unit,” then, is not meant
to suggest fragmentation, but rather the opposite: the poem in progress is
built from a series of poetic units coalescing into one.
In its final version, the poem brings together three volumes that had been
published separately and in different circumstances. In his preface, Butterick
offers a detailed description of the poem’s history.3 The first volume was
published in 1960 under the name The Maximus Poems and appears now as
Part One in the final version of the whole poem. Although the first volume is
not formally divided into three parts, the name of the second book, which was
published in 1968 (Maximus Poems: IV, V, VI), can also attest to the inner
structure of the previous one. The third book was published in 1975 as The
Maximus Poems: Volume Three. Olson did not edit this volume, but still
managed to be involved in the editing of specific poetic units. The final
version of the poem, dated 1984, includes revisions in the organization of the
last volume, whose format was decided by the editor after Olson’s death.
Due to these circumstances, our reading of the last volume can, at best, be
partial and suggestive. As I will argue, however, Olson’s poetics, based on
openness at the micro level (in any of the “letters” for instance), is yet a
unifying poetics, narrative in aspiration, at the macro level. Thus, Olson’s
poetics enables us, to some extent, to maintain a cautious reading that follows
the characteristic movement of the poem. But the poem is still incomplete,
and not only because of its progressive character or of Olson’s habit of writing
“poetic units” and notes on scattered pieces of paper. Most probably, the
editor of the last volume also took into account Olson’s sense of failure, as
exposed both in his writings at this time and in private talks.4 I discuss this
sense of failure in regard to Olson’s poetics and to the sequence of the poetic
units in chapter 8.
My work is actually merely a reading, or an opening of this one poetic unit
(“A Later Note on Letter # 15”), which encapsulates the main elements of
Olson’s worldview. The Olsonian poetics involves an endless creative process
and develops into an increasingly comprehensive understanding of the
world—a process that invariably begins with the concrete and brings together
elements that interpenetrate and influence each other, a concrescence creating
a new momentary wholeness continuously expanding. This process is based
on the principle of transition between micro and macro, which allows the
integration of openness and determinism, suspension and fluency, spatial and
14 CHARLES OLSON AND ALFRED NORTH WHITEHEAD
“watersheds,” and Olson musters their support in the poetic battle he wages
against the Western canon. Questions about the relationship between the one
and the many, and the difficulties posed by the concept of time (including all
its implications, particularly concerning the modern, “spatial,” scientific per-
ception) will be the focus of my concern in these chapters. It is through them
that I examine Olson’s poetry.
The theoretical discussion will unfold through the reading of various po-
etic units chosen from The Maximus Poems. The greater the empathy shown
in this reading, and the greater its success in presenting the fulfillment of
Olson’s demands and his critique, the easier the presentation of the inevitable
difficulties that follow from Olson’s worldview and from the ability to concre-
tize it. Due to the scope of the long poem, it is impossible to include the
whole text. The choice of specific poetic units will disclose the philosophy
and the methodology typical of the full text, providing “keys” for a com-
prehensive reading.
Chapter 6 deals with the second source that exerted a decisive influence on
Olson’s work: the mythopoeic thinking of the “ancient,” “primitive” world, as
Olson understood it. This chapter will portray a cultural worldview, which
Olson assembled from a variety of sources, representing to him a mode of
thought and action antithetical to the one he considered typical of the deca-
dent West. The sources I use are not necessarily Olson’s, but clearly demon-
strate his case. They are models, or paradigms imposed on scanty “facts,” to
make them retrospectively intelligible. My argument is poetic rather than
historical or philological. The mythopoeic framework I build is meant to
illustrate Olson’s method of consuming eclectic sources and turning them
into a unified whole. Hence, the generalizations and interpretations I use in
this chapter (“ancient” versus “modern”; “mythopoeic” versus “western”
thought) reflect Olson’s poetic needs when building his poetry.
I examine how Olson weaves his mythopoeic approach into a modern
scientific outlook, in his wish to preserve some of its basic aspects in our
attitude to the world and to the other as Thou. The poetic discussion of these
aspects focuses on such topics as story, history, myth, and logos. The extensive
theoretical discussion in the previous chapters, particularly concerning the
dimension of time, substantiates the discussion of these concepts. Olson’s
long poem, despite its reliance on the discoveries of modern science, is actu-
ally interested in preserving the “arrow of time” and its ritual and narrative
character. In chapters 6 and 7, I also stress that discussions of Olson’s texts are
actually revealed as arguments we tend to confine to the category of “the
reading process.” Since Olson claims that poetry exists only as a concrete
activity of the body (breathing and the link with orality will be discussed in
this context), and since poetry is a creative ritual that (re)tells and (re)creates a
INTRODUCTION 17
story and a world, the poet is revealed as a person whose activity depends on
the other, on the reader, for the full actualization of her/his work. Many
obstacles derive from the position in which Olson places the other—the later,
but also the early, reader of his letters: the people of Gloucester, his city, whose
story he wishes to (re)tell, and to whom he addresses his letters-poems. His
call goes unanswered. His Weltanschauung and his path are misunderstood
from the start, and his letters are subject to a “mistaken reading,” apparently
leaving Olson at the end of the way, namely, at the end of his poem, at the end
of his life, with a sense of failure. Olson’s “aesthetic” path (a word alien to the
cultural connotations acceptable in Olson’s world) is a priori moved by ethical
and philosophical considerations; the acute sense of failure in the concluding
section of the poem is a result of the continued separation “between faculties”
evident in the world around him, as opposed to his own project of healing the
breach: Olson’s endeavor, his poetic endeavor, is basically his life’s endeavor.
Olson, who does not distinguish “poetry” from “life,” ends his poem with his
death: no other end appears possible.
1
The Battlefield
18
1: THE BATTLEFIELD 19
and the whole poem, as we will see, is an event. The event “belongs” to
Whitehead, who returns in order to conclude the unit opened by Descartes:
this is a movement forward through a return backward (Herodotus and
Thucidides). But the event also “belongs” to the “poetics of the situation,” to
the poem, to Olson/Maximus, and to the reader who embarks on its re-
discovery.
Olson does not perceive the movement and the collision between the
elements in the poem in metaphorical terms. Understanding Olson’s inten-
tion requires some acquaintance with Whitehead’s worldview and with the
concept of “field,” which guided Olson’s approach even before he knew
Whitehead. The field of the page is the battlefield between Descartes and
Whitehead, an actual field of energy activated by the reader: “First, some
simplicities that a man learns, if he works in OPEN, or what can also be called
COMPOSITION BY FIELD, as opposed to inherited line, stanza, over-all
form, what is the “old” base of the non-projective.”1
The poetic manifesto “Projective Verse,” which Olson wrote in 1950,2 is
already part of the battle against the “poetics of furniture,” which the poet
identifies as an old, Western, canonic poetics. Latent in Olson’s discussion of
the “poetics of the situation” in “A Later Note” are his previous steps in the
poetic struggle he was waging. The fact that “PV” is not part of The Maximus
Poems will later be revealed as irrelevant, not only because “PV” has become a
poetic landmark, but also because Olson’s perception of reality (and of poetry)
abolishes the fundamental division, the entrenched traditional dichotomy
between poetry and reality and between different genres of writing.
The highly significant role of “PV” and its influence on the American
poetic tradition is today unquestionable. Olson, however, began by challeng-
ing poetic conventions, as required by his critique of Western tradition in
general.3 The relevance of all materials to the activity that is poetry overrides
the arbitrary fact that “PV” was written before Olson had decided to embark
on The Maximus Poems project.4 Thus, the ending of “A Later Note” is
actually a return to “PV” for the sake of a forward projection, for the sake of
revelation, progress, expansion, a dynamic characteristic of the very thinking
about poetry in “PV.”
The key concept that shapes Olson’s picture of reality already in “PV” and
enables the energetic projection, is “the field.” The enormous importance of
this concept in scientific discourse eventually resonated in the cultural dis-
course in general. Olson was not the first to internalize scientific ways of
thinking, but his interest and his extensive reading of texts from the philoso-
phy of science single him out as the one who noted a particularly strong
closeness between the world of poetry and the world of science. This close-
ness, which Olson conveyed in his work, follows also from Olson’s sense of
20 CHARLES OLSON AND ALFRED NORTH WHITEHEAD
reality as one, as a unity where the various manifestations are merely multiple
facets. He eventually formulated this sense into articulate statements, follow-
ing his acquaintance with Whitehead’s philosophical method, as we will see
below.
The concept of field, together with the world picture derived from it,
denotes a dismissal of the traditional perception of space. In this sense, it is
related to the efforts that Olson invested in clarifying the question of space in
his early book on Moby Dick and Melville.5 The concept of field had a
tremendous effect on our understanding and imagining of reality, as Einstein
himself explains:
A new concept appears in physics, the most important invention since Newton’s
time: the field. It needed great scientific imagination to realize that it is not the
charges nor the particles but the field in the space between the charges and the
particles which is essential for the description of physical phenomena. The field
concept proves most successful and leads to the formulation of Maxwell’s equations
describing the structure of the electromagnetic field and governing the electric as
well as the optical phenomena.6
space. But the concept of aether created new problems, namely, incom-
patibility between mechanics and electromagnetism concerning the relativity
of motion. Einstein dismissed the assumption about aether and made the
relativity of motion a general principle, which relies on an understanding of
the speed of light as fixed and unchangeable from the perspective of every
observer in the universe. Fields themselves were now perceived as the funda-
mental variables and replaced the forces acting-at-a-distance between bodies
in a space filled with aether. Once it became clear that light, magnetism, and
electricity are aspects of one single force, there was no longer a need for a
medium such as aether to transfer waves of light in space; changes in the field
spread in it like waves. “Einstein had replaced Newton’s space with a network
of light beams; theirs was the absolute grid, within which space itself became
supple.”8The measurement of space changes for different observers moving at
different velocities, as the measurement of time changes; distance is rela-
tive, as bodies in motion become longer and shorter. In fact, space and time
are joined together by two different physical sizes into a four-dimensional
space-time continuum, curved by matter, whose description requires a non-
Euclidean geometry.
As was hinted in the description of the concept of field, other physical
values, such as mass, energy, and momentum, also become aspects of one
physical entity. The preceding discussion stresses two points that are clearly
echoed in Olson and became a crucial foundation of his thinking after his
reading of Whitehead: (1) It is possible to relate to the whole universe as a
single physical system. This point is also linked to the question of the one and
the many, which is central to the understanding of Olson’s world. (2) The
universe, as Hubble had already discovered in 1929, is expanding, a view only
a short step away from the Big Bang theory. Expansion, or concrescence in
Whitehead’s scheme, is a cornerstone of Olson’s thinking about human beings
and the world. These concepts, following his reading and concern with
physics and with the philosophy of science came to replace what Olson, in
1950, had called projection in “PV”—Olson found a philosophic grounding
for what he had earlier intuited.
Olson internalizes the concept of field as a junction of acting forces. He
internalizes the dynamism of the space that is a “product” of these forces, both
concerning the textual space “on the page,” and concerning the poem as a
junction of forces “in reality.” Points 1 and 3 in “PV” demonstrate this clearly:
(1) the kinetics of the thing. A poem is energy transferred from where the poet got
it . . . by way of the poem itself to, all the way over to, the reader. . . .
(3) the process of the thing . . . : ONE PERCEPTION MUST IMMEDIATELY
AND DIRECTLY LEAD TO A FURTHER PERCEPTION . . . keep moving,
22 CHARLES OLSON AND ALFRED NORTH WHITEHEAD
keep in, speed, the nerves, their speed, the perceptions, theirs, the acts, the split
second acts, the whole business, keep it moving as fast as you can, citizen. And if
you also set up as a poet, USE USE USE the process at all points . . . that every
element in an open poem (the syllable, the line, as well as the image, the sound, the
sense) must be taken up as participants in the kinetic of the poem just as solidly as
we are accustomed to take what we call the objects of reality; and that these
elements are to be seen as creating the tensions of a poem just as totally as do those
other objects create what we know as the world. (CP, 240, 243)
“Projective Verse” aims to blaze a trail for a poetics that would be suitable
to a view of the world as field, as dynamism. A poetics implementing this view
of the world implies that the “space of the poem” that is “frozen” in formal
traditional structures will now become an outcome of processes or forces of
which we tend to speak as happening and working within the poem. When
the definition of field is “transposed” to the realm of poetry, we have a domain
or environment where we can describe the actual or potential activity of a
force for any point in space, when force, as “the agency responsible for a
change in a system” is, in this case, language in all its aspects. Words are
energy rather than only meaning or sound. The poetic space is not only a
textual space, and the textual space itself, as an expression of forces, is not
atoms (syllables) that create entities (words) connected to one another across
the empty space (the page). The blank, “empty” page, is “full” of energy,
meaning that before us is a field whose textual phenomena (blank and writ-
ten) are an expression of the movement of energy, breath, in and out. Space
itself is the processes, the active forces, the potentiality actualized as energy:
Let’s start from the smallest particle of all, the syllable. It is the king and pin
of versification, what rules and holds together the lines, the larger forms, of a
poem. . . . For from the root out, from all over the place, the syllable comes, the
figures of, the dance: “is” comes from the Aryan root, as, to breath. The English
“not” equals the Sanscrit na, which may come from the root na, to be lost, to
perish. “Be” is from bhu, to grow. . . .
But the syllable is only the first child of the incest of verse. . . . The other child is
the LINE. . . . And the line comes (I swear it) from the breath, from the breathing
of the man who writes, at the moment that he writes. . . .
Let me put it baldly. The two halves are: the HEAD, by way of the EAR, to the
SYLLABLE the HEART, by way of the BREATH, to the LINE. (CP, 241– 42)
The poem, in all its space, is dynamic, flexible, variable. “The American
poem, Olson’s poem, is not trying to project something ideal, but rather to
reenact something radically earthly, radically local, and radically temporal—
i.e., a man’s encounter with the particulars of his experience, his environment,
and the history of his locale. This poetics is hardly an idealization.”9 Bové’s
1: THE BATTLEFIELD 23
In the earlier, Fifty-first Section, Descartes states: “By substance we can conceive
nothing else than a thing which exists in such a way as to stand in need of nothing
beyond itself in order to its existence.” . . .
Thus we conclude that, for Descartes, minds and bodies exist in such a way as to
stand in need of nothing beyond themselves individually. . . .
It is difficult to praise too highly the genius exhibited by Descartes in the
complete sections of his Principles. . . . But the fundamental principles are so set
out as to presuppose independently existing substances with simple location in the
community of temporal durations, and in the case of bodies, with simple location
in the community of spatial extensions. Those principles lead straight to the theory
of a materialistic, mechanistic nature, surveyed by cogitating minds.1
24
2: WHITEHEAD VS. DESCARTES 25
concern with mythopoeic thinking, the ancient world, and myth. The long
poem that Olson develops relies on a nonmechanistic poetics, no longer based
on the Cartesian concept of substance. Hence, Olson perceives the space of
the poem as living and breathing. He develops a poetics of events and process
whereby the long poem is viewed as a continuously expanding poetic uni-
verse, enabling a poetics of multiplicity within unity. The epigraph of The
Maximus Poems says: “All my life I’ve heard one makes many.” As Butterick
explains, these words were:
the yellow sweetings are Blackstone apples, first grown by William Blackstone on
Beacon Hill before the settlement of Boston, and the word “pertinence” is a
thematic pun. These apples will not only be shown to be pertinent to the poem’s
theme, they will also be shown to be pertinences, in the sense of adjuncts to
property.8
The apple, fruit of Nature and fruit of knowledge, thus becomes a com-
modity, the fruit of the capitalistic market where individualism reigns, and
the fruit of the West’s legacy, Cartesian dualism. From here follow the corrup-
tion and the transformation of fellow human beings (the Quakers) into a
commodity, since they are matter but lack spirit (which is reserved only for
the Puritans). Descartes thus defaces the sense of proportion that had pre-
vailed at the beginning, at the origin, when human beings had been an
integral part of their natural environment. The Maximus Poems is thus the
unfolding poem (story) of Gloucester, the city of Maximus that Descartes,
according to Olson, curbs, and through which he deflects from “the right
path”:
The first 1630 original settlement, to be called Boston soon after, is the
beginning (the opening) that was missed—the battlefield, the new world that
is already controlled by Cartesian values, as Olson writes in “A Later Note.”
Descartes curbs the development that should have unfolded. It is not the
savages who prevented the growth that had been hoped for, but the mistake in
the cogito statement, which persisted until Whitehead’s arrival on the scene:
“I am, I exist” means “I exist as substance,” hence the return to a world that is
divided and lacks unity. “A Later Note,” as a unit dated later than the units
quoted above (and as many others that could obviously have been cited) also
encompasses this story, although it is “folded,” hidden: the movement in the
space of the unit, the “collision” between its elements at the micro level,
which are enacted by the reader. This movement is woven into the movement
at the macro level, in the story that Olson spins from unit to unit. Before us,
then, is a poetics of movement: on the one hand, an open battlefield at the
micro level, but, on the other hand, conditioned by the units that precede it
and directing the story at the macro level. Descartes is a soldier in various
wars, which are joined together by the storyteller, the poet, who directs the
wars, halts them, weaves them together:
Descartes soldier
in a time of religious
wars
even as he is absent. The war is fought over the semblance of the new world;
this war, that shapes Gloucester, the city of Olson/Maximus, of which Dog-
town is part, is still going on, enacted by Olson himself.
Fishermen’s Field was the site of the Dorchester Company in Cape Ann in
1623, which became part of Gloucester in the course of time, and is located
about a hundred yards from Olson’s own front yard.9 On 10 September,
1953, Olson wrote to Frederick Merk, an American historian at Harvard
University:
Again I have the distinct pleasure to write to you. This time, it is to ask you if you
can advise me about the state of knowledge about what is, in fact, the very grounds
I was raised on: Fishermen’s Field, Cape Ann. I am engaged in a work which pivots
from that field, and wish to saturate myself on all the history of it which is known
. . . have put it thus specifically, not to point any of the pieces at you, but to suggest
the sort of saturation that my own front yard—literally, that field was where I grew,
our house being on “Stage Fort Avenue,” Gloucester!—bred in me.10
The battles are the fishing battles and the battle for a livelihood,11 the battle
to survive in the new world that is a battle against Mother England, which
had tried to control the settlers’ economic and religious life. Sophia, the
Gnostic “Mother,” a figure of wisdom, is an ironic hint to these battles and to
herself as “the Spirit of God,” a symbol of the religious wars in Europe and in
the New World as well as between them.
All are latent in the battle of words, and inseparably linked to the battle
between Descartes and Whitehead. The field of the page is a potentiality for
various fields and wars; wars are waged on the field of the page between the
armies of words deployed on its sides. In fact, we are partners to Olson’s battle,
which is the enactment of the story, the actualization of the contact with
reality: “I take it that contest is what puts drama (what they call story, plot)
into the thing, the writer’s contesting with reality, to see it, to SEE.”12
The poetic unit “A Later Note” is already a wide-scale story, which ex-
panded further and further along the poem until reaching this unit, and will
continue expanding beyond it. This is a momentary unity, whose story imme-
diately continues its onward flow. The storyteller is the one to shape the story,
in which he also takes part. To understand the full depth of this process we
must return to Whitehead,
IN LINE WITH THE CHANGES IN THE PERCEPTION OF SPACE AND TIME, AND
wishing to suggest an overall speculative explanation of nature as a unity
(multiplicity within unity), Whitehead constructs a process philosophy, a
philosophy of organism based on the concepts of becoming and actual entity.
I quote below at length, because these two passages outline Whitehead’s basic
worldview:
“Actual entities”—also termed “actual occasions”—are the final real things of
which the world is made up. There is no going behind actual entities to find
anything more real. They differ among themselves: God is an actual entity, and so
is the most trivial puff of existence in far-off empty space. But, though there are
gradations of importance, and diversities of function, yet in the principles which
actuality exemplifies all are on the same level. The final facts are, all alike, actual
entities; and these actual entities are drops of experience, complex and inter-
dependent.1
Newton in his description of space and time has confused what is “real” poten-
tiality with what is actual fact. He has thereby been led to diverge from the
judgment of “the vulgar” who “conceive those quantities under no other notions
but from the relation they bear to sensible objects.” The philosophy of organism
starts by agreeing with “the vulgar” except that the term “sensible object” is
replaced by “actual entity”; so as to free our notions from participation in an
epistemological theory as to sense-perception. . . . I will also use the term “actual
occasion” in the place of the term “actual entity.” Thus the actual world is built up
of actual occasions; and by the ontological principle whatever things there are in
any sense of “existence,” are derived by abstraction from actual occasions. I shall
use the term “event” in the more general sense of a nexus of actual occasions, inter-
related in some determinate fashion in one extensive quantum. An actual occasion
is the limiting type of an event with only one member. (73)
30
3: EXPERIENCE 31
Does Olson’s endeavor thereby come to nothing? And why should the towns-
people, or the readers, accept Olson’s worldview and agree to see it as prefer-
able to their own, as implied in his letters to them?
Any attempt to answer these questions requires an understanding of the as-
sumptions underlying Olson’s thought, and his need to resort to Whitehead’s
theory in order to establish them. An “actual entity,” as Whitehead argues,
enjoys a primary ontic status, and all other modes of existence depend on it.
The “final facts” of reality, without exception, are “actual entities,” which are
“drops of experience.” Reality is immediate, in the sense of experience here
and now: an “actual entity” is an experiencing “subject,” in the sense that its
becoming is merely an act of experience. As a primary category of existence, it
is indivisible; in fact, it is realized all at once.4 Olson is thus strengthened in his
view that: (1) Existence is realized in full, undivided fashion; the vari-
ous dichotomies (body/soul, I/other, nature/culture, individual/collective,
subject/object, and so forth) that are characteristic of Western culture, are
abstractions mistakenly perceived as “final facts.” (2) Existence is realized as
experience, since the “final facts” are “drops of experience”; poetry, then, has
no meaning except as an activity, a creation, an experience.
Olson finds that Whitehead provides him with a systematic formulation of
his own point of departure as a poet: although life takes many forms, it is in
fact multiplicity in unity. Classic Western culture, as a written culture, a
“culture of logos,” split up experience and established a rigid hierarchy that
conceals the body, the experience that is always integral and indivisible in
actual reality, although it can be, and indeed was, analyzed (as in Whitehead’s
method). Olson’s critique of the classic cultural and poetic legacy of the West
targets the misconception of experience as unity, and the preference of the
“spiritual” over the “physical.” Already in “Projective Verse,” Olson had
conceived the poem and the word as a physical act, attesting to one entity, to
poetry as an event: breathing in and out, experiencing the world. Descartes’s
concept of substance had entangled him in the well-known “body and mind”
problem that is paradigmatic of the split thinking failing to perceive unity. An
“actual entity” is the outcome of Whitehead’s conclusion that “spiritual”
elements cannot possibly be separated from “physical” elements, because the
concreteness of the experience precedes these abstractions. This approach is
consistent with Olson’s perception and, in order to emphasize it, he even
resorts to Whitehead’s concepts in his poem.5
He also alludes to this in his essays and oral expositions: “that beautiful
concept of Whitehead’s, the eternal event that strikes across all object and
occasion.”6 These are merely random examples: Olson is highly influenced by
Whitehead’s thinking, which is so compatible with his own. As a teacher, he
guides us to relate to the poetic unit as an “actual entity,” an “occasion” to be
“taken” (as when saying “take a deep breath,” when to breathe equals to sing),
3: EXPERIENCE 33
to be realized. His poetic materials serve him in the same direction: to show
that experience is not necessarily linked to consciousness, and the body is the
immediate “environment” for our growth, the body, as can be seen in “Max-
imus Letter # whatever,” is our home:
The story about the man with his “house on his head,” which recurs several
times in the course of the poem, is beautifully illuminated in the following
passage by Whitehead:
And yet, the unity “body and mind” is the obvious complex which constitutes the
one human being. Our bodily experience is the basis of existence. . . . And yet our
feeling of bodily-unity is a primary experience. It is an experience so habitual and
so completely a matter of course that we rarely mention it. No one ever says, Here
am I, and I brought my body with me. In what does this intimacy of relationship
consist? The body is the basis of our emotional and purposive experience. It
determines the way in which we react to the clear sensa. It determines the fact that
we enjoy sensa.7
Poets, then (and, in this sense, myth is poetry) should indeed remind us of
what is not self-evident, at least not in the split poetry that, according to
Olson, is written in the West. The story of the man with his “house on his
34 CHARLES OLSON AND ALFRED NORTH WHITEHEAD
head”, taken from Algonquin Legends of New England,8 is the story of aliena-
tion from the body, which in Western culture is “heavy” and “earthy,” op-
posed to “spirituality.” Yet spirituality, as is clearly evident from the end of the
story, is part of the body and within it: the growth of wings, its transformation
into a bird, spring—all are part of the human being’s “projection” from
within; “projective verse” denotes a physical projection from within the body,
which results in human growth.
Olson had been concerned with the “theme” of the body from a very early
stage.9 The body as a “first fact” remains, for Olson, the foundation of
“spiritual growth.” He who is at one with his body can grow from within
himself, expand from within himself, “fly.” The “earthy,” the “physical,”
became derogatory concepts in Western culture, while in actual fact they
represent an option of growth “upward,” to the “spiritual.”10 The human
who does “return to the body” is the one who touches the spirit, becomes
“spiritual.” Olson’s use of these prose passages (or documents, notes, journals,
and so forth) indeed attests to the removal of the traditional borders between
“prose” and “poetry” (or any other form of genre classification), since these
are arbitrary dichotomic divisions of something that is one. As is slowly
becoming clear, Olson views the “long poem” as a form that precedes all these
genre divisions: the long poem is indeed life in its entirety (“body and mind”).
The organization of the unit attests to that very unity of perspectives that is
the whole, unsplit individual:
he who walks with his house on
his head is heaven he
who walks with his house
on his head is heaven he who walks
with his house on his head
(TMP, 311)
Olson seeks to emphasize that the (renewed) encounter with the body is
always an encounter with the other and with space. In other words: all
dichotomies is but an extension of that false division between substance (that
is the subject) and the “other.” Descartes had perceived substance as that
which requires nothing else for its survival. He set clear borders to “the
substance,” thereby fixing its isolation from the surroundings. The poem tells
us that the encounter with the body (the “other” of the “I” in Western
tradition) is also the meeting with “other” humans from “other” places. This,
then, is the otherness of “origins” after which Olson searches obsessively in
order to renew their relevance. As Bové describes it: “Olson’s sense of origins
means an attempt to regain an awareness of man’s temporal and geographical
nature in a world where poetry should be written out of the complex, deep
3: EXPERIENCE 35
historical relationship between a man and the objects within his world, his
environment, his ‘field.’ ”11
To be at one with the body means returning to one’s origins, to be at one
with earth, with nature, with the rest of its creatures. The experience of the
body is the experience of the “other,” and that other is primarily nature, or
space. Nature works within and on human beings, since they are bodies, to
the same extent that human beings work on nature as “body.” Thus, “to
return to the body” means “to return to space,” to take part in that field of
energy surrounding you and including you, to be part of the earth, of creation
as a whole:
Mother Dogtown
of whom the Goddess
was the front
Father Sea
who comes to the skirt
of the City
(TMP, 317)
The city is part of the Earth, which itself is a body: borders become blurred
and the mythical name Earth resumes its concrete bodily presence. The city is
the fruit of the Earth and a part of it, as human beings are the fruit of the
body, part of space. Olson explains the meaning of the concept home, to be at
home, while building this home at the same time. The myth itself illustrates
this issue: in the passage about the gods (TMP, 317), Olson refers to Fran-
kfort’s study of Egyptian myth, which describes the birth of the gods from
Ptah, the god of the city of Memphis who is the creator of all.13 Ptah is
perceived at times as a “spirit,” or as “reason,” and at times as a “body,”
“earth,” and so forth. Hence, when the gods “enter into their bodies” (TMP,
317), they are actually returning to the body, since they are creatures of Ptah to
begin with, like their bodies. This paradox is intentional. The mythopoeic
attitude, as Olson understands it, does not think of the world in terms of the
fragmentation, of the principle (or law) of bivalence that already permeates
the language we use. The two passages below illustrate how Olson (in the
second paragraph), following Whitehead (in the first paragraph), found close
propinquity between the mythopoeic thinking of antiquity and the discov-
eries of modern science, concerning the unity of experience and the blurring
of the separation between human beings and the world. Both are linked to the
balance required for a full description of reality:
it was visible truth he was after. For example, that light is not only a wave but a
corpuscle. Or that the electron is not only a corpuscle but a wave. Melville couldn’t
abuse object as symbol does by depreciating it in favor of subject. Or let image lose
its relational force by transferring its occurrence as allegory does. (SW, 50)
the body. The page of the book (and it is the first page, of the first “letter” that
opens the poem: “I, Maximus of Gloucester, to You”) is also a seething space
that engenders the dance and the song:
The lance is a metonymy of the fisherman but also of the poet (his pen),
and the figures are the syllables (the unit repeats Olson’s words in “Projective
Verse”): the poem itself, according to Olson, has a “physical” presence, and
the poet himself is a dancer, who activates his body and thereby transcends
himself, expands, and grows.16 The balance between the various aspects of
unity, which means relativity, is already intimated here (in the unit that opens
The Maximus Poems): here the lance arises from the dynamic, from the
movement, as growth results from a momentary stability of unity out of
dynamism. The same principle is also at work at the level of the unit, which
grows into momentary unity from the dance of the syllables. As a lance, it is
also hinted here that the dance, the unit, has a purpose and a direction, which
is the direction of Olson’s growth into Maximus and of Gloucester into a
polis. The mistaken attitude to the body in Western culture is the mistaken
attitude to space and is responsible for a poetry and a culture that are alien-
ated, mechanical, arrogant, and craving control. Olson had already clarified
in “Projective Verse” his attitude toward the West’s alienation from space (or
nature, in line with the nature-culture dichotomy, another binarian division
characteristic of Western culture and its poetic tradition); he points to an-
other ethical “stance,” which he terms objectism: “that peculiar presumption
by which western man has interposed himself between what he is as a creature
of nature (with certain instructions to carry out) and those other creations of
nature which we may, with no derogation, call objects. For a man is himself an
object” (CP, 247).
Olson’s aim, then, is not projection in the psychological sense, implying
that one’s ego is imposed on space, but a growth from within space and with
space. But the question remains open: does not every writing entail some
form of coercion (of the other, of space)? And is this not especially true of one
who writes as a teacher and mentor? Indeed, Olson identifies in the course of
the poem with such figures as Buddha or Confucius; however, and particu-
larly at the beginning, his approach seems authoritarian and coercive.17
3: EXPERIENCE 39
getting the universe in (as against man alone.” It is Olson that leaves paren-
thesis open “as against man alone,” and it is Whitehead, who formulates clear
metaphysical assumptions for him, who gets in. Whitehead’s assumptions
realize the concepts Olson anticipated in “Project Verse”:20 how do you grow
from the body, from space, enabling the place and the entire universe to grow
with you; how is experience translated into the activism of growth, inhaling
and exhaling—the very projection that Olson had sought from the start. The
concept of growth makes the poetics of the long poem a poetics of poetry in
general. That is because growth, as Olson learns from Whitehead, is actually
one kind of fluency—a concept I will examine in detail in the following. Both
concepts of fluency together—one working at the micro level (the level of the
isolated unit in the poem), and one at the macro level (the level of the one
long poem)—describe the entire world (including the poetic one), and in-
clude its various aspects and levels. Aspects of space and time are linked to
both concepts of fluency, as is the balance that Whitehead and Olson together
try to establish between the extremes characteristic of Western thinking pat-
terns throughout history.
4
Concrescence
One kind is the concrescence which, in Locke’s language, is “the real internal
constitution of a particular existent.” The other kind is the transition from particu-
lar existent to particular existent. This transition, again in Locke’s language, is the
“perpetually perishing” which is one aspect of the notion of time; and in another
aspect the transition is the origination of the present in conformity with the
“power” of the past.1
42
4: CONCRESCENCE 43
It is the imposing
of all those antecedent predecessions, the precessions
more than I am
for my inheritance.
The poetic unit “Letter 27” is built as a body contained within a body. The
description of the landscape, which opens the unit, generates the body of
Maximus at the center of the unit, and also closes it: Maximus rises, stands,
within his space, and the unit shows how this space is his home, his place. The
geographical space is also the space of memory. Family is the basic unit giving
rise to the polis, meaning that the family is also a “body” within a broader
“body,” and so forth. Family memories are linked to the physical, geograph-
ical space of the city: as a human being, you are the fruit of space, of a concrete
place, as well as the offspring of your parents, the outcome of concrete events
in space coming forth at the unit’s outset. The human being, as Olson
paraphrases Whitehead (beginning at l. 20 and up to the section that closes
the unit, where he returns to the “geography of the place”), is neither a
product of abstractions nor an abstract form; human beings are the outcome
of events, of the place, of people and concrete experiences. In Whitehead’s
formulation: “It was the defect of the Greek analysis of generation that it
conceived it in terms of the bare incoming of novel abstract form”;2 “In
addition to the notions of the welter of events and of the forms which they
illustrate, we require a third term, personal unity” (240); “So intimately
obvious is this bodily inheritance that common speech does not discriminate
the human body from the human person. Soul and body are fused to-
gether. . . . But the human body is indubitably a complex of occasions which
are part of spatial nature” (243).
4: CONCRESCENCE 45
Where does my body end and the external world begin? For example, my pen is
external; my hand is part of my body; and my finger nails are part of my body. Also
the breath as it passes in and out of my lungs from my mouth and throat fluctuates
in its bodily relationship. Undoubtedly the body is very vaguely distinguishable
from external nature. It is in fact merely one among other natural objects.6
a deconstruction that has already been performed through language, the present
study as a whole is an analysis of Olson’s experience, which brought forth the
unit “A Later Note.” In the analysis of the unit, I deconstruct it down to “those
potentials” realized by Olson, which generated the unit when fused together.
Obviously, I thereby re-create the unit but as an “actual entity” different from
Olson’s, since the wishes, sensations, knowledge, physical situation, and other
elements that for me, as a “subject” in the analysis are present as components,
were not potentials for Olson, or were not the same potentials they had been for
Olson. Olson internalizes Whitehead’s emphasis on the relativity of the con-
cepts “potentially” and “actually”: “Letter 27,” after its initial realization from
“pure potentiality” into “actual fact,” becomes once more a potential for
realization, for any realization. In Whitehead’s terms, it could now be called a
“real potentiality”: this is a potentiality that has already been realized in the
past and is now again subject to new realizations. Olson learns from White-
head9 that a distinction is required between real potentiality and actual fact.
The emphasis is on the transition from the actual entity, the actual fact, to the
status of a renewed potentiality that is the real potentiality. An actual entity,
then, unlike the Cartesian (and Aristotelian) substance, neither persists nor
“perishes”; it goes on existing and influencing the world in another mode of
existence. Olson accepts the view that a “real potentiality” is itself a “stubborn
fact,” once more an element in every experience in the world. “Letter 27” will
be realized anew not only by the reader but by Olson himself, in his own
experience in “Letter 28,” where it is again an element, a different kind of
potentiality, one of the elements in the fusion that engenders “Letter 28.”
The potentiality to be an element in the real “concrescence” of many
entities into one actuality applies to all elements in the universe. As Olson
learns from Whitehead, this is a metaphysical characteristic generally valid for
all entities, actual and nonactual; this is the principle of relativity—“it be-
longs to the nature of a ‘being’ that it is a potential for every ‘becoming’ ” (22).
The solution to the problem of the abstraction necessarily created through the
use of language, and particularly in a written culture based on texts, lies in the
reader’s ability to turn the unit once again into actuality, shifting his/her status
from “subject” to the actual experience, thereby becoming an “actual sub-
ject.” This solution raises problems related to the culture of reading and to the
character of the reading process: do readers indeed read as “required”? How
does the reader’s status as a “subject” evolve at the time of the reading and
reactivating the unit if s/he is unaware of Whitehead’s metaphysics or does
not believe in its permanence? The principle of relativity enables Whitehead
to create a balance between becoming and perishing. Adopting that principle
is one step in making the long poem the form synonymous with poetry as
such; the isolated poetic unit, “a poem,” does not “end” but continues to
influence the becoming of the next poetic unit.
48 CHARLES OLSON AND ALFRED NORTH WHITEHEAD
For Olson, relativity is the principle that also validates the status of the
“subject” vis-à-vis the “object.” In “Letter 27,” Olson attempts to show that
all divisions are actually but extension of one (false) dichotomy, and that unity
means unity with every single “other” anywhere—the body, space, the neigh-
bor, and so forth. This attempt unfolds through Olson’s own experience “in”
Whitehead and through his experience of his body in Gloucester, the concrete
space of his existence. It is this experience that turns him into a “subject” in
that particular here and now. The components, or the various “beings,” are
potentials for Olson’s becoming a “subject” since, in this unit, he is a “subject”
constituted through his experience, and every element in his experience is
qualified to him, as an element of it. Whitehead is a particle of Olson’s
experience in “Letter 27” through the prehension of the “subject” Whitehead
as an “object,” as Olson is an element in my own experience when reading
Letter 27. The concepts themselves are relative, since the world is merely a
process of becoming events, and the question relates to the perspective for
approaching this process, the perspective for describing the world. Having a
vantage point attests to one’s being a “subject”; the perspective is what defines
the status of “subject” and “object,” of the prehensor and the prehensible
element, the perceiver and the perceived. Olson accepts Whitehead’s ap-
proach, which makes experience a mark of reality. The alternative is to return
to a Cartesian dualism that includes, besides substances or thinking “I’s” such
as ourselves, expanding substances without subjectivity, leading once again to
the well-known problem of body and soul. Experience is the multiplicity of
objects prehended by a “subject” and, as such, constitute the subject’s autono-
mous identity. This is the distinctively ethical approach that Olson calls
objectism, which stresses the equality between all creatures, all of whom are
simultaneously “subjects” and “objects” (SW, 24). “Letter 1” constitutes the
bird as “subject,” prehending from its higher perspective the city and its
inhabitants as “objects.” Its building of the nest, “feather to feather added,”
stresses the particular that is at hand and that we ourselves find and carry,
“the string/you carry in your nervous beak.” The protecting nest is here,
nearby:
Out of the look, the blessing, the bird’s nest, grows the (phallic) energy, the
projection that will carry one forward.10 From high above, the goddess, the
patron of the city, launches the poet’s voyage; the voyage itself is the building
of his polis, of his poem, of himself into Maximus. Looks intersect, perspec-
tives alter, and identities merge into one another: the perspective from above
becomes the perspective of Olson/Maximus, since the city is his city. Hence
the subject’s identification with his object, which Olson also finds in my-
thopoeic thinking: the exchange of looks attests that the city itself is an event
arising from space through the look of the bird, the look of the poet and the
look of the goddess, who is the poet’s muse. The poet is also part of the city, as
the roofs are part of the bird’s look; the process is always internal, the growth
is internal, and every “outside” is merely a matter of perspective rather than a
true frontier. Olson seeks to break the hierarchical stance of the Western
perspective, which rises above nature or above the “other.” Human beings,
according to Olson, are part of the universe, part of the event that is the
universe; thus, they themselves become a potentiality for actualization
through nature, just as nature is a potentiality for actualization through them.
This ontic relativity shatters the primacy of the “I,” since the human is
prehended by the bird as an “object,” just as the bird is prehended by the
human as an “object”; hierarchy becomes relativity according to the perspec-
tive, or the “prehension,” as Whitehead describes it:
An occasion of experience is an activity, analysable into modes of functioning
which jointly constitute its process of becoming. Each mode is analysable into the
total experience as active subject, and into the thing or object with which the
special activity is concerned. This thing is a datum, that is to say, is describable
without reference to its entertainment in that occasion. An object is anything
performing this function of datum provoking some special activity of the occasion
in question. Thus subject and object are relative terms. An occasion is a subject in
respect to its special activity concerning an object; and anything is an object in
respect to its provocation of some special activity within a subject. Such a mode of
activity is termed a “prehension.”11
Olson could not prevent the growth of his own “subjectivity,” his own con-
stitutive activity in his poetry, even when calling upon the other citizens to act
and constitute themselves. Many questions arise: Olson tries to present in the
poem the vantage points of the “other,” but this “other” then becomes an
“object” through its own growth—how can he realize and clarify in his own
writing that he is an “object” for another “subject”? Even when the look is the
bird’s, or the city’s, or some other person’s, since the text brings documents or
stories by others and about others, someone might claim that the perspective
is ultimately subjugated, or qualified,12 to the “subject” who is Olson/
Maximus. To formulate this in more general terms: Are we again facing the
dichotomies of writing/speaking, poetry/reality, and so forth? Does Olson’s
claim that reality is a realization of potentialities turn us into someone who, in
Olson’s terms, realizes the unit? And does our knowledge of Whitehead
change the reading mode of the poem in a deep, metaphysical sense? In-
stances such as the bird’s look expose another problematic facet: the “other” is
not always nature, and a critical view might argue that Whitehead’s cosmol-
ogy becomes a social instrument for Olson, at least in a considerable section
of the first and even of the third volume of The Maximus Poems. In the second
volume, Olson made an attempt to change perspective, which explains his
turn to the mythical and his concern with “Mother Earth,” “Okeanos,” and
other cosmic forces. But does his anthropomorphization of nature turn nature
into a “subject” relating to humans as “objects”? To what extent is it possible
to say that nature “perceives” us as we “perceive” it? Can this assumption be
more than a mere aphorism? Can it be concretized in a text that is a human
abstraction from nature? Olson, who wishes to change social reality, to shape a
community with different values, faces an additional problem: his argument
about lack of hierarchies clashes with the view he had endorsed previously,
stating that Whitehead’s metaphysics and the ethic implied by it are, accord-
ing to his own understanding, the correct approach.
The bird’s eye “mapping” the city, then, perfectly matches Olson’s eye,
which “maps” the city, the space, and thus generates Maximus: it “prehends”
and constructs the “actual entity” that is Maximus in the same act of percep-
tion and “prehension” of experience itself. Reality, as Olson wishes to empha-
size, is always particular, immediate, singular, perceived in order to change
with you and, of course, relative: “there are eyes in all heads” for which you
are also a “datum of prehension,” a “real object” in the creation of another
“subject”:
There are no hierarchies, no infinite, no such many as mass, there are only
eyes in all heads,
to be looked out of
(TMP, 33)
4: CONCRESCENCE 51
colored pictures
of all things to eat: dirty
postcards
And words, words, words
all over everything
No eyes or ears left
to do their own doings (all
song
(TMP, 17)
In “The Songs of Maximus” (which is “Letter 4”) and other poetic units in
the beginning of TMP, Olson deals with the present plight of his community,
and his observation of it is part of his attempt to expose the faults and
mistakes of the tradition that had engendered it. Olson attacks the values of
52 CHARLES OLSON AND ALFRED NORTH WHITEHEAD
the Fertile Crescent, from Tyre, to America. Maximus, the philosopher from
Tyre, is transfigured into Maximus from Gloucester and, according to Olson,
should also be transfigured into the reader, the child of a place that singles
him out, whatever that might be.
“One wants phenomenology in place,” Olson writes, “in order that event may
rearise” (Prose, 51). The freshness of space must be allowed to assert itself so it can
reveal its own form. Perception in the Maximus is an interchange between outward
space and the inward self which takes place at the surfaces of the body, before it is
confronted with the abstract systems which form in the centers of consciousness.15
Birth from the body, as Byrd emphasizes, is birth from space, which marks
out a place for the individual, a home. Even before becoming acquainted with
Whitehead, Olson, as an American (see “Letter 27”), had sensed himself as “a
complex of occasions/ themselves a geometry/ of spatial nature”: “I take
SPACE to be the central fact to man in America, from Folsom cave to now. I
spell it large because it comes large here. Large, and without mercy” (CMI,
11). And elsewhere: “It started, for me, from a sensing of something I found
myself obeying for some time before, in Call me Ishmael. It got itself put
down as space, a factor of experience I took as of such depth, width, and
intensity.”16
As a result of the movement westward, Olson sensed the American space as
the possibility of a new opening confronting a culture that had renounced its
living space and repressed its experience in space. He sees Americans as “the
last first men,” and assumes they will still be granted the possibility of growth
in a space that is not yet entirely spoiled, despite the “Cartesian” mistakes that
the people of Boston and the rest of the original settlers made when they came
to the continent. The end of “Letter 27” clarifies that the power of individuals
lies not only in their own growth since, invariably, it is also the growth of the
space of which they are part. Gloucester now relies on Olson, who, by
growing into Maximus, will also lead to its own growth. The emphasis is
twofold: one must grow from space, but space must be concretized, a place is
required. Olson views himself as a means for Gloucester to discover its own
shape, and thereby also shaping him to be Maximus. Growth, then, is dis-
covering, it is the prehensive look, the concrete observation that engenders
the whole from its details. This process is revealed (to the growing reader) as
early as “Letter 2”:
they hid, or tried to hide, the fact the cargo their ships brought back
was black (the Library, too, possibly so founded). The point is
(hidden
city
(TMP, 9)
The mast that Olson seeks to raise in “Letter 1,” the bird’s wings, the bird’s
perspective, the sailing and the flight—all face the corruption of the present,
which “slows” its growth. Olson is forced to create a hierarchy in order to
build a new, “nonhierarchical” ethos. And why, and according to what “objec-
tive” criterion besides Olson’s view, is the flight of the lance preferable to “mu-
sick”? And why is the poetry of Ferrini, to whom “Letter 1” was sent as a real
letter, before becoming the first unit of the poem, considered no good ? Why
is there no room for Ferrini’s poetry in a “nonhierarchical” reality? To build a
new world, we must apparently destroy whatever preceded it or, at least,
replace it with a hierarchy that will advance a new purpose. To penetrate so as
to reveal the “true” city, to build it anew, is to stick a lance: the opening lines
of The Maximus Poems attest to the didactic, guiding facet of Olson/Maximus:
In the name of the way, or so it would appear, the lance is sharpened, and
the dance is celebrated on islands of blood. Is not Olson, who obeys his
creatures, imposing his way and setting up clear hierarchies? At the beginning,
Olson’s approach is definitely critical and hierarchical, and only toward the
middle of the volume does he seem to allow his zealous pen to cool down.
This is how things appear for as long as he goes on digging (“the archeology of
the morning”) inward, into the city, into himself, so that he might grow
upward, outward:
Olson’s wings, and those of the other city’s inhabitants, are fettered by the
chains of a three-hundred-year-old American settlement that has ignored
space. Olson declares he must do the “clearing out” that he ascribes to
Whitehead in “A Later Note.” In order to become the foundation of the city,
Olson adopts at the outset a sharp and critical wording. “Letter 1” is crowded
with forceful and even violent verbs: “o kill kill kill kill kill” (TMP 8). After
establishing his faith in his own power, Olson will acknowledge that his own
process of growth also enables the growth of the city: the personal is also
invariably collective. The light, in “Letter 2,” “does go one way toward the
post office,” since the post office is a metonymy of Olson’s father, the post-
man.17 The city being discovered revolves around the axis that is Olson/
Maximus, the center on which revelation relies and from which its rebuild-
ing becomes possible. Obviously, the dis-covery is also invariably a self-
discovery, as Olson puts it in “Maximus, at Tyre and at Boston” (which is
“Letter 21”):
Olson is a child of the concrete space that is Gloucester and, in this sense,
not only is the unity multiplicity, but the one makes many: the place is a
multiplicity of the one, and Gloucester is an event created through one’s
“phenomenology of place.” Maximus is a junction of “external” and “inter-
nal” forces in the space and the body that is Olson, of “prehensions” whose
concrescence gives rise to him and to the city, as well as to the world and the
cosmos, as “subjects.” Olson/Maximus as a “subject” differs from other “sub-
jects” due to the specific form in which all the data are mutually qualified.
The process, however, is always “internal”: the “prehended” “object” is not
something external to the prehending “subject,” but a concrete element in its
becoming; the “subject” is identified with its object, and Maximus is identi-
fied with his place, his city. The “subject” and the “object” both continue
growing, realizing themselves in a maximalist process as the poem develops.
In the first volume, Olson walks the streets of the city bearing his words to his
fellow citizens, as in “Letter 5”:
I’ll put care where you are, on those streets I know as well as (or better:
I have the advantage
I was a letter carrier
(TMP, 26)
That’s
the combination the ocean
out one window rolling
100 yards from me, the City
out the door on the next quarter up a hill was a dune
300 years covered very little so that, a few years back
a street crew were and I picked up the white
sand
On my back the
Harbor and over it the long arm’d shield of Eastern
point. Wherever I turn or look in whatever direction,
and near me, on any quarter, all possible combinations of
Creation even now early year Mars blowing
crazy lights at night and as I write in the day light snow
covering the water and crossing the air between me and
the City. Love the world—and stay inside it.
Concentrate
Enyalion, the Cretan god of war, is another name for Ares in The Iliad. He
represents both Mars and Hephaestus, with whom the poet wrestles. The
struggle conducted in “Letter 27,” is thus a war of Titans about the shape of
the world. From another perspective, this is a war against the dying of Myth
in order to make it newly relevant in the present; it is the creation of the story,
the drama. The design of the lines in “Letter 27”—the breaths—attests that
the battle in the space of the unit is also the battle that Olson, this time
perhaps as a poet who is himself Enyalion, wages against the Greeks, namely,
against the classic abstractions and dichotomies that stop growth (“Greeks is
the stopping”). In this sense, the struggle of Olson and Whitehead against the
“Greeks” “parallels” another battle taking place in the unit between Olson’s
father and the druggist who had “made a pass” at Olson’s mother. The battle
is the same battle: Olson is the child of his parents as he is the child of a
civilization moving westward, while Greece diverts it from its proper course.
Enyalion represents the principle of multiplicity—the battles—in unity, the
principle that every growth, every battle, is internal, since the “subject” is the
same as the “object” of the struggle. “Internal” growth means turning the
multiplicity of elements coming together into a whole that is more than the
sum of its parts, but without requiring something else, “external,” in order to
transcend and grow beyond its parts:
he turns back
Enyalion
Enyalion
the earth
shines
(TMP, 406–7)
these things
which don’t carry their end any further than
their reality in
themselves
(TMP, 46)
Growth from within yourself, within your own borders—which are the
borders of reality because there is no split between you and reality, no de-
tachment—this is the law of proportions that Enyalion, the Cretan war god,
concretizes and represents here. He grows from his own body, from his own
proportions, which are the measurements of the city, of the earth, of the entire
world. Olson also hints here at the Greek concept of beauty, which for him
“symbolizes” harmony, not only in the sense of the right proportions between
parts so as to create a “pleasing” combination, but in the sense of that which is
measured through identical measurements.22 Human beings rely on them-
selves for their growth. Olson growing into Maximus does so through his own
power, without relying on any external source. The battle in which Olson/
Enyalion is involved is a poetic battle, and the arena, as Fredman describes it,
is the poem:
Enyalion struggles to pry open the lid on human possibility, using a “picture” as
weapon. The picture is both the imago mundi and the display of his own naked
body; because he is the fully embodied imago mundi, however, these two versions
of the picture are really the same. He proves his heroism and his virility by making
himself vulnerable, by stripping naked and facing the present moment with noth-
4: CONCRESCENCE 61
ing but his own, innate visionary capacity. Enyalion, the imago mundi, represents
the naked, heroic powers of recognition resident in each individual (“all men/are
the glories of Hera [the etymology of ‘Heracles’] by possibility”), a power that
projective verse summons forth.23
Color is part of the armor of the poet, the warrior; he is the one shaping
reality in his own measure:
Honor, or color, point
sidered. The next phrase, “he has lost his hand,” reveals Enyalion also to be
Tyr. . . . While what appears to be the first version of the present poem also
describes Enyalion as follows:
Referred to is the story of Ares caught in bed with Aphrodite by her husband,
Hephaestus, who created a special net for the purpose. . . . However, in another
version of the present poem, Enyalion, or Ares, is also spoken of in terms of
Hephaestus . . . yet who also killed “the smith” (Hephaestus) himself. Further, Tyr
is not “the son of Odin,” as mentioned in the earliest version, Vidar is. So the
images are continuously confused, reversed, or interwoven, until the new figure—
who is also a Wanax and at times . . . has the traits of an ancient Irish hero—is
created, an archetypal composite but also a unique and novel hero.24
Before us is one who is many, many who are one, a thing and its opposite
contained together, the elimination of borders between one body and an-
other, the identity of the subject with its object. Enyalion, who is also Her-
cules, whose name means “the glory of Hera,” is Olson/Maximus as well as
his opponent. He is concrete in every unit but “brings with him” his various
faces, which had already been concrete and had already been realized in the
past. This “realization-in-the-past” influences the present realization, confers
on it the purposeful direction of the flow from one unit to another. This self-
functioning is the real internal constitution of the “subject,” the one that gives
the “subject” its identity. The way in which elements are linked to one
another is the “essence” of the thing itself. Hence the growth toward a self-
identity that does not rely on externals, as Whitehead phrases it: “An actual
entity is called the “subject’ of its own immediacy, and it combines self-
identity with self-diversity.”25 The content is constituted by the form; becom-
ing, as Whitehead states, constitutes being; prehension is what constitutes the
existing “subject.” The unit below is a “subject,” Maximus at a particular
moment in time, created from the field of words reactivated by the reader, and
deals with the becoming of the “subject” out of his/her “prehensions”:
The units of the poem, says Olson, are reactivated and they too are an
event. They rise from the page that is their space, while the reader-creator
reveals their power and experiences them:
I, dazzled
The present tense projects the process or revelation, which is also the
process of flourishing and the process of concrescence, onto the reader. The
“come in” in this unit is the same as “getting the universe in,” “as against man
alone . . .” that Olson ascribes to Whitehead in “A Later Note”: Olson is
Maximus, who, at the present of the unit, concresces as a fruit growing from
and with his living space, and his words are his breaths coming from the body,
from space. The “entrance” of indented stanzas on the page is evidence of the
breathing context that inhales, “prehends,” experiences in space and body, in
order to go out, fuse, and concresce.
For Olson, Whitehead’s worldview was not merely a metaphor: his poetry,
the movement inward into his memories, toward Gloucester’s past, to the past
of the cosmos in general, to the mythical and the primeval is a projection
forward, a building of himself as Maximus, of his city as a polis and of the
entire universe. The poet, Olson believed, influences the world, actually
creates it, as he learned from Whitehead’s thought and modern science as well
as from mythopoeic thinking, which he understood as having a ritual of re-
creation at its foundation. The problematic entailed by this process has
already been noted and will be revealed as more acute when we examine the
second concept of fluency, linked to time and to the transition from one unit
to another. To sum up the present chapter, I have chosen a poetic unit where
Olson brings together his thoughts about growth from place. “Letter 7”
64 CHARLES OLSON AND ALFRED NORTH WHITEHEAD
illustrates again the difficulties attending on the attempt to show the way to
the other. When Olson embarks on Maximus’s way, it is clear to him that the
poem is not a product; it is not a substance, a “furniture,” an aesthetic
product, but an unsplit experience, an event arising from the place and from
the body:
The Maximus Poems began with the letters that Olson wrote in 1950 to
Vincent Ferrini, who was then planning to edit a local periodical in Glouces-
ter.26 These letters include the first poetic unit and “Letter 7” cited above,
wherein Ferrini, the poet and editor, also emerges as a later—and earlier, from
the perspective of his appearance in the poem—ally of Descartes: a poet of
doctrines—“I think”—rather than a man singing—“I experience.” Fer-
rini, according to Olson/Maximus, does not activate his lungs, he does not
breathe, does not experience, does not create. As Olson explains in “Letter 5,”
Ferrini does not “use” the potentiality latent in the world in order to actualize
it, to grow with it:
You have had a broken trip, Mr Ferrini. And you should go hide in your cellar (as a
Portuguese skipper once had to, he’d so scared before a storm, and run for it,
leaving two of his men on the sea in a dory). (TMP, 24)
nor is it life
with a capital F
It’s no use.
There is no place we can meet.
You have left Gloucester.
You are not there, you are anywhere
where there are little magazines
will publish you
(TMP, 29)
67
68 CHARLES OLSON AND ALFRED NORTH WHITEHEAD
of multiplicity within unity has so far been discussed here at the micro level,
when dealing with the concrescence of the potentialities or “prehensions” that
constitute the poetic unit, the “subject” as a whole at the moment of experi-
ence. This concrescence is one of the two meanings of fluency. The special
problem of the long poem focuses on the second meaning of fluency which is
the continuity of becoming—how, if at all, is there fluency at the macro level,
in the transition between poetic units? How are they joined together in one
long poem? Does Olson’s long poem tell a story and preserve a narrative
character?
Olson seeks to concretize a poetics of the long poem that will integrate
thinking at two levels, which are the two kinds of fluency he finds in White-
head. Olson’s long poem works through the transition from the micro to the
macro levels: growth at every “here and now” of a poetic unit that is experi-
ence, and the fluency of one unit into the next, thus becoming a continuity
and culminating in one long poem, one story (the story of Maximus, the story
of Gloucester, and of the earth as a whole). The second concept of fluency, as
we saw, is linked to the concept of time:
The other kind is the transition from particular existent to particular existent. This
transition, again in Locke’s language, is the “perpetually perishing” which is one
aspect of the notion of time; and in another aspect, the transition is the origination
of the present in conformity with the “power” of the past.1
The “character” (the “personality”) Maximus was born and can penetrate
future acts of experience as a datum: at the end of the second poetic unit,
Maximus is the realization of a new pure possibility for whom “Maximus
1”—“Letter 1”—is a “datum,” a real element in other “data” (the materials
of “Letter 2”), whose synthesis is Maximus at this moment of experience, here
and now. And so on: no “actual entity” can possibly emerge in the world from
.
now on without taking into account the “object” Maximus in its process of
becoming (even if only as part of an excluding selection). Every Maximus,
every actualized Maximus, every actualized poetic unit faces now an objective
immortality. It ceases to exist as an “actual entity” in its initial mode of
existence, but continues to exist in other modes of existence and to affect the
world as an actual “object.” It loses its status as a subject, but acquires
“objective immortality.”
In a poetics relying on the concept of fluency developed by Whitehead,
Olson wages a twofold struggle in order to preserve the possibility of telling a
story, to be able to claim that a real link exists between the units, and a real
unity within the growing multiplicity of the (“poetic”) experiences. On the
one hand, he must contend with the difficulties that arise from renouncing
the concept of an object persisting through time, of a substance persisting
over changes; on the other hand, he must contend with the answers given by
modern physics to seventeenth-century physical theory, answers that left the
world (and the human being) fragmented, frozen, and “spatialized,” as a
result of the new perceptions of time. How can we say that Maximus is one,
that Gloucester is one, that the poem is one? How can we tell a story, join the
fragments, the units, in a scientific and poetic world (an obviously artificial
split for Olson) that no longer believes in the concept of entity and does not
accept the creative dimension of time? In an era increasingly skeptical about
purposeful validity or causal validity (two kinds of “metanarratives”), Olson
tries to link a poetic “drop of experience” here and now to the next poetic
“drop of experience” in order to tell a story that is more “open,” but still
marked by causal and purposeful determinacy. The poetics of multiplicity
within unity, as Olson learns from Whitehead, relies on equilibrium, on
balance, on mutual dependence and relativity rather than on the subordina-
tion of one concept to another. Whitehead’s philosophy attempts to build a
description of the world that will not rely solely on one side in the conceptual
confrontation between time and space, fluency and atomization, movement
and stability, freedom and determinacy (and so forth), which had charac-
terized Western culture. The intuition that “all things flow,” Whitehead tells
us, is one of humanity’s first generalizations, which he phrases as “the flux of
things.” Then, he qualifies this statement: “But there is a rival notion, anti-
thetical to the former. . . . This other notion dwells on permanences of
70 CHARLES OLSON AND ALFRED NORTH WHITEHEAD
things.” Whitehead finds these two notions united in one integral experience
in two lines of a famous hymn:
Here the first line expresses the permanences, “abide,” “me,” and the “Being”
addressed; and the second line sets these permanences amid the inescapable flux.
Here at length we find formulated the complete problem of metaphysics. Those
philosophers who start with the first line have given us the metaphysics of “sub-
stance”; and those who start with the second line have developed the metaphysics
of “flux.” But, in truth, the two lines cannot be torn apart in this way.3
they are moving. Time, as Hawking argues, “became a more personal con-
cept, relative to the observer who measured it,” so that anyone trying to unify
gravity with quantum mechanics had to introduce the idea of “imaginary”
time:
But, of course, our sense of time tells us a big difference prevails between
the forward and backward directions, and we wonder with the physicist,
“Where does this difference between the past and the future come from? Why
do we remember the past but not the future?” The laws of science, then, do
not distinguish between the forward and backward directions of time. But
there are at least three arrows of time that do distinguish the past from the
future, as Hawking sums up: “They are the thermodynamic arrow, the direc-
tion of time in which disorder increases; the psychological arrow, the direc-
tion of time in which we remember the past and not the future; and the
cosmological arrow, the direction of time in which the universe expands
rather than contracts” (152).
From the perspective of physical theory, the problem is how to reconcile
the symmetric laws of physics—which are universally valid and do not
distinguish between here and there, between left and right, between past and
future—with a number of processes that do not follow this symmetry and
show direction, an “arrow of time,” asymmetry. In another formulation (less
precise though more “popular”), the question is: Does time flow? Does the
concept of time convey “true” development? Or is time given as space, as a
dimension, past and future existing “in the same sense”? Is the universe a
collection of situations that exist to the same extent, the “now” merely a cross-
section of space-time; for some observers in the universe events taking place
“now” are in my past as well as in my future? Are “drops of experience,” poetic
units, mutually isolated and detached? If so, we must agree with Einstein that
science cannot grasp our sense that the “now” differs from the past and the
future, and that “psychological” time, with its emphasis on the now, lacks
objective meaning:
Sceptic: You still haven’t explained to me why I feel the flow of time.
Physicist: I’m not a neurologist. It has probably got something to do with short-
term memory processes.
Sceptic: You’re claiming it’s all in the mind—an illusion?
Physicist: You would be unwise to appeal to your feelings to attribute physical
qualities to the external world. Haven’t you ever felt dizzy?
Sceptic: Of course.
Physicist: So, I maintain that the whirling of time is like the whirling of space—a
sort of temporal dizziness—which is given a false impression of reality by our
confused language, with its tense structure and meaningless phrases about the past,
present and future.11
The question of the long poem touches precisely on this issue: Is there
indeed a real link between the poetic units, which turns the long poem into a
unity? Is it possible to grow as one and build a story, or are the split, the
fragmentation, the detachment, and the lack of contact between the elements
of the illusion that is the subject or its story perhaps inevitable? Olson wished
for more than this illusory link: there is continuity; there is an inner link and a
possibility of renewal, of “creativity,” of growth. Thus was Maximus, the man
and the poem (two that are one), created; Whitehead’s method provided him
with the metaphysical foundation. We face here the same problematic pre-
sented at the micro level, concerning Olson’s understanding of the becoming
of the isolated poetic unit. But this problem becomes more acute when we
consider, at the macro level, the long poem as a whole: in order to read Olson
correctly, particularly in an era that is “antimetaphysical” and hence disdain-
ful of the notion of “correct” reading—do we need to know and accept his
worldview, which is systematically formulated in Whitehead’s method? Does
the poem rely on the “correctness” of a metaphysical method that is Olson’s
74 CHARLES OLSON AND ALFRED NORTH WHITEHEAD
therefore, the long poem is not yet another poetic form but poetic work prior
to any classification. But the reader remains troubled: if Olson’s truth is not
the reader’s truth, if Olson’s truth is not even known to the reader, if science
will eventually dismiss Olson’s worldview (considering that, even in his own
time, several prominent trends found it unacceptable), if concepts such as
truth are no longer solid—how will the re-enactment process take place in the
course of reading the poem?
In the context of discussing fluency and the flow of time, it could be said
that Olson was, on the one hand, part of the poetic process of breaking
dichotomies. The binary compound text-world of American poetry had been
progressively eroded by Lowell, Berryman, and Ginsberg, to name but a few
of his close contemporaries. On the other hand, Olson advances a serious
claim whereby the creative process is synonymous with the “poem” and thus
writing poetry is actually writing a long poem, since any poem is always a
constituent of a longer poem. This claim is going far beyond a mere blurring
of boundaries. Olson transcended his time and place, venturing metaphysical
claims about reality and relying on assumptions considered unorthodox in
terms of the dominant cultural trends. Lowell or Berryman thus becomes the
hallmarks of a fragmentation in which the next (not necessarily chrono-
logically) poetic steps lead to a retreat into language and to increasing detach-
ment from “true reality,” despite or precisely because they were poets dealing,
as it were, directly with life. The crisis in their poetry, ostensibly personal, is
obviously a poetic and “metaphysical” crisis; poetry will now declare itself to
be concerned a priori with itself or, in other words, with language. Poets
whose starting point is cosmological will necessarily appear “weird” against
this background, and certainly in their attempt to write an epos. In another
formulation: to write in the epic tradition after Pound is, so to speak, an
inconceivable move, and even in Pound’s time it had been an altogether
different kind of epic.
Except that Olson did want to write an epos: indeed a different one, but
still one preserving the cosmological and metaphysical dimension. Already in
his poem “The Kingfishers,” which is addressed to Pound, he points to the
breakup of boundaries in Western tradition that had led Pound and his long
poem to a dead end. As he makes progress in the “project” of The Maximus
Poems, he understands his need for the second kind of fluency, which is the
macroscopic process explaining the continuity of the world, of the human
being, of the poem. This is the continuity of the organism, “the subject,” “in
the course of time,” “with the flow of time,” unlike the initial growth, the
microscopic process that describes the act of becoming here and now. Olson
wanted to go on telling stories or, in another formulation, to preserve the
arrow of time rather than accept its spatialization. The orthodox approach
76 CHARLES OLSON AND ALFRED NORTH WHITEHEAD
accepts the asymmetry of time and views it as an open problem, but views the
passing of time as only an illusion, derived from this asymmetry. Philosophers
like Whitehead and Bergson13 are unusual in this regard, in their attempt to
save the flow of time from a physics that does not acknowledge it.14 Time and
space do indeed become with his growth into Maximus, with his breathing,
with his speech; his poetry, as energy, as an individual’s activity, makes him
grow. This is the very struggle within reality, with reality, creating reality by
contending with it, which obviously extracts a price:
of the dog
(TMP, 414)
The mouth is Olson’s, who, while singing, grows himself, the world, space
and time; the event that is the human being is embodied for Olson in his
breathing, which leads to his actual growth; poetry is singing, is breathing, is
actual growth. But the mouth is, at the same time, the mouth of the dog (the
wolf ) Fenris, with whom Maximus struggles, this time in the shape of Tyr
(which is also another facet of Enyalion, as noted). The Nordic god of war
loses his hand in the mouth of the wolf, but manages to imprison him. A river
named Von, or Expectation, flows from the wolf ’s saliva. Fenris, the dog, is
also a “reincarnation” of, for instance, Cerberus, the Greek guardian of the
infernal gates, whose drooling saliva when carried by Hercules resulted in the
growth of the aconite. This is an illustration of “objective immortality” (the
hand goes on living in the wolf ’s mouth), of creating by taking in and taking
out: the wounded, amputated hand is Olson’s writing hand, which keeps
growing back again and again, in Olson’s as well as in the reader’s mouth. The
renewal of the event, its repeated recreation, forms space and time with its
experience; growth is always internal.15
Olson’s reliance on “internal” growth, on experience as the starting point,
compels him to look at the other aspect of fluency as well, which we defined as
a “continuity of becoming,” following Whitehead. The thermodynamic arrow
(the lack of order in closed systems increases with time) and the cosmological
arrow, the prominent aspects of the asymmetry of time vis-à-vis space, con-
verge in Olson’s perception of the human being as an expanding universe
within an expanding universe, a story within the story being told. Time and
5: FLUENCY 77
space, “the organizing frameworks” of the narrative, grow with the character,
with the story, with the poem. The body, the organism, actually represents the
biological arrow, which is merely an outcome of the thermodynamic arrow. It
is the basis of the macroscopic asymmetry (which is conveyed in the second
law of thermodynamics), the basis for growth in the temporal sense of the
human being (as individual, as community, as civilization, and as species), of
the flower. Human beings must learn to acknowledge boundaries, their
boundaries, and the limitations of their bodies, thus actually enabling their
growth, their dance, their poetry, which will break through these boundaries:
Tyrian Businesses
1
The waist of a lion,
for a man to move properly
2
how to dance
sitting down . . .
II
a hollow muscular organ which, by contracting vigorously, keeps up the
(to have the heart
. . . . .
(When M is above G, all’s
well. When below, there’s
upset. When M and G are coincident,
it is not very interesting)
1
(peltate
is my nose-twist, my beloved, my
trophy
tropical American diffuse and climbing pungent
78 CHARLES OLSON AND ALFRED NORTH WHITEHEAD
3
The seedling
of morning: to move, the problems (after the night’s presences) the first hours of
He had noticed,
the cotton picks easiest
As my flower,
after rain, wears
such diadem
As a man is a necklace
strung of his own teeth (the caries
of ’em . . .
4
(the honey is the lion, the honey
in woman
5
“felicity
resulting from life of activity in accordance with”
Our body, the source of our growth, also determines and dictates possible
directions for this growth. To grow from within yourself means to grow from
within your body; being part of space means that your body is part of it. The
dance comes out of your body, from its concreteness and its weight: the
combination is between total passivity, in the sense of awareness of the body’s
5: FLUENCY 79
presence, and activity, which can only emerge from this total passivity. In Part
I of “Tyrian Businesses” (which is “Letter 8”), Olson emphasizes the “weight”
of the body, which directs and prompts human movement. Part II opens with
a lexical definition of the heart, the center of the body, as Tyre, and Glouces-
ter, are a center for growth and expansion. “The waist of a lion” that teaches
“a man to move properly” and thus allows growth, relies on center and
balance. The biblical riddle “out of the strong came forth sweetness” dons a
“tangible” garb in Olson, stressing the physical (hence Samson) as a power
that shapes growth, as the basis of growth, latent in which is (the potentiality
of ) honey. The heart itself, as a metonymy of the body, attests to the integra-
tion between passivity and activity; the human being is the product of the
body, its diadem. The sailing mast (see again “Letter 1”) is raised from the
basis of the body rather than from reason; Olson cites Aristotle in order to
answer the question anew. Instead of Aristotle’s saying in Ethics—“felicity
resulting from a life of activity in accordance with reason”—Olson offers a
version that is slightly but significantly modified—“felicity resulting from a
life of activity in accordance with the metacenter.” The lexical definition of the
metacenter is quoted in answer to the question raised in the poetic unit cited
above, after it had already been identified with the heart (again, through a
quotation of part of its lexical definition) in the previous section of the poetic
unit. The metacenter, Byrd reminds us, is:
the critical point in the distribution of weight which determines the orientation of
a floating body. Of course, it is relevant to a ship, in which the metacenter must be
kept above the center of gravity or “there’s upset,” and, by implication, to the
dancer who drags herself across the ground, her metacenter and center of gravity
coinciding, and to western culture as a whole which has spread itself horizontally.16
The body is the home, is the ship. Both expressions recur throughout The
Maximus Poems, and since Gloucester is a fishing village and the history of
various ships features prominently in the poem, the body of the city is also
ships. The body, as Whitehead says, is a projection toward the future:
The macroscopic meaning is concerned with the givenness of the actual world,
considered as a stubborn fact which at once limits and provides opportunity for the
actual occasion. . . . Also in our experience, we essentially arise out of our bodies
which are the stubborn facts of the immediate relevant past. We are also carried on
by our immediate past of personal experience.17
The poetic unit “Tyrian Businesses” situates Tyre as a body that is the basis
for the growth of civilization and its move westward; Gloucester, which is
80 CHARLES OLSON AND ALFRED NORTH WHITEHEAD
identified with Tyre, must be a place where growth begins anew, where a new
morning dawns, a new beginning. The word morning, which is omitted
throughout Part 3—“the first hours of ” [morning]; “the cotton picks easiest”
[in the morning]—emphasizes that the poem as a whole functions at the time
of its writing (and its reading) as an “exercise” and a “seedling” of morning (of
Olson/Maximus and of the reader/Maximus). Gloucester and Tyre are identi-
fied here not only with the (body of the) ship, and not only with the flower in
its manifestation as tansy (which “wears a diadem after rain”), but also with
the nasturtium, of which Olson cites part of the lexical definition (“peltate / is
. . . / a garden species”).
Von Hallberg explains in great detail the present appearance of the flower
as nasturtium:
First, nasturtium is derived from nasus, “nose + torquere, tortum, “to twist,” so
pungent is its odor. Its generic designation: Tropaeolum majus. Webster’s on Tro-
paeolum: “A genus of tropical American diffuse or climbing pungent herbs con-
stituting the family Tropaeolaceae (order Geraniales). They have lobed or dissected
peltate leaves and showy variously colored flowers. . . .” Tropaeolum derives from
Greek tropaion, the etymon not only of tropism but also of trophy—a monument
of the enemy’s being turned around. Trophy because “the climbing plant was
considered as representing ancient trophies, with its shield-shaped leaves and its
flowers suggesting gilded helmets spattered with blood and punctured with
lances.” That would be irresistible to one who began with the promise to “tell you/
what is a lance, who obeys the figures of/ the present dance” (M I, i). Nasturtium,
then, comes from bellicose beginnings: twisted noses and trophies. And nasturtium
leads in other directions: “cadmium yellow,” says Webster’s; Cadmus killed a dragon
(Tiamat), sowed the dragon’s teeth, reaped an army, founded a city (Thebes), and
introduced the Phoenician alphabet to Greece—Tyrian businesses.18
generic model that interests Olson is precisely the opposite of that intended
by someone choosing to write “serial poetry.” The reader is the one experienc-
ing, thus turning potentiality into actuality. The reader’s experience is the
teleological immediacy of the poem’s process. Only in this way can one
describe, by means of language, a reality that is actually a process. This
approach emphasizes reading as a concrete experience of existence, as grant-
ing a voice (in other words, breath) to the poem, which as a written text is an
abstraction about the world. Only in this way can the reader realize and feel21
the unity in the (vast and extensive) textual multiplicity that is the (poetic)
world. Olson contends here with the problem posed by language. Language
shatters unity in the microcosmic sense (turning the here and now, the
immediate, into something that exists in time—in language—and is analyz-
able—sequentially narrated), and in the macrocosmic sense (isolating events
from one another and assuming entities instead of process). Language as-
sumes beings (names) instead of becoming, thereby suppressing the nature of
reality as process, as becoming.22
Rather than serial advance, which breaks up concepts of time and world
and leaves them lacking real, “inner” continuity, the macroscopic process of
fluency is based on “creative advance” and on re-enactment. The flower
budding in “Tyrian Businesses” is recreated every time anew, bigger and fuller
because of previous seedlings and becomings. We have already read (i.e.,
activated) along the poem:
and my song
a cantus firmus
(TMP, 97)
flower grows and develops: peltate (in the poetic unit “Tyrian Businesses,”
which is “Letter 8”) blooms and becomes Olson’s shield in the unit above
(which is “Letter 21”). This unit reminds us of the battlefield with which we
opened this book, where this unit was already mentioned. The field of flowers
is a battlefield; that is, a battle is growth. This growth unfolds by realizing the
potential latent in the nasturtium, the flower opened by the reader in the unit
that is “Letter 21,” which includes its previous realization in the unit that is
“Letter 8,” protects the heart that had already throbbed in “Letter 8”; the
heartbeats are added in a “creative advance”; the flower returns to bloom,
Maximus grows and, with him, the city and the reader who opens the shield
to his heart. But latent in the flower are also further blooms, for instance in
“Letter 9” (“the flowering plum”); in the unit that is “Letter 13” (“And for
flowers, always / it’s flowers, presented”); in “Letter 14” (“Or might it read /
‘compare / the ripe sun-flower?’ ”); in the unit that is “Letter 17” (“they throw
flowers”); in the poetic unit “The Twist” that is “Letter 18” (in various ways,
some of which I consider below); and in “Letter 20,” among other ways
through a further link to the shield (“as it was a shield”). All these mentions
appear before the unit that is “Letter 21,” where the nasturtium that was the
starting point for the present discussion emerges.
The reader of the poem, which follows a linear course, encounters the
flower again and again in its different facets, re-enacting in every one of these
meetings its latent potential from previous units that have now become an
“object” (in Whitehead’s sense) in the concretization of the new unit. The
experience reconstructs the elements that were an actual experience in the
previous units and thus, slowly, the flower grows. The meaning of objectifica-
tion, the participation of the “actual entity” that has already been realized as
an element in the process of creating the new “actual entity,” is in fact a re-
enactment of the first “actual entity” in the becoming of the second “actual
entity.” The first “actual entity” is a unity of perceptions, or of “prehensions”
in Whitehead’s terms, and so is the second. Hence, this is a “prehension” that
has a “prehension” as an object, meaning a re-enactment of the first “prehen-
sion” by the second “prehension.” A real, “inner” continuity is thus created:
an “actual entity” emerges as a real factor that influences the new becoming of
a new “actual entity.”
Whitehead bestows a new, more “open” content on the concept of caus-
ality: the macroscopic process is conditioned by the past, but is open to
changes suggested by the present with its new “prehensions.” The “subject”
re-enacts the world and grows with it.23 This process applies to Olson as well
as to the reader: through their experience, both re-create the (poetic) world as
they advance from unit to unit, from one “drop of experience” to another, to
make up a cantus firmus.24
84 CHARLES OLSON AND ALFRED NORTH WHITEHEAD
This is the “golden flower” of Chinese and medieval alchemy [ . . . ] See esp. Jung,
Psychology and Alchemy, pp. 74 –75 and note: “The solar quality has survived in the
symbol of the ‘golden flower’ of Chinese alchemy . . .
The identification of Ocean with the Black Chrysanthemum here has been
prepared for in the line “Okeanos the one which all things are . . . [p. 172] and [p.
6] for the simply visual or descriptive aspect of this passage: “the water glowed,
//black, gold” . . . and also [p. 7] where the water of the harbor is described as “a
black-gold loin”—out of which spring the “seeds” which eventually “flower,” etc.
The combinations are endless.25
reading of the poetic unit, every experience, is a ritual, a retelling of the tale, a
re-creation of the world. The world was created by breath—that of every
single one of us; everyone is a creator, a narrator, as well as a part of the story.
The potentials for realization available to the reader when experiencing the
unit are infinite, as Butterick points out: “the combinations are endless.”
Everything is related to everything in The Maximus Poems, and it is hard to
even embark in an attempt to describe this phenomenon (my choice of the
“flower” is arbitrary in this regard): “Okeanos the one which all things are,”
for instance, refers to Heraclitus, who himself is “reincarnated” in various
manifestations along the poem; the flower, then, includes these manifesta-
tions as well. Furthermore, one should add that experiencing readers also
bring with them, “from outside,” prehensions that unite with their own
experience; the flower blooms again and again, always new, always different,
and the advance is always “creative.” “Creativity,” according to Whitehead, is
“that ultimate principle by which the many, which are the universe dis-
junctively, become the one actual occasion, which is the universe conjunc-
tively. It lies in the nature of things that the many enter into complex unity.”
Since an actual occasion is “a novel entity diverse from any entity in the
‘many’ which it unifies,” “creativity” introduces novelty into the content of
the many. Whitehead’s “creative advance” is the application of this principle
of creativity to each novel situation that it originates. Thus he arrives at “the
ultimate metaphysical principle,” in which the advance from disjunction to
conjunction creates a novel entity different from the entities given in disjunc-
tion. “The novel entity is at once the togetherness of the ‘many’ which it finds,
and also it is one among disjunctive ‘many’ which it leaves; it is a novel entity,
disjunctively among the many entities which it synthesizes.” As noted, the
many become one, and are increased by one.26
The Maximus Poems rests upon this principle. Olson’s fundamental as-
sumption, the assumption of his poetry, is that the poem is an organism and
the world itself is an organism. According to Olson, we have the ability to
create, which is the ability to narrate, which is the ability to bloom. Every one
of us is the chrysanthemum, or the black stone, which does not require
alchemy but self re-enactment. As Olson indicates, “that which exists through
itself is what’s called meaning.”27 This sentence was the epigraph that Olson
had suggested for a lecture he prepared in 1965 (“Causal Mythology”). But-
terick points out that it is taken from “the opening passage of the Chinese
sacred text translated by Richard Wilhelm as The Secret of the Golden Flower
(London, 1945).”28 But this is no secret for us, and the source of this
apparent secret—whether alchemy or Taoism—is irrelevant. Olson rejected
all the various forms of blurring mystical perception. The clarity of what
86 CHARLES OLSON AND ALFRED NORTH WHITEHEAD
exists through itself, and the experience of it, is what bestows meaning. Olson
holds that the strength of any comparison, in the legacy of Western tradition,
is in its ability to remove us from “the thing itself ”:
We do not find ways to hew the experience as it is, in our definition and expression
of it, in other words, find ways to stay in the human universe, and not led to
partition reality at any point, in any way. . . . All that comparison ever does is set
up a series of reference points: to compare is to take one thing and try to under-
stand it by marking its similarities to or differences from another thing. Right here
is the trouble, that each thing is not so much like or different from another thing
(these likenesses and differences are apparent) but that such an analysis only
accomplishes a description, does not come to grips with what really matters: that a
thing, any thing, impinges on us by a more important fact, its self-existence,
without reference to any other thing, in short, the very character of it which calls
our attention to it, which wants us to know more about it, its particularity.29
The experience of the thing itself is what reveals its quality and its being
part of a larger unity. What is ostensibly a symbol (the black flower) is actually
an opening to the unity of the experience and the creation. Particularity is the
only way to penetrate reality, the unity of it. Comparison is based on the
assumption of dichotomies. But if the “many” are to become “one” particu-
larity is reentering creation in its unity. Olson’s poetics is always methodology
and ethos, since it is form that creates content (becoming creates being). The
black flower is “reincarnated” into a lotus, the birthplace of the gods, in the
next poetic unit (“Maximus, to himself, as of ‘Phonicians’ ”):30
. . . the padma
is what was there BEFORE
one was. Is there. Will be. Is what ALL
issues from: The GOLD
The one who opens the leaves of the lotus, the padma, finds within it not
only the gods but also the (black) flower in its various manifestations. And
these, as the unit tells us, were there before, are there now, and will be there in
the future: the flower generates itself anew every time in all its facets, man-
ifestations, and realizations. Here too, then, the flower (the lotus) attests to
creation, which is internal, self-generated, from within. But this creation is
the creation of everything (“flower All the heavens”), the growing universe
5: FLUENCY 87
itself, the time and space themselves that expand in the very act of creation.
Hence the unity of opposites, which is also a principle in mythopoeic think-
ing according to Olson, enabling the sun in black heavens. Note again, for
instance, “Letter 14,” where the sun is already linked to a flower—“sun-
flower.” The sun itself is, of course, a god. Olson had read extensively on
ancient Egyptian myths and on Mesopotamian myths in general, and mate-
rials he borrowed from them are scattered throughout the poem. Heavens are
again linked to the ocean and to Heraclitus, for instance in the poetic unit
“MAXIMUS, FROM DOGTOWN—I” mentioned above: from the mating
of heaven and earth, Okeanos is born—according to Olson who quotes/
elaborates on Hesiod. “The world is a web of mutually linked and dependent
events,” as Whitehead tells us, and the poem is multiplicity within unity.
Thus will the flower continue to bloom from the poetic space in every
reading. The smell of the flower bears its increasing pungency from unit to
unit:
Nasturtium
is still my flower but I am a poet
who now more thinks than writes, my
nose-gay
(TMP, 632)
The appearances of the flower at the end of the long poem concretize the
entire way; latent in them is the complete story of the flower, which is the
story of Gloucester, which is Olson’s story. Ultimately, Olson preserves the
most basic feature of the long poem in its generic tradition: Olson builds a
world, he is a builder (or, to use another “image” central to The Maximus
Poems, he is a carpenter); the bricks are meant to be joined together for the
purpose of creating a structure. An architecture and a texture that relies on all
the bricks in order to create a “home,” which had not existed before and is
now an “object” in the world. But Olson goes even further in his thinking: the
building is a re-enactment of yourself, of the world, of the story. Olson knows
that “inside” and “outside” are one; he knows that every act of becoming in
the poetic unit re-enacts/rebuilds the act of previous experience, and only
thus are the world, the city, the poem, built. Olson tells a story, even if its
88 CHARLES OLSON AND ALFRED NORTH WHITEHEAD
organization differs from traditional plot patterns and is more open, “hiding
behind,” as it were. The story of himself, the story of Gloucester (as a city and
a community) are tied to each other, and they are parts of one story. But this is
also the story of Olson’s striving and disappointment, as it seems, over his
inability to make the city grow with him. The poetic unit (TMP, 632)
illustrates the split that Olson had felt throughout the third volume of The
Maximus Poems (as we know it): the split between the poet and the flower in
the second line, and between writing and speaking in the last line, two
dichotomies that were shattered at the beginning of the struggle (“Letter 8” or
“Letter 21,” for instance) in order to realize the unity of a concrescent world.
As we see in another unit “Maximus of Gloucester” (on p. 473, which is
discussed elsewhere), Maximus withdraws, abstains, forsakes his crown, re-
nounces his power to shape the city and the world. The problematic we have
presented concerning the possibilities of communication between Olson,
who presents his beliefs, and the readers, who have their own, leaves its mark
on Olson/Maximus himself; he feels a failure, his fellow citizens do not listen
to him, do not cooperate with him.
In the process of his story-growth, as Olson understood it, the function of
the narrator is always emphasized (connecting, once again, with the tradition
of oral culture as the source of the epical). The narrator returns to the position
of strength he had lost as writing came to dominate speech, to his capacity to
shape and influence the world. Narration is the process of the story’s actual
production and not only the process of its being told. The story, then, is never
finished, always in a process of creation-narration, always in the present (for
the narrator; the “right” reader becomes a narrator too, although her story is
necessarily different). The human being narrates herself, her city, and creates
them (with)in her story. The story is open but conditioned. When “nose-
twist” becomes “nose-gay,” or splits (in TMP, 634) between “the Twist the
Nasturtium,” Olson is already renouncing his unifying, narrating, construct-
ing power. “The Twist,” found here in lowercase, is the name of a poetic unit
(which is “Letter 18”), and appears there in capitals. This transition is a
testimony to the disappointment, the withdrawal, the shrinking that Olson
experiences at the end of the road. The nose-twist (“Letter 8”) is a seedling
opening up in “Letter 18,” “The Twist.” In this unit, the turning inward
toward himself, the taking inward, is projected outward and gives rise to
Maximus in the first part of the book. Latent in the “nose-gay” at the end of
the book is the absence of this turning, implying withdrawal, taking in
without taking out, namely, a split. “The Twist” (“Letter 18”) is itself a
realization of another twist as well, which is actually the same, as can be seen
in “Letter 15”:
5: FLUENCY 89
He sd, “You go all around the subject.” And I sd, “I didn’t know it was a sub-
ject.” He sd, “You twist” and I sd, “I do.” He said other things. And I didn’t
say anything.
. . . .
I sd, “Rhapsodia . . .
(TMP, 72)
In The Maximus Poems, for example, the Black Chrysanthemum becomes a central
image, associated with the ocean (2, 172–176, 180), with Heraclitus (172) with
Whitehead (501–502), with the sun (181, 441), with heaven (386, 441– 443,
501–502, 568) and the World Tree with its roots in heaven (509), with the
underworld (600), with flowering trees (45– 48) and with a number of the specific
flowers praised throughout the book: tansy (13–16) nasturtium (40– 41, 86–90,
634), lotus (181, 441– 443), and rose (478– 481, 565).33
Every unit, like a flower whose opening never ends, contains within it its
previous realizations, which were melted together and combined into an
open, though conditioned, story. This story, as Whitehead says, is
a process proceeding from phase to phase, each phase being the real basis from
which its successor proceeds towards the completion of the thing in question. Each
actual entity bears in its constitution the “reasons” why its conditions are what they
are. These “reasons” are the other actual entities objectified for it.34
90 CHARLES OLSON AND ALFRED NORTH WHITEHEAD
91
92 CHARLES OLSON AND ALFRED NORTH WHITEHEAD
story. “Story” in the sense that the only thing that really counts, again, is what’s so
exciting. After all, Herodotus goes around and finds out everything he can find
out, and then he tells a story. . . . So, that idea of breaking that word so that we
don’t talk about a concept “history”—that’s why I offered the damn thing is to
break up that word immediately, break it back to either a verb of Herodotus,
which, as some of you know, I’ve put a whole lot of weight on in working on a
longer—a “long” poem, like they say. And I found that, when Robert took that
split and did introduce the idea, that the minuteness that you’re after is the
histology, and the result that you may come up with is story, OK? (MUT 1:3)
The battle, then, as we are told from the start, is always the same battle,
and only its appearance and its representations differ: the contest with the
split, with the breakdown of Western culture and its severance from ex-
perience, from self-discovery (including all the connotations of this concept),
from growth—are once again the “topics on the agenda,” viewed from a
different perspective and with the aid of other concepts. The reader re-
quires only a minor name substitution, replacing Herodotus with Maximus,
in order to understand the meaning of Olson “being all over” the ancient
Middle East, the Mediterranean basin, Tyre, Egypt, and, obviously, the early
settlement in the United States, including Boston, Gloucester, and all the
cultures, people, and places filling the pages of his book in the process of his
growth with The Maximus Poems. Olson, as a historian-poet, gathers the
voices and the stories, and revives a history taking shape anew through him; as
Karlins notes, “the use of ‘he sd’ has the effect of peopling the poem with a
democratic host of anonymous people. It suggests a multitude of voices
coming together, rather than Olson’s isolated voice.”2 This, then, is insertion
for the sake of extraction, a re-building of the split continent, a retelling of
what is now his story, which is the story of the place and the community
growing with him:
Here again is Maximus, giving birth to himself with space and time in the
dog’s mouth, with the flowers he sends, with the poem that keeps growing.
This poetic unit, as Butterick indicates,3 like other poetic units in The Max-
imus Poems (177, 264, and others), presents Maximus as a voyager in some of
his “guises,” faces, and “transfigurations”: Pytheas, Odysseus, Hercules,
Manes; these figures are related to his own manifestation as Enyalion, as a
poet, as recurrently struggling with the dog, with reality, in order to reactivate
himself, to go on expanding, growing with his poetry. The issue, obviously, is
that the third person is identified here with the character of Maximus: he is
the one rising from all the characters that were and are realized within him.
These are his voyages; this is a mappemunde that Maximus builds, that
emerges from him—he is the one who gives birth to the world and he is the
one contained in it. The historical materials are again relevant, exist in their
present concretization, in their presence here and now, in their configura-
tion into an “actual entity,” an actual experience. History exists as a poten-
tial for realization, and is realized anew at every moment. The map of the
world, and Maximus himself, expand and change, and the “name”—the
identity—of the map is therefore fixed only for this moment of experience.
History is part of the present, “serves” the present in its growth, grows
anew with the creation of every here and now. Olson’s voyages in time
(and in space) are always in the present, the movement backward is in-
variably a movement forward (the movement toward the past is the move-
ment toward the future), and from it grows Maximus, from it grows his
city. The second volume of The Maximus Poems, showing on the cover a
map of the Earth (and Okeanos) before the separation began, opens with
“Letter 41”:
The battlefield of the poetic unit is alive; the battle is waged anew here and
now, and is ongoing: it is the poem. The opening, the movement forward (the
opening of the volume) is a movement backward, toward the past. In other
words: the present concretizes the past, reactivates it, as an immediacy of a
teleological process in which reality becomes actuality. The storm mentioned
in the poem marks the beginning of Olson’s path as a poet:
tion of Maximus himself (who wages his battle at the last frontier of classic
Greek thought):
to arrive at Ireland
anyway to get into the Atlantic
to make up a boil . . .
to travel Typhon
from the old holdings
(TMP, 265)
Thunder and lightning, wind and rain, storm and tempest might fitly be classed as
peloria, portents. . . . The word peloria covers, I [Butterick] think, both Earth-
powers and Sky-powers, both Giants and Titans; but it is not a little interesting to
find that quite early the word differentiated itself into two forms . . . what is earth-
born, and . . . heavenly signs.6
96 CHARLES OLSON AND ALFRED NORTH WHITEHEAD
exactly
300
years
writing
at the stile
before
the town
age
29
(TMP, 299)
Like Whitehead in “A Later Note,” Olson struggles in this unit with three
hundred years of deviance (from Olson’s perspective, the emphasis is on
poetic deviance), namely, the years of Descartes’s unquestioned domination.
Five years younger than Descartes, Olson embarks on a life endeavor aimed at
(re)building the settlement that Descartes had diverted from its desired course
(“Descartes, age 34, date Boston’s/ settling” (TMP, 132); Olson was born in
December 1910, and the storm marking his first poem occurs in the spring of
1940). This storm is already part of Maximus as Peloria: even the forces of
nature direct him and are directed to that purpose. The struggle represented
by these forces is analogous to the struggle represented by people like Stevens
the carpenter in the human environment; this is part of the movement
seeking to smash the cultural canon, which is the breakup of the Western
hierarchy: in the ritual of the poem, Maximus “summons” and brings into life
ancient forces (again the flower of the alchemy) against the rationality of the
West. Illustrating the possibility of “upward” growth, he breaks the orderly
Cartesian line (in both content and form; see the unit above) so that he might
“climb” on it, begin a new beginning.
98 CHARLES OLSON AND ALFRED NORTH WHITEHEAD
“Letter 41” demonstrates how history, in the Olsonian sense, brings all
paths together: the spatial movement from East to West, which is the history
of human wanderings over the globe; the movement along the time axis from
past to present (although this, as noted, is reversed); and the movement from
the bottom up (volcanoes, the Great Valley Rift, Okeanos—also present as a
monster—with its subterranean currents, linked in one sense to the wander-
ings of nations and not only of continents, and in another to the transition
from the unconscious to the conscious—Olson hints at Jung in the poetic
unit above):8 the present is a synthesis of historic data in the sense that they
actualize and touch the individual as such. History is a story whose narration
is always the present; to be a storyteller is to participate in the story.
In “Letter 23” (TMP, 103), Olson proclaims “the historical principle” and
simultaneously implements it. The poetic unit deals with the beginnings of
Gloucester.9 The letter opens by presenting “the historical facts”10 and pro-
ceeds to clarify the question of what is a historical fact, what is its status, and
what is history:
that muthos
is false. Logos
isn’t—was facts. Thus
Thucydides
6: STORY, HISTORY, MYTH 99
We thereby return to the field, which yields the historical facts stored
within it. For Olson/Maximus, the facts, history, are in the yard. But not only
in the conventional sense, meaning that they coincidentally fit the biography
of Olson (who grew up across fishermans ffield), and characterize the tradi-
tional historian: facts that document events from the past and thus Merk, who
may be scared by Olson’s lack of historiographic responsibility. History is a
potentiality for realization and, as such, is a “stubborn fact.” The question of
what is history and what it means to be a historian is related to an understand-
ing of the concepts of myth, and of logos, and to the interpretations that have
shaped our views regarding the distinction between “history” and “myth” and
how these two are—or not—related to “story.”
Olson points to Pindar’s distinction11 between two concepts that, prior to
their split, were synonymous in their use, and now denote truth and falseness.
Pindar identifies the concept of muthoi with Homer, asserting it can distort
human judgment to distinguish truth from falseness through its poetic power,
thereby fixating the concept of muthos as a false story. According to Thomson,
this use of the concept creates the meaning known to us, of myth as a fictional
story (while logos assumed the philosophical meaning that we ascribe to it of
truth, rationality, the word, God, and so forth). But at first, Olson remarks,
logos and muthos had meant the same, as can be seen in Homer: “Muthos with
him means ‘what is said’ in speech or story exactly like Logos in its primary
sense” (SVH, 20). Olson ends the unit in TMP, 502, with the word “Dixit”
(which means “he said”). The concepts of truth and falseness that have
entered the discussion are an aspect of the struggle, originating in oral culture,
between the authority of the poet as a hegemony that refines the story
through its (rhythmical, organizing) tools, and the clinging to a “historical
fact” that bestows legitimacy on the story. In other words, this is the struggle
between Herodotus and Thucydides: does the story become valid by virtue of
its inner coherence and synthesis, for which the poet is responsible? Is the
poet the one who shapes the historical in the story of the present of which he
100 CHARLES OLSON AND ALFRED NORTH WHITEHEAD
is part (and, in that sense, “subjective”)? Or, rather, is the historian seeking
“objective” truth without, as it were, affecting the description of the events
presenting a “historical story”? Is his story based on a correlation suggested by
a purportedly detached outsider, construing abstractions that fit the “objec-
tive” molds of universal place and time. The historian of the logos tells us that
“History is the Memory of Time,” as Olson names the poetic unit that quotes
the early seventeenth-century settler John Smith (TMP, 116) in order to
correct him: “my memory is/ the history of time” (TMP, 256). As Thomson
says, the Greek word mousike means not only music but also “the state of self-
organization and intensity of attention which the bard must attain”:12 “As the
people of the earth are now, Gloucester / is heterogeneous, and so can know
polis / not as localism, not that mu-sick (the trick”) (TMP, 10). No more mu-
sick, says Olson, “a sick story from a sick mouth,”13 says Von Hallberg, but
rather mousike, a story relying on the narrator’s rhythm, which is the meaning
of history as Olson understands it:
(the LIE of history is that man can find or take any relevance out of the infinite
times of other man except as he pegs the whole thing on his time: and I don’t mean
times, that sociological lie, I mean your TEMPI—mine, in short, all that TIME
IS, is RHYTHEM (and there is no way of knowing any rhythym OTHER THAN
YOUR OWN than BY your own.14
tell the “story of Gloucester,” emphasizes that the heart, the breath (or, the eye,
the ear, and other examples already cited), namely, the living organism, is what
shapes his story and the story of his place. According to this basic perception of
reality, the time dimension originates in the growing organism (the beatings of
the heart, the various recurring cycles of the organism, and so forth), and in the
parallel sense of process known to us from the surrounding world; it is Olson’s
view, that human beings in the ancient world did not derive the abstraction of
the concept of time from the experience of time for them; time is an expression
of the willed order of creation: it weaves the events into a story.
This ancient worldview matches the direction that Olson’s quests and his
feeling had taken from the start. Olson had learned from his experience that
the movement backward—toward the mythical—is a movement forward,
with Whitehead, beyond the traditional perception of the present. His obser-
vation of the ancient world reveals to Olson the aim to which Melville, who
“closes” the canon of Western culture, is striving in his efforts. What Olson
wrote in CMI, for instance, on the harpoon hurled at the whale, about full
activity out of the physicality of presence, fits this perception of the ancients
as laid out by Frankfort: “the knowledge which ‘I’ has of ‘Thou’ hovers
between the active judgment and the passive ‘undergoing of an impression’;
between the intellectual and the emotional, the articulate and the inarticu-
late.” “Letter 2,” about the discovery, the exposure of the city, acknowledges
the city as a “Thou,” as a live presence whose potentialities can be articulated,
because “Thou” is “a presence known only in so far as it reveals itself . . .
experienced emotionally in a dynamic reciprocal relationship” (13).
Olson holds that myth, in the meaning preceding the split created by
Western philosophy severing it from its relevant and concrete context, plays a
central role in the ancient world. It is not legend, fiction, or some other
similar concept derived from its essence as a counterconcept to the logos. It is
neither an allegory nor a symbol: people in the ancient world do not think in
terms of signifier-signified; rather, for them “there is a coalescence of the
symbol and what it signifies” (21). Olson finds this concreteness among the
Mayan people,18 and strives for it in his own writing. In this regard, The
Maximus Poems are themselves myth, exploring and revealing a metaphysical
truth about the world, a work that preserves and ensures the discovery of the
“Thou” around us and with us. The telling of the myth becomes the ritual of
exposing the “Thou” and achieving real contact with it. The ritual is not
simply a symbolic act but an event in the universe, the recreation of the
universe, the creation of a new beginning by returning to the initial one;
hence the emphasis in the story of Maximus and Gloucester on “THE BE-
GINNINGS” (TMP, 235), on the “morning exercise,” which is the actual
work of the poet, the poem itself. Eliade illustrates this conception of myth
when arguing that it is “always an account of a ‘creation’; it relates how
104 CHARLES OLSON AND ALFRED NORTH WHITEHEAD
something was produced, began to be. Myth tells only of that which really
happened, which manifested itself completely.”19 For Olson, myth really
happens in his poem. Myth reminds humans of the story of their creation, of
their beginning, but it is also the story of the present since it allows them to
begin anew. According to Olson, the ancients saw themselves as part and
product of mythical events, hence their home is the entire universe:
The capital letters suggest that the forces of Nature are actual, present
entities affecting human beings. This approach contrasts with that of modern
humanity, whose members see themselves as a product of history; the differ-
ence Olson sees between modern and ancient men and women is precisely the
difference between their perception of beginnings. People in the modern
world regard themselves, in Eliade’s phrasing, as “the result of the course of
Universal History,” and thus do “not feel obliged to know the whole of it.”
But in this image of the ancients, “archaic societies are not only obliged to
remember mythical history but also to re-enact a large part of it periodically”
(13). Thus, the historian-poet that is Olson/Maximus has the possibility of
returning and beginning anew, to be always at the beginning. Although the
past has indeed ended and is now an object, in Whitehead’s terms it is a fact in
the present and, in this sense, it can be reactivated, it is a presence. White-
head’s metaphysics is, according to Olson, a response to a world of beginnings
expressed by the ancient perception of myth, although accommodated to
modern times: every experience is a ritual that recreates the universe and
reactivates the process of creation from the beginning. The concern with
myths of creation recurs often in Olson (particularly in the second volume,
and note again the mappemunde prior to the split on the cover); the “return”
to cosmogonic myths is a beginning, an opening that shapes his way as a poet
since “the cosmogony is the exemplary model for every creative situation”
(32). Olson’s “application” of the cosmogonic myth to all areas of life obvi-
ously attests, again, to his understanding of the unity of multiplicity, namely,
to the perception of myth as the story of a harmonious, organistic, and what
could be called ecological worldview.20 Olson’s worldview coincides here with
Eliade’s picture of man in “primitive” societies, who “feels the basic unity of
6: STORY, HISTORY, MYTH 105
all kinds of ‘deeds,’ works,’ or ‘forms,’ whether they are biological, psychologi-
cal, or historical” (31).
The myth enables re-creation by returning to the source, to the start, to
“the first beginning,” which is the cosmogonic beginning. For Olson, then,
the cosmogonic story is the source of all these stories, or, in other words, the
“local” myths are always a continuation or a return of/to the first story.
Hence, the poet, the storyteller, while (re) narrating the myth “lives” its time,
the mythical enters the present, the myth is made present through its narra-
tion, and, in this sense, the poem is a ritual. For instance, Okeanos and Earth
are active forces when Olson/Maximus stands at the harbor and when he
narrates their story (as well as when the reader reactivates the unit):
The time of the myth is not a simple “return” but rather a “revival” of the
primeval forces (Okeanos, the Earth) in a present whose “countenance”
differs from the reality of the past. The arrow of time, then, absorbs within it
the initial time of the creation as a creative force at every single moment in the
future of the universe (and the countenance of this future is constantly
changing). The poetic unit goes on to say:
(her hemispheres
loomed above me,
I went to work
like the horns of a snail
. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
And the thought of its thought is the rage
of Ocean : apophainesthai
(TMP, 240)
106 CHARLES OLSON AND ALFRED NORTH WHITEHEAD
In the unit, the movement from the “general” to the “personal,” from the
many to the one, illustrates the presence of the mythical as a force now acting
on the individual, on the speaker; Olson/Maximus activates the mythical
through his search for a new beginning. The beginning, the birth, of love,
from the body, from the earth, the growth of the one out of the many, in their
various expressions, is summed up in the Greek word apophainesthai, mean-
ing “that which shows forth.” From the fall into the “clefts of women” (which
hints at the union with the mythical Great Mother), the unit ends with a
projection (in the Olsonian meaning) of the mythical onto the future, which
will bring forth the wanted son: “The great Ocean is angry. It wants the
Perfect Child.” This ending attests to the tension between the individual and
the collective, between the narrator and the audience whose story the narrator
seeks to tell but feels that he has failed to turn his listeners into actual
participants, as it were.
For Olson, every new story is activated by the first story (while it re-
activates the first story), but its concretization is always changing. The return
to the first moment, to the cosmogonic myth, is actually the source of the
power to change, namely, the power of re-creation, to move forward with the
arrow of time: participation in the origin is what ensures control over this
power in the present; you cannot begin something unless you know its source,
how it first came into existence. This kind of knowledge is not external and
abstract but, to use Eliade’s language, “knowledge that one ‘experiences’ ritu-
ally, either by ceremonially recounting the myth or by performing the ritual
for which it is the justification.”21
At the conclusion of the poetic unit above (TMP, 240), Olson appears to be
asking himself what happens when the audience refuses to cooperate, or fails
to listen and therefore fails to know the source, when it does not experience in
order to know itself and its place so that it might change and grow. Olson tries
to “wake up” the citizens of the ailing city: he performs a ritual (for instance,
casting flowers upon the water) and sings the myth, their own stories, to the
townspeople.22 In the last volume of the TMP, however, Olson’s sense of
failure, signs of which are already evident midway, resonates clearly.
The split between myth and logos, then, represents for Olson the chain of
splits that began to characterize the Greek worldview in a process whose
beginning was marked by the pre-Socratic philosophers. As soon as the Greek
worldview began to grant autonomy to thought (to the intellect) and to draw
away from the concrete and the experience in favor of abstraction and con-
sistency; as soon as it began to separate ontic and epistemic levels (revealed
versus concealed, apparent versus concrete); as soon as the concept of “sub-
ject” and “object” separated from each other; as soon as the religious character
lost its holiness to secular representations—as soon as these processes became
6: STORY, HISTORY, MYTH 107
This tension also seems to characterize the work of Olson, who moves
within a textual culture but tries to preserve principles characterizing the oral:
“by mouth and by ear” are the poetic principles already listed in “Projective
Verse.” Olson tries to be a Homeric poet in a textual world, which made us, as
he argues, “unaware how two means of discourse the Greeks appear to have
invented hugely intermit our participation in our experience, and so prevent
discovery” (SW, 54). With his poetics of realization (by the readers) Olson
tries to preserve the speech dimension of oral culture, the concreteness of
speech, which leaves the task of memory (of the historical legacy) open to
variations and given to changes because it is in a continuous present. Olson
tries to preserve a way of contact between the individual and the community,
between the “I” and the “Thou” (which is the entire world). This is his war
against “logic and classification,” the two means of discourse that the Greeks
appear to have invented, which prevent discovery and experience, that is,
prevent actuality. The actuality of the world, in Whitehead’s terms, is the
actuality of speech, which transforms into “object” when put into writing; it is
a realized potential that will only become actual at a time of a renewed
6: STORY, HISTORY, MYTH 109
ity: to tell what is relevant to the story you are telling, to the memory you are
building, from your own way, in the place you are telling, through your seeing
eyes, through your feeling body, through the identity you are building. The
historian-poet Olson wants to be the one who chooses and selects his data,
without being obsessed by a duty to record everything.29 He “mentions” what
is worth mentioning. “To mention,” Detienne reminds us, in Greek is “ ‘to
remember’ (mnesthenai) or ‘to give a name to’ (epimnathai). That is to say,
simply to speak of it” (57).
The distinction between Herodotus and Thucydides, between myth and
logos, between history and story, is one of Olson’s landmarks in the deviation
of Western culture, which led to its decline. Thucydides is an ally of Descartes
in the ongoing battle waged by Olson, who enlists Whitehead and Herodotus
in the battlefield of his unit “A Later Note” and of the long poem as a whole.
Thucydides, like Descartes, marks the watershed that the poet-warrior must
return to cross, since he represents a rationalist historian that no longer has
anything in common with “tellers of tales who are logographers and in the
same category as poets.” Olson shares Detienne’s view that “the Peloponne-
sian War puts an end to the desultory and scattered history of myth, the will-
o’-the-wisp that amuses Herodotus.” (61)
If to be a poet is to be a historian, then it is to be like Herodotus, a teller of
tales, a reteller of myths, and generally, to practice a craft to be taken seriously.
Work and creativity are pleasurable, but also, in their deep meaning, they are
political and ethical terms. The poet warrior is taking a stand vis-à-vis reality.
7
Stance
I knew no more then than what I did, than to put down space and fact and
hope, by the act of sympathetic magic that words are apt to seem when
one first uses them, that I would invoke for others those sensations of life I
was small witness to, part doer of. But the act of writing the book added a
third noun, equally abstract: stance. For after it was done, and other work
in verse followed, I discovered that the fact of this space located a man
differently in respect to any act, so much so and with such vexation that
only in verse did I acquire any assurance that the stance was not in some
way idiosyncratic and only sign of the limits of my own talent, only
wretched evidence of the lack of my own engagement at the heart of life.
But the mark of life is that what we do obey is who and what we are.
And we have no other recourse than to see what we do as evidence of what
we are, and use it, for good or worse, (1), to make more use of what we
obeyed in the first place, and, thereby, (2), continue the pursuit of who we
are (which pursuit seems to me now only a permanent one, if the only
excusable one of men so inclined).
—Olson/Melville
weave
your birds and fingers
new, your roof-tops,
clean shit upon racks
...
with others like you, such
...
o kill kill kill kill kill
those
who advertise you
out)
(TMP, 6–8)
Maximus is the character that rises and grows from Olson against this
background, this ugly present, as a personal and general need to direct a re-
building process and adopt a stance toward action. We are what we do, and
our actions invariably take place within a given space, in a place that grants us
identity through our deeds. Gloucester—the city, the community, the nest—
is now exposed to an alienated world that Olson characterizes as a pejoroc-
racy; a word first used by the poet in his poem “The Kingfishers” and
meaning, “Literally, ‘worse-rule’ (Latin pejor, and -ocracy, as in democracy,
from the Greek krateia), a worsening form of government. Borrowed from
Pound, Canto LXXXIX of The Pisan Cantos.”2
Olson condemns a cultural reality lacking in genuine contact—either of
the people with one another or between them and their city or between them
and the space in which they live. Contact is blocked by an abstract language,
unrelated to actual reality, which leaves individuals in their isolation.3 The
attitude to language reflects the attitude to the human being:
This is the recurring critique of Western capitalism and its values, using the
language of advertising as its metonymy: an abstract, passive language that
represents an isolated, passive life, taking away individual identity, and with it
the freedom and the will to act and engage in a life of action. “The big
machinery of the word, press, radio, movies is horrible,”4 says Olson, who
watches the aging Pound confined at St. Elizabeths due to his treason and his
fascist broadcasts, and is appalled: “Cut off, he is cut off from life. That a poet
should choose hate!” (44). The nest, the city, were shaped by a love that is love
of the world, of the other, of the community, and of oneself as part of all these,
while also being characterized as possessing an independent identity. Olson’s
basic stance, which guides Maximus’s behavior, is one of love. Love is form,
creativity, giving, birth, to create and pad the nest, to build while singing: the
feather in the bird’s beak building the nest is the poet’s pen, the web of the text
that, as noted above, is a “rhapsody.” What is at first glance hidden should
perhaps be emphasized—love and the search for love is the power that drives
Olson to begin with. The flight from the “lyrical,” egocentric self is replaced
by love of the other and with the other (of the world). Love is an expression of
contact and a search for contact. Olson seeks contact with the reality hiding
behind the abstract language, back to the language of the body, which is the
language of the world.5 The language of advertising represents the sickness of
a sick government, whose patterns attest to the decay of its ethical-political
life. Tired of a politics he well knew, of the conflict between power groups,
Olson wishes human beings to return to political activity in the old sense of
this term. He regards the aim of politics and political institutions, as Murray
characterizes Greek’s politics: “to discover or to aid in the creation of a general
will to action, and to express that general will in an ordered ritual.”6 But this
“concept of the eunomia (good order)” that dominated the early history of the
polis (21) should be understood as multiplicity within unity and not as unity
in the sense of sameness. Olson believes that politics should be concerned
with the whole, with the community, but this community is made of diver-
sity. The purpose of politics is to enable this multiplicity and diversity by
weaving them together into “good order,” that is the harmony of the polis as
unity. His own experience in politics taught him that political fragmentation
leads to stasis, making growth impossible. If Gloucester is to become a grow-
ing polis, unity is imperative.
Since a political life is the expression of human beings acting within their
social body, the concepts of creativity, ritual, and unity are now manifest in
the collective realm as polis. Olson’s sociopolitical critique is merely another
facet of the unity and multiplicity issue (or a different perspective on it), and
of the attempt to shake free from divisive Western culture. The polis is Olson’s
sociopolitical “answer” to present woes, attained through the search for a
human social framework that will fit the needs of the human creature, who is
114 CHARLES OLSON AND ALFRED NORTH WHITEHEAD
naturally also a homo politicus; the building of such a framework may provide
the chance for a new beginning.
The “dream of creating a city” mentioned by Olson (MUT, 102) im-
plies building a society that is a polis, thereby avoiding the trap that had
tripped Winthrop and most settlers through their religious vision, which
began to collapse almost from the outset and led Gloucester to its present
plight.7 In the life of the polis, there is no distinction between words and
deeds. Word is deed, as Von Hallberg reminds us: “The written language is
associated, in Olson’s mind, with European class society, whereas the spoken
language belongs to the people. His discussion of breath is meant to give to
poetic language all the actuality and power of the working people.”8 Lan-
guage is a real force in the world—The Maximus Poems that does not accept
the aesthetic/ethical (or cognitive) separation of powers. Life is one, and
multiplicity is merely an expression of unity. Creativity is an ethical-political
act, with direct implications for reality; writing poetry means adopting a
stance in the world; it is a deed, an act toward the world, toward yourself,
which includes “taking” responsibility. The work of the good poet, says
Olson, is
of an order that causes him to demand back what he gives: utmost care & openness
in discussion of. On top of that, he has, like any of us to whom the thing is already
our life stretching down to our death, a sense of the responsibility of the act of
writing by anyone anywhere: that sense of the public domain that only the most
serious men ever have, and to which they give, and sacrifice anything. (LO, 87)9
For Olson, art is the metaphysics of life itself, which re-enacts the kinetic of
the world and of human beings:
There is only one thing you can do about kinetic, re-enact it. Which is why the
man said, he who possesses rhythm possesses the universe. And why art is the only
twin life has—its only valid metaphysic. Art does not seek to describe but to enact.
And if man is once more to possess intent in his life, and to take up the responsibil-
ity implicit in his life, he has to comprehend his own process as intact, from
outside, by way of his skin, in, and by his own powers of conversion, out again.
(CP, 162)
Art is the activity of the organism that is the human being. The kinetics of
art is the concrescence of perceptions, of prehensions, the experience that
constitutes the “subject.” It is the objectification of this “subject” as an
“object” in the emergence of a “new” subject—the “re-enactment” of an
experience (or a “prehension”) during the new experience. In Whitehead’s
formula: “the subjective form of a physical feeling is re-enaction of the subjec-
7: STANCE 115
tive form of the feeling felt. Thus the cause passes on its feeling to be
reproduced by the new subject as its own, and yet as inseparable from the
cause.”10
This process is the one underlying such basic mythopoeical concepts as
ritual or re-creation. Olson is actually seeking to return to the work of art its
ancestral meaning aided by modern scientific patterns. Not only is the work
of art “creative” and “innovative,” but it is also a deliberate act of building an
actual world, and always bearing political, active, social significance—the
work of art should recognize, and give place, to a Thou. Olson wishes to
cancel the distinction between craft and art, as is clear from his identification
of Stevens the carpenter with the first Maximus.11 The polis is composed of
people who enact themselves, and thereby enact the body of the entire com-
munity, as can be seen in “Letter 7”:
(Marsden Hartley’s
eyes—as Stein’s
eyes
Or that carpenter’s,
who left Plymouth Plantation,
and came to Gloucester,
to build boats
And he displays,
in the record, some of those traits
goes with that difference, traits present circumstances
keep my eye on
116 CHARLES OLSON AND ALFRED NORTH WHITEHEAD
a man’s hands,
as his eyes,
can get sores)
. . . . .
What Hartley did was done according to his lights
as Jake’s did,
from baiting hooks for sixty years,
(TMP, 34 –38)
The polis is the place where craft is art, an inseparable part of the citizen’s
life. Polis is/eyes: Stevens the carpenter, like Hartley the painter, like Jake the
fisherman, like Verrocchio (which means “true eye”), the Florentine sculptor
and painter, and also like Olson’s father and several others who experience
reality, have the eyes that see reality as is and lead to the right actions (the right
hands), to a life of action, a life of work. Olson makes “work” a keystone of his
worldview; Ferrini, as mentioned, lacks these features, and Olson is therefore
critical of him and his actions. The sharp criticism and the strong language of
Olson make the reader of “Letter 7” (as well as other letters) wonder if
7: STANCE 117
Eyes,
& polis,
fishermen,
& poets
or in every human head I’ve known is
busy
both:
the attention, and
the care
(TMP, 32)
The rhythm of the body is the rhythm of love, of care. If Olson’s poem
begins with the force of the lance, in the same breath it is also driven by love, by
attention, and by care. Stevens the carpenter, whom Olson “joins” through
space, through the places they both share (for instance, Cressy and Half Moon,
above), is the first Maximus. He identifies the decay spreading through the
settlement, the estrangement from those characteristics that could lead to the
growth of the people and the place, and leaves it. This is Ferrini’s weakness
precisely: he lacks the measure of care, since this measure grows from the place.
How, asks Olson, will you find closeness and care, if you do not know your
environment, if you have not established any contact with your surroundings?
Ferrini, as noted in chapter 5, is not a native of the place, although he lives
there. Ferrini’s poetry is “everywhere,” it is an abstraction, without any links to
the concrete space, it is not an act of growth. Ferrini and Stevens stand, once
again, as enemies on two sides of the battlefield.15 Olson strengthens the link
between himself (as Olson and as Maximus) and Stevens, through the tansy
that characterizes his childhood and the city in general16 and whose roots
Stevens has seen. The tansy is again a specific transfiguration of the flower, and
poetry is a flower since it grows from/with the place, and its “smell” is the smell
of the place; the tansy flowers, the flowers of poetry, were destroyed by people
like Ferrini who strive, according to Olson, for a static homogeneous
universality:
Tansy was brought on the bottom of bags in cargoes to Stage Head originally out
of Dorchester’s entry. . . . It is strong (like goldenrod) and smells almost offensive
7: STANCE 119
with a pineapple odor. It doesn’t grow anymore at the same place but that is due
to more efficient mowers, and the desire (like blacktop) to have anything smooth
and of one sort or character. We therefore celebrate TANSY MORE THAN
BEFORE.17
Olson finds eunomia (good order) in the polis,18 the possibility of creating
a general will to action, which sustains it as a world within a world; Maximus
builds this eunomia throughout his poem. This is his craft, this is his purpose:
to build the city. The polis must be as a “society,” in a sense similar to this
term in Whitehead: a nexus of actual entities in an order that characterizes
their mutual relationships, with itself as its cause. Obviously, each “society” of
this type is not really isolated, but rather perceived against a broader back-
ground of actual entities, of “societies” upon which it depends and to which it
is related:19 Olson actualizes Whitehead’s metaphysics as sociopolitical prin-
ciples by turning, if we formulate this in terms of a critique, metaphysics into
ethics (although ethics is patently latent within metaphysics). Olson is ap-
prehensive about developments that resulted in the collapse of the polis,20
such as stagnation, the split between word and act, homogeneity, and other
such “evils” that already characterize the nation:
As the people of the earth are now, Gloucester
is heterogeneous, and so can know polis
not as localism, not that mu-sick (the trick
of corporations, newspapers, slick magazines, movie houses
. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
The word does intimidate. The pay-check does.
But to use either, as cheap men
Olson shares this image of the polis as an organism that concretizes the
principle of the micro and the macro, and Whitehead’s concept of “society.”
The polis is related to the physical space and to the concrete contact between
individuals; the polis was, in Victor Ehrenberg’s definition, “community, self-
absorbed, closely united in its narrow space and permeated by a strong
political and spiritual intensity that led to a kind of special culture of every
Polis.”27 Olson retains two elements that Aristotle and Ehrenberg consider
conrnerstones of the polis: a citizen body and a territory. The polis is a
community of place with common concerns. In Griffeth’s terms, “the charac-
teristics of community of place and community of people were so inextricably
fused that it may be without profit to debate the priority of one or the other
factor.”28
As abstract space turns into place, Maximus turns out to be a native son.
Life (experience) is concretized into a given space that imposes limitations
and shapes life within it, so that one “place” is different from another “place.”
This is the social system of a “world” sustaining multiplicity and unity within
a “world” that also sustains multiplicity and unity, beside other such “worlds”
with which it comes into contact. The polis is a sociopolitical system where
the preservation of multiplicity enables unity; in Griffeth’s wording, “the
citizen body (the Demos) was united by its divisions” (267).
Thus, Olson idealizes the polis as a substitute for a life based on nationality
in its imaginative version, since the polis is both a city and a state. The polis
supplies the needs of the human being, “by nature, a political animal” accord-
ing to Aristotle’s definition in his Politics.29 Rather than an imagined com-
munity, Olson’s ideal is a community that is experienced and immediate. He
borrows the concept of the polis because one of the basic features of the
ancient polis was its small size. The area of the Athenian polis, for instance,
which was unusually large for a Greek city-state, did not exceed 2,500 square
kilometers; the large commercial state of Corinth extended over an area of
880 square kilometers. The island of Crete had no less than fifty city-states,
each averaging 150 square kilometers. Population figures suited the physical
size: Corinth, numbering 20,000 citizens, and Athens, numbering 43,000,
appeared to the Greeks as gigantic. Greek political theory was based on these
facts: in Plato’s ideal state, there would be 5,040 citizens. The prevalent view
7: STANCE 123
in Greece was that a good city-state has a population of 10,000. In any event,
it was not desirable, according to these views, for the area of a state to be so
large as to make it impossible for a citizen at any time of the year to take an
active part in its political life. Citizens should know one another lest personal
selection to state positions and effective participation in state affairs become
impossible. Of course, this ideal phrasing—to know one another—is trans-
lated more than once to: be familiar with one’s political, educational, cultural,
and geographical surroundings, with one’s family and genealogy and so forth:
criteria for judgment if a citizen does not know a candidate “personally.” This
“lesser extent” of knowing is yet completely different (in aspiration as well as
in its actual form) from embracing imaginary model. For the citizens of the
ideal polis their “state” is no abstract concept but a daily reality, acquired
through feeling and experience. Olson’s use of the concept refers to the polis
as a “microcosm,” an entire world on its own, based on its small size. The
citizens of the polis only need to climb the Acropolis, the fort of their
homeland, in order to envision the entire state. They know it perfectly, and all
its paths are clear. Every clod of earth is close and familiar.30 This is the true
meaning of Olson’s “mapping” the city, the native son’s wanderings in his
known and beloved polis built within him through its “prehension” (through
the eye, the ear, the foot: through his body). Maximus climbs and looks down
from the tower:
having descried the nation
to write a Republic
in gloom on Watch-House Point
(TMP, 377)
Watch-house
Point: to descry
anew: attendeo
& broadcast
the world (over the
marshes to the outer limits
. . . . . . . . .
one house-
one father one mother one city
(TMP, 394)
Maximus sees a space that becomes place, that becomes home; and home,
as we learned, is also a “note” for the body; in other words, the human body is
the body of the world is the body of the polis (the polis, as we know, is
founded on the demos, “the body of citizens”), a city that is part of the space,
grows with it, takes part in it:
124 CHARLES OLSON AND ALFRED NORTH WHITEHEAD
The organism that is Gloucester adapts itself to its own living space.
Economy and work rely on the same organic movement from the outside
7: STANCE 125
inward, and then outward again, according to the character of the body,
which is the space. Economic activity also emerges from the existence within
space. The early settlers worked with space, not against it. In “Letter #10,”
Olson/Maximus examines the first settlement in Cape Ann to indicate that
the beginning, the movement forward, was based on fishing, which suits the
character of the place, rather than stemming from Puritanical aspirations
(which did not act with the space and from it). Olson juxtaposes Roger
Conant, the governor of the Dorchester Company settlement in Cape Ann,
to the “later” Conant (James). Once again, he sets them up as opponents in a
battle, which is the story he is telling, in order to point to the factors that led
to the decay of the city and to reawaken its growth. Growth is hard because
of the straying away from reliance on the local; the fins, the fishing, are
gone:
And how, now, to found, with the sacred & the profane—both of them—
wore out
The beak’s
there. And the pectoral.
The fins,
for forwarding.
It was fishing was first. Only after (Naumkeag) was it the other thing, and Conant
would have nothing to do with it, went over to Beverly, to Bass River, to keep clear
(as a later Conant I know has done the opposite, has not
kept clear)
. . . .
As you did not go,
Gloucester: you tipped, you were our
scales
national, international,
even learning slide
by the acts of another Conant than he who left his Tudor house, left fishing,
and lost everything to Endecott, lost the colony
to the first of,
the shrinkers
. . . .
Now
. .
Harvard
owns too much
Roger Conant did not destroy, was, in fact, himself destroyed, as was the city, 1626
. . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
my Conant
only removed to “Beggarly”,
as the smug of Salem—the victors!—
called that place still is, for me
(when I go down 1A or take the train
the opening out
of my countree
(TMP, 49–51)
presently existent and, as is readily visible, oriented toward the future, which
Maximus wishes to build in better, and more ethical ways. “Historians-poets”
are able to put together a topical story from “historical materials” relevant to
them and to the place of whose growth they are part.
Olson, a “historian-poet,” does not discern “temporal gaps,” nor does he,
as “poet-citizen-man of the polis,” discern separate “fields of activity” or
accept divisions between the various “domains of life.” The “categorical
status” of the two different Conants is identical regarding their activity as men
of the city, the polis: Maximus shows us how the later Conant, the educator,
failed to rely on the local in order to grow and bring about the city’s growth;
he destroyed Harvard because he tried to bring his “materials” from the
(human) space that is outside the polis. The early Conant is one of Maximus’
“twin-figures,” relying on the physical space of the polis in order to grow from
within it. Olson emphasizes Conant’s unwillingness to compromise his prin-
ciples, when he left and lost the settlement to Endecott, who marks the onset
of the restriction process that led to decay. Throughout the entire poem,
Olson recurrently signposts the deviations from the correct path when he
deals with Gloucester and when he deals with Western culture in general.
Endecott marks the beginning of the decay that Maximus knows from the
present of his life; for him however, (the first) Conant is a real presence here
and now,31 and he meets him when he travels from Boston to Gloucester
along the road passing through Beverly, the place to which Conant had
moved. The A1 is an “an alternate route between Boston and Gloucester,
passing through Beverly. Before the construction of route 128, the main
highway into Gloucester from Boston,”32 a point that is again an instance of
Olson’s method: the real details hint at the thought hiding behind them.
Indicating the name of this road actually hints at the move that interests
Olson/Maximus, which he then performs: the search for an alternative identi-
fying the point of deviation from the right road. In this way, then, the path is
reopened for Maximus at the end of the poem, an opening to his city is now
available. There are no full stops at the end of the poetic units, in order to
suggest the continuous movement forward, the one movement. The archaic
spelling (“countree”) hints at a move backward, which is an opening, a move
forward, growth—as the tree that is hidden and revealed anew.
In “Letter 16,” Olson also points to the crumbling of the polis that was the
city, and to the beginning of the separation between the private and the
public. Maximus’s words at the beginning of the letter are typical of both the
merchant and the poet:
. . . . . . . . . . . . . . .
The polis, then, must rely on its given space for its economic growth, and
the mistakes made in the past, which led to the city’s decay, serve Maximus in
his attempt to rebuild the city as a polis, this time from the space and with it.
The space gives rise to the cultural uniqueness, to the myths and stories of the
place. Gods and mythical figures, monsters and heroic deeds, are always
related to local aspects of the territory and its characteristics. Those who grew
and set the community on the right path economically, by relying on its
7: STANCE 129
features, are also heroes. “The religion of the polis” is not based on saints
performing miracles but rather the opposite—on the many daily activities
that are all facets of the one body. As Murray describes the Greek polis, so
Olson wishes his own city to be: “Religion is present in all the different levels
of social life, and all collective practices have a religious dimension.”34
Olson, as a native, tells-shapes the “stories of the place,” the “religion of the
polis.” This story-ritual is the inner determination that gives (self ) identity
and difference (from another place, another polis). The first volume of The
Maximus Poems in particular is the ritual of the polis that is Gloucester, which
is performed through the (narrative) ritual of the “local heroes” as, for in-
stance, the fishermen stories that Olson/Maximus sings in “Letter 2,” and
particularly the rescue story of Carl Olsen, the captain of the “Raymonde.”
This “local hero” recurs along The Maximus Poems;35 as is evident in the
poetic unit entitled “The Death of Carl Olsen” (TMP, 474), Olson/Maximus
“raises” this character to the rank of a “naval hero” and sets up a memorial to
him in his living space:
. . . . . . . . . .
This was Carl Olsen
captain of the Raymonde,
and in the time of our lives the instance
of the men who were called
captains, of the vessels which made up
the Gloucester fishing fleet.
The plural subject that Maximus uses points to the shared ritual of the
townspeople, but the speaker sings alone, and it is not even clear that there are
any listeners. Olson/Maximus seeks to bring the townspeople to participate in
its shaping by means of well-known local ritual stories of this type, stories
“making the rounds” in the common space. The hero of another story-ritual
is James Merry, a former sailor who fought the bull in Dogtown.36 The unit
called MAXIMUS, FROM DOGTOWN—I (TMP, 172–76), is wholly
devoted to this local hero (who also returns elsewhere along the book), and
takes place in the space where the hero had acted: Maximus tells the story of
the place that is Dogtown. Byrd analyzes this poetic unit37 in terms of the
archetypal forces of the earth in their representation as the “Great Mother,”
and of “deep-swirling Okeanos,” which are also archetypes of gender:
The feminine archetype which presides over Merry’s struggle “to manifest his soul”
is a relatively late form of the Great Mother. . . . Obviously the bullfight is an
appropriate celebration of the Lady of the Beast, because she is the symbol of man’s
emerging domination over the natural world. In his failure, Merry, as a projection
130 CHARLES OLSON AND ALFRED NORTH WHITEHEAD
Byrd argues that this is an anti-ritual, since the “hero,” Merry, actually
represents the vain “ego” (“to show off his / Handsome Sailor ism”) who
attempts to subdue Nature; the result of his acts was that the space itself, the
place, and the bull as his extension, kills Merry:
Merry’s death, (“as he died / in pieces / In 400 pieces”) illustrates the break-
up of the “ego” that enables the communion with space:
Then only
after the grubs
had done him
did the earth
let her robe
uncover and her part
take him in
(TMP, 176)
Instead of the “anti-ritual” terminology that Byrd uses to describe the story
of Merry and the bull, we could say that this is a ritual chiefly concerned with
a pattern of alienation in space, a ritual that concretizes the conflict between
the place and the stranger who negates it. It is as such that its importance
becomes evident: Olson cannot successfully activate the ritual since there is
no one to share it with. The ritual is taking place not for himself but for the
city, the polis, the community. From the start, Olson aims to build the city,
which is why the disappointment, at the end of the day, is so great. This, then,
is a ritual that concretizes the death of the “self,” of the negative hero, at the
hands of the superior powers of space. The polis must participate in this
ritual, thereby acquiring its self-identity through the union of the individual
with the collective and of the collective with space, in a necessary process of
contending with a “self ” seeking “violent” expression toward the surround-
ings, an expression finding its way in the ritual itself. The return of the “self,”
toward the end of The Maximus Poems, will concretize the failure of the shared
ritual, manifest in the individual’s withdrawal into himself.
7: STANCE 131
The examples of “stories of heroes” and “ritual stories” that I chose here are
arbitrary.39 The poem is filled to the brim with such stories, from a myriad of
sources: Indian legends, stories of fishermen, records of the early settlers,
letters, and so forth. Their common denominator is the place that engendered
them or that accepts them and takes them into its (territorial-geographical)
bosom. “Its heroic cults in particular gave the religious system of each polis
much of its individuality, its sense of identity and difference, which were
connected with the mythical past and sanctified the connection of the citizens
with that past to which they related through those cults.”40 As Murray
successfully conveys, the ritual of the story engenders the polis with its local
“religion.”
In the early Maximus Poems, Olson appeals to the goddess of the city,
protector of the community who, of course, is also the muse of the local poet
telling-building the place. This attests that, despite the openness of the begin-
ning, the poem, and the poet, have a “purposeful end” that drives and directs
their growth:
forwarding
(TMP, 6)
“The poem is a voyage, and I want a good voyage,” says Olson.41 The
purpose is to build a polis, and the active cause is the laws of the polis
themselves, which establish it and the citizens living within it. “The polis was
the institutional authority that structured the universe and the divine world
in a religious system, articulated a pantheon with certain particular configura-
tions of divine personalities, and established a system of cults, particular
rituals and sanctuaries, and a sacred calendar.”42 As in Murray’s description of
the Greek polis, Olson emphasizes that to be a citizen of the polis means to
take an active part in its life. The activity of the organism is based on the
experience of every one of its citizens. Hence, every activity, or experience, is
always a “political” act, because the activity preserves individuals as part of the
world, affecting their environment and affected by it, “opening” or “closing”
possibilities of action. Individuals are an “actual potentiality,” responsible for
their own growth and for that of the world to which they belong. The
activities and the rituals create the unity of the body of citizens, and empha-
size the subject’s active power and responsibility, even in activities ostensibly
quotidian and “unimportant”; every act is invariably participation and “a will
132 CHARLES OLSON AND ALFRED NORTH WHITEHEAD
133
134 CHARLES OLSON AND ALFRED NORTH WHITEHEAD
I must make it known, now that I have had the great dream
have waked from the shock of myself confronted with
myself. I standing, before my own eyes, naked, and charging
myself with what? There I was, and I was he, and it was me,
just as I am, the exact body. And we stared at each other.
I do not know that we asked anything, I, of him,
or he, of me. Yet we did look at each other, we were
sibs. And the I who was naked had a single look.
Olson struggles here with the “Western self,” through what Karlins calls
“distancing himself ”: “The final version is not only pared down, but the angle
of perception is entirely different. Olson postulates a ‘man’ to tell the dream
and Olson himself becomes ‘he’ and his dream double becomes ‘him.’ ”3
Thus, a distance is created and the involvement of the poet’s “I” is lessened.
Olson, in other words (his own words) is looking for an image of man made
out of the material known to him:
It is not I,
even if the life appeared
biographical. The only interesting thing
is if one can be
an image
of man, “The nobleness, and the arete.”
(TMP, 473)
The City (capitalized) restrains the fears, the primary forces that had once
been more exposed: in order to tell the “story” (which makes up most of the
first part of the above unit) one must reawaken these forces, stand naked
before them again, allow them now to enter the home, into the picture-
postcard reality that covers up the fears:
borders, open up to the space and its forces, to the past and its forces. True
continuity means re-experiencing the hardships of the beginning, renouncing
your identity in order to grow it anew—stripping and donning the “attire of
the other” during the ritual. “The turning” (TMP, 10) mentioned regarding
the space of the city is “The Twist” (which is “Letter 18,” TMP, 86), both in
the sense of a “transfiguration” of identities and a blurring of borders. This is
the Annisquam river that appears in the poetic unit “The Twist,” itself indi-
cating the movement (inward and outward) that becomes a presence imbued
with power. On the one hand, there is a threat; on the other, however, there is
an intimation of sowing and growth (in the flowers he plants, actually for
Pound, which again link the act of doing in the world to the doing in the
poem itself ):
As I had it in my first poem,
the Annisquam
fills itself, at its tides
. . . . . . . . . . . .
my neap,
my spring-tide, my
waters
(TMP, 86)
along his journey. If the storyteller lacks an active audience; if the letters
actually have no addressees, then Olson, a postman’s son, himself a postman,
carries Maximus’s letters to nowhere. Maximus is the guide; more than one
“transfiguration” of his figure in the poem strengthens this attitude toward
him. He holds the secret of the nasturtium, the “secret of the Black Chry-
santhemum,”5 which is “the secret of the Black Gold Flower”—the flower of
Chinese alchemy—serving Master Lu Tzu and also Olson, who is Maximus
the teacher.6 The flower’s appearance as the lotus, “The Cosmic Flower”
(TMP, 73), leads Olson to the gate of another teacher, Buddha, who returned
in order to light the path for others (for instance, TMP, 473). When Olson/
Maximus calls out to bring the ships into the port for sailing, to cross the
borders, he is joining his role as an actual guide with his role as a poet-teacher,
who also provides tools for the sailing:
As Olson explains, “The Return, The Flower, The Gift, and The Alligator, are
ketches owned by a Gloucesterman who built them.” Ketch, continues
Olson, “is an old name for sloop, a fishing sloop—but they spell it in the
record ‘catches,’ and you know catches is ‘song’ ” (MUT, 158). Olson hints
here at the poet’s quality as a carpenter, providing his audience with a means
of transportation to their shared destination. Stevens the carpenter, the ship-
builder, is presented in TMP as the first Maximus. The poem is a boat and
Olson/Maximus steers it: the poetic units coalesce into a long and continuous
voyage to an old-new world. Beginning with “The Twist,”7 Olson/Maximus
brings together the voices, one after another (one makes many), weaves-builds
the poem, the ship. But without a crew, without the townspeople and the
readers as his fellow workers, he cannot function as a teacher or as a poet.
Without them his ship has no purpose.
The method of Olson/Maximus is that of self-discovery and, as a teacher,
he cannot offer his own to others but relies on those stirring to action with
him, in his wake. For Olson, education means “educere, to lead out,” and
methodology for him means to “go back to root, to methodos.” Olson explains
this root as “ ‘The way’ (road, path tao)” or “with a way” (LO, 106). The result
is that “methodo”-“logy” is “(1) to have a path (2) and that such a path is only
accomplishable by the habitual practice of orderliness and regularity in ac-
tion” (LO, 107).
138 CHARLES OLSON AND ALFRED NORTH WHITEHEAD
Olson holds that we must grow out of our own selves, without coercion,
out of our own experience, without a path being laid out in advance and
without presuppositions directing the way. The teacher is also the sailor, one
of the crew, a citizen of the town who is on the way (his “location” is “outside
and inside”). But if no one is with him on the way, he has no function as
teacher in his role to wake the others to their ways, which will eventually
become the way of the polis.
Maximus casts flowers upon the water from the mole;8 this is an annual
ritual in memory of the Gloucester fishermen lost at sea, and Olson seems to
have been present at the ceremony performed on the day he wrote this unit.
Between the two poetic units describing the same ritual, there are two promi-
nent differences: (1) On page 157 the townspeople are described as casting
flowers upon the water, while Maximus is a commenting observer. But on
page 257 Maximus is the subject of the poem and he himself casts flowers
upon the water; the ritual here is mentioned as part of his voyages in one of
his various guises. (2) The second difference is the location: whereas Maximus
sends the flowers in Tyre, the ritual itself, as it is performed on page 157, is the
annual ceremony taking place in Gloucester.
Throughout The Maximus Poems, Tyre is Gloucester’s “twin city,” Max-
imus’s other home. The poem indeed opens with Maximus “off-shore, by
islands hidden” (which, as it emerges, are hidden to the poet himself ); this is
an instance of the discovery latent in the process, which is exposed with the
growth of the character, since in Tyre he stands “beyond time”:
Tyre (when choosing Tyre, Olson also relied upon the geographic-physical
similarities with Gloucester) is the quintessential polis, and also represents
nonsurrender to Western culture. It is a temporal and spatial beginning,
preceding the philosophical-cultural deviation; the starting point for the
native expansion westward. Accordingly, Gloucester is the place of the “last
first people”:10
I regard Gloucester as the final movement of the earth people, the great migratory
thing . . . migration ended in Gloucester . . . the motion of man upon the earth
8: FAILURE? 139
. . . northwest-tending line, and Gloucester was the last shore in that sense. The
fact that the continent and the series of such developments as have followed, have
occupied three hundred and some-odd years, doesn’t take away that primacy or
originatory nature that I’m speaking of. I think it’s a very important fact. And I of
course use it as a bridge to Venice and back from Venice to Tyre, because of the
departure from the old static land mass of man which was the ice, cave, Pleistocene
man and early agricultural man, until he got moving, until he got to towns. So the
last polis or city is Gloucester.11
Metaphysics brings along an ethic or, rather, it is the other way around.
Olson/Maximus takes it upon himself to begin anew. Olson’s view is so
comprehensive that beginning anew means introducing a sweeping change
into Western cultural values but, as always, the comprehensive and inclusive
can only be accomplished through concrete elements and at a specific place.
In other words, the relationship, the stance vis-à-vis the world and your
responsibility for it, are measured in your care for the concrete here and
now, in your stance vis-à-vis the concrete place, in your being the child
of a concrete place. The relationship between Tyre and Gloucester, between
Maximus from Tyre—not only Jung’s Homo Maximus, which is an arche-
typal figure of large dimensions, but also the Greek philosopher of the sec-
ond century B.C.—and Maximus from Gloucester, is the basis not only for
understanding Olson’s ethical stance but also for “measuring” the realiza-
tion of the project that Olson/Maximus has taken upon himself. The char-
acter of Maximus is the measure (of that “Human Universe”): he is the one
who builds the city, the world, himself. If we measure Olson as Maximus—
as it seems Olson himself did at least partially—we face such questions that
blur the distinction between the poet and his persona. Can the poet be judged
according to his success in transforming a center that once again grants
his city its unity, its coherence, its purpose, its place in the surrounding
universe (so that it should become a navel for him as well, for his own
growth)? But if not how come the poet himself expresses disappointment
from his fellow-citizens’ failure to follow his way, as a teacher? Is it not Olson
that feels disappointed when Maximus is left alone to cast flowers upon the
water? Can we seriously say that it is only Maximus’s failure, or that only
as Maximus he feels a failure? But does Olson really think he can create a
shared experience for the townspeople and build a power base for its activ-
ity? Does Olson differentiate between the townspeople as audience and the
readers of poetry as audience? And if it seems sometimes that Olson does
not draw the line between Maximus (as a persona) and himself should we
do it? At what price? Does the swap between observation posts, between-
places, between the ritual that Olson/Maximus—observes? shares?—in
Gloucester, and the ritual in which Maximus participates—in whose com-
140 CHARLES OLSON AND ALFRED NORTH WHITEHEAD
pany? alone?—in Tyre denote the gap between Maximus and the people of
his town Gloucester, or the gap between Maximus and Olson, or, yet, the gap
between phases of the same identity? If we take what emerges from the
description of the ceremony in Gloucester (TMP, 157) as the failure of the
townspeople to understand the meaning of the ritual,12 we will not be sur-
prised to find Olson/Maximus retreating into his solitude, feeling as a man
from Tyre.
As noted, a sense of closure characterizes the poem toward the end. The
figure of Maximus from Tyre, the attempt to replace the canonical power
center, to offer an alternative to the Western Greek-Hellenistic world—all
appear as a utopic call for action from this point of view. We remain, there-
fore, with the well-known question of art’s ability to affect reality and be part
of reality without impairing its own autonomy and maintaining an indepen-
dent perspective. Olson’s work seems to be another example, indeed a distinc-
tive one, of an oeuvre contending with these questions, which could them-
selves be rephrased as the problem of multiplicity within unity. Poetry (for
Olson) is an act of many, even if it opens and is opened from the one, and
Olson’s long poem is the quintessential expression of this. The importance of
the poem is not in the poetizing, in the confession or the pleasure. It is not art
for art’s sake, but art for life’s sake. The relationship between Tyre and
Gloucester, between Maximus of Tyre and Maximus of Gloucester, is thus a
measure of the “unity” or the “division” that the poem ultimately presents.
Olson “calls,” “summons,” makes real the Maximus of Tyre as a “realized
potential,” who can direct the process whereby he himself wishes to be the
center of the new polis of Gloucester:
He represents to me some sort of a figure that centers much more than the second
century A.D.—in fact, as far as I feel it, like, he’s the navel of the world. In saying
that I’m not being poetic or loose. We come from a whole line of life that makes
Delphi that center . . . and this I think is the kind of a thing that ought to be at
least disturbed. . . . He is a transfer for me to that vision of a difference that Tyre is,
or proposition that Tyre is, as against, say, Delphi.13
Maximus of Gloucester
Only my written word
The split of “every” and “thing” (in the second line above); the split that is
intimated between writing and speech; his deliberate mention of Half Moon
beach (a small, well-protected crescent-shaped beach);17 the “Padma,” the
lotus, the gods’ dwelling and birthplace, now closes in on him like the sea; a
process of shrinking and withdrawal is now taking place, rather than this
place becoming the starting point for the growth of everything.18 Gloucester
itself loses its concreteness and becomes an external diagram; Maximus cuts
off from the world, becomes a mere shadow lying on the rock, a picture like
that of his father. Reality again becomes Platonic (the question of unity and
multiplicity; how “the brave” is “the good” is “the beautiful,” one that is
many; and Olson asks, is this possible?), art goes back to being mimetic, the
soul departs the body, the individual departs from society, the monk needs
only “robe and bread,” and shuts himself in his cell, as is well emphasized in
other “evidence” Butterick brings:
The word [conventual] appears underlined in the poet’s copy of Brooks Adams’
Law of Civilization and Decay. . . . Olson wrote . . . around that same time: “I
really do prefer the soul to society; and think that the conventual is now solely the
imagination which applies.”19
142 CHARLES OLSON AND ALFRED NORTH WHITEHEAD
Olson/Maximus, then, feels that the city, the polis, is not being built. The
flower becomes the flower “of the poet,” growing with him and from him. It
is not, however, the flower of the city, and a dissociation emerges or, should
one say, remains between the individual and the collective, a dissociation
between body and soul, between writing and speech:
Nasturtium
is still my flower but I am a poet
who now more thinks than writes, my
nose-gay
(TMP, 632)
This poetic unit, which was already noted, illustrates the tension well: the
breaths on the page, “the instrument” attesting to the one source of the
multiplicity, the organism that is the whole standing behind the apparent
splits—all attest now to concrete separations and splits in the world upon
which the subject cannot prevail because of the blindness of his fellows who,
in his view, prefer the isolation of the “Cartesian monad” (TMP, 132). The
smell is now reserved for the individual, the plant is cut, and the bouquet is
not cast with the other bouquets upon the water: the placement in a separate
line, two pages before the end of The Maximus Poems (about two months
before his death and several days before he was transferred to the hospital,
implying this is one of the last texts he ever wrote) attest that the unit is itself a
bouquet to his poem, that the poem itself is a bouquet to his life, but not to
the polis. The renunciation, the withdrawal, and the closure sensed here, turn
into a clear declaration in the last unit of The Maximus Poems, which is made
up of only one line;20 the “self ” returns to rule the poet’s life:
143
Notes
INTRODUCTION
Charles Olson, The Maximus Poems, ed. George F. Butterick (Berkeley and Los Angeles:
University of California Press, 1984), 249. Subsequent quotations from this work are cited in
the text, abbreviated as TMP.
1. Alfred North Whitehead, An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Natural Knowledge
(New York: Cambridge University Press, 1919); idem, Science and the Modern World (New
York: Cambridge University Press, 1925); idem, Adventures of Ideas (New York: Macmillan,
1933); idem, Modes of Thought (New York: Macmillan, 1938); idem, Dialogues of A. N.
Whitehead as Recorded by Lucien Price (New York: New American Library, 1956).
2. Charles Olson, The Special View of History, ed. Ann Charters (Berkeley: Oyez, 1970),
49. Subsequent quotations from this work are cited in the text, abbreviated as SVH.
3. George F. Butterick, A Guide to the Maximus Poems of Charles Olson (Berkeley and Los
Angeles: University of California Press, 1978).
4. See the last chapters in the biography of Tom Clark, Charles Olson: The Allegory of a
Poet’s Life (New York and London: W. W. Norton, 1991), especially the account of Olson’s
decline after the death of Betty, his second, common-law wife. George Butterick, the editor of
The Maximus Poems, was Olson’s student and became his friend, bibliographer, and editor.
5. Christopher Beach, ABC of Influence: Ezra Pound and the Remaking of American Poetic
Tradition (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1992), 84.
6. Robert Von Hallberg, Charles Olson: The Scholar’s Art (London: Harvard University
Press, 1978), 63.
7. Sherman Paul, Olson’s Push: Origin, Black Mountain, and Recent American Poetry (Baton
Rouge: Louisiana State University Press, 1978), 102.
8. Stephen Fredman, The Grounding of American Poetry: Charles Olson and the Emersonian
Tradition (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993), 30.
9. Paul Christensen, Charles Olson: Call Him Ishmael (Austin: University of Texas Press,
1979), 5–6.
144
NOTES 145
3. Paul Bové, Destructive Poetics: Heidegger and Modern American Poetry (New York: Co-
lumbia University Press, 1980), 217–34, extensively and persuasively describes the generally
hostile attitude of the critics (mostly of New-Criticism) toward Olson. As Bové shows, even
after the influence of “PV” had begun to filter down, critics still failed to contend with his
poems, nor did they really grasp that the essay (or the “theoretical” writing in general) and the
poetry are inseparably linked and part of one continuum. In the discussion he devotes to
Olson, Bové explains the need for this “essayistic” or “theoretical” writing in the struggle
against the static canon and its representatives, the critics, for the purpose of opening it up.
4. Fredman, The Grounding of American Poetry, 3– 4, offers another formulation that, in
some senses, spans Bové’s and my own position concerning the elimination of dichotomies and
the perception of the whole as one activity: “Lacking a grounded tradition to draw upon, Olson
uses his essays, lectures, interviews, book reviews, and letters to present an alternative ground-
ing method I call ‘containment,’ which makes his poetry both possible and effective.” Fred-
man’s terminology bridges the perspective of the attitude to tradition and the perspective of
immanent unity in Olson’s activity as a whole. Nevertheless, it is worth noting that, contrary to
Bové, who presents Olson as a “destructive poet” vis-à-vis the tradition, Fredman’s formulation
actually points to Olson’s link to the Emersonian tradition and particularly to Thoreau, with
whom he shares the “grounding” method that Fredman calls containment. Nevertheless, both
Fredman and Bové do agree with the view that has since become the prevalent consensus
regarding Olson’s writing, namely, that it accepts no dichotomies.
5. Charles Olson, Call Me Ishmael: A Study of Melville (San Francisco: City Lights Books,
1947). Subsequent quotations from this work are cited in the text, abbreviated as CMI.
6. Albert Einstein and Leopold Infeld, The Evolution of Physics (Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1947), 258–59.
7. Timothy Ferris, Coming of Age in the Milky Way (New York: William Morrow, 1988),
186, 398.
8. Ibid., 192.
9. Bové, Destructive Poetics, 229.
10. Charles Altieri, Enlarging the Temple: New Directions in American Poetry During the
1960s (Lewisburg: Bucknell University Press, 1979), 78.
11. This is another topic that was also previously considered in CMI, Olson’s book on Moby
Dick, and obviously characterizes Gloucester as a port city and as the early settlement in the
new world.
12. Charles Olson, Human Universe and Other Essays, ed. Donald Allen (New York: Grove
Press, 1967), 123. Subsequent quotations from this work are cited in the text, abbreviated as
HU.
CHAPTER 3. EXPERIENCE
1. Whitehead, Process and Reality, 18.
2. On these concepts, see below.
3. This attitude characterized Olson’s behavior in the classroom as well. See, for instance,
Clark, The Allegory of a Poet’s Life, 209–10. Although, as Clark suggests, this attitude may be
rooted in his childhood anxieties concerning social performance, the tension between the poet
in his life and in his figure as Maximus remains. The reader should bear this in mind when
considering “the failure” of the last volume.
4. Ibid., 22.
5. For instance, Olson writes in “A Later Note”:
or in “Letter 27”:
An American
is a complex of occasions
6. Charles Olson, Muthologos: The Collected Lectures & Interviews, ed. George F. Butterick,
2 vols. (Bolinas, Calif.: Writing 35, 1978), 58. Subsequent quotations from this work are cited
in the text, abbreviated as MUT.
7. Whitehead, Science and the Modern World, 156.
8. Butterick, A Guide, 289.
9. Thus, for instance, he regrets his failure to speak to Ezra Pound (when he visited him at
St. Elizabeths) about his most important project at the time (March 1946):
That’s the book on the Human Body. A record in the perfectest language I can manage of the HEART,
BRAIN, LIVER, KIDNEY, the organs, to body them forth, to give a full sense of the instrument of the
organism, approached on the simplest of premises: viz., the BODY is the first and simplest and most
unthought of fact of a human life.
10. As we will see, human beings grow multidimensionally; the use of the vectorial axis is
meant for emphasis, in an attempt to follow the reader’s patterns of thinking.
11. Bové, Destructive Poetics, 228.
12. Butterick, A Guide, 435.
13. “On p. 28 of Frankfort’s study, occurs the following section (much of it underlined in
the poet’s copy) dealing with the origins of the major gods in Ptah: ‘And the final phrase of the
section closes the circle: while it has started by stating that the gods came forth from Ptah,
NOTES 147
objectified conceptions of his mind, it ends by making those gods “enter into their bodies”
(statues) of all kinds of material—stone, metal, or wood—which had grown out of the earth,
that is, out of Ptah’ ” (Butterick, A Guide, 436).
14. Whitehead, Process and Reality, 36.
15. Ferris, Coming of Age, 289. Ferris’s description of the process whereby we change our
perspective on the world is formulated in rather poetic terms:
Traditionally, scientists were free to think of themselves as passive observers, sealed off by a pane of
laboratory glass or a telescope’s lens from the outer world they examined. But on the microscopic level,
every act of observation is disruptive—countless photons of starlight die upon the eye, protons smash
into accelerator targets—and the manner in which we choose to make the observation (to “collapse the
wave function,” as the physicists say) influences the results of the interaction. Subatomic particles
sometimes resemble particles, sometimes waves, depending upon how we examine them. They are not
“really” one or the other—and, in any event, the two images are mathematically equivalent. Rather,
they are participants in an act of observation, the nature of which influences the qualities they present to
us. Quantum physics obliges us to take seriously what had previously been a more purely philosophical
consideration: That we do not see things in themselves, but only aspects of things.”
16. The poet did have a physical presence, clearly emerging in his letters to his lover and
muse, Frances M. Boldereff. The early draft of the first letter was “composed in two inter-
mingled languages: one public and literary, one private and coded for translation only by his
directive Muse. The poem went on to address a ‘lady of good voyage’ who represented, on the
one hand, the statue of the Virgin cradling a schooner on the Church of Our Lady of Good
Voyage in Gloucester, and on the other, Frances, whose recent invitation to voyage, in the letter
intercepted by Connie [the poet’s wife], had made such a powerful impact. It was boldly sexual,
thrust forward on images of phallic masts, beaks and lances directed with propulsive energy
toward receptive female nests” (Clark, The Allegory of a Poet’s Life, 167).
Clark’s biography reminds us that the tension between the dichotomies that Olson seeks to
dismantle is not easily removed, as is evident in Clark’s title for his biography, The Allegory of a
Poet’s Life. For another biographical reference of the poet’s writings see Ralph Maud and Sharon
Thesan, eds., Charles Olson and Frances Boldereff: A Modern Correspondence (Hanover, N.H.:
University Press of New England, 1999). Yet, note Creeley’s remark:
Olson would be dismayed when persons wanted to identify Maximus as being an egocentric projection
of his own values of himself. And he’d say “No! No! No! It’s simply a possibility of material. I mean it’s
‘me’ because I’m here this thing is here so it’s my agency for the recognition of what else is here. I’m the
material of my poem. I’m not the center of it in some egocentric demand.”
William V. Spanos, “Talking with Robert Creeley,” Boundary 2, 6.3–7.1 (spring-fall 1978): 42.
17. According to Bové, Destructive Poetics, 232–33: “Olson’s destructive poetics militates
against the reestablishment of some fixed order.” Bové states this conclusion when discussing
the building of an alternative canon and tradition, a new center, which various critics claim that
Olson offers as a substitute for Western tradition. See, for instance, Joseph N. Riddel, The
Inverted Bell: Modernism and the Counterpoetics of William Carlos Williams (Baton Rouge:
Louisiana State University Press, 1974), 186. Bové argues that “Olson’s position is extreme: his
ontology, his ‘epistemology,’ not only destroys the onto-theological ‘tradition,’ but it destroys
the very means by which any ‘canon’ can become static and passed on verbally as percept. . . .
The very word ‘tradition’ is deconstructed by his poems and shown to be a mystified center of
the logocentric ‘tradition.’ ”
18. Ibid., 46– 48.
19. Ferris, Coming of Age, 200.
148 CHARLES OLSON AND ALFRED NORTH WHITEHEAD
20. On this question, see the following passage (Von Hallberg, The Scholar’s Art, 124 –25):
Olson’s readings of Whitehead came at a decisive time, during those years in the mid-fifties when Black
Mountain was faltering to its dispersive close. . . . Although Olson actually shared many of White-
head’s most fundamental principles long before he read the cosmologist, this does not lessen White-
head’s importance for Olson. Through Pound, especially through Pound’s renderings of Fenollosa and
Confucius, Olson may have come to the notions of reality as process, the dynamism of objects, and the
ethical imperative of action, but until he read Whitehead, Olson seems not to have felt the coherence of
these and other ideas in a system that could legitimately be called a metaphysics . . . which is to say that
Whitehead offered Olson clarifications, definitions, and above all else, a way of systematically organiz-
ing a set of metaphysical principles.
CHAPTER 4. CONCRESCENCE
1. Whitehead, Process and Reality, 210.
2. Whitehead, Adventures of Ideas, 242.
3. Charles Olson, Additional Prose (Bolinas: Four Seasons Foundation, 1974), 11. Subse-
quent quotations from this work are cited in the text, abbreviated as AP.
4. Mark Karlins, “The Primacy of Source: The Derivative Poetics of Charles Olson’s The
Maximus Poems (vol.1),” Sagetrieb 4, 1 (spring 1985): 34.
5. Whitehead, Adventures of Ideas, 242– 43.
6. Whitehead, Modes of Thought, 155.
7. Whitehead, Process and Reality, 22.
8. The concept of time itself undergoes changes, which lead to further problems I discuss
in the chapter about the second type of fluency.
9. Whitehead, Process and Reality, 18, 73.
10. I stress the relationship between the masculine and the feminine here because, generally,
as is pointed out by Judith Halden-Sullivan, The Topology of Being: The Poetics of Charles Olson
(New York: Peter Lang, 1991), 34: “Put frankly, Olson is a ‘macho’ poet. He uses feminine
referents only in stereotypic contexts: When poeticizing about the powers of nature, love and
sex.” As Halden-Sullivan herself remarks, however: “Never does he explicitly exclude women
from participating in the ontology he envisions.” I suggest that we refrain from overstating the
significance of this limitation, because “his ideas may survive his sexism, which are typical yet
to his times.” See also the biographical data in Clark, The Allegory of a Poet’s Life, and Maud and
Thesan, Charles Olson and Frances Boldereff.
11. Whitehead, Adventures of Ideas, 226.
12. The choice of term is evidence of the reader’s empathetic or critical attitude.
13. Whitehead, Adventures of Ideas, 300.
14. I discuss this “failure” of communication in chapter 7 below, when trying to examine
the causes for the mounting feeling, in the third volume of The Maximus Poems, that Maximus
withdraws further and further into himself after his letters to the townspeople go unheeded and
remain unanswered.
15. Don Byrd, Charles Olson’s Maximus (Urbana: Universiy of Illinois Press, 1980), 45.
16. Olson/Melville: A Study in Affinity, ed. Ann Charters. (Berkeley: Oyez, 1968), 83.
Subsequent quotations from this work are cited in the text, abbreviated as O/M.
17. As well as for himself, who had also worked at the post office. Olson dedicated his book,
The Post Office (Bolinas: Grey Fox Press, 1975), to his father.
18. On Olson’s source for the term automorphism: “Cf. Weyl, Philosophy of Mathematics
and Natural Science, p. 72: ‘We now consider the special case when our domain of objects is
NOTES 149
mapped not upon another domain but upon itself, and thus arrive at the notion of automor-
phism: an automorphism is a one-to-one mapping p-p’ of the point-field into itself which leaves
the basic relations undisturbed” (Butterick, A Guide, 210).
19. Altieri, “Olson’s Poetics and the Tradition,” Boundary 2, 2.1–2 (fall 1973–winter
1974): 182.
20. On the cover of the second volume, Olson chose to present a map of the globe before
the continents had split off. Mapping the space of the earth is closely linked to the historical
move that Olson makes along The Maximus Poems.
21. Butterick, A Guide, 140.
22. Ibid., 547.
23. Fredman, The Grounding of American Poetry, 91.
24. Butterick, A Guide, 544.
25. Whitehead, Process and Reality, 25.
26. Olson was then living in Washington. In 1957 he returned to Gloucester, the site of his
childhood summers.
CHAPTER 5. FLUENCY
14. Because if time itself develops, a higher supratime is required for this development to
occur, and so on ad infinitum, hence Whitehead’s tendency to see becoming as a primary
concept that takes precedence over others.
15. John Taggart, Songs of Degrees: Essays on Contemporary Poetry and Poetics. (Tuscaloosa:
University of Alabama Press, 1994), 161–62, suggests a most interesting explanation of Olson’s
attitude to Melville. He views Melville as “Olson’s center and source that, once saturated, once
‘in himself,’ gave him the key to ‘everything else very fast.’ ” Olson however, deliberately
misread or misreported his reading of Melville, “with his insistence on Melville’s value as an
author of physical detail and factuality.” Olson “turns Melville’s physical space into a physical
entity.” The animus for this, according to Taggart, “is a proprietary desire to keep his central
source to himself. . . . To gain power, you must defeat an opponent stronger than yourself, you
must partake of that power (eat from the body, magnum corpus) and you must keep something
of the once stronger opponent as a souvenir of the power you now possess yourself.”
I choose to deal with this issue now rather than when I noted how Olson views Melville as a
writer of “physical entity” (p. 37), or when I considered Olson’s quality as a “derivative poet”
(p. 45), because at this point, after we have already covered some distance, we can draw further
conclusions from Taggart’s statement (and thus return to the places noted above). The picture
described in TMP, 414, as well as in other poetic units, allows us to view Taggart’s analysis as a
possible principle guiding Olson’s attitude to texts in general; the wars of Enyalion, Tyr,
Hercules, and others, could actually appear as the war of Olson/Maximus who, as Taggart
describes him, is a cannibal of texts:
This has to remind us of Ishmael who, as his author’s book’s etymology and extracts prologue make
clear, is a cannibal of texts. This sort of cannibalism allows what “experience” never could, the creation
of fictional space. It is the fictional narrator cannibal, not Queequeg, who survives. . . . The imperative
first sentence he took for his title has a doubly reflexive reference to the earlier cannibal and to himself,
Olson, the later one.
Taggart’s analysis thus strengthens the tension I had noted (and will also note below
regarding Olson’s ritual dimension that is indeed our concern here): the lot of a poet attempt-
ing to be a teacher without pulling rank; seeking to rebel and break a tradition and a canon
without turning himself into their replacement; trying to rebuild a world without resorting to
the violence (even if only textual) of the world in which he is rooted and is actually seeking to
destroy.
16. Byrd, Charles Olson’s Maximus, 85. See also Butterick, A Guide, 58–64.
17. Whitehead, Process and Reality, 128–29.
18. Von Hallberg, The Scholar’s Art, 155. Von Hallberg also adds other puns derived from
Olson’s choices. See pp. 150–58, which he devotes to general aspects of “Tyrian Businesses.”
19. See Whitehead, Process and Reality, 61.
20. Joseph M. Conte, Unending Design: The Forms of Postmodern Poetry (Ithaca: Cornell
University Press, 1991), characterizes two forms of the postmodern, serial and procedural. The
emphasis is that, contrary to the misleading appearances, Olson’s poetry is not serial. Certain
descriptions of Olson’s way of working seem to fit procedural poetry, in Conte’s terms. Thus,
for instance, Christensen, Call Him Ishmael, writes: “My premise that there is such unity is
‘conjectural’ in the sense that Olson used the term; its etymology reaches back to Latin
conjicere, ‘to throw together,’ or toss, as Marcel Duchamp tossed the rods in his studio, allowing
them to fall randomly and make a design, from which he fashioned ‘The Mechanical Bride,’ a
work of the most deliberate precision.” As is clear from my writing here, I do not accept this
view, which leaves randomness (clear to the postmodern artist) as the central element of Olson’s
poetics, and no further comment seems necessary.
NOTES 151
21. Whitehead’s choice of the term feeling is understandable, since “positive prehension” is
“the definite inclusion of the item into positive contribution to the subject’s own real internal
constitution” (Whitehead, Process and Reality, 23, 41).
22. Whitehead, then, reminds the reader that a gap prevails between language and reality,
which can only be bridged through a leap of imagination. Beyond this, however, he adopts a
writing technique that takes into account these difficulties, making this leap of imagination
easier for the reader: by coining this new philosophical conceptualization, and after opening
and presenting the conceptual scheme of the categories he had created, Whitehead recurrently
explains the systematic conceptual approach throughout the book, at various levels and in
various formulations, by pointing to, analyzing, and contending with the relevant philosophi-
cal sources of these terms.
Whitehead thereby attains two aims that share the same purpose. First, he contends with the
problem of the “baggage” that is a priori inherent in language for anyone who uses it: the
cultural, philosophical, and other associations fixated and internalized in the linguistic system
(see, for instance, Whitehead, Adventures of Ideas, 200). The problem posed by the “baggage”
borne by language is particularly important for Whitehead, since his approach challenges the
traditional pattern of Western canonic thinking, certainly from Descartes onward, but in many
ways even from Aristotle. Although this reflects a reversal in the scientific worldview, it is
specific to Whitehead because he assumes his stand as a philosopher rather than as a scientist,
in an attempt to rebuild a comprehensive speculative method to explain the world—despite,
and precisely because of, this scientific reversal. Removing old patterns because of new ones
therefore implies a release, as far as possible, from a loaded language: the old philosophical
problems require reformulation; the philosophical language requires us to invent new concepts,
enabling liberation from the old cosmology and the thinking patterns it enforces. Whitehead’s
new terms reflect the new analysis of an old problem, and the new terminology attests to the
direction of the new solution now suggested.
Reaching Whitehead’s first aim by building a new conceptual system entails confusion for
the reader. The organization of the text (Process and Reality) helps to contend with this
inevitable difficulty. In a sense, Whitehead imposes a process quality on his philosophical work
in order to attain his second aim: the internalization of the new conceptual world, the creation
of a closed linguistic microcosm to describe the world, where concepts are elucidated and
become meaningful within this microcosm. The conceptual system emerges along the work, in
the course of the reading process, from within and out of the world it describes; in order to
clarify his concepts, Whitehead recurrently explains the categorical scheme he had originally
presented, in different ways and with the help of various examples, by coining synonymous
terms for every concept, and obviously by relating to philosophical tradition and its concepts.
The method itself is an inner network of concepts closely linked to each other and assuming
each other, in order to create a coherent system. Obviously, then, concerning The Maximus
Poems as well, and by analogy to Whitehead’s contents and cosmology, a world containing its
own explanation is presented that, in the course of the reading, reaches (textual) lucidity and
unity.
23. Whitehead, Process and Reality, 236–38.
24. The reader familiar with Pound’s poetry will recognize here the critique already pointed
out. Olson emphasizes that we will now obtain a cantus firmus, meaning unity, but as it occurs
in time: “I couldn’t write a canto if I sat down and deliberately tried. My interest is not in
cantos. It’s in another condition of song, which is connected to mode and has therefore to do
with absolute actuality. It’s so completely temporal” (The Paris Review, 1970: 198).
25. Butterick, A Guide, 257–58.
152 CHARLES OLSON AND ALFRED NORTH WHITEHEAD
CHAPTER 7. STANCE
1. “I cannot be responsible for the way the Dept. of Justice tries the citizen Ezra Pound.
But I say I nor any other writer can allow Ezra Pound the writer to go untried. For he stands
forth in all his violence to be judged. It is here the fact that he is a poet, and a good one, has
bearing” (Charles Olson, Charles Olson and Ezra Pound: An Encounter at St. Elizabeths, ed.
Catherine Seelye [New York: Paragon House, 1991], 16. Subsequent quotations from this
work are cited in the text, abbreviated as COEP).
The tension that Olson felt with Pound, which is not resolved as we sense when we end the
reading of COEP, stems from this nonseparation of powers, a separation that would have made
it easier to cope with Pound’s “separate sides.” Olson, who was born in 1910, belongs to the
generarion of postwar poets deeply affected by the terrors of the war (Auschwitz, Hiroshima).
He was also involved in political activity. After resigning from the Office of War Information,
he joined the Democratic National Committee as director of the Foreign Nationalities Divi-
sion. But “in January 1945, deciding ‘to write like forever!,’ he declined two offers of govern-
ment positions (O/M, 9). In April, he returned to Washington from a vacation in Virginia and
learned of Roosevelt’s death: ‘I started Ishmael that afternoon, the afternoon I kissed off my
political future.’ ” (Von Hallberg, The Scholar’s Art, 5). See ibid., ch. 1, 5– 43 on Olson’s
development as a political poet; on the political-economic-cultural background of his times; on
aspects of leadership, treason, law, and democracy that affected and shaped, for instance, the
characters of the “protagonists” of The Maximus Poems (Stevens the carpenter; Conant, who
averts corruption and sordidness); on Mao’s influence; on his shaping as an educational figure
in the political context and, as noted, on the context that generated his idea that “subject
matter is primary” and “lyric poetry that is more engaged by its own language than by its
ostensible subject . . . derives from aestheticism, a blight on modern poetry” (p. 22).
2. Butterick, A Guide, 13.
3. Obviously the opposite of the language that Olson tries to revive throughout the entire
poem, a language directly and concretely related to human breathing and to the world of which
he is part, and potentially capable of returning the power of the “object” to the world of which
154 CHARLES OLSON AND ALFRED NORTH WHITEHEAD
it is the “picture.” See again Olson’s remarks on the language of hieroglyphics concerning the
culture of the Maya in, for instance, SW, 58.
4. COEP, 83.
5. I noted above the tension affecting a critique of language through language.
6. Oswyn Murray and Simon Price, eds. The Greek City: From Homer to Alexander (Ox-
ford: Clarendon Press, 1991), 21.
7. See, for instance, TMP, 113, 133.
8. Von Hallberg, The Scholar’s Art, 178.
9. From this passage, dealing with Robert Creeley, we must infer again concerning the
Pound case, which was noted above.
10. Whitehead, Process and Reality, 237.
11. The movement backward in time, to the beginning of the settlement before decay set in,
is a movement toward a previous stage, before mistaken and conceptual divisiveness.
12. TMP, 37.
13. See Murray, The Greek City; Victor Ehrenberg, The Greek State (London: Basil Black-
well, 1960); Robert Griffeth and Carol G. Thomas, eds. The City-State in Five Cultures (Santa
Barbara, Calif.: ABC-Clio, 1981); Alexander Fuks, The Athenian Commonwealth: Politics,
Society, Culture (in Hebrew) (Jerusalem: Bialik Institute, 1975).
14. As noted, Ferrini resides in Gloucester and intends to publish a journal there. The letter
Olson sent him, “Letter 1” in The Maximus Poems, set the entire process of the poem in
motion.
15. Binarity, then, is inescapable: Olson’s divisions into pairs of rivals, as is well emphasized
in “A Later Note,” show that this pattern of thought is relevant to various needs, even in a
world with pluralistic aspirations.
16. See “Letter 3.”
17. Butterick, A Guide, 22–23, citing Olson’s description of the herb in a note to editor
Donald Allen, c. 22 July 1963.
18. See Murray, The Greek City, 21.
19. Whitehead, Process and Reality, 89.
20. As described in Murray, The Greek City, 21.
21. Benedict Anderson, Imagined Communities: Reflections on the Origin and Spread of
Nationalism (London: Verso, 1991), 6. This became the prevalently accepted definition to
many prominent scholars in various areas of discourse, not only political science.
22. HU, 141. Pound’s case, which is so relevant, deserves to be mentioned again here. See,
for instance, Olson’s critique of Pound for his arrogant attitude toward the guard at St.
Elizabeths: “But it was the fascist too, as a snob, classing the guard” (COEP, 50). The growth of
the idea of the polis, in all its denotations, is unquestionably tied to the case of Pound, who was
one of Olson’s poetic ancestors, and to Olson’s visits to him in the mid-forties.
23. This is true concerning a nationality that senses itself superior to others, or a person who
feels superior to others—both are the result of a sense of superiority concerning the environ-
ment itself. Traditional Western humanism, as we know, is extremely violent.
24. See the “I-thou” relationships we discussed in chapter six, concerning the Weltanschau-
ung of antiquity and of myth.
25. Aristotle, Politics, trans. T. A. Sinclair (New York: Penguin Books, 1978).
26. Murray, The Greek City, 267–68.
27. Ehrenberg, The Greek State, 194.
28. Griffeth, The City State, 31.
29. Aristotle, Politics, 28.
30. See Fuks, The Athenian Commonwealth, 2–3.
31. In Whitehead’s terms, he is an “actual potentiality.”
NOTES 155
32. Butterick, A Guide, 76.
33. Ibid., 108.
34. Murray, The Greek City, 200.
35. TMP, see pp. 23, 31, 37, 43.
36. See Butterick, A Guide, 239– 42, for Olson’s sources on this story.
37. Don Byrd, Charles Olson’s Maximus, 114 –17.
38. Byrd returns to the sources Olson had used for his concepts, in this case the book by Eric
Neumann, The Great Mother: An Analysis of the Archetype (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton Univer-
sity Press, 1974).
39. See the previous chapter on myths or stories with a mythical aspect.
40. Murray, The Greek City, 305.
41. Butterick, A Guide, 11.
42. Murray, The Greek City, 302.
CHAPTER 8. FAILURE?
1. Olson was influenced by various Asian doctrines and by Asian thinkers. Due to the
scope of this work and to considerations of coherence, I have refrained from delving into this
conceptual realm. Let me just point out that Olson’s use of these sources is generally compatible
with his Weltanschauung, as well as with the correspondence he finds between modern science
and ancient thought. On the links between Buddhism, Zen, and even Hinduism on the one
hand, and modern science on the other see, for instance, Capra, The Tao of Physics.
2. Butterick, A Guide, 155–56.
3. Karlins, “The Primacy of Source,” 43.
4. Von Hallberg, The Scholar’s Art, 70.
5. Like the title of Olson’s essay. See TMP, 180.
6. For Olson’s sources, see Butterick, A Guide, 413, 512.
7. As he himself indicates; see MUT, 1:159.
8. TMP, 257. This unit was discussed above. This ritual is at the center of TMP, 157–59.
9. Butterick (citing Olson), A Guide, 9.
10. “We are the last ‘first’ people” (CMI, 14).
11. Butterick (citing Olson), A Guide, 7.
12. See, for instance, Byrd, Charles Olson’s Maximus, 109.
13. Butterick (citing Olson), A Guide, 7.
14. TMP, 39; parts of this unit were discussed above.
15. “Maximus, at Tyre and at Boston,” as the title of the poetic unit in TMP, 97.
16. See TMP, 476, 482, 483, 488, as instances of this sense of failure.
17. My emphasis.
18. See TMP, 172, 181.
19. Butterick, A Guide, 607.
20. TMP, 635; Olson explicitly designated this unit as the concluding one, although he did
not edit the last volume.
21. Butterick, A Guide, 751.
22. See the discussion on color as related to the shield of the body, the heart, and the shield
of the flower, concerning “Letter 20,” “Letter 21,” and more.
References
SECONDARY WORKS
Altieri, Charles. Enlarging the Temple: New Directions in American Poetry during the 1960s.
Lewisburg: Bucknell University Press, 1979.
——— “Olson’s Poetics and the Tradition.” Boundary 2, 2.1–2 (fall 1973–winter 1974): 173–
88.
Anderson, Benedict. Imagined Communities: Reflections on the Origin and Spread of National-
ism. Revised and Extended Edition. London: Verso, 1991.
Aristotle. Politics. Translated with an Introduction by T. A. Sinclair. 1962. Reprint, New York:
Penguin Books, 1978.
Beach, Christopher. ABC of Influence: Ezra Pound and the Remaking of American Poetic Tradi-
tion. Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of California Press, 1992.
156
REFERENCES 157
Bové, Paul. Destructive Poetics: Heidegger and Modern American Poetry. New York: Columbia
University Press, 1980.
Butterick, George F. A Guide to the Maximus Poems of Charles Olson. Berkeley: University of
California Press, 1978.
Byrd, Don. Charles Olson’s Maximus. Urbana: University of Illinois Press, 1980.
Capek, Milic. Bergson and Modern Physics: A Reinterpretation and Reevaluation. Dordrecht,
Holland: D. Reidel, 1971.
Capra, Fritjof. The Tao of Physics. Berkeley: Shambhala, 1975.
Christensen, Paul. Charles Olson: Call Him Ishmael. Austin: University of Texas Press, 1979.
Clark, Tom. Charles Olson: The Allegory of a Poet’s Life. New York: W. W. Norton, 1991.
Conte, Joseph M. Unending Design: The Forms of Postmodern Poetry. Ithaca: Cornell University
Press, 1991.
Davis, William P. God and the New Physics. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1984.
Descartes, Rene. The Philosophical Works of Descartes. Vol. 1. New York: Dover Publications,
1955.
Detienne, Marcel. The Creation of Mythology. Translated by Margaret Cook. Chicago: Univer-
sity of Chicago Press, 1986.
Draper, R. P., ed. The Epic: Developments in Criticism. London: Macmillan, 1990.
Ehrenberg, Victor. The Greek State. London: Basil Blackwell, 1960.
Einstein, Albert, and Leopold Infeld. The Evolution of Physics. Cambridge: Cambridge Univer-
sity Press, 1947.
Eliade, Mircea. Myth and Reality. Translated by Willard R. Trask. New York: Harper Torch-
books, 1963.
Ferris, Timothy. Coming of Age in the Milky Way. New York: William Morrow, 1988.
Frankfort, Henri, Mrs. Henri Frankfort, John A. Wilson, and Thorkild Jacobsen. Before
Philosophy. Harmondsworth: Penguin Books, 1951.
Frazer, Julian T. Time: The Familiar Stranger. Redmond, Wash.: Tempus Books of Microsoft
Press, 1987.
Fredman, Stephen. The Grounding of American Poetry: Charles Olson and the Emersonian
Tradition. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1993.
Fuks, Alexander. The Athenian Commonwealth: Politics, Society, Culture (in Hebrew). Jerusa-
lem: Bialik Institute, 1975.
Genette, Gerard. Figures III. Paris: Seuil, 1972.
Griffeth, Robert, and Carol G. Thomas, eds. The City-State in Five Cultures. Santa Barbara,
Calif.: ABC-Clio, 1981.
Halden-Sullivan, Judith. The Topology of Being: The Poetics of Charles Olson. New York: Peter
Lang, 1991.
Havelock, Eric A. Preface to Plato. Cambridge: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press,
1963.
Hawking, Stephen W. A Brief History of Time: From the Big Bang to Black Holes. London:
Bantam Press, 1988.
Karlins, M. “The Primacy of Source: The Derivative Poetics of Charles Olson’s The Maximus
Poems (vol. 1).” Sagetrieb, 4, 1 (spring 1985): 33–60.
Kraus, Elizabeth M. The Metaphysics of Experience: A Companion to Whitehead’s Process and
Reality. New York: Fordham University Press, 1979.
158 CHARLES OLSON AND ALFRED NORTH WHITEHEAD
Lockwood, Michael. Mind, Brain and the Quantum: The Compound “I.” Oxford: Basil Black-
well, 1995.
Maud, Ralph, and Sharon Thesan, eds. Charles Olson and Frances Boldereff: A Modern Corre-
spondence. Hanover, N.H.: University Press of New England, 1999.
Murray, Oswyn, and Simon Price, eds. The Greek City: From Homer to Alexander. Oxford:
Clarendon Press, 1991.
Neumann, Eric. The Great Mother: An Analysis of the Archetype. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton
University Press, 1974.
Paul, Sherman. Olson’s Push: Origin, Black Mountain and Recent American Poetry. Baton Rouge:
Louisiana State University Press, 1978.
Preminger, Alex, ed. Encyclopedia of Poetry and Poetics. Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University
Press, 1965.
Riddel, Joseph N. The Inverted Bell: Modernism and the Counterpoetics of William Carlos
Williams. Baton Rouge: Louisiana State University Press, 1974.
Spanos, William V., “Talking with Robert Creeley,” Boundary 2, 6.3–7.1 (spring–fall 1978):
12–74.
Taggart, John. Songs of Degrees: Essays on Contemporary Poetry and Poetics. Tuscaloosa: Univer-
sity of Alabama Press, 1994.
Von Hallberg, Robert. Charles Olson: The Scholar’s Art. London: Harvard University Press,
1978.
Whitehead, Alfred North. Process and Reality. Edited by David R. Griffin and Donald W.
Sherburne. 1929. Reprint, New York: Free Press, 1978.
———. Dialogues of A. N. Whitehead as Recorded by Lucien Price. New York: New American
Library, 1956.
———. Modes of Thought. New York: Macmillan, 1938.
———. Adventures of Ideas. New York: Macmillan, 1933.
———. Science and the Modern World. New York: Cambridge University Press, 1925
———. An Enquiry Concerning the Principles of Natural Knowledge. New York: Cambridge
University Press, 1919.
Index of Poetic Units
The following is a list of the poetic units, or “letters,” examined in this book. The titles appear
in accordance with The Maximus Poems’ index of poems, where first lines serve as titles to poetic
units otherwise untitled.
after the storm was over, (TMP, 264): 95 Letter 7, (TMP, 34): 64, 115, 116, 117
Letter 9, (TMP, 45): 60, 63, 83
BEGINNINGS (facts), THE, (TMP, 235): Letter 10, (TMP, 49): 126
103 Letter 16, (TMP, 76): 127–28
Blow is Creation, the, (TMP, 634): 87 Letter 20: not a pastoral letter, (TMP, 93):
61, 83
Death of Carl Olsen, The, (TMP, 474): Letter 23, (TMP, 103): 98–99
129 Letter # 41 [broken off ], (TMP, 171): 93–
Descartes soldier, (TMP, 226): 28 94, 96, 98
earth with a city in her hair, The, (TMP, Maximus, at the Harbor, (TMP, 240): 105–
289): 36, 124 6
Maximus, at Tyre and Boston, (TMP, 97):
FRONTLET, THE, (TMP, 315): 36 57, 61, 82, 83, 88
MAXIMUS, FROM DOGTOWN-I,
having described the nation, (TMP, 377): (TMP, 172): 87, 129, 130
123 MAXIMUS, FROM DOGTOWN-II,
he who walks with his house . . ., (TMP, (TMP, 179): 58, 84
311): 34 Maximus, to Gloucester [I don’t mean, just
History is the Memory of Time, (TMP, 116): like that . . .], (TMP, 110): 133, 135
100 Maximus, to Gloucester: Letter 2, (TMP, 9):
54 –55, 57, 100, 103, 129, 136
I looked up and saw, (TMP, 343): 62 Maximus, to Gloucester: Letter 14 (TMP,
I, Maximus of Gloucester, to You, (TMP, 5): 63): 83, 87
12, 23, 38, 48– 49, 55–56, 79, 111–12, Maximus, to Gloucester: Letter 15 (TMP,
131 71): 89, 13
Maximus, to Gloucester, Letter 27 [withheld],
Later Note on Letter # 15, A, (TMP, 249): (TMP, 184): 42– 44, 46, 48, 53, 54, 59,
11–15, 18–19, 23, 26, 28, 29, 40, 47, 107
57, 63, 71, 91, 97, 110 Maximus, to Gloucester, Sunday, July 19,
Letter 3, (TMP, 13): 112, 119 (TMP, 157): 138, 140
Letter 5, (TMP, 21): 57, 64 –65, 66 Maximus, to himself, as of “Phoenicians,”
Letter 6, (TMP, 30): 40, 50, 124 (TMP, 181): 86
159
160 INDEX OF POETIC UNITS
Maximus Letter # whatever, (TMP, 201): 33 Song and Dance of, The, (TMP, 58): 83
Maximus of Gloucester, (TMP, 473): 88, Songs of Maximus, The, (TMP, 17): 51
134, 137, 141 Space and Time the saliva, (TMP, 414):
my memory is, (TMP, 256): 100 76
my wife my car . . ., (TMP, 635): 142 Stiffening, in the Master Founders’ Wills,
(TMP, 132): 26–27, 97, 142
Nasturtium / is still my flower . . ., (TMP,
632): 87, 88, 142 That’s / the combination . . ., (TMP, 582):
58
On First Looking out through Juan de la to enter into their bodies, (TMP, 317): 35,
Cosa’s Eyes, (TMP, 81): 83 36
to travel Typhon, (TMP, 265): 95
Peloria . . ., (TMP, 257): 92–93, 138 Twist, The, (TMP, 86): 83, 88, 89, 94, 136,
Physically, I am home. Polish it, (TMP, 137
456): 104 Tyrian Businesses, (TMP, 39): 77–80, 82, 88
rages / strain / Dog of Tartarus, (TMP, Watch-house / Point . . ., (TMP, 394): 123
405): 60, 61 Wrote my first poems, (TMP, 299): 94, 97
Index
Achilles, 71 Cadmus, 80
Activity: of inner sources, 39, 79; and phys- Call me Ishmael, 54, 74, 103
ical entity, 20, 49; poetry as, 16, 18, 26, Cape Ann, 29, 99, 125, 126, 135
31, 40, 51, 53, 64, 74, 93, 106, 113, Cerberus, 76
114, 117, 131, 132 Christensen, Paul, 15, 150 n. 20
Actualization, 12, 46, 94; by the reader, 17, Clark, Tom, 144 n. 4, 146 n. 3, 147 n. 16,
29, 31, 46– 47, 82, 84; in “A Later Note 148 n. 10
on Letter # 15,” 18, 23, 47 Conant, James, 125–27
Agyasta, 128 Conant, Roger, 125–27
Algonquin Legends of New England, 34 Concrescence, 13, 21, 42–66, 68; and En-
Altieri, Charles, 23, 58, 100 yalion, 61; and experience, 45– 47, 57,
Anderson, Benedict, 119, 120 63; in “letter # 27”, 46; and writing, 50,
Aphrodite, 62 114
Ares, 59, 62 Confucius, 38
Aristotle, 24, 26, 30, 47, 79, 121, 122 Conte, Joseph M., 150 n. 20
Atomism, 20, 36, 69, 70, 81 Continuity: and atomism, 36, 70, 81; and
becoming, 70, 73, 76, 81, 83; of the
Beach, Christopher, 144 n. 5 event, 18; of the experience, 12, 45, 75,
Bergson, Henri, 71, 76 136
Berryman, John, 75 Creativity, 12, 16, 70, 73, 75, 81, 85, 110,
Body: and experience, 32, 33, 52, 54, 64 – 113, 114, 117
65, 77, 78, 79, 102–3, 117, 125, 134;
and family, 45; and home, 33–34, 36, Darwin, Charles, 37
37, 40, 44, 79, 123, 135; and inheri- Davis, William, 73
tance, 44, 45; and the “other,” 34 –35, Descartes, Rene, 15, 18, 23, 71, 110; as
95, 113; and poetry, 16 anti-atomist, 20; and Boston’s settling,
Boston, 26, 27, 28, 40, 92, 127 26–28, 40, 54, 66, 97; his concept of
Bove, Paul, 22, 34, 39, 145 n. 3, 147 n. 17 substance, 24, 25, 30, 32, 47, 48, 64,
Breathing: in “Later Note on Letter # 15, 142; as Whitehead’s rival, 18–19, 23,
A,” 18, 23; in “Letter 9,” 63; in “Letter 24 –29, 71
41,” 96; and nature, 45; and poetry, 16, Detienne, Marcel, 108, 109, 110
18, 22, 25, 32, 39, 76, 84, 89, 100; in Diorite, 95
“Songs of Maximus, The,” 52–53 Dogtown, 28, 29, 35, 36, 55, 57, 129, 136
Buddha, 38 Duncan, Robert, 91
Butterick, George F., 25, 35, 61, 84, 85,
93, 95, 96 Ehrenberg, Victor, 122
Byrd, Don, 54, 79, 129, 130 Einstein, Albert, 20, 21, 70, 72, 145 n. 6
161
162 INDEX
Eliade, Mircea, 103, 104, 106 65, 66, 79, 80, 82, 87, 88, 89, 92, 95,
Emerson, Ralph Waldo, 14, 145 n. 4 98, 100, 103, 109, 112, 114, 115, 120,
Entity: actual, 30–31, 32, 42, 46– 47, 50, 124, 127, 129, 133, 135, 138, 140
61, 62, 66, 67, 68, 74, 83, 85, 89, 93, Greek influence, 40, 43, 44, 59, 60, 67, 76,
96, 102, 118, 143; nouns and, 24; per- 80, 89, 100, 106, 107, 108, 110, 112,
ceiving, 51; physical, 20–21 113, 117, 122, 123, 125, 128, 131, 140
Enyalion, 76, 93, 95; and multiplicity, 59; Griffeth, Robert, 122
and the law of possibility, 61; and the Growth: and body, 33–34, 37, 38, 41, 45,
law of proportions, 60, 61 77, 79; and the “other,” 50, 53, 74, 76,
Ethos: of action, 12, 26, 111, 112, 113, 80; and space, 37–38, 39, 41, 49, 54,
116, 119, 127, 132, 135–36; and experi- 55, 80, 97, 125; and unity, 38, 42, 59,
ence, 51, 86; and hierarchies, 50, 56; and 60, 73, 118, 131
history, 55; of objectism, 38, 48
Event: and body, 44, 64; the city as, 49; and Halden-Sullivan, Judith, 148 n. 10
creating, 46; the poetic unit as, 18, 63; Hartley, the painter, 116
the world as, 12, 30–31, 48, 49, 87, 102 Havelock, Eric A., 107, 117
Experience, 30– 41; and becoming, 30–31, Hawking, Stephen, 72
53, 69, 83; bodily, 33, 34 –35, 51, 52, Hephaestus, 59, 62
79, 109; and existence, 25, 30–31, 40, Hera, 61, 62
41, 47, 65–66, 86, 106, 111, 120, 123; Heraclitus, 70, 74, 85, 87, 89, 107
and the “other,” 34 –35, 45, 46, 48, 53, Hercules, 62, 76, 93
85, 102, 131–32, 133–35, 139; in rela- Herodotus, 18, 19, 91, 92, 94, 99, 109, 110
tion to the subject, 30–31, 46, 82, 114, Hesiod, 87
120 History, 16, 55, 91–110; and facts, 91, 96,
98–99, 101, 111, 121; and the present,
Failure, 133–142; Olson’s sense of, 13, 17, 93, 96, 98, 100; and story, 98–100,
31, 52, 88, 106, 136, 139 109–10
Fenris, 76 Homer, 98, 99, 107, 108
Ferrini, Vincent, 31, 56, 64, 65, 66, 116, “Human Universe,” 40, 45, 101
118, 120, 124, 154 n. 14
Ferris, Timothy, 20, 37, 39, 147 n. 15 Jake, the fisherman, 116
Field: composition by, 19, 83; of energy, Jung, Carl Gustav, 84, 98, 139
19, 22, 35; Fishermen’s, 28–29, 98–99,
135; and the perception of space, 20, 34, Karlins, M., 45, 92, 134
121; theory of, 20–22 “The Kingfishers,” 75, 112
Flower, 77–78, 80, 82–87, 88, 89, 93, Kraus, Elizabeth, 71
118, 119, 136, 137, 138, 139, 141, 142
Fluency, 13, 26, 41, 68–90; and becoming, Lady of Good, 35, 49, 117, 131
42, 68, 69; and creativity, 71, 73, 82; Locke, John, 42, 68
and permanence, 70–71 Logos, 16, 32, 98, 99, 100, 103, 106, 107,
Frankfort, Henri, 36, 101, 102, 103, 107, 108, 120
146 n. 13 Long poem: and the arrow of time, 16, 73,
Frazer, Julian, 70 75, 81, 90; and the concept of substance,
Fredman, Stephen, 60, 89, 144 n. 8, 145 n. 25; and epic tradition, 67, 75, 81, 87,
4, 152 n. 32 102, 107, 108; as life itself, 34, 67, 136;
as a poem of growth, 14, 23, 25, 41, 80;
Ginsberg, Allen, 75 its scope, 12, 16; as what precedes genre
Gloucester, 14, 17, 26, 27, 28, 29, 35, 36, divisions, 34, 41, 47, 75
37, 38, 40, 44, 48, 54, 57, 58, 63, 64, Lowell, Robert, 75
INDEX 163
Macro level, 13–14, 26, 28, 41, 68, 73, 75, Orality, 16, 46, 88, 108, 109
77, 79, 82, 83, 84, 96, 122 Orentes, 94
Manes, 93 Organism: philosophy of, 30, 74, 121, 124;
Mars, 59 the poem as, 12, 81, 85, 89, 122; reality
Massalia (Marseilles), 94 as, 14, 85, 89, 102–3, 122, 132, 142
Maud, Ralph, 147 n. 16
Maximus: as a guide or a teacher, 31, 32, Parmenides, 70, 107
38–39, 137–38, 139; the poet as, 18, Paul, Sherman, 144 n. 7
29, 35, 37, 38, 39, 49, 50, 58, 61–62, Pindar, 98, 99
69, 73, 80, 93, 112, 134, 139; the reader Place: living in, 64 –66, 96, 100, 112, 118,
as, 18, 53, 62, 69, 80; Stevens as, 115, 119, 120, 121, 122, 139; an opening
118, 137; from Tyre, 54, 138, 139, 140 place, 11–13, 23, 27–28, 52, 94, 95,
Maxwell, James Clerk, 20 96, 138–39, 143; phenomenology in,
Melville, Herman, 15, 20, 36, 37, 39, 103, 54, 57
150 n. 15 Plato, 98, 108, 122, 141
Memphis, 36 Polis, 26, 38, 44, 46, 49, 53, 100, 101,
Merk, Frederick, 29, 98 114, 116, 117, 121, 122, 124, 127, 128,
Merry, James, 129–30 131; and body, 46, 95, 109, 113, 115,
Micro level, 13–14, 26, 28, 41, 68, 75, 82, 117, 122, 123, 131, 132; Gloucester as,
84, 122 63, 113, 119, 131, 138–39, 140, 141
Modern science, 19–21, 70–71, 72, 73, 80; Potentiality, 20, 26, 29, 39; in nature, 49;
as influence, 12, 15, 19–20, 23, 39, 40, and poetry, 46– 47, 68, 81, 82, 89; real,
70, 71, 74; and mythopoeic approach 30, 47, 68, 131, 143
16, 36, 39, 100–101, 104, 115 Pound, Ezra, 14, 75, 112, 113, 136, 146 n.
Multiplicity. See Unity 9, 151 n. 24, 153 n. 1
Murray, Oswyn, 113, 121, 128, 131 Process: of becoming, 49, 69; Olson’s po-
Myth, 12, 15, 16, 33, 74, 87, 91–110; and etics as, 12, 13, 21–22, 23, 39, 46, 68,
creation, 35–36, 104, 106; and place, 88, 114; and perception, 52; of reading,
37, 129; understanding of, 99–100, 16–17, 18, 31, 47, 50, 75, 82, 84
103– 4, 132 Projection, 49, 88, 89; and the body, 34, 41,
Mythopoeic thinking: as influence, 12, 14, 79; in “Later Note on Letter # 15, A,” 18–
15, 100, 107; Olson’s understanding of, 19; in “Letter 9,” 63; and modern physics,
16, 25, 36, 49, 53, 63, 84 –85, 87, 101, 21, 40; in “Songs of Maximus, The,” 52
104 “Projective Verse,” 19, 21, 22, 23, 32, 34,
38, 41, 49, 74, 100, 108
Narrativity, 13, 16, 67–68, 77, 81, 85, 88, Ptah, 36
98, 102 Pytheas, 93, 94
Nationalism, 119–20, 122
New England, 15, 55, 112 Realization: and enduring object, 36; and
Newton, Issac, 20–21, 30, 36, 71, 74 identity, 62; and poetry, 31, 46– 47, 50,
53, 68, 83, 86, 88, 96, 108
Odin, 62 Ritual, 12, 16, 85, 104, 106, 130, 133,
Odysseus, 93 134 –35, 136, 138, 139; poetry as, 16,
Okeanos, 35, 50, 84, 85, 87, 93, 96, 98, 63, 103, 108, 109, 113, 129, 132
105, 129
Olsen, Carl, 129 Samson, 79
Olson, Karl Joseph (father), 116, 117 Seriality, 45, 81, 82, 121
One and many, 16, 21, 24, 25, 34, 57, 62, Space: and body, 34 –36, 37, 39, 40, 44 –
68–69, 81, 85, 124, 137 45, 54, 117, 130; in physics, 20–21,
164 INDEX