NELSON, Cary & GROSSBERG, Lawrence (Ed.) - Marxism and The Interpretation of Culture
NELSON, Cary & GROSSBERG, Lawrence (Ed.) - Marxism and The Interpretation of Culture
NELSON, Cary & GROSSBERG, Lawrence (Ed.) - Marxism and The Interpretation of Culture
PAUL WALTON
COMMUNICATIONS AND CULTURE
Executive Editors STUART HALL, PAUL WALTON
Published
Tony Bennett and Janet WoollacottBOND AND BEYOND: THE
POLITICAL CAREER OF A POPULAR HERO
Victor Burgin (ed.) THINKING PHOTOGRAPHY
Victor Burgin THE END OF ART THEORY: CRITICISM AND
POSTMODERNITY
lain Chambers URBAN RHYTHMS: POP MUSIC AND POPULAR
CULTURE
Andrew Davies OTHER THEATRES: THE DEVELOPMENT OF
ALTERNATIVE AND EXPERIMENTAL THEATRE IN BRITAIN
Erving Goffman GENDER ADVERTISEMENTS
Stephen Heath QUESTIONS OF CINEMA
Herbert Marcuse THE AESTHETIC DIMENSION: TOWARDS A
CRITIQUE OF MARXIST AESTHETICS
Cary Nelson and Lawrence Grossberg MARXISM AND THE
INTERPRETATION OF CULTURE
John Tulloch and Manuel Alvarado'DOCTOR WHo': THE
UNFOLDING TEXT
Janet Wolff THE SOCIAL PRODUCTION OF ART
Forthcoming
Jerry Booth and Peter Lewis RADIO: MEANINGS AND
AUDIENCES
Philip Corrigan CULTURE AND CONTROL
James Donald (ed.) CULTURAL ANALYSIS: PSYCHOANALYSIS
AND CULTURAL THEORY
Stuart Hall REPRODUCING IDEOLOGIES
Dick Hebdige THE MEANING OF SUBCULTURES
Claire Johnston FEMINISM AND CINEMA
Simon Jones: BLACK CULTURE, WHITE YOUTH
John Tagg THE BURDEN OF REPRESENTATION
Peter Widdowson (ed.) CONSUMING FICTIONS? POPULAR
LITERATURE TODAY
Marxism and the
Interpretation of Culture
Edited and with an Introduction by
CARY NELSON and LAWRENCE GROSSBERG
M
MACMILLAN
EDUCATION
© Board of Trustees of the University of Illinois 1988
All rights reserved. No reproduction, copy or transmission
of this publication may be made without written permission.
No paragraph of this publication may be reproduced, copied
or transmitted save with written permission or in accordance
with the provisions of the Copyright Act 1956 (as amended),
or under the terms of any licence permitting limited copying
issued by the Copyright Licensing Agency, 7 Ridgmount Street,
London WClE 7AE.
Any person who does any unauthorised act in relation to
this publication may be liable to criminal prosecution and
civil claims for damages.
Published by
MACMILLAN EDUCATION LTD
Houndmills, Basingstoke, Hampshire RG21 2XS
and London
Companies and representatives
throughout the world
Preface, ix
Cornel West
Marxist Theory and the Specificity of Afro-American Oppression, 17
Discussion, 30
Stuart Hall
The Toad in the Garden: Thatcherism among the Theorists, 35
Discussion, 58
Henri Lefebvre
Toward a Leftist Cultural Politics: Remarks Occasioned by the
Centenary of Marx's Death, 75
Chantal Mouffe
Hegemony and New Political Subjects: Toward a New Concept of
Democracy, 89
Discussion, 102
Catharine A. MacKinnon
Desire and Power: A Feminist Perspective, 105
Discussion, 117
Paul Patton
Marxism and Beyond: Strategies of Reterritorialization, 123
Discussion, 137
A. Belden Fields
In Defense of Political Economy and Systemic Analysis: A Critique of
Prevailing Theoretical Approaches to the New Social
Movements, 141
Etienne Balibar
The Vacillation of Ideology, 159
Oskar Negt
What Is a Revival of Marxism and Why Do We Need One Today?:
Centennial Lecture Commemorating the Death of Karl Marx, 211
Gajo Petrovic
Philosophy and Revolution: Twenty Sheaves of Questions, 235
v
Ernesto Laclau
Metaphor and Social Antagonisms, 249
Christine Delphy
Patriarchy, Domestic Mode of Production, Gender, and Class, 259
Discussion, 268
Perry Anderson
Modernity and Revolution, 317
Discussion, 334
Franco Moretti
The Spell of Indecision, 339
Discussion, 345
Fredric Jameson
Cognitive Mapping, 347
Discussion, 358
Andrew Ross
The New Sentence and the Commodity Form: Recent American
Writing, 361
Fred Pfeil
Postmodernism as a "Structure of Feeling," 381
Eugene Holland
Schizoanalysis: The Postmodern Contextualization of
Psychoanalysis, 405
Julia Lesage
Women's Rage, 419
Michele Mattelart
Can Industrial Culture Be a Culture of Difference?: A Reflection on
France's Confrontation with the U.S. Model of Serialized Cultural
Production, 429
Simon Frith
Art Ideology and Pop Practice, 461
Michael Ryan
The Politics of Film: Discourse, Psychoanalysis, Ideology, 477
vi
Jack L. Amariglio, Stephen A. Resnick, and Richard D. Wolff
Class, Power, and Culture, 487
Jean Franco
Beyond Ethnocentrism: Gender, Power, and the Third-World
Intelligentsia, 503
Stanley Aronowitz
The Production of Scientific Knowledge: Science, Ideology, and
Marxism, 519
Discussion, 538
Sue Golding
The Concept of the Philosophy of Praxis in the Ouaderni of Antonio
Gramsci, 543
Richard Schacht
Marxism, Normative Theory, and Alienation, 565
Armand Mattelart
Communications in Socialist France: The Difficulty of Matching
Technology with Democracy, 581
lain Chambers
Contamination, Coincidence, and Collusion: Pop Music, Urban
Culture, and the Avant-Garde, 607
Discussion, 612
Terry Eagleton
The Critic as Clown, 619
Michel P~cheux
Discourse: Structure or Event?, 633
Hugo Achugar
The Book of Poems as a Social Act: Notes toward an Interpretation of
Contemporary Hispanic American Poetry, 651
Darko Suvin
Can People Be (Re)Presented in Fiction?: Toward a Theory of
Narrative Agents and a Materialist Critique beyond Technology or
Reductionism, 663
vii
Michele Barrett
The Place of Aesthetics in Marxist Criticism, 697
Fengzhen Wang
Marxist Literary Criticism in China, 715
Index, 733
viii
Preface
Marxism and the Interpretation of Culture grew out
of a series of events organized by the Unit for Criticism and Interpretive
Theory at the University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign in the summer
of 1983: a group of courses taught by several of the contributors (An-
derson, Fields, Grossberg, Hall, Jameson, Lesage, Petrovic, Schacht, Spi-
vak) were attended by several hundred faculty members and students;
the Marxist Literary Group held its annual meeting; and the summer cul-
minated in a large international conference. For many of those who at-
tended the conference, therefore, it was very much a culmination and
working out of discussions and disputes that had not only a long prior
history but also a very specific and extended interactive history that sum-
mer. During the following two years most of the papers were very heavily
revised, in part as a result of the challenge of the whole summer's events.
Several additional essays were solicited from people who were invited
but could not attend the conference, and a few people who attended the
conference but did not present papers submitted essays on their own.
We have retained from the conference itself only
those commentaries and discussion sessions that suggest substantive
critiques of a position, develop significantly the central issues of a par-
ticular essay, or provide interesting contrasts among positions. We have
included the names of people asking questions or offering comments
whenever they were willing to be identified; and we have cooperated
with those who preferred to remain anonymous. We have also tried to
follow people's wishes about such matters as whether or not to capitalize
"Marxism." Finally, we should note that the editors assisted with the
translation of the essays by Achugar, Balibar, Lefebvre, Mouffe, Negt,
and Wang.
Neither the conference nor the book would have been
possible without the help of a great many people. For advice, continuing
assistance, and the benefit of their experience we give special thanks to
Daniel Alpert, Nina Baym, David Bright, Theodore Brown, David Colley,
Judith Edelstein, William Fierke, Joel Hersig, Roger Martin, Mark Netter,
Gary North, William Plater, William Prokasy, Edward Sullivan, Patricia
Wenzel, Richard Wentworth, and Linda Wilson. Jefferson Hendricks
helped coordinate the conference, and many people worked long hours
during it: Roberta Astroff, Steve Ater, Van Cagle, Meredith Cargill, Sri-
ankle Chang, K. C. Chen, Karen Cole, Jon Crane, John Duvall, Michael
Greer, William May, Nelly Mitchell, Lisa Odell, Steve Olsen, David Riefman,
Mary Robinson, Phillip Sellers, and Tim Vere. James Kavanaugh provided
helpful advice on the Balibar translation. Karen Ford, Michael Greer, Mar-
sha Bryant, Teresa Magnum, Gail Rost, and Anne Balsamo assisted us
in assembling the final manuscript. The book was copyedited by Theresa
L. Sears. Financial support within the University of Illinois at Urbana-
Champaign came from the School of Humanities, the College of Liberal
Arts and Sciences, the College of Communications, the Research Board,
the George A. Miller Endowment Fund, International Programs and Ser-
vices, the Office for Women's Resources and Services, the School of
Social Sciences, the Center for Latin American and Caribbean Studies,
the University Library, the Institute of Communications Research, theRe-
ix
ligious Studies Program, and the Departments of Anthropology, English,
French, Germanic Languages and Literatures, History, Philosophy, Polit-
ical Science, Sociology, and Speech Communication; external support
came from the National Endowment for the Humanities. The book was
designed by David Colley.
X
Lawrence Grossberg and Cary Nelson
Notes
For example. Berel Lang and Forrest Williams. eds .• Marxism and Art (New York: David
McKay Co .. 1972); Maynard Solomon. ed .. Marxism and Art: Essays Classic and Contem-
porary (New York: Alfred A Knopf. 1973); and David Craig. ed .. Marxists on Literature: An
Anthology (Harmondsworth: Penguin Books. 1975).
2 Karl Marx and Frederick Engels. On Literature and Art. ed. Lee Baxandall and Stefan Morawski
(New York: International General. 1974).
12
Grossberg and Nelson
3 See David Laing, The Marxist Theory of Art. An Historical Survey (Atlantic Highlands. N.J.:
Humanities Press. 1978). For further discussions. see Mikhail Lifshitz. The Philosophy of Art
of Karl Marx. trans. Ralph B. Winn (New York: The Critics Group, 1938; reprinted, London:
Pluto Press. 1973); Henri Arvon. Marxist Esthetics. trans. Helen Lane (Ithaca: Cornell Uni-
versity Press. 1973). For overviews of the development of Western Marxism. see Perry
Anderson. Considerations on Western Marxism (London: New Left Books. 1976); New Left
Review. ed .. Western Marxism-A Critical Reader (London: New Left Books. 1977); and
Dick Howard and Karl E. Klare. eds .. The Unknown Dimension: European Marx1sm smce
Lenin (New York: Basic Books. 1972).
4 See, for example. Christopher Caudwell, Illusion and Reality: A Study of the Sources of Poetry
( 1937; New York: New World. 1963); Ernst Fischer. The Necessity of Art: A Marxist Ap-
proach, trans. Anna Bostock (Baltimore: Penguin Books. 1963); and Georg1 Plekhanov, Art
and Social Life. trans. E. Fox and E. Hartley (Moscow: Progress Publishers. 1957).
5 Antonio Gramsc1. Selections from the Prison Notebooks. ed. and trans. Ou1nt1n Hoare and
Geoffrey Nowell Sm1th (New York: International Publishers. 1971).
6 Georg Lukacs. History and Class Consciousness: Studies in Marxist Dialectics. trans. Rodney
Livingstone (Cambridge: MIT Press. 1971).
7 Karl Korsch, Marxism and Philosophy, trans. Fred Halliday (New York: Monthly Review Press.
1970); Rosa Luxemburg, Selected Political Writings, ed. Dick Howard (New York: Monthly
Rev1ew Press. 1971).
8 Ernst Bloch et al, Aesthetics and Politics (London: New Left Books. 1977).
9 Many of the developments in Western Marxism built on ideas that only became available
with the eventual translation of The Economic and Philosophic Manuscripts of 1844. first
published in German in 1932. See Karl Marx. Early Writings, ed. and trans. Tom B. Bottomore
(London: Penguin, 1963).
10 See. for example. Georg Lukacs. The Historical Novel, trans. H. and S. Mitchell (Boston:
Beacon Press. 1963). and Studies in European Realism. trans. Edith Bone (New York: Grosset
and Dunlap, 1964).
11 Ernest Mandel. Late Capitalism. trans. Joris De Bres (London: New Left Books. 1975).
12 Max Horkheimer and Theodor W. Adorno. Dialectic of Enlightenment. trans. John Cumming
(New York: Herder and Herder. 1972). See also Andrew Arata and Eike Gebhardt, eds .. The
Essential Frankfurt School Reader (New York: Urizen Books. 1978).
13 Bertolt Brecht. Brecht on Theatre. The Development of an Aesthetic, ed. and trans. John
Willett (London: Methuen, 1964); Walter Benjamin. Illuminations: Essays and Reflections.
ed. Hannah Arendt (New York: Harcourt Brace and World, 1968); Henri Lefebvre. Everyday
Life in the Modern World. trans. Sacha Rabinovitch (New Brunswick. N.J.: Transaction. 1984);
Gramsci, Selections from the Prison Notebooks.
14 Jean-Paul Sartre, Critique of Dialectical Reason. trans. Alan Shendan-Sm1th (London: New
Left Books, 1976); John Berger, Ways of Seeing (Baltimore: Penguin Books. 1972); Raymond
Williams. The Long Revolution (London: Chatto and Windus. 1961); E. P Thompson. The
Making of the English Working Class (New York: Random House. 1963); GaJO Petrovic. Marx
in the Mid-Twentieth Century (Garden City, N.Y.: Anchor Books. 1967).
15 Ferdinand de Saussure. Course in General Linguistics. trans. Roy Harris (La Salle. Ill: Open
Court. 1986).
16 Louis Althusser, For Marx. trans. Ben Brewster (New York: Vintage Books. 1970).
17 Michel Foucault, ·'Prison Talk.·· in Power/Knowledge: Selected Interviews and Other Wntings.
1972-1977. ed. Colin Gordon (New York: Pantheon Books. 1980). p. 52
13
I Rethinl<ing the Crisis in Marxism
Cornel West
And on the other hand, Linda Burnham and Bob Wing wrote in Line of
March,
Notes
1 In this definition. "materiality" simply denotes the multiple functions of power of racist prac-
tices over Africans; by "logics" I mean the battery of tropes. metaphors. notions. and con-
cepts employed to justify and legitimate white supremacist practices. This racial problematic
is related to but not identical with other possible investigative frameworks that focus on racist
practices toward other peoples of color. I do believe this problematic is useful for such
endeavors. yet I deliberately confine my major focus to peoples of African descent, especially
Afro-Americans. Also, this problematic does not presuppose that a nostalgic undifferentiated
umty or homogeneous universality will someday emerge among black, white, red, yellow,
and brown peoples. Rather, it assumes the irreducibility of racial (that is. cultural) differences.
The task is not to erase such differences but rather to ensure that such differences are not
employed as grounds for buttressing hierarchical social relations and symbolic orders.
2 The major texts I have in mind of these two prolific and profound thinkers are Michel Foucault.
Discipline and Punish: The Birth of the Prison. trans. Alan Sheridan (New York: Vintage,
1979); and Jacques Derrida, Of Grammatology, trans. Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak (Baltimore:
Johns Hopkins University Press. 1976). For a brilliant critique and contrast of these two texts,
see Edward W. Said, The World, the Text. and the Critic (Cambridge: Harvard University
Press. 1983). pp. 118-225.
3 My political stance is autonomistic in that it is existentially anchored not simply in responses
to class exploitation but more immediately in cultural degradation and political oppression-
as is the National Black United Front led by Rev. Herbert Daughtry. Yet this autonomistic
stance does not slide into mere micropolitics because it envisions and encourages links with
those movements based primarily on class exploitation. My political stance is prefigurative
in that it is. in principle, motivated by the fundamental transformation of U.S. capitalist civ-
ilization and manifested in working within an organization (the Democratic Socialists of Amer-
ica) whose moral aspirations and internal mechanisms prefigure the desirable socialist so-
Ciety-one that is radically democratic and libertarian. This prefigurative stance does not
degenerate into reformism because. following Rosa Luxemburg's formulations in Reform or
Revolution ( 1900). it supports reforms yet opposes illusions about reforms.
4 Eugene Debs, "The Negro in the Class Struggle" and "The Negro and His Nemesis,"
International Socialist Review, Nov. 1903, Jan. 1904.
5 Quoted from PhilipS Foner. American Socialism and Black Americans (Westport, Conn.:
Greenwood Press. 1977) For a noteworthy response to Debs's disappearance thesis. see
Manning Marable, "The Third Reconstruction: Black Nationalism and Race Relations after
the Revolution," Blackwater: Historical Studies in Race. Class Consciousness and Revolution
(Dayton. Ohio: Black Praxis Press. 1981 ). pp. 187-208. For the major work of this important
Afro-Amencan Marxist figure. see How Capitalism Underdeveloped Black America: Problems
in Race, Political Economy and Society (Boston: South End Press, 1983).
6 George Breitman. "On the Negro Struggle, etc.," Socialist Workers Party Discussion Bulletin,
Sept. 1954; Bolshevik League, Liberation for the Black Nation (Bronx. 1983); Nelson Peery,
The Negro National Colonial Question (Chicago: Workers Press, 1978); Revolutionary Union,
National Liberation and Proletarian Revolution in the United States (Chicago, 1972); Amiri
Baraka, "Black Liberation and the Question of Nationality," Unity, 4:12 (1981). p. 6; Amiri
Baraka. ··Black Struggle in the 80's.·· The Black Nation: Journal of Afro-American Thought.
1: 1 ( 1981). pp. 2-5; Philadelphia Workers' Organizing Committee. Black Liberation Today:
Against Dogmatism on the National Question (Philadelphia, 1975); James Forman. Self-
Determination and the African-American People (Seattle: Open Hand Publishing, 1981). To
put it crudely, Breitman argues that Afro-Americans in the Umted States constitute an "em-
bryonic nation"; Peery holds the "Negro Nation" to be a colony; Bob Avakian's Revolutionary
Communist party claims that dispersed black communities constitute a "proletarian nation"
of a new sort; Baraka. the Bolshevik League. and Forman argue for a Black Nation in the
Black Belt South of the United States; and the Philadelphia Workers' Organizing Committee
holds that there once was a Black Nation, but it dissolved in the fifties with vast industriali-
zation. proletarianization. and urbanization of Afro-Americans.
7 Joseph V. Stalin, Marxism and the National Question (Moscow: Foreign Language Publishing
House. 1954). p. 16.
8 This almost inescapable Gramscian perspective-the nearly unavoidable theoretical and prac-
26
Cornel West
tical confrontation with the problem of culture-has been a major preoccupation of the leading
Marx1st figures in develop1ng nat1ons. For brief samples of original third-world contributions
to Marxist theory. see Mao Tse-tung, "Report on an Investigation of the Peasant Movement
in Hunan." Selected Works, vol. 1 (Peking: Foreign Language Press. 1966). pp. 23-59; "On
the Correct Handling of Contradictions among the People." Four Essays on Philosophy (Pe-
king: Foreign Language Press, 1968), pp. 79-133. See also Jose Carlos Mariategu1, "People
and Myth," The Morning Spirit ( 1925); and "The Religious Factor," Seven Essays of Inter-
pretation of the Peruv1an Reality ( 1927). Unfortunately, most of Mariategui's works have not
yet been translated into English. For noteworthy treatments of his thought and praxis, see
Geraldine Skinner, "Jose Carlos Mariategu1 and the Emergence of the Peruv1an Socialist
Movement." Sc1ence and Society, 43:4 ( 1979-80). pp. 447-71; and Jesus Chavarria, Jose
Carlos Mariategui and the Rise of Modern Peru (Albuquerque: University of New Mexico
Press. 1979). See also Kwame Nkrumah, Consciencisrn: Philosophy and Ideology for De-
colomzatlon (New York: Monthly Review Press. 1970); Frantz Fanon. The Wretched of the
Earth. trans. Constance Farnngton (New York: Grove Press. 1964); Am1lcar Cabral, "Pre-
suppositions and Objectives of National Liberation in Relation to Soc1al Structure" and "Na-
tional LiberatiOn and Culture,·· Unity and Struggle: Speeches and Writmgs of Ami/car Cabral.
trans. M1chael Wolters (New York: Monthly Rev1ew Press, 1979). pp. 119-37. 138-54.
9 For the most thorough and convincing critique of the Black Nation Thesis, see Linda Burnham
and Bob Wing, "Toward a Communist Analysis of Black Oppression and Black Uberat1on.
Part 1: Crit1que of the Black Nation Thesis," Lme of March: A Marxist-Leninist Journal of
Rectification, 2: 1 ( 1981). pp. 21-88.
10 R. S Fraser. "For the Matenalist Conception of the Negro Struggle." 1n What Strategy for
Black Liberation? Trotskyism vs. Black National1sm, Marxist Bulletm 5, rev. ed .. The Spartac1st
League, pp. 3, 16, reprinted from Socialist Workers Party Discuss1on Bulletm, A-30 ( 1955).
11 Linda Burnham and Bob Wing, "Toward a Communist Analys1s of Black Oppression and
Black LiberatiOn, Part II: Theoretical and Histoncai Framework," Line of March. A Marxist-
Leninist Journal of RectificatiOn, 8 ( 1981). p. 48.
12 For the recent pronouncements of the Afro-American freedom struggle by the Communist
party of the United States, see Henry Winston, Class, Race and Black Liberation (New York:
International Publishers, 1977). and the resolution on the Afro-American struggle-Wmston's
Struggle for Afro-American Liberation-adopted by the party's Twenty-second National Con-
vention in August 1979. See also Oliver C. Cox, Caste, Class, and Race: A Study in Social
Dynam1cs (New York: Doubleday, 1948); James A. Geschwender. Class, Race and Worker
Insurgency: The League of Revolutionary Black Workers (Cambndge: Cambridge Umversity
Press, 1977); Mario Barrera. Race and Class in the Southwest: A Theory of Racial Inequality
(Notre Dame: Un1versity Press of Notre Dame, 1979). Although Barrera IS primarily concerned
w1th the rac1al problematic as it relates to Chicanos and Ch1canas. his theoretical formulations
are relevant to peoples of African descent 1n the Un1ted States of Amenca.
13 William Julius Wilson, The Declining Significance of Race: Blacks and Changing Amencan
Institutions (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1978); Thomas Sowell. Race and Eco-
nomics (New York: David McKay Co., 1975); Martin K1lson, "The Black Bourgeo1s1e Revisited:
From E. Franklin Frazier to the Present," Dissent (Winter 1983), pp. 85-96. This latter essay
is from Kilson's forthcoming book. Neither Insiders nor Outsiders: Blacks in American Society.
14 Stanley Aronowitz, The Cnsis in Historical Materialism: Class, Politics, and Culture in Marxist
Theory(New York: Praeger Publications, 1981). pp. 89-112.
15 These distinctions are necessary if we are to sharpen and refine the prevailing loose usage
of domination, subjugation, exploitation. repression, and oppression. In my view. domination
and subjugation are discursive affa1rs; the former relates to rac1al. sexual, ethnic, or national
supremacist logics, whereas the latter mvolves the production of subjects and subjectiv1t1es
within such logics. Exploitation and repression are extradiscursive affairs in that they result
from social formations and Institutions such as modes of production and state apparatuses.
Dom1nation. subjugation, exploitation. and repression constitute modes of oppression, wh1ch
are distinguished for analytic purposes. Needless to say, they relate to each other in complex
and concrete ways. These distinctions were prompted by Michel Foucault. "The Subject
and Power," Criticallnqwry, 8:4 (1982). pp. 775-95.
16 Wmthrop Jordan. White Over Black.· Amencan Attitudes toward the Negro. 1550-1812 (New
York: Norton, 1968). pp. 18-20, 36; Thomas F. Gossett, Race. The History of an Idea in
Amenca (Dallas: Southern Methodist University Press. 1965). pp. 3-31.
17 For a further e'laboration of this logic. see Cornel West. "A Genealogy of Modern Racism,"
Prophesy Deliverance! An Afro-Amencan Revolutionary Chnstlamty (Philadelphia: Westmins-
ter Press. 1982). pp. 47-65. And for the metaphilosophical motivation for th1s inquiry, see
Cornel West, "Philosophy, Politics and Power: An Afro-American Perspective," in Philosophy
Born of Struggle: Anthology of Afro-Amencan Philosophy from 1917, ed. Leonard Harns
(Dubuque Kendall/Hunt Publishing Co .. 1983). pp. 51-59.
27
18 The best exposition of this logic rema1ns Joel Kovel's White Rac1sm A Psychoh1story (New
York: Pantheon. 1970). For an mteresting. yet less theoretical. treatment. see Calvin C.
Hernton. Sex and Rac1sm in America (New York: Grove Press. 1965).
19 Jacques Derrida, Pos1t10ns. trans. Alan Bass (Chicago: Univers1ty of Chicago Press. 1981).
p. 51.
20 Primarily owing to parochial secular sens1b1lities. black and wh1te Marxist thinkers-with ex-
ceptions such as Eugene Genovese in h1s magnum opus Roll. Jordan. Roll: The World the
Slaves Made (New York: Random House. 1974). pp. 159-284. and Orlando Patterson's
masterful Slavery and SoCJal Death.· A ComparatiVe Study (Cambndge: Harvard University
Press. 1982). pp. 66-76-have overlooked the tremendous 1mpact of evangelical Protes-
tantism on Afro-Americans in the United States. and espec1ally the subtle ways in which
Afro-Americans have employed the1r appropriation of this Protestantism for counterhege-
moniC a1ms. The major legacy of this appropnat1on is that present-day Afro-American re-
sistance rema1ns under the auspices of the small. yet quite visible. prophetic wing of the
black church. as exemplified by Rev. Herbert Daughtry's cha1rmansh1p of the leftist National
Black Un1ted Front and the Afncan People's Christian Organ1zation. by Rev. Joseph Lowery's
presidency of the left-liberal Southern Christian Leadership Conference (founded by Rev.
Martm Luther King, Jr.). by Rev. Benjamin Hooks's executive directorship of the liberal National
Association for the Advancement of Colored People. and by Rev. Jesse Jackson's leadership
of the l1beral People United to Save Humanity. It is no historical. political. and existential
acc1dent that. as an oppos1t1onal African Intellectual and activist in the United States. I teach
in a Protestant seminary and wnte as an Afro-American neo-Gramscian Christian! For four
noteworthy texts on the rel1g1ous dimension of the rac1al problematiC 1n the Un1ted States.
see Albert Raboteau's superb Slave Religion: The "Invisible Institution" in the Antebellum
South (New York: Oxford University Press. 1978); James Cone and Gayraud Wilmore's
1nd1spensable Black Theology: A Documentary History, 1966-19 79 (Maryknoll. N.Y.: Orb is
Books. 1979); my own provocative work. Prophesy Deliverance! An Afro-American Revo-
lutionary Chnstiamty (Philadelphia: Westminster Press. 1982); and James Washington's bril-
liant hundred-page mtroduct1on to Afro-American Protestant Spirituality (New York: Paul1st
Press. 1984).
21 The seductive powers of Foucault must be resisted by leftist thinkers on two fronts: the trap
of discurs1ve reductionism. wh1ch posits the absolute (as opposed to relative) autonomy of
discursive practices. and the trap of full-blown (as opposed to provisional) antitotalism. which
promotes revolt yet precludes revolution. The Marxist path that incorporates Foucault's in-
sights has been blazed by the grand p1oneer of cultural studies, Stuart Hall. See espec1ally
h1s "Cultural Studies Two Paradigms." Media. Culture and Society. 2(1980). pp 57-72.
and "The Rediscovery of 'Ideology': Return of the Repressed in Media Studies," in Culture,
Society and the Media. ed. M1chael Gurevitch, Tony Bennett. James Curran. and Janet
Woollacott (New York: Methuen. 1982). pp. 56-90. For subtle elaborations of this per-
spective on untouched frontiers, see Hazel V. Carby, "Schooling 1n Babylon" and "White
Woman Listen! Black Femin1sm and the Boundanes of Sisterhood." in The Empire Strikes
Back: Race and Racism in 70s Britain, Center for Contemporary Cultural Studies (London:
Hutchinson. 1982). pp. 183-211. 212-35.
22 Antonio Gramsci. Selections from the Prison Notebooks, ed. and trans. Quintin Hoare and
Geoffrey Nowell Sm1th (New York: International Publishers, 1971 ). p. 407. For his formu-
lations of a "histoncal bloc," note pp. 136ff.. 365-66. For a useful treatment of thiS complex
issue of the relation of base and superstructure. see Raymond Williams, Marxism and Lit-
erature (New York: Oxford University Press. 1977). pp. 75-89.
23 The best theoret1cal formulation I know of this Gramscian metaphor is found in Bob Jessop's
superb work The Cap1tal1st State: Marxist Theories and Methods (New York: New York Uni-
versity Press. 1982). pp. 211-59.
24 Ernesto Laclau, "The Impossibility of Soc1ety," Canadian Journal of Political and Social The-
ory. 7 12 (1983). pp. 21-24.
25 I cons1der the onginary text of poststructuralism to be Gilles Deleuze's Nietzsche and Phi-
losophy, published m 1962 and translated into English in 1983. This provocative and often
persuasive attack on Hegel and dialectics from a Nietzschean v1ewpoint initiated and legiti-
mated the now fam1liar poststructuralist assaults on totalizmg frameworks. teleological nar-
ratives, homogeneous continUities in history. and recuperative. nostalgic strategies in inter-
pretation. The rejection of ontology left Marx1sts with no grounds for theorizing. given their
rel1ance on Hegel1an d1alect1cs. Smce I agree with this rejection. the theoretical cris1s of
Marx1sm is, I bel1eve, a serious one. Aronowitz's call-influenced by Adorno's philosophy of
difference and Murray Bookchin ·s ecolog1cal perspective-for a new will to totality guided by
1deals of workers' self-management. sexual and racial freedom, and the liberation of nature
is noteworthy. as IS Deleuze's and Guatarn's call-mediated by Spinoza and Nietzsche-for
theoret1cal nomadism guided by a political metaphysics of desire. Both call for a new Marxist
or matenalist ethics. yet neither 1s forthcoming. The major alternative is to opt for a pragmatic
v1ewpomt (1nformed by the work of Richard Rorty, Richard Bernstein. and others) in which
28
Cornel West
dialectical modes of thinking become rhetorical strategies employed in intellectual, social,
and existential warfare against dogmatic ways of thought, forms of oppression. and modes
of despair. Such rhetorical Marxism or dialectical pragmatism (to use Max Eastman's term)
preserves historically constituted human agency. accents the multileveled character of
oppression. and demystifies poststructuralist strategies by circumscribing and thereby tri-
vializing the radical skepticism that sustain them while accepting their powerful insights re-
garding the role of otherness and alterity in philosophies of identity, including most forms of
dialectical thinking. Since energizing emancipatory visions are. to put it bluntly, religious
visions. I see little alternative other than appropriating the subversive potential of Christianity
and other religions.
29
Discussion
Comment
Despite your efforts to escape logocentrism, you maintain
the logocentric duality of black and white to describe the structure of a nation that
is, on the contrary, clearly based on multiple dominations. To make the question
of Afro-American problems central to Marxism may, for example, be to ignore
Latinos and Indians. Though you acknowledge that we are sometimes dealing with
quite specific subgroups, say Caribbean blacks, I wonder if there still may not be a
problem in your project.
West
I believe there is a specificity to the various forms of the
African experience that is distinct from that of other peoples of color. I was speaking
to just that highly limited but crucial specificity. Of course, I do not want to reenact
the very exclusion I would criticize in the dominant culture, and I do believe my
framework could (and should) be enriched by analyses of the situations of other
peoples of color. But it is important not to move too quickly to speak about a broad
spectrum of peoples of color. On the other hand, you can't talk solely about specific
oppressions without understanding the relations between the different oppressions
of Latinos, Asians, indigenous peoples, etc. For example, in a discourse against
slavery, one needs to distinguish between the oppression of indigenous peoples and
the oppression of Africans. Finally, we need to recognize that oppression is mani-
fested in different forms of discursive power.
Question
Many of us have started to study the history of black and
white Hispanic people since they came to America. We have found that they begin
a system of stratification that ironically replicates the existing black and white duality.
When I ask black Latinos whether they are light or dark, most of them say they are
light. It seems that every measure of color one takes on is simply a bourgeois tool
of self-identification. If you study kinship structures and marital selection, you see
again a stratification system inside the Latino community in which patterns of race
relations around black and white begin to replicate themselves. How does one ac-
knowledge the specific histories of these peoples while accounting for what is ob-
viously a general structure for the reproduction of racial difference?
West
Understanding the function of racial differences raises the
theoretical issue of the very play of difference itself. I do not have any Hegelian
nostalgia for undifferentiated unities now or in the future. We are in a world of
differences forever. That means we are talking about the irreducibility of differences
in the racial sphere. Yet, historically, racial differences are always constituted as
"scientific" by ideological discourses. I cannot envision, within the logics of the
modem West, with its legacy of slavery, societies that do not have racial differences.
Consequently, our social emancipatory visions and projects have to acknowledge
the irreducibility of racial differences but fight against a translation of such differences
into hierarchical social relations and symbolic orders. So we will not get beyond the
play of differences and binary oppositions. The question is how we arrest the political
and economic translation of such differences into hierarchical relations. That, to me,
is the problematic. And I would say similar things about sexuality. I do not see an
eschatological possibility of erasing these differences. To give an example: Frank
Snowden's work on black antiquity suggests that if we could only get back to the
way the Greeks interacted with the Ethiopians (when Heraclitis talked about how
beautiful black women were), then we could get beyond these black/white prejudices.
I can understand his motivations, but I think that is precisely the kind of nostalgia
that must be resisted.
30
Cornel West
Question (Stanley Aronowitz)
Two recent texts suggest very different models of oppression
and exploitation. Each proposes a mode of determination and makes a universal
claim for it, which seems to contradict your strong bias toward historical specificity.
In Slavery and Social Death, Orlando Patterson argues that the transhistorical de-
velopment of slavery is based on the existence of a form of social domination that
produces a category of otherness within the symbolic order. This form of social
domination precedes economic exploitation and the labor process. This proposal
almost turns Marxism on its head but still maintains the methodology of a primary
contradiction (as Mao says). Class and race mediate this category of social domi-
nation; they are mechanisms by which the deratiocination process takes place. The
second text is Barrington Moore's. Moore argues that there is no possibility for
oppression to take place without consent. Thus the basis of revolt, if not revolution,
is not a struggle against oppression and exploitation but the breaking of the contract
between the oppressed and the oppressor, a contract fundamentally based on caste
considerations. As long as people have a "contractual" place in the symbolic, social,
and economic order, they are likely to reproduce their conditions of subordination.
Can you comment on these two positions?
West
First, in regard to Patterson: his notion of modal alienation,
in which a people born with no rights to predecessors (without a past) and with no
right to progeny (without a future), is part of a discourse in which black people have
no social ontology. Patterson is very ambiguous about the status of this view. If he
believes this form of alienation is prior to social processes, then I think his position
is unintelligible. If, however, he wants merely to accent the weight of that moment
of alienation, then I am with him all the way. So for me the question is how modal
alienation interacts with the various logics I have been talking about. Indeed, I think
that is the direction Patterson himself takes. Patterson invokes Marx in arguing that
slavery is a relation of domination. So Patterson views this as part of the Marxist
project, and Perry Anderson and company published his essay in New Left Review.
Second, what Barrington Moore is attempting to get at is
already clearly articulated by Ernest Becker: the relation between hegemony-the
mobilization and reproduction of the consent of the oppressed to their domination,
subjugation, exploitation, and repression-and the need for cosmic recognition, the
horror of death. How are these issues manipulated, not in any crude sense by a
ruling class, but so as to inscribe them within various modes of socialization which
ensure that human beings consent to their domination? Unfortunately, Becker sees
the horror of death in terms of Otto Rank's view of immortality-the need not to
go in and out of this thing we call life without some kind of recognition, even if it's
in a hierarchical order. But that's only one of its dimensions.
Question
Stanley suggested one way that an ontological category of
otherness precedes social processes and structures oppression. Obviously feminism
could say the same for the oppression of women by way of an already given category
of otherness. Could you give us an example, within the contemporary black liberation
movement, of how this needs instead to be read in terms of its precise historicity?
West
On a general level, I want to begin by saying that black
feminists like Audre Lorde and others are the major figures that both the black Left
and the American Left in general must come to terms with. Now I'll cite a specific
historical context in answer to your question: consider the central role of the black
church in black liberation. It is a radically patriarchal institution, even though its
membership is 70 percent black women. Thus, the black feminist movement must
in many ways be antichurch. Yet within the church itself there are black feminists
who are struggling with the history of the doctrine and the various liberation theo-
31
logies that come out of it. Nonetheless, this very specific history, with black men in
leadership roles, provides many possibilities for polarization. It isn't simply that
black men are in conflict with black women but that their relations are mediated
by various institutions. So the issue of feminism within black liberation is always
already traversed by class, by race, and by the institution of the black church. It's
crisscrossed by class fractions as well. There is no doubt, for example, that gay life-
styles will be much more acceptable among a black petit-bourgeois strata, because
they interact with the larger culture and are not as affected by the patriarchal sen-
sibilities of the black church. Yet most of these folks come out of the church, if not
in one generation then two, so there are still internal struggles going on.
Question
I'd like to know your views on the growing struggle in South
Africa. Can it be a mobilizing force for blacks in America?
West
I think that South Africa will continue to serve, in many
ways, as a symbol of evil. It represents a massive concentration of white supremacist
logic, inscribing this logic in institutions across the social spectrum. And it is no
accident that the ruling classes in late-capitalist European societies repress infor-
mation about this crypto-fascist society in the mass media. This repression will come
back with a vengeance. Yet how one goes about mobilizing resistance to South Africa
is a very difficult question. You are not only talking about the possibility of resistance
by the armed forces in South Africa, of which about 22 percent are now of African
descent; you are also talking about increasing black entrepreneurial interests in South
Africa. You are talking about the rise of a diverse black trade union movement in
South Africa that will have to define its own direction and its relation to the black
petit bourgeoisie. These are all open-ended questions. The question for us will be
whether the vocal opposition to the apartheid regime in South Africa can move
toward an anticapitalist view and not remain simply, though importantly, antiracist.
Question
I'm interested in hearing your view ofliberation theology-
what it's trying to do, how it fits into Marxist theory, and its relevance to your
project.
West
I believe it is important to understand the Christian view-
point as a particular discursive formation, one that has had tremendous impact on
people, particularly on the struggle for freedom among African peoples in the United
States. That is not to say that there are not some crucial manipulative and reactionary
elements in the black church. But if we take my neo-Gramscian framework seriously,
we have to set aside all a priori enlightenment-informed, antireligious perspectives.
We have to look at religion in very different ways, different even from that of the
so-called master (small "m" for me), Karl Marx. That is important not only for
Afro-American cases but also for understanding what is going on in Iran, in Nica-
ragua, in Chile. Although there are no acceptable nostalgic moves back to represen-
tational notions of God, God remains a very important signifying term. As Karl
Barth understood, truth is always eschatological.
Question
Are you happy and hopeful about the black movement in
this country?
West
I'm not happy with the black movement; I'm not happy with
anyplace in the world. But I'm hopeful. The grounds of my hope are very complex
because I'm a Christian and a whole lot of other things. Or at least I subscribe to
that discourse in which God is a significant signifying term. I also subscribe to
32
Cornel West
Gramsci's optimism of the will. Yet as long as you are part of the struggle, pure
hope becomes abstract because the actual historical process produces tremendous
setbacks and certain small gains.
33
Stuart Hall
Notes
Edward Thompson, The Poverty of Theory (New York: Monthly Review Press, 1978).
2 lnst1tute for Economic Affa1rs. The Emerging Consensus (London: lEA 1981 ).
3 Louis Althusser, "Notes on the ISA's," Economy and Society 12:4 (1983)
4 Michel Foucault, The Archaeology of Knowledge (New York: Pantheon. 1972). p. 45.
5 Antonio Gramsci, Prison Notebooks.· Selections, trans. Quintin Hoare and Geoffrey N. Smith
(New York: International Publishers, 1971). p. 168.
6 Gramsci, pp. 181-82.
7 Gramsci, p. 178.
8 Gramsci, p. 160.
9 Gramsci, "The Study of Philosophy," in Pnson Notebooks.
10 Gramsci, p. 195.
11 Gramsc1, p. 324.
57
Discussion
Question
You seem to imply that there is a zero-sum game of political
ideology in Britain; that the Right could only move ahead because the Left was weak.
Is this a general claim or is it particular to Great Britain at this time?
Hall
I don't want to suggest it is a zero-sum game. I want to
oppose the notion that the Right advances by, as it were, setting into place an already
formulated whole conception of the world; or that it is only through its positive
statements that it is able to become a pole of new articulations. The Right's success
depends as much on its capacity to address precisely the contradictions that are
already within the formations of the Left, to move effectively into positions of
contestation. For example, the Right picked up the actual mixed and contradictory
experience of ordinary people within the welfare state, and on the basis of that
insertion into the vocabularies of the Left began to construct the discourses of an-
tistatism. So, many positions on the Right are secured not by displacing but by
disarticulating the discourse of the Left. Of course, the reasons why those discourses
on the Left are in disrepair don't necessarily have to do with that process of con-
testation/opposition. There are a whole range of real historical tasks the Left did
not and could not resolve within the limits of the program it adhered to. The Left
in Britain is, in its own terms, very close to the end of one historical program, one
whole kind of politics. So it's not simply a zero-sum game in the sense that the Right
precipitates the crisis, but rather that the Right advances through occupying strategic
territory within the terrain of the Left.
That is, therefore, the way I want to talk about the nature
of ideological struggle. I don't think the ideological field is divided into elements of
ideological discourses that have a necessary class connotation. In societies like ours,
ideological contestation does not take place between fully formed, competing world-
views-theirs and ours. The field of ideology is not divided in that way. It's a field
in which there are many different discourses and social forces in play at the same
time. Contestation often has to do with the engagement around existing ideological
symbols and slogans, winning them away from the connotative chains of association
they have acquired, which build them into languages that seem to construct topics
so that they deliver an answer that favors one end of the political spectrum. The
language of nationhood, for example, is not a language we speak but a language that
speaks us. So, in England, if you open your mouth and say "Britain," before you
know where you are, you are off to the South Atlantic. Because there is no identity
between one class and that nation, everybody has some investment in what Britain
is about; it's their future; it's a place they live in; it has a real purchase for everyone.
Everyone has some patriotic sentiments into which particular problems or projects
can be inserted. People's social identity is going to depend on the way they negotiate
themselves in relation to the nation. Consequently, I think the ideological struggle
takes place precisely over what the nation means. What are the values associated
with it and what are the excluded values? And what is the way in which those
powerful symbols can be detached from their entanglement with one set of historical
associations and rearticulated in a different direction? Now this is not only a question
about what is happening in the field of discourse but also about the way in which
social groups, social movements, or social classes come to locate themselves inside
one or another ideological configuration-how they come to see themselves as au-
thored, addressed, hailed by those statements.
Question
You seem to place very little importance on the systematic,
coherent ideological statements, such as monetarist economics or the products of
the Centre for Policy Studies. But isn't it necessary for ideological analysis to expose
the weaknesses and contradictions in such positions?
58
Stuart Hall
Hall
It is perfectly true that much of the everyday monetarist
economics the Thatcherites speak is not very internally consistent as a theoretical
system, so theoretical economists can dismantle it in a moment. This lack of intel-
lectual rigor doesn't make Thatcherism go away, partly because it operates else-
where-in more commonsense ways, at the point where it connects with the ongoing,
more episodic and contradictory common sense of people. It is at that level that
monetarism has a kind of truth, a way of referencing the way real economic devel-
opments are constructed experientially. It has a way of placing into experience what
people feel to be the errors and problems of the past. In this way, the theory connects
with people's experience.
Remember Gramsci's argument that ideology has two do-
mains-philosophy, or theoretical ideologies, and common sense-and that the re-
lations between them are governed by politics. One has to investigate quite precisely
how more elaborated theoretical ideologies fit, often very contradictorily, into peo-
ple's actual local and immediate experience. I am therefore not arguing (as con-
servative pluralists did at a certain point) that the working class is "really" reac-
tionary. The working class isn't "essentially" any one thing; like the rest of us, it's
full of conservative feelings hiding behind a lot of radical language, and vice versa.
Popular consciousness lies at the intersection of very fragmentary, contradictory
discourses. Popular ideology is not consistent. The nature of systematic ideologies
is precisely to begin to operate on common sense and to render common sense more
consistent.
To take another example, I am interested in how grand the-
ories of sovereignty, among people who have never read a word of Jefferson or
Hobbes, nevertheless link with ideas of what is "right" about our country and where
our country stops and where its boundaries symbolically should lie. The theoretical
discourse of sovereignty sometimes clarifies popular conceptions of sovereignty, but
when people move into action it's not because they have just read the Declaration
oflndependence.lt's because some of those philosophically elaborated concepts have
connected with a deeper groundwork of emotional loyalties and moral sentiments
and bits of knowledge and so on. Symbolic identification-that is the real popular
field on which those things are sorted out. In spite of the power of the media and
of the central institutions and apparatuses of ideology, it's not possible simply to
organize and deliver popular consciousness where it has to be delivered; it has a
very complicated structure, and that is what provides for the politics of interven-
tion-finding the appropriate cracks that just can't be filled in. Sometimes, precisely
at moments of hegemony, those institutions begin to work so well on so many
different sites that you despair of ever cracking it. But there is no permanent he-
gemony, only the struggle to construct and sustain it, which never ends.
Question
Can you clarify some of the ideas in your notion of ideo-
logical struggle, in particular the relation between language and ideology and the
lack of guarantees in this relation? Is hegemony the attempt to produce such guar-
antees?
Hall
A fundamental insight of modern linguistics is that all lan-
guage is multireferential, that there isn't a one-to-one relationship between the lin-
guistic form and the object to which it intends to refer. It is, therefore, very difficult
to argue that the material conditions in which people live can generate a single set
of meanings, as if the concept of class always means just one thing. To put it another
way, the appearance of social classes in relation to language is not that one class has
ascribed to it a whole language, discontinuous from another. You can hear the
different idioms of a language-class and gender, ethnicity and group, in the way
people use the ideolects of language. But, broadly speaking, people in a single-Ian-
59
guage community can quite often understand one another across those boundaries.
So the field of language is not strictly segmented by class but is obviously more
open. Yet the semiotic systems of meaning are not, therefore, entirely disconnected
from the social or class positions in which the speakers are placed. The play of power
between different social groups is worked out within language, partly by the different
ways in which shared terms are accentuated, or the ways in which shared terms are
inserted into different discourses, as well as by different subcultural dialectics.
To give a concrete example, it's not the fact that some people
are the democrats and other people are not that is important. The real problem is
which meaning of democracy is actually in play. The struggle in this case is over
the different meanings of the same word. Different meanings will share some com-
mon characteristics but differ in their connotations. In ideology, in the kind of
struggle over languages that goes on, the struggle is to fill out the precise way in
which my "popular democracy" differs from your "liberal democracy." It's exactly
there, in the intersection of different connotations within the same linguistic sign,
that the struggle takes place. And it does matter which becomes the dominant def-
inition. It has real effects. Every time the word "democracy" is used, which of those
two associations does it trigger? So you can't exempt the domain of meaning, lan-
guage, representation from the play of social forces. But you cannnot think of it as
being chopped up and ascribed in blocks to those forces, so that there is always a
language those people speak and then there is our language. The linguistic or ide-
ological domain is not structured in that way.
In that sense I am a revisionist. I accept the critique of the
vulgar marxist theory of ideology in terms of reductionism. But I don't go so far as
to say that, therefore, there are simply disparate, fragmented discursive chains, one
after another, endlessly slipping past one another. I'm trying to think that relationship
in a way that brings them back together, but not as a simple unity or identity. One
can understand this project temporally. Marxism's temporal perspective suggests
that the connections between the people, say, and the slogans that mobilize them
are given in their class position or place in the mode of production. The same things
that formed them as a class also formed their ideology.
From my perspective, it is only when you get the right people
to speak the right language at the right time, to have the right identifications, that
you can mobilize them behind a set of concrete slogans. So the class/ideology identity
marxism assumes in the beginning is, for me, the end result, the product of politics.
Politics must construct the meanings and deliver the group to the slogans, not assume
that the group always "really" knew the slogans and always believed in them. They
didn't! It's quite possible for a class to be mobilized behind other slogans. Can one
develop a political practice that makes those slogans or those ways of defining the
word make sense to that group at the right moment? That is what gives political
practice a certain necessary openness. Somebody else might have a more effective
politics and organize the class around some other slogan; then the connections get
forged in a different way.
I no longer believe in the marxist notion of connections being
"given" in the origins of the social formation. There are points where connections
can be forged or radically transformed-hegemonic moments-where a wide variety
of people in different social positions all find that a particular set of symbols or
languages speaks their condition better than any other. This is the moment when
people who are not at all, socially, Thatcherites or from the same class origins
suddenly say, "Well, they aren't our kind of people, but she is talking a good deal
of sense!" Mrs. Thatcher makes sense, but from a universe other than our own. That
is a political moment of extraordinary complexity-when people you wouldn't think
would find answers in Thatcherism, if you simply analyzed their class position,
suddenly find her language more convincing, more resonant with their experience,
than that of the welfare state or Keynesianism. This is the critical moment, when
60
Stuart Hall
masses of people are detached from their allegiance to a particular language they
have used to frame and define their experience and reattached to another language.
I still think this is why I was right when I predicted Thatch-
er's 1979 victory. I heard large numbers of people stop talking the language of
labourism, the welfare state, social democracy, and suddenly begin talking another
language of cost effectiveness, value for money, choice, freedom, etc. I heard people
responding to a set of different ideological concepts. You couldn't explain that by
a straight class analysis. You couldn't explain the fact that the majority of them
were unionized skilled and semiskilled workers who live in traditional labor, work-
ing-class communities, who appear to be fixed in their political loyalties by all the
processes that have kept the British political system stable. Yet here was a moment
when they just walked to another position altogether.
Indeed, Thatcherism gives you a better understanding of
what the struggle for hegemony is about than almost anything one has seen in the
politics of the Left. The Thatcherites were not the natural inheritors of something;
they had to engage in ideological struggle, to contest the opposition in their own
party, to construct their own position. They had to dismantle the particular sort of
social-democratic consensus that had been in place since the war. They had to unpack
the commitment to the welfare state and unravel a whole field of ideology that people
had come to take as perfectly obvious and unquestionable. They actually attacked
the groundwork of politics, not merely policy. They changed the frame, shifting the
basic forces in a fundamental way. And in order to do that they had to engage in a
powerful struggle on a whole series of fronts. The whole field of positions-the
position of women, the position of the family, the position of race, the position of
law and order-is a variety of different discourses that have been reconstructed by
the Thatcherite interventions in such a way as to construct new possible subject
positions. Then these new subject positions echo and reverberate off one another.
To give a rough example, there is a sense in which the Thatcherite project depends
on seeing the mother, who is trying to represent and understand the inability of her
child to get on in a competitive situation at school, as the same mother who is
concerned about women who go out to work and neglect their responsibility to the
family, the same as the woman who says to the miners, "You can't possibly go on
strike tomorrow because your wives and children don't have enough to live on."
These are all different positions, but the point where people begin to recognize
themselves in all of them is what I call the "point of articulation." By the notion
of hegemony I want to invoke precisely the capacity of a political formation to
intervene on all these different sites.
This way of defining hegemony is almost impossible to es-
tablish in English because of the distinction between reality and appearance. The
moment you say "appears," everyone hears "that's how it appears but it really is
something else." The notion that appearances are real is something that English finds
difficult, philosophically, to say. Similarly, it is difficult to establish a notion of
hegemony as something other than domination. As soon as you say "hegemony"
people see marching boots, rolling tanks, censorship, people being locked away. What
they cannot understand is the one thing we need to understand in societies like ours,
which is how people can be constrained while walking free; being utterly subject to
determinations that make you apparently free to say what you like. The problem
with liberal capitalism is the nature of the compulsion of a particular kind of freedom,
not the total denial of freedom. I don't mean to say that there aren't places in our
society where freedom is denied, just as I don't mean to say there aren't conspiracies.
But just as conspiracies don't explain history, so notions of direct coercion, social
control, and total domination, which is the way hegemony is customarily conceived,
are inadequate to explain the real negotations around power and language, control
and consent, on which hegemony depends.
Question
But where do these different hegemonic moments come from
and how are they effectively communicated?
61
Hall
One is describing a circuit of relations. Not all the moments
in the circuit have equal power. There is unequal power at different points in the
circuit. The power to initiate and formulate, for instance, is not decisive because
you can't impose that formulation on everybody; but it does give you a first shot
at the field-the power to formulate the question, to set the terms. Other definitions
then have to respond to you; it's your definition that is being negotiated. The political
apparatuses are effective precisely because of the monopolization of the power to
formulate in our society. Think of how Star Wars came to be taken seriously. Thus,
a greal deal happens when policies first begin to be visibly promulgated, even though
they have a hidden prehistory.
Thatcherism has a prehistory, not only in popular discourse,
but in previous elite and expert discourses as well-in the free-market doctrines of
the Institute for Economic Affairs, for instance, which has been going since the late
fifties. So you have to start the story somewhere, for convenience, say, 1975, when
Sir Keith Joseph was going to run for prime minister but didn't make it, and Mrs.
Thatcher took his place; that is how she came to power. And it is interesting why
he didn't run and she did. Joseph was a more consistent, philosophical Thatcherite
than Mrs. Thatcher. But he went to Birmingham, a large industrial city, and he made
what were to be three keynote speeches. In one speech he referred to the problem
of overpopulation of working-class families and the inability of working-class moth-
ers to cope or to organize their lives. He was absolutely finished right there. If his
project had been to continue the paternalistic version of Toryism, that would have
been acceptable because the squire can tell mothers in the village how to bring up
their children. But if you are going into the populist, libertarian variety of conserv-
atism, that is the last thing you can do. Within a week it was decided that Joseph
was not going to run. Then the question was Where are his votes going to? and Mrs.
Thatcher came on. In that sense she is very much produced by a whole set of previous
discourses, both popular and expert ones. Nevertheless, the moment when they are
condensed in a single popular figure, and when that begins to get publicity in the
media, when that is the only figure that gets talked about, and when it gets the
highlight treatment of an election-which she dominated personally, and she had a
personal victory in the Tory party, dispersing the old crew-that condensation adds
a new dimension of power.
I want to give an account that is genuinely open at both ends
but doesn't talk about a circuit as if it were equal at all points; everybody in the
circuit does not have equal power. If you monopolize a piece of the mass media-
the apparatus of cultural production-you have a certain kind of formative power.
But it doesn't give you an absolute power. Yet we need to ask how such monopolies
might be fought, for the fact is that the popular press in Britain is less varied than
it used to be. There used to be a wider spectrum between, say, the tabloid Daily
Mirror and the Times. Those intermediary papers have been squeezed out by in-
creasing market polarization. So there are two or three quality newspapers at one
end and then a mass of popular papers that all look alike. And increasingly those
are monopolized by three or four multinational media corporations. So the actual
room for openings in the existing structure of the media are very slim.
Now there has been a good deal of discussion over the last
ten years about the possibility of starting a rival, not necessarily Labour, paper.
There used to be two Labour papers: the Mirror supports Labour but is a multi-
national tabloid with a foot in both camps; the Daily Herald was quite committed
to the Labour party and the cooperative movement, and it went out of business
with still over a million readers. The argument has been that it is impossible for
Labour to make any headway at all unless it enters the field of popular journalism
and establishes an authentic, legitimate press of its own. The trouble now is that it
is extremely difficult to capitalize such a venture. The costs of setting up a distribution
network for a new national newspaper are very serious, and, though there has been
62
Stuart Hall
money on offer, there has not been enough. This absence is not countered by ex-
tensive internal political education. You could try to counter a national hegemony
in the press by a great deal more education in the trade unions, and Labour party
constituencies, and so on, which would build up informed public opinion able to
challenge media definitions. But both the trade unions and the Labour party remain
largely electorally rather than education-oriented. There is no counterinformation
to bring to bear against the media's simplistic ways of constructing the news. So it
is true that the whole structuring organization of the media makes it very difficult
to compete. Even if you know what to say, you don't have the channels that allow
you access to a wide slice of public opinion.
Question
How would you respond to the argument that you over-
emphasize ideological elements and exclude both the economic and the political?
Hall
The moment you give the ideological dimension of the anal-
ysis its proper place, people invert the paradigm, accusing you of thinking that things
work by ideology alone. Ideology is tremendously important, and it has its own
specificity, its own kind of effects, its own mechanisms, but it doesn't operate outside
the play of other determinations; it has social, political, economic conditions of
existence. One has to take the question of the nucleus of economic activity seriously,
as Gramsci said, even when using a hegemonic approach.
A comprehensive analysis of Thatcherism would be a col-
lective research project using a whole range of skills, addressed to a range of different
sites, including the economic. I am aware that I am cutting into this field from a
particular dimension. But there is a difference between the research programs you
define for the world and the more limited ones you engage in yourself In any case,
I don't think there is an either/or between economically and organizationally oriented
work and ideological work. The question is how to understand the articulations
between them, nonreductively. Moreover, while I don't believe that economics is
the primary definer in the sense of the first instance, or that the economy stitches
up the results in the end, it is possible to see where economic determinacy operates
in structuring the ideological field of play at any one time. It's one of the structuring
principles; it helps to set the constraints, the lines of tendency and force within which
ideology operates. What it doesn't do is deliver the right answer, the correct, pregiven
closure at the end.
That's why I am against determination in the last instance.
But I do believe in provisional analysis. Wherever your research starts, you have to
make some significant allowances in the direction of the dimensions you left out.
So those doing economic analysis have to look at the ideological traditions that are
at work, just as those analyzing ideological discourse or texts ought to look at the
operation of those legal apparatuses, economic forces, etc., that are helping to es-
tablish the field they are looking at. That is because the object of analysis is the
social formation, which is an ensemble of practices and relations; it is concrete
because it has many determinations.
Question
Why, then, are there so few studies where the two elements
are addressed, where one of them is not reduced to a skeleton?
Hall
It is difficult to do both. Practically, it means either that you
have access to a wide range of analytic skills or that you have a well-differentiated
research team. In your own work you accumulate certain insights that you can't
match in other areas. I ask myself whether I should combine a sort of naive economic
analysis with a highly sophisticated ideological one, and it doesn't seem to fit. In a
more open intellectual climate we would take some risks like that. This is one of
63
the arguments for more collective intellectual work. The Centre did try. Policing the
Crisis did try to say something about a lot of areas we didn't know a lot about,
individually, but that we didn't want, collectively, to leave off the agenda. And I
think perhaps one should even be more risky than that-risk some generalizations.
But the professionalization of intellectual life means the temptations are strong to
play it safe.
Question
Could you say something about what you think the Left
needs to be doing. Can the New Right be defeated?
Hall
If I knew that, I would be in business. But I do think one
can begin to identify some weak spots, some contradictions, places where the dis-
courses don't match up, or where there is a disparity between the promises and the
delivery. There are lots of contradictions there, but they don't easily break in our
direction or offer us big political opportunities; they require the constitution of an
equally powerful, equally convincing alternative, all the way across the political
terrain. The more hegemonic the Thatcherite alternative becomes, the more the Left
must generate a whole alternative philosophy or conception oflife or it will collapse.
Otherwise, it simply can't match what the Right is offering, which is a hegemonic
vision oflife from birth to death. There is a Thatcherite way ofbeing born, of rearing
children, of going to hospitals, of being prosperous in business; there is an image
for everyone and everything: how to bring up babies, how to teach, what you should
wear to stand in front of the classroom. It's a hodgepodge of all kinds of different
discourses; nevertheless, it does offer a set of positive social positionalities, which
condense and connote one another. And the thing about the Left is that there is no
such coherent alternative set. There is no way of being a teacher, to counter the
Thatcherite style of being a teacher. All the Left has is a disarrayed, dispersed series
ofpositionalities. Mounting a counteroffensive involves offering and setting in place
alternative and equally powerful frames for life in the twenty-first century. I don't
know whether the Labour party can be made to see that as its historical task.
Question
You have, on other occasions, stressed the key role of dis-
courses of the nation in Thatcherism-for example, in the way the nation was mo-
bilized for the Falklands war. But how does one decide whether the struggle over
terms like "the nation" is possible to win? What is the strategic question one raises
here? Can the Left engage in significant ideological struggles against Thatcherism
around the nation, or is it so likely that the Left is going to lose that we had better
find other issues?
Hall
You could make the same argument about law and order.
You could argue that you cannot possibly engage with the issues that are concealed
in the slogans of law and order because they always deliver results that are of a
deeply conservative and reactionary kind. Then, one after another the domains of
public argument are snatched away from you; you can't touch any of them because
they all seem to be articulated, organized, and structured in such a way as to deliver
a victory to the other side.
It is perfectly clear, historically, why the notion of the nation
in Britain tends in that direction. Historically, the ideological terrain is tendentially
articulated that way. But I still think that it is possible to begin to intervene on or
engage the same terrain. The problem is that, as against the way the ideological
terrain is historically articulated around the nation, it seems an abstract argument
to ask ordinary people in the street, who are being appealed to powerfully in terms
of the concrete experience of their sons sailing away on the Falklands task force, to
reidentify, against the flag, with the Argentine people. It's totally outside their ho-
64
Stuart Hall
rizon. They've never heard of it; they have no living connections with it. The only
way they know the Argentine is as the team that always beats us at football. There
is not a lot of mileage in "We are one with the Argentines!" as a popular slogan.
I'm talking, then, about the kind of long groundwork or
preparation that is necessary. Does any nation build solidarity with another nation
when it doesn't know what it is? I suspect not. I suspect internationalism comes out
of people having a sense of their own national, popular, or community identity,
which allows them to build bridges to other people. After all, differences of national
history, culture, and identity have to be recognized. The Argentines do have different
interests from us. They do have a quite good claim to the Falklands, for example.
So these are not easy contradictions to reconcile. But the building of solidarity has
to come out of an actual, grounded sense of where we belong and fit into the world,
a sense that is different from the old national-imperial one.
It is a very risky strategy, and I'm not recommending it. I
recommend asking the questions so that the Left can actually begin to engage strat-
egies within and around the languages of popular calculation, the languages of prac-
tical consciousness, the discourse in which the man-in-the-pub says, "I'm for the
war," or "That hasn't anything to do with us." We really need to shift him and his
wife and his family from "Of course let's get at the 'Argies'," at least to "This war
is not our concern." I don't know that I could do it by saying, "Identify with the
enemy, feel at one with them." I have to begin to talk the language in which popular
calculation goes on, if I'm to appeal to any powerful counternotions that don't send
people marching off into the sunset. Furthermore, the question of interests is always
there, even though interests are themselves ideologically constructed. But that doesn't
mean there aren't contrary interests, around which alternatives can be constructed
that make sense to people. I can think of instances where the appeal to international
solidarity does eventually overcome genuine differences. The Vietnam war, in the
end, was such an example.
Comment
But it is clear that, historically, the British Empire no longer
exists. Yet Thatcher seems to use it so centrally in her anticommunism.
Hall
I think the language of empire, and the wars that have been
fought around it, still constitute a massive ideological repertoire in British history.
The fact that the empire has been worn down doesn't tell you anything about how
the vocabulary of the empire plays into present fears and anxieties about no longer
being a powerful nation and so on. In fact, it still provides a lot of the discourses
in which people construct what Britain's role in the world is. It is a living language,
although it may refer to a real situation no longer historically pertinent. I think that
those imperial traces invest the language of the holy war against communism. The
holy war against communism is not, in England, a very popular language in its own
terms. It could become popular precisely because it might mobilize traces of these
other imperial languages one forgets. People did respond to Thatcher's self-construc-
tion as the "Iron Lady" and "telling the soviets where to go," but not in the same
way as Reagan's "holy war." People are very terrified of Cruise and Pershing missiles.
There are, at the moment, counterpositionalities in popular
languages that provoke powerful resistances. We could speak the language-the true
language of the cold war-if we invested it with the energy that is associated with
an older kind of war-Falklands-type wars-that place Britain in a much stronger,
more leading position. But notions of sovereignty get in the way. Thus, notions of
sovereignty aren't entirely reactionary. The question of national independence is an
important question in the struggle against nuclear Atlanticism. People do have some
sense of their rights in saying, "If we are going to be blown up it should be on our
own decision and not because somebody else happens to be occupying 200 bases in
our country." So even those concepts one thinks of as the pillars and underpinnings
65
of a rather reactionary position are not entirely uncontradictory. They are not entirely
without a certain popular counterpositional discursive force.
Question
Where can you possibly find the resources to struggle over
the concept of "the nation"?
Hall
If the dialogue is constantly one that constructs the nation
in the direction of Great Britain, the people will be interpellated only as subjects
for war. But it's not necessarily the case that every way of being English is one that
has to justify itself by waging war. There are a lot of associations in common popular
traditions in England that are democratic. Cinema and TV in England are constantly
representing the English civil war as one between the goodies and the badies, and
the goodies are always Royalists; or all Puritans are systematically presented as dour
Cromwellians, etc. But this is also the beginning of the English revolution, the be-
ginning of popular movements secured at the price of cutting off the head of the
king. It's the beginning of the parliamentary tradition, of the curtailment of absolute
royal power. That is the English revolution-a bourgeois revolution that secured
much wider popular support. There is no preordained reason why people who feel
English shouldn't be English because of the English revolution rather than because
of the Restoration. There is a popular content to English identity-the content of
the struggle to make the nation into a popular nation rather than a nation of elites
and kings. That is a struggle that goes on all the time. The offical language is, of
course, wrapped up in the language of the crown, the royal navy, etc. But even that
language is not uncontradictory. And there are constantly struggles to win some
purchase for popular interpellations in an area that appears to be sewn up by alter-
native definitions.
Wherever you find popular struggles, the nation is always at
issue. The field of national interpellations doesn't simply disappear because time
and again one finds it inserted into a dominant discourse that is very reactionary.
It does not cease to play an important part in countermovements. The antiwar,
antiimperialist movement is one that has been sustained through a counterdefinition
of nationhood.
But it is impossible to enter this argument without asking
about the nature of popular memory in relation to language. After all, these terms
are constructed out of some sense of what the history is, and there is always a struggle
over popular historical memory. Contemporary questions always have a historical
content-not necessarily the "real" content, but content as filtered and structured in
the categories of popular memory. I don't want to suggest that the field of contestation
is so open that you can construct any articulation you wish. Quite the reverse. But
the only thing that would stem a tide like the Falklands one is some equally powerful
set of counterimages, which would call up some different connotations in the popular
memory. If you argue that nationalism has always been a difficult ideology to rear-
ticulate because of the way Britain's history as an imperial formation has tendentially
constructed the field, I would respect that answer. I disagree with the Laclau position
that all discursive articulations are possible, but I do want to hear the argument gone
through. To engage in that strategy, we will have to rethink and finally reject strategies
based on the assumption that the great mass of people live permanently in false
consciousness. I do not think it is possible to argue that a small number of people,
who are themselves, of course, not in false consciousness-the Left-should address
and mobilize large numbers of people who are. I don't think you will convince
anyone by saying, "I'm sorry. I can see through you, but you can't see through
yourself."
Comment
I'm concerned about your prioritizing "nation" to the ex-
clusion of "class" and "race."
66
Stuart Hall
Hall
First, in relation to the discourses of popular conservatism,
nation is an interpellation that directly crosscuts and neutralizes the interpellations
of class. The way to construct the notion of the nation as composed of people linked
into an organic unity is to say that what people share as a nation is larger and more
inclusive than what divides them into classes. That, essentially, is how the super-
imposition of nation over class was achieved by the Conservative party. And it has
exactly that capacity to draw people together from different sectors of the population
to suppress class differences and differences of class interest, etc., in order to unify
them around shared common characteristics on a national basis, that made con-
servatism "popular."
It is important to emphasize that racism was already present,
for instance, as the other, the unspoken of nation-for example, in the way the
Falklands war was represented. When people said "Argies," it carried a highly racist
connotation. It isn't just that these people are different, non-British; racism doesn't
exist only in relation to blacks, but in relations to all foreigners. That is the imperialist
connotation of "nation" in the British discourse. In the struggle to reach ordinary
British people, the element of what they think of themselves in relation to other
nations cannot be left out. If you leave that space empty it will constantly play the
discourse against you. Those of us who do not belong to that nation also have to
think about how we think about ourselves in relation to it.
And actually, there is a struggle, odd as it may sound, that
blacks have had to wage in order to transpose the one-race notion of the nation that
persists in the British discourse and give it a content that interpellates them; that is
to say, that makes it refer to kids who are now born of black families who have
lived in Britain for three generations, kids whose parents, for example, aren't Ja-
maican anymore. What are they? They are black British. So the question of racism
does not take you outside the terrain of national identifications necessarily but is
part of the struggle over the popular identifications present in the society. If the
British are allowed to go on thinking of themselves only in terms of the great white
British who have an imperial destiny, they will fix us all. Thus, we have to work on
the ground in which people establish their national identity and associate it with a
different range of understandings. Are the blacks Afro-Caribbeans? Are they black
British? Are they West Indian immigrants? Etcetera. The question is one of the long-
term stakes involved in the different interpellations. What is at issue is the positive
content, for both the black and white sections of the population, of the discourses
used. These don't foreclose the other struggles, which blacks conduct on another
front, about their problematic insertion in the discourse of class.
Question
Given your emphasis on the struggles over identity, what
does that imply about the Althusserian-Lacanian notion of the relationship between
ideology and subjectivity? Do we discard the notion of the intimate connection
between ideology and the concept of the subject?
Hall
Certainly, in traditional marxism, ideology has at its center
the concept of the authorially centered, Western, epistemological "I": the author of
the ideology is the person or group that speaks it, etc. So I regard the dismantling,
or dethronement, by structuralism (structural linguistics, Levi-Strauss, Althusser,
and so on) of the already integrated "I" at the center of all ideological discourses as
a major theoretical revolution. Obviously, then, there was a time when we tried to
think the operation of discourse without any reference to subjectivity. Levi-Strauss
tells us that the mythmaker is just an empty narrative point of punctuation, spoken
by the myth. But that is obviously inadequate. So we are beginning to get more
sophisticated ways of trying to theorize subjectivity. I think the attempt to theorize
the constitution of subject positions within ideological discourse, exclusively through
67
psychoanalytic mechanisms (the Lacanian moment), is an important advance for
understanding the establishment of basic orientations to language. I think that level
lays down, again, certain tendential positionalities in relation to language. And those
tendential positions are crucial in some domains. For instance, I think it is quite
right that in the domain of sexuality a great deal happens at that stage. But what I
am not prepared to say is that those primary psychoanalytic scenarios and resolutions
contain the whole of the theory of ideology; or that once those mechanisms are in
place, all that happens after that is the repetition of those same subject positions in
a succession of later discursive formations. I don't think that is so; that is, I don't
think we can replace economic determinism by a psychoanalytic reductionism. What
is constituted are the fragmentary subject positions that are then open to a range of
subsequent interpellations.
People with identities and relations to language already se-
cured nevertheless can find themselves repositioned in new ideological configura-
tions. I think Lacanianism is in danger of substituting a psychoanalytic essentialism
for a class essentialism; and that, like class essentialism, precisely leaves out the
actual play of negotiation, contradiction, interchange, etc. It leaves out the fact that
ideologies have to struggle to recruit the same lived individuals for quite contra-
dictory subject places in their discourses. I want to ask how people who already have
an orientation to language nevertheless are constantly placed and replaced in relation
to particular ideological discourses that hail and recruit them for a variety of po-
sitions.
I stand on the theoretical break that structuralism has made,
but I refuse the new poststructuralist theoretical absolutism. I think there is some-
thing built into structuralism that, once it made the break, refuses to learn anything
from what it has dethroned. You can see that in the language of many poststruc-
turalist texts. A number of times Foucault says, "I'm interested not only in that,
but also in that," and then only the "but also" is silenced. What happened to the
"not only"? Everything in Foucault is periodized around the bourgeois revolution-
ancien regime to modem-which is never itself theorized. Why do all the epistemes
shift just then? Structuralism drives itself to detotalize everything, but it doesn't go
back and recover the elements in the detotalized field, and I think that is an incorrect
notion of theorizing. Theory is always what Marx did to Ricardo. Marx said, "He
is the summit ofbourgeois thought." Being that, Ricardo is clearly ideological. Where
have I learned everything I know? Of course, from Ricardo. Where else can you go
except to the cleverest man who ever thought that system of political economy?
You deconstruct a problematic, but the new problematic
must retotalize the rational core of the paradigm it dethrones. Theory is a quite
different thing from the leap from error to truth; it releases the problem from the
terms in which the old problematic set it. But it doesn't abandon the problem. The
problem has to be rethought in better, more adequate conceptual terms. I still think,
then, that there is something about the complex interplay between subjectivity and
objective social practice, etc., that needs work within the problematic of marxist
structuralisms.
Question
Could you elaborate on your notion of theory? The way you
were just talking, theory sounds like a kind of conversation with the past. Is this
connected to the Centre's commitment to collective work?
Hall
I want to undermine the notion that theory consists offully
clarified concepts that are in a box in somebody's attic and one day you go up and
open Pandora's box and let the truth out. I want to suggest that theorizing is a
process-the operation of scientific concepts on the ground of theoretical ideolo-
gies-that always operates by deconstructing existing paradigms and at the same
time snatching important insights from what it is tossing out. So it has a necessarily
68
Stuart Hall
mixed nature. You recover things that stand in the wrong place in the old conceptual
matrix but that nevertheless give you insights into aspects of society and culture you
did not have before. You have to reposition them.
I do want to add as well a description of the contradictory
and unformed exploratory nature of trying collectively as a group to develop a set
of theorizations in a particular area. We need to disestablish a highly possessive,
individualistic notion of what research and intellectual practice is about, which is
the dominant notion in the humanities and, indeed, to some extent, in the social
sciences. But I don't want to give an easy picture of the attempts to do collective
work at the Centre-for example, the project to write collectively. I should tell you
it's not easy; it's bloody hard. And unless you are feeling really strong, and unless
you are not addicted to those well-wrought sentences of yours (which are bound to
be the ones that nobody else likes; those are always the ones they want to rewrite,
in their style, etc.), it's very difficult. I learned a lot about what practice means in
this process. We tried to write and do research in a slightly more collective way than
the dominant way-it wasn't a big shift you know; it wasn't like we were trying to
take over the state or the telephone exchange or something. We just wanted to do
intellectual work in a slightly different way, to make a small shift, to actually displace
a dominant practice. The point is that when my favorite sentence was on the table
and somebody said, "I just struck it out," that's when I learned what practice is.
Practice is a hard taskmaster: harder to change in practice than appears in the head.
I remember especially the way in which the practice would advance well for several
weeks and then slip back; and people would say, "What does Raymond Williams
do? Doesn't he just go away and write, by himself, what he wants to write, in a
room? There is something to be said for that kind of individualism, too." And
everyone would say, "There sure is!"
Question
It's interesting that you use Gramsci against the Althusser-
ians, but Althusser himself uses Gramsci. How do you justify your reading of Gram-
sci in this context?
Hall
Gramsci is where I stopped in the headlong rush into struc-
turalism and theoreticism. At a certain point I stumbled over Gramsci, and I said,
"Here and no further!" Gramsci represented a kind of test of historical concreteness
for me against the overtheoretical claims of structuralism. He wrote out of a par-
ticular historical configuration, a particular society. When I read him, I can see
Gramsci's Italy; I can see north and south; I can see the problem the Italians have
had in attempting to form a nation; I can see the absence that left in Italian life.
You can see what Gramsci meant by saying that these are peoples who haven't yet
become a nation; they have an aspiration for the national popular but it's never
been constituted. You can see what Gramsci meant by saying that we all misun-
derstood fascism as an external force, as if it wasn't intrinsic to Italian political and
cultural life. It was in the very field of play that the Left was engaged in. The people
they won were the people we lost!
So Gramsci gave me an alternative to the antihistorical thrust
of Althusserianism. I deeply resented Althusser's conflation of historicism with the
historical. Historicism is a particular way of looking at history; but the historical is
something quite different. That is the sense in which I use Gramsci as a kind of
corrective. And I've gone on finding Gramsci extremely generative for me in two
ways. One is just that sense of the historical concreteness of theory, of theorizing
for particular cases. Althusser and Poulantzas thought that Gramsci was not properly
theorized and that their task was to fully theorize him. But the moment you fully
theorize Gramsci you lose what is most important about him, because the nature
of his theorization is precisely its concreteness. If you ask me what is the object of
my work, the object of the work is to always reproduce the concrete in thought-
69
not to generate another good theory, but to give a better theorized account of concrete
historical reality. This is not an antitheoretical stance. I need theory in order do to
this. But the goal is to understand the situation you started out with better than
before.
I suppose the second thing that attracts me to Gramsci is
precisely the un-fully theorized nature of his work. It enables me to appropriate him
more easily. He doesn't dominate the concepts I borrow from him because his
concepts aren't embedded in a full textual apparatus. It's very suggestive. There are
hints about what he means by "the national popular," but there are no good texts
on it; he never sat down and wrote it out. And therefore I have to work on it to see
what he could have meant. So I find that Gramsci prevents me from becoming a
disciple or a ventriloquist or a believer.
On the other hand, there is a danger in Gramsci. In spite of
his attack on, say, class reductionism, there is no question that Gramsci regards class
as the fundamental social dimension; whereas his notion of the politics of the war
of positions, of the struggle for hegemony on many fronts, doesn't exclusively priv-
ilege one site but precisely asks you to attend to a whole range of social contradictions
and movements. Nevertheless, one has to struggle, in a Gramscian framework, not
to give class a kind of automatic place but to understand its massive historical
constitution of the field of thought and action.
70
Stuart Hall
One of the main problems of seizing power in modem democracies is that you don't
know where power (in the singular) lies. It is not in any one place. Foucault thinks
that the nature of the power derived from the state is a rather useless issue; he is
interested in the play of power at all the other intersections across a social body.
Everybody has everybody else locked into power in some ways, as well as being the
object of power. Oddly enough, this is a rather Durkheimian notion of social control
dressed up in poststructuralist language. But I want to insist that there are centers
that operate directly on the formation and constitution of discourse. The media are
in that business. Political parties are in that business. When you set the terms in
which the debate proceeds, that is an exercise of symbolic power. So I want to
continue to question the radiation of power from the constituted centers of the state,
parties, social groupings, and so on. Even then you've only just begun. Because the
power didn't begin there; these apparatuses, including, by the way, organic intellec-
tuals, operate to transform power that probably came from elsewhere. But within
the framework of popular democracy they had to get it first in order to do anything
with it. So power is already in circulation. But it circulates between constituted
points of condensation. In that sense I do borrow the Foucaultian notion but refuse
his absolute dispersion.
Question
Would you also say that power is creative in Foucault's sense,
rather than negative?
Hall
Yes, I would certainly go along with that. It is powerful
because it is positive. Think about the power to formulate terms: it is not only a
prohibition but also a positive inducement to think about something in this way.
To set those rules and promulgate a new way of conceptualizing, for example, how
the economy works is a very positive instance. But I want to know about how that
power gets supported, internalized, by those who appear to be its recipients, about
how the conduits include them and are transformed by them, as well as about the
centers from which it radiates.
Question
I am interested in how you deal with one position, a kind
of undercurrent in what you have been saying, and that is Wilhelm Reich's question
of ideology: What if the masses aren't just deluded but indeed desire, want, need
their own oppression? How do you respond to that and how does that change our
thinking about tactics?
Hall
My answer to that is not a very developed one. I know the
position, but it is not one I've really tried to think my own position in relation to.
But I don't believe people are essentially anything. I don't think that historically
one can show the masses to be exclusively in love with power anymore than that
they are outside the radii of power. The desire for power, the desire for domination
is there. But what I am extremely dubious of is the attempt, especially in the moment
of disillusionment (which I think is a moment Reich faces; it's a moment that Adorno
faces; it's a moment that the Left has faced again and again), to avoid the troublesome
problem of actually engaging with the analysis of a really contradictory field, of
intervening in a real field of struggle, by simply assigning the people whom you hope
to rescue permanently to one or the other of the poles. Everything we know about
the way in which popular consciousness is formed historically suggests perfectly
good reasons why people who have been systematically and structurally oppressed
should be implicated in their oppression. It's inscribed in the nature of secondariness
over any historical period of time in which you come to live with it and thus, indeed,
to find pleasure in it. So it's not a denial of that dimension that Reich addresses.
But the moment you collapse everything into that level, so as to say there is nothing
71
but their desire to escape from their freedom, that they are nothing but the depen-
dency of the worker on the hand that feeds him or her, nothing but the implication
of the slave with the master, you run a real risk of reductionism. You've won an
insight the simple-minded Left often denies, namely, that those inconvenient things
can exist. But you've also moved past the insight and gone over to what is, in fact,
an inversion of the earlier position. Now, in place of the endless revolutionary
potential of the proletariat, one has constructed the endlessly deceived, or endlessly
authoritarian, masses. And I think when you go back to the actual conditions in
which those situations appear in extreme form, such as fascism, you don't need a
one-sided theory of that kind. You can see why those were the elements of popular
consciousness that could be built on in certain historical situations; you can see why
the irrational made rational sense at a certain moment; you can see why the collapse
of alternative ways of understanding what was happening to them didn't connect in
the same way. But you always see other oppositional elements as well.
This is not to undermine or deny the powerful subliminal
force of unpleasant ideas. It's one of the things that in England we have had to do,
and have had to insist on, and sometimes to insist on despite sounding very reac-
tionary. For example, the problem of understanding working-class racism: we must
avoid endlessly denying it and avoid as well the simple myth that racism really
comes from above. We have had to insist that working people are deeply implicated
in forms of racism, built on deep ideological foundations; and there are good reasons
why that should be so. And you can't begin to operate in that field politically at all
unless you accept that as a given fact of life.
So I don't want to deny the kinds of observations that Reich
has made about extreme historical situations. What I object to is essentializing those
observations, freezing the historical process, and assigning it to a set of permanent
categories. When you look at the situation historically, it doesn't remain the same.
One can see that there are always other tendencies. In relation to fascism, one of
the most perplexing problems is precisely why fascism so obviously begins as an
anticapitalist revolution. Now you don't explain that simply by talking about the
built-in authoritarianism of the Germans or Italians. You also have to talk about
the intrinsic appeal to a certain "radicalism of the masses" that nevertheless was
articulated to very conventional slogans and politically reactionary positions. I don't
think Reich's view gives you enough of a purchase, by itself, even on those situations
that appear to have historically delivered very simple and stark results. I don't trust
it.
Question
Given all that you have said, in what sense would you still
describe yourself as a marxist? What, if anything, do you retain from Marx?
Hall
There are a lot of things in Marx that I choose to keep. I
choose to keep the notion of classes; I choose to keep the notion of the capital/labor
contradiction; I choose to keep the notion of social relations of production, etc.-1
just don't want to think them reductively. That is the point. It's the reductionist
understanding of the importance of economic relations that I am opposed to, not
the categories themselves. And I quite deliberately talked about the working classes
and about the level at which that is a pertinent level of abstraction.
My critique of marxism attempts to dethrone marxism from
its guarantees, because I think that, as an ideological system, it has tried to construct
its own guarantees. And I use the word "ideological" very deliberately. I think of
marxism not as a framework for scientific analysis only but also as a way of helping
you sleep well at night; it offers the guarantee that, although things don't look simple
at the moment, they really are simple in the end. You can't see how the economy
determines, but just have faith, it does determine in the last instance! The first clause
wakes you up and the second puts you to sleep. It's okay, I can nod off tonight,
72
Stuart Hall
because in the last instance, though not just yesterday or today or tomorrow or as
far as I can see forward in history, but in the last instance, just before the last trumpet,
as St. Peter comes to the door, he'll say, "The economy works."
I think those are very ideological guarantees. And as soon
as you abandon that teleological structure under marxism, the whole classical edifice
begins to rock. Now that isn't any news theoretically these days. Almost everybody
of any note is in the business of rocking the marxist foundations. My question is,
should we now admit that, since the guaranteed philosophical and epistemological
underpinnings of the theory do not stand up, it is finished as a problematic? I want
to try to account theoretically for what is still there, what needs to be retained.
Can one retheorize the theory in a nonreductionist way? I
have tried to suggest some ways in which a modem, more discursive understanding
of ideology, which mediates the link between ideas and social forces through language
and representation, can accomplish that. That is the contemporary theoretical rev-
olution: the notion that the arena or medium in which ideology functions is one of
signification, representation, discursive practices. That is the intervening term that
has changed the nature ofthe debate. I have tried to rethink some of the things that
Marx was saying in that more discursive framework. My work, therefore, is in the
very unfashionable mode of salvage work, of deconstruction/reconstruction-a dan-
gerous enterprise in the age of deconstruction.
73
Henri Lefebvre
Information
Information is often spoken about; it is employed in an ordinary
sense: to become informed-get information through the press, the radio,
the TV. Today information is something entirely different. First, it is a
mathematical quantity-a theory that is at once mathematical, physical,
biological; that extends beyond these sciences and seems to be in full de-
ployment. Information is an advanced technique, dominated by certain
multinationals. It is also a commodity to be bought and sold, a product
that is consumed (notably through the media) but is not a material object.
It is, finally, a social practice, a way of communicating, with a usage and
even a political application. Information processing can be located neither
at the level of the base nor at the level of the superstructure in the usual
sense, for it covers the whole of modern society, from the base to the su-
perstructure. This is why it is necessary to have a Marxist and critical theory
of information systems.
The Project
We have to elaborate a cultural project, but it must, these days,
be connected to other elements of a qualitative development, one more and
more distinct from quantitative growth, that is to say, purely and simply
economic. It is a question, at least in Europe and France, of the extension
of the activities that are deployed outside the spheres dominated by the
commodity, its laws, and its logic. 3 It is a question of a slow but profound
modification ofthe everyday-of a new usage ofthe body, oftime and space,
of sociability; something that implies a social and political project; more
enhanced forms of democracy, such as direct democracy in cities; definition
of a new citizenship; decentralization; participatory self-management (au-
togestion); and so on-that is, a project for society that is at the same time
86
Henri Lefebvre
cultural, social, and political. Is this utopian? Yes, because utopian thought
concerns what is and is not possible. All thinking that has to do with action
has a utopian element. Ideals that stimulate action, such as liberty and
happiness, must contain a utopian element. This is not a refutation of such
ideals; it is, rather, a necessary condition of the project of changing life.
These considerations, these perspectives, and this project to change
life can partly be found in Marx, but not entirely. They are implicit in Marx,
in the sense of a renewed humanism. In terms borrowed from Hegel, Marx
envisaged a total person of the future, being deployed as a body, as a relation
between the senses, as thought. These investigations converge toward a
supreme and final question that goes beyond classical philosophy. It is not
a matter of understanding what the verb "to think" signifies, as Heidegger
did, but of responding to the question, What remains to be thought now?
Marx certainly thought the world in which he lived, but the modem world
has not yet begun to think Marxism.
Thus, we need to rethink the nature of humankind. Human beings
are not merely the theoretical essence they appear to be in many pre-Marxist,
Marxist, or post-Marxist texts. To understand this in Marxist terms we need
to reformulate the conflictual relations within the triad: nature/matter/hu-
man. If a person is first and foremost an earthly being and a human body,
how do we relate the person to a representation of the world that includes
the recent contributions of all the sciences, including cosmology, astro-
physics, and microphysics? These types of knowledge extend from the in-
finitely small to the infinitely large. What, then, is the relationship of human
beings to the world of which they continue to be a part? The paradox of
Marx, which seems to escape most Marxists, is that human beings are their
own self-creations: they create themselves. In sum, the number of concep-
tions of the world seem rather limited, and Marx introduces one into them.
The other conceptions of the world take account either of the relationship
of human beings with creative nature or of their relationship with some
transcendence. Marx's thesis differs from these conceptions. The relation-
ship of human beings to themselves is considered no longer as a temporal
and spatial center of the universe but as a nucleus and center of self-creation.
This includes, at the same time, a conception of the world and a project
for life. Human beings are engaged in a perpetual adventure with its at-
tendant risks. More deeply, however, they place themselves not only into
question but also in play; they are perpetually at stake for themselves. Today
this occurs dramatically: the risk of nuclear self-destruction accompanies
self-creation.
Notes
I have elsewhere distinguished /a v1e quotid1enne (daily life) from /e quotidien (the everyday)
from Ia quotid1ennete (everydayness) "Let us simply say about da1ly life that it has always
existed, but permeated with values, with myths. The word everydav designates the entry of
this da1ly l1fe mto modernity the everyday as an object of a programming (d'une program-
marion), whose unfold1ng 1s 1mposed by the market, by the system of equivalences. by
marketmg and advertisements. As to the concept of 'everydayness,' it stresses the homog-
enous, the repetitive, the fragmentary in everyday l1fe" (Le Monde, Sunday, Dec. 19, 1982.
pp. ix, x). I have also stated that "the everyday, 1n the modern world, has ceased to be a
'subject' (abundant m poss1ble subjectivity) to become an 'object' (object of social organi-
zation)" (La v1e quotidienne ans le monde modern, Pans Gall1nard "Idees," 1968, p. 116).
87
2 The concept of alienation. in moving from Marxist thinking into culture. has lost much of its
integrity and force. For example, young women have come to me to say they do not want
any children because children represent self-alienation. I suggest that if you have a child
against your will, that constitutes alienation. But it is different if you want the child. Alienation
is determined not by the condition of women but by the action of will and desire.
3 The project described here begins with the question of how people live their everyday lives.
It leaves unanswered those considerations that might result from looking especially at those
whose incomes are well below the social average. How do the Northeastern Brazilians. the
peasants of Upper Volta. the inhabitants of the Mexican campamientos survive? [Translator's
note: This is an untranslatable play on words. The verb used. sou-vivre. does not actually
exist in French. The verb for survive is survivre and Lefebvre is playing with the prefixes sur-
(over) and sou-(under. as in underdevelopment).] Do they manage? But how? Is there not a
parallel and underground economy being constructed in relation to ultramodern industry? It
is not only a matter of turning one's attention to the way in which hundreds of millions of
people manage to survive. but to know if this modern society-from the capitalist side-is
not in the process of breaking up. A theoretical. practical. and political problem. as soon as
one does not accept that the growth of production as well as of information is sufficient to
conserve the unity of society.
88
Chantal Mouffe
101
Discussion
Question
Could you elaborate on what it is about liberal democracy
that needs to be redefined, and what a superseded or redefined liberal democracy of
the Left would be like?
Mouffe
Let me reiterate what I said in the paper while elaborating
a number of points. First, it is important to distinguish between democratic and
liberal theory. What we know today as a single ideology-liberal democracy-is in
fact the result of an articulation that took place during the nineteenth century. While
many Marxists have assumed that democracy is in essence liberal, that there is no
contradiction between the two, C. B. MacPherson has shown that the idea of de-
mocracy was articulated to that of liberalism only through struggle. That struggle
created the organic ideology that is still, in some sense, dominant today-liberal
democracy. The cost, of course, was that democracy was liberalized, though one can
also say liberalism was democratized. In this way democratic ideology became linked
with the defense of private property. Liberty came to mean the liberty to have your
own property. I think we have to fight this restriction of the idea of democracy by
rearticulating democracy with other important concepts to elaborate what I call a
"radical, plural, and libertarian democracy."
Of course, we are also confronted by the neoconservative
effort to sever the link between liberalism and democracy by redefining democracy
as individual freedom. This is clearly a defense of private property, one that severs
the link between democracy and political equality. If the idea of democracy as po-
litical equality has been incorporated and disarmed through its articulation with
liberalism, it nevertheless remains potentially subversive. That is why the New Right
is attempting to break with liberal democratic ideology by rearticulating liberalism
without democracy, thereby transforming liberal democracy into liberal conserva-
tism. I think the Left should also be trying to sever the link between liberalism and
democracy, but in order to radicalize the concept of democracy. To do that we need
to work at the level of political philosophy, to rearticulate ideas of equality and
justice.
Finally, we need to consider what kind of institutions we
would need in a radical democratic society. Left-wing Euro-communists have done
some reflection here, proposing to augment representative democratic institutions
with several forms of grass-roots democracy, both at the level of the workplace and
at the level of the community. This is necessary but not enough, because it will not
guarantee the inclusion of the wide range of democratic demands that must be
represented in the expansive hegemony I have called for. For example, grass-roots
democracy in a factory will not necessarily involve feminism or ecology. These
questions clearly call for a new type of autogestion, a type of self-management that
cannot be seen simply as laborers managing their own factory. We can perfectly well
imagine a situation in which workers manage their factory without really taking care
ofthe environment, without responding to the demands of women. To do so would
involve rethinking what kinds of products we want to see produced by society. This
new model of self-management would constitute a generalized, extended autogestion.
This is the form of institution needed for a radical libertarian democracy to be
implemented. It must be a democracy with a plurality of such institutions at different
levels of the social formation.
Question
Could you elaborate on the concept of expansive hegemony
and on how different demands would be related within the collective will?
Mouffe
First, as I read Gramsci, I don't think it is correct to see
hegemony as the imposition of a class ideology on undergroups, as many have done.
102
Chantal Mouffe
What I've been defending is a view of hegemony as the articulation of demands
coming from different groups to what Gramsci called a "hegemonic principle." But
he distinguished two ways in which such demands can be articulated. One is through
neutralization: you can take account ofthe demand of some group, not to transform
society so as to resolve the antagonism it expresses, but only so as to impede the
extension of that demand. That is what the New Right is doing when it takes account
of some of the resistances against the new hegemonic system. It tries to neutralize
demands by creating antagonisms that prevent the creation of a chain of equivalence
between various democratic demands. That is how I understand hegemony by neu-
tralization.
The opposite way demands are articulated is in what Gram-
sci called the "expansive hegemony." Rather than neutralize demands, an expansive
hegemony links them with all other democratic struggles to establish a chain of
equivalence. Of course, the wider the chain of equivalence, the wider the democ-
ratization of society, and the wider the collective will to be built on that basis. Then
it would be unthinkable for workers to fight for their rights only and not, at the
same time, for the rights of gays and women. It is important to reiterate that what
makes a struggle democratic is not where it comes from but the way it is articulated
with other democratic struggles. Yet such an expansive hegemony must respect the
autonomy and specificity of the demands of different groups. It is not just a matter
of saying that all those demands are implicit in the demands of the working class;
that once the working class comes to power, racial, sexual, and gender contradictions
will disappear.
Once we accept that there is no one privileged struggle, no
single origin to all forms of domination, we must then avoid creating a hierarchy
of struggles. Moreover, when we realize that most struggles are struggles to demand
rights, we can recognize that in many cases rights have been acquired by creating
inequalities with respect to other groups. The rights of some exist because others
are in a subordinate position. That is certainly the case for the demands of the
working class. The workers now have some rights by virtue of the oppression of
blacks and women; the demand to give these oppressed groups their rights must
mean that some of the rights of the workers must be abridged. Thus, any attempt
to reduce inequalities among the working class requires the transformation of the
subjectivity of the workers. And for that we need a new organic ideology that defines
equality in a different way, not just on the basis of rights. In a sense, we need the
elaboration of a postindividualist liberalism in which rights are defined not as a
personal possession but as a form of solidarity among all oppressed groups. In calling
this a form of liberalism I am suggesting that it is dangerous to do away with
liberalism entirely, a danger reflected in the Soviet Union.
Question
Given your emphases on the need not to compromise the
autonomy of various movements and on the plurality of discourses, how can you
speak of a single collective will? Who could possibly interpret such a will?
Mouffe
I suppose you are right; "collective will" is a metaphor, and
it is not necessarily a very good one! It was obviously a reference to Gramsci. In
Gramsci the collective will is organized through the party on the basis of the he-
gemony of the proletariat. He believed that the working class necessarily provides
the articulating principle for an expansive hegemony. To import that notion into
my discourse creates a series of problems. Although I don't want to argue that the
working class can never be the articulating principle-of course, in some circum-
stances it might be-l do want to argue that it won't always be. While it may, under
certain historical conditions, develop the political capacity to represent the interests
of others, we can also imagine that in other circumstances another social movement
103
can be the center. We can also imagine that there might not be any center; there is
no reason why there should necessarily be a center of an expansive hegemony.
As a consequence, contrary to Gramsci, I do not believe that
the party-and I am not thinking only of the Leninist party, but of any party-will
necessarily be the agent of change. A party can be too authoritarian and too rigid
to articulate all those different movements so as to maintain their autonomy. On
the other hand, some people argue that once you question the necessary hegemony
of the party and the working class, you are left with pure diversity; they go on to
argue that there need not be any articulation of those struggles. But if you believe
there must be an articulating principle, and it is not provided by the party, where
will it be found? I think it is a mistake to look for one organization, the "good"
organization. We need to think in terms of the articulations that must take place.
Those forms of articulation will differ according to the country. For instance, I do
not believe that trade unions can always play an important role. They can play an
important role in France and Italy, but it is very unlikely that they can in England
or Germany.
So there are no recipes. Intellectuals must abandon the idea
that they have to tell the people how to organize, to design a blueprint for the "good"
organization. All spontaneous revolutions-such as those in Hungary and Poland-
have shown that people find their own form of organization. Each society must find
its own way of articulating its different struggles together. And there will be different
forms of articulation. So we can only use the Gramscian notion of a national col-
lective will, or a popular national will, in a metaphoric way. Like Rousseau's concept
of a general will, it can imply too much homogeneity.
Question
It seems to me that we are witnessing two different theoret-
ical moves in Marxism today, with different political consequences. The first is a
more traditional materialism and looks at the economic impact of and on discourse.
But it apparently results in political pessimism. The second, which seems to be yours,
privileges discourse as a way of transforming consciousness and agency. It gives a
more optimistic political prognosis, but it fails to connect discourse to actual social
groups and institutions. In that sense, it seems to be a new form of idealism. Could
you comment on this?
Mouffe
I must say that I cannot accept the opposition between ide-
alism and materialism-it doesn't pertain to my semantic world- and in that I think
I follow Gramsci. One can show that materialism is idealist, because to think that
there is only one principle of explanation, be it matter or ideas, is in fact the same
problematic. In any case, I don't understand what you mean by describing me as
idealist, especially since by discourse I understand not only speech and writing but
also a series of social practices, so discourse is not just a question of ideas. That
doesn't mean that the elaboration of a level of ideas is not important, which is why
I made the point about political philosophy. Here, again, I follow Gramsci who said
that philosophy, as ideology, permeates all levels of consciousness. Even common
sense is informed by philosophy. Philosophy is where the categories of thought are
elaborated, allowing us to speak about our experience. For example, many people
who have never read anything about democratic theory nevertheless speak and act
as political subjects on the basis of ideas elaborated by philosophers. That is why I
insist on that level of analysis. But I am not saying this is all we need. We won't
transform the world simply by writing the last word on equality. But it is important
in constructing new political subjects, so it is one dimension of the struggle.
104
Catharine A. MacKinnon
Notes
Note: MacKinnon refers at several points to papers presented at the conference on Marxism
and the Interpretation of Culture. Her reference to Michele Barrett's argument, however. is
not to Barrett's paper but to her response to Christine Delphy, which may be found on pp.
268-69. Though Stanley Aronowitz's and Stuart Hall's papers are considerably expanded,
they still deal with the issues to which MacKinnon alludes.
Catharine A MacKinnon, "Feminism, Marxism, Method and the State: An Agenda for Theory,"
Signs 7 ( 1982). pp. 515-44.
2 Cathanne A. MacKinnon, "Feminism, Marxism. Method and the State: Toward Feminist
Jurisprudence." Signs 8 ( 1983). pp. 635-58.
3 Diana E. H. Russell. Sexual Exploitation (Beverly Hills. Calif.: Sage Publications, 1984); Diana
E. H. Russell and Nancy Howell, "The Prevalence of Rape in the United States Revisited,"
Signs 4 ( 1983). p. 688.
4 On incest: D. Finkelhor, Child Sexual Abuse: Theory and Research (New York: Free Press,
1984); J. Herman, Father-Daughter Incest (Cambridge: Harvard University Press. 1981 ); J.
Renvo1se. Incest. A Family Pattern (Boston: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1982). On battery:
R. and E. Dobash. Violence agamst Wives (New York: Free Press, 1979); L. Walker, The
Battered Woman (New York: Harper, 1979); D. Russell, Rape in Marriage (New York: Mac-
millan. 1982). On prostitution: K. Barry, Female Sexual Slavery (Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Pren-
tice-Hall, 1979); P. Alexander, quoted in M. Griffin, "Wives. Hookers and the Law," Student
Lawyer, Jan. 1982, p. 18. On pornography: J. Cook, "The X-Rated Economy," Forbes,
1978, p. 18; M. Langelan, "The Political Economy of Pornography," Aegis, 1981, pp. 5-
17; A Dworkin, Pornography: Men Possessing Women (New York: Putnam's, 1979); L.
Lovelace and M. McGrady, Ordeal (Berkeley, Calif.: Berkeley Books, 1980). On murder: J.
Boudouris, "Homicide and the Fam1ly," Journal of Marriage and the Family, 33 (1971). pp.
667-71; E. G1bson and S. Klein, Murder 1957 to 1968 (London: HMSO, 1969); D. Molvihill,
M. Tumin, and L. Curtis, Crimes of Violence, Eleventh Report of the National Commission
on the Causes and Prevention of Violence, (Washington, D.C.: U.S. Government Printing
Office, 1969); L. Bowker. "The Criminal Victimization of Women," Victomology: An Inter-
natiOnal Journal, 4 ( 1979). pp. 371, 384.
5 N. Chodorow, The Reproduction of Mothering: Psychoanalysis and the Sociology of Gender
(Berkeley: University of California Press. 1978); D. Dinnerstein, The Mermaid and the Min-
otaur.· Sexual Arrangements and Human Malaise (New York: Harper, 1977).
116
Catharine A. MacKinnon
Discussion
(At the conference, Gayatri Spivak's talk immediately pre-
ceded Catharine MacKinnon's. Spivak, MacKinnon, and Ellen Willis were all on
stage during the discussion.)
117
the situation of right-wing women, Andrea Dworkin argues that they realize there
is no way out of this system of absolute male power and absolute female power-
lessness. Feminists who hold out for change apparently don't see the gravity of
women's situation; they have chosen to make an accommodation with that aspect
of the male power structure that they think offers them the best deal. So the issue
Catharine is raising has concrete consequences within the feminist movement and
for feminist activism.
My own view is that power is not a monolithic system but
a system of overlapping contradictions. Women have always struggled against their
situation both individually and collectively. They have seized on contradictions in
the system-demanding, for example, that the concept of human rights be applied
to women-thereby using the discontinuities in the system to mobilize for their own
power. And they have allied themselves with men when the ruling classes were seen
to be oppressing them both.
This suggests a Marxist understanding of power exercised
for the sake of particular interests, whereas the system Catharine has articulated-
the system of absolute male power and absolute female powerlessness-implies a
notion of power exercised for its own sake. Men get specific economic and social
benefits from male supremacy, including having a class of people devoted to meeting
their needs. Such interests also create a situation where the dominant class is de-
pendent on the subordinate class for meeting its needs, which gives the subordinate
class a certain opening wedge of power. Threatening to withhold meeting those needs,
organizing to meet those needs in their own way, and finally opting for broader
struggle. But if one has a notion of power exercised for its own sake, then this dialectic
does not apply; there is only the closed system of absolutes. Catharine's view of
feminism, indeed, requires a kind of metaphysics of power, of power exercised for
the sheer pleasure of it; in effect, a conflation of power and eroticism.
This brings us to the issue of sex. I would agree that the
manipulation and construction of our sexuality is central to the creation of gender.
Yet I also think it cannot be subsumed under gender relations. The construction of
sexuality underpins the entire culture's authoritarian relations; it influences the struc-
tures of class and race, of dominance and submission in general. Gender is a central
example of this, but not the only one. Here, my difference with Catharine is illustrated
by the fact that she talked about the eroticization of dominance and submission,
whereas I would talk about the politicization of Eros. I do believe there is an erotic
dimension that is bodily, physiological, and, in some sense, precultural. Sexual grat-
ification is one element of eroticism, which includes the infant's intense bodily
pleasure in eating. But I want to concentrate on sexuality, since it is the key political
issue in feminist debates.
The political differences between our two positions are pro-
found. If sex is simply a function of an all-pervasive male power, then there can be
no meaningful female sexuality. Within this closed system a woman who feels desire
and pleasure is really experiencing an abnegation of self. There seems to be a fun-
damental contradiction here. Is there such a thing as pleasure that is purely negative
and imposed? I would argue that, despite contexts of powerlessness that are bound
up with pleasure, pleasure nonetheless offers something like moments of self-affir-
mation or empowerment. This again contradicts the idea of absolute powerlessness.
There is a moment of autonomy and empowerment in the demand that one's needs
be gratified, in directly seizing pleasure. At the same time there is a moment of
surrender-loss of ego control and surrender to one's feelings. In a hierarchical society
these two elements are split and the moment of empowerment is confused and
conflated with dominance. And surrender is confused and conflated with submission.
This all comes to pass through the ways the culture manipulates one's sexuality, a
process in which the relations between parents and children are as salient as those
between men and women. In fact, our sexuality is constructed in the family and in
118
Catharine A. MacKinnon
the convergence of power relations between parents and children. These relations
are often hierarchical and oppressive in ways that cannot be subsumed within male
supremacy.
The division of eroticism-and the association of empow-
erment with dominance and of surrender with submission-occurs in both sexes,
but there are differences in how this division is fantasized and acted out socially.
Women often cannot overtly seek empowerment, even as men cannot overtly seek
surrender, but both sexes covertly seek that to which they are not overtly entitled.
Rape fantasies exemplify this pattern, to the extent that the man overtly identifies
with the rapist but also, on some level, secretly identifies with the victim, while the
woman may overtly identify with the victim but can also secretly identify with the
rapist. None of this, of course, detracts at all from the fact that it is men who have
the opportunity to act out dominance; men's confusion of empowerment and sexual
pleasure with dominance wreaks great devastation on women. At the same time,
however, it is important to realize that sex is not monolithic; it's a minefield of all
these contradictions; it's an area of struggle. Sex is not entirely given over to oppres-
sion and thus women are not limited to refusing compliance. Every time women
demand their own pleasure-despite the contradictions that may entail within het-
erosexuality-it is a moment of empowerment and liberation and a kind of wedge
into struggle in other areas. In fact, the contradiction in male sexuality-the per-
version of empowerment into dominance and the compulsion to repress the impulse
to surrender-brings a real loss of pleasure. Forcing men to realize this provides
another way into fighting male power generally.
Within the closed system of male power, heterosexuality
simply becomes a scenario of dominance and submission, and sex and rape become
indistinguishable. At that point, rape is hardly worth singling out as an issue. I see
sexuality as a more complicated set of dynamics, as a contested terrain, not a static
area of oppression. It involves the channeling of eroticism and all the culturally
produced fantasies of dominance and submission. Yet there is also a utopian aspect
to sexuality. Part of the heterosexual impulse, for example, has to do with the desire
to transcend the antagonism between men and women. Men experience this but
want to have it both ways-to maintain their power while transcending the antag-
onism, an impossibility. Women's sexuality has an undercurrent ofhope-ofgetting
men to give up their power. Even as a fantasy, it shows that part of women's sexuality
is self-assertive rather than accommodating. The cultural fantasies of intercourse as
merger and transcendence are just as real as the cultural fantasies of violation.
Moreover, on some level the fantasies of merger prefigure political possibilities. This
is not, however, intended to urge the virtues of individualism but rather to suggest
what contradictions the women's liberation movement is working on.
MacKinnon
On the issue of my effort to open up the structure of the
conference, let me say that I don't see what I did as even remotely adequate to the
critique that I suggested. I don't pretend to have made us all free. I do think, however,
that a certain kind of knowledge is created under certain conditions, and that this
conference has reproduced those conditions. Those conditions include the maleness
of the authority of the position that I'm in; but I don't imagine that, as a feminist,
I'm going around making everyone free. I'm acknowledging how the structures we're
living out right here and now are part of the cultural structures that are the topic
of my talk. I don't pretend that I changed them.
Now, as to my concept of power. I don't think of power as
something that floats freely, like some looming omnipresence, precultural or other-
wise, and then takes specific forms. In other words, I don't think of power as some-
thing that just is and then becomes economic, racial, sexual, and finally individual.
I think of power only as a socially constituted meaning, as existing only in its social
forms. I use male power to refer to what men have appropriated and arrogated to
themselves in a way that I take to be authoritative. If I don't speak of countering
male power with female power it's because that suggests we are already equal. That's
119
why I resist using a term like "female power" at all; indeed, I rarely use "female"
except to refer to biological issues. I guess I use "male" because I've so carefully
given it a social meaning, not because I think it is biological. It isn't that women
have no ways to resist, because obviously we do. But calling these resistances "power"
is misleading because they're a form of powerlessness. The reason we don't exhibit
"power" is because, whenever we do, we get pushed back into line in ways that are
forcible, painful, and depriving.
Of course, subliminal to much of this discussion is the work
of Andrea Dworkin, in particular Pornography: Men Possessing Women and Right-
Wing Women. As to the critique that Dworkin's work promotes a politics of despair,
I would suggest that the same critique would have to be made of Stuart Hall's analysis
of Thatcherism. In other words, Dworkin's analysis of right-wing women is very
similar to the one Stuart Hall made of people who choose Thatcherism; that is, they
are, at least in part, under conditions where they choose survival over militancy.
Yet it's difficult to understand the meaningfulness of the term "choice" under con-
ditions of constraint. So, either these are conditions of constraint we're talking about
or they're not. Either we operate under a condition where certain choices are he-
gemonically defined and other choices are blocked or we do not. I'm glad to hear
Ellen Willis say, for example, that she thinks Eros is in some sense precultural,
because I think that's implicit in much of the argument that stands against the
argument I make, in which sexuality is cultural to the ground. It's a lot easier to see
freedom of choice operative in your sexuality if the ground you're standing on is
partly precultural as well as in part constrained by culture. Now I see these choices
as operating within a closed system, not an absolute system, but one that is closed,
rigid, and imposed. I don't like the reality of this system; neither the system nor my
analysis of it give me pleasure.
In my overall project, what I would like to do is to redefine
what it means to be human (a concept now dominated by maleness) so that it includes
a revaluing of everything that women have always done but that has been relegated
to femaleness or the feminine. In addition, I would like to work toward a transfor-
mation in the content of what being human refers to, so that it can be something
to which women as well will want to aspire. A radical feminism involves not merely
taking on those things that men have always done but instead transforming the
content of those things in the light of women's experience.
Question
I would like to ask that you address the issue of homosex-
uality and place it in the context of your work.
120
Catharine A. MacKinnon
MacKinnon
The issue of choice is particularly relevant to issues of ho-
mosexuality. I cannot, for example, make a lot of sense out of what people call the
choice of heterosexuality; it's like saying you choose to be a capitalist or a worker.
I can understand the choice to be with a particular man who is engaged in a struggle
against the dominant male sexuality. A choice that goes against the dominant culture
is a real choice. A choice to be a lesbian, however, is different from a choice to be
a gay man. For women to choose to affirm other women, both in terms of gender
and sexuality, is very different from the choice to be a gay male. A choice to be a
gay man can represent seeing through the way sex roles have made heterosexuality
compulsory and thus be an affirmation of the feminist struggle. But it can also be
an extension of the male bond, the ultimate conclusion of heterosexuality: men come
first, men are better in every way, so why not also sexually? Yet some gay men may
make this choice because they don't want to oppress women. In other words, so
long as something in fact works against the structure of male supremacy and male
dominance, I'm willing to countenance that the word "choice" begins to apply to
it.
121
Paul Patton
Notes
See espectally Stanley Aronowttz. The Crisis in Historical Materialism (New York: Praeger,
1981 ); Alex Callinicos. Is There a Future for Marxism? (London: Macmillan, 1982); Russell
Jacoby, D1alectic of Defeat (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981 ). Barry Smart,
Foucault, Marxism and Critique (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1983), discusses much
of this literature and the relationship of Foucault's work to contemporary marxism. There are
also many arttcles on th1s theme, beginning with Althusser's address to the II Manifesto
conference ( 1977), repnnted in Power and Revolution in Societies (London: Ink Links, 1979).
Cf. P. Sweezy, "A Crisis 1n Marxtan Theory," Monthly Review, 31:2 (1979); E. Altvater and
0. Kallscheur, "Soctaltst Politics and the Cris1s in Marxism," The Socialist Reg1ster (1979).
2 Ernesto Laclau and Chantal Mouffe, "Socialist Strategy-Where Next?" Marxism Today,
25:1 (1981)
134
Paul Patton
3 Callimcos. p. 3.
4 Callinicos, p. 111.
5 M1fle Plateaux (Paris: Editions Minuit, 1980). The introduction, "Rhizome," appears in De-
leuze and Guattari, On the Lme (New York: Semiotext[e]. 1983). An earlier version, published
separately, is translated in Ideology and ConsCiousness, 8 ( 1981)
6 Notably Mia Campioni and Elizabeth Gross. "Love's Labours Lost: Marxism and Feminism,"
in Beyond Marxism? Interventions after Marx, ed. Judith Allen and Paul Patton (Sydney:
Intervention Publications, 1983). A clear case for the methodological and political importance
of an autonomous femin1st theory was put forth by Christine Delphy in "Pour un feminism
materialiste," 1n L'Arc, 61:6 (1975). an issue devoted to Simone de Beauvoir.
7 Callinicos, chap. 8.
8 Callimcos. pp. 160-62.
9 Anti-Oedipus (New York: Viking Press, 1977), pt. 3, sees. 9, 10. In Mille Plateaux, the authors
insist on the nonmetaphorical character of this comparison: "It IS the real characteristics of
axiomatic systems which enable one to say that capitalism and current politics are literally
a system of axioms" (pp. 576-77).
10 On the Lme, p. 3; a slightly different rendering of the same passage is given in Ideology and
Consciousness, 8, p. 50.
11 Andre Glucksmann, La cuisiniere et le mangeur d'hommes (Paris: Seuil, 1975).
12 See The Left Academy, ed. B. Oilman and E. Vernoff (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1982).
13 Gregor Mclennan, Marxism and the Methodologies of History (London: New Left Books,
1981). p. 233. For examples of this kind of response to non-marxist feminism, see Michele
Barrett, Women's Oppression Today (London: New Left Books, 1980). and the discussion
in Jud1th Allen, "Marxism and the Man Question: Some Implications of the Patriarchy De-
bate." in Beyond Marxism? Interventions after Marx.
14 Franco1s Ewald, "Anatom1e et corps politiques," Critique, 343 (1975), p. 1246.
15 Aronow1tz. p. 26.
16 Aronowitz, pp. 59-60.
17 She1la Rowbotham, Lynne Segal, and Hilary Wainwright, Beyond the Fragments: Feminism
and the Making of Socialism (London: Merlin Press, 1980). p. 5. A similar argument is
developed in the concluding passages of the article by Laclau and Mouffe (see note 2).
18 Callinicos. p. 133.
19 Compare the explanation offered for the relative weakness of the autonomous social move-
ments in France and the strength of the extrapolitical opposition in West Germany in A.
Touraine, "State and Soc1al Forces in Socialist France." Telos, 55 (1983). The vitality of
the German "scene" is evident in The German Issue, 4:2 (1982).
20 In a more recent article, Aronowitz continues to campaign for a "social and cultural left"
umfied at the most general level by its challenge to "the capitalist domination of nature."
The prospects for such a "social ecology" movement, however, are more circumspectly
expressed. See Stanley Aronowitz, "Socialism and Beyond: Remaking the American Left.
Pt. I," Socialist Rev1ew, 69 ( 1983).
21 Stuart Hall raised an objection of this kind in his opening night address to this conference,
arguing for the importance of a global analysis of hegemony, where this is understood as
the punctual alignment of social forces in a given conjuncture. It is not clear that he needed
to do this, smce pointmg to specific connections between, say, the reconstitution of social
relations such that late capitalism can survive in Britian and the reinforcement of patriarchy
does not require any systematic homogeneity between these two objects. For a classic
example of th1s kind of response to Foucault, see Nicos Poulantzas. State, Power. Socialism
(London: New Left Books. 1980), pp. 67-68.
22 This is evident in Gerard Raulet, "The Agony of Marxism and the Victory of the Left," Telos.
55 ( 1983). where in the context of arguing for the need for a new political rationality as part
of a process of resoc1alizat10n, it is asserted that, "in contrast to the dominant modality of
consensus which only gives us a pseudo-consensus, both unfree and manipulated, a new
political culture is needed which will develop a totalizing strategy that takes differences as
its starting point. This strategy must be a totalizing one because the new rationality-a non-
reductive rationality-can no longer tolerate a purely dualistic mode of existence which JUX-
taposes technical rationality and traditional symbols" (p. 177).
23 An account of modern philosophy as a state form is given in Richard Rorty, Philosophy and
the Mirror of Nature (Princeton: Princeton University Press. 1979). Paul Feyerabend, in a
recent discussion of the relationship between theory and practice, distinguishes between
135
the position of participant and that of observer in relation to any well articulated practice,
whether it be artistic, political, or ecclesiastical. In the philosophy of science, this distinction
covers the difference between the philosopher and the practicing scientist. Much of the force
of Feyerabend's attack on theories of scientific method rests upon his appeal to the position
of participant. He is, of course, too kind to the philosophers in describing their position as
merely that of observers who only want to know what is going on. See Paul Feyerabend,
Science in a Free Society (london: New Left Books, 1978). pp. 18-19.
136
Paul Patton
Discussion
Question (Peter Rose)
Don't you think we need a theoretical and strategic basis for
creating linkages between different progressive movements? If they are left in con-
stant isolation and nomadism, they are susceptible to various kinds of co-optation
and differentiation that may not ultimately be progressive. In fact, without some
common ground, what basis is there for judging a particular movement to be pro-
gressive?
Patton
I was not rejecting any attempt to find a common ground
but rather the claim of certain totalizing perspectives to define the only possible
form of coding for these new social movements. Certainly one of the consequences
of the view of micropolitics that I alluded to as a political strategy would be to find
and encourage productive and broadly effective connections between these move-
ments. The example that I referred to in passing-the interest of certain British
women in peace and antinuclear movements-seems to me a very good example
of the connection between two specific concerns but one that doesn't require any
particular global political framework.
137
Comment (Nancy Fraser)
I disagree on a number of points on the question of the
relation of theory and practice. I want to defend a certain kind of totalizing theory
by making a sharper distinction than you do between theory and practice. I do this
not to defend traditional Marxism because, ironically, traditional Marxism too closely
connects them in a way somewhat homologous with your position. Let me put it
this way: You seem to want to argue directly from a style of theorizing to the kind
of politics that follow from it. You claim that totalizing, monocausal, empirical
theories somehow necessarily lead to Stalinist-Leninist centralized forms of political
practice, and that if we stand back from such theoretical practices, we are guaranteed
a democratic, pluralistic political practice. It seems to me that theory and practice
don't have that kind of close connection. One way I might get at this is to raise a
hypothetical question: What if it should tum out that some monocausal, empirical
theory of society could actually have a real explanatory power in accounting for
more phenomena than other available theories? You seem to say we can't choose
that style of theorizing because the politics are bad. It is logically conceivable that
such a theory might, in fact, be able to tell us things and that we would still have
all kinds of political choices. Our political responses are not determined by the style
of our theorizing in that close way. Let me put it another way: I think there are at
least three kinds of critical theorizing that we need. First, an empirical, critical theory
of what is happening in contemporary society, of where the tendencies for crisis are,
of what the possibilities for change are. This should be as absolutely broad and as
explanatorily powerful as we can make it. Second, we need the kind of normative
political theory that Chantal Mouffe talked about: theorizing about what kinds of
institutions we want to guarantee plurality and difference and nomadism and all
those things you want-that is a political question. And finally, we need a critique
of ideology of the sort that Deleuze, Foucault, and Derrida have been developing.
In other words, I want to detotalize critical theory in order to argue that some parts
should be as totalized as possible.
Patton
The question of the relationship between theory and practice
is the important one, and it can be taken up in a variety of ways. I wasn't talking
about the political consequences that flow from certain kinds of theory-the usual
sense in which marxist discussions of the relationship are carried on. I was, rather,
treating them, insofar as they can be treated as distinct domains, on the same plane
and talking about a homology between a politics of theory and political practice. In
that sense, what I am objecting to in a style of theorizing are the effects that it has
on our ability to theorize. In particular, I am objecting to the way in which certain
conceptions of the nature of theory impose limitations, close out the possibility of
alternative theorizations. (One only has to look at the debates between marxists,
marxist-feminists, and other kinds of feminists to see how it operates.) It is that
politics of theory that was my concern.
And I agree with your plea for a certain kind of totality and
the need for an understanding of society as a whole. The distinction I made between
the two senses in which one can say that a perspective is totalizing was directed in
part at that, since the kind of totalization I was objecting to was not the totalizing
of a powerful, universalizable general theory (although it is a further question of
how likely it is that we would ever find a theory that would apply to social phenomena
in general). I was objecting to the view that if we have a powerful general theory
like that, then there is no need to encourage alternatives; that, indeed, the fact of
its being powerful and strongly explanatory should be taken as an argument against
the elaboration of alternatives. In that sense, the politics of theory that I am defending
is very close to the kind of epistemological pluralism that Feyerabend defends. And
my response to your hypothetical question-What would we do if we had such a
138
Paul Patton
powerful theory?-would be the same as Feyerabend's: we should still encourage the
search for alternatives because it is only on that basis that criticism is possible.
Indeed, a society in which one dominant mode of explanation or theoretical form
is imposed, taught, and funded for research is undemocratic in the realm of ideas.
139
A. Belden Fields
Conclusion
One of the major advantages of a dialectical approach is its em-
phasis upon the concept of mediation of apparently contradictory social
currents. When that concept of mediation is ignored, the way is paved for
rigid dichotomizations and an opting for one side or the other. "Workerist"
approaches and "new social movement" approaches as mutually exclusive
options strike me as equally baseless. We ought not to turn away from the
most dogmatic interpretations of the base/superstructure metaphor only to
walk into another metaphoric trap that prioritizes language or discourse and
constructs theory-proof roofs over local sites of contestation.
I would like to make two other observations. First, at least from
the U.S. perspective, it is a bit late to be talking about new social movements
in the way Habermas and Patton do, because imperialism has reached such
an aggressive pitch in the policies of the overtly ideological Reagan admin-
istration. Particularly by its actions in Central America, its prioritization of
the military and business sectors, and its cutbacks on domestic programs
to aid the worst off, that administration has clearly demonstrated the dis-
tributive systemic stakes involved in imperialistic behavior and their re-
lationship to the structures of capitalism, racism, and patriarchy at home.
As opposed to the seventies, when imperialism took more subtle and less
154
A. Belden Fields
militaristic forms, an anti-imperialist movement has arisen whose function
is to show the practical and theoretical implications of this phenomenonY
Second, the thrust of micrologic analysis is toward a single-issue
strategic approach, precisely the opposite of the above anti-imperialist ap-
proach. Within the U.S. context, the micrologic approach receives strong
support from the "ideology of practicality." One of the major ways by which
U.S. political culture has been rendered nonideological is precisely by the
emphasis placed upon local, short-term results and the correlation of such
"success" with micrologic strategies. Thus, Martin Luther King, Jr., was
severely criticized for jeopardizing possible advances in civil rights when
he criticized the war effort in Indochina. This micrologic approach frustrates
systemic analyses which reveal dynamics in the political economy that are
not otherwise obvious to those who think and act in purely compartment-
alized terms. The kind of theorizing done by pluralists in the political science
discipline has been a scientific discourse that reinforces compartmentalized
thinking and delegitimizes systemic, political economy approaches by la-
beling them unscientific "ideologies." 48 It would be sad and ironic if the
same tendency were to arise from the ranks of neo-Marxists today when
the strategic stakes in the anti-imperialist struggle are at a more acute level.
Notes
1 The CFDT is the second largest labor confederation in France. It is characterized by a strong
attachment to the concept of worker control over industry (autogestion).
2 Michel Foucault. "Revolutionary Action: 'Unttl Now,"' Language, Counter-Memory, Practice,
trans. Donald Bouchard and Sherry Simon (Ithaca Cornell University Press, 1977). p. 230.
3 Michel Foucault, The Archaeology of Knowledge, trans. A. M. Shendan Smith (New York:
Harper and Row. 1972). p. 107.
4 Michel Foucault, "Prison Talk," Power/Knowledge, trans. Colin Gordon et. al. (New York:
Pantheon Books, 1972). p 52.
5 Foucault, The Archaeology of Knowledge, p. 162.
6 Foucault. "The Eye of Power." Power/Knowledge, p. 159.
7 Foucault. Power/Knowledge, p. 159.
8 Foucault. "Intellectuals in Power," Language, Counter-Memory, Practice, p. 216.
9 Foucault, "Two Lectures." Power/Knowledge, p. 99.
10 Foucault. Language, Counter-Memory, Practice, p. 231.
11 Foucault. Language, Counter-Memory, Practice, p. 230.
12 Foucault, Language, Counter-Memory, Practice, p. 231.
13 Foucault, "Power and Strategies," Power/Knowledge, p. 142.
14 Foucault, Power/Knowledge, p. 145.
15 Foucault. Power/Knowledge, p. 107.
16 On La Gauche Proletarienne see A. Belden Fields, "French Maoism." in Sohnya Sayres et
al., eds., The 60s without Apology (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1984). and
Ftelds, Trotskyism and Maoism: Theory and Practice in France and the United States (New
York: Praeger and Autonomedia, 1987).
17 Foucault, "On Popular Justice: A Discussion wtth Maoists," Power/Knowledge, p. 1.
18 Foucault, Power/Knowledge, p. 28.
19 JOrgen Habermas. Legitimation Crisis, trans. Thomas McCarthy (Boston: Beacon Press, 1973).
p. 3.
20 Habermas, Legitimation Crisis, p. 4.
155
21 In this sense, I think that the theorizing of Anthony Giddens represents an advance over that
of Habermas. Giddens takes care to introduce the "acting" subject into his theory of "struc-
turation." See Central Problems in Social Theory (Berkeley and Los Angeles: University of
California Press, 1979).
22 JOrgen Habermas, "New Social Movements," Telos 49 (1981). p. 33.
23 Habermas, "New Social Movements," p. 33.
24 Habermas, "New Social Movements," pp. 33-34.
25 Habermas, "New Social Movements," p. 34.
26 Habermas, "New Social Movements." p. 35.
27 Habermas, "New Social Movements," p. 35.
28 Habermas, "New Social Movements," p. 37.
29 Habermas, "New Social Movements," p. 34.
30 See Ronald lnglehart, "The Silent Revolution in Europe: lntergenerational Change in Post-
Industrial Societies," American Political Science Review 65:4 ( 1971), pp. 991-1017, and
The Silent Revolution (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1977).
31 Chantal Mouffe, "Discussion," in this volume, p. 104.
32 Ernesto Laclau, "Populist Rupture and Discourse," Screen Education, no. 34 (1980), p.
89.
33 Laclau, p. 90.
34 Chantal Mouffe, "Hegemony and New Political Subjects: Toward a New Concept of De-
mocracy," in this volume, p. 94.
35 Mouffe, "Hegemony and New Political Subjects," pp. 95-96.
36 Mouffe, "Hegemony and New Political Subjects," p. 98.
37 Mouffe, "Hegemony and New Political Subjects," p. 100.
38 Mouffe, "Hegemony and New Political Subjects," p. 99.
39 Barry Hindess and Paul Hirst. Mode of Production and Social Formation.· An Auto-critique of
Pre-capitalist Modes of Production (London: Macmillan, 1977).
40 Paul Patton, "Marxism and Beyond: Strategies of Reterntorialtzation," tn thts volume, p. 131.
41 Patton, p. 133.
42 See Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopta (New York: Basic Books, 1974).
43 Patton, p. 133.
44 Patton, p. 131.
45 Patton, p. 131 .
46 For a classic study of this see Michael Parenti, "Power and Pluralism: A View from the
Bottom," in Marvin Surkin and Alan Wolfe, eds., An End to Political Science (New York:
Basic Books, 1970), pp. 111-43.
47 I deal more explicitly with this in "U.S. Anti-imperialist Movements in Two Contexts: The
War in Indochina and the Intervention in Central America," Scandanavian Journal of Devel-
opment Alternatives 5:23 (1986), pp. 209-46.
48 See, for example, Nelson W. Polsby, Community Power and Political Theory (New Haven:
Yale University Press, 1963). where class, elite, and stratification theories are attacked from
an empirical, "scientific" perspective. This was written before there was even an explicitly
Marxist body of literature in U.S. political science.
156
II Toward a Contemporary Marxism
Etienne Balibar
See Alain Badiou, Theorie du SUJet (Paris: Seuil, 1982) and his presentation on January 1 7,
1983, at the Ecole Norm ale Superieure (to appear in Re)Ouer le politique. Ill, Ed1t1ons Galilee).
2 I leave aside the very interesting question of Marx's retrieval of the term "ideology" from
the French sensualist ideologues and the distortion it undergoes in the process.
3 In this schematic account there is one notable exception: the reference made in the preface
of A Contribution to the Critique of Political Economy to the "ideological forms" identified
with "social consciousness." This text is explicitly retrospective, alluding in particular to The
German Ideology, whose persistent trace it carries. But its importance lies elsewhere. It
teaches us nothing about ideology in any direct way, unless about its insistence within
Marxism, even at the cost of the most outright conceptual indeterminacy (see the theme of
··correspondence'').
4 The classic French translation (Roy's) obscures the conceptual precision of fetishism in Cap-
Ital. The recent publication, after a long delay, of J. P. Lefebvre's translation, by Editions
Sociales, provides a definitive text for this question and others.
5 It is, however, important to note that the materialism of The German Ideology does not relate
to the idea of matter, that 1t is a "materialism without matter," because it is nonsubstantial.
See also the Theses on Feuerbach.
6 Marx is neither the first nor the last philosopher to take up the problem of the production of
idealities, or the process of idealization, in this overdetermined form (see Spinoza before and
Freud after). It is remarkable that these three intellectual efforts, clearly related but formulated
within entirely d1fferent concepts, have actually surfaced Independently and heterogeneously.
Marx read Spinoza closely; but by way of an astonishing quid pro quo, inscribed within the
tradition of the Aufklarung, and in his struggle against romantic pantheism. he has only seen
in Spinoza an apology for rationalism and democracy. On this point see A. Matheron, "Le
traite theologico-politique vu par le jeune Marx," Cahiers Spinoza, 1 ( 1977).
7 This identification of the place of theory with the place of practice must be given as already
there. But 1t IS, more accurately than my hasty presentation suggests, in the vein of a tendency
that Marx seeks to define 1t after a fashion itself historical-a tendency toward the simulta-
neous breakup of manual labor and intellectual labor specifically, and hence the1r distance
or divergence. See my study "Sur le concepte marxiste de Ia 'division du travail manuel et
intellectuel' et Ia lutte de classes." in Manuels et intellectuels dans le transition au socialisme,
ed. Jean Belkhir (Paris: Editions Anthropos, 1985).
8 Both Marx and Engels bear witness to the true answer: we have seen this proletariat radically
stripped of ideology. See The Condition of the Working Class in England: "I discovered that
you were much more than members of an insular nation who would only be English: I have
affirmed that you were men. "
9 It is tempting to explain, in addition to editorial rejections and the difficulties suffered in these
troubled times through the insecurity of their personal situations, that Marx and Engels aban-
doned The German Ideology "to the nibbling critique of the mice."
10 I have tried to show elsewhere that this analysis, in spite of its dialectical power, and because
it is offered in the form of a simple demonstration of the logic of commodities, had to become,
for Marxism, a lasting obstacle to the analysis of economic ideology as the dominant 1deology,
or the ideology of the state. And so it has, paradoxically, encouraged the "return" of the
economic "repressed" in this economism, one repeated Indefinitely ever since as the "return
to the young Marx" (in Ludwig Feuerbach and the End of Class1cal German Philosophy).
11 I am thinking of a contemporary example, the "episteme" of Michel Foucault, and more
generally of the universals of the culturalists.
12 Indeed, Marx, who is faithful on this point to his own German ideology, suggests that the
proletariat alone can save the classical culture of humanity (Homer, Dante, Shakespeare)
from its degeneration into bourgeois philistlnism (see the 185 7 introduction to the Critique
of Political Economy).
13 It is an analysis that is in no way mechanistic. Preceding the Lenin of the articles on Tolstoy
and the Mao of Talks at the Yenan Forum, 1t already implies the distinction (and the articulation)
of existence (or origin) from class and class positions, hence the analysis of their conjunctures.
14 This is a reformism in which, it should be noted, Marx and Engels explicitly place the 1dea
of the "transformation of the State as the simple administration of production."
15 Hence, the dominant model in Marx's thought regarding this strategy 1s that of a "permanent
revolution" which offers the long-term transformation of bourgeois revolutions into proletarian
revolutions and the short-term transformation of the radical democratic program into the
communist program (because the polarization of the class struggle nullifies the petite bourgeoisie
204
Etienne Balibar
as an autonomous force). See Stanley Moore, Three Tactics, the Background in Marx (New
York: Monthly Review Press, 1963) and my article, "Dictature du proletariat." in Dictionnaire
critique du marxisme, ed. G. Labica and G. Bensussan (Paris: P.U.F , 1982).
16 Another symptom of th1s disintegration is the generalization in the 1850s (when Marx was
pondering the "immaturity" of the proletanat) of the conceptual pair class in itself/class for
itself. which works symmetncally as much for the bourgeoisie as for the proletariat. the two
"revolutionary classes" of history. But th1s is preceded, in the Manifesto, by a return to a
"conspiracy" theory, a purely instrumentalist one, of the law as the will of the ruling class:
"Your law is only the will of your class worked into the law, a will whose content is determined
by the concrete conditions of existence of your class."
17 See Raison Presente, 66 ( 1983).
18 The first version of the following analyses took the form of a presentation on May 17, 1980,
in the research seminar on the history of materialism led by Oliver Bloch at the Universite de
Paris I. I would like to thank G. Labica. B. Lacorra, Cl. Ma1nfoy, S. Mercier-Josa, M. Pecheux,
J. Texier, and E. Walter for observations that have been very useful to me in preparing this
study.
19 Although the pairs abstract/concrete and thought/real are not strictly commutative, Engels's
formulations on this are clearly more empiricial than those of Marx in the 185 7 introduction
(unpublished) to the Critique of Political Economy, where it is the scientific method. inasmuch
as it proceeds from the abstract to the "concrete of thought," that seems to engender the
real. start1ng from the concept. and thus creates an idealistic illusion. In his cntical reading
of Hegel, Marx touches on the idea of the conditions and ideological effects inherent in
scientific practice itself, but he does not use the term.
20 From the Grundrisse to the Cntique of the Gotha Program. by way of books 1 and 3 of Capital,
Marx presents a similar critical analysis of the categones "liberty" and "equality" as an
internal reflection of production and commodity circulation, which produces (for example. in
the chapter on commodity fetishism) a comparison between Juridical and religious idealities
(or abstractions) and a substitution of one for the other within history. However, what is never
really clear in Marx is whether the law is itself ideological or whether it is better to make a
distinction between law (property, contract, etc.) and juridical ideology (liberty and equality).
21 See the examples given in "ldeologie," in Geschichtliche Grundbeariffe, Brunner. Conze, and
Koselleck, eds. (Stuttgart: Band 2, 1978).
22 The problem of terminology which Engels comes across here is far from idiosyncratic. At
th1s same time, French positivists like Littre also posit a substitution of "worldview" for
"philosophy" in order to designate the form in which, unconsciously and spontaneously, the
positivist spirit becomes self-conscious and systematic (I owe this information to E. Coumet).
23 Remember that in this period Marx was the first to make a reference to the dialectic (and
not only in matenallsm). See the postface to the second German edition of Capital (1872),
where some of his formulations are rather close to the conclusions of the Critique of Political
Economy published by Engels in 1859.
24 On the use of this term and on the ambivalence of the relations first Marx and then Engels
have with it. see G. Hapt's detailed account. "Marxe il marxismo," in E. Hobsbawm et al.,
Storia del marxismo (Einaudi, vol. 1). On the crisis of Marxism, seeR. Racinaro, La cris1 del
marxismo (Bari: De Donato, 1976); H. J. Steinberg, "II partito e Ia formaziore dell' ortodossie
marxiste," 1n Storia del marxismo, vol. 2.
The question of knowing whether the older Engels effected a change in point
of view or still mainta1ned. as Ch. Andler believes ("Fragment d'une etude sur Ia decom-
position du marxisme," Revue socialiste, 1913). "two successive systems" has been the
object of contemporary debates. See, lastly, the absorbing study of Oskar Negt, "II marxismo
e Ia teoria della rivoluzione nell' ultimo Engels," in Storia del marxismo, vol. 2. Although in
complete agreement with the idea of a critical application of historical materialism to its own
history (of the sort already performed by Korsch). and hence of a program of material analys1s
of the working class. I cannot agree with Negt that the latter ought to take the form of a
"critique of the political economy of the force of labor," nor, a fortiori, of an "application of
the law of value" to this critique. This would involve a special discussion, primarily about the
meaning and the lim1ts of validity for an identification of ''force of labor'' as a ··commodity'·-
in short, about the reading of Capital.
25 See the essential article by Engels, "Notwendige und Oberflussige Gesellschaftsklassen,"
Marx-Engels Werke, vol. 21 .
26 F. A. Langue's Histoire du materialisme, which represents the union between Marxist, neo-
Kantian, and Darwinian circles, was published in 1866. 0 Bloch's commentary on it clearly
shows that while Engels rejects its epistemological theses, he does borrow a plan from it.
or rather a historical project It is with Dilthey, at the end of the century, as we know, that
the term Weltanschauung, of Romantic origin (Schelling, Schleiermacher) becomes the
205
watchword of the philosophy of history and hermeneutics developed by the vitalist and sub-
Jectivist currents of neo-Kantlanism against the rationalist currents (from Cohen to Cassirer).
27 The idea of a history of thought. understood in th1s way, obviously leads to several interpre-
tations or programs of research: that of an empirical history of the sciences and their effects
upon philosophy; that of a history of theories of the sort proposed by Althusser in Reading
Capital. in reviving an expression of Hegel's; and. finally, that of a history of class struggle
w1thin theory, ultimately considered by the same Althusser as the proper terrain of philosophy
(see Lenm and Philosophy, Positions) and wh1ch we will come across later on in taking up
the difficulties of Engels's text.
28 The study by B. Kedrov. "Engels et ses pn§decesseurs," La classification des sciences. val.
1 (French translation of the 1977 Russian edition). is unfortunately fiawed by his persistent
desire to present Engels's thinking in terms of "the Marxist solution" to "the problem of the
classification of the sciences." It seems. by contrast. that there are some original ideas to
be found in the highly documented study by Sven Eric Liedman. Motsatsernas Spel: The
Philosophy of Engels and Nineteenth-Century Science (Lund: Bo Cavefors Bokforlag. 1977).
but I have only been able to consult a short resume of it in English.
29 G. Canguilheim. G. Lapassado. J. Piquemal. J. Ulmann. "Du developpement !'evolution a
au XIXe siecle," Thales. annee 1960. special 1ssue (Paris: P.U.F .. 1962). is far and away
the most rigorous study of the history and concepts of evolutionism before and after Darwin.
30 A stnk1ng illustration of this theme can be found in H. G. Wells. A Short History of the World.
which tells the story of humanity starting from the formation of the solar system and ending
with socialism.
31 See G. Canguilheim. ldeologie et rationalite dans /'histoire des sciences de Ia vie (Paris: Vrin.
1977). Canguilheim's work (see also Thales) proves that it is impossible to discuss evolu-
tionism as such; rather. we must speak of evolutionisms (Lamarck. Comte. Spenser. Darwin.
Haeckel) according to their .. constants" and their incompatibilities-what Foucault aptly char-
acterizes as "points of heresy" in The Order of Things-and also the totally different effects
produced by the inscription of evolutionist statements within theoretical/experimental or spec-
ulative fields. The studies of Y Conry and D. Lecourt. particularly those in Raison Presente.
no. 66. seem to me to subscribe clearly to this point of view.
32 We can read Engels's "historical" account in the following way (see. e.g., particularly in
Dialectics of Nature. the text entitled "Old Preface to the Anti-Duhring"): ( 1) Greek dialectic.
(2) classical metaphysics. (3) modern dialectic; or this way: ( 1) the abstract unity of dialectic
and ("phys1cal") materialism. (2) the division of dialectic from materialism, (3) a new concrete
unity of dialectic and (historical) materialism; or finally: ( 1) the unity of philosophy and the
sciences (within the sphere of philosophy). (2) the division of philosophy (speculation) and
the sciences (empiricism). (3) the new unity of philosophy and the sc1ences (within the sphere
of the sciences).
33 Paradoxically, thought only avoids this autonomization when it is "false," a dialectical idea
we could use to rect1fy the teleological conceptions of knowledge (in material terms. the
"falsity" is the "truthful" element). but only on the condition that it no longer be presented
in the form of a failure or an objection. Nonetheless. it is in Anti-Duhring, in response to the
"eternal verities" of positivism (this critique is also made of Haeckel). that Engels comes to
terms with the Hegelian critique of the "moral opposition between truth and error," that is.
the critique of the classical metaphysical dualism of knowledge. preserved intact by positivism.
It is only 1n this indirect manner that the practical and the political point of view are found to
be represented.
34 See in particular "Bruno Bauer und das Urchistentum" ( 1882). in Marx-Engels Werke. val.
19. which constructs a parallel between modern ideologies. those of the ancient world
(philosophical and. above all. JUridical). and those of the medieval world (theological and
generally clerical). All these texts were first published in Neue Zeit. Kautsky' s review and the
bastion of orthodox Marxism.
35 This reduction is the grand proof. the unflaggingly repeated Marxist argument as it is practiced
by Conrad Schmidt. Lafargue. or Kautsky. It involves, on the one hand. retracing the origin
of the philosophical categories garnered by Engels (the distinction between simple causality
and reciprocal action. first articulated by Kant) and. on the other. giving some idea of its
afterlife (particularly in Gramsci and Sartre. who both consistently rework Engels's outline).
36 Let us judge the extent of this progress in relation to Marx's formulations in Capital. where
it is the regulative intervention of the state (the legislation of the manufacturers) that is given
as the "conscious reaction" of society to its own "organism."
37 Gramsci. from this point of view. is not mistaken in posing together the problem of proletarian
hegemony and of the "crisis of the state" (ignored by Engels. if not by Lenin).
38 .. Juristensozialismus." Marx-Engels Werke. val. 21 . p. 491. It is to the credit of Petter
Schettler. who gives us an illuminating analysis of it. to have brought to our attention the
206
Etienne Balibar
importance of th1s text (see his study "Engels und Kautsky als Kritiker des Juristensozialis-
mus," Demokratis und Recht. no. 1, 1980).
39 One constantly comes across this denegation of the existence of a juridical ideology, artic-
ulated from very different perspectives. One recent and very interesting example is in the
work of J. F. Lyotard, starting from his "pragmatic" analyses of the relations of commumcation
1n advanced capitalism. See, for example, Instructions pai'ennes (Paris: Galilee. 1977). pp.
55-56, "showing" that there is no bourgeois. JUridical Ideology because. generally speaking,
there 1s no dominant ideology within capitalism; capital would be. as such, indifferent to
ideology (to "semantics"). in contrast to archaic structures like the state, the party, the
Church, and so on. Similarly, he writes later (p. 76) that money, as a medium of commu-
nication, is outside of ideology, even JUridical ideology. The most delicate position to discuss
would, of course, be that of juridical positivism (Kelsen). which explicitly distinguishes juridical
ideology and legal norms from natural law.
40 See my article "Dictature du proletariat. .. in Oictionnaire critique du marxisme, ed. G. Labice
and G. Bensussan (Paris: P.U.F., 1982). It is stnking that. during this penod, Engels is moved
to say someth1ng new about the ancient City (in The Ongin of the Family) which clarifies the
"civic" sense of the idea of community present within the term "communism ... In the ancient
city-note that its own worldview has not yet. in itself. been properly named-the citizens
directly and collectively pursue the common public interests without being "displaced" toward
the religious Nebenzwecke (albeit upon the repressed base of slavery). which clarifies the
ulterior motive behind the curiously Aristotelian phrase in The Erfurt Program (written against
the anarchists), according to which "the workers are political by nature." More than a nos-
talgic definition of politics, by way of the Greek example, it is a question of thinking the crux
of the proletarian worldview in reference to what, throughout the entire classical tradition,
symbolizes politics as such. Following upon the analysis of the Greek city as the first form,
in its contradictory development, of the fus1on of politics and statism in the history of class
struggle, it 1s a way of showing that, in the transition to communism. the crucial stake of
struggle is the possibility of dissociating politics from statism by associating (or fusing) politics
with labor-two poles of a contradiction that cuts across all of history. See E. Balibar, C.
Luporini. A. Tosel, Marx et sa critique de Ia politique (Paris: Maspero, 1979).
41 "Zur Gesch1chte des Urchristentums" ( 1894-95), Marx-Engels Werke, vol. 22, p. 449; and
see Marx and Engels, The Holy Family.
42 The work of Gustave Le Bon, The Psychology of Crowds, which Freud discusses (for better
or worse?) in Mass Psychology and the Analysis of the Ego. Labriola and Plekhanov, in
particular, are very much taken up with the question of the relation between the theory of
ideology and social psychology.
43 Is such a retrospective critique, coming, by definition, "too late," not at once an oversimplified
and perfectly useless exercise? But suppose-as I suggest at the beginning of this study-
that the problems of current Marxism and its crisis are posed in a less linear fashion? This
might be a way out of the false dilemma of repetition and liquidation, neither of which change
anything.
44 SeeM. Heidegger's project to move out of the "doldrums" of the disputes around Weltan-
schauungen ("The Age of the World-View." 1938). establishing a distance from historicism
but particularly from a certain form of direct identification of the "destination" of humankind
and its mobilization. Read the interesting sixth issue of the review Metamorfosi (Turin, 1982).
"La decisions." with articles by C. Preve and M. Turchetto, among others.
45 In this respect it is difficult to see-unless we question the very idea of a class politics-how
the meaning of the party form in the workers' movement could not correspond to the de-
velopment of a certain "schismatic spirit" within the working class. Not only does the con-
stitutive role played by intellectuals over the entire history of the workers' movement not
present an obstacle, it largely contributes to the phenomenon of workerism. It is all the more
interesting to see Lenin (in What Is to Be Done?) defining the proletarian political party by
its capacity to intervene in all classes of soc1ety, that is, together, as a "unity of opposites."
46 Sorel says the organizing "myth." But. conversely, has every organization not its own working
myth? Gramsci, in particular, asks this question.
47 For the most elaborate thoughts on th1s, one should consult the recent work of Lecourt,
L 'ordre et les jeux (Paris, 1981), chap. 4, and La philosophie sans feinte (Paris, 1982). In
a prev1ous study ("Etat, parti, ideologie," 1n E. Balibar. C. Luporini, A. Tosel. Marx et sa
critique de Ia politique [Paris: Maspero. 1979]), I tried to relate this gap between "two
centers" that pers1st in Marx and Engels's analyses of the party to what Althusser calls the
"double inscription" of the theory of Marx within its own "topic": first, as the thought of
the historical whole, fictively exterior to 1ts action (proces); and second, as the "ideological
form," 1nscribed and acting within this whole (and hence determined by it). But it was also
a case of demonstrating the limits of th1s representation, preventing the party from really
analyzing its own history, thereby falling far short of subsequent Marxist theorization.
207
48 See my article "Marx le JOker," 1n Re1ouer le politique, ed. Luc Ferry (Paris: Galilee, 1981)
49 See the study by S Mercier-Josa, "Espnt du peuple et ideologie," Pour lire Hegel and Marx
(Paris: Editions Sociales, 1980). p. 69.
50 This same difficulty does not rule out some interesting though puzzling conceptual creations:
witness Engels's distinction between "revolution from above" and "revolution from below"
(1n relation to the way in which Napoleon Ill or B1smarck would have been "prevented" from
making themselves the "testamentary executors" of the revolutions of 1848, after having
surpressed them-which IS also a way of explaming why the proletariat is prevented from
acting upon the base of B1smarckian or Napoleonic society, even in its political forms, 1nstead
of "reviving" 1848, according to the model of "permanent revolution"). With his own notion
of "passive revolution" (implicitly opposed to "active revolution" or to "revolutionary revo-
lution"). Gramsc1 seems to be on the same track.
51 In this Situation each word becomes a double-edged weapon. The notion of a "proletarian
worldview" can act as the 1ndex of work1ng-class ideologies (in the sense of practice, rather
than opmions). Irreducible to the dom1nant ideology. But it can also prevent all critical de-
velopment of these ideologies in themselves-in the case of labor, family, or the state-to
the extent that. according to the log1c of speculative empiricism, it pos1ts these ideologies
as d1rect "representatives" of the universal (and through them the archetype of the worker).
Conversely, it IS not at all clear that the fact of speaking about working-class ideology, as
Marx and Engels do not do, is enough to ruin the specular relation; "the worker" is a place
within the action of capitalist labor. Under the guise of "g1ving power" (ideas or words) to
the workers, such a notion perpetuates their position (even puts them back in it) It can thus
be the instrument of a "new bourgeoisie" (including a "new bourgeoisie" of the party).
52 I try to use the very terms of Marx and Engels "out of the necess1ty to attack them," wh1ch
seems to me to be one of the indispensable ways of determming what they think.
53 "Classical" political theory from Machiavelli to Hobbes and Rousseau (w1th its conformists
and its heretics) is an admirable example-perhaps too much so-of this vacillation of ide-
ology, from theology to the JUridical, along with the moment of political recognition of the
real state it contains. This moment, however, is never "pure" (even in Machiavelli), since
the untwistmg movement of theological recovering is always already also the twistmg move-
ment of the JUndical recovenng.
54 That politics is also 1ts own mask is what prevents it from being based upon a concept or
theory of "social ties," contractual or otherwise-no more so, of course, 1f it is defmed as
"alienation" from the onginary social bond. Through his concept of the "social relations of
production" and the1r history, Marx enters onto another terra1n. However, inasmuch as the
crit1que of ideology means, for him, foreseeing an end to ideology, an absolute transparency
of soc1al relations, or, 1f you will, a society in which individuals are at last contemporaries
and thus the omnipotent creators of their own social relations, the problematic of the "soc1al
tie" is seen to be freshly inserted into all of his analyses.
55 This does not mean that proletarian ideology has become "dominant" in the modern state;
but it undoubtedly has played a determining role in its transformations, both before and, even
more, after the Soviet revolution, the lessons of which bourgeo1s capitalists have been as-
Similating and preaching aga1nst ever since. Every bourgeois, even capitalist. state, is today,
in this sense, postrevolutionary. Negri is correct on th1s point; see La classe ouvriere contre
l'etat (Paris: Gal1lee, 1976). This is a better explanation of the fact that the crisis of the
state-otherwise known as its restructuring-implies, on the part of the avant-garde ideo-
logues of the ruling class, coming to terms with what they themselves call "proletarian
ideology," or, rather, whatsoever of proletanan ideology has been incorporated into the
bourgeois state. Th1s is the meaning of neoliberalism, of antitotalitarian d1scourse, and so
on.
56 In his book Language, Semantics and ldeolpgy, trans. Harbans Nag pal (New York: St. Martins,
1982). Michel Pecheux has shown the implications, as far as a discourse theory is concerned,
of an ideological pos1tion (or better, within ideology); such a position can only be defined as
the not inconsiderable sum (and this is different from a reciprocal neutralization) of the '' dom-
inant" worldview, and the proletarian class struggle, with no other support or point of ref-
erence than to this very struggle. The paradox that is central to his analyses is that of a
subJect who has to be able to pull h1mself out of the mess he or she has fallen into (the
"Munchhausen" effect)-is this not, strictly speaking, the truth of any revolutionary practice?
57 A hint of this problem can be found in Marx, though in as contradictory a fashion as the
relation to ideology, namely, in the hesitation often experienced in the use of the two terms
"proletanat" and "working class" (Arbeiterklasse). The former, which carries all of the po-
litical weight of the Manifesto, IS practically absent from Capital, particularly in its first edition,
except specifically as an oblique reference back to the Manifesto. Moreover, if the term
"proletariat" connotes the aggregate of the living conditions and reproduction of the work1ng
class (and not only its productive function). these are-in spite of the polemic against Mal-
208
Etienne Balibar
thusianism and the thesis of the "brazen law of wages" -at once standardized, and hence
neutralized in their historical diversity and political relevance. within the concept of a tendency,
inherent to the capitalist system. toward the minimal reproduction of the market labor force.
58 Naturally, the temptation to regard the object of historical materialism as a necessary and
sufficient whole and to present it with its would-be missing link can take forms other than
those of a theory of ideology. In particular. it can take the altogether different form of a theory
of the state. which is hardly surprising when one begins to suspect that every historical form
of the state has. as Marx put it. a double "base": both in the form of relations of production
and that of ideological relations. It is striking that all of Althusser's theoretical work (from his
initial definition of the overdetermination of historical causality to the introduction of the
concept of ideological state apparatus) oscillates between two tendencies: one takes up
again, albeit in a somewhat novel way, the Marxist project of a theory of ideology (or a theory
of the state); the other explicitly considers the concept of ideology in terms of a constant
excess, or deficiency, in relation to any totalization of social complexity or political practice,
at the risk of crediting Marx with the very opposite of what he thought. Consequently, the
work of Althusser, better than others, it seems to me, is able to anticipate the most significant
features of the crisis of Marxism.
209
Oskar Negt
Notes
(Translator's note: I am grateful to Jochen Hoffman for his meticulous advice on the many
problems this text presented.)
In an extemporaneous speech I lectured on the viewpoints presented here, first in a forum
for adult education at the New Market Square, in Cologne (February 4, 1983) and then at
the Social Academy in Dortmund (February 10, 1983). Subsequently, I worked these view-
points into an essay and expanded on them considerably. Wherever possible, however, I
have kept the lecture format.
2 The most famous instance is Marx's reckoning with the Willich-Schapper faction in a session
of the central governing body of the Communist League on September 15, 1850: "In the
place of critical observation the minority puts a dogmatic one, in the place of a materialist
observation an idealist one. For you the driving-wheel of the revolution is not real conditions
but the will alone. We tell the workers: you must experience fifteen, twenty, or fifty years of
bourgeo1s wars and peasant battles, not only in order to change conditions but also in order
to change yourselves and to prepare yourselves for political rule. You say, on the contrary:
either we must come to power immediately or we will lie down and go to sleep."
234
Gajo Petrovic
1 The twenty sheaves of questions were orig1nally prepared to be read on August 21, 1968,
as part of the F1fth Sess1on of the Korcula Summer School, wh1ch was devoted to "Marx
and RevolutiOn." However, early in the morning of that day the news spread that the troops
of the Warsaw Pact had invaded Czechoslovakia. The work of the school was interrupted,
the 1nvasion was d1scussed. and an appeal to world public op1nion and a number of telegrams
(such as a protest telegram to Brezhnev) were issued. The appeal was first signed by Ernst
Bloch; the Signatures of Herbert Marcuse, Serge Mallet, Alfred Sohn-Rethel, Lucien Gold-
mann, Thomas Bottomore, Eugen Fink, Jurgen Habermas, and others followed. On August
22 the school resumed 1ts work. Some of the papers that had been scheduled for the
preceding day were squeezed into the remaining program, but I renounced reading m1ne.
Thus. I f1rst read my text at a Croat1an Philosophical Society meeting in autumn 1968. It was
published in the Belgrad Student, a paper that played an 1mportant role in the Yugoslav
student rebellion of 1968. and then in the JOurnal Praxis, nos. 1-2 ( 1969). which brought
out the proceedings of the 1968 Korcula Summer School.
2 In M. Markovic and G. Petrovic, eds., Praxis: Yugoslav Essays m the Philosophy and Meth-
odology of the Social Sciences, Boston Stud1es in the Philosophy of Science, val. 36, (Dor-
drecht, Boston, London: D. Reidel, 1979), pp. 151-64.
3 Philosophie and revolutiOn (Reinbek be1 Hamburg Rowohlt, 1971 ); Filosofia y revolution
(Mex1co: Editonal Extemuoraneos, 1972); Filozofija i revolucija (Zagreb Naprijed, 1973);
M1sljenJe revoluc1}e (Zagreb: Napnjed, 1978).
4 See my Filozoflja i marks1zam (Zagreb Mladost, 1965). translated mto English as Marx in
the Mid- Twentieth Century (New York: Doubleday, 1967).
5 See K. Marx, F. Engels, Werke (Berlin, 1969). vol. 19, pp. 102-6, 209, 335-36.
6 Most 1mportant among those attempts is probably Habermas's reconstruction of histoncal
materialism; see Zur Rekostruktwn des Historischen Materialismus (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp,
1976). A number of interesting attempts 1n the same direction have been collected m: U.
Jaegg1 and A. Honneth, eds., Theorien des historischen material1smus (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp,
1976). and A. Honneth and U. Jaeggi, eds., Arbeit, handlung, normativitiit: Theorien des
histonschen matenalismus, 2 (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1980)
7 Robert C. Tucker, ed., The Marx-Engels Reader (New York: W W Norton, 1972). p. 640-
41.
8 "A quo1 bon praxis," Praxis.· A Philosophical Journal (International Edition), 1:1 (1965). pp.
3-7.
248
Ernesto Laclau
Notes
1 The present essay was delivered orally at the conference that provided the basis for th1s
volume. The full argument is developed in the first three chapters of Ernesto Laclau and
Chantal Mouffe, Hegemony and Socialist Strategy: Towards a Radical Democratic Politics
(London: New Left Books, 1985).
257
Christine Delphy
Notes
Originally published in 1970, "The Main Enemy" is reprinted in Chnstine Delphy, Close to
Home: A Materialist Analys1s of Women's Oppression (Amherst: University of Massachusetts
Press. 1984).
2 C HenneqUin, E. Lesseps, and C. Delphy, "L'interdiction de l'avortement: Exploitation econ-
omique," Partisans ( 1970). no. 54-5.
3 J. Hanmer, "Violence and the Social Control of Women." in G. Littlejohn et al.. eds., Power
and the State (london: Croom Helm, 1978).
4 On the issue of rape. see the mimeographed paper "Patriarchal Justice and the Fear of
Rape," issued by Feministes RevolutiOnnaires in 1976.
267
Discussion
Comment (Michele Barrett)
I want to make three comments on Christine's position which
I think are particularly central for understanding the relation between Marxism and
feminism. I don't want to dwell very long on any of them, since I have engaged
them in a more detailed way elsewhere.
The first point concerns the question of gender. I think Chris-
tine is absolutely right that the analysis of gender has not taken off in the way that
a lot of feminists hoped it would. But I think that is partly because there has been
a theoretical debate about how we analyze gender. I might briefly characterize this
debate along a continuum between two extreme positions. At one end (and I would
locate Christine here) is a theory that sees gender as, in a sense, a Durkheimian
social fact. What we are studying when we look at the acquisition of gender is the
acquisition of a social identity that is already there. At the opposite pole is the
theoretical view that there is no such fixed social category already there but, rather,
that the meaning of gender-the meaning of femininity and masculinity-is con-
structed anew in every encounter. I would associate this view with discourse theory
and the various kinds of feminist appropriations of discourse theory.
Neither of these poles is very satisfactory. The Durkheimian
position doesn't explain social change, and I think that there has been a considerable
amount of change in the meaning of gender. The discourse position doesn't explain
persistence. If you insist that gender is created anew on every occasion, you can't
explain how it is that familiar things keep popping up time and time again. So it
seems to me that the more useful way to approach gender would be somewhere
between these two extremes. And I think the failure of gender analysis to really take
off is due to the way the debate has been defined already.
The second issue I want to raise involves the concept of
class. While I agree to some extent with what Christine says, I think it is necessary
to pose the difficulties of reconciling a Marxist and a feminist approach. Christine
reconciles these through the concepts that she uses (e.g., patriarchy, domestic mode
of production, and wage-labor). Clearly, one might use different concepts but still
pose, in a very general way, the theoretical relationship between Marxism and fem-
inism. I've argued in the past that this is an extremely difficult project and that, to
put it crudely, the success of the project is not really assisted by simply using a
Marxist concept of class in relation to gender. Christine acknowledges that it is not
ideal but maintains that it is the least unsatisfying term with which to analyze
oppression. But when we are trying to reconcile Marxist and feminist approaches,
we must face the problem that Christine raises at the very beginning, which is the
question of the distinction between exploitation and oppression. The real key to the
debate is to describe how we might say that women are exploited rather than op-
pressed by men. The concept of class, as developed by Marx, does not simply register
dichotomy; it is not simply a descriptive term that can be transferred onto other
sets of relations-or, at least, it can only be transferred metaphorically. The question
is crucial politically because it raises the question of the status of economic arguments
and the status of exploitation as an economic category in political theory and political
strategy. And it seems to me-I'll float this as a rather provocative point-that it
doesn't help us in thinking about feminist questions to reproduce some of the dif-
ficulties associated with the concept of class that Marxism has plowed through with
great pain and suffering.
My third point concerns the relations between political strat-
egies and theoretical interpretations. I will give two examples. The first is the question
of biology: whether feminism is, as it were, infected by naturalism as soon as it
raises the question of biology. While I completely agree with Christine in principle,
I think that a political difficulty remains because we are not in a situation where
impeccable logic rules the world. We are in a situation where biologistic arguments
absolutely hold the commanding heights of popular sentiments on the question of
268
Christine Delphy
gender. We simply cannot afford the luxury of saying that biological or biologistic
arguments should not be addressed by feminists. In fact, our arguments have too
often been very unconvincing. There is a political imperative that demands more
work here, more serious engagements with and refutations of pseudoscientific ar-
guments, and more popular campaigning as well.
The other example I want to give is perhaps a bit more
controversial: abortion. Of course, it's true that abortion is a feminist issue. But we
will be in a lot of trouble politically if we rest there, because abortion is an issue
that cannot really be posed exclusively in terms of the antagonism between men and
women, or of male control over women. To pose it in that way is to deny the role
of women in the antiabortion movement, and that is, in some ways, a rather pa-
tronizing approach. Nor is it politically helpful at this moment because it leaves the
Right too much in control of popular ideologies. And it doesn't give due recognition
to the complexity of women's experience. Instead, it tends to imply that women
mistake their own interests, rather like the traditional Marxist view of the working
class as misperceiving their own objective interests. Neither position really engages
with the question-at the level of either experience or popular ideology-of why
people want these things that we are, analytically, so critical of. The refusal to engage
with the question of consent leads us into a victimology ofwomen. Those ofus who
come from the other side of the Atlantic are very conscious of this because of the
phenomenon of Thatcherism: that you cannot make do with a theoretical position
in which you don't take seriously the "nonprogressive" needs, wants, and desires of
people. Paradoxically, that leads me back to my first point, that we need to consider
in a more nuanced, more complex way how gender is constructed and the political
parameters of that process.
269
Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak
Notes
308
Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak
It is important to note that the greatest "influence" of Western European
intellectuals upon U.S. professors and students happens through collections of essays rather
than long books in translation. And, in those collections, it is understandably the more topical
pieces that gain a greater currency. (Derrida's "Structure, Sign, and Play" is a case in point.)
From the perspective of theoretical production and ideological reproduction, therefore, the
conversation under consideration has not necessarily been superseded.
4 The·re is an implicit reference here to the post-1968 wave of Maoism in France. See Michel
Foucault, "On Popular Justice: A Discussion with Maoists," Power/Knowledge: Selected
Interviews and Other Writings 1972-77, trans. Colin Gordon et al. (New York: Pantheon).
p. 134 (hereafter cited as PK). Explication of the reference strengthens my point by laying
bare the mechanics of appropriation. The status of China in this discussion is exemplary. If
Foucault persistently clears himself by saying "I know nothing about China," his interlocutors
show toward China what Derrida calls the "Chinese prejudice."
5 This is part of a much broader symptom, as Eric Wolf discusses in Europe and the People
without History (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1982).
6 Walter Benjamin, Charles Baudelaire: A Lyric Poet in the Era of High Capitalism, trans. Harry
Zohn (London Verso, 1983). p. 12.
7 Gilles Deleuze and Felix Guattari, Anti-Oedipus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia, trans. Richard
Hurley et al. (New York: Viking Press, 1977). p. 26.
8 The exchange with Jacques-Aiain Miller in PK ("The Confession of the Flesh") is revealing
in this respect.
9 Althusser, Lenin and Philosophy, pp. 132-33.
10 For one example among many see PK, p. 98.
11 It is not surprising, then, that Foucault's work, early and late, is supported by too simple a
notion of repression. Here the antagonist is Freud, not Marx. "I have the impression that
[the notion of repression] is wholly inadequate to the analysis of the mechanisms and effects
of power that it is so pervasively used to characterize today (PK, 92)." The delicacy and
subtlety of Freud's suggestion-that under repression the phenomenal identity of affects is
indeterminate because something unpleasant can be desired as pleasure, thus radically rein-
scribing the relationship between desire and "interest" -seems quite deflated here. For an
elaboration of this notion of repression, see Jacques Derrida, Of Grammatology, trans. Gayatri
Chakravorty Spivak (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1976). p. 88f. (hereafter
cited as OG); and Derrida, Limited inc.: abc, trans. Samuel Weber, Glyph 2 ( 1977), p. 215.
12 Althusser' s version of this particular situation may be too schematic, but it nevertheless seems
more careful in its program than the argument under study. "Class instinct," Althusserwrites,
"is subjective and spontaneous. Class position is objective and rational. To arrive at proletarian
class positions, the class instinct of proletarians only needs to be educated; the class instinct
of the petty bourgeoisie, and hence of intellectuals, has, on the contrary, to be revolutionized"
(Lenin and Philosophy, p. 13).
13 Foucault's subsequent explanation (PK, 145) of this Deleuzian statement comes closer to
Derrida's notion that theory cannot be an exhaustive taxonomy and is always formed by
practice.
14 Cf. the surprisingly uncntical notions of representation entertained in PK, pp. 141, 188. My
remarks concluding this paragraph, criticizing intellectuals' representations of subaltern groups,
should be rigorously distinguished from a coalition politics that takes into account its framing
within socialized capital and unites people not because they are oppressed but because they
are exploited. This model works best within a parliamentary democracy, where representation
is not only not banished but elaborately staged.
15 Karl Marx, Surveys from Exile, trans. David Fernbach (New York: Vintage Books, 1974). p.
239.
16 Karl Marx, Captial: A Critique of Political Economy, val. 1, trans. Ben Fowkes (New York:
Vantage Books, 1977). p. 254.
17 Marx, Capital, I, p. 302.
18 See the excellent short definition and discussion of common sense in Errol Lawrence, "Just
Plain Common Sense: The 'Roots' of Racism," in Hazel V. Carby et al., The Empire Strikes
Back: Race and Racism in 70s Britain (London: Hutchinson, 1982). p. 48.
19 "Use value" in Marx can be shown to be a "theoretical fiction"-as much of a potential
oxymoron as "natural exchange." I have attempted to develop this in "Scattered Specu-
lations on the Question of Value," a manuscript under consideration by Diacritics.
309
20 Derrida's "Linguistic Circle of Geneva," especially p. 1431., can provide a method for as-
sessing the irreducible place of the family in Marx's morphology of class formation. In Margins
of Philosophy, trans. Alan Bass (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1982).
21 Marx, Capital, I, p. 128.
22 I am aware that the relationship between Marxism and neo-Kantianism is a politically fraught
one. I do not myself see how a continuous line can be established between Marx's own
texts and the Kantian ethical moment. It does seem to me. however, that Marx's questioning
of the individual as agent of history should be read in the context of the breaking up of the
individual subject inaugurated by Kant's critique of Descartes.
23 Karl Marx, Grundrisse: Foundations of the Critique of Political Economy, trans. Martin Nicolaus
(New York Viking Press, 1973). pp. 162-63.
24 Edward W Said, The World, the Text, the Critic (Cambridge: Harvard Un1versity Press, 1983).
p. 243.
25 Paul Bove, "Intellectuals at War: Michel Foucault and the Analysis of Power," Sub-Stance.
36/37 ( 1983), p. 44.
26 Carby, Empire, p. 34.
27 This argument is developed further in Spivak, "Scattered Speculations." Once again, the
Anti-Oedipus did not ignore the economic text. although the treatment was perhaps too
allegorical. In this respect, the move from schizo- to rhyzo-analysis in Mille plateaux (Paris:
Seuil, 1980) has not been salutary.
28 See Michel Foucault, Madness and Civilization: A H1story of Insanity in the Age of Reason,
trans. Richard Howard (New York: Pantheon Books, 1965), pp. 251, 262, 269.
29 Although I consider Fredric Jameson's Political Unconscious: Narrative as a Socially Symbolic
Act (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1981) to be a text of great critical weight, or perhaps
because I do so. I would like my program here to be distinguished from one of restoring the
relics of a privileged narrative: "It is in detecting the traces of that uninterrupted narrative,
in restoring to the surface of the text the repressed and buried reality of this fundamental
history, that the doctrine of a political unconscious finds its function and its necessity" (p.
20)
30 Among many available books, I cite Bruse Tiebout McCully, English Education and the Origins
of Indian Nationalism (New York: Columbia University Press, 1940).
31 Thomas Babington Macaulay, Speeches by Lord Macaulay: With His Minute on Indian Ed-
ucation, ed. G. M. Young (Oxford: Oxford University Press, AMS Edition. 1979). p. 359.
32 Keith, one of the compilers of the Vedic Index, author of Sanskrit Drama in Its Origin, De-
velopment, Theory, and Practice, and the learned editor of the Krsnayajurveda for Harvard
University Press, was also the editor of four volumes of Selected Speeches and Documents
of British Colonial Policy ( 1763 to 1937), of International Affairs ( 1918 to 1937). and of the
British Dom1nions ( 1918 to 1931 ). He wrote books on the sovereignty of British dominions
and on the theory of state succession, with special reference to English and colonial law.
33 Mahamahopadhyaya Haraprasad Shastri. A Descriptive Catalogue of Sanskrit Manuscripts
in the Government Collection under the Care of the Asiatic Society of Bengal (Calcutta: Asiatic
Society of Bengal, 1925). vol. 3, p. viii.
34 Dinesachandra Sena, Brhat Banga (Calcutta: Calcutta University Press. 1925), vol. 1, p. 6.
35 Edward Thompson, Suttee: A Historical and Philosophical Enquiry into the Hindu Rite of
Widow-Burning (London: George Allen and Unwin, 1928). pp. 130, 47.
36 Holograph letter (from G. A. Jacob to an unnamed correspondent) attached to inside front
cover of the Sterling Memorial Library (Yale University) copy of Colonel G. A. Jacob, ed .. The
Mahanarayana-Upanishad of the Atharva-Veda with the Dipika of Narayana (Bombay: Gov-
ernment Central Books Department, 1888); italics mine. The dark invocation of the dangers
of this learning by way of anonymous aberrants consolidates the asymmetry.
37 I have discussed this issue in greater detail with reference to Julia Kristeva's About Chinese
Women, trans. Anita Barrows (London: Marion Soyars, 1977). in "French Feminism in an
International Frame," Yale French Studies, 62 (1981).
38 Antonio Gram sci, · 'Sorne Aspects of the Southern Question,·' Selections from Political Writ-
ing: 1921-1926, trans. Quintin Hoare (New York: International Publishers. 1978) I am using
"allegory of reading" in the sense developed by Paul de Man, Allegories of Reading: Figural
Language in Rousseau, Nietzsche, Rilke, and Proust (New Haven: Yale University Press,
1979)
39 Their publications are: Subaltern Studies 1: Writing on South Asian History and Society, ed.
RanaJit Guha (Delhi: Oxford University Press, 1982); Subaltern Studies II: Writings on South
Asian History and Society, ed. RanaJit Guha (Delhi: Oxford University Press, 1983); and RanaJit
310
Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak
Guha, Elementary Aspects of Peasant Insurgency in Colonia/India (Delhi: Oxford University
Press. 1983).
40 Edward W. Said, "Permission to Narrate," London Review of Books (Feb. 16, 1984).
41 Guha, Studies, I, p. 1.
42 Guha, Studies, I, p. 4.
43 Jacques Derrida, "The Double Session," Dissemination, trans. Barbara Johnson (Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1981 ).
44 Guha, Studies, I, p. 8 (all but the first set of italics are the author's).
45 Ajit K. Chaudhury, "New Wave Social Science," Frontier, 16-24 (Jan. 28, 1984), p. 10
(italics are mine).
46 Chaudhury, "New Wave Social Science," p. 10.
47 Pierre Macherey, A Theory of Literary Production, trans. Geoffrey Wall (London: Routledge,
1978), p 87.
48 I have d1scussed this issue in "Displacement and the Discourse of Woman," in Mark Krupnick,
ed., Displacement. Derrida and After (Bloomington: Indiana University Press, 1983), and in
"Love Me, Love My Ombre, Elle: Derrida's 'La carte postale,' " Diacritics 14, no. 4 ( 1984),
pp. 19-36.
49 This v1olence in the general sense that is the possibility of an episteme is what Derrida calls
"writing" in the general sense. The relationship between writing in the general sense and
writing in the narrow sense (marks upon a surface) cannot be cleanly articulated. The task
of grammatology (deconstruction) is to provide a notation upon this shifting relationship. In
a certain way, then, the critique of impenalism is deconstruction as such.
50 "Contracting Poverty," Multinational Monitor, 4, no. 8 (Aug. 1983), p. 8. This report was
contnbuted by John Cavanagh and Joy Hackel, who work on the International Corporations
Project at the Institute for Policy Studies (italics are m1ne).
51 The mechanics of the invention of the Third World as signifier are susceptible to the type of
analysis directed at the constitution of race as a signifier in Carby, Empire.
52 Mike Davis, "The Political Economy of Late-Imperial America," New Left Review, 143 (Jan.-
Feb. 1984), p. 9.
53 Bove, "Intellectuals," p. 51.
54 Terry Eagleton, Literary Theory: An Introduction (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press,
1983), p 205.
55 Perry Anderson, In the Tracks of Historical Matenalism (London: Verso, 1983), p. 53.
56 Anderson, In the Tracks, p. 52.
57 Sa1d, The World, p. 183.
58 Jacques Dernda, "Of an Apocalyptic Tone Recently Adapted in Philosophy," trans. John P
Leavy, Jr., in Semia, p. 71.
59 Even in such excellent texts of reportage and analysis as Gail Omvedt's We Will Smash This
Prison! Indian Women in Struggle (London: Zed Press, 1980), the assumption that a group
of Maharashtrian women in an urban proletarian situation, reacting to a radical white woman
who had "thrown in her lot with the Indian destiny," is representative of "Indian women"
or touches the question of "female consciousness in India" is not harmless when taken up
with1n a first-world soc1al formation where the proliferation of communication in an interna-
tionally hegemonic language makes alternative accounts and testimonies instantly accessible
even to undergraduates.
Norma Chinchilla's observation, made at a panel on "Third World Feminisms:
Differences in Form and Content" (UCLA, Mar. 8, 1983), that antisexist work in the Indian
context is not genuinely antisexist but antifeudal, is another case in point. This permits
definitions of sexism to emerge only after a society has entered the capitalist mode of pro-
duction, thus making capitalism and patriarchy conveniently continuous. It also invokes the
vexed question of the role of the" 'Asiatic' mode of production" in sustaining the explanatory
power of the normative narrativization of history through the account of modes of production,
in however sophisticated a manner history is construed.
The curious role of the proper name "Asia" in this matter does not remain
confined to proof or disproof of the empirical existence of the actual mode (a problem that
became the object of intense maneuvering within international communism) but remains
crucial even in the work of such theoretical subtlety and importance as Barry Hindess and
Paul Hirst's Pre-Capitalist Modes of Production (London: Routledge, 19 7 5) and Fredric Jame-
son's Political Unconscious. Especially in Jameson, where the morphology of modes of
production is rescued from all suspicion of historical determinism and anchored to a post-
311
structuralist theory of the subject, the "Asiatic" mode of production, in its guise of "oriental
despotism" as the concomitant state formation, still serves. It also plays a significant role in
the transmogrified mode of production narrative in Deleuze and Guattari' s Anti-Oedipus. In
the Sov1et debate. at a far remove, indeed, from these contemporary theoretical proJects.
the doctrinal sufficiency of the "Asiatic" mode of production was most often doubted by
producing for it various versions and nomenclatures of feudal, slave, and communal modes
of production. (The debate is presented in detail in Stephen F. Dunn, The Fall and Rise of
the Astatic Mode of Production [London: Routledge, 1982].) It would be interesting to relate
this to the repression of the imperialist "moment" in most debates over the transition from
feudalism to capitalism that have long exercised the Western Left. What is more important
here 1s that an observation such as Chinchilla's represents a widespread hierarchization within
third-world feminism (rather than Western Marxism). which situates it within the long-standing
traffic with the impenalist concept-metaphor "Asia."
I should add that I have not yet read Madhu Kishwar and Ruth Vanita, eds.,
In Search of Answers: Indian Women's Voices from Manushi (London: Zed Books, 1984).
60 Jonathan Culler, On Deconstruction: Theory and Criticism after Structuralism (Ithaca: Cornell
University Press, 1982). p. 48.
61 Elizabeth Fox-Genovese, "Placing Woman's History in History," New Left Review, 133 (May-
June 1982). p. 21.
62 I have attempted to develop this idea in a somewhat autobiographical way in "Finding Fem-
inist Readings: Dante-Yeats," in Ira Konigsberg, ed., American Criticism in the Poststruc-
turalist Age (Ann Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1981).
63 Sarah Kolman, L'{migme de Ia femme: La femme dans les textes de Freud (Paris: Galilee,
1980)
64 Sigmund Freud, " 'A Child Is Being Beaten': A Contribution to the Study of the Origin of
Sexual Perversions," The Standard Edition of the Complete Psychological Works of Sigmund
Freud, trans. James Strachey et al. (London: Hogarth Press, 1955), vol. 17.
65 Freud, "'Wild' Psycho-Analysis," Standard Edition, vol. 11.
66 Freud, "'A Child Is Being Beaten'," p. 188.
67 For a brilliant account of how the "reality" of widow-sacrifice was constituted or "textualized"
during the colonial period, see Lata Mani, "The Production of Colonial Discourse: Sati in
Early Nineteenth Century Bengal" (masters thesis, University of California at Santa Cruz,
1 983). I profited from discussions with Ms. Mani at the inception of this project.
68 J. D. M. Derrett, Hindu Law Past and Present: Being an Account of the Controversy Which
Preceded the Enactment of the Hindu Code, and Text of the Code as Enacted, and Some
Comments Thereon (Calcutta: A. Mukheqee and Co., 195 7). p. 46.
69 Ashis Nandy, "Sati: A Ninteenth Century Tale of Women, Violence and Protest," Rammohun
Roy and the Process of Modernization in India, ed. V. C Joshi (Delhi Vikas Publishing House,
1975). p. 68.
70 The following account leans heavily on Pandurang Vaman Kane, History of the Dharmasastra
(Poona: Bhandarkar Oriental Research Institute, 1963) (hereafter cited as HD, with volume,
part, and page numbers).
71 Upendra Thakur, The History of Suicide in India: An Introduction (Delhi: Munshi Ram Manohar
Lal, 1963). p. 9, has a useful list of Sanskrit primary sources on sacred places. This laboriously
decent book betrays all the signs of the schizophrenia of the colonial subject. such as bour-
geois nationalism, patriarchal communalism, and an "enlightened reasonableness."
72 Nandy, "Sati."
73 Jean-Francais Lyotard, Le differend (Paris: Minuit, 1984).
74 HD, 11.2, p. 633. There are suggestions that this "prescribed penance" was far exceeded
by social practice. In the passage below, published in 1938, notice the Hindu patristic
assumptions about the freedom of female will at work in phrases like "courage" and "strength
of character." The unexamined presuppositions of the passage might be that the complete
objectification of the widow-concubine was just punishment for abdication of the right to
courage, signifying subject status: "Some widows, however, had not the courage to go
through the fiery ordeal; nor had they sufficient strength of mind and character to live up to
the high ascetic ideal prescribed for them [brahmacarya]. It is sad to record that they were
driven to lead the life of a concubine or avarudda stri [incarcerated wife]." A. S. Altekar, The
Position of Women in Hindu Civilization: From Prehistoric Times to the Present Day (Delhi:
Motilal Banarsidass, 1938). p. 156.
75 Quoted in Sena, Brhat-Banga, II, pp. 913-14.
76 Thompson, Suttee, p. 132.
312
Gayatri Chakravorty Spivak
77 Here, as well as for the Brahman debate over sati, see Mani, "Production," pp. 71 f.
78 We are speaking here of the regulative norms of Brahmanism. rather than "things as they
were." See Robert Lingat, The Classical Law of India, trans. J. D. M. Derrett (Berkeley:
University of California Press, 1973). p. 46.
79 Both the vestigial possibility of widow remarriage in ancient India and the legal institution of
widow remarriage in 1856 are transactions among men. Widow remarriage is very much an
exception, perhaps because it left the program of subject-formation untouched. In all the
"lore" of widow remarriage, it is the father and the husband who are applauded for their
reformist courage and selflessness.
80 Sir Monier Monier-Williams, Sanskrit-English Dictionary (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1899). p.
552. Historians are often impatient if modernists seem to be attempting to import "femin-
istic" judgments into ancient patriarchies. The real question is, of course, why structures of
patriarchal domination should be unquestioningly recorded. Historical sanctions for collective
action toward social justice can only be developed if people outside of the discipline question
standards of "objectivity" preserved as such by the hegemonic tradition. It does not seem
inappropriate to notice that so "objective" an instrument as a dictionary can use the deeply
sexist-partisan explanatory expression: "raise up issue to a deceased husband"!
81 Sunderlal T. Desai, Mulla: Principles of Hindu Law (Bombay: N. M. Tripathi, 1982). p. 184.
82 I am grateful to Professor Alison Finley of Trinity College (Hartford, Conn.) for discussing the
passage with me. Professor Finley is an expert on the Rg-Veda. I hasten to add that she
would find my readings as irresponsibly "literary-critical" as the ancient historian would find
it "modernist" (see note 80).
83 Martin Heidegger. An Introduction to Metaphysics. trans. Ralph Manheim (New York: Dou-
bleday Anchor, 1961). p. 58.
84 Thompson, Suttee, p. 37.
86 Thompson, Suttee, p. 15. For the status of the proper name as "mark." see Derrida, "Taking
Chances."
86 Thompson, Suttee. p. 137.
87 Michel Foucault, The History of Sexuality, trans. Robert Hurley (New York: Vintage Books.
1980), vol. 1, p. 4.
88 The fact that the word was also used as a form of address for a well-born woman ("lady")
complicates matters.
89 It should be remembered that this account does not exhaust her many manifestations within
the pantheon.
90 A position against nostalgia as a basis of counterhegemonic ideological production does not
endorse its negative use. Within the complexity of contemporary political economy, it would.
for example, be highly questionable to urge that the current Indian working-class crime of
burning brides who bring insufficient dowries and of subsequently disguising the murder as
suicide is either a use or abuse of the tradition of sari-suicide. The most that can be claimed
is that it is a displacement on a chain of semiosis with the female subject as signifier. which
would lead us back into the narrative we have been unraveling. Clearly, one must work to
stop the crime of bride burning in every way. If, however, that work is accomplished by
unexamined nostalgia or its opposite, it will assist actively in the substitution of race/ethnos
or sheer genitalism as a signifier in the place of the female subject.
91 I had not read Peter Dews. "Power and Subjectivity in Foucault," New Left Review. 144
( 1984). until I finished this essay. I look forward to his book on the same topic. There are
many points in common between his critique and mine. However. as far as I can tell from
the brief essay, he writes from a perspective uncritical of critical theory and the intersubjective
norm that can all too easily exchange "individual" for "subject" in its situating of the "ep-
istemic subject." Dews· s reading of the connection between "Marxist tradition" and the
"autonomous subject" is not mine. Further. his account of "the impasse of the second
phase of poststructuralism as a whole" is vitiated by his nonconsideration of Derrida, who
has been against the privileging of language from his earliest work. the "Introduction" in
Edmund Husser!, The Origin of Geometry, trans. John Leavy (Stony Brook, N.Y.: Nicolas
Hays, 1978). What sets his excellent analysis quite apart from my concerns is. of course,
that the Subject within whose History he places Foucault's work is the Subject of the European
tradition (pp. 87. 94).
313
Ill The Politics of Modernity and Postmodernity
Perry Anderson
Notes
Perry Anderson's "Modernity and Revolution" was first presented at the conference on
Marxism and the Interpretation of Culture. It was subsequently published in New Left Review
and 1s reprinted here with their permission.
Marshall Berman. All That Is Solid Melts into Air (New York Simon and Schuster. 1983). p.
15.
2 Berman, All That Is Solid, p. 16.
3 Berman, All That Is Solid, p. 18.
4 Berman. All That Is Solid, p. 24.
5 Berman. All That Is Solid, p. 24.
6 Berman. All That Is Solid. p. 24.
7 Berman, All That Is Solid, p. 36.
8 Berman, All That Is Solid, p. 104.
9 Berman. All That Is Solid, p. 114.
10 Karl Marx. Grundnsse der Kritik der Politischen Okonomie (Frankfurt, 1967). p. 439.
11 Arno Mayer. The Persistence of the Old Regime (New York Pantheon. 1982). pp. 189-273.
12 Fredric Jameson, Marxism and Form (Princeton: Princeton University Press. 1971). p. 96.
13 Jameson. pp. 103-4.
14 Jameson. p. 105.
15 Franco Moretti, S1gns Taken for Wonders (New York: Schocken. 1983). p. 209.
16 Regis Debray, "A Modest Contribution to the Rites and Ceremonies of the Tenth Anniver-
sary," New Left Review 115 (1979). pp. 45-65.
17 Marshall Berman. The Politics of Authenticity (New York: Atheneum. 1970). p 181.
18 Berman, Politics, p. 181 .
19 Berman. Politics. p. 317.
20 Berman. All That Is Solid, p. 128.
21 Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels, The German Ideology (New York: International Publishers
Co .. 1970). p. 83; cited by Berman. Politics. p. 97.
22 Norman Geras, Marx and Human Nature (New York: Schocken, 1983).
23 Marx, Grundrisse. pp. 387. 440.
24 Berman. All That Is Solid, pp. 95-96.
25 Antonio Gramsci, Selections from the Prison Notebooks. eds. Quintin Hoare and Geoffrey
Noweii-Smith (New York: International Publishers Co .. 1971). p. 276.
333
Discussion
Question
What do you mean by human nature?
Anderson
Marx never really fully articulates his concept of human
nature. But there are innumerable passages of his work we can use to bring out the
contours of and assumptions behind his implicit conception of human nature. That
conception clearly has a biological origin, in the sense that the human physiognomic
structure is that of a specific animal species. This endows us with certain potentials,
obvious psychological needs, physical powers, and certain dispositions as well-the
latter a word he uses quite a lot. On the other hand, the course of human history
immensely enlarges, elaborates, and complicates that primary physiological basis,
so that human nature is an indissoluble compound of the biological and the social.
The fact that the biological is always coded in social terms does not mean that it
can be simply absorbed by the social. We cannot simply say that human nature is
the ensemble of social relations at any one given moment. The biological basis sets
certain determinate limits to what kinds of change any given historical variation
can impose. Indeed, it is only because human nature has a determinable core of
meaning that we can speak of human emancipation at all. Were it not for that core,
we would have no markers at all, no criteria for talking of liberation, emancipation,
or of a better society.
Comment
The fact of a biological substrate is what a lot of the debate
about modernism and postmodernism is all about. As I understand Berman, the
end of the road for modernism was its attempt to describe, to create, to represent
in many forms of art precisely the field of energies and the structure of human nature
that would provide the ground for its liberating project. But modernism kept running
into the dead end of fascism. While I share many of your attitudes toward modernism
and postmodernism, I think you undervalue the postmodernist project; it is a useful
corrective to many of those premature claims for closure that modernist art and
sociology initiated. Berman's fear is that the malleability of human nature, its ability
to be saturated by many sociosymbolic codes, does not in itself solve the value
problem. Your discussion of the problems of a revolutionary communism that too
quickly totalizes itself does not necessarily suggest how communism is to define the
ethical principles that will enable it to avoid falling into traditional structures of
victimization (antisemitism, the Gulag). For Berman, the benefit of the capitalist
order is the limit it sets on such ethical transgressions, limits it so far has not broken.
334
Perry Anderson
Anderson
I don't entirely disagree, but I think Berman greatly over-
states the degree of human malleabilility. His assumption is empirically just not so.
Thus the frightening scenario he conjures up is not one we should be overly worried
about. There are many other more serious problems than those of a kind of com-
munism that capsizes over into generalized nihilism. I think that particular worry
is a fairy story.
Question
You set out in a very impressive way the conjunctural con-
ditions for modernism as it distinguishes itself from an older realist discourse. And
you mention Lukacs, who, although acutely conscious of this transformation, is
unable to grasp the spirit of modernist literature. But you repeat Lukacs's gesture,
it seems to me, in the way you dismiss postmodernism. Why do you refuse a dia-
lectical assessment of what succeeds modernism if, as you say, modernism is over
after the Second World War?
Anderson
There are two differences. Lukacs has a homogeneous and
evolutionary conception of historical phases. Once capitalism enters into what, for
him, is a period of historical decline after 1848, then everything has to go into decline.
That's not a position I would subscribe to. Capitalism today remains both an im-
mensely dynamic and a stable economic force; at the same time it is manifest that
its political powers of innovation or renewal are bankrupt. You have only to look
at the quality of its world leaders. Compare them with the generation of Roosevelt,
Churchill, and de Gaulle. It's obvious that changes have occurred and, from the
point of view of the loyal bourgeoisie, not for the better. The economic and the
political don't necessarily go in tandem.
Now, as far as aesthetic practices since the war are concerned,
it's not that all works of art since then are negligible. I can think of some you could
describe as great. Rather, my point is that, if we look at the whole panorama, it is
difficult to see anything that stands comparison with the creative years of the early
part of this century. If people want to contest that, the onus of proof would be on
them to come up with some names similar to the ones Franco Moretti cited in
literature. The point about postmodernism is that I don't take it to be an aesthetic
practice at all. I think it is a doctrine, a very tenuous doctrine indeed, built on the
back of something that is also enormously tenuous, namely, modernism. What strikes
me about it is the absence of those positive aesthetic programs we identify with the
great moments of symbolism, expressionism, futurism, constructivism, and surre-
alism. All of these words denote quite specific aesthetic biases, practices, and em-
phases. Postmodernism is simply a reference of a purely temporal sort; it has no
determinate content. And today I don't think we can find aesthetic programs op-
erative across more than one art form of the sort we find in the modernist epoch.
That's what strikes me most forcibly and makes me very wary of the notion of
postmodernism.
Finally, I would insist on the possibility of identifying great
individual works of art. I would deny the nihilist position of excluding the possibility
of anything of significance emerging today. But I do react strongly against a complete
historical relativism, one that simply assumes that any one historical age necessarily
produces as good art or as much art as another historical age. Nobody in his or her
right mind has ever claimed that the art of the dark ages is equivalent to the art of
classical Greece. I'm not saying we're in a dark age now-we aren't-but I do think
you cannot just level out historical epochs on the presumption that there is a constant
fund of human creativity that is always going to find equivalent expression.
Question
You offer a utopian vision for the postrevolutionary world.
Not that you are offering it in recompense for all the costs of the revolution-no
335
one would pretend that a revolution is made for art-but you speak nevertheless
about the proliferation of art in the postrevolutionary period. Could you offer us an
explanation, comparable to the triangulation you described for the period of the late
nineteenth/early twentieth century, that would provide us a material basis for un-
derstanding why art might flourish in the postrevolutionary period? Then perhaps
you could comment on whether our historical experience of socialist revolutions
supports your claim.
Anderson
If you look back at all the utopias-from William Morris's
to Marcuse's-in nearly all of them, even in the utopian socialists, there is a great
emphasis on simplicity; and simplicity usually implies uniformity as well. The whole
utopian tradition, in effect, assumes that a free and equal society would be trans-
parent. My presumption, on the contrary, is that a socialist society would be a far
more complicated one than what we have today. It seems perfectly clear that if you
actually had a socialist society in which production, power, and culture were gen-
uinely democratized, you would have an enormous multiplication of different ways
of living. People would choose how to live, and it is perfectly obvious that people
have different temperaments, gifts, and values. These differences are suppressed and
compressed within very narrow limits by the capitalist market and the inequalities
of bourgeois society.
The simple monolithicity of capitalist private property con-
trolling all the means of production would be broken down into a great variety of
different forms of social control of the economy and of wealth. The political system
would be enormously more complicated. You wouldn't just have elections every
five years of a more or less symbolic sort-elections of a powerless parliament or a
too-powerful president with a permanent bureaucracy. You would have multiple
electoral mechanisms.
The number of people who can create art in our society, who
can find any sort of aesthetic self-expression, is a fraction of what would be possible
if society were democratic in this more radical socialist sense. You would get some-
thing like what existed in the epoch of high modernism. The really interesting thing
about that period is not the completely confected and bogus notion of modernism.
What is interesting is how many quite different and incompatible but concurrent
aesthetic programs and practices there were. That is the richness of the period from
1900 to 1930. I think that richness would be reproduced on a much larger scale if
you didn't have the particular triangulation of the early twentieth century-a de-
clining aristocratic order, an incipient bourgeois technology, and the prospect of
social revolution. After a revolution that installed a postcapitalist socialist democ-
racy, you would have the material basis for a much richer social and cultural life.
Question
You seem to argue for a concept of revolution as a single
transformative event. Do you see no value in a view of revolution as a more gradual
social process?
Anderson
I think the notion of revolution should be valued and upheld,
but also limited; the two operations necessarily go together. Marx's theory of his-
torical materialism is more than simply a sociology of revolution. While it includes
a program for socialist revolution, that is not its totality. The totality of history is
not merely the history of revolutions. Nor is the history of socialism the totality of
the history of revolutions. To retain the utility of the concept of revolution you have
to set some kind of boundaries. This doesn't depreciate the importance of the long-
term social, economic, and cultural transformations that must occur in any postrev-
olutionary society. But there is an enormous danger, as twentieth-century political
history has shown, in a demagogic extension of the notion of revolution beyond the
336
Perry Anderson
period when one state is overthrown and replaced by another. We saw that very
clearly in China in the 1960s, just as we saw it in the Soviet Union in the 1930s,
which are not dissimilar experiences. So it's necessary to be both hard and sober
about revolution.
Question (Cornel West)
I would like to go back to the charge that your position is a
repetition of Lukacs's evolutionism. Given the papers at this conference that have
trashed classical versions of Marxism, it is important to note that you represent a
highly refined version of classical Marxism. Indeed, when you specify the three
coordinates of the conjuncture, you still start with the economic and the political.
The ideological and the cultural are reflected and refracted by those first two dom-
inant and determinant coordinates. If that is so, then your ritualistic gesture to
overdetermination is a mask for an economism, for a classical logocentric view. In
many ways this is a breath offresh air, given a certain discourse analysis. Nonetheless,
one wants to know, how do your views differ from Lukacs's evolutionism?
Anderson
What you are calling classical Marxism is not something I'm
particularly ashamed of; actually, I think it's a kind of common sense. Culture has
material conditions of possibility, and it's important to look at those rather than
become simply bemused or bewitched by the genuine magnificence of modernist
works of art. In my analysis I did emphasize some cultural determinants as well.
For example, if one is going to look at the range of practices we now call modernism,
we have to look at the bogey of realism as well. The real enemy at the time the
modernist movements crystallized was academicism, not realism.
Finally, my position is not evolutionistic. I've suggested that
the conjuncture that produced modernism can recur at other times and at other
points across the globe. Berman is right to see a lot of third-world contemporary
fiction as having some of the vitality of the original modernist forms.
Question
If the only masterpieces are now coming out of the Third
World (and the only hope for revolution is in the Third World), is any significant
art being produced in modem Western capitalist societies that furthers the analysis
of revolution?
Anderson
I'm not certain that the function of art is to further the
analysis of social developments in an instrumental sense. But it wouldn't be difficult
to cite major works of art that have come out of first- or second-world experiences.
They are not necessarily modernist or postmodemist. I regard Solzhenitsyn's First
Circle as a very great novel, although much of the rest of his work is inferior. The
other example, cited in my paper, is the highly conservative, multivolume novel by
Anthony Powell, A Dance to the Music of Time; this is the most important piece of
postwar fiction in the English language for the metropolitan world. I'm confident it
will be looked back on as a very great work, although it's not modernist in any strict
sense.
Question
Could you comment on the ostensible antimodemism of
nazism? Because it was actually nazism, not World War II, that wiped out Wiemar
culture.
Anderson
I don't think nazism by itself destroyed those creative im-
pulses. Don't forget that Brecht's masterpieces were actually produced well after the
triumph of German fascism. The question of the attitude of successive political
regimes of the thirties to various forms of avant-garde art is rather complex. One
337
would have to explore the reasons why nazism was implacably hostile to anything
other than the most sterile neoacademic art, whereas Italian fascism was not. Right
down to the end, Italian fascism maintained a fondness for certain avant-garde and
modernist art. It's not the case, for instance, that all Italian architecture ofthe period
is bad. We would also have to discuss the attitude of the Soviet regime institution-
alized under Stalin and the way it wiped out an extraordinarily rich and experimental
cultural life.
338
Franco Moretti
Notes
1 Richard Sennett. The Fall of the Public Man (New York: Random House. 1976). p. 144.
2 Georg Simmel. "The Metropolis and Mental Life." On Individuality and Social Forms: Selected
Writings (Chicago: University of Chicago Press. 1971). p. 325.
3 J. W. Goethe, Faust. trans. Bayard Taylor (london: Sphere Books. 1969). w. 1649-50.
344
Franco Moretti
Discussion
Comment (Colin MacCabe)
Much as I respect your ability to restate a traditional Marxist
case, I find it difficult to contain my anger at the way those who invoke "comrade
history" never pay much attention to particular histories. I'd like to focus on a
couple of your examples from Joyce. You argue that the treatment of adultery in
Ulysses represents a decline from its treatment in the bourgeois novel of the nine-
teenth century. In the nineteenth-century novel, you claim, adultery at least was
seen as a major problem; it typically focused the difference between two possible
fives. I want to suggest that your position ignores the way adultery functioned
throughout the nineteenth century and ignores, as well, the way Joyce produces it
in Ulysses. Within the novel adultery is linked with art, as when Stephen has a vision
ofhimselfas the great artist, as Shakespeare, in the moment in which his and Bloom's
faces congeal in the mirror, underneath the antlers of the cuckold. I think Joyce is
suggesting that that kind of serious art, with its commitment to absolute meaning,
is inextricably linked to the concerns of the cuckold, to the man's desire to control
his seed. So I think your reading slights the text.
The second point I want to make is about the whole notion
of public life and the way in which Joyce's texts are considered to back away from
an interest in and concern with public life. Once again, it is important to reflect on
the actual history in which Joyce's text was issued in 1922, in exactly the same year
as the Irish Free State gained independence. It is difficult to imagine-and I am sure
that Joyce could not imagine it-a public life in a state in which the national liberation
movement was linked to a totally reactionary church. This left someone like Yeats
in 1928 and 1929 having to speak in the senate as divorce was outlawed, indeed as
a whole series of reactionary measures went through. (Even now the Irish state is
going to enshrine abortion in its constitution.) Once we supply that historical context,
we can understand why Joyce felt that there was no public voice for him in Ireland.
He made that very clear in a whole series of writings very early on in Trieste and
then in the novels. This in turn reflects back on a general problem in Marxist ethics.
It seems to me that what Franco was saying is that one of the things we have to
think very seriously about-and perhaps this is one of the times when we have to
think very seriously about it-is what one does when public positions cannot be
taken.
Moretti
Although adultery occupies a large section of the text, it has
ceased to be a highly meaningful and potentially tragic event in the lives of the
characters. Adultery did function that way in the nineteenth-century European novel,
but it no longer does in Ulysses. My effort, then, was to explain how the concept of
adultery was dissociated from the idea of anxiety. This seems to me one of the
strangest psychocultural events of our century.
As for the issue of public life, I would not want to say that
public life is good in itself, that any public position is worthy simply because it is
public. But to be more specific, consider the history of the genre to which Ulysses
belongs, the history of the novel. For two and one-half centuries the novel has been
a sustained effort to fix the meaning of an individual's life in its connection with
public events, with history, macro-history, if you wish. Now, I would maintain that
Ulysses tends to break down this connection in a very radical way. You object by
recalling the conditions oflrish public life and you end up by asking what one should
do when public positions are impossible. Well, a hundred years before Joyce wrote
Ulysses, Stendhal faced this problem in writing The Red and the Black, which is the
story of a young man who believes in certain values that are no longer publicly
tenable. Stendhal dealt with the problem of the untenability of a public voice in a
particular historical context. Ulysses does not confront this problem. In Ulysses the
weight is placed on subjective dreaming, and public life seems less important as a
result. I suppose we need a shootout on Ulysses; we've been disagreeing for years.
345
Question (Darko Suvin)
I would like to take a position halfway between Franco Mor-
etti and Colin McCabe. The way to deal with an important process such as mod-
ernism is dialectically, to identifY its contradictions and the dominant moment within
them. This is also a problem of deciding what is the true canon of modernism.
Marxists have too often accepted the canon of bourgeois theoreticians which moves
from Kafka to Joyce. The proper canon of modernism would be the one significant
for us today. What is the dominant contradiction in this canon? It is the tension
between those who tried to have their work intervene in history and those who
despaired of it, the tension between Brecht and Joyce. We also need to consider the
place of mass literature within modernism.
Moretti
"Modernism" is a portmanteau word that perhaps should
not be used too often. But I don't think I would classifY Brecht as a modernist-
perhaps the young Brecht, but then several of the problems I have identified in other
modernists might also apply to the young Brecht. I certainly would not include Saint
Joan, the Lehrstucke, or The Measures Taken within modernism. I just cannot think
of a meaningful category that could include, say, surrealism, Ulysses, and something
by Brecht. I can't think of what the common attributes of such a concept could be.
The objects are too dissimilar.
Comment
You maintain the reflection theory of culture when you deny
the conflictual status of modernism and assert its complete harmony with the goals
of capitalism in the age of the big department store. And then, by way of an essen-
tialist and moralistic invocation, you argue that our need for stories is fulfilled by
mass literature once modernism abandons plot. Finally, your call for a modernist
irony connected with decision is based on no ground that I can identifY except
voluntarism.
Moretti
When I say we all need stories, that is not a moralistic in-
vocation; it is a statement of fact. We all need to have stories in our heads, plots
that give meaning. But the main question concerned irony and decision. You object
that there is no ground for my reconnection of irony and decision, that it is ultimately
voluntaristic. You are absolutely right. It is a choice we have to make. I'm not saying
No to modernism-it is certainly a great cultural development. The point is that it
has a reverse side, one I have been trying to elucidate. And I wonder whether this
great development, which is modernist irony, can be put to use by combining it
with other values. I have proposed that irony be joined with decision. But I am not
at all sure it is a connection that can be worked out. While at present I don't see
any ground for their combination, it would be a pity if it proves impossible, because
either way you lose something that could be very important for human culture.
346
Fredric Jameson
Cognitive Mapping
Notes
Dan Georgakis and Marvin Surkin, Detroit: I Do Mind Dying, A Study in Urban Revolution
(New York: St. Mart1n's Press, 1975).
356
Fredric Jameson
2 Kevin Lynch, The Image of the City (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1960)
3 Quoted in Kenneth Frampton, Modern Architecture: A Critical History (New York: Oxford
University Press, 1980). pp. 276-77.
357
Discussion
Question (Nancy Fraser)
First, I want to say something, for the record, about the
implicit political gesture built into your presentation of the question of totality, which
seemed to me rather irresponsible, given that there have been many discussions of
the issue and that many nuanced positions have been expressed. You essentially
conflated many differences and subtle positions on this question. But I do have a
more constructive question to ask, because I am also sympathetic to a certain kind
of totalizing thought, namely, a critical social science that would be as total and
explanatorily powerful as possible. Thus, I wonder why you assume that cognitive
mapping is the task of the aesthetic? Why wouldn't that be a task for critical social
science? Or are two different kinds of tasks conflated in your paper?
Jameson
The question of the role of the aesthetic as opposed to that
of the social sciences in explorations of the structure of the world system corresponds,
for me, to the orthodox distinction (which I still vaguely use in a somewhat different
way) between science and ideology. My point is that we have this split between
ideology in the Althusserian sense-that is, how you map your relation as an indi-
vidual subject to the social and economic organization of global capitalism-and the
discourse of science, which I understand to be a discourse (which is ultimately
impossible) without a subject. In this ideal discourse, like a mathematical equation,
you model the real independent of its relations to individual subjects, including your
own. Now I think that you can teach people how this or that view of the world is
to be thought or conceptualized, but the real problem is that it is increasingly hard
for people to put that together with their own experience as individual psychological
subjects, in daily life. The social sciences can rarely do that, and when they try (as
in ethnomethodology), they do it only by a mutation in the discourse of social science,
or they do it at the moment that a social science becomes an ideology; but then we
are back into the aesthetic. Aesthetics is something that addresses individual ex-
perience rather than something that conceptualizes the real in a more abstract way.
Question
Your paper suggests that cognitive mapping is an avenue by
which we might proceed at this point in time. Is this a tactical or a strategic choice?
If it is tactical, then how do you conceive the question of strategy? And if it is
strategic, what do you consider the problem of tactics today? The reason I raise such
a question is that there seem to be opportunities now to create an interconnected
culture that might allow real political problems to be discussed. If that's true, the
question of strategy and tactics seems central.
Jameson
That's an important question. I would answer it by trying
to connect my suggestion with Stuart Hall's paper, in which he talked about the
strategic possibilities of delegitimizing an existing discourse at a particular historical
conjuncture. While I haven't used it, the language of discourse theory is certainly
appropriate here (along with my own more dialectical language). My comrade and
collaborator Stanley Aronowitz has observed that whatever the Left is in this country
today, it has to begin by sorting out what the priorities really are. He takes the
position that our essential function for the moment is pedagogical in the largest
sense; it involves the conquest of legitimacy in this country for socialist discourse.
In other words, since the sixties, everybody knows that there is a socialist discourse.
In the TV serials there's always a radical; that has become a social type, or, more
accurately, a stereotype. So while people know that a socialist discourse exists, it is
not a legitimate discourse in this society. Thus no one takes seriously the idea that
socialism, and the social reorganization it proposes, is the answer to our problems.
Stuart Hall showed us the negative side of this struggle as the moment in which a
358
Fredric Jameson
hegemonic social democratic discourse finds its content withdrawn from it so that,
finally, those things that used to be legitimate are no longer legitimate and nobody
believes in them. Our task, I think, is the opposite of that and has to do with the
legitimation of the discourses of socialism in such a way that they do become realistic
and serious alternatives for people. It's in the context of that general project that
my more limited aesthetic project finds its place.
Question (Darko Suvin)
First of all, I would like to say, also for the record, that I
agree with your refusal to equate totality with totalitarianism. I want to remind
people of the strange origins of the connotations of the word "totalitarianism." They
arose after the war, propagated by the Congress of Cultural Freedom, which was
associated with such names as Stephen Spender and Irving Kristol and with journals
such as Encounter, funded by the CIA as it turns out. This is admittedly not a
conclusive argument; even people funded by the CIA can come up with intelligent
ideas now and then. But it should make us wary of such an equation. So I think
your rebuttal is well taken and not at all irresponsible.
Now to my question. I have a major problem with this idea
of postmodernism, even though your elaboration of it is more sophisticated than
Ihab Hassan's. I would like to try to suggest a way out of this problem. Rather than
thinking of your three stages of capitalism-which I gather are coextensive with
realism, modernism, and postmodernism-as closed, Hegelian world-historical mon-
ads subsequent to each other in time, so that at some point (around 1910 or 1960)
one begins and the other ends, couldn't we think of capitalism as a whole (beginning
whenever you wish), and then a series of movements (such as realism, modernism,
postmodernism) that have become hegemonic in a given subphase of capitalism but
that do not necessarily disappear. After all, most literature and painting today is still
realistic (e.g., Arthur Hailey). In other words, we have shifting hegemonies, although
I think it is still a question of how one proves that a shift of such major dimensions
(e.g., the shift associated with the names Picasso, Einstein, Eisenstein, and Lenin)
really occurred in the 1960s. But in that case, postmodernism could emerge as a
style, even become hegemonic in the United States and Western Europe, but not in
India and Africa, and then lose its dominant position without our having to shift
into a new episteme and a new world-historical monad. And you would have a
subtler interplay between a simultaneously coexisting realism, modernism, and post-
modernism, on various levels of art and literature.
Jameson
The questions of periodization, coexistence, and so on, are
difficult and complex. Obviously, when I talk about such periods they are not sealed
monads that begin and end at easily identifiable moments (beginning in 1857 and
ending in 1913, or beginning in 1947 or 1958, etc.). And there are certainly survivals
and overlaps. I would, however, like to say something about the problem people
have with the concept of postmodernism. For me, the term suggests two connected
things: that we are in a different stage of capital, and that there have been a number
of significant cultural modifications (e.g., the end of the avant-garde, the end of the
great auteur or genius, the disappearance of the utopian impulse of modernism-
about which I think Perry Anderson was both eloquent and extremely suggestive).
It's a matter of coordinating those cultural changes with the notion that artists today
have to respond to the new globally defined concrete situation of late capitalism.
That is why it doesn't bother me too much when friends and colleagues like Darko
Suvin or Perry Anderson or Henri Lefebvre find this concept of postmodernism
suspicious. Because whatever Perry Anderson, for example, thinks of the utility of
the period term-postmodernism-his paper demonstrates that something really fun-
damental did change after 1945 and that the conditions of existence of modernism
were no longer present. So we are in something else.
Now the relative merit of competing terms-postmodernism
or high modernism-is another matter. The task is to describe that qualitatively
359
different culture. By the same token, I trust that people who have some discursive
stake in other terms, such as totality or its refusal, do not take my remarks on the
subject too narrowly. For example, I consider the work of Chantal Mouffe and
Emesto Laclau an extremely important contribution to thinking about a future so-
cialist politics. I think one has to avoid fighting over empty slogans.
Comment (Cornel West)
The question of totality signals an important theoretical
struggle with practical implications. I'm not so sure that the differences between
your position and Perry Anderson's, and those put forward by Stanley Aronowitz,
Chantal Mouffe, Emesto Laclau, and a host of others can be so easily reconciled.
And it seems to me that if we continue to formulate the question in the way that
you formulate it, we are on a crash course, because I think that holding on to the
conception of totality that you invoke ultimately leads toward a Leninist or Leninist-
like politics that is basically sectarian, that may be symptomatic of a pessimism
(though that is a question). If we opt for the position that Mouffe, Laclau, Aronowitz,
and others are suggesting, the results are radically anti-Leninist as well as radically
critical of a particular conception of totality. It is important to remember that nobody
here has defended a flat, dispersive politics. Nobody here has defended a reactionary
politics like that of the nouveaux philosophes. Rather, their critiques of totality are
enabling ones; they are critiques of a totality that is solely a regulative ideal we never
achieve, never reach. And if that is the case, I really don't see the kind of reconcil-
iation that you are talking about. I think you were very comradely in your ritualistic
gestures to Chantal and Emesto and others, but I am not so sure that we are as close
as you think. Now that means we're still comrades within the Left in the broad
sense, but these are significant differences and tendencies within the Left, and I
didn't want to end the discussion with a vague Hegelian reconciliation of things
when what I see is very significant and healthy struggle.
Jameson
I don't understand how the politics I am proposing is re-
pressive, since I don't think I have yet even proposed a politics, any more than I
have really proposed an aesthetics. Both of those seem to be all in the future. Let
me try to respond by expanding on the distinction that came up in the second
question, the notion of tactics versus strategy. It is not a question of substituting a
total class/party politics for the politics of new social movements. That would be
both ridiculous and self-defeating. The question is how to think those local struggles,
involving specific and often different groups, within some common project that is
called, for want of a better word, socialism. Why must these two things go together?
Because without some notion of a total transformation of society and without the
sense that the immediate project is a figure for that total transformation, so that
everybody has a stake in that particular struggle, the success of any local struggle is
doomed, limited to reform. And then it will lose its impetus, as any number of issue
movements have done. Yet an abstract politics that only talks socialism on some
global level is doomed to the sterility of sectarian politics. I am trying to suggest a
way in which these things always take place at two levels: as an embattled struggle
of a group, but also as a figure for an entire systemic transformation. And I don't
see how anything substantial can be achieved without that kind of dual thinking at
every moment in all of those struggles.
360
Andrew Ross
Notes
These lines are from an earlier draft of a chapter in Mary Oppen, Meaning a Life: An Au-
tobiography(Santa Barbara: Black Sparrow, 1978). which appeared 1n Ironwood, 5 (1975).
p. 58.
2 Interview with Charles Amirkhan1an and David Gitin, Ironwood, 5 (1975), p. 23.
3 Kenner. of course. has been one of the most successful apologists for Pound. Notwithstand-
ing the consequences of th1s k1nd of apology, 1nasmuch as it coincides with an apology for
poetry tout court, one might want to begin by asking Hans Magnus Enzensberger' s question
of all the plaintiffs against poetry: Why is it always poetry as a whole that is put on trial? On
this point. Plato stands 1n the same camp as traditional Marxist aesthet1c1ans. See Enzens-
berger's sweeping "Poetry and Politics," Critical Essays, ed. Reinhold Grumm and Bruce
Armstrong, trans. M1chael Roloff (New York: Continuum, 1982).
4 Oppen's answer to Brecht, however, reads as if it m1ght also be the grounds of a response
to Enzensberger's question posed above: "The actually forbidden word Brecht. of course,
could not wnte. It would be something like aesthetic. But the definition of the good life is
necessarily an aesthetic definition, and the mere fact of democracy has not formulated it,
nor 1f 1t is achieved, will the mere fact of an extension of democracy, though I do not mean
of course that restriction would do better." From "The Mind's Own Place," Kulchur. 3:10
(Summer 1963). p 8.
5 Charles Olson. Charles Olson and Ezra Pound: An Encounter at St. Elizabeth's, ed. Cathenne
Seelye (New York: GrossmansNiking, 1975), p 53.
6 Oppen, Meaning a Life, p. 136.
7 The terms are Althusser' s, or are associated primarily with Althusser' s critique of Marxist
humanism, but the reaction against these tendencies can be traced back through Gramsci,
Lukacs, and Lenin to Engels's attempts at "revisionism" after Marx's death.
8 See Terry Eagleton's extravagant discussion of BenJamin's description of the flaneur as a
self-contradictory commodity form in Walter BenJamin: Or Towards a Revolutionary Criticism
(London: Verso, 1981).
9 "Mayan Letters." Selected Writmgs. ed. Robert Creeley (New York: New Directions, 1966).
p. 82.
10 Preposttions: The Collected Critical Essays of Louis Zukofsky (Berkeley: University of California
Press, 1981).p.12.
11 Geoffrey Thurley, The American Moment: American Poetry in the Mid-Century (London: Ed-
ward Arnold, 1977). pp. 184, 36.
12 "Lenin mvented . . a new medium, something between speech and action, which is worth
... study." Zukofsky quoting Pound in Eric Mottram, "1924-1951: Politics and Form in
Zukofsky," Maps. 5 ( 1973). p. 76.
13 Contributor's note to New Directions m Prose and Poetry, ed. James Laughlin (New York:
New Directions, 1938).
14 Roman Jakobsen. "The Generation That Squandered Its Poets," Literature and Revolution,
ed. Jacques Ehrmann (Boston: Beacon Press, 1970). p. 125.
15 For a concise and evenhanded account of the abandonment of economism, see Raymond
Williams, "Base and Superstructure in Marxist Cultural Theory," Problems in Materialism and
Culture (London: Verso, 1980).
16 Althusser's response to cnticism, in Essays in Self-Criticism, trans. Graham Lock (London:
New Left Books, 1976). includes his famous confession of and apology for "theoreticism."
378
Andrew Ross
17 "In the final days of Western Marxism, one can, indeed, speak of a veritable hypertrophy of
the aesthetic-which came to be surcharged w1th all the values that were repressed or denied
elsewhere in the atrophy of living social 1st politics: utopian images of the future, ethical maxims
for the present, were displaced and condensed into vaulting meditations on art with which
Adorno or Sartre concluded much of their life's work." Perry Anderson, In the Tracks of
Historical Materialism (London: Verso, 1983). p. 17.
18 Georg Lukacs, History and Class Consciousness, trans. Rodney Livingstone (Cambridge: MIT
Press, 1971 ), p. 82.
19 Baudrillard· s attack on the concept of ·'production'' can be found in The Mirror of Production,
trans. Mark Poster (St Louis: Telos Press. 1975).
20 "The Ecstasy of Communication," The Anti-Aesthetic: Essays on Postmodern Culture, ed.
Hal Foster (Port Townsend, Wash.: Bay Press. 1983). p. 127.
21 "Towards a Critique of the Political Economy of the Sign," For a Critique of the Political
Economy of the Stgn, trans. Charles Levin (St. Louis: Telos Press, 1981). p. 150. Anal-
ternative metaphorical model for the circulation and exchange of Information would be Der-
rida's "postal state"-the product, as he sees it, of the historical development of capitalism
and the process of postal rationalization. Derrida's counterprinciple-"a letter can always
not reach its destination" -is an appeal to the undecidability of reception/consumption, as
opposed to production. See La carte postale (Paris: Flammarion, 1980).
22 Marc use is quoting Stanley Gerr on "the linguistic tendency 'to cons1der the names of things
as being indicative at the same time of their manner of functioning, and the names of prop-
erties and processes as symbolical of the apparatus used to detect or produce them.' "
From One-Dimensional Man: Studies in the Ideology of Advanced Industrial Society (Boston:
Beacon Press. 1964). pp. 86-87.
23 To choose two symptomatiC manifestations of this debate, Peter BUrger's neglect of con-
temporary art practices in Theory of the Avant-Garde, trans. Michael Shaw (Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press, 1984), could profitably be balanced against BenJamin Such-
low's incisive rev1ew of Burger's book, "Theorizing the Avant-Garde," Art in America (Nov.
1984). pp. 19-21. For an argument that considers both sides but leans toward Burger's,
see Andreas Huyssen, "The Search for Tradition: Avant-Garde and Postmodernism in the
1970s," New German Critique, 22 (Winter 1981), pp. 23-40.
24 Ron Silliman, "The Political Economy of Poetry," L=A=N= G= U=A= G=E (Open Letter
5:1). vol. 4, pp. 60-65. For a full-blown analysis of the commercial nepotism that regulates
social groupings among American intellectuals, see Richard Kostelanetz's "naming names"
expose of the "New York literary mob" and others in The End of Intelligent Writing-Literary
PolitiCS in America (New York: Sheed and Ward, 1974).
25 See Jed Rasula's revealing "year by year listing of books of poetry prominently reviewed in
the trade press. as denved from the Book Review Index." The percentage of reviews devoted
to small-press books is, of course, infinitesimal, while writers who have had both trade and
small-press publishers have "benefited" or "suffered" respectively from the disparity in the
attention paid to their work. Rasula's intention IS to show how the representation of Poetry
IS produced, not to argue that well-known writers are more mediocre than small-press writers.
See "The Role of Critics and the Emperor's New Clothes in American Poetry," Sulfur, 9
(1984), pp. 149-67.
26 Silliman, "The Political Economy of Poetry."
27 Silliman, for example, comments on the radical difference between the content-specific ori-
entation of minority, oppressed, or gay/lesbian writers, on the one hand, and the "purely
aesthetic" schools of white middle-class writers, on the other. He argues that "in fact the
aesthetics of those (latter] schools is a direct result of ideological struggle. . It is char-
acteristic of the class situation of these schools that this struggle is carried on in other
(aesthetic) terms." From "The Political Economy of Poetry," p. 62.
28 Response by Charles Bernstein to Silliman's comments on his "Thought's Measure,"
L=A=N=G=U=A=G=E, vol. 4, p. 22.
29 A representative selection of the early "talks" is in Hills, 6, and a later selection has been
published as Writmg!Talks, ed. Bob Perelman (Carbondale: Southern Illinois University Press,
1985). Poet's Theater scripts are published in Hills, 9.
30 In the case of the later talks, for example, many of which are subsidized through arts centers
in the form of writers' residence grants from the NEA, one has to consider the NEA's erratic
decisions in recent years to cut residency grants for artists and to axe critics' grants altogether,
while leaving the writers' quota largely intact The ideological constraints of working under
state sponsorship are familiar enough. The NEA, perceived as a national ornament, enjoyed
its most prominent period of financ1al and Ideological autonomy under the Nixon administra-
tion. The contrast with its impoverished condition under the New Right, which perceives it
379
as a purely ideological organ, is quite stnking. On some recent developments-the political
overridmg of the "peer-panel" system for grant distnbution, the preferential treatment of
m1d-career as opposed to younger artists-see Catherine Lord, "The President's Man: The
Arts Endowment under Frank Hodzoll," Afterimage, 10:7 (Feb. 1983).
31 Charles Bernstein, "The Conspiracy of 'Us'," The L=A=N=G=U=A=G=E Book, ed.
Charles Bernstein and Bruce Andrews (Carbondale: Southern Illinois Umversity Press, 1984),
pp. 186-87.
32 Viktor Shklovsky, "The Resurrection of the Word," Twentieth-Century Studies, 7/8 (Dec.
1972), p. 41.
33 "If Written Is Wnting," The L=A=N=G=U=A=G=E Book, p. 29.
34 Quoted by Bill Berkson in "Talk," Hills, 617 (Spring 1980), p. 19.
35 Ron Silliman, "Disappearance of the Word, Appearance of the World," The L=A=N=
G=U=A=G=E Book, pp. 121-32.
36 Charles Bernstein, "Wnt1ng and Method," Poetics Journal, 3 ( 1983), p. 8.
37 Barrett Watten, "Russian Formalism and the Present," Hills, 617 (Spnng 1980), pp. 50-74.
38 Charles Bernstein, "The Dollar Value of Poetry," The L=A=N=G=U=A=G=E Book, p.
140.
39 "1) The paragraph organizes the sentences; 2) The paragraph is a unit of quantity, not logic
or argument; 3) Sentence length is a unit of measure; 4) Sentence structure is altered for
torque, or Increased polysemy/amb1gu1ty; 5) Syllogistic movement IS a) limited b) controlled;
6) Pnmary syllog1stic movement is between the preceding and following sentences; 7) Sec-
ondary syllogistic movement is toward the paragraph as a whole, or the total work; 8) The
limiting of syllogistic movement keeps the reader's attention at or very close to the level of
language, that is most often at the sentence level or below." From Ron Silliman, "The New
Sentence," Hills, 617, (Spring 1980), p. 216.
40 Bertold Brecht, "On the Formalistic Character of the Theory of Realism," in Ernst Bloch et
al., Aesthetics and Politics, ed. Ronald Taylor (London: New Leh Books, 1977), p. 72.
41 Quoted from "Footnotes," a collage of comments about realism collected for a public pre-
sentation m the catalog for Eighty, Langton Street Residence Program 1981 (San Francisco,
1982), p. 133.
42 Jakobson, "The Gerneration That Squandered Its Poets," p. 124.
380
Fred Pfeil
Labour is, in the first place, a pro- So hold me, Mom, in your long
cess in which both Man and Nature arms.
participate, and in which Man of So hold me, Mom, in your long
his own accord starts, regulates, and arms.
393
controls the material reaction be- In your automatic arms. Your elec-
tween himself and Nature. He op- tronic arms. In your long arms.
poses himself to Nature as one of So hold me, Mom, in your long
her own forces, setting in motion arms.
arms and legs, head and hands, the Your petrochemical arms. Your
natural forces of his body in order military arms.
to appropriate Nature's production In your electronic arms. 44
in a form adapted to his wants. By
thus acting on the external world
and changing it, he at the same time
changes his own nature. He devel-
ops his slumbering powers and
compels them to act in obedience
to his sway. 43
394
Fred Pfeil
not of the domination of nature in production but of the domination of
women in the family-is a history of the manifold forms and relations of
sex-gender systems. Such a history would supply the basis for an account
of the Lacanian categories of the Imaginary and the Symbolic, categories
left unhistoricized until now. 47 But there is another task for a feminist ma-
terialism: the task of accounting for itsel£ Marx willingly admitted and
explained the extent to which his method of historical materialism and its
allied utopian vision of communist society was explicitly enabled by the
emergence of capitalism: the stripping away of all human relations but the
"cash nexus," he argued, permits us to see at last that "the history of all
hitherto existing society is the history of class struggles, " 48 just as the historic
rise ofthose two great antagonists, Capital and the massed Proletariat, points
the way toward a communist society in which all domination-except of
Nature-is only a reminder of the past. How, then, does the feminism of
Benjamin, Balbus, and Dinnerstein theorize its own historical enablement
out of the crux of the postmodemist moment? Does the de-Oedipalization
of contemporary middle-class culture really contain any utopian dimension
or revolutionary potential? If so, what is that potential for, and where does
it point from here?
The key question in this series is the second, and for Marxists
the obvious answer is No. The de-Oedipalization of middle-class life is a
capitalist pathology; the postmodemist culture arising from this pathology
is a mystification expressing only a very local, representational truth. Rev-
olutionary practices thus must await the moment when the revolutionary
subject constitutes itself through a re-Oedipalized entry into the Symbolic,
either through full recognition of its name as the Proletariat, master of
Nature, vide Jameson, or else through a reconstitution within the family of
the authorized Father, as suggested in the recent reactionary work of the
Marxist Christopher Lasch. 49 But for a materialist feminism, the answer is
Yes. De-Oedipalization opens the way to new, more coherent and complete
definitions of domination and Utopia alike. Moreover, insofar as its ap-
pearance is itself the perverse dialectical outcome of an earlier hegemony
of the Oedipal, with all its associated effects-an emphasis on instrumen-
tality, objectification, the flight from the pre-Oedipal Imaginary into the
Symbolic, and the male domination of Nature and women alike-it is a
prime example of that very "cunning of History" Marx and Hegel first
perceived. Our present confrontation with the social world we have created-
a Nature in which we are deeply implicated and from which we derive our
being-a social realm now coextensive with what is left of the other nature
on which it was built, is the result of a long era ofOedipality and the neurotic
domination of Nature.
This problem of Nature and our relationship to it is first and
most dramatically experienced by the subject as the problem of that Mother
who appears both coextensive and excruciatingly detached from us, who
has the power to meet or frustrate our every need. 5° The Oedipal break with
the Mother, moreover, serves not to resolve this painful ambiguity of good
mommy/bad mommy, inside and outside, but to allow the subject to take
flight from it into the Symbolic, where it will be repressed, only to reemerge
as the domination of nature and the subjugation of women. The dialectical
return of pre-Oedipality closes off this perverse escape route, and the de-
Oedipalized subject now must face itself within an ecosystem whose "nat-
395
ural" and "social" elements are inextricably fused. De-Oedipalization makes
possible a domination-free conception of political association and action as
well. However hostile male leftists and progressives may still be toward
women in general and feminism in particular, 51 their origins in de-Oedi-
palized middle-class homes account in large part for a profound shift in
political style, away from vanguardist conceptions and democratic-centralist
modes of organization toward grassroots mobilization and conscious de-
cision making. 52
Such changes are not merely the result of opportunistic thefts or
"lessons taken" from the women's movement but are also the result of a
deep convergence. This same general process of de-Oedipalization, which
loosens the bonds of male domination of women enough to release women
and their hitherto repressed social vision of reciprocity and nurturance into
the public realm, also dictates that the Oedipal break for the male child
more and more closely resembles that incomplete accession to the Symbolic
that has been historically characteristic of female psychic development. In
Stephanie Engels's terms, "the augmented importance of emotional relat-
edness, embeddedness, and dependence, and the decline of radical emo-
tional rupture and devastation [i.e., of the Oedipal break] put the contem-
porary boy in an effective and developmental position that looks much like
that traditionally characteristic of little girls." 53
From a feminist-materialist perspective, then, the de-Oedipali-
zation of American middle-class life releases historically new and progres-
sive social forces into American life-forces that Marxism, with its hypos-
tatization ofOedipality, is essentially incapable ofjoining or even evaluating
at their full worth. Yet these new forces all point to the necessity of a further
development within the sex-gender system, for if, as these new materialists
maintain, "the character of the relationship between the adult self and its
sexual, political and 'natural' others is decisively shaped by the character
of the relationship established between the childhood self and its first and
most salient, i.e., its parental others," 54 then the problems for those who
participate in the new social movements arising from de-Oedipalization-
feminism, the environmental movement, and a host of progressive grass-
roots coalitions-must be traced back to an unresolved dilemma within the
sex-gender system. De-Oedipalization may, for example, determine the sub-
ject's reinsertion back into a newly expanded Nature, but it does not supply
the material prerequisites for a newly articulated, deliberate yet benign re-
lationship with it. The subject reimmersed in an essentially pre-Oedipal
relationship to the world appears more likely to swing from one pole of
internality to another, from a rage at all that surrounds and threatens it to
a deliriously dispersed self-exaltation across the whole terrain of hollowed-
out signifiers. Neither, of course, are the new strategies of consensus and
grassroots consciousness raising and mobilization, however salutary these
may be compared to their antecedents, presently equipped to deal with
internal disagreements or to move from consciousness raising to concrete
social action.
Finally, it is clear that the increasing number of de-Oedipalized
middle-class male subjects, even ostensibly politically progressive ones, in
no way guarantees any decrease in their fear of and hostility toward women.
The relative closing off of the Oedipal escape route often seems to have
increased that hostility and fear, now that the safety of domination and the
396
Fred Pfeil
flight to the Symbolic is no longer available. Thus, it is possible to return
in partial agreement to the Marxist critique of the postmodernist moment
in American culture. Lasch's pessimistic depiction of the de-Oedipalized,
narcissistic subject's susceptibility to "soft" authoritarianism should not be
taken lightly; nor can Jameson's linkage of what he calls "micro-politics"
to terrorism, and his judgment of both as politically ineffectual, be dis-
missed. 55 But from a feminist-materialist standpoint, the solution to such
problems lies not in returning to the Symbolic-neither by restoring paternal
authority nor by messianic class struggle on a global scale-but in supplant-
ing the false resolution-through-escape offered by Oedipality to the intol-
erable swings of pre-Oedipality with a genuine passage through the pre-
Oedipal into a new sense of identity/otherness made possible by the co-
equal presence of male and female partners as mothers.
A transformation from exclusively female mothering to shared
mothering would be revolutionary, then, not only insofar as it would entail
wide-ranging transformations in the forms (and, arguably, relations) of pro-
duction, and in the relation of "public" to "private" life, but inasmuch as
the child's subjectivity could for the first time be defined and constituted
in a real dialectical interchange between Imaginary and Symbolic realms.
This essentially political project could be put in more strictly Hegelian terms,
as the transcendence of the antithetical terms ofnonidentityjimmersion and
identity/detachment through a historically new sense of identity as a mu-
tually reciprocal otherness56-a sense that would open the way for the de-
velopment of the new social forces both released and reconstrained by the
present hegemony of the de-Oedipal. 57
I have taken this detour through recent feminist theory in order
to lay the ground for an evaluation of the postmodernist structure offeeling,
one far different, and far more deeply ambivalent, than either the celebratory
fervor of its poststructuralist adherents or the dialectically tempered dis-
approval of the Marxist camp. The Jamesonian critique of postmodernist
cultural practice is correct insofar as it allows us to see the roots of these
practices in the de-Oedipalization of middle-class American society. Yet in
its privileging of the Oedipal escape into the Symbolic-a privileging in-
scribed within Marxism's general ontological assumptions-Marxism is un-
able to discover the historical possibilities of the postmodernist structure
of feeling or to specify preconditions for their development. A return to this
postmodernist structure of feeling, and more specifically to the experience
of those postmodernist works in music and performance art that have re-
cently begun to attract a mass audience, inevitably suggest, from a feminist-
materialist perspective, a more dialectical, even ambiguous judgment of that
experience-a judgment giving full weight to both the possibilities such work
offers us and the constraints it reproduces and distills.
I would like to conclude by trying to describe the experience of
postmodernist work from a feminist-materialist standpoint, in something
like its full ambiguity and irresolution. I have chosen exemplary moments
from three postmodernist works in which there seems to surface, at least
for an instant, something like a distinct political or historical reference point.
The first moment is the explicit appearance of the figure or image "Einstein"
in the Wilson/Glass opera Einstein on the Beach. Or perhaps "explicit fore-
grounding" is the better term, for in a sense the Einstein figure is never
397
absent. In every scene and interlude (or "Knee Play"), performers "dressed
'like Einstein,' as Wilson sees him, in grey pants, suspenders and black tennis
shoes,'' are present on stage. 58 Thus the figure of "Einstein" is decentered,
replicated, dispersed across the decelerated, oneiric landscape of the work.
Moreover, when an unmistakable representation of Einstein appears-a pho-
tograph of the young Einstein flashes on the backdrop, accompanied by the
spoken announcement "Berne 1905"; a figure dressed as Einstein, wigged
and mustachioed, plays the violin on the forefront of the stage-its presence
is immediately folded back into the musical and/or dramatic ground of
nonconsequential repetition and succession. In Einstein on the Beach, we
experience this constant engulfment of the historical figure more or less
wholeheartedly as a pleasure; the embedding and scattering ofthe Symbolic
figure, so problematic and disturbing in the range of contradictory meanings
its presence calls up (Einstein the socialist and devout pacifist; Einstein the
"Father of the Atom Bomb," etc.), defuses the potential force and compli-
cation of those meanings by dissolving them in a preverbal Imaginary space.
Wilson freely admits how much his dramaturgic practice owes to his ob-
servations of the mother-infant relationship; 59 and he describes the goal of
his productions as a relationship of Imaginary, preverbal communication-
through-identity between spectator and performer: "Ideally, someone in the
audience might reach a point of consciouness where he is on the same
frequency as one of the performers-where he receives communication di-
rectly."60 Needless to say, this is an impossible ideal, insofar as any com-
munication involves some perception of difference, some relation to that
Symbolic realm Wilson wants to efface. Yet the pleasure we are invited to
experience is precisely that of an unambiguous, pure, and omnipotent return
to life in the Imaginary-to pre-Oedipality as a new, sublime Benign.
Such moments from Einstein on the Beach, and the blissful pre-
Oedipal immersion they offer us, may be compared with a more troubled
moment in the recent work of Wilson's collaborator, composer Philip Glass,
in collaboration with filmmaker Godfrey Reggio in his 1982 Koyaanisqatsi.
As reviewers noted, the film itself is both rather simpleminded and sur-
prisingly incoherent. 61 A narrationless contrast between the steady majestic
grace ofunspoiled Nature and the brutal, senseless frenzy of contemporary
Western industrial society is apparently intended to make us aware that our
world is "out of balance" (Koyaanisqatsi being a Hopi word for such a
world); yet this explicit intent is undercut by the berserk excitement we
come to feel during the long montage sequence of speeded-up footage of
crowds streaking down stairs, zipping in and out of corporate towers, and
of traffic smearing into multicolored veins. The perverse beauty and ex-
citement of this sequence, moreover, are extended and complicated by Glass's
music, in which a slowly rising set of choral arpeggios, through ascension,
repetition, and crescendo, gradually turn into a nearly intolerable screamfest.
In this way-for the music never ceases to be overwhelmingly, repetitiously
gorgeous-Glass's score contributes to the film's decoding of the very set of
Symbolic categories introduced at its conclusion, when the audience is given
a set of Hopi words and proverbs with which, presumably, we are intended
to structure and encode the experience we have just been through. The
problem is that this literal accession to the Symbolic is rather too much like
the Oedipal moment for the American middle-class child, that is, both too
weak and too late.
398
Fred Pfeil
Although the experience of Koyaanisqatsi thus proves to be in
its own way as much an aesthetic (re)experience of the pre-Oedipal Ima-
ginary as Wilson's Einstein on the Beach, here our pleasure in that Imaginary
engulfment is more problematically riddled with a pre-Oedipal aggressive-
ness absent from most of Wilson's work. Such a troubled, delirious, oscil-
lating pleasure is typified in our reaction to the musical sequence just de-
scribed: so gorgeous, continuous, and overwhelming that we want it never
to stop, yet so shatteringly intrusive and monotonous that it is simultane-
ously a menace to be resisted.
From the critical and political position I have taken here, I would
like to say that this latter pleasure seems preferable to the former, not by
any criterion of aesthetic "quality" or intensity of feeling, but in terms of
the recognitions and affirmations these two different modalities of pleasure
call upon us to make. Evidently, both Wilson's dramaturgy and (at least in
the sequence discussed) Glass's music invite us to enjoy our fundamentally
pre-Oedipal relationship to the world, the reclamation of social experience
and historical representation by the Imaginary. Yet whereas in Wilson's
work the pleasure induced by that reclamation is a regression to be wished
for and enjoyed, in Glass's music it is also experienced as intolerable. Insofar
as a modality of pleasure encourages a given attitude toward the structure
of feeling it draws on, and so valorizes certain attitudes toward the world,
Wilson's work is liable to the charge that it encourages a heedless acceptance
and acquiescence on the part of the enjoying subject, while Glass's work
more dialectically invites us to enjoy such a pre-Oedipal relationship yet
wish for a resolution of its antinomies.
That may be all that the best postmodernist work can do for the
mass audience now seeking it out: in this moment-characterized both by
the release of new sociopolitical forces through the de-Oedipalization of
middle-class American life and by the hegemony of this same de-Oedipalized
social-sexual structure that tends to block the further development of those
social forces-the most progressive postmodernist work can only foreground
our inherent irresolution. Thus, postmodernism offers its mass audience the
most scandalously ambivalent pleasure possible. Yet as I see and hear these
works, there are rare moments that seem to edge slightly past this threshold
to hint at the possibility of a genuine passage through the pre-Oedipal into
another structure of feeling, another form of life.
Such a moment occurred for me at the end of a performance by
Laurie Anderson when, in the characteristically neutral, even empty voice
that constitutes a sort of pedal point in her vocal repertoire, she announced
"Born-never asked," without inflection. On the screen behind her a series
of still images appeared, slide projections of old colored rotogravures de-
picting various wild animals-leopards, snakes, and so on-in their tropical
habitats; meanwhile, a low, percussive cadence of saxophone and taped
sound gradually transformed itself into a slowly varying melody, simulta-
neously blues-y and vaguely "Eastern" in character, familiar from her having
performed it on the violin earlier that night. "You were born," she said in
the same toneless voice, "and so you're free. Happy Birthday."
The words and pictures offered us a pleasure not so different from
that I have just described in connection with Glass's music-a pleasure
fundamentally in recognition of our real ambivalence. The covert melan-
cholia of the music, the sense of past time saturating the slides of the old
399
pictures, seemed to hint either that we are inevitably not, after all, so fully,
preverbally immersed and/or that perhaps the freedom of such an Imaginary
existence was not so free anyway. The very flatness of Anderson's voice
both affirmed and retracted its own liberatory announcement. Then the
music stopped and the sequence of images concluded with one rotogravure
depicting two white men in colonial uniforms astride two elephants, out
hunting in what had suddenly become an Empire, a dominated zone. It was
an astonishing instant, exhilirating yet perplexing; rather as if, with the
entrance of the historical-political into the ambiguous postmodemist pleas-
ure of the pre-Oedipal, I was being hailed by a new sense, a new kind of
relationship to the Real, which neither I nor Laurie Anderson nor anyone
else in the hall was as yet able to live or name.
My aim in this essay has been not only to articulate the social
transformations that have made such a call liminally possible within the
most engaged postmodemist work, but to explain this final, most vexing
pleasure, and the structure of feeling it might rest on.
Notes
Marjorie Perloff, Frank O'Hara. Poet among Painters (New York: G. Braziller, 1977). or "Con-
temporary/Postmodern: The 'New' Poetry," in Romanticism. Moderntsm. Postmodernism.
ed. Harry R. Garvin (Lewisburg: Bucknell University Press. 1980). pp. 171-79. In both these
writings, Perloff offers interesting insights into the techniques and effects of the poetry she
describes but fails to consider the question of what makes such poetry pleasurable to what
groups of readers. In other words. her criticism remains enclosed within a formalism that
stunts its own best insights.
2 Hilton Kramer's game defense of modernism and high culture in general may be followed in
the New York Times. Most of Gerald Graff's "pacification" operations to date are collected
in Literature against Itself: Literary Ideas in Modern Society (Chicago: University of Chicago
Press. 1979).
3 For an example of the major arguments and positions involved in the Marxist debate. see
Ernst Bloch et al., Aesthetics and Politics (London: New Left Books, 1977).
4 See Fredric Jameson, "Reflections in Conclusion," in Aesthetics and Politics, pp. 196-213,
from which most of my examples of modernist "trickle-down" have been taken, and his
equally remarkable "Reification and Utopia in Mass Culture," Social Text. 1 (Spring 1979),
pp. 130-48.
5 See, for example, the contributions by lhab Hassan and Wallace Martin in the final section
of Romanticism. Modernism. Postmodernism, pp. 117-26, 146-54; lhab Hassan, "Joyce.
Beckett, and the Post-modern Imagination," in Triquarterly, 34 (Fall 1975), pp. 179-200;
and/or David Antin, "Modernism and Postmodernism: Approaching the Present in American
Poetry," boundary 2. 1. no.1 (Fall 1972). pp. 98-133.
6 Raymond Williams. Marxism and Literature (New York: Oxford University Press. 1977). pp.
133-34 (final emphasis mine).
7 In another essay I have explicitly criticized this very concept. and Williams's Marxism and
Literature as a whole, for its incompatibility with the Marxist-materialist tradition it purports
to follow and extend; see Fred Pfeil, "Towards a Portable Marxist Criticism: A Critique and
Suggestion." College English. 41, no. 7 (Mar. 1980). pp. 753-68. I now wish to alter that
criticism, but not retract it. Specifically, it seems to me that Williams's use of concepts like
"structure of feeling" and criticisms of such standard Marxist terminology as the familiarly
opposed "base" and "superstructure" slide into a proto-idealist abstraction and insubstan-
tiality precisely because his allegiance to the primacy of production blinds him to another at
least equally primary process and level of material practice: the acquisition and construction
of self, language, and gender, a process that feminists argue is at least as fully constitutive
of production in the Marxist sense as it is constituted or determined by the latter. Without
the grounding of a feminist theory rooted in the psychosociological history of selfhood, en-
genderation. and the subject's accession into the universe of signification, Williams's critique
of orthodox Marxism rests upon air; and his emphasis on the process of signification appears
400
Fred Pfeil
as an idealist "invisible man," both swathed and blindfolded by the Marxist wrappings that
hold its shape barely in place.
8 See the landmark essay by Barbara and John Ehrenreich, "The Professional-Managerial Class,"
in Between Labor and Capital, ed. Pat Walker (Boston: South End Press, 1979). pp 5-45.
9 For a vivid social history and analysis of this transformation, see Barbara Ehrenreich and
Deirdre English, For Her Own Good: 750 Years of Experts' Advice to Women (New York:
Doubleday, 1979), pp. 211-324; and for an insightful account of the profound psychological
shifts resulting from it. and of their political significance, see Nancy Chodorow, "Oedipal
Assymetries and Heterosexual Knots." Social Problems, 23 (Apr. 1976). pp. 454-68.
10 On the relative stability of the ruling-class and working-class family structure, see Amy Swerd-
low, Renata Bridenthal. Joan Kelly, and Phyllis Vine, Household and Km (Old Westbury, N.Y.:
Feminist Press, 1981 ), pt. 2, pp. 50-105. For a further examination of the life cycle of the
contemporary American working-class family, see Lillian Rubin's moving Worlds of Pain: Life
in the Working-Class Family (New York: Basic Books. 1976)
11 Lyrics from "A1r," on Talking Heads, Fear of Music (Sire Records, SKR-6076, 1979).
12 Lyrics from "0 Superman," on Laurie Anderson, B1g Science (Warner Bros. Records BSK-
3674, 1982)
13 Text by Christopher Knowles, quoted from a booklet accompanying Robert Wilson and Philip
Glass, Einstein on the Beach (Tomato Records TOM-4-290 1, 1979).
14 Cra1g Owens, "Amplifications: Laurie Anderson:· Art in America, Mar. 1981, p. 122.
15 The quotation from Levi-Strauss is the epigraph to Nadine Gordimer, Burger's Daughter (New
York: Viking, 1979); I do not know its original source. The quotation from Laurie Anderson
is 1n Cra1g Owens, "The Allegorical Impulse: Towards a Theory of Postmodernism.'' October,
12 (Spring 1980). p. 59.
16 From my notes on her sold-out performance in Portland, Oregon, sponsored by the Portland
Center for the Visual Arts, April 24, 1982.
17 "Let X~ X" is on Anderson's Big Science, "Air" and "Animals" (from which the quotation
is taken) are from Talking Heads's Fear of Music.
18 Fredric Jameson, "Language and Modes of Production" (unpublished manuscript), pp. 28-
29.
19 "0 Superman.'' on Anderson's Big Science.
20 "Heaven.'' on Talking Heads's Fear of Music.
21 Back liner notes to Wilson and Glass's Einstein on the Beach.
22 In recent works by postmodernist composers Phil1p Glass and Steve Reich Glassworks, Var-
iations for Wmds, Strings and Keyboard, 1979, and Vermont Counterpoint, 1982-both to
my knowledge presently unrecorded-! believe it is possible to hear distinct signs of such
harmonies reminiscent of those of Gershwin-signs that may be symptomatic of a movement
toward the tropes and satisfactions of mass culture.
23 I should note that, in his recent work, Craig Owens has been concerned to describe and
endorse a v1ew of postmodernist cultural production that is simultaneously far more political
and more discriminating than the view ascribed to him here; see. for example, "The Discourse
of Others.'' in The Anti-Aesthetic: Essays on Postmodern Culture, ed. Hal Foster (New York:
Bay Press, 1983). Nonetheless. Owens's mam concern remains the politics and intended
political effects of specific, politically self-conscious postmodernist works; whereas my aim
here, as I hope has now become clear, is to provide a symptomatic political reading both of
certain mternally unpolitical, even retrograde postmodern works that have managed to reach
a mass audience, and-even more decisively-of the mass audience that consumes them.
24 The phrase is Roland Barthes's. quoted by Rosalind Krauss, "Poststructuralism and the
'Paraliterary'.'' October, 13 (Summer 1980), p. 190.
25 Charles Russel, ·'The Context of the Concept.·' in Romanticism, Modernism, Postmodernism,
p. 190.
26 The members of Talking Heads have New York art school backgrounds, for example, while
Laurie Anderson at one time was herself a practicing art historian. In addition to such bio-
graphical details, I suspect close relationships inevitably exist as well between the artists and
their academic-intellectual publicists.
27 The one exception to th1s silence that I know of is Rosalind Krauss's suggestion that students'
interest in contemporary postmodernist literature-chiefly the work of Barthes and Derrida-
follows from their absorption of the modernist tent of self-reflexiveness in both texts and
readings; see her "Poststructuralism and the 'Paraliterary' :· p. 40. But such an explanation
scarcely touches the question of pleasure; rather, it opens up the ground for another round
401
of the stale argument over whether or not postmodernism is distinct from modernism, a
debate I have already suggested we should not have to engage in anymore.
28 Fredric Jameson, "The Concept of the Sixties" (unpublished manuscript). p. 23.
29 Jameson, "Language and Modes of Production," p. 28.
30 Those whose degrees come from community colleges and/or elite schools are invited to
investigate the social dynamtcs of thetr own educational experience as well. For any such
mvestigation, the most detailed and useful text is, of course, Samuel Bowles and Herb Gintis,
Schooling in Capitalist America (New York: Basic Books, 1976). especially pp. 201-23.
31 "The bureaucrattzation of the world" is the tttle of Henry Jacoby's historical analysis of the
rise and spread of bureaucracy (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1973); the second
quotatton is from Anthony Giddens, Sociologv.· A Brief but Critical Introduction (London:
Macmillan, 1982). p. 88.
32 Cf. Rtchard Edwards's use of this term, as differentiated from etther "technical" or "direct"
control, in Contested Terrain: The Transformation of the Workplace in the Twentieth Century
(New York: Baste Books, 1979).
33 Jon Schiller, "The New 'Family Romance'," Triquarterly, 52 (Fall 1981). p. 70.
34 Judith Wtlliamson, Decoding Advertisements: Ideology and Meamng in Advertisements (Salem:
Marion Soyars, 1978). pp. 44-45.
35 See Jacques Lacan, "The Mirror Phase as Formative of the Function of the I," New Left
Review, 51 (Sept.-Oct. 1968). pp. 71-77.
36 Willtamson, p. 65.
37 Jean-Paul Sartre, Search for a Method, trans. Hazel Barnes (New York: Knopf, 1963). p.
63.
38 My account here is particularly reductive insofar as 1t conflates highly significant differences
between female and male engenderation and psychtc formation in both the pre-Oedipal and
Oedipal stages. For a far more comprehensive analysis, see Nancy Chodorow, The Repro-
duction of Mothering: Psychoanalysis and the Sociology of Gender (Berkeley: University of
Caltfornia Press, 1978). especially pp. 57-140; and Isaac Balbus, Marxism and Domination:
A Neo-Hegelian, Femmist, Psychoanalv.ttc Theory of Sexual, Political, and Technological Lib-
eration (Princeton: Princeton Universtty Press, 1982). pp. 303-22.
39 Schiller. "The New 'Family Romance'." p 83.
40 lbtd., p.71.
41 A good deal of the concrete historical data necessary for the construction of this argument
with regard to American soctety in particular may be found in Carl Degler, At Odds: Women
and the Family in America from the Revolution to the Present (New York: Oxford University
Press, 1980)
42 Michel Foucault. The History of Sexuality, vol. 1, trans. Robert Hurley (New York: Pantheon,
1978). p. 93.
43 Karl Marx, Capital, vol. 1 (New York: International Publishers, 1967), p. 177 (my emphasis).
44 "0 Superman," on Anderson's Big Science.
45 My reading here summarizes and extends that of Balbus in Marxism and Domination, pp.
269-78; and of Phyllis Zuckerman, "Nature as Surplus-the Work of the Text in Marx," the
minnesota revtew, (n.s.) 20 (Spring 1983). pp. 103-11.
46 Michele Barrett and Mary Mcintosh, "Narcissim and the Family A Critique of Lasch," New
Left Review, 135 (Sept.-Oct. 1982). p. 48.
47 See Gayle Rubin, ''The Traffic in Women,'' in Toward an Anthropology of Women, ed. Rayna
Retter (New York: Monthly Review Press, 1975). pp. 15 7-21 0-probably the first feminist
work to lay the grounds for such an undertaking. Isaac Balbus attempts a very brief and
inevitably reductive historical sketch of the Western sex/gender system as the determinant
of what he calls the "mode of symbolization" in Marxism and Domination, pp. 303-52. Of
course, much more work needs to be done.
This is perhaps also the place for a bnef word on the peculiar relevance and
obstructiveness of Lacantan terminology and analysis in such an undertaking. I suspect. for
example, that many Lacanians, perhaps especially Lacanian Marxists, would want to criticize
my rough equation of the Lacanian "mirror-stage" with the pre-Oedipal stage as defined by
femtnist-materialists after Klem. Yet it is this very disengagement of the process of the for-
mation of the self from the mother-child relationship by means of the frankly hypothetical
scenario of the child before the mirror that arouses my suspicion. It may be that the importance
of Lacanian thought for much recent Marxist theory-for example, in the work of both Jame-
son and Williamson, ctted above-ts not only a functton of the real value of the concepts of
402
Fred Pfeil
the Imaginary, the SymboliC, and the Real, for Marxist and feminist work alike, but of the
opportunity Lacanian analysis offers Marxism to speak of the constitution of the self in psy-
choanalytiC terms without opening a Pandora's box of the sex/gender system-and thus of
sexual politiCS generally. So, while the categones of the Imaginary and the Symbolic seem
to me of fundamental importance for feminist analysis, they must not only be historicized by
that analySIS but detached as well from any unrevised concept from which the presence of
the subject's f1rst and most s1gnificant Other and the whole question of engenderation are
elided.
48 Karl Marx, "The Communist Manifesto." in Karl Marx. Selected Wntmgs, ed. David Mclellan
(New York: Oxford University Press. 1977). p. 222.
49 The messian1c moment of class struggle proper is called up frequently and regularly in Jame-
son's work. See. for example, the closing pages of his essay "On Interpretation," The Political
Unconscious: Narrative as a Socially SymboliC Act (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1981).
pp. 17-102, and the prophecy with which "The Concept of the Sixties" closes: "even if
Marx1sm is . not now true, it will become true again as the global development of this
new stage of capitalism unfolds before us" (p. 35).
Lasch's more confused and regressive prescriptions may be found in Haven
in a Heartless World: The Family Besieged (New York: Norton, 1974) and The Culture of
Narc1ssism: American Life in an Age of Dimimshing Expectations (New York: Norton, 1979)
Unfortunately, the undialectical harshness of his JUdgment of de-Oedipalization infects work
that IS far more suggestive and interesting than his own. Jon Schiller's "The New 'Family
Romance'," for example, IS crippled by a reading of de-Oedipalization that owes too much
to Lasch and too little to D~nnerstein and Chodorow; thus is he able to conclude that de-
Oedipallzatlon leads only to a "rebellious practice" whose "psychology . . seems to pre-
clude any active political significance" (p. 84).
50 For a fuller exposition of both this point and those that follow, see Dorothy Dinnerstein, The
Mermaid and the Minotaur: Sexual Arrangements and the Human Malaise (New York: Harper
and Row. 1976); and Balbus, Marxism and Domination, pp. 303-52.
51 For an insightful analysis of this de-Oedipalized hostility, see Balbus, pp. 384-98. especially
p. 393.
52 Unfortunately, the converse seems to be true as well. Insofar as working-class men and
women stilll1ve and labor within a world in wh1ch Oedipality remains supreme, working-class
women may cont1nue to find it hard to make common cause with feminism; and working-
class men and women alike may find political organizations with one form or another of top-
down control-from the Revolutionary Communist party to the local Democratic party ma-
chine-most "natural" to them.
53 Stephanie Engels, "Femininity as Tragedy: Re-examining the 'New Narcissism'," Socialist
Review (Sept.-Oct 1980). p. 97.
54 Balbus. p. 303.
55 Lasch, "The Concept of the Sixties," pp. 31-35.
56 See Balbus. pp. 279-302. Once again, moreover, it is interesting to compare the de-Oed-
ipalized utopia sketched out by feminist-materialists like Balbus and Dinnerstein with Marx's
equally tentative, deliberately sketchy observations on the Utopia at the origin and end of his
youthful speculation on communist society 1n his notes on James Mill; for example, "our
products would be like so many mirrors, out of wh1ch our essence shone'' (Karl Marx: Selected
Writings, p. 122). appears in light of Lacanian terminology and a feminist-materialist analysis
as a flagrant example of the Oedipalized subject's hopeless longing for its pre-Symbolic "Ideal-
Ego."
57 I should make clear that of the three maJor feminist-materialists whose work I have drawn
upon here. it is D1nnerstein and Balbus who have argued the case for "co-mothering" along
these holistic lines. By contrast, Chodorow calls for co-mothering as a necessary step in the
achievement of sexual equal1ty and freedom, that is, for the cause of women's liberation
spec1f1cally.
58 Susan Flakes. "Robert Wilson's Einstein on the Beach," The Drama Review, 72 (Dec. 1976).
p. 71.
59 See Calvin Tomkins, The Scene.· Reports on Post-Modern Art (New York: Viking, 1976). p.
240.
60 Quoted in Tomkins, p. 263.
61 See. for example, Gregory Sandow's review in The Village Voice, Oct. 12, 1982, p. 58.
403
Eugene Holland
Capitalism
Despotism I XI y
Permanent
Revolution
I
I
-Y I -X
Savagery
Figure 1.
lates throughout the community and does not accrue to a single group or
individual. This is no rousseauistic Utopia, however, since savage society
is the one most harshly governed by exacting codes of conduct, belief, and
meaning-codes that Deleuze and Guattari consider inherently repressive.
And since authentic, unconscious desire is radically indeterminate-or
"schizophrenic," in their term, any fixed determination of it, such as that
imposed by linguistic and social codes, hence inevitably distorts and mis-
represents it. 6
As much as the Symbolic codes of savage society may irrevocably
fix and therefore distort desire, savage coding nonetheless operates in a
comparatively egalitarian manner so as to avoid and even actively defuse
accumulated power. Under despotism, by contrast, distorting representa-
tions are promulgated precisely in order to establish class divisions and
hierarchy, as the distortions inherent in all forms of coding are bent to the
service of explicit political power and direct social domination. Only here
does the name-of-the-father-or, more aptly, the name-of-the-despot-gov-
ern the entire Symbolic order; only here are the name-of-the-father and
patriarchal domination in the nuclear family homologous with the name-
of-the-despot and political domination in society as a whole; only here are
all social codes in the Symbolic order subordinated to the all-powerful im-
perial "overcoding" of the despot. As the privileged source of all "author-
ized" meaning and true possessor of all social wealth, the despot represents
and occupies the fixed center of the Symbolic order in traditional power
society.
Under capitalism, by contrast, there is no fixed center of this
kind, no transcendental signified, no established authority figure; rather,
exchange value and the market ruthlessly undermine and eliminate all tra-
ditional meanings and preexisting social codes: 7 the fabric of capitalist so-
ciety is knit not by concrete, qualitative relations but by abstract, quanti-
tative ones-by the "cash nexus. " 8 The basis of capitalist society is not
territory, as in savagery, nor the priest, king, or god, as under despotism,
but the abstract calculus of capital itself. Capital, as an abstract, quantitative
calculus, provides no universal codes capable of organizing and compre-
hending the whole of social life. In opposition to savage "coding" and des-
potic "overcoding," then, the semiotic process governing the Symbolic order
under capitalism is "decoding," market society's aggressive elimination of
all preexisting meanings and codes. 9
407
According to Deleuze and Guattari, more important than the
Oedipus complex in determining the nature of psychic life, given the dif-
fering nature of the Symbolic order in different types of society, is the specific
form ofsemiosis operative in a particular social formation. And the decoding
process, inasmuch as it frees desire from capture and distortion by social
coding, must be considered one of the positive features of the capitalist
Symbolic order: one corollary of the immense productivity of capitalism
admired by Marx is the freedom it grants desire to escape fixture in estab-
lished codes. But the liberating effects of decoding that stem from the eco-
nomic component of capitalist society are always accompanied by opposing
processes of recoding stemming from its power component, which tie freed
libidinal energy back onto factitious codes so as to extract and realize pri-
vately appropriable surplus value. This opposition between decoding and
recoding derives not so much from the classical, nineteenth-century con-
tradiction between outright owners of capital and the dispossessed as from
the contradiction between the generally socialized production of surplus
value, on the one hand, and its private management, on the other. Capi-
talism devotes itself to production as an end in itself, to developing the
productivity of socialized labor to the utmost; yet due to private investment
in the means of production, social labor and life also are restricted to pro-
duction and consumption which valorize only the already existing capital-
stock.
In the third volume of Capital, Marx outlines these two moments
of capital's ongoing self-expansion. 10 In a first moment, a new, more pro-
ductive capital-stock transforms the preexisting apparatuses of production
and consumption, and this "continual revolution of the means of produc-
tion" characteristic of capitalism spawns decoding throughout society. But
in a second moment, this progressive movement is abruptly stopped and
everything is recoded: the evolving apparatuses of production and con-
sumption alike are tied down to now-obsolete capital-stock solely to valorize
it and realize profit on previous investment. The decoding process liberates
all kinds of creative energies (in consumption as well as in production) at
the same time that it revolutionizes and socializes productive forces; but
then recoding yokes and stultifies the relations of production and con-
sumption in the service of private surplus appropriation.
In this light, one of the aims of revolution is to eliminate the
power component from capitalism so as to enable the decoding process
inherent in economic society to free libidinal energy as much as possible
from the constraints of social coding. Thus, having disappeared as the basis
of despotic society as a whole, the semiotic form of power society never-
theless reappears under capitalism in a host of miniature despotisms, each
imposing a factitious code on a domain of human activity whose libidinal
energies relentlessly seek to escape it. A marxist cultural criticism wants to
target and dismantle the processes of recoding that serve to perpetuate the
power component of capitalist society and thus prevent the realization of
permanent revolution. This is, in fact, one of the aims ofwhat Deleuze and
Guattari call "schizoanalysis," their postmodern transmutation of psycho-
analysis. For convenience' sake, we may locate these recoding processes
schematically in three domains-the sphere of production, the nuclear fam-
ily, and the sphere of consumption-according to whether the temporary
and local meanings they introduce serve to enable people to perform jobs
408
Eugene Holland
and administrative functions, induce them to consume certain commodities
to realize profit on invested capital, or finally prepare them to accept psy-
chological manipulation in a wide range of oedipal forms.
In the sphere of production, the most pervasive and widely rec-
ognized form of recoding is bureaucratization. In bureaucracy, a given do-
main of human activity is isolated from the warp and woof of social life,
stripped of its traditional meanings and practices, and then subjected to the
abstract rationality of formal administration. Free human activity is de-
prived of its spontaneous self-determination and subordinated to the process
Max Weber calls "rationalization." But this rationalization takes place in
a host of parallel and semiautonomous domains of application linked only
by the market; hence, Lukacs's concept of reification is more appropriate
and revealing. Full-scale capitalist development witnesses the taylorization
and technologization of production, the professionalization of knowledge
and expertise, the bureaucratization of public administration. Reification
in all these domains means that
artificially isolated partial functions [are] performed
in the most rational manner by "specialists," [which]
has the effect of making these partial functions auton-
omous [so that] they develop through their own mo-
mentum and in accordance with their own special laws
independently of other partial functions of society....
All issues are subjected to an increasingly formal and
standardized treatment ... in which there is an ever-
increasing remoteness from the qualitative and ma-
terial essence ofthe "things" to which [such] bureau-
cratic activity pertains. 11
One counterpart to the administrative mode' of capitalist recoding
exemplified in bureaucracy is the aesthetic of modernism. Although its do-
main of application is very different, the same form of semiosis applies: cut
off from direct communication with its public, the modernist artwork is no
longer conceived of as expressing social life itself but rather as presenting
the artist's own privileged point of view or mode of perception; reference
to the work of art itself replaces reference to social life as the organizing
master code of the work. This form of reified recoding appears with par-
ticular clarity in architecture of the so-called International Style, especially
in the monumental buildings of Mies van der Rohe and the urban plans of
Le Corbusier. The office building, referent of high modernist design-the
social relations that the signifying systems of architecture and urban plan-
ning ultimately refer to-has been banished; and the dense and complex
interlocking network of city life has been completely ironed out by Le Cor-
busier into vacuous parkland punctuated by high-rise towers linked by free-
ways. The aesthetic domain is emptied of its conventional, social content
and reorganized according to a new and more abstract master code. All that
remains once social reference has been eliminated in these ways is the special
meaning these designs are intended to convey, their signified. And what the
high modernist monument or cityscape in fact signifies is rationalization
itself, the notion of a purely formal or abstract rationality that will solve
409
the problems of the city through systematic simplification and the problems
of architectural aesthetics through absolute purification. Thus the decoded,
abstract rationality of"form follows function" (the elimination of ornament,
the subordination of design to technology, etc.) is reendowed with a positive
meaning-recoded "on the spot" or "in place" (sur place), as Deleuze and
Guattari would say-with the slogan "less is more." 12
Because, under capitalism, it is segregated from social production,
where decoding operates at full throttle, the nuclear family is a prime locus
of recoding. 13 Isolated from society at large, and thus restricted to the family
triangle for its objects of desire, the individual psyche takes the full impress
of the Oedipus complex; hence the relative adequacy of freudian psycho-
analysis in describing oedipal desire in the nuclear family under classical
or market capitalism, that is, insofar as the nuclear family itself retains a
relative autonomy from "external" social forces. But the nuclear family does
not long retain even that relative autonomy, as Christopher Lasch has shown,
once capitalism moves from the market to the monopoly stage around the
tum of the century.
Whereas Lasch considers a renewed Oedipus to be our last hope
for psychic health and social stability in the face of rampant pathological
narcissism, Deleuze and Guattari see the nuclear family's oedipal inscription
of the psyche as a last-ditch effort to repress desire in its authentic, schiz-
ophrenic form. Sequestered from the decoding process at work in capitalist
society at large, the nuclear family reinscribes the oppressive but now so-
cially obsolete role of the despot in the repressive figure of the father, which
the individual then internalizes as the name-of-the-father function of La-
can's Symbolic order. Furthermore, as the nuclear family breaks down and
increasingly fails to perform the oedipal reinscription of desire, according
to schizoanalysis, it is precisely psychoanalysis that steps in to finish the
job. If need be, the psychoanalyst shoulders the mantle of the despot (in
the famous "transference") to ensure that no desire at all escapes oedipal
triangulation. From the point of view of schizoanalysis, then, the Oedipus
is an archaic and reactionary despotism installed at the heart of the nuclear
family under capitalism to recontain the free flow of desire unleashed by
capitalist decoding in society at large. And the institution of psychoanalysis
is the repressive agency of last resort whenever the deteriorating nuclear
family fails to ensure complete oedipalization all by itself.
Comparing schizoanalysis with Lasch's perspective is illuminat-
ing because both address some of the same material-the disappearance of
the autonomous bourgeois ego-but from opposing points of view: the lib-
eration Deleuze and Guattari celebrate under the rubric of schizophrenia,
Lasch castigates as a feature of pathological narcissism; Lasch explains the
development of what he calls the "culture of narcissism" in terms of the
decline of the family, whereas Deleuze and Guattari insist on placing the
family in its sociohistorical context and considering culture and society as
a whole. Based on the ego psychology of Otto Kernberg and Heinz Kohut,
and taking the family as its pivotal determining instance, Lasch's "histor-
ical" explanation runs something like this: The autonomous bourgeois fam-
ily is dissolved by the pervasive administration of monopoly capitalism,
with two principal results. First, paternal authority declines, stunting the
development of the child's superego; and second, maternal instinct falters,
410
Eugene Holland
as the mother's ambivalent feelings split the child's self-image into good
and bad versions that cannot be synthesized, while the child's inconsistent
behavior traumatizes frustration, on the one hand, by inculcating exagger-
ated expectations that are, on the other hand, systematically denied. The
result is a narcissistic personality that will eventually contribute to a nar-
cissistic culture.
The problem with this explanation is not so much that it is wrong-
Lasch's work contains valuable insights despite its flaws-but that it retains
the centrality of the nuclear family in an orthodox-psychoanalytic interpre-
tation of a culture in which, as Lasch himself documents, the nuclear family
plays a less and less decisive role in the formation of the individual psyche.
Rather than interpret culture in terms of the vicissistudes of family life,
schizoanalysis proposes to understand capitalist culture in terms of capital's
basic social processes-decoding and recoding-yet without denying the fam-
ily unit and the Oedipus complex their particular function within capitalist
society.
Schizoanalysis would thus explain the decline of superego func-
tions, and indeed the increase of ego instability itself, not in terms of the
demise of the family, as Lasch would have it, but in terms of the decoding
of social authority and of experience in general, which takes place (in France,
at any rate) during the latter half of the nineteenth century. Schizoanalysis
is poststructuralist as well as postmodernist, in that it retains the structuralist
axiom that subjectivity is an effect of social codes; hence, when they break
down, so does the "autonomous" bourgeois subject. The transition from
feudal and mercantile despotism to capitalism had already been secured
during the period of bourgeois ascendancy through the replacement of au-
thority figures (God, the Sun King, etc.) by the authority of reason. However
universal a structure the superego may be, its functions are considerably
increased in this first moment of bourgeois cultural revolution, with the
internalized conscience of the Protestant spirit and the internalized ration-
ality of the Enlightenment. But as market relations spread throughout so-
ciety, even this enlightenment reason succumbs to decoding: market society,
Marx says, "strips of its halo every profession hitherto regarded with rev-
erence and awe."I 4
In his Eighteenth Brumaire of Louis-Napoleon, Marx not only
strips bourgeois political philosophy of its halo-by parodying Hegel-but
also ruthlessly deflates the social authority of the Second Empire itself,
showing why, under democratic conditions, the bourgeoisie had to forfeit
its direct political rule and cultural expression in order to maintain its eco-
nomic rule behind the scenes. And with characteristic accuracy, Marx rec-
ognizes that both the humiliated bourgeoisie and the defeated proletariat
would retreat from the pursuit of their "rational interests" in the public
sphere of class struggle into the private sphere of domestic consumption
just coming into its own under the Second Empire and which has expanded
ever since.
Consumerism is, indeed, the principal vehicle for recoding. Our
own experience of the rhythms of fad and fashion in consumer society; the
general effects of advertising, mass marketing, public relations, and political
propaganda analyzed by Jean Baudrillard, Guy Debord, J. P. Faye, and
others; and also accounts of the "successive private religions" of the mod-
411
ernist avant-gardes since the late 1880s offered by Renato Poggioli, Walter
Benjamin, and others-all provide ample evidence of the ways in which
recoding introduces various local and temporary meanings into the other-
wise barren landscape of life under capitalism. 15
Acknowledging the emergence of consumerism in the latter half
of the nineteenth century puts Lasch's decline-of-the-family thesis in a dif-
ferent, somwhat broader perspective: the issue is not just the collapse of
paternal authority or maternal instinct but the function of the family in
society as a whole. The nuclear family of the late nineteenth century is not
some isolated refuge from capitalist competition-indeed, it is no "haven
in a heartless world"-but is, rather, the very locus of consumption. Pho-
tographs from this period present a telling image, for example, of the bour-
geois domestic interior-stuffed full of every last gewgaw and knickknack
imaginable. 16 Indeed, if modernist recoding is private religion, then the
home is its altar; and its idol, as Walter Benjamin put it, 17 is the fetish called
"Commodity." In the garish light of consumerism-which has become blind-
ing and now floods into the public sphere as well (in the form of"recreational
shopping," for example), so that the individual body itself has become a
temple of narcissistic recoding-narcissistic rage cannot be imagined to be
directed against mothers who traumatize frustration by acting inconsis-
tently, but must be understood in relation to an entire society that constantly
offers instant and unlimited gratification yet ultimately refuses to "deliver
the goods." Consumer society promises everyone satisfaction but can allow
no one enough satisfaction ... to stop consuming.
In the same vein, narcissists' inability to synthesize good and bad
is not primarily a result of ambivalent mothering but stems, rather, from
the pervasive disjunction under capitalism between the dreary, exploited
sphere of work and the glittering rewards of administered leisure and con-
spicuous consumption. Narcissists may insist that "living well is the best
revenge," but no amount of cynical hedonism can bridge the gap between
production and consumption-a gap that the expansion of capital steadily
reproduces on a larger and larger scale. Thus, narcissistic personality split-
ting, cynical-defensive disdain for others and for community, and desperate
self-absorption are not just the result of absent fathering and bad mothering
but a product of the libidinal structure of capitalism itself: narcissism man-
ifests what we might call the "capital-logic" of contemporary culture.
Schizoanalysis provides a means not of simply deriving culture
from the logic of capital but of answering Althusser's question regarding
how we explain the historical effectivity of a given semiautonomous de-
velopment.18 The issue is not whether narcissistic parents are likely to raise
narcissistic children (which is all ego psychology by itself can tell us)-of
course they are. Nor is the point to deny the family any role whatsoever in
perpetrating the culture of narcissism, for Althusser's concept of overde-
termination enables us to consider a variety of relations (interdependence
or independence, mutual reinforcement or cancellation, etc.) that may ob-
tain between various instances in society. The point here is that nowadays
the infantile narcissism fostered by the nuclear family is not resolved in
adult life but reinforced and exacerbated by a social formation in which
narcissism resonates wherever the logic of commodities and recoding has
penetrated: in bureaucracy, in the professions, in modernist art and archi-
tecture-indeed, as Lasch suggests, nearly everywhere.
412
Eugene Holland
Now the main thrust ofpostmodemism-in art as well as theory-
and what distinguishes it decisively from modernism, is its refusal of re-
coding. In the history of architecture-where its advent is particularly clear-
cut and well understood 19-postmodemism defines itself against modernism
by ironically playing with existing architectural codes instead of elaborating
new ones of its own, and particularly by playing various codes off against
one another. In a public low-income housing project in New Haven, Con-
necticut, for example, the prominent postmodem architect/urban planner
Charles Moore has designed an apartment tower for the elderly in explicit
relation to a Knights of Columbus office tower located just across the free-
way. The insurance headquarters occupy six or eight glass-walled floors
supported on !-beams suspended between massive cylindrical pillars that
form the four comers of the building. In the old-age apartment tower, by
contrast, the right angles where the four main bare concrete walls would
have met have been neatly shaved away, creating a more or less square
tower that appears to have no comers at all. Rather than existing inde-
pendently as a self-contained monument with its own architectural code,
Moore's building makes ironic reference to local buildings and architectural
codes, thereby highlighting the disparities between the massive stability and
presence of the insurance industry and the meager insufficiency and depen-
dency of public housing.
In addition to embedding itself in its specific context in this way,
postmodem architecture often borrows from the architectural tradition, un-
abashedly mixing styles from widely dispersed historical periods or geo-
graphic regions. As opposed to modem architecture, and by ironically re-
ferring to other buildings and other styles while insisting on relating design
to the particular cultural context and physical location, postmodem archi-
tecture proclaims not an abstract necessity but its own contingency; not self-
contained autonomy but self-confessed relativity; not pure transcendence
but particular, historical contextuality. It thereby refuses recoding. 20
As a postmodem critique and renewal of psychoanalysis, schi-
zoanalysis also refuses recoding, denying privileged status in The Anti-Oed-
ipus, for example, to either the marxian or the freudian interpretive code.
Instead, it plays the one off against the other, so as to avoid erecting its own
master code. Just as the introduction of history into freudian theory rela-
tivized the Oedipus complex and politicized psychological analysis, so too
is the introduction of the unconscious into economics and politics bound
to have far-reaching consequences for marxist political and cultural analysis.
Less important for schizoanalysis than so-called rational interests and im-
puted "class consciousness" are the unconscious dynamics or "forms of
semiosis" underlying all kinds of human activity-from the production of
value in a factory, for example, to the production of consensus and action
in a political group, to the production of meaning in a work of art.
As a form of cultural criticism, schizoanalysis opposes interpre-
tation, for interpretation merely reinforces semiotic despotism by translating
one authorized code-that of the author or "creator"-into another author-
ized code-that of the critic. Rather than reinforce authority by multiplying
equivalent codes in this way, postmodemist schizoanalysis produces inter-
ference between codes and so acts to undermine their authority. Decon-
struction is an important precursor to schizoanalysis, in that Derrida has
rendered most forms of interpretation inoperative by demonstrating the
413
inherent instability of the master codes on which interpretation has been
based. Yet even though he manages to decode logocentrism, Derrida does
so, as he says, strictly from within its own parameters. As a discourse of
philosophy, deconstruction remains, like modernism, a basically self-refer-
ential discourse; so even while heralding the "end of western metaphysics,"
Derrida remains only on the threshold of postmodernism.
Postmodernist criticism is explicity contextual, and by treating
philosophical discourses from Plato to Searle out of context, as so many
versions of the same logocentric master code, Derrida inevitably overlooks
contextual differences. So, at the limit, deconstructive decoding results merely
in dazzling displays oflexical pyrotechnics. Normally, semiotic codes func-
tion through the interplay of paradigmatic and syntagmatic relations; but a
("decoded") unstable code cannot impose the constraints on paradigmatic
substitution necessary to produce determinate meaning. One result is the
so-called textual indeterminacy that has become the trump card of much
neo-derridean criticism in the United States-for example, J. Hillis Miller
discussing his difficulties interpreting Wallace Stevens's poem "The Rock":
"The multiple meanings of the word 'cure,' like the meanings of all key
words in 'The Rock,' are incompatible, irreconcilable. They may not be
followed, etymologically, to a single root which will unifY or explain them,
explicate them in a single source.... However hard [we try] to fix the word
in a single sense it remains indeterminable, uncannily resisting [any] at-
tempts to end its movement." 21 The so-called abyss ofthe paradigmatic axis
of discourse henceforth appears as an unavoidable obstacle to interpretive
procedures that would curtail the free play of semiosis and limit paradig-
matic substitution according to some law of equivalence (such as cigar
"means" penis, money "equals" feces, or whatever).
But discourse always entails syntagmatic relations as well. And
whereas the paradigmatic relations of substitution in discourse are virtual
(hence, "open to interpretation"), the syntagmatic relations of combination
in a given discourse are actual: a discourse consists precisely of a particular
combination of signs that has been realized. The hallmark of Foucault's
discourse analysis is that it eschews interpretation and concentrates instead
on this facticity of actualized discourse. Rather than relate a particular dis-
course to the entirety ofWestern metaphysics, Foucault analyzes the specific
rules of combination it displays and relates it, along with other discourses
displaying these rules, to the specific institutional contexts that form their
conditions of existence. Discourse is thus analyzed in its singularity and
contingency, instead of being recoded in terms of a personal experience it
would express, a period-style it would reflect, or a historical tradition it
would transmit and perpetuate. Foucault's sole points of reference are the
rules by which a discourse is constituted and the contexts within which it
coexists. In refusing the historical master plots of Hegel, Marx, and others,
Foucault emphasizes the unexpected, thereby evoking a history that is, by
its very constitution, subject to change.
If Foucault's discourse analysis examines the codes operative in
specific discursive formations and the effects of power they achieve in par-
ticular historical contexts, Deleuze and Guattari's schizoanalysis examines
the other side of the coin: the forces at work in discourse and society that
challenge the imposed closure of codes and strive to free desire from capture
in codified representation. Assuming the effective integration ofthe classical
414
Eugene Holland
proletariat into capitalist hegemony-and it is important to be clear on the
assumption Deleuze and Guattari are making in a book written in the wake
of May 1968 when even the French Communist party sided with the forces
of order against the general strike: that there is perhaps not total but, prac-
tically speaking, effective integration of the proletariat into the development
plan of late capitalism-Deleuze and Guattari assert that the fundamental
contradiction in the fully developed capitalist mode of production operates
not between discrete social classes but between the socialization of produc-
tion, on the one hand, and the private appropriation of surplus, on the
other. Hence their promotion of schizophrenic decoding as the very move-
ment of permanent revolution, as opposed to the constriction and limitation
of social revolution by capitalist recoding.
As a result, schizoanalytic criticism is primarily a pragmatic anal-
ysis of texts, one that assesses the impact on readers' desire, regardless of
content or meaning. A work of art, just as much as a political formation or
an economic process, has a form of semiosis that tends either to limit desire
to the exigencies of a code or to free desire to pursue its own schizophrenic
trajectories. 22 The aims of schizoanalysis are thus to expose strategies of
recontainment and closure wherever they operate to recode desire; and,
more important, to locate and intensify the "lines of flight" by which, in
art as well as politics, desire may avoid and undermine the pervasive re-
coding of power relations under advanced capitalism.
Notes
1 Jean-Paul Sartre, L'idiot de Ia famil/e (Paris: Gallimard, 1971-72), vol. 3, pp. 40-41; also
cited by Hazel Barnes, Sartre and Flaubert (Chicago: University of Chicago Press. 1981),
who agrees that "Sartre wants to show that Flaubert became the writer he was m response
to two lines of conditioning .... One line represents the Influence of the family, the other
that of society and cultural tradition" (p. 11 ).
2 See, in particular, Christopher Lasch, The Culture of Narcissism: Amencan Life in an Age of
Diminishing Expectations (New York: Norton, 1979); see also his earlier study, Haven in a
Heartless World: The Family Beseiged (New York: Basic Books, 1977).
3 Freud introduces this important concept in "Project for a Scientific Psychology," Standard
Edition, vol. 1, esp. pp. 356-58; it also figures prominently in his discuss1on of the "Wolf
Man" case, in Standard Edition, vol. 17, esp. pp. 37-38.
4 The English version, Anti-Oedipus: Capitalism and Schizophrenia, trans. R. Hurley, M. Seem,
and H. Lane (New York: Viking, 1977), appeared five years after the French, L 'anti-Oedipe:
Capitalisme et schizophreme (Paris: Seuil, 1972).
5 For clarity's sake, I present the three social formatiOns Deleuze and Guattan outline in Chapter
3 of Anti-Oedipus ("Sauvages, barbares, civilises"), along with the fourth, projected stage
(permanent revolution), in a semantic rectangle derived from A. J. Greimas, Du sens (Paris:
Seuil, 1970).
6 It is crucial to understand that Deleuze and Guattari distinguish absolutely between the pro-
cess of schizophrenia and the clinical entity "the schizophrenic." The latter is a product of
psychiatry's forced receding of the free-flowing libidinal energy characteristic of the process
of schizophrenia. Deleuze and Guattari do not condone the institutional production and con-
finement of "schizophrenics," nor do they idealize their condition.
7 Thus, in a project closely aligned with Deleuze and Guattari's perspective (Discipline and
Punish, trans. A. Sheridan [1975; New York: Pantheon, 1977]), Foucault distinguishes the
centralized form of power characteristic of despotism from the dissemmated, quantifying
power appropriate to capitalist decoding. The latter IS a form of power Foucault himself says
is Integral to the development of industnal capitalism (in Power/Knowledge, ed. Col1n Gordon
[New York: Pantheon, 1980]. p. 105 )
8 That is (usmg terms Deleuze and Guattari do not), capitalist soc1ety is constituted by digital
rather than analogous relations: the capitalist "axiomatic" (to revert to their terminology)
415
JOins decoded (digital) flows-of wealth, labor power, knowledge, consumer tastes, and so
on-for the sake of extracting a differential surplus from them; whatever local (analogue)
codes may temporarily spring up in the process are strictly incidental to capital's basic "ax-
iomatic" process of self-expansion.
9 Some sense of the content of "decoding" may be suggested by recalling how science
replaces sense experience with a mathematical calculus, as in lockean psychology where
color (henceforth a mere "secondary" quality) is decoded by the calculus of wavelengths
("primary" quality).
10 See Karl Marx, Capital, trans. Ernest Untermann, (New York: International Publishers, 1967).
vol. 3, pp. 249-50.
11 See Georg Lukacs, "Reification and the Consciousness of the Proletariat," History and Class
Consciousness, trans. Rodney Livingstone, (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1B71 ), especially sec.
1, "The Phenomenon of Reification." I quote from pp. 103, 99.
12 The postmodern critique of modern1st city planning and urban "renewal" was initiated in
1961 by Jane Jacob's important book, The Death and Life of Great American Cities (New
York: Random HouseNintage Press).
13 More properly speaking, the nuclear family for schizoanalysis is the prime locus of "reterri-
torializatJon" rather than recoding. Terntorialization is the process of fixing desire on an object
whereas coding (and overcoding and recoding) fix desire to representation. Thus, the nuclear
family reterritorializes schizophrenic desire by restricting it to certain objects (Mommy and
Daddy). while it is actually psychoanalysis that recodes-by providing desire with the socially
sanct1oned representation of the "Oedipus complex."
14 See Karl Marx, The Communist Manifesto, 1n Marx and Engels: Basic Writings on Politics
and Philosophy, ed. Lewis Feuer (Garden City: Doubleday, 1959). pp. 6-41, where Marx
descnbes the basis of decoding in this way: "The bourgeoisie has stripped of its halo every
occupation hitherto honored and looked up to with reverent awe. It has converted the phy-
sician, the lawyer, the priest the man of science into its paid wage laborers. . The bourgeoi-
Sie cannot live without constantly revolutionizing the instruments of production, and thereby
the relations of product1on, and with them the whole relations of society. Constant
revolution1z1ng of production, uninterrupted disturbance of all social conditions, everlasting
uncertainty and agitat1on distinguish the bourgeois epoch from all earlier ones. All fixed, fast-
frozen relations, with their train of ancient and venerable prejudices and opinions, are swept
away, all new-formed ones become antiquated before they can ossify. All that is solid melts
into air . " (p 10)
15 See Jean Baudnllard, Pour une critique de l'econom1e politlque du signe (Paris: Gallimard,
1972). and Simulacres et simulation (Paris: Galilee, 1981 ); Guy Debord, La societe du
spectacle (Paris: Buchet-Chastel, 1967); J. P. Faye, Langages totalitaires (Paris: Hermann,
1972); Renata Poggioli, The Theory of the Avant-Garde, trans. Gerald Fitzgerald, (New York:
Harper and Row, 1968); Walter Benjamin, Charles Baudelaire: Epic Poet in the Era of High
Cap1talism, trans. Harry Zohn, (London: NLB, 1973). The term "private religion" has been
used by Fredric Jameson to refer to the modernist aesthetic in literature.
16 See, for example, chapter 13 of E. J. Hobsbawn, The Age of Capital, 1848-1870 (New
York: Scribner's Sons, 1975). and the discussion in Rosalyn Williams, Dream Worlds: Mass
Consumption in Late-19th-Century France (Berkeley: University of California Press, 1982).
17 See Benjamin, Charles Baudelaire, especially "Paris, Capital of the 19th Century," sec. 1,
3,4.
18 This IS a question posed by Althusser' s rewriting the historical problematic in terms of "struc-
tural causality" and "overdeterminatJon." See For Marx, trans. Ben Brewster (1965; New
York: Random House, 1969). specifically: "Contradiction and Overdetermination," pp. 87-
128, esp. pp. 119-26; and "On the Materialist Dialectic," pp. 161-218, esp. pp. 200-10.
19 Thanks in large part to the works of Charles Jencks: The Language of Postmodem Architecture
(New York: Rizzoli, 1977) and Late-Modem Architecture and Other Essays (New York: Rizzoli,
1980)
20 For an insightful analysis of postmodern art, see Craig Owens, "The Allegorical Impulse:
Toward a Theory of Postmodernism," October 12 ( 1980). pp. 67-86, and 13 ( 1980). pp.
59-80, esp. pp. 79-80.
21 See J. Hillis Miller in Georgia Review (Spring 1976). p. 10.
22 In the Anti-Oedipus, the schizoanalysts denied having any political program; but Deleuze and
Guattanlater actively supported Italian Marxist Toni Negri, to date the most important theo-
ritJcian of m1cropolitics. As Michael Ryan puts it in his very suggestive book Marxism and
Deconstruction: A Critical Articulation (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1982).
"we have reached a point in history where the wealth of struggles has outrun the abstractly
mediating ["recoding"] form of authority" (p. 217).
416
IV Culture, Domination, and Resistance
Julia Lesage
Women's Rage
428
Michele Mattelart
Notes
9 Boris Vian, Autres ecrits sur le Jazz, 1 ("Jazz-Hot/Combat"). texts collected, prefaced, and
annotated by Claude Remeil (Paris Christian Bourgeo1s, 1981)
10 "lncroyable Mais Vra1" is, furthermore, based on paired sequences that show the inven-
tiveness, extraordmary performance, or explo1ts of all kmds of ord1nary people from places
like Arizona or the Auvergne. The "local" is transcended through the spectacular The French
host. incidentally, works in collaboration with an Amencan hostess.
11 Alexandr Petrovich Dovjenko, La palabra y el escntor en el cme (Montevideo: Ed1ciones
Pueblos Unidos, 1957).
443
12 Tomas Gutierrez Alea. "Dramaturgie (cinematografica) y realidad," document presented to
the Semmaire de Dramaturgie Cinematographique held on the occasion of the Fourth Festival
of New Latin-American Cinema, Havana, Dec. 2-12, 1982.
13 "Non a l'austerite, le spectacle doit continuer," Tambour, Tete 7 rouge (Paris, Winter 1982-
83)
14 Document from the Agence de Cooperation Culturelle et Technique (Paris, Sept. 1982).
15 A brief comparison will illustrate the risk these industries face. At about the time when the
Cuban film 1ndustry had its "commercial" failure because it had concentrated all its resources
on a single production, United Artists went into bankruptcy because of the failure of an
enormously expensive superproduction. It was bought up by MGM.
16 "TV's Drive on Spiralling Costs," Business Week, Oct. 26, 1981.
17 Figures given in the Japanese review Movie/TV Marketing, 4 (Tokyo, 1983).
18 Claude Degand, "La situation economique du cinema en Europe," Le Cinema et I'Etat.
Colloque (Lisbon, June 1978). Quoted 1n Filmaction, special issue on "Les ecrans colonises"
(Feb.-Mar, 1982).
19 This matter is explored at length in "Education, television et culture de masse. Reflexion sur
une industrie des contenus," in A. Mattelart andY. Stourdze, Rapport de Ia Mission. Vol.
2: "Technologie, culture et communication" (Paris: La Documentation Franc;aise, 1983),
pp. 150-78.
20 The cartoon seems to be the TV form most likely to generate by-products. The Japanese
cartoon industry (which has taken over dominance in this market, formerly held by North
America) IS a good example. The cartoon "Dr. Slump," which appeared on Japanese TV
screens in May 1981, gave rise, by the end of the same year, to 8,000 different derivative
products. Certain Japanese senes programmed in France were responsible for 200 such
products. See Jacques Mousseau, "Piaidoyer pour une industrie franc;aise du dessin ani me,"
Communication et langage, 2• trimestre ( 1982).
21 Le Monde. May 3. 1983.
22 Cahiers du Cinema, Jan. 1982.
23 Michele Mattelart, "Education, television et culture de masse."
24 The incredibly large number of episodes in telenovelas is significant. Armand Mattelart and
I have published some hypotheses on this subject in Femmes et industries culturefles (UNESCO,
Document file no. 23, Division of Cultural Development, 1981-82).
25 It has been noticed that the characters of Kojak and Columbo (in the series so named) referred
respectively to Eastern Europe and to "ltalianness." Thus, these guardians of law and order
served admirably as signs of the Integration of ethnic minorities into the American nation.
The name "Kojak" also seems to answer to the demand for universal appeal by its similarity
to one of the most universally known brand names: Kodak. George Eastman, the inventor of
celluloid film. decided to name h1s products "Kodak" because he wanted a worldwide market
and the phonemes in this word are pronounced the same in most known languages.
The move toward the "global film," with as little dialogue as possible, is
another symptom. It implies the use of big stars, strong images, and violent action, which
do not require subtitles. The French firm Gaumont has moved toward this formula, though
rather tamely, in its plans for La petite bande, "a charming story without dialogue which will
be marketed as a film for children of all languages." Le Film Franc;ais, May 11, 1983.
26 In "Materiali sui telefilm," 4, Teleconfronto (Mostra lnternaziale del Telefilm). May 29-June
5, 1983. In Femmes et industries culturefle. Armand Mattelart and I examine this question
of hab1t and ntual t1me in order to correlate the use of daily episodes over a long period of
t1me by telefilms and particularly by telenovelas with what we call "feminine temporality,"
the spec1fic temporal rhythm of feminine subjectivity, which may be found in the lived ex-
penence of other oppressed groups.
27 Brazilian Television in Context (London: British Film Institute, 1982).
28 Cf. A. and M. Mattelart, De /'usage des medias en temps de crise (Paris: Editions Alain
Moreau, 1979); in Italian, I mas media nella crisi (Editiori Riuniti, 1981 ), in which this idea
1s developed at length.
29 Here is how the magazine VSD presented Stephen Spielberg's E. T. on its front page, when
it opened in Paris theaters in December 1982: "E. T., the extra-terrestrial/ He makes you
laugh, cry, and he earns /750 million centimes every day I for his producer Stephen Spielberg."
30 A. Mattelart, Transnat1onals and the Third World: Struggle for Culture (South Hadley, Mass.:
J. F. Bergin, 1983).
444
Michele Mattelart
31 Press conference by Didier Motchane, national secretary for cultural action of the Socialist
party, Cannes, May 9, 1983.
32 In Le Film Fram;ais, Feb. 18, 1983. The ad continues: "Antenne 2 is co-produc1ng this
series with a consortium of private companies which, for the occasion, have allied under the
name 'Groupment d'lnteret Economique. · Shooting will begin at the end of 1983 and, if the
series is successful, another 26 episodes will be prepared. It will be programmed in groups
of 13 episodes, shown weekly starting in September, 1983."
445
Fernando Reyes Matta
Notes
Nueva Canci6n, Canto Nuevo, Nuevo Cancionero, and so on. are among the different names
assumed by a similar process of artistic search and expression within the Latin American
459
struggle for liberation. Consequently, I use these terms (especially the first two) synonymously.
Since Nueva Trova, Nueva Canci6n, and Canto Nuevo refer to specific national movements,
they are left in the original Spanish. In any case, all the terms mentioned denote a new
popular musical creation, linked to mass organizations and other grass-roots groups and with
a problematic relation to the existing economic base. I have defined them collectively as the
"new popular song movement."
2 In the context of the "New Song," the term "American" is understood as "Latin American,"
a projection of Bolivar's conception. It therefore opposes the term "North American," or the
more colloquial or pejorative "gringo," commonly used to refer to U.S. citizens.
3 La Bicic/eta (Santiago de Chile), Apr. 11, 1981.
4 Cees Hamelink, "The Cultural Synchronisation of the World," WACC Journal, 11 (1978).
5 La Bicicleta.
6 El Dia (Mexico). Dec. 21, 1980.
7 Cadernos do Terceiro Mundo (Rio de Janeiro), June 24, 1980.
8 Uno mas Uno (Mexico). June 29, 1980.
9 Uno mas Uno.
10 M. Moskowitz et al., Everybody's Business (New York: Harper and Row, 1980).
11 Excelsior (Mexico). Nov. 9, 1980.
12 Excelsior (Mexico). Sept. 26, 1980.
13 Poder econ6mico y libertad de expresi6n, Diego Portales C., Editorial Nueva lmagen/ILET,
1981 , Mexico.
14 La Bicicleta.
15 Cadernos do Terceiro Mundo.
16 El Hera/do (Mexico), Jan. 4, 1980.
17 Humor (Buenos Aires). Nov. 1983.
18 El Dia (Mexico). July 19, 1983.
460
Simon Frith
475
Michael Ryan
Notes
485
2 See Michael Ryan, "Militant Documentary: Mai 68 par lui-meme," Cinetracts, 24:3-4 (Fall
1979L pp. 1-21.
3 See Richard Johnson, "What Is Cultural Studies Anyway?" (Mimeograph, Occasional Paper
#74, Centre for Contemporary Cultural Studies, Birmingham); and Lisa Gornick, "Turning
the Tables: Women Analysts with Men Patients," Ph.D. dissertation, Department of Psy-
chology, Yale University.
4 For a general overview of the theory, see H. Guntrip, Psychoanalytic Theory, Therapy, and
the Self (New York: Basic Books, 1971 ).
5 The critique of realism is, of course, carried out in the name of a higher realism or truth-
revealing the workings of the cinematic apparatus, destroying the illusion. Like socialist re-
alism. which also criticized fantasy and debunked the personal realm in favor of public duty,
the new antisocial realism is critical of the imaginary or self-oriented domain of social life.
The problem with raising a formal tactic (displaying the apparatus) to a political principle is
that it neutralizes substance or content as a criterion of politics (since content depends on
the acceptance of the realist illusion). Some conservative or liberal films- The Asphalt Jungle
or Knock On Any Door, for example-could thus be termed radical because they conclude
with a figure of authority addressing the camera and breaking the narrative illusion. Ultimately,
of course, content resolves into form, and vice versa. The critique of realism is not that it is
bad form but that is has bad political content (ideology). And social content also collapses
into a matter of form. for the struggle for social power ultimately comes down to a struggle
over the way society will be organized, the form it will take.
6 G. Platte and F. Weinstein, Psychoanalytic Sociology (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University
Press. 1973). p. 23.
7 For a further elaboration of these ideas, see the conclusion to Douglas Kellner and Michael
Ryan, Camera Politica: The Politics and Ideology of Contemporary Hollywood Film (forthcom-
ing).
486
Jack L. Amariglio, Stephen A. Resnick, and
Richard D. Wolff
Notes
1 We are most interested 1n the recent attempts to establish antiteleological and antiessentialist
Marxist notions. See L. Althusser and E. Balibar, Readmg Capital, trans. Ben Brewster (Lon-
don: New Left Books, 1975); L. Althusser, For Marx, trans. Ben Brewster (New York: Vintage,
1970); L. Althusser, Essays m Self-Criticism, trans. Grahame Lock (London: New Left Books,
1976); B. Hindess and P. Hirst. Pre-Capitalist Modes of Production (London: Routledge and
Kegan Paul, 1975); B. Hindess and P. Hirst, Mode of Production and Social Formation
(London: Macmillan, 1977); S. Resnick and R. Wolff, "The Theory of Transitional Conjunc-
tures," Review of Radical Political Economics 11 :3 (1979); S. Resnick and R. Wolff, "Classes
in Marxian Theory," Review of Rad1cal Political Econom1cs 13:4 ( 1982); S. Resnick and R.
Wolff, "Marx1st Epistemology The Critique of Economic Determinism," Social Text 6:2/3
(Fall 1982); S. Resnick and R. Wolff, Marxist Theory, forthcoming.
2 The essentialism we discuss here is what we call essentialism in discourse or theory, which
we distinguish from epistemological essentialism or essentialism of discourse or theory. We
rejeCt the epistemological notion that objects of knowledge exist independently of thought
and thus can be appropriated in thought. This notion is an essentialism ot theory. Our an-
tiessentialist position IS also incompatible with essentialism in theory, which discursively pnv-
ileges a subset of conceptual statements within theory from wh1ch others are log1cally derived.
For further discuss1on, see Resn1ck and Wolff, "Marx1st Epistemology" and Marxist Theory.
3 The concept of overdetermination initially emerged as a concept in the Freud1an theory of
dream interpretation. To our knowledge, Lukacs was the first Marxist to try to appropriate
and reformulate this concept for Marxist theory. However, Althusser was the first Marxist
both to claim that Marx's own concept of historical causality and epistemology was one of
overdeterminatiOn. See G. Lukacs, "The Tasks of Marxist Philosophy 1n the New Democracy,"
quoted in Resnick and Wolff, "Marxist Epistemology"; L. Althusser, "Contradiction and Ov-
erdetermination," 1n For Marx, pp. 89-128; Resn1ck and Wolff, "Marxist Epistemology."
4 Certainly, many noneconomists have rejected the essentialist thought built upon the epis-
temological positions of empincism and rationalism. It seems to us they approach but never
quite reach the Marx1st pos1tion of overdeterm1nation. The structural linguistics imtlated by
Ferdinand de Saussure was an attempt to show the arbitrariness of meaning, decentering
the signification of a word into the arb1trary relation of Signifier to signified. Similarly, Jacques
Derrida's deconstructionist interventions suggest the futility of trying to center a text and find
its "given" meaning (1ts ventnloquist "logos") through a process of interpretation. In place
of this logocentrism, Derrida suggests the play and dispersion of textual meamngs that are
liberated through a process of deconstruction. R1chard Rorty's discuss1on of philosophy as
"a m1rror of nature" presents a somewhat similar attack on logocentrism, but one restricted
to the philosophical dichotomy of th1nking/be1ng. F1nally, the noted critic of sociobiology,
Richard C. Lewont1n, has argued that we need to replace mechanistiC and reductionist notions
of the human organism with a new conception of the orgamsm as an intereffective totality
of determinations. For Saussure, see Course in General Linguistics (New York: McGraw-H1II,
1966). Our understandmg of Derrida is taken from Writing and Difference, trans. Alan Bass
(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1981 ); and see especially the interview in Positions
entitled "Positions," 1n which Derrida discusses h1s problematiC relation to Marxism. For
Rorty, see Philosophy and the Mirror of Nature (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1980)
and "Philosophy As a Kind of Writing," New Literary History, 1978. We are particularly taken
with R. C. Lewontin's review of two texts written by the Dialectics of Biology Group. His
review, "The Corpse in the Elevator," appears in The New York Review of Books, Jan. 20,
1983.
5 In this context, it is interesting to note that Gramsci's well-known opposition to economic
determinism does not lead him to accept any form of noneconomic determinism. Instead,
he argues that the search for last instance determinisms amounts to the "search for God."
See A. Gramsci, Selections from the Prison Notebooks, trans. and ed. 0. Hoare and G. N.
Smith (New York International Publishers, 1971). p. 437.
499
6 Our wording here deliberately echoes that of the Marxist anthropologist Marc Auge. Auge
claims that after the in1t1al interest in but consequent rejection of "Aithusserianism," Marxism
in France was discredited. In its stead, "with the help of history and fashion ... waves of
'desire· flooded the sociological banks, and a new disembarkation threatened. This was
actually a new Holy Alliance (Nietzche, Reich, Bataille, Deleuze) and one for which the Marxists
were quite unprepared ... Auge clearly recogmzes that these newly arisen protagonists wish
to reject a "formalist" Marxism only to replace it with a social theory centered once again
on the concept of desire. See Marx Auge, The Anthropological Circle, trans. Martin Thom
(Cambridge: Cambridge University, 19B2). p. 66.
7 M. Sahlins, Culture and Practical Reason (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1976). p.
viii; see also pp. 205-21.
8 Th1s tendency shows up quite clearly in contemporary discussions of "sexual politics" and
focuses on social "relations" rather than processes that we regard as the operation of a
theoretical humanism (an essentialism of the subject).
9 This notion of exploitation should not be confused with Marx's enunciation of the concept
of exploitation in Capital (New York: International Publishers. 1977). Marx's conception spec-
ifies the particular economic process of extracting surplus labor or "unpaid labor" and must
be differentiated from the more conventional use of the term to express a general relationship
between social agents.
10 We restrict our criticisms here to Hindess and Hirst's earlier books, Pre-Capitalist Modes of
Production and Mode of Production and Social Formation.
11 See P.-P. Rey, "The Lineage Mode of Production," Critique of Anthropology no. 3 ( 1975).
pp. 27-29.
12 See especially N. Poulantzas, Classes in Contemporary Capitalism, trans. David Fernbach
(London: Verso, 1978). pp. 13-36.
13 For a detailed discussion of the concept of class process and its use in Marxist theory, see
Resnick and Wolff, "Classes in Marxian Theory" and Marxist Theory.
14 Marx begins to elaborate his notions of fundamental and subsumed class processes in the
three volumes of Capital. See Resnick and Wolff, "Classes in Marxian Theory."
15 See Marx's brief discussion of these fundamental class processes in Grundrisse, trans. Martin
Nicolaus (New York: Vintage, 1973). pp. 471-514.
16 See Resnick and Wolff. Marxist Theory, for an elaboration of the notion of the "social prev-
alence" of a fundamental class process.
17 Marx, in val. 3 of Capital, focuses on this particular development in the example of advanced
capitalism. As Marx sees 1t, in advanced capitalism managers, owners. financiers of capital
often ex1st separate from industrial capitalists. The direction and control of the capitalist
fundamental class process are in the hands of these social groups, but they do not extract
(exploit) surplus labor. See in particular chap. 23, pp. 370-90, of Capital.
18 For a detailed discussion of the concepts of class position and class struggle, see Resnick
and Wolff, Marxist Theory.
19 One of Marx's most developed discussions of such "class alliances" can be found in The
18th Brumaire of Louis Bonaparte (New York: International Publishers, 1968).
20 Our notion of subjectification is clearly related to Foucault's "two meanings of the word
subject: subject to someone else by control and dependence, and tied to his own identity
by a conscience or self-knowledge"; and also to Althusser's discussion of the "mirror-struc-
ture" of the process of subjectification. as agents are "interpellated" simultaneously as
subjects and as subjected to a Subject (such as God or the state) See Foucault, "The
Subject and Power," which is the afterword to H. Dreyfus and P. Rabinow, Michel Foucault:
Beyond Structuralism and Hermeneutics (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1982). p.
212; and Althusser, "Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses, .. Lenin and Philosophy,
trans. Ben Brewster (New York: Monthly Review, 1971). pp. 170-83.
21 Three books in which these problems are taken up are R. Williams. Marxism and Literature
(Oxford: Oxford University Press. 1977); R. Coward and J. Ellis, Language and Materialism
(London: Routledge and Keg an Paul, 19 77); J. McCarney. The Real World of Ideology (Atlantic
Highlands: Humanities Press, 1980).
22 See also the sections of Gramsci's prison notebooks entitled "The Study of Philosophy" and
"Problems of Marxism," pp. 321-472, in Selections from the Prison Notebooks. A recent
study of Gramsci that places him within the context of an "overdeterminist" conception of
culture and ideology is Chantal Mouffe's "Hegemony and Ideology in Gramsci," in C. Mouffe.
ed., Gramsc1 and Marxist Theory (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1979), pp. 16B-204.
500
Amariglio, Resnick, and Wolff
23 See M. Foucault, The Archaeology of Knowledge, trans. A. M. Shendan Smith (New York:
Harper and Row, 1976), pp. 184-86.
24 See Foucault, The Archaeology of Knowledge, pp. 178-95.
25 See Foucault, The Archaeology of Knowledge, pp. 178-95. See also Lecourt, Marxism and
Epistemology, trans. Ben Brewster (London: New Left Books, 1975), pp. 199-201.
26 See especially M. Foucault, "Truth and Power," 1n Power/Knowledge, ed. C. Gordon (New
York: Pantheon, 1980).
27 See Foucault, "The Subject and Power," p. 208, where he d1scusses "three modes of
object1f1cat1on which transform human beings into subjects."
28 See Foucault, "Body/Power" and "Truth and Power," in Power/Knowledge.
29 See Foucault, "The Subject and Power," p. 213.
30 Foucault, "The Subject and Power," pp. 217-18.
31 Foucault, "The Subject and Power," p. 218.
32 See Althusser, "Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses," in Lenin and Philosophy.
33 "Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses," pp. 170-77.
34 "Ideology and Ideological State Apparatuses." pp. 162-65.
35 D. Lecourt, Marx1sm and Eptstemology, p. 210.
36 D. Lecourt, Marxism and Epistemology, p. 204.
37 See J. Amariglio, '"Primitive Communism' and the Economic Development of lroquios So-
ciety," Department of Economics, University of Massachusetts, Amherst, 1983, chap. 3;
and Rolf Jensen, "The Transition from Primitive Communism: The Wolof Social Formation
of West Africa," Journal of Economic History 42: 1 ( 1982), pp. 69-76.
38 See Grundrisse, pp. 471-79.
501
Jean Franco
mother virgin
phallus
not virgin mother
not mother virgin
(whore) (Mary)
Figure 1.
507
Yet the compound is also prisonlike; the "public" women are immobile
and privatized just as much as the mother or the nun. 13 Finally, there is the
impossible other, the mother who is a virgin, the mother of God who is
not only the unattainable ideal term but the woman who has given birth
to the Creator. (Consider this ironic parallel: Fidel Castro visits Chile, and
Mrs. Allende states that the highest task of Chilean women is to give birth
to sons who would be like Che Guevara.)
Certainly, what strikes us about this diagram of feminine mean-
ings is the immobility and privacy that it implies. To understand how nat-
ural this disposition appears, even to the most sophisticated of the intelli-
gentsia, we have only to read Garcia Marquez's interview in Playboy, in
which he declares that women "stay at home, run the house, bake animal
candies so that men can go off and make wars." 14 Whether this was said in
earnest or in jest is beside the point. It is along this axis that social meanings
accrue so that the madre patria in nationalist discourse is productive or
sterile, prostituted or sacred.
Yet in a society scarred by the violence and death that inevitably
accompanied capitalist penetration of Latin America, it is not surprising to
observe a certain "femininization of values" (to use Terry Eagleton's phrase).
Thus, in a poem by Vallejo, the mother's body is depicted as a house, and
the womb acquires the configuration of rooms and corridors: "Your archway
of astonishment expects me I The tonsured volume of your cares I That
have eroded life. The patio expects me 1 The hallway down below with its
indentures and its I feast-day decorations." When the father enters this
temple/house, it is on his knees. He has become the subordinate partner in
the act of creation. The mother's body, on the other hand, offers the only
unchanging territory in an uncertain world: "Between the colonnade of your
bones 1 That cannot be brought down even with lamentations I And into
whose side not even Destiny 1 can place a single finger."
This poem, written before Vallejo joined the Communist party,
is in sharp contrast to his Soviet-inspired poems, in which the miners make
history through work, or his poems of the Spanish Civil War, where the
forging of history is in the hands of the male militia. 15 We also note that
the mother can only (literally) embody certainty because of her immobility,
because she is related to physical territory. Indeed, it was the female territory
of the house that allowed private and family memory to be stored; there,
archaic values, quite alien to the modem world, continued to flourish.
In the fifties and sixties, for reasons that are too complex to
examine here, there was a radical shift in the meanings attached to the
feminine. This period was marked by two quite contrary trends. On the one
hand, the Cuban revolution aroused hopes that other countries could adopt
original versions of socialism. Marxist theory could be Latin Americanized.
Yet, during this same period, the struggle for national liberation was count-
ered by a massive onslaught of advanced capitalism. At the very moment
Latin America was asserting its difference, the armies of metropolitan cor-
porations-in the form of mass media advertising and consumer goods-
were poised, ready to destroy those very structures (urban/rural, commune,
plantation) that had for so long been an embarrassment and yet had become
the very source of Latin American originality.
The rich heterogeneity that formerly had to be subordinated as
irrational began to be proudly displayed by Latin American writers as proof
508
Jean Franco
of cultural vitality. Writers like Asturias, Arquedas, Carpentier, Roa Bastos,
and Rulfo undertook the recycling of ancient legends, traditional cultures,
and archaic ways of life, not as folklore but as literary models of autarkic
societies. As the literary intelligentsia discovered the utopian elements in
popular culture, it also discovered in that very camivalesque pluralism the
claim on metropolitan attention that had so long eluded it. Thus, when
Mario Vargas Llosa, at the outset of his career, declared that the Latin
American novel "ceased to be Latin American," he meant that it had finally
broken out of the backwater of provincialism and regionalism and had,
indeed, become "recognizable." 16 Like Evita Peron, the literary intelligentsia
had finally entered into immortality. 17 It was not even necessary for it to
follow in Borges's footsteps and abstract plot from all regional and local
references so that it could circulate as the agonic confrontation of pursuer
and pursued, unencumbered by referentiality. The "new novelists" of the
early sixties discovered the shock value of catachresis and juxtaposition in
which those once embarrassing heterogenous elements became positive de-
vices for defamiliarization.
This valorization of heterogeneity was accompanied by the rein-
vention of a myth of authorship, which once again affirmed the difference
between natural reproduction and the masculine province of creativity. The
slogan of the sixties-liberation through the imagination, immortality through
the invention of imaginary worlds or the real autonomous societies like
Cuba-was underpinned by the resemanticization of the sexual division of
labor:
mother author
child creation
In a masculine world dominated by death and violence, the space of the
mother had come to seem utopian, the space of a community that does not
reproduce agonal relationships. Yet instead of trying to understand what
this might mean for the construction of a more humane society and for
revolutionary politics, both political leaders and writers during this period
felt compelled to reaffirm political and artistic creativity as an exclusively
male activity.
Let us take a recent transparent example. In Mario Vargas Llosa's
play La Senorita de Tacna (1981), the central character is, unusually, a
woman. Once the daughter of a prosperous family from Tacna, Mamae is
now senile, poor, and incontinent, kept alive only by her memories of the
past. In her youth, during the Peruvian/Chilean war of the 1880s, she had
been engaged to a Chilean officer. Learning of his infidelity with a married
woman, she decided not to marry him but to become the surrogate mother
of her sister's children and the weaver of romantic memories. In a traditional
semiotic arrangement, Mamae might have occupied the position of the nun.
In Vargas Llosa's play, however, she is both virgin (that is, she is not caught
in the lowly cycle of reproduction) and mother. She thus occupies the po-
sition of the Virgin Mary, the one woman who escapes mortality. Mamae
is the source of legend and fantasies that are woven out of her self-denial;
nevertheless, she cannot be an author in the true sense. That is why the
true protagonist lurks in the wings: Mamae's grandnephew, Belisario, an
apprentice writer who acts as spokesman for this figment of his past and
509
who presents Mamae to the public. Seated at his desk at the side of the
stage, he agonizes over writing, describing himself as "impotent." His im-
potence is only cured when he allows himself to be seduced by the romantic
memories of Mamae. He watches her, interrogates her on her past, and fills
the gaps in her memory with his own inventions. In the final moments of
the play, he recognizes that his material comes from Mamae, that it has
been her romantic stories that have turned into the "demons" that haunt
him as a writer and provide him with energeia. The play clearly allegorizes
a debate within Vargas Llosa himself, who is drawn to "feminine" material
(romance) and needs a surrogate masculine character to launder this ma-
terial and put it into literary circulation.
Not surprisingly, Mamae bears a family resemblance to some of
the women characters in Garcia Marquez's One Hundred Years of Solitude
(1967). Here, too, it is a woman, Ursula, who serves as the memory of the
Buendia family by weaving lives together in the chain of domesticity. But
it is a male, the gypsy Melquiades, who writes down the epic of the Buendia
family in Sanskrit (i.e., a literary language that needs competent decipher-
ing), and it is a male, Aurelino, who discovers how to interpret Melquiades's
manuscript and thus affirms literature as an act of communion between
male readers.
What most clearly demonstrates that the old statutes of author-
ship were problematic, however, was the recurrence in the novels of the
sixties and seventies of a topos of monstrous birth and births of monstros-
ities. Perhaps rather than a topos (i.e., a mere literary commonplace), it
would be more appropriate to call the monstrous birth an ideologeme or a
collective fantasy. As such, it was intended to resolve the problem of"fem-
inizing values" and criticizing machismo, while at the same time reserving
true creativity for the male author. Childbirth was thus depicted as horren-
dous, more akin to death than life. In Onetti's novel The Shipyard (1961),
the protagonist, Larsen, is on his way to his death and passes a cabin in
which a women he had loved is giving birth: "He saw the semi-naked woman
on the bed, bleeding, struggling, her hands clutching her head that was
shaking furiously and rhythmically. He saw the astonishing round belly,
distinguished the rapid flash of her glazed eyes and her clenched teeth.
Finally he understood and could imagine the trap he had just avoided.
Trembling with fear and disgust he left the window and began to walk
towards the shore." At the end of One Hundred Years ofSolitude, Amaranta
Ursula dies in a massive outpouring of blood, leaving the child of her
incestuous love affair "a dry and bloated bag of skin that all the ants in the
world were dragging towards their holes along the stone paths in the garden."
In the eyes of these novelists, women can never separate them-
selves from nature. Fuentes's Terra Nostra (1975) opens with a vision of
the year 2000 and a collective miracle: "women of all ages, forms, and
conditions giving birth" by the banks of the Seine. Among them walks the
one-armed writer-hero (one-armed like Cervantes), who imagines them
pleading with him to accept the paternity of their children. In Jose Donoso's
The Obscure Bird of Night (1979), the entire novel is constructed around
the writer's futile attempt to take hold of this archaic power that comes
from the creation of life, to steal it from the witches who preside over its
secrets and assert their power over it. The recurrence of this ideologeme
suggests, therefore, both the writer's ambiguous relation to an unconscious
510
Jean Franco
that is defined as feminine and, at the same time, a reaffirmation of women's
imprisonment in nature, as if this were the only way that the preservation
of authorship as a male activity could be justified.
Yet this was not incompatible with the attribution of new and
more positive connotations of the feminine. The very immobility of women,
their "territoriality," made them the repository of an underground power
that seemed to come from the land itself. In Garcia Marquez's mythic uni-
verse, a whole prehistory of Latin America centers on the depiction of
primitive matriarchy. We know that this matriarchy already obsessed him
even before he became a novelist, for one of his early journalistic pieces is
a description of a remote area (rather like Macondo) called La Sierpe. 18 He
first heard of La Sierpe when a man from that region of Colombia arrived
at a Barranquilla hospital claiming that he was pregnant and about to give
birth to a monkey. Thus Garcia Marquez was, even at this early stage, lured
by the fantasy of male pregnancy. It led him to a veritable voyage of dis-
covery of La Sierpe, a region whose malaria-ridden inhabitants stubbornly
live out their lives in the midst of an impenetrable swamp, connected to
the outside world only by trade. What consolidates their proud refusal to
be integrated into Colombian society is the myth of the Marquesita, a myth
that accounts for their difference, their originality. La Marquesita was a
Spanish woman, a virgin who had the power to live as long as she liked
but chose to live for 200 years. She accumulated vast wealth in cattle, but
before her death she had the cattle trample the land until it became an
impenetrable morass. Her treasure was then buried under a tree, access to
which was barred by the miraculous swamp.
Garcia Marquez heard this legend from the only person ever to
approach the tree under which the Marquesita's treasure was buried; but
rather than pursue his journey to the end, this adventurer preferred to return
home and tell the story to the world, thus keeping both the legend and the
treasure intact. The story can be interpreted as the fantasy of a society of
scarcity in a region in which the once bounteous earth had mysteriously
become unproductive. By introducing the storyteller and adventurer, how-
ever, Garcia Marquez adds another element, for the treasure is associated
not only with material wealth but also with the legend itself, indeed with
the whole domain of the legendary that both consoles and consolidates the
community.
Women could not be storytellers in the age of reason except as
witches; as such, they were made into scapegoats. Witches were bearers of
the irrational and the archaic, hated and feared since they worshiped a power
that was outside the realm of official religion and culture. In contemporary
novels such as those of Donoso and Fuentes, witches are the focus of a
deep-rooted fear of all that lies outside the male-controlled spectrum of
meaning. In Garcia Marquez's legend of La Sierpe, on the other hand,
women acquire a different social significance. They are equated with territory
and code social meaning as a relationship to the land. These meanings persist
long after the material wealth of the land has been exhausted, but they can
only be recodified in this new historical stage by male storytellers.
Garcia Marquez elaborates on this myth in interesting ways. In
"Mama Grande's Funeral," he describes a territory ruled by a sterile, bloated
matriarch who has accumulated vast capital but leaves it in her will to a
nun (that is, like the Marquesita, her wealth ceases to circulate after her
511
death). Mama Grande's funeral, which marks the end of the ..colonial"
epoch, is attended by a spectacular array of dignitaries, circus performers,
beauty queens, and relatives and is celebrated by gargantuan feasts. A car-
nivalesque society whose meanings derive from the body-territory of the
matriarch is about to wither away and be replaced by an abstract national
state. The story tries to reconstitute a society in which economy, culture,
and symbolic production are codified through the matriarchy.
In another version of the matriarchy myth, however, .. The In-
credible and Sad Story ofErendira and Her Wicked Grandmother," the two
women of the title inhabit a desert region between the frontier and the sea
(the land is thus no longer a source of wealth). The grandmother accumulates
gold ingots by prostituting Erendira because the latter has burned down her
house, in other words, has destroyed her territory. Erendira has the hero,
Ulises, kill her grandmother, and then she disappears with the gold ingots
into the land of legend. Once again myth has been salvaged from the gross
material world. In a further stage of this imaginary history, a patriarch (in
The Autumn of the Patriarch) is the absolute master of a territory that has
less and less material reality and is little more than a rhetorical slogan or
a sign in a system of exchange controlled by foreign powers.
While Garcia Marquez gives a certain importance to the precap-
italist matriarchal society, he still predicates this on a traditional separation
between feminine nature and male enterprise. Like other novelists of the
sixties and seventies, he upholds utopian values that seem to derive from
the sphere that society has designated as .. feminine." For instance, in his
Nobel prize acceptance speech, he appealed for a Utopia of love to replace
the apocalypse of death and destruction of advanced capitalism. Yet in his
Playboy interview he also showed that he regards politics as an elite activity
carried on by a group of representative males-General Torrijos, Fidel Cas-
tro, Francois Mitterand, and him.
This leads me to the connection between the literary intelligentsia
of the sixties and the oppositional politics of this same period, a politics
dominated by the guerrilla movements and their hero, Che Guevara. No
one will deny the heroism of these national liberation movements, many
of which ended tragically. Yet the literature they produced, with its ideal
of the .. new man" activated by nonmaterial incentives, bears out Nancy
Hartsock's description of a left-wing theory that is trapped within a negative
eros, one that values the violent confrontation with death over community
and life. It is only recently that women who participated in these movements
have begun to speak of their experiences and to criticize an ideal of the
militant that suppressed feelings of weakness. A former Tupamara (of Uru-
guay) writes: .. Feminine sexuality, desire to have children or not to have
them, the disposition of our bodies was not taken into account. For instance,
maternity was lived by us as an obstacle that prevented us from continuing
the struggle, especially the military struggle." 19 Even when a woman man-
aged to become a militant, she was often forced into a traditional gender
role and classified as either butch or seductress. Women "were not militants
in the true sense. " 20 These comments were made by women who admire
Che Guevara and neither regret nor reject armed struggle. Yet they are forced
to recognize the unbalanced nature of a movement in which one gender
constitutes revolutionary meaning and practice.
512
Jean Franco
Before discussing some of the factors that have led to this kind
of criticism, let me briefly summarize my argument up to this point. In its
confrontation with metropolitan discourses that placed its members in a
traditionally female position in the play of power and meaning, the Latin
American intelligentsia attempted to speak on behalf of the nonliterate, the
indigenous, and women who, through "archaic" institutions and practices,
maintained forms of symbolic production that allowed them to deal with
and even resist capitalism. In the fifties and sixties this repressed material
and the interesting incongruities that had arisen because of the coexistence
of different modes of symbolic production led some writers-Asturias, Ar-
guedas, Roa Bastos-to incorporate these subjectivities which were alien to
capitalism into their narratives as utopian elements. In other writers, the
critique of violence and machismo similarly led to a feminization of values.
However, creativity-the active creation of real or imaginary societies that
would perpetuate the originality ofLatin America beyond the span of mortal
life-was still regarded as a masculine province. Women's sole creative func-
tion was the lowly task of reproducing the labor force.
Clearly, this state of affairs, in which one sector ofthe population
monopolizes creativity and makes it a quest for immortality, has been se-
riously challenged in recent years. The reinstallation of military govern-
ments and the breakdown of traditional political parties, as well as the
establishment of revolutionary governments in Cuba and Nicaragua, has
led to serious questioning of the past. Democratic participation has been
reevaluated and is no longer regarded as a bourgeois deception but as the
only practical basis for socialism. Such participation cannot be developed
as long as one gender continues to be subordinate.
At the same time, the violence of military governments in the
southern cone, the wars in Central America and the activities of death
squads, have all been directed at those places, like the home and the Church,
that have harbored "archaic" subjectivities. The murder of the archbishop
in El Salvador, of priests and nuns, the attack on the cathedral, the uprooting
of indigenous peoples from their homes in Guatemala, the resettlement of
working-class populations in Argentina and Chile, the sterilization of Puerto
Rican women, the rape of women in front of their husbands and children,
all represent ferocious attacks on the family and the Church by the very
forces (the military) that rhetorically invoke these institutions. By attacking
them and by appealing to more deterritorialized forms of domination-
"mass media" and electronic religion or abstract notions of nationhood-
the military governments have also unwittingly contributed to the subver-
sion of these formerly "sacred" categories. Moral rights, which formerly had
been attached to particular territories or genders, are rapidly undergoing
resemanticization, not only by the military, but also by new oppositional
forces. The present stage of"deterritorialization," which has separated women
from their traditional regions of refuge in the home and the Church, and
indigenous peoples from their communities, represents a cultural revolution
brought about by imperialism. 21 But this conservative cultural revolution
has been so radical that it has also opened up new areas of struggle; as a
consequence of these social changes, new types of power, no longer solely
identified with masculinity, have become increasingly important.
Let me give one example-the resistance of the "madwomen" of
the Plaza de Mayo in Argentina. These women have not only redefined
513
public space by taking over the center of Buenos Aires on ore afternoon
every week but have also interrupted military discourse (and now the silence
ofthe new government) by publicly displaying the photographs of sons and
daughters who have "disappeared." This form of refusing a message of death
is obviously quite different from the quest for immortality that has tradi-
tionally inspired the writer and the political leader. The women interrupted
the military by wrestling meaning away from them and altering the con-
notations of the word "mother." To the military, they were the mothers of
dead subversives, therefore, of monsters. But they have transformed them-
selves into the "mothers of the Plaza de Mayo," that is, in the words of one
of them, into "mothers of all the disappeared," not merely their own chil-
dren. They have thus torn the term "mother" from its literal meaning as
the biological reproducer of children and insisted on social connotations
that emphasize community over individuality.
In using the term "mother" in this way, these women show that
mothering is not simply tied to anatomy but is a position involving a struggle
over meanings and the history of meanings, histories that have been ac-
quired and stored within unofficial institutions. While "mothers of subver-
sives" is univocal, stripped of any connotation but that of reproduction,
"mothers of the disappeared" signals an absence, a space that speaks through
a lack-the lack of a child-but also a continuing lack within the government
of any participatory dialogue, of any answer to the question of how their
children disappeared.
The activities of the women of the Plaza de Mayo are sympto-
matic of many grass-root movements in Latin America, from the comu-
nidades de base in Brazil to the popular song movements in Chile and
Argentina. These are movements in which the so-called silent sectors of the
population are forging politics in ways that no longer subordinate popular
culture and women to the traditional view of culture determined by met-
ropolitan discourse. In addition, the postrevolutionary societies of Cuba
and Nicaragua have been forced to deal with the participation of women.
Nicaragua has, indeed, recognized that creativity is not exclusive to a male
elite but is something that is dispersed among the entire population.
In countries under military dictatorship, there is a growing rec-
ognition of the importance of cultural politics in the creation ofnongendered
solidarity groups. To go back to Fanon, this involves transcending the tra-
ditional fear of the intelligentsia of immersing its members' individuality
in the masses. It also entails realizing that violence, while necessary in self-
defense, as in present-day Central America, is not the only way to be rev-
olutionary. That is why an understanding of the socially constructed nature
of sexual as well as class and racial divisions is so important, for it enables
us to recognize the ethnocentricity of knowledge/power. The fact that the
metropolis has always been the place in which knowledge is produced has
reinforced the association of domination with masculinity in the Third World
and has, therefore, restricted the balanced development of revolutionary
movements.
Marx offered an epistemological position that allows us to un-
derstand the world as if we belonged to the proletariat. Fanon forces us to
see the world as if we were people of color. One of the lessons of revolu-
tionary movements of the last several years is that we have to resemanticize
preconstructed gender categories by taking meaning into our own hands and
514
Jean Franco
overcoming the traditional associations of the feminine with nature and the
immobile. For those of us living in the metropolis, there is another essential
process of defamiliarization. We must step outside the display window of
advanced capitalism and look through it from the point of view of societies
of scarcity. Then it may appear not only replete but also grotesquely reified.
And only then will we understand that the becalmed sea traps not the
colonized but the colonizers.
Notes
1 Frantz Fanon. The Wretched of the Earth (New York: Grove Press. 1968). p. 51.
2 Fanon, p. 52.
3 For clarification of Foucault's theory and methodology, see "Two Lectures," Power/Knowl-
edge: Selected Interviews and Other Writings, 1972-77 (New York: Pantheon, 1981 ).
4 Pierre Bourdieu, Le sens pratique (Paris: Les Editions de Minuit, 1980).
5 I am extending the notion of "interruption" as it is developed by David Silverman and Brian
Torode, "Interrupting the 'I'." The Material Word (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1980).
pp. 3-19.
6 Alfonso Reyes, "Discurso por Virgilio," Antofogia de fa revista contemp6ranea (Mexico,
1973). pp. 163-89. The reference to Neruda is to "Alturas de Macchu Picchu," which IS
part of Canto General.
7 For the relation of this organization to indigenous culture, see Nestor Garda Canclin1, Las
culture popufares en ef capitafismo (Mexico: Nueva Imagen, 1982).
8 Terry Eagleton, The Rape of Clarissa (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press. 1982). p
7.
9 Rene Marques, "En una ciudad llamada San Juan," En una ciudad 1/amada San Juan (Mexico:
UNAM, 1960).
10 Nancy Hartsock, Money, Sex, and Power: Towards a Feminist Historical Matenafism (New
York: Longman, 1983).
11 Hartsock, p. 203.
12 Hartsock, p. 253.
13 Jose Marfa Arguedas, Ef zorro de arriba y ef zorro de abaJO (Buenos Aires· Losada. 1971 ).
14 Playboy Magazine, 30:2 ( 1983).
1& "Madre, me voy manana a Santiago," in Trifce ( 1922). my translation. The Spanish Civil
War poems "Espana. aparta de mi este caliz" ("Spain. Take This Cup from Me") were
published posthumously.
16 Mario Vargas Llosa. "Novela primitiva y novela de creac16n en America Latina," Rev1sta de
fa Universidad de Mexico. 23: 10 ( 1969). p. 31.
17 This refers to a phrase that radio announcers in Argentina repeated daily at the time of Eva
Peron's death.
18 Jacques Gilard, ed., Articufos Costeflos, vol. 1 (Barcelona: Brughera. 1981)
19 Ana Maria Auraujo, Tupamaras, des femmes de Uruguay (Paris: des femmes. 1980). p.
163.
20 AurauJO, p. 145.
21 For terms such as "overcoding" and "deterritorialization." I am Indebted to Gilles Deleuze
and Felix Guattari, Anti-Oedipus: Capitalism and Schizophrema (New York: Viking Press.
1972).
515
V Science, Technology, Politics, and Ethics
Stanley Aronowitz
Notes
Stanley Aronowitz, "Marx, Braverman. and the Log1c of Capital," Insurgent Socwlog1st (Fall
1978)
2 Karl Marx, Capital, val. 1, especially chaps. 12-15.
3 Harry Braverman, Labor and Monopoly Capital (New York: Monthly Review Press. 1974).
4 Paul Baran and Paul Sweezy, Monopoly Capital (New York: Monthly Review Press, 1966).
5 Andre Gorz, "The Tyranny of the Factory: Today and Tomorrow." in Andre Gorz, ed . The
Division of Labour: The Labour Process and Class Struggle in Modem Capitalism (London:
Harvester Press, 1976).
6 Serge Bologna, "Class Composition and the Theory of the Party at the Ong1n of the Workers
Councils Movement," in Gorz, ed., The DIVision of Labour.
7 Christian Palloix, "The Labour Process from Fordism to Neo-Fordism," 1n Gorz, ed .. The
Division of Labour.
8 Georg Lukacs. "Re1ficat1on and the Consciousness of the Proletanat," History and Class
Consciousness (Cambridge: MIT Press, 1971 ).
9 Georg Simmel, The Philosophy of Money (London Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1978). Rei-
fication for Simmel is a property of an economy in which money dom1nates all soc1al relations.
In contrast, Lukacs locates the phenomenon in a specific histoncal context and a particular
soc1al formation, namely, capitalism. It IS only when the commodity form penetrates all social
relations that reification comes to dominate consc1ousness, according to Lukacs.
10 Serge Mallet, The New Working Class (London: Spokesman Books, 1975)
11 According to Palloix, "we must emphasize that Fordism, wh1ch still charactenzes the labour
process today, is not the same as Taylorism; it is a real innovation. . Ford took over the
essential aspects of Taylorism (separation of design and innovation from execution, divis1on
and sub-division of jObs, each movement allowed a spec1fic time) but he also went further
1n introducing two further pnnciples: a new method of controlling labour-power, the intro-
duction of the flow-line pnnciple (conveyors) 1n the concrete shape of the assembly line" (in
Gorz, ed., The Division of Labour, p. 59). The new method of control of labor-power was
the day-wage system (1n place of piece rates), "thus making it possible to 'regulate' the
externally-Imposed control of labour-power." Th1s day rate-the famous five-dollar day-
" assured capital of an unmterrupted supply of labour" and dampened militancy. It is inter-
esting to note that dunng the rise of the CIO (1935-41 ), Ford was the last major automaker
to be unionized. The company combined terror w1th relatively h1gh wages to prevent the self-
organization of workers.
12 Andre Gorz, "Technology, Technicians, and the Class Struggle," in Gorz, ed .. The Division
of Labour.
13 See Stanley Aronow1tz and Henry Giroux. Education under SeJge (South Hadley, Mass.: Bergm
and Garvey, 1985). espec1ally chap. 8, "Neo-conservative Ideology and the Crisis in Higher
Education."
535
14 See especially Max Horkheimer, Cntical Theory(NewYork: Seabury Press, 1972); and Stanley
Aronowitz, The Cnsis in Historical Matenalism (South Hadley, Mass.: Bergin and Garvey,
1981)
15 Here we must dist1nguish Marx, who made th1s claim once m The German Ideology, and the
Marxism of the Second and Third Internationals, which never tired of presenting itself in the
guise of a natural sc1ence. following Engels's suggestion in Anti-DDhring. The writings of
Lemn and Kautsky are especially Important in mak1ng the case for Marxism as a "natural
science." See V. I. Lenin, Materialism and Empirical Criticism; and Karl Kautsky The Class
Struggle (Ann Arbor: University of M1chigan Press, 1975).
16 Sidney Hook, Reason, Social Myth. and Democracy (New York: John Day and Co., 1940),
p. 107.
17 See Jacques Derrida, Speech and Phenomena (Evanston, Ill.: Northwestern University Press,
1970)
18 Michel Foucault, The Order of Things (New York: Pantheon Books, 1970).
19 JOrgen Habermas, "Reconstruction of Historical Materialism." Communication and the Ev-
olution of Soc1ety (Boston: Beacon Press, 1979)
20 JOrgen Habermas, Theory of Communicative Action (Boston: Beacon Press, 1984).
21 For an excellent collective study of the British group, see Gary Werskey, The Visible College
(New York: Holt, Rhinehart and Winston, 1978) No such history exists of the Americans,
but a good starting point is Alice Kimball Smith, A Peril and a Hope: The Scientists' Movement
in America (Cambridge: MIT Press. 1970) The latter volume deals with the postwar effort
of some Amencan phys1c1sts to respond to the decis1on of the Truman administration to use
the atom1c bomb as an instrument of war. Werskey' s study deals principally with British Left
sc1ent1sts 1n the 1930s. See also Ronald Clark, Haldane (Oxford: Oxford University Press,
1984). Sadly, th1s biographer, fundamentally hostile to J. B. S. Haldane's political views,
makes l1ttle effort to understand his Marxism and the Social Relations of Science movement
of which he was a part, although not the most theoretically interesting member. See J. D.
Bernal, The Social Function of Science (London, 1939). for a fuller explication of the attempt
of this fascinating group to comprehend science in soc1al terms.
22 Christopher Caudwell, The Crisis in Physics (London: Bodley Head, 1950). This work, orig-
inally published in 1939, was perhaps the most sophisticated effort by any English-speaking
Marxist to deal w1th science as a discourse, hence subject to ideological influences. That is,
as Hyman Levy, one of the leading figures in the Social Relations of Science movement notes
in the Introduction to the volume, "any scientific theory IS necessarily the specialized de-
velopment of a general social view, even although those who init1ate the theory may be
profoundly unaware of the connection" (p. vi1i).
23 See especially Charles Sanders Peirce, "The F1xation of Belief," in Justus Buchler, ed., The
Philosophy of Pe1rce: Selected Writings (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1940); and
Thomas Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific Revolutions (Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
1962)
24 Francis Crick, Life Itself (New York: Touchstone Books. 1982).
25 Louis Althusser, For Marx (New York: V1ntage Books, 1970).
26 Max Horkheimer and Theodor Adorno, Dialectic of Enlightenment (New York: Seabury Press.
1973)
27 Theodor Adorno, Negative Dialectics (New York: Seabury Press, 1974).
28 Max Horkhe1mer. Critical Theory (New York: Continuum Books, 1972).
29 Loren Graham, Between Science and Values (New York: Columbia University Press, 1981 ).
30 Paul Feyerabend, Against Method (London: New Left Books, 1970).
31 Thomas Kuhn, Structure of Scientific Revolutions (2d ed.; Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1970); and, more recently, The Essential Tension (Chicago: University of Chicago
Press, 1979).
32 Karl Popper, The Log1c of Sc1ent1fic Discovery (London: Hutchinson, 1961 ).
33 John Dewey, "Ouest for Certainty," in John Dewey: The Later Works, vol. 4, ed. J. Ann
Boyleston (Carbondale: Southern lllino1s University Press, 1984). p. 136.
34 Dewey, "Ouest for Certainty," p. 142.
35 Dewey, "Ouest for Certainty," p. 142.
36 Ludwig Fleck, The Genesis of a Scientific Fact (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1979).
See also Bruno Latour and Steve Woolgar, Laboratory Life (Los Angeles: Sage Publications,
1980); and Arthur Koestler, The Case of the Midwife Toad(NewYork: Vintage Books, 1973).
536
Stanley Aronowitz
All of these writers. in quite different ways, show the social constitution of what counts as
scientific knowledge. In particular. these works demonstrate the power of the scientific com-
munity in determining the truth value of the experimental and theoretical work itself. One
could also add the controversy surrounding the observations and theones of Immanuel Ve-
likovsky for ev1dence that Peirce was right: truth is defined by those professionally certified
to name 1t.
37 W. Newton-Smith. The Rationality of Science (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. 1981 ).
Newton-Smith has made the most serious defense of the realist theory of science in many
years. His polemic against the relativ1sm of Popper. Kuhn. and Feyerabend is ably argued.
Yet this work. an internalist theory of scientific progress. remains unreflective about the way
in which sctentific rnethod is constituted socially. The charge that the Popperian school IS
an irrationalist theory stmply stacks the deck against every nonrationalist effort to challenge
the truth claims of science. As I have indicated above. this school remains. for the most
part. rationalist even if 1t does not accept a realist account.
537
Discussion
Question
Since Husserl, European philosophy of science has recog-
nized the social and historical constitution of the objects, methods, and communities
of scientific inquiry. Even in Anglo-American philosophy of science, at least in the
current postempiricist phase, these claims are no longer controversial. The question
is, what follows from this? Does it follow that we cannot distinguish between sci-
entifically warranted assertions and ideological ones? Second, what do you mean by
ideology here? Third, how would you constitute scientific inquiry so that it is not
oriented to prediction and control?
Aronowitz
Let me start by saying that we have a different perception
of both Anglo-American philosophy of science and Marxist attempts to analyze the
question of scientific method. I have not encountered one critique of scientific method
as socially and historically constituted by activities that themselves may be construed
ideologically. Although Feyerabend studied the constitution of the scientific object
and the plurality of theories, Kuhn studied the constitution of scientific communities,
and Black studied the form of scientific results, they all ultimately defend the neu-
trality of science by appealing to the status of scientific method. I would argue that
scientific method-a method characterized by decontextualization and by the sep-
aration of quality from quantity-is itself a social activity. Furthermore, the issue
of intervention, which is an epistemological as well as a historical issue, has not
been addressed systematically. Finally, although European philosophy of science is
concerned with the effects of rationality, it does not challenge the nature of that
rationality. What we have are piecemeal defenses of plurality. For example, Fey-
erabend ultimately accepts the scientific method and shows that two theories, in-
commensurable with respect to their results, nevertheless refer rigorously to the same
object by means of their procedure. That procedure is held to be historically correct
because he never challenges the Popperian view of falsifiability, a view grounded in
the project of prediction and control.
Your second question addresses the concept of ideology. I
mean to suggest that there is a hegemonic discourse that is socially and historically
constituted. This ideology refers to its own conditions of discursive competence, on
the one side, and to a prevailing set of practices, on the other. The validity of science,
grounded in a theory of correspondence, depends upon the ability of scientific dis-
course to appear in a relation of verisimilitude with its own practices. Even the
Kuhnian theory of paradigm shifts never questions the relation between scientific
practices and what science calls the "real."
Your third question is how to reconstitute the object of sci-
entific knowledge. One example would be Ernesto Laclau's attempt to reconstitute
society as a set of discourses. A second example is Althusser's insistence that Marx
transferred the focus of scientific inquiry from people to society and the mode of
production. Once we recognize that we are constituting a counterhegemonic dis-
course whose relation to the real is forever problematic and linked to our own
political, social, and cultural practices, then we are free to do genuinely ecological
science, to do genuinely social science. Then the integration of linguistic theory, or
for that matter discourse theory, with the ongoing social practices of a putatively
radical movement can actually take place. As long as we insist on the closed system
of scientific inquiry, one in which both the object of knowledge and the methods
by which we know the world are fixed, we can never evolve into a critical science.
Thus the first task is a deconstruction that is ruthless, pitiless, and thoroughgoing,
including a deconstruction of our own scientific paradigm, which we call Marxism.
Question
Gramsci's Prison Notebooks-particularly the tenth and elev-
enth-deal with the question of science by responding to Vico's notion of scientific
certainty. What place does Gramsci's work have in your definition of science?
538
Stanley Aronowitz
Aronowitz
I have attempted to avoid defining either science or ideology
because I think that such definitions become problematic by fixing the limits of this
kind of discourse. This refusal is a methodological, not a rhetorical, move. The
attempt to define them involves an infinite regress of the relationship between specific
hegemonic discourses and historically evolving social interests. We define as certain
those discourses that fix particular relations of the so-called natural and social worlds
and achieve thereby a kind of aesthetic elegance: as Christine Delphy suggests in
her paper, both scientific philosophy and science seek the utmost simplicity and the
greatest scope in the explanation of the world.
In this context, let me invoke Dewey, since, although I'm
interested in international Marxist and post-Marxist discussions, I want us to get
used to thinking and working with Americans. Otherwise we aren't going to make
any political progress in this country. John Dewey's Quest for Certainty discusses
the Gramscian point about hegemonic discourses and the relation between thought
and action. (I realize many people would think pragmatism old-fashioned. But wait
another five years and analytic philosophy of language will be relegated to the dust
bin temporarily because Rorty is raising questions about the role of warranted as-
sertability and pragmatic relations in the constitution of scientific discourse.) The
"quest for certainty" is always linked, particularly as a definition of science, to
moments of crisis. Certainty, as distinct from the actual practice of science, becomes
a kind of religiosity scientists invoke to put Humpty Dumpty back together again.
But Humpty Dumpty is rent; he will be put together again only temporarily. Our
temporary certainties will present themselves as science, when, in fact, they will be
hegemonic ideologies for a particular era.
This has important implications for reconstituting a critical
science, which must confront the necessity to understand itself and which can only
produce temporary certainties. In the old Frankfurt dialogue this is called "reflex-
ivity," not deconstruction: practices reflect upon and continually modify themselves
in recognition of their relativity and historicity in relation to social discourses and
social struggles.
Question
You are not denying-or are you-the claim of realism in
the last instance, that there is a moment that belongs to the world, a moment that
is being interrogated by scientific practices?
Aronowitz
I'm arguing something entirely different. It is evident that
there is a natural history prior to human development. It is evident that both physical
and biological states or levels of reality have an existence prior to the appearance
of human beings. Realism as a theory refers to the status of the referent and of
knowledge about the referent. I am arguing that the world of things, our world of
referents, is constituted by the practices and discourses of social life. This is no
different from Marx's notion of the humanization of nature and the naturalization
of "man." This applies not only to the world of everyday life, culture, and work,
but also to the world of the natural sciences. Most scientists and philosophers of
science do not accept this notion-that the referent is itself the product of historically
constituted activity. Once this becomes the new common sense, we can tum our
attention toward the new critical science I am talking about, a science devoted to
constructing a world out of utopian discourses.
Question
Would a critical science counteract the intrusion of techno-
logic into the moral-practical sphere of society?
539
Aronowitz
The project of critical science is informed by the interests
of a counterhegemonic discourse. But the first task is to reduce the privileged space
that scientific and technological discourses occupy within social affairs. We need to
reintroduce ethical and moral considerations into social and discursive practices. As
long as science presents itself as anormative (outside the realm of ethical judgment),
we are caught in a circle of having to validate Marxism, feminism, or other oppo-
sitional practices in the terms set by the Enlightenment; that is, they are outside
rationality, even nonrational, with less claim than science to speak of the real. Science
presents itself as a neutral discourse, yet it is a mechanism of subordination; it
subordinates women, working people, black people.
There is, however, an antagonism within science. This mo-
ment of difference is, as Laclau has argued, produced by the confrontation between
two blocks of scientific discourse. Too many Marxists have apparently decided that
we need not struggle to produce this second, counterhegemonic science because they
have assumed that there is only one science. That's Habermas's argument.
Now let's talk about the technological element of this con-
flict. Technology is a system of reifications and discourses, one that hides a broad
range of ideological interests, including those of science. Marxists have always wanted
to separate the scientific from the technological in order to preserve the former and
appropriate it for themselves. That cannot be done. One has to make a thorough-
going, fundamental critique of the presuppositions ofboth, to show that the Greek
notion of techne as human practice has been radically disjoined from the notion of
technology. Technology, in turn, has become a new religion.
541
Sue Golding
Because we can only "know" reality, can only "know" what exists
(otherwise we would return to some form of transcendentalism or mysti-
cism), the argument that "objective truth" entails historic specificity also
bears on Gramsci's concept of "prediction": it can never be "scientific"; it
can never be an act of knowledge as such. "And how could prediction be
an act of knowledge?" Gramsci remarked rhetorically; "one knows only
what has been and what is, not what will be, which is something 'non-
existent' and therefore unknowable by definition." 56 In Gramsci's estima-
tion, "prediction" has been confused with "science" precisely because the
concept "law," and more particularly "law of historical movement," has
been rigidified, itself confused with "permanency" and "automatism" and
equated to formal logic. But, if we again follow Vico on this point, law can
be nothing other than tendency, probability, regularity. Indeed, it is with
Ricardo's scientific discoveries in the field of political economy that this
connection between law and history is made more specific; that is, in the
"concept and fact of determined market: i.e., the scientific discovery that
specific and permanent forces have risen historically and that the operation
of these forces presents itself with a certain 'automatism' .... " 57
But the question for Gramsci is not one, as he puts it, "of 'dis-
covering' a metaphysical law of'determinism', or even establishing a 'gen-
eral' law of causality." 58 The question is precisely how relatively permanent
forces are constituted and maintained in history. This is where "prediction"
reenters. Prediction, if not an act of knowledge, was for Gramsci a "practical
act," the practical politics of creating consensus, of creating the result "fore-
seen"; the practical politics of establishing a collective will, of creating virtue
as both "vital impulse" and "fortuna." 59 In other words, it is the practical
political activity of creating "what ought to be," of creating the realm of
possibilities. In this sense prediction is a part of the ethical-political moment,
indeed, a part of progress. 60 Moreover, because prediction is practical ac-
tivity (i.e., "real," and not a metaphysical event), it is connected to the law
of tendency, necessity, even change. But the more complex answer to the
question ofhow prediction constitutes (at least in part) development, praxis-
552
Sue Golding
indeed, what is meant by this notion of change and progress-was detailed
by Gramsci through the concept of immanence and by what he called the
"real" dialectic.
The "Real" Dialectic
Gramsci reasoned that science means both creative discovery and
the methodology of that creation (i.e., the methodology of history in the
making). Thus he proceeded with a notion of science that operates on two
levels: as theoretical or practical activity, 61 and as the unified expression of
that activity-as the "organic unity of history, politics and economics" or
the unified expression of the "rational and real," outside of which there is
no meaningful concept or knowledge. Accordingly, because Gramsci situ-
ated-as did others before him-the rational and real within history, as a
part of history, as well as an expression of history itself, that theoretical-
practical activity is always "man-made" necessary, rational. 62 This led
Gramsci to conclude that there can be no omnipotent truth devoid of human
activity or historical specificity, nor can there be an underlying, arbitrary,
or general logic to knowledge or scientific methodology. Indeed, it allowed
him to argue that there can be no "science-in-general" and that, in this
context, scienza (science/knowledge) is "political."63
But to reason as Gramsci did-that is, to acknowledge and em-
phasize as continuous this "organic unity" while developing these arguments
about science and philosophy in terms of a creativity and method "rooted"
in history-is not what divorces Gramsci's philosophy of praxis from the
difficulties encountered either in Vico's dualist development of truth and
certainty as science or from the transcendental metaphysics of the kantian
categories of knowledge. Nor is it that emphasis which divorces the phi-
losophy of praxis from the speculative "history" of Croce's idealist Spirit,
or even from the "vulgar evolutionism" of mechanistic or reductionist ma-
terialism. Finally, it is not simply this emphasis on science as history or
politics that prevents the subsequent equivalences of history, politics, sci-
ence, and philosophy from becoming an indistinguishable swamp of con-
ceptual identity. What separates the philosophy of praxis from these so-
called philosophical errors and, moreover, what prevents it from lapsing
into simple tautological reasoning is the way in which the "historical" in
"historical materialism" is understood. 64
For Gramsci, this "knowing how" meant not only conceptual-
izing history as an active unity of theoretical and practical activity, or as
the synthesis ofthe rational and real, or even as an expression of movement,
but also conceptualizing concretely what the terms "active unity," "syn-
thesis," expression," and "movement" actually mean in the philosophy of
praxis. It is thus the full comprehension of what it means to "take" the
hegelian dialectic and "stand it on its feet"; the full comprehension of how
the "real" dialectic is conceptualized in the philosophy of praxis, what it
means to say that it is the heir of German philosophy, French cultural
politics, and English political economy, and why that conception removes
it from its transcendentalist, materialist, idealist, even positivist roots-
namely, why it is "orthodox," totalizing, a break from tradition. In short,
knowing how the "historical" of historical materialism is conceptualized is
precisely knowing the meaning of immanence or becoming, and why Gram-
sci often emphasized that that is the central conception in the philosophy
of praxis or, indeed, is the philosophy of praxis itsel£ 65
553
Gramsci wrote in a fragment called Speculative Immanence and
Historicist or Realist Immanence,
it is affirmed that the philosophy of praxis was born
on the terrain of the highest development of culture
in the first half of the nineteenth century, this culture
being represented by classical German philosophy, En-
glish classical economics and French political litera-
ture and politics.... But in what sense is the affir-
mation to be understood? That each of these
movements has contributed respectively to the elab-
oration of the philosophy, the economics, and the pol-
itics of the philosophy of praxis? Or that the philos-
ophy of praxis has synthesized the three movements,
that is, the entire culture of the age, and that in the
new synthesis, whichever "moment" one is examin-
ing, the theoretical, the economic, or the political, one
will find each of these three movements present as a
preparatory "moment"? This seems to me to be the
case. And it seems to me that the unitary "moment"
of synthesis is to be identified in the concept of im-
manence, which has been translated from the specu-
lative form, as put forward by classical German phi-
losophy, into an historicized form with the aid of
French politics and English classical economics. 66
This "unitary" moment, this so-called synthesis, conditioned as it were by
its distinct "preparatory moments," is not a starting point of investigation
or knowledge; it is not a "point of departure." 67 Nor is it unitary in the
sense of an indivisible, static, or eternal subjectivity, a "thing-in-itself."
Rather, it is a unitary moment in the sense of representing the epoch or
bloc of a "history in the making," where that historical epoch, bloc, spirit,
or culture of the age is precisely and always an expression of our theoretical
and practical creativity or, to use Gramsci's phrase, an expression of absolute
historicized immanence. 68
But for the fuller, more developed meaning of this "arrival," this
so-called absolute historicized immanence, Gramsci directed our attention,
once again, to the Theses on Feuerbach. He commented that, in the first
thesis, the unity of the theoretical and practical activity referred to by Marx
is precisely the dialectical unity of matter and "man," where matter is under-
stood to mean the material forces of production, the "economic elements, " 69
whereas "man" is understood to mean "the complex social relations" or,
"more exactly, the process of his actions." 70 But as we have seen, since
Gramsci acknowledged that for the philosophy of praxis there is no such
thing as an objective truth free from error, no truth outside history, no
thing-in-itself, this suggests that the meaning of both matter and "man" is
constructed in and by reality and that, consequently, there neither exists a
general or pure economic science nor a natural "man" or "man-in-general."
In other words, the meaning of "what is man" is always subject to history;
it is historically created, "changes with changes in the circumstances," is
the "synthesized" unitary moment of our theoretical and practical activity.
554
Sue Golding
It is a meaning that Gramsci argued is always, consequently, in the process
of becoming. 71 This led him to conclude, as well, that not only is the meaning
of"what is man" a historical creation, but that meaning itself is a historical
creation. 72 Meaning is also, in other words, the synthesized unitary expres-
sion of our creation, our theoretical and practical activity. It implies dis-
covery, possibility, change-but not of an arbitrary kind, that is, not of a
kind without foundation in the distinct preparatory moments of the rational
and real. Meaning, which changes continually with changes in the circum-
stances, is constructed out of both the realm of necessity and the realm of
possibility, where necessity is not opposed to possibility. Rather, necessity
is the condition without which the realm of possibility could not exist; or,
more to the point, meaning is always an expression of historicized imma-
nence, of becoming.
By rendering Vico's verum ipsumfactum into the "real" dialectic,
meaning was, for Gramsci (as he claimed it was for Marx), rational, nec-
essary, the "universal-subjective," always in relation to (and created out of)
this process of change, this process called history. 73 Science, then, is the
methodology of this "coherent unitary expression" of the rational and the
real; it becomes linked with the notions of regularity, law of tendency, ne-
cessity, certainty. Even humanity itself is this coherent unitary expression
(or synthesis) of a people acting in, acting on, and creating anew, not only
themselves, but "the inherited living nightmares of the dead," or, in a word,
society. This coherent unitary expression, this active unitary or process, was
Gramsci's historicized immanence, his "absolute humanism," his "becom-
ing," the "critical act," making the rational and real more "coherent"; in
short, a return to the terrain of politics.
But it is a politics that includes on its terrain not only a histo-
ricized rationality and necessity but the realm of the possible, where pos-
sibility is connected to necessity. If, as Marx concluded in the Theses on
Feuerbach, the "critical act" is the politics of creating from the unity of
theoretical and practical activity "changes in the circumstances," then pol-
itics is also, to quote Gramsci's reference to Machiavelli and sleight-of-hand
to Croce, "the art of the possible." It is this politics as the art of the possible-
or the dialectic it implies-that became for Gramsci the cornerstone of his
attack against Bukharin's "flat, vulgar evolutionism" of mechanical mate-
rialism and the "pure historical movement/progress" of Croce's "scientific-
utopianism." Scorning the fact that both Bukharin and Croce (he included
here the "actual idealists" as well as other "scientific" and "orthodox" marx-
ists) acknowledged that material conditions change with changes in the cir-
cumstances, they did so by "forgetting" that it is people who change cir-
cumstances; and they did so neither out of arbitrary speculation nor out of
carefully developed predictions around the iron-clad laws of historical de-
velopment. "The uneducated and crude environment has dominated the
educator," conceded a sarcastic Gramsci, "rather than the other way around.
If the environment is the educator, it too must be educated, but the Manual
does not understand this revolutionary dialectic. " 74
What is so revolutionary about the real dialectic is precisely this
point about becoming and change as not only linked to necessity, the rational
and real (i.e., history) but as linked to possibility, to freedom; as a result,
the realm of possibility is not simply conceivable, it is obtainable. 75 More-
over, in so historicizing immanence, Gramsci was able to reemphasize that
555
the power to overcome or overthrow, change or make society better, does
not materialize out of the air but is born from the old society itself-from
human activity, knowledge, science, in all its impure senses. That "no new
society ever emerges without the seeds of its development having first been
planted in the old" means precisely that the old is the necessary condition
without which the new cannot be realized, and that the passage from ne-
cessity to freedom is always a political-or critical-act, the synthetic unity
of theory and praxis.
But it also means that the struggle to create society, and what it
means to talk about, develop, and maintain a better one, a progressive
society as such and for whom, is also and always a political struggle, a
struggle of becoming, a struggle around potentiality, a struggle to unite the
"preparatory moments" of the rational and real into a "unitary moment,"
one that is never permanent, static, or arbitrary but forms instead a "historic
bloc." It is a struggle that involves making more coherent both concrete
will (as the first moment of our practical-political activity) and the ethical
morality appropriate to it, that is, the articulating of and/or creating anew
the ethical assumptions underlying any conception of the world. And that
making "more coherent" the synthetic unitary moment-which, as we have
seen, is always actively political and one not divorced from history-marks
the "passage" or "catharsis" from the old society to the new. Its realization
is precisely what Gramsci called "ethico-political hegemony": the political
battle to transform society.
The proposition contained in the "Preface to a Con-
tribution to the Critique of Political Economy" ...
should be considered as an affirmation of epistemo-
logical and not simply of psychological and moral
value. From this, it follows that the theoretical-prac-
tical principle of hegemony has also gnoseological sig-
nificance, and here it is that Illich's greatest theoretical
contribution to the philosophy of praxis should be
sought. ... The realization of a hegemonic apparatus,
in so far as it creates a new ideological terrain, deter-
mines a reform of consciousness and of methods of
knowledge: it is a fact of knowledge, a philosophical
fact. In Crocean terms: when one succeeds in intro-
ducing a new morality in conformity with a new con-
ception of the world, one finishes by introducing the
conception as well; in other words one determines a
reform of the whole of philosophy.
[Moreover] structure and superstructures form an
"historical bloc," that is to say the complex, contra-
dictory and discordant ensemble of the superstructures
in the reflection of the ensemble of social relations of
production.... that is, that the "rational" is actively
and actually real. This reasoning is based on the nec-
essary reciprocity between structure and superstruc-
ture, a reciprocity which is nothing other than the real
dialectical process. 76
556
Sue Golding
[Finally it can be said that] the term "catharsis" can
be enployed to indicate the passage from the purely
economic (egoistic-passional) to the ethico-political
moment.... This also means the passage from "ob-
jective to subjective" and from "necessity to free-
dom." Structure ceases to be an external force which
crushes man, assimilates him to itself and makes him
passive; and it is transformed into a means of freedom,
an instrument to create a new ethico-political form
and new sources of initiatives. To establish the "ca-
thartic" moment becomes, therefore, it seems to me,
the starting point for all the philosophy of praxis, and
the cathartic process coincides with the chain of
syntheses which have resulted from the evolution of
the dialectic. 77
Gramsci himself did not, because he could not, develop a the-
oretical framework for detailing the cathartic moment, for while able to
redress the problems of reductionism and dogmatic orthodoxy by incor-
porating into the marxist dialectic a notion of science as philosophy of
praxis, he did so, in the end, by reintroducing a teleological notion of the
economic moment. Thus, while emphasizing people's participation in cre-
ating permanency and change, while emphasizing that we create, in the
context of that dynamic history, not only the very notion of what it is to
be human but also what it ought to be, as such and for whom, his analytic
discussion could not readily account for why certain popular movements
might emerge (or the forms they might take) without having to reintroduce
a self-contained, homogeneously defined economic notion of class. It is as
if, by posing this double entendre of science as both creativity and law,
Gramsci was able to take us to a precipice over which he himself could not
leap, namely, the entire rethinking of politics. But the leap he could not
make was the very terrain of what, in contemporary terms, has been labeled
"discourse theory" -that is to say, the very terrain of reanalyzing the mi-
croprocesses of how the political may be constructed; how meaning is es-
tablished, made permanent, or changed.
To put it slightly differently, Gramsci's concept ofthe philosophy
of praxis provides the necessary-but not sufficient-conditions for analyzing
and intervening in the processes of social construction. Unlike the work of
Foucault, Gramsci's framework cannot explain the movement of how, per-
haps even why, for example, societal norms became "medicalized" or even
how the advent of changing sexual attitudes resulted in the emergence of
various sexual categories and laws regulating their proliferation. Only in the
most general terms can Gramsci's nonreductionist notion of the political
account for the wide range of social movements that have been named
"liberation" movements-the women's movement, the black civil rights
movement, or even the gay movement.
This gap, as it were, in Gramsci's work should not blind us to
the importance of his insights, particularly for the contemporary debates
erupting on the left around notions of science, indeed, politics itself. By
arguing that the concept of the philosophy of praxis is itself the "science"
of the absolute historicized dialectic, Gramsci was able to begin to reem-
phasize and relocate all the various manifestations of the political. It be-
557
comes a complete denial of a dual reality, the complete historicization of
the rational and the real, the posing as "active" of the synthesis of their
unity, an activity that is nothing less than politics. And therewith comes
the complete recognition that it is people, and people alone, who possess
the ability to intervene in and change that process called history.
Notes
This is not to imply that censorship or, indeed, prison life itself did not take an exacting toll
on Gramsci's ab1lity to think, let alone write. But it is to suggest that some scholars writing
on Gramsci's Ouaderni have been somewhat sidetracked by the fact as well as the brutality
of his imprisonment. so that it becomes an explanatory feature of his code names for Lenin
[lllich] or Trotsky [Bronstein]; indeed, it becomes an explanatory feature in which unfamiliar
concepts are attributed as, at least in part, code names. See, for example, "General Intro-
duction,·· 1n Selections from the Prison Notebooks of Antonio Gramsci, trans. and ed. Quintin
Hoare and Geoffrey Noweii-Smith (New York: International Publishers, 1971). pp. xxi-xxv.
References to the official Italian edition, Quaderni del carcere: Edizone dell' lnstituto Gramsci,
ed. Valentino Gerrantana, 4 vols. (Torino: Einaudi, 1977). are by volume number (roman).
notebook (QC) number, section, page numbers, and cross-reference (cr.) or further citation
to the earlier or later versions by Gramsci himself.
2 The attempts to "uncover" the "real" Gramsci are scattered throughout the literature. The
well-known attempts to explain the Ouaderni as leninism par excellence are by the Italian
Communist Party (PCI). Less bold but equally sympathetic to the leninist interpretations are,
for example, Palmira Togliatti, On Gramsci and Other Writings, ed. Donald Sassoon (London:
Lawrence and Wishart, 1979); Christine Buci-Giucksmann, Gramsci and the State, trans.
David Fernbach (London: Lawrence and Wishart, 1975). In the backlash against official
translations of the PCI, and in part to recuperate the complex meaning obscured by those
translations, several articles appeared that replaced the various forms of leninism with various
forms of idealism. See, for example, Maurice A. Finachiaro, "Gramsci's Crocean Marxism,"
Telos. 41 ( 1979). pp. 7-32; Paul Piccone, "Gramsci's Hegelian-Marxism," Political Theory,
2:1 (1974), pp. 32-45.
3 Quaderni Ill, QC 13 [1 0]. p. 1569; Prison Notebooks, p. 137, for first quote; Ouaderni II,
QC 10 [40], pp. 1290-91; Prison Notebooks, pp. 367-68.
4 Gramsci argued in the philosophical fragments of the Ouaderni that the "answer" to the
question "What is man?" always carries with it historically constructed assumptions on the
nature of humankind. But the question for Gramsci was not "What is man?" Rather, the
question was "What can man become?" This implies a notion of potentiality and possibility,
not only for every individual, but for society as well-the "terrain" on which our "becoming"
is realized. In short, it implies a notion of politics that deals with the "art of the possible."
Although this point is central and will be elaborated further in the second part of this essay,
cf. Ouaderni II, QC 10 [54] and Prison Notebooks, pp. 351, 354-5 7.
5 "Cleanse" is precisely the word Gramsci used when referring to a resystematizing of idealist-
even transcendental and positivist-philosophy for use in a philosophy of praxis. Cf. Ouaderni
II, QC ii [301]. p. 1443 and Prison Notebooks, p. 466.
6 See, for example, Ouaderni II, OC, 7 [33]. "Posizone del problema," p. 881, and QC 11
[70]. "Antonio Labriola," pp. 1507-9; Ouadernilll, QC 16 [2]. "Ouistioni di metoda," pp.
1840-44; cr. Prison Notebooks, pp. 361, 386-88, 382-86, respectively.
7 Vico's most well known work, The New Science, went through several editions where major
changes occurred in the logic. The most profound break was the difference between his
1725 version and that of 1730 (later merely updated in 1744). For his earlier dualist for-
mulation dividing knowledge between that of "man" and that of God, see excerpts contained
in Vico, Selected Writings, ed. and trans. Leon Pompa (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press, 1982). pp. 81-158. His later formulations are collected from the ( 1744) third edition,
The New Science of Giambattista Vico, trans. Thomas G. Bergen and Max H. Fisch (New
York: Cornell University Press. 1948). hereafter referred to as The New Science (Ill). Cf.
Ouaderni II, QC 11 [54]. p. 1482; earlier version, QC 8 [199]. "Unita della teoria e della
practica," p. 1060; cr. Prison Notebooks, p. 364.
8 Croce, The Philosophy of Giambattista Vico, trans. R. G. Collingwood, (London: Howard
Latimer. 1913), pp. 2, 5.
9 Croce, pp. 32, 33-35; see also Alfonsina A. Grimaldi, The Universal Humanity of Giambattista
Vico (New York S. F. Vanni, 1958). pp. 247-53.
558
Sue Golding
10 It should be pointed out here. of course. that Gramsci was not strictly relying on Croce's (or
even Vico's) debat1ng pomts about sc1ence, a point I will clarify shortly. Suffice 11 to quote
Gramsc1 himself on his reference to Lenin (lllich) and Marx: "Statement of the problem:
Product1on of new Weltanschauugen to fertilize and nourish the culture of a historical epoch.
and philosophically directed production according to the original Weltanschauugen. Marx IS
the creator of a Weltanschauug. But what is lllich's position? Is it purely subordinate and
subaltern? The explanation is to be found in Marxism itself as both sc1ence and action. The
passage from utopia to science and from science to action. The foundation of a directive
class [classe dingente] (i.e. of a state) is equivalent to the creation of a Weltanschauung."
Prison Notebooks. p. 381; cr. Ouaderni II, OC 7 [33]. p. 881.
11 Although this point will be clarified directly, I refer the reader to Ouaderni II, OC 10 [48. 11].
pp. 1335-36, and OC 10 [40]. pp. 1290-91; cr. Prison Notebooks. pp. 35 7-58, 367-68,
for a general indication of the direction the argument will follow.
12 Cf. Ouaderni II, OC [6]. pp. 1244-45.
13 Ouaderni II, OC 11 [59]. p. 1486; cr. Prison Notebooks, p. 346.
14 Ouaderni Ill, OC 13 [1 0]. pp. 1568-69; cr. Prison Notebooks, p. 137.
15 The precise mean1ng of "immanence" as Gramsc1 used it will be developed more fully later.
But for the general outline of the argument. see "Immanence and the Philosophy of Praxis,"
Prison Notebooks, pp. 449-52. Cr. Ouaderni II, QC 11 [28]. pp. 1438-39; cf. OC 11 [24].
"lllinguaggio e le metafore," pp. 1426-28; OC 11 [22.1V], pp. 1424-26; cr. Prison Note-
books, "The Dialectic," pp. 434-36. For a brief reference to "d1stincts" (universal concepts
that hold their separate 1dentit1es when originally developed by Croce to refute Hegel's po-
sitioning around dialectical synthesis). see Ouaderni Ill, OC 13 [1 0]. pp. 1568-70; cr. Prison
Notebooks, pp. 137-38.
16 See in particular Quaderni II, OC 10 [48.11 L pp. 1335-38; cr. Prison Notebooks. "Progress
and Becoming," pp. 350-57. See also Gramsc1's "Che cosa e l'uomo?" QC 10 [54]. pp.
1343-46; cr. Pnson Notebooks, pp. 357-60.
17 A brief but concise statement can be found in Ouaderni II, OC 6 [135]. "Pasato e presente.
II fordismo," pp. 799-800.
18 This a complex point which draws on Croce's usage of "concordia discors" as well as on
the Theses on Feuerbach regarding pract1cal and theoretical act1vity and the1r dialectical un1ty.
It forms a basis upon which the notion of organic intellectual and ethical-political hegemony
can be further articulated. For an indication of the direction 1n which Gramsci developed it
in terms of "organic Intellectuals" and hegemony, see Ouaderni II, OC 11 [12]. nota 1, pp.
1385-87; cr. Prison Notebooks, pp. 334-35. For general comment on the theory praxis
nexus and its relation to science, see Ouaderm II, OC 8 [199]. p. 1060; updated version
OC 11 [54]. p. 1482; cr. Prison Notebooks. For Croce's development of "concordia discors"
in relation to pract1cal act1vity, cf. What Is Living and What Is Dead in the Philosophy of Hegel.
trans. Douglas Ainslie (London: Macmillan, 1915). pp. 15-17; and The Philosophy of Spint.
vol. 1: Aesthetic m Science of Express1on. trans. D. A1nslie (London: Macmillan, 1909). pp.
220-22
19 In general, this is a point clearly articulated and elaborated upon in the work of C. B. Mac-
pherson. For his well-known arguments regarding the specificity of the assumptions in theories
of liberalism, see The Theory of Possessive Individualism· From Hobbes to Locke (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1962). esp. "The Roots of Liberal-Democratic Theory," pp. 1-8,
and pp. 166-67, 192-93 regarding (in brief) the assumptiOns of Machiavelli.
20 For example, cf. Ouaderni Ill, OC 20 [4]. "Azione Cattolica, ecc.," pp. 2101-3; also cf.
Ouaderni I, QC 5 [141]. "Cattolici integrali, gesuiti, modernisti," p. 672.
21 Ouaderni 11, OC 10 [48.11]. p. 1338; cr. Prison Notebooks, "Progress and Becoming," p.
360.
22 This IS to point out the following: ( 1) that Gramsci argued for a conception of politics as
"practical activity," which he equated with "will" and deposited as the first moment or bas1s
of philosophy (e.g., cf. Quaderni II, OC II [59]. p. 1485; cr. Prison Notebooks, p. 345); (2)
that history/philosophy has not only its basis as political act1vity but activity produces "politics"
(e.g., QC 11 [12], nota 11-IV, pp. 1376-80; cr. Prison Notebooks, pp. 324-27; see also
Gramsci's arguments concerning the "realm of possibility" and "prediction" as political. in
Ouaderni II, OC 10 [48.11], p. 1338; cf. Pnson Notebooks, p. 36; and OC 11 [15]. pp.
1404-5; cf. Prison Notebooks, pp. 438-39); and (3) that the unity of philosophy-history
(included in the identity is also "economics") as that which is mediated (or "assured") by
politics. Th1s allowed Gramsci to argue later that not only is the "realm of necessity" and
the "realm of freedom" pol1t1cal-philosophical activity, but that the very passage from the
realm of necessity to the realm of freedom 1nvolves struggle, IS political. indeed, is the very
basis of ethical-political hegemony (see Ouaderni II, OC, p. 1383; cr. Prison Notebooks, p.
331; and OC 8 . Egemonia e democraz1a," p. 7056). See also Ouaderni II, OC 8 [195].
559
"La proposizone che 'Ia societa non si pone problemi per Ia cui soluzione non esistano gia
le premesse materiali.'" pp. 1057-58.
23 The term "specificity of the political" is taken directly from Laclau's intervention in the Pou-
lantzas-Miliband debates. See in particular "The Specificity of the Political.'' Politics and
Ideology in Marxist Theory: Capitalism-Fascism-Populism (london: New Left Books. 1977).
pp. 51-80.
24 Ouadernill, QC 11 [15). pp. 1403-6; QC 10 [48.11). pp. 1335-38; QC 11 [59). pp. 1485-
86; cr. Prison Notebooks. "The Concept of Science.'' "What Is Man." and '"Creative'
Philosophy,'' pp. 437-40, 357-60. 345-46.
25 See, in particular. Frederick Engels. "Socialism: Utopian and Scientific.'' MESW. val. 3, pp.
95-151. Aside from the familiar targets (DOhring. Owen. and. one could include among this
number. the nonsocialist Proudhon). Gramsci's arguments around science, political practice,
and the debates that ensued also engaged the work of Bornstein. Kautsky, Plekhanov. even
Loria, since these theorists represented, albeit in different ways, the interpretation of historical
materialism as reducible to an "economic science" (cf. Quaderni II, QC 10 [26). pp. 1264-
65; Ouaderni Ill, QC 15 [74]. pp. 1833-34; QC 17 [40). p. 1942; Letter #42 in Prison
Letters. p. 163 and its addendum note). But an additional point must be made concerning
Gramsci's attack on Plekhanov's Fundamental Principles of Marxism. Although the point
concerning Plakhanov's notion of science as that which is "pure" demands longer attention.
it raises an interesting point in the debates between scientific and utopian marxism: the
tendencies that fight against Plakhanov' s assumptions (notably in the work of Otto Bauer)
end by posing a utopian v1ew of science itself. That is to say, the debate no longer becomes
one between either/or po1nts but is moved onto the terrain of "science" as the value-free
rationalized attempt to construct a more democratic society. To some extent, but from equally
different assumptions, the work of Sorel and Bergson, even that of Gentile, tends to cling to
a notion of science that allows a reading of activity as that which ought to be more "scientific"
(read: rational/progressive). This po1nt will not be addressed here in greater detail given the
constra1nts of space, but since much of Gramsci's subsequent analysis drew on these various
posings of "science,'' it is important to give an initial indication of the variety of positions
that were produced in the debates on science and political practice. For an initial reference
to Gramsci's criticisms regarding, 1n particular. Plekhanov and the way in which he used the
work of Antonio Labriola to refute it, see Ouaderni II, OC 11 [70). pp. 1506-9; cr. Prison
Notebooks. pp 386-88.
26 Ouaderni II. OC 11 [50]. "Storia della terminologia e della metafore.'' pp. 1473-76; see
also QC 10 [27). "Punti di meditazione per lo studio dell'economia. A propos1to del cost
detto homo oeconomicus,'' p. 1265. In the Prison Notebooks, see, for example, p. 400,
n.39.
27 This is particularly in reference to A. Loria, who wrote, accordingly, "For if, as the new
apostles of force contend, the proletariat masses can at any moment annihilate the prevailing
economic order, why do they not rise against the capitalism they detest. and replace it with
the long cooperative commonwealth for which they long? Why is it that after so much noisy
organization, the utmost they are able to do is tear up a few yards of railway track or to
smash a street lamp? Do we not find here an irrefragable demonstration that force is not
realizable at any g1ven moment, but only in the historic hour when evolution shall have
prepared the inevitable fall of the dominant economic system?" In Karl Marx. trans. E. Paul
and C. Paul (London: George Allen and Unwin, 1920). pp. 88-89.
28 Karl Marx, The Poverty of Philosophy: Answer to the "Philosophy of Poverty" by M. Proudhon
(Moscow: Progress Publishers, 1975). particularly pp. 96-118.
29 D. Suvin, "On Two Notions of 'Science' in Marxism," in Brave New Universe. ed. Ron
Henighan (Ottawa: Tecumseh Press, 1980). pp. 27-43.
30 Popular Manual (Saggio popolare) was the abbreviated title used by Gramsci in the Ouaderni;
its full t1tle cited in the Prison Notebooks is Theory of Historical Materialism: A Popular Manual
of Marxist Sociology. The authorized English translation from the third Russian edition notes
the title as Historical Materialism: A System of Sociology (New York: Progress Publishers,
1925) All subsequent references will use Gramsci's annotated title.
31 Ouaderni II, QC 11 [31]. "La causa ultima," p. 1445; cr. Prison Notebooks, "On Meta-
physics,'' p. 437. See Ouaderni 11, QC 9 [59]. "Nozioni enciclopediche. Empirisimo.'' p.
1131, for an assault on "empiricism" as a category of truth. Criticizing Bukharin directly,
Gramsci wrote that h1s "vulgar contention is that science must absolutely mean 'system',
and consequently systems of all sorts are built up wh1ch have only the mechanical exteriority
of a system and not its necessary coherence" ("Science and System.'' in Prison Notebooks,
p. 434; cr. Ouaderni II, QC 11 [22.1V]. "Ouistioni generali.'' p. 1424)
32 Ouaderni II, QC 11 [17]. p. 1412; cr. Prison Notebooks, "The So-Called 'Reality of the
External World.'" pp. 441-42.
560
Sue Golding
33 Ouaderni II, OC 11 [14]. "Sulla Metafisica"; cr. Prison Notebooks, "On Metaphysics," p.
437. Clearly Gramsci was referring not only to Marx's Poverty of Philosophy but to the
"Theses on Feuerbach" as well.
34 Ouaderni II, OC 11 [14].
35 Ouaderni II, OC 11 [15]. pp. 1403-5; cr. Prison Notebooks, pp. 437-39.
36 Ouaderni II, OC 8 [176]. "La 'nuova' scienza," pp. 1047-48; see also OC 11 [36.111]. "La
scienza e le ideologie scientifiche," pp. 1451-55; cr. Antonio Gramsci, "Science and 'Sci-
entific' Ideologies," trans. Maurice A. Finocchiaro, Telos, 39(1979), pp. 151-55.
37 Ouaderni II, OC 10 [2]. "ldentita di storia e filosofia," pp. 1241-42. Gramsci stated that
while this cla1m seems similar to Croce's identity of philosophy and history, for the philosophy
of praxis it is "mutilated" if it does not also include the identity of history with politics and
therefore make that identity "also equal to the identity of politics and philosophy" (p. 1241).
He argued that this is what (in part) differentiated his claim of equivalences from that of
Croce. See also Quaderni I, QC 11 [12]. "Aicuni punti preliminari di riferimento," pp. 1375-
95; cr. Prison Notebooks, pp. 323-43.
38 Ouaderni II, QC 11 [52]. p. 1479; cr. Prison Notebooks, p. 412.
39 Marx. "Theses on Feuerbach," MESW, 1:1. p. 13.
40 "History and Anti-History," Prison Notebooks, p. 369; cr. OuaderniJJ, QC 10 [II 28.11]. p.
1266.
41 Useful meaning "practical" (as in "efficient"). See Prison Notebooks, p. 365; cr. Ouaderni
Ill, QC 15 [22]. "lntroduzione alia studio della filosofia," p. 1780.
42 Ouaderni II, QC 7 [35]. "Materialismo e materialismo storico," p. 886.
43 Ouaderni II, QC 11 [62]. pp. 1488-89; cr. Prison Notebooks, pp. 406-7.
44 Ouaderni II, OC 10[44]. "lntroduzione alia studio della filosofia," p. 1332; cr. Prison Note-
book, pp. 350-51. For the connection to the notion of "distincts" the reader is referred to
Ouaderni Ill, QC 13 [10]. pp. 1568-70; cr. Prison Notebooks, "Politics as an autonomous
science," pp. 136-38.
45 Ouaderni II. QC 10 [44]. p. 1332; cr. Prison Notebooks, p. 351.
46 OuaderniJJ, QC 11 [20]. "Oggettivita e realta del mondo esterno," p. 1420. The emphasis
on the unity of (and identity with) "the real and the rational" is not meant to bring Hegel
through the back door, as Gramsci wrote: "Without having understood this relationship [that
the "rational and real become one"] it seems that one cannot understand the philosophy
of prax1s, its position in comparison with idealism and with mechanical materialism. the
importance and significance of the doctrine of the superstructures. It is not exact, as Croce
maintains. to say that in the philosophy of praxis the Hegelian 'idea' has been replaced by
the 'concept' of structure. The Hegelian 'idea' has been resolved both in the structure and
in the superstructures and the whole way of conceiving philosophy has been 'historicized,'
that 1s to say, a whole new way of philosophizing which is more concrete and historical than
went before it has begun to come into existence" (cr. Prison Notebooks, p. 448). The concept
of "historic bloc" was developed in the work of Sorel. It suffices to note at this point Ouaderni
II. QC 8 [182]. pp. 1051-52; cr. Prison Notebooks, "Structure and Superstructure,'' pp.
365-66.
47 Prison Notebooks, pp. 350-51; cr. Ouaderni II, OC 10 [44]. p. 1332.
48 QuaderniJJJ, OC 15 (II) [10]. pp. 1765-66; Prison Notebooks, pp. 244-45, translation slightly
altered.
49 Ouaderni II, OC 7 [35]. pp. 883-86; OC 11 [14]. pp. 1401-3; QC 11 [15]. pp. 1403-6;
cr. Pnson Notebooks. pp. 354-57,436-37, 437-40.
50 Ouaderni 11, QC 10 [II] [9]. p. 1246; cr. Prison Notebooks, p. 399; see also Ouaderni Ill,
QC 16 [9]. p. 1855; cr. Prison Notebooks, p. 388.
51 Ouaderni II, QC 11 [27]. p. 1434; Prison Notebooks, "Concept of Orthodoxy,'' p. 463; see
also Ouaderni II, OC 11 [70]. pp. 1507-9.
52 Ouaderni II, QC 11 [17]. pp. 1415-16; cr. Prison Notebooks, p. 445.
53 The problem. or rather the importance, of error is one to which Gramsci continually referred.
Often he used it as a play on the idealist notion of "pure" knowledge or truth(s). He inflated
Croce· s own use of "error" or falsity in itself to argue. for example. that life can never be
only and totally "life" but must consist of both life and death. The same could be said of
Being (being and nothing constituting Being, etc.). Error in this sense comes to mean "spec-
ificity," even "history,'' where history is all life itself in all its "impure" activity. In that sense
the philosophy of praxis becomes precisely the "philosophy of act (praxis, development).
but not of the 'pure' act. but rather to the real 'impure' act. in the most profane and worldly
sense of the word" (Prison Notebooks, '"Objectivity' of Knowledge,'' p. 372; Ouaderni lA,
oc 11 [64]. p. 1492)
561
The use of "error" by Gramsci was also an attack on Gentile's attempts to
revise the Crocean "practical activity" as a "pure act" devoid of intellectual/theoretical ac-
tivity. Cf. Gentile, The Theory of Mind as Pure Act, trans. Wildon Carr (london: Macmillan,
1922); also cited in Pnson Notebooks, p. 372, n. 66. See also Ouaderni Ill, OC 13 [1 0],
pp. 1568-70; cr. Prison Notebooks, pp. 136-38.
54 "Preface to A Contribution to the Cntique of Political Economy," MESW, 502-3; cf. Quaderni
II, OC 10 (II) [12], pp. 1249-50; OC 11 [29], p. 1439; Ouaderni Ill, OC 13 [1 0], p. 1570;
cr. Pnson Notebooks, pp. 365, 458, 138.
55 Ouaderm II, OC 11 [17], p. 1415; OC 11 [20], pp. 1419-20; cr. Prison Notebooks, pp.
445, 447-48.
56 Ouaderni II, OC 11 [15], p. 1404; cr. Pnson Notebooks, 438.
57 See further Ouaderni II, OC 11 [52], p. 14 77; cr. Prison Notebooks, p. 410.
58 Ouaderni II, OC 11 [52], p. 1479; Prison Notebooks, p. 412.
59 Ouadernilll, OC 13 [1], pp. 1555-61; cf. Prison Notebooks, pp. 125-33; see also OC 11
[52], pp. 1480-81; cr. Prison Notebooks, pp. 413-14.
60 Although this pomt will be developed later, the reader is referred to Gramsci's arguments
on progress/development and "becoming," outlined in Ouaderni 11, OC 10 [48.11], pp.
1335-38; cr. Prison Notebooks, pp. 357-60.
61 Ouaderni II, OC 11 [301], pp. 1442-45; cr. Prison Notebooks, "Matter," pp. 465-68.
62 An argument developed in part of Gramsci's attack on the equating of history with "natural"
history. See, for example, Ouaderni I, OC 3 [33], "Aicune cause d'errore," pp. 310-11.
63 See also Ouaderni I, OC 4 [41], "La SCienza," pp. 466-67; cr. OC 11 [37], pp. 1455-56.
64 Gramsci writes, "It has been forgotten that in the case of a very common expression [historical
materialism] one should put the accent on the f1rst term-'historical' -and not on the second,
which is metaphysical in origin. The philosophy of prax1s is absolute 'historicism,' the absolute
secularisation and earthliness of thought, an absolute human1sm of history. It IS along this
line that one must trace the thread of the new conception of the world" (Prison Notebooks,
"Concept of Orthodoxy,'' p. 465; cr. Ouaderni II, OC 11 [27], p. 1437).
65 Cf. Ouadernill, OC 10 [14], pp. 1401-3; cr. Prison Notebooks, pp. 436-37.
66 Prison Notebooks, "Speculative Immanence and Historicist or Realist Immanence," pp. 399-
400; cr. Ouadernill, OC 10 II [9], pp. 1246-47.
67 "What the idealists call 'spint' is not a point of departure but a point of arrival; it is the
ensemble of the superstructures movmg towards concrete and objectively universal unification
and it is not a unitary presupposition" (Prison Notebooks, pp. 445-46; cr. Ouaderni II, OC
11 [17], p. 1416)
68 Ouadernill, QC 10 II [17], pp. 1255-56; cr. Prison Notebooks, pp. 344-45; see also Ouaderni
II, OC 11 [27], p. 1437; cr. Prison Notebooks, p. 465.
69 Cf. Gramsci's fragment on "matter,'' Ouaderni II, OC 11 [30], pp. 1442-45; cr. Prison
Notebooks, pp. 465-68.
70 Cf. Ouaderni II, OC 10 [54], "lntroduzione allo studio della filosofia. Che cosa e l'uomo?,"
pp. 1343-46; OC 7 [35], pp. 883-86. These fragments are two of the most powerful
developments by Gramsci of Marx's sixth thesis on Feuerbach. They present the argument
that not only is "man" a historical product, created by "man" himself, but it is "man" alone
who determmes "what we are and what we can become, whether we really are, and if so
to what extent, 'makers of our own selves,' of our own life and our destiny." Cr. Prison
Notebooks, pp. 351-5 7.
71 Prison Notebooks, p. 355; cr. Ouadernill, OC 7, [35] p 884 (altered slightly from the English
translation).
72 For a brief reference, cf. Ouaderni II, OC 11 [28], "L'immanenza e le f1losofia della praxis,''
pp 1438-39; OC 11 [24], "lllinguaggio e le metafore,'' pp. 1426-28; cr. Prison Notebooks,
"Immanence and the Philosophy of Praxis,'' pp. 449-52.
73 Cf. Ouaderni II, OC 11 [16], "QuistiOni di nomenclatura e di contenuto,'' p. 1411; cr. Prison
Notebooks, pp. 456-57.
74 Pnson Notebooks, "The Dialectic,'' p. 436; cr. Ouaderni II, OC 11 [22.1V], "Ouistioni ge-
neral!,'' p. 1424.
75 In his "Progresso e diven1re," Gram sci connected the concept of "progress" with becoming
and the concept of "freedom" with possibility (Prison Notebooks, p. 360; cr. Ouaderni II,
oc 10 (48.11], p. 1338)
562
Sue Golding
76 The first quoted passage is from Ouadernill, OC 10 [12]. pp. 1249-50; cr. Prison Notebooks,
pp. 365-66 (translation slightly modified). The second passage is from OC 8 [ 182]. "Struttura
e superstrutture," pp. 1051-52; cr. Prison Notebooks, p. 366.
77 Oaderni II, OC 10 II [6. 1L "II termine di 'catarsi.'" p. 1244; cr. Prison Notebooks, pp. 366-
67.
563
Richard Schacht
Notes
1 Louis Althusser. For Marx. trans. Ben Brewster (London: New Left Books, 1977), p. 235.
2 Althusser. p. 247.
3 Althusser. p. 232.
4 Bertell Oilman. Alienation: Marx's Conception of Man in Capitalist Society (Cambridge: Cam-
bridge University Press, 1971). p. 51.
5 Oilman. p. 44.
6 Oilman, p. 47.
7 Oilman, p. 47.
8 Oilman, p. 46.
9 Oilman, p. 48.
10 Robert C. Tucker, Philosophy and Myth in Karl Marx, 2d ed. (Cambridge: Cambridge University
Press. 1972). p 21.
11 Eugene Kamenka, Marxism and Ethics (New York: St. Martin's Press. 1969). p. 3.
12 Karl Marx, "Economic and Philosophical Manuscripts of 1844," The Marx-Engels Reader,
2d ed .. ed. Robert C. Tucker (New York: W. W. Norton. 1978). p. 85.
13 Marx. "The German Ideology," The Marx-Engels Reader, p. 154.
14 Marx. "The German Ideology," pp. 154-55.
15 Marx. "The German Ideology," p. 159.
16 Marx. "The German Ideology," p. 164.
17 Marx, "Manifesto of the Communist Party," The Marx-Engels Reader. p. 489.
18 Marx. "Manifesto of the Communist Party," p. 489.
19 Cf. Friedrich Nietzsche, On the Genealogy of Morals, trans. Walter Kaufmann and R. J.
Nottingdale (New York: Vintage, 1967). esp. the first and second essays; and G. W. F.
Hegel, Philosophy of Right. trans. T. M. Knox (Oxford: Clarendon Press. 1942). esp. the
preface and the third part. For an extended discussion of Nietzsche in this connection. see
Richard Schacht, Nietzsche (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1983). chap. 7. On Hegel,
see W. H. Walsh, Hegelian Ethics (London: Macmillan, 1969).
20 Cf. Alan Wood, Karl Marx (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul, 1981 ). chap. 10, "Morality
and Ideology."
21 Marx. "Contribution to the Critique of Hegel's Philosophy of Right." The Marx-Engels Reader.
p. 60.
22 Marx, "Theses on Feuerbach," The Marx-Engels Reader, p. 145.
23 Marx, "Manifesto," The Marx-Engels Reader. p. 500.
24 Marx. "Capital," vol. 3, The Marx-Engels Reader. p. 441.
25 Marx. speech delivered in Amsterdam. The Marx-Engels Reader.
26 Marx. "The German Ideology," The Marx-Engels Reader, p. 193.
27 Marx, "The German Ideology," p. 197.
28 Marx, "The German Ideology," p. 200.
29 Marx. "Manifesto," p. 491.
30 Marx, "Manuscripts of 1844," p. 84.
31 Marx, "On the Jewish Question." The Marx-Engels Reader, p. 43.
579
32 Marx, "On the Jewish Question," p. 46.
33 Marx, "Manuscnptsof 1844," p. 97.
34 Marx, crit1cal marg1nal notes on the article "The King of Prussia and Social Reform," The
Marx-Engels Reader, p. 131 .
35 Marx, "The German Ideology," p. 197.
36 Immanuel Kant. The Moral Law (Groundwork of the Metaphysic of Morals}, trans. H. J. Paton
(New York: Barnes and Noble, 1961). p. 96.
37 Kant, pp. 98ft.
38 Marx. "Manuscripts of 1844," pp. 83-84.
39 Marx, "Manuscripts of 1844," p. 105.
40 Marx, "Manuscripts of 1844," p. 85.
41 Friednch Engels, "Anti-Duhring," The Marx-Engels Reader, p. 727.
42 Cf. Marx, "Capital," The Marx-Engels Reader, p. 441.
43 Marx, "Manifesto," The Marx-Engels Reader, p. 491.
44 Cf. Adam Schaff, Marxism and the Human Individual, trans. Olgierd Wojlasiewicz, ed. Robert
S Alen (New York McGraw Hill, 1970); GaJo Petrovic, Marx in the Mid-Twentieth Century
(Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday Anchor, 1967); Leszek Kolakowski, Main Currents of Marxism:
The Founders, trans. P. S. Falla (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1978); also Richard Schacht,
AlienatiOn (Garden City, N.Y.: Doubleday Anchor, 1971).
45 Cf. Schacht, A!Jenatwn, esp. chap. 2.
46 Schacht, Alienation, chap. 7.
580
Armand Mattelart
Share of
Commercial Network in
Country Production• Market• Sales• GNP(%)
United States 668 ( 46%) 648 ( 45%) +20 3.5
Japan 228 ( 16%) 164 ( 11%) +64 3.7
Western Europe 379 ( 26%) 409 ( 28%) -30
West Germany 113 ( 8%) 113 ( 8%) 3.3
France 83 ( 6%) 82 ( 6%) - 1 3.0
Great Britain 74 ( 5%) 75 ( 5%) - 1 3.8
Othersb 175(12%) 229 ( 16%) -54
Worldb 1450 (100%) 1450 (100%)
•Figures are in millions offrancs; five francs = one dollar.
•Excluding COMECON and China.
Source: DIEHL-FIEE-FARNOUX Report.
the American journal Business Week (May 31, 1982) notes, draws its lessons
from the experience of rivals, especially Japan. With nationalization, public
companies now account for 49 percent of the network, while the private
French companies, including small and medium-sized outfits, represent 21
percent, and foreign groups 30 percent (13 percent for IBM and 7 percent
for Philips). The laboratories and national research centers are completely
public. Ninety percent of the research, study, and development of the elec-
tronics network is therefore under state control today.
One major aspect of this liberationary plan is a new scheme for
relations between private and nationalized industry, between industries of
the same sector (to avoid domestic rivalry), between local industry and
academe, and also between designers and users. The launching of flexible
national products proves that there is a commitment to ensuring the fluency
of the horizontal transfers of technology by bringing together teams of public
and private researchers, both industrial and user-oriented, in order to pro-
mote new products. All this serves to foreground the need to integrate no-
tions of industrialization and commercialization within the very conception
of a new product.
The Redistribution of Transnational Economy
This industrial plan implies that the siting of French companies
and their optimum markets should be reconsidered. Because of the size of
its market (half of the world, and ten times larger than that of France) and
its technological wealth, the United States is a priority site for the inter-
nationalization of French firms. Since the European market constitutes close
to a third of the world market, economic recovery by way of high technology
can only come about in a Europe that is technologically united. Hence the
need for a dynamic of alliances and cooperation to aid the development of
new products, especially those in the large public domain. On the other
hand, the potential for automating the process of production of electronics
products "favors the siting, or even the re-siting, of network production in
the most developed countries." 17
Surely there is enough here for us to acknowledge that any dis-
cussion of the relation between democracy and communications technology
588
Armand Mattelart
should involve an examination of the logic of redistribution in the inter-
national economy, a logic that appears to be inherent in the recovery model
offered by high technology. What are the long-term consequences of this
twofold movement of relocalizing-a strengthening of industrial ties with
the United States and a predictable falling-off of relations with the under-
developed countries-for the state of the north/south balance? Does the
structure of industrial alliances (which follows the lines of the Atlantic mil-
itary alliances) not reduce to a bare minimum the space for economic ne-
gotiation with the Third World? The attitudes ofthe Western powers in the
wake of recent world events (since the Falklands war, for example) tend to
prove that Europe as a whole still believes, perhaps wrongly, that the prin-
cipal contradictions are aligned on an eastjwest axis, whereas the third-
world countries think that they are already aligned, and each day increasingly
so, on a north/south axis, and that it is precisely the reorientation of the
east/west axis that is really at stake. The case is far from closed. The growing
commercial rivalry between the Common Market and the United States is
quite capable of causing another fracture in a bloc that is thought of as too
good to be true.
There is another question: What could be the impact of the in-
dustrial planning of several European countries on an independent French
industrial plan that did not tally with their individual ideas about what
constitutes a national plan for reindustrialization? The rapid growth of neo-
liberal economic models in countries like Great Britain has pushed it to the
European forefront. Is such a model of development based on the trans-
national logic not likely to interfere with the unfolding of a national strategy
aimed, across numerous contradictions, at circumventing the Japanese and
American empires? The rapidity with which the new communication tech-
nologies can be installed (Great Britain will be the first in Europe, for ex-
ample, to have a private telecommunications system run on optical fibers,
in direct competition with the nationalized network) should warrant further
reflection upon the new deals that determine the concrete structure for form-
ing and shaping technical advances in Europe. One sign, among others, of
the leading role played by Great Britain is in its transborder data flows: 66
percent of all data flows from Western Europe to the United States come
out of Great Britain. Transatlantic data flows, in fact, account for two-thirds
of the transborder data flows of that country, against an average of 10 percent
for all the other Western European countries. 18
Moreover, in 1977-78 the large electronics firms chose as their
priority target for launching the home video recorders in Europe, Great
Britain and then West Germany. Several reasons, insufficiently analyzed in
my opinion, led them to act in this way. These reasons drew as much on
the patterns and modalities of audiovisual consumption (the importance,
for example, of a network of sited installations in Great Britain compared
to the French equivalent) as on the structure of the industry of televisual
production (in the two chosen countries, an extremely disparate national
industry that fell further apart when the video recorder arrived); reasons
that were similarly related to the nature of the televisual system in each of
these countries. In short, to be able to describe the factors that have had
some bearing upon the case of the video recorder, we would need access to
a comparative history, which scarcely exists, ofthe communications systems
of Europe; a history that ought to help explain why Great Britain has out-
589
stripped the rest of Europe in introducing audiovisual technology ever since
the advent of the radio. A comparative study of this kind would be obligatory
for anyone who wants to answer this essential question: Why in 1962 did
France have one of the smallest television audiences in Europe?-27 percent
of all French homes had a television aerial against 29 percent in Italy, 37
percent in Belgium, 41 percent in Germany, 50 percent in the Netherlands,
and 82 percent in Great Britain. Another question should be addressed in
the same way: Why is there such a disparity today among the European
countries in the ownership of video recorders?-in 1982, 2.5 percent of
French homes against 10 percent in British homes. Unless we rest easy with
a unilateral, mechanistic response that would be a throwback to an analysis
of income range, a much more complex study must be taken up.
Some Poles of Cultural Production?
In one way or another, certain problematic features of French
planning regarding what are called the "hardware industries" appear again
in their own specific way when it comes to drawing up plans for the "software
industries." This is unavoidable, since the latter are equally bound up within
a similar kind of unifying movement. This movement no longer must be
proved, either in the field of information merchandising, where the logic of
the interdependent chain of electronics services works toward integrating
the various participants (gatherers-producers-carriers), or in the leisure field,
which is often confused with the former (multimedia conglomerates, etc.).
The factors involved in programming, software, and network planning are
at once economic, industrial, social, and cultural.
Although it is relatively easy to sketch the outlines of a plan for
developing the electronics technologies-even if they are only in an embry-
onic phase-it is much more difficult to isolate the features of a correspond-
ing plan for cultural production.
It is clear that this problem arises out of the need to name various
partners in order to provoke a national response in the face of the hegemony
of transnational productions (television series, video games, videocassettes,
etc.). The real differences emerge, however, when those partners have to be
identified. Listen to the director in charge of new projects at Hachette, the
fifth largest publishing company in the world:
Because of its position, Hachette has been among the
first to be implicated in a process of change that in-
volves all the participants in the cultural sector. The
handicaps of French audiovisual production and dis-
tribution, compared to that ofthe U.S., are such that
the challenge is posed not so much in terms of the
competition between French publishers or producers,
as in terms of their solidarity and complementarity.
This is one of the active issues which we are address-
ing. With a view to establishing the bases of a politics
of publishing in this area (particularly its legal aspects),
we hope that an allied commitment on the part of the
principal French groups in audiovisual production can
be developed and extended to other groups, and other
publishers. 19
590
Armand Mattelart
However, the obstacles in the path of effectively building up this
understanding between different publishers or producers are much more
complex in the case of electronics. There is no evidence of any kind of
understanding between a public sector heavily involved in audiovisuals and
the big private groups. Not only do these private groups have a very limited
experience of televisual production because of public sector domination,
but, more to the point, their relations with the state are often at loggerheads.
There are quite definite reasons for this, and I will come back to them,
reasons suggested here by A. Lefebure, the director for the development of
new technologies at Havas, the large, partially state-controlled multimedia
group:
Everything which is not in the public sector suffers in
France from a real lack of symbolic legitimacy wher-
ever audiovisuals are involved. So it is no surprise
that negotiations between the State and private enter-
prise, or even a mixed economy, are so fraught with
conflict when it comes to managing audiovisual affairs.
Since they are accused of only being interested in com-
mercial growth inasmuch as it is linked to a market
logic (a familiar danger in itself in this domain), the
French communications groups are unable to declare
their real ambitions. The field is therefore left open
for other transnational groups to establish their pub-
lishing interests before going on to tackle the audio-
visual market by using processes of deregulation that
are becoming so familiar in a number of countries in
Europe. 20
According to the same Havas executive, who is clearly speaking
in a personal capacity, the search for a new legitimacy in the affairs of
audiovisual broadcasting outside of the public sector "can only take place
through a reasoned and voluntary act of support for the creative opportun-
ities that exist in France in this field." This kind of diagnosis points toward
the constitution of a new socioindustrial substructure; it advocates relying
on some ofthe complementary poles of creation and production (Hachette,
Havas, Sofirad, local radio and public television networks) to promote growth
capable of competing closely for international audiences and using these
poles to create new relations between multiple partners. 21
A. Lefebure points to some of the other groups with a potential
to be involved: "For well-known reasons, there are many difficulties in-
volved in the development of small, ambitious, and innovative audiovisual
structures. There is no shortage of designers, journalists eager to shape the
future of the press, technicians capable of important innovations (software,
high frequency systems, hi-fi, video), all of them hoping for a chance to
realize their potential. Clearly it is up to the State, along with the big com-
panies in the field, to give this kind of initiative a chance, since it is likely
to bring commercial success, and will also be a privileged way of winning
legitimacy in the public mind, all too easily impressed by events in this
domain. " 22
Similar proposals ventured on behalf of the television channels
point in the same direction, and thanks to new rulings on audiovisuals, they
591
are hoping to find other partners: "I also hope," declared the programming
head of Channel One (TFl ), "with the help of various partners, to be able
to create an offshoot committed to producing alternatives and thus increas-
ing our audience potential. The channel should make its presence felt in all
ofthe markets of audiovisual creation (teledistribution, video-cassettes, etc.)
through direct contact with the manufacturers. " 23
The future of this set of alliances (big/small, national/local, cen-
tral/provincial apparatus, private/public, commercial/associated sector) will
be crucial, since it will determine the form of power relations between part-
ners of unequal strength who do not necessarily have the same idea of
national independence, let alone the same idea of democracy as it applies
to the field!
The State in All of Its States
Poor state! So much is asked of it and in the form of demands
that are difficult to reconcile: it is required not only to set itself up as an
arbiter, by coming to the rescue of the big shots, so to speak, the large
companies in a bad way, but also to concern itself with the whole base of
the pyramid, all of the small-fry responsible for winning credibility for the
new solidarity. Perhaps the time has come to question the function of the
state, for that is precisely where we shall find the essentials regarding the
relation between technology, communication, and democracy.
For those who cared, the socialist victory in many ways repre-
sented an opportunity to deliver France from the logics at work in the
majority of the large advanced capitalist countries. To work its transfor-
mation into the whole restructuring of the world economy, a socialist France
would bracket off those fundamental movements that continue to affect its
neighbors or its partners. For example, it would not have to face up to those
painful questions that plague neo-liberals in England and the United States
as part of their obligation to take on the role of "thinkers of the state."
France would be concerned only with those logics of privatization that paved
the way for a welfare state, given its second wind under the socialist plan.
A simple electoral victory has not put an end to these logics; for
those who believe it has, nothing could be further from the truth. These
logics continue to shape French society, using the appropriate channels to
reintroduce familiar problematics.
1. In the field of communications, there are numerous signs that
the redistribution of modes of administrating the public/private relation
was stepped up during the late seventies. To make up for its loss of legit-
imacy, the state, and its administrative logics, sought the kind of support
provided by procedures at work in the private sector. By contrast, the private
sector was rethinking the "social" and thus taking up where the state had
left off. To check the crisis of the state, which is also the crisis of an image,
management was called upon to provide the state with a means of ration-
alizing itself, a way of avoiding wasteful expenditure, while marketing tech-
niques were recruited to cater to other areas of public relations. As a result,
we experienced the explosion of "public communication." The total state
expenditure for advertising space in the media rose from 39.7 million francs
in 1977 to 62.3 million in 1979, of which half was borne solely by the
Ministry of Labor and Industrial Relations. In comparing these figures we
must take into account the lowering of tariffs granted to campaigns certified
592
Armand Mattelart
as being in the public interest (for television time, the administrations only
paid a quarter of the commercial rate.) This sum would thus correspond to
a budget of 128 million francs, a figure much closer to that of the two or
three biggest private advertisers: L'Oreal, Colgate-Palmolive, or Unilever. 24
The second clear evidence was the telematics campaign, sched-
uled to take off in 1976. With the general head of telecommunications at
the Ministry of PTT as its director, this campaign clearly represented a
major intervention in state administration at the level of managerial plan-
ning. The commercial logic that accompanied the promotion of the new
technologies had made its effects felt as much in the advance of the domestic
market as in the fundamental movements of the international markets (es-
pecially in the large Latin American countries). As there has been very little
analysis of the transformation of state practices from this point of view, it
is difficult to properly place the malfunctions and asynchronies that are
unfailingly produced within one section of the state apparatus-in this case,
the Ministry ofPTT-by the modernization of some of its branches. It would
be incorrect to think that what is rightfully the process of commodifYing
administrative action infiltrates the state apparatus in a uniform fashion.
Resistances of every sort crop up (from those that spring up in the defense
of public service to those that prevail in professional or institutional cor-
poratism, not to mention the terra incognita of users) and frequently give
rise to conflict and dislocation.
Another example of change in the management of the public/
private relation is what seemed to be the first large move in France to bring
together a hardware producer (the electronics firm Matra) and a producer
of programs (Hachette). We cannot, however, fully appreciate this merger
at the end of 1980 without knowing about the subtle pressures that were
involved as a result of a spontaneous act on the part of the government of
Giscard d'Estaing in its anxiety to redefine the alliance between the state
and the large multimedia groups as the new technologies were being ushered
in.
Finally, and on a more global level, the ideological debate around
the role of the intellectuals (and their relation with the media) has also, in
its own way, provided evidence of an epistemological rupture. As part of
the transitory epiphenomenon of the "new philosphers," and their inse-
parability from a media image, a new mode of disseminating (and thus of
producing) knowledge made its appearance just as the law of value was
stepping up its influence on the intellectual scene. Aside from rumors, this
was the first concrete sign of the necessary redefinition of relations between
the petit bourgeoisie, the bureaucrats of knowledge (whose diversity has not
been examined closely enough because our concept of them-an all too
quickly hallowed concept-was narrow and ill-adapted to the new historical
conditions of the intellectual), the state apparatus, and the logic of the mar-
ket.2s
2. Similarly, in the late seventies the legitimacy of the state was
put to the test by other forces in a shake-up not only of relations between
the state and civil society but also of the different modes of action of various
elements of civil society. The forms of state legitimacy are crumbling fast,
from the center outward. The defense of decentralization has become an
issue marked by social confrontations and, consequently, much ambiguity.
In "decentralizing" themselves, some sectors hoped to find new forms of
593
legitimizing the center by working from the edges; others saw this return to
the local as a special way of broadening the dimensions of democracy in
the sense of real power sharing. Any number of struggles, not to mention
fantasies, about the democractic virtues per se of the whole structure of
decentralization, revolve around this issue of the "local." 26 One very rele-
vant example in this context is the "free-radio" movement and its equivalent
in the movements for reclaiming alternative forms of expression, less well
advertised because they do not involve the new technology.
In the face of this interrogation of the workings of civil society,
a monolithic and manipulatory conception of the state collapses. The state
is no longer perceived as a site for the endless reproduction of power but
as the site of the production of power: a site marked by power relations
between groups, classes, and social projects, where the affirmation of a he-
gemony coexists with strategies of evasion and deviation. Also on trial in
this inquiry are our ways of conceiving party action and its relation to party
militants.
The Private/Public Relation
What is the state of the fundamental movements under the so-
cialist government? The tendency to entrust the advertising sector with large
public interest campaigns has been borne out, for example, in the first cam-
paign to promote reading. In addition to short broadcasts entitled "Reading:
the Roads to Freedom," programed over two months of television time,
the campaign has been pursued through posters in bookshops. The cost of
backing these campaigns has increased considerably: in 1982 it rose to an
estimated 150-160 million francs, compared to 62 million in 1979. There
is every reason to ask, as Bernard Miege does, whether "public commu-
nications lends itself to the process of manipulating public opinion, a process
all the more dangerous inasmuch as it takes the place of democratic channels
of debate." 27 Perhaps in the course of asking too much of marketing, one
forgets to expect civil society to provide the requisite ethic for instilling in
each citizen a degree of conscientiousness about such issues as reading,
contraception, solidarity, and so on. As it is, the marketability of a technique
(in this case, for the launching of a supposedly social product) seems to
have already been established prior to any serious questioning of the vertical
forms of social relation that it perpetuates. This is one more item to be
added to the catalog of technical perversions.
The debate about the state and the public/private relation in the
field of communication is, however, more complicated now than it was
before May 1981. The statements from Hachette and, in particular, from
Havas seem to suggest this much. And for those faced everyday with the
more concrete search for democratic alternatives, the ways of living out the
public/private relation have become less straightforward. One thing at least
can never be overstated: there exists in France a true "public culture," lived
as a legitimate culture of excellence within certain sectors, especially those
whose upward mobility depends on the statist or parastatist apparatus. This
culture, which has its repressed underside-a genuine repugnance for the
private-is no mean obstacle to the rethinking of the alliance of science,
research, and industry as it was formulated by the national colloquium-
all the more so since it is constructed on a paradox. Because of this "public
culture," the relation to the state is lived on a sadomasochistic level. We
594
Armand Mattelart
expect the state to act as protector and arbiter, and then we rush to accuse
it of conditioning with a venom that matches our level of indebtedness. In
the domain of symbolic production, the chances of any critical discussion
of the question of a rapprochement between public and private are even
rarer, for this "public culture" is curiously distinguished by its hyper-in-
dividualized and aestheticized idea of creation-manifest in some as a con-
stitutional mistrust of anything that could give rise to an industrially re-
producible matrix. It is not easy, moreover, to decide between the positive
and negative sides of this show of reticence, no more so in the case of the
actual process of internationalizing the culture industries than in the de-
ployment of mechanisms of resistance to the normalization of ways ofliving,
thinking, and creating.
That some of the large multimedia groups have made tacit de-
mands on the question of official political support testifies clearly to de-
velopments in relations between the state and private enterprise. This only
makes sense, however, if we see it in the much larger context of a change
in relations between private enterprise and the whole of society, and es-
pecially in the domain that interests us, with its vital resources of social
creativity and innovation. So how do we interpret the "open letter to the
innovators" from Matra-Hachette, published on one whole page of Le Monde
on February 17, 1982, and addressed to "all innovators, designers of hard-
ware and software in each sector: personal computers, video games, business
organization, office equipment, telecommunications, or scientific instru-
ments"? The letter continues:
Notes
1 J. P. Chevenement (minister for research and technology), in Le Monde. Sept 23. 1981.
p.1
2 Ministry for Research and Technology, Recherches et technologie. Actes du colloque na-
tional. 13-16 janvier 1982 (Paris: La Documentation Franc;:aise. 1982). p. 7.
3 Recherches et technologie. p. 7.
4 "Annexe 1: Note d'orientation." Recherches et technologie. p. 41.
5 MOINOT Report. published by La Documentation Franc;:aise. 1982.
6 See F. Guattari, "Note concernant un projet de fondation pour les initiatives locales, les
innovations 1nstitutionelles. Ia recherche en science sociale, !'animation et Ia creation cul-
turelles ... Paris. Feb. 1982, mss. In the same spirit of incorporating local collectives, as-
sociations. and unions within this "research action ... see the interview with Philippe Barret
(representative for the social sciences at the Ministry for Research and Technology). "Les
sciences de l'homme et de Ia societe.'' Revue NON! (Reperes pourle socialisme). 12 ( 1982).
pp. 114-22.
7 On this po1nt. see my A. Mattelart. Mass Media, Ideologies and the Revolutionary Movement
(Atlantic Highlands. N.J.: Humanities Press. 1980).
8 Mitterand. in Recherches et technologie. p. 15.
9 Technologie. emploi. et croissance (report by President Mitterand at the summit meeting of
the industrial powers). Versailles. June 5. 1982. See Le Monde. June 6-7. 1982.
10 Recherches et technologie. p. 39.
11 J. P. Chevenement. in Temoignage chretien, Paris. June 14-20, 1982.
12 Mission Filiere Electronique. In French. the term fi/Jere electronique has recently begun to be
used for all eleven sectors of industrial electronics production: components. products for the
general public. computers. automated office equipment. software and data banks. robotics.
medical electronics. sc1entlfic instruments. telecommunications. professional electronics (civil
and miltary). space technology.
13 Ministry for Research and Technology, Extraits du rapport de synthese de Ia mission filiere
electronique. Paris. mimeo. Mar. 1982. annexe 7. p. 3.
14 Extraits. annexe 5. p. 12.
15 Extraits. annexe 4. pp. 7-8.
16 Extraits. annexe 4. pp. 7-8.
17 Extraits. annexe 5. p. 12. Let us recall some of the aims of the manifesto for technological
growth advanced by F. Mitterand at the Versailles summit: "Priority action for technological
co-operation between pnvate and public companies. and between nations ... ; the pro-
gressive creation of a world market for technology (standards. patents); a joint initiative to
604
Armand Mattelart
assure that the Southern nations master the new technologies." See Technologie, emploi,
et cro1ssance.
18 Un1ted Nations, Transnational Corporations and Transborder Data Flows: A Technical Paper
{New York: U.N. Center on Transnational Corporations, 1982)
19 In Livres-Hebdo, Paris, Sept: 22, 1981.
20 A. Lefebure, "Mass media, groupes de communication et societe," a personal contribution
to the commission on "Technologie, diffus1on de Ia culture et communication," June 1982.
21 Here are some figures to help gauge the internationalization of the French culture industnes.
In 1980, the sale of French films abroad was only a tenth of book sales and a half of the
number of records sold. The sale of television programs itself was only one-fifth of film sales,
and the foreign television market represented almost a third of that purchased from abroad.
In additiOn, exports for the publishing industry for the same year were less than 20 percent
of its turnover and were concentrated on the Francophone countries, which accounted for
80 percent of this export flow {see J. Rigaud, Les relations culturelles exterieures, [Pans: La
Documentation Fran<;:aise, 1980]). In 1980, the French television network {TF1, A2, FR3,
INA-commercial sale, SFP-Ioss of franchise) had foreign sales of 5,596 program-hours,
against 1 ,567 in 1978. Also in 1980, 6,000 program-hours were del1vered as part of cultural
aid to twenty-nine countnes, fifteen of which were 1n North Afnca (3,500 hours) and the
rest to Mahgreb, Haiti, and several Arabophone and Anglophone nations. The number of
coproductions in 1980 rose to 94 hours for TF 1 and 36 hours for A2 (for the period 1979-
80, an estimated 60 hours were coproduced for FR3). Otherwise, the coproducers were
still the traditional partners {Francophones and RFA). with the exception of FR3 {Japan,
Mexico) {figures taken from a report by the study group "Action internationals" on the
MOINOT Commission, August, 1981)
22 A Lefebure, "Mass media, groupes de communication et societe."
23 Interview with Andre Harris, "Le deficit de 1'1mag1nat10n," Le Monde, May 27, 1982.
24 On the crisis of the image of the state, see the several contributions to the colloquium ''Where
Is PubliC Management Go1ng?" (May 28-30, 1980). organized by the University of Paris-
Dauphine and the Center for H1gher Education in Business Studies (CESA). especially those
by J. Lendrevie and R. Laufer. Also see J. L. Albert et al, Production de Ia ville et amen-
agement du discours, Grenoble Ill, GRESEC, Jan. 1980, mimeo.
25 See Regis Debray, Teachers, Wnters, Celebrit1es. The Intellectuals of Modern France {lon-
don: New Left Books, 1982); F. Aubral and X. Delcourt, Contre Ia nouvelle philosophie {Pans:
Galhmard, 1977).
26 See L 'objet local: colloque dirige par Lucien Sfez {Paris: collection 10/18, 1977)
27 B. M1ege, "Le pouvoir et les systemes d'information: S'interroger sur les enjeux fondamen-
taux," paper delivered at the Third French Congress on Communication and Information
Sc1ences, May 1982, mimeo.
28 A. Mattelart, " Introduction," Communication and Class Struggle {New York: International
General, 1983), val 2, pp. 17-67.
29 Interview with Andre Harris, Le Monde, May 27, 1982.
30 One can think what one wants about programs like "Ulysses 31" as models of television
for children, but the history of its production is, from an industrial point of view, quite in-
structive. Conceived by a Frenchman, the series was not taken up in France, and after many
ups and downs, like the majority of animated cartoon senes, was produced in Japan thanks
to a coproduction agreement. The study group on the politiCS of the image set up by the
pnme minister has noted that in th1s case, as in many others, all of the necessary elements
for 1ts production were there, albe1t scattered throughout university laboratories and the
electronics industry, but the "honzontal" relation between technology and individual talent
was sadly lacking. Conv1nced, then, that the state should not itself create an animated cartoon
Industry but only develop the conditions for it to expand and flourish, the director for children's
broadcasts at TF1 wrote: "We have thousands of professionals with the talent and the
capacity to properly establish animated French cartoons in the world of modern television,
if only they were salvaged from their working isolation, encouraged and supported by man-
agement with experience in the affairs of the new industry, and above all, if their own en-
thusiasm were rewarded by concrete measures." (J. Mousseau, "Piaidoyer pour une in-
dustrie fran<;:aise du dessin amme," Communication et langages, no. 52 [1982])
31 "Commission no. 1. L'apport culture! de Ia recherche scient1fique et technologique" {re-
porter: Robert Fossaert). Recherches et technologie, pp. 92-93.
32 Letter from J. P Chevenement to the presidents of the commission on "Technologie, diffusion
de Ia culture et communication" {A. Mattelart andY. Stourdze), Mar. 1982, in Technologie,
communication et culture (Pans La Documentation Fran<;:aise, 1982).
605
33 F. Guattari, "Note," pp. 114-22.
34 M. J. Carrieu-Costa and M. Calion, Pro}et d'un centre de recherche et de formation sur les
mnovations technologiques et sociales. Mar. 1982. mimeo.
35 See. for example, the dossier "Pour un autre television," NON! (reperes pour le socialisme)
( 1982). w1th contributions from A. Sp1re and D. Goldschmidt; Y. de La Haye and 8. Miege,
"Les socialistes fran9ais aux prises avec Ia question des media," Raison presente, Paris,
Winter 1982; P. Flichy, "Pour une politique de !'innovation sociale en audiovisual," Le monde
diplomatique, May 1982.
36 President Mitterand, Versailles summit.
37 See C. Collin, "Villeneuve; de Ia videogazette au centre de ressources," Sonovision (1978).
The Italian experiment with free radio and television deserves a special mention here, not so
much in itself, but inasmuch as it fosters a number of myths sustained by the enemies of
the democratization of communication. How many times here in France have we seen those
who support restricted democracy in the media block a whole discussion by invoking the
situation in Italy as one characterized by audiovisual "anarchy."
38 The study group for social experimentation on the MOINOT Commission noted quite correctly,
in July/August 1981, that it was possible to adopt two different experimental approaches:
"The first. beginning with the technological system, involves the desire to test and observe
the way in which an environment adopts, rejects, or transforms the system. If 1t is necessary
for an organism vital to the future of communications to keep itself informed about these
experiments, even to be in some way associated or intimate with their ways, then we should
ask ourselves how the question could be turned around in order to accommodate different
forms of experimentation; instead of starting with technique and then examining its applic-
ability, starting with innovative social practices and then examining what kind of technical
response can be brought to the material needs of communication. New means can certainly
be utilized but only inasmuch as they would appear to respond better than the current media,
and eventually, in conJunction with these media, to the needs articulated by the users. Such
expenments could be carried out by using the existing networks and would not have to wait
for the installation of new ones."
39 J. C. Passeron, Images en bibliotheque. images de bibliotheque (Paris: Documents du Gides,
1982), pp. 46-47.
40 On the "local" question, see A. Mattelart and J. M. Piemme, Television: Enjeux sans fron-
tieres (Presses universitaires de Grenoble, 1980); in English by the same authors, see "New
Means of Communication: New Questions for the Left," Media, Culture, and Society, no. 2
a
(1980). pp. 321-38; J.P. Garnier, "De Ia crise d'une gestion Ia gestion d'une crise ou le
charme discret de Ia decentralisation," Cahiers Secteur Public (Paris, 1982).
41 This is where some reflection on experiments like that of the ANTELIM network, which has
steadily established radio links between the families of sailors, might provide ballast for the
boundless enthusiasm for local radio that has been officially Inspired by the plan for decen-
tralizing the public monopoly of radio-television.
606
lain Chambers
Notes
Luigi Russolo, L'arte dei rumori (Milan: Edizioni Futuriste di "Poesia," 1916). Republished
as a supplement in Alfabeta. no. 43, Milan. Dec. 1982.
2 Walter Benjamin, "The Work of Art in the Age of Mechanical Reproduction," Illuminations.
trans. Harry Zohn (london: Fontana. 1973). All references to the essay are to this edition.
3 lain Chambers, Urban Rhythms (London: Macmillan, 1984), p. 14.
4 Peter Wollen. Readings and Writings (London: Verso. 1982). p. 176. It is worthwhile recalling
a note of Benjamin's on the relation between film and technology: "In the case of films.
mechanical reproduction is not. as with literature and painting. an external condition for mass
distribution. Mechanical reproduction is inherent in the very technique of film production.
This technique not only permits in the most direct way but virtually causes mass distnbution"
(Benjamin, p. 246) The same can be said for the contemporary production of pop music.
5 The context of this quotation is, "The subsequent industrialisation of camera technology only
carried out a promise inherent in photography from its very beginnings: to democratise all
experiences by translating them into images" (Susan Sontag, On Photography [Harmond-
sworth: Penguin, 1979]. p. 7). The history of recorded music. where we all have the possibility
of indulging our tastes and becoming "experts," leads toward similar conclusions.
6 Benjamin, p. 242.
7 Chambers. p. 210.
8 Richard Hoggart. The Uses of Literacy (Harmondsworth: Penguin, 1958). p. 81.
611
Discussion
Comment (Dick Hebdige)
In your paper I hear a displaced, fragmented, overdeter-
mined discourse, a discourse undermined by libido. I hear description in the sense
of de-scription, a talking out. I hear logic escaping, limits acknowledged, transgressed,
and reinscribed.
Chambers
Perhaps the best way to begin responding to your suggestive
metaphors is to lay out what I see as some of the premises of my work. The closer
we move to the different experiences of pop music and popular culture, the more
we are forced to acknowledge certain limits. There is a limit in being English and
white and writing about black music; there is a limit to what I can say about a
female experience of rock music. This is not necessarily an impoverishment. The
recognition of limits is also the recognition of differences, of heterogeneity: the rec-
ognition of voices that were previously unheard, unacknowledged. As you have put
it: "a reflexive awareness of the knowledge/power relation." The presence of these
voices, these relations, these possibilities, these powers, registers a series of tensions
that have to be worked into a "sense" where previously there was silence.
Taking urban culture as my referent and mechanical repro-
duction as its privileged mode of cultural production, I have tried to provide a
framework-which extends well beyond the physical environs of the actual city-in
which the presence and specificity of popular musics and cultures could be discussed.
Obviously, details were overlooked, there were many gaps, but I would like to think
that the outline of a suggestive project managed to come through.
Comment
Rock has been defined as a blanket modality that rips off,
incorporates, and cannibalizes many other styles, the styles of other cultures. One
of the things it does is to eliminate many of the differences that have been socially
constructed in those other cultures. Perhaps one of the reasons why some of the
Latin music, specifically Salsa, which is also a global style, hasn't had a major impact
on rock is because there is little awareness that 25 million Latino people live in the
United States. I would argue that rock, as a phenomenon created in the metropolitan
centers of the world-the United States, England-has a function of eliminating
difference and inscribing indifference imperialistically throughout the world.
Chambers
Let me take the example of Hispanic culture in the United
States, of Latin musics in the context of U.S. rock music. This gives me an oppor-
tunity to say something more about the idea that the details and differences of
particular cultures, musics, and minority tastes come to be systematically cancelled
in the logic of present-day urban culture, come, to use an expression, to be "co-
opted." The argument runs like this: subaltern cultures, alternative and oppositional
forces, are progressively sucked into the hungry urban machine where, their original
powers and identities now nullified, they are reproduced among the vacuous choices
of metropolitan taste.
It's neat, but beyond its linear simplicity and a suspect ro-
manticism-the "corruption" of"origins," the corruption of the city-it reduces cul-
tural differences to a series of simple antagonisms: "non-co-opted"/"co-opted,"
"original"/"false." As Ernesto Laclau pointed out, it is a form of reasoning that is
forced to treat "meaning" as fixed; "society" as a stable, conceptual "totality"; and
"power" as the exercise of a unilateral, direct domination. Naturally, the co-optation
thesis can acquire a flexible tone; I wouldn't deny that. But the way it is generally
used does suggest that an underlying conceptual rigidity prevents it from acknowl-
edging the real complexity that can be recognized in the cities, in the sights, sounds,
and sense of popular urban culture.
612
lain Chambers
Question
I want to build on the last question and redirect it to ques-
tions about gender, sexuality, and the body. In Latino culture, for example, one
immediately notices a concern about the body and what it signifies. Indeed, I think
cultural differences involve kinesic differences, including styles of dance and move-
ment. Moreover, on the issue of the body, I thought it strange that disco was not
mentioned. One of my students argued that in rock music the body that is being
expressed and activated has to do with genitality, but in disco the heartbeat is at
the center. In any case, the materiality of the body in its modalities in rock 'n' roll
does create different significations. Finally, I wonder if we don't have to examine
the ways the body in rock 'n' roll works in a gender-specific manner.
Chambers
I made the body one of the central themes in my talk because
I think it is a central semantic zone in pop or rock music. It is, if you like, the site
of the senses: of the sexual as well as the more obviously social, of the cultural as
well as the corporeal. It is a space-a critical one, a material one-crisscrossed by
many forces, including race, gender, and class experience. I tried in passing to suggest
some of these, but others were not mentioned. So the criticisms made about the
gaps in my paper-the absence of Hispanic music and culture; of gendered subjec-
tivities and rock music; of disco music, which, I thoroughly agree, is the music of
the 1970s to be considered when talking about musical languages organized around
the body-are right.
The discussion of all these aspects could certainly be taken
further. It can be argued, for instance, that disco's repetitive cycle and pulse disrupts
the ubiquitous sequential logic of rock music and its progression toward climax.
Richard Dyer, discussing the importance of disco music in gay culture, has argued
that disco breaks down phallocentricity; that is, it celebrates the whole body rather
than restricting its attention to genital satisfaction. This possibility, if initially based
on formal musical distinctions, acquires conviction as it is related and connected
back to the effects and presence of disco in the repertoire of pop, to its history on
the dance floor, to its place in gay culture, to its presence as a possibility in contem-
porary urban culture.
Finally, I think we must come to terms with the specificity
of the feminine experience, which has been largely silenced, hidden beneath the
dominant ways of talking about pop music and the dominant ways in which pop
music is experienced. That is why I wanted to emphasize that the major romantic
mode in pop music is that of a masculine, imaginary street life.
Comment
One of the things that really interested me in your paper is
how much it depended on what I would take to be a specifically modernist project.
You began by quoting the futurist exhaltation of the "voluptuous" sonorities of the
new urban environment. It seems to me that one of the things we might do is to
look at words like "voluptuous" when they appear in a futurist or modernist project
and think about what kind of landscape they codify. From that point of view, the
constant appropriation and bricolage that you talked of appear less as a liberatory
space and more as a symptom of the immense "tedium of ownership" in a highly
developed society and of its need to incorporate and then obliterate difference. In
the Hungarian film Time Stands Still, kids use music to make open spaces for
themselves, but only in the context of a larger defeat. And I would maintain that
in the case of people of color, colonized people, and women, the meanings and the
liberational spaces are real, but only within a larger structure of oppression.
Chambers
A significant part of that complexity to which I have just
referred arises in the transitory, mobile, expansive urban culture in which we all
live. Puerto Ricans in New York City, like West Indians in Birmingham, England,
613
have their culture. But this culture is not a sealed testament. It echoes with everyday
experience; it comes out ofliving your presence in the present; it comes out of New
York, out of Birmingham.... This culture also exists as a part ofthis city, this time,
these conditions. Such proximities have indeed usually heightened racial and cultural
identities rather than reduced them.
Question
I want to question your apparent assumption about the lib-
erating potential of rock as a source of meaning to youth subcultures. Personally,
I'm just a little bit fearful, and not at all celebratory, about the energizing potential
of what is perhaps a rather nihilistic form of music and social energy.
Comment
I'd like to respond to that before lain does. I think there are
differences between the music and the people who are listening to it, and these
differences may enable us to understand some of these questions about the effects
of the music in the Third World-about the homogenization of culture. It seems
true that this music is used as an imperialistic form of culture, but it can also be
used by the people who listen to it as an element of youth rebelliousness. I want to
defend rock 'n' roll against charges of nihilism and retreat. There are points where
rock 'n' roll serves as a focal point for young people's rebelliousness, mixed up with
all their ideas of conscience. And in some cases this inchoate rebelliousness may
take active political dimensions.
Chambers
What I have been trying to suggest is that cultural powers,
arising through differences, choice, heterogeneity-whether Jamaican, Hispanic, or
of a more local variety-are reproduced in new forms in the expanding, increasingly
electronic context of contemporary urban culture. It is the powers and possibilities
of these new forms, where the "meanings" are by no means fixed, where there is
still a confusing "order," that is important. If we are not willing to accept this reality-
and its particular forms of power, of knowledge-then we are left out in the cold,
facing a very grim scenario. On the defensive, desperately seeking to preserve our-
selves and our choices from "co-optation," critical intelligence is concentrated in
the doomed task of delaying the inevitable: the moment when we pass into the
Langian citizenship of Metropolis.
Question
On the issue of art and politics, and particularly the politics
of rock 'n' roll, I thought you made some very provocative remarks at the very end
of your talk. You suggested that there is a conjuncture in advanced capitalist cities
between some of the demands of the Left and some of the demands of youth culture
to change life, to restructure society. Could you elaborate on this?
Chambers
I think it is very important to begin thinking through, in the
here and now, the full implications of this expanded, urban culture; that is, to
construct a project that can effectively meet its terms. That is why I insist on its
rich complexity. It is all very well to say, "We just gotta live it" -everybody is already
doing that! The problem is how to live it most effectively, how to grasp the potential
that is already in play, how to widen the political project without reducing the possible.
This is the Gramscian task, although one might want to say post-Gramscian, of
creating a "hegemony" adequate to the present. That, for me, is the real question.
To conclude, I would also insist on a very wide sense of the
term "politics." I am not simply talking about the relationship between the political
party and culture. I'm referring to the heterogeneous and different possibilities that
presently circulate within urban culture. These are frequently not commensurable.
There is, as Emesto Laclau suggested, a "surplus of meaning," an "open" discourse
614
lain Chambers
where differences, distinctions, and particulars do not necessarily find an equivalence.
But it is there, and not in an assumed conceptual order, that the everday struggle
for recognition, meaning, direction, prospects, hegemony, occurs. As Larry Grossberg
said, discussing the analysis of pleasure and rock music, something is always left
over, left out. I think that "left over" has to do with the threshold, the limits, of
analysis. There is something left out of the stilled order of writing, analysis, and its
conceptual frames. But it is important that this "left-over" is recognized, is inscribed,
in the re-presentation, in the analysis, for what it signals are precisely those trans-
formatory powers that threaten to make our present analysis redundant by producing
something new: a new reality.
615
VI The Politics of Theory and Interpretation
Terry Eagleton
The sense is: "I am telling you not to have your head
turned by military glory, you little idiot, not because
you will take my advice, since the fact that I have to
plead with you in the first place reveals just the in-
sensitivity which will deafen you to it, but because if
I do not advise you thus you will impute to me just
the kind of indifference I am asking you not to impute
to yourself, and so give yourself an excuse for denying
620
Terry Eagleton
your own finer instincts, which you have anyway done
by putting me in this humiliating situation in the first
place." (There is probably some sort of smack here at
Puritanism).
The interplay between poetic statement and critical commentary forms a
kind of pastoral indeterminacy in which the question of which party has
the upper hand is left deliberately ambiguous. In one sense the prose com-
mentary humbly flattens itself before the poetry, caricaturing in its breezy
colloquiality its helpless incapacity to adequate it, wryly acknowledging an
unsurpassable rift between the two registers. In another sense the commen-
tary is considerably more elaborate than the text, tempting us by its com-
monsensical tone to believe that its own subtle turns are merely derivative
of the poem in the very act of outdoing it in intricacy. The two discourses
seem at once continuous and incommensurate: the literary text is both
enriched and demystified by the criticism; left poorer but more honest in
one sense, but impressively complicated in another. A pastoral transference
of qualities has been effected: "If my criticism can have something of the
subtlety of the text, then the text may have something of the straightfor-
wardness of my criticism, in which case neither piece of writing is exactly
what we thought it was." The critics are both richer and poorer than the
poem, something of the jester in their heavy-footed cavortings before the
majesty of the literary yet also superfluously cerebral and refined in contrast
with the simple, passionate spontaneity they analyze.
All cultural critics for Empson are pastoralists, since they cannot
escape the occasionally farcical irony of being fine, delicate, and excessively
complex about a writing whose power lies ultimately in its embodiment of
a "common humanity." The critics are continually haunted by the irony
that the very instruments that give them access to those powers also threaten
to cut them off from them. This, for Empson, is a permanent rather than
a historical condition: Some Versions of Pastoral opens with a chapter on
proletarian literature which denies the real possibility of the genre since "the
artist never is at one with any public." But this liberal-romantic mystifi-
cation (What exactly is meant here by "at one"?) is surely undercut by a
glance at the social history that produced the early Empson. Seven Types
of Ambiguity was published between the Wall Street crash of 1929 and the
financial collapse of Austria and Germany, when British unemployment
stood at around two million; Some Versions of Pastoral appeared in 1935,
the year of the Italian invasion of Ethiopia, the formation of a national
government in Britain, and the founding of the Left Book Club. It is not
difficult, in this situation, to see why the literary intellectual might have felt
somewhat less than at one with the public, or why one fascinated by the
verbal cavillings of minor seventeenth-century poets might have experi-
enced some slight need to justify his or her enterprise. Thus, pastoral is, in
a sense, Empson's political self-apologia, a form that exposes the ironic
contradictions of intellectual sophistication and common wisdom; it is an
implicit reflection on the dazzling pyrotechnics of Seven Types ofAmbiguity
in a darkening political scene. The real swains, now, are the hunger marchers.
Insofar as the pastoral form is generously capacious, good-humoredly con-
taining the conflicts it dramatizes, it is, of course, as Raymond Williams
has protested, a flagrant mystification.' But what Williams fails to see (un-
621
derstandably enough, for one from the rural proletariat) is that this spurious
harmonization of class struggle is the heavy political price Empson mo-
mentarily has to pay for a politically well intentioned aesthetic which, in
the epoch of wars and revolutions, seeks to return the increasingly fine-
drawn analyses ofliterary critics to their roots in a practical social wisdom.
Empson's life-long guerilla campaign against the whole portentous gamut
of formalisms and symbolisms, his brusque dismissal of all metaphysical
poetics, is the fruit of a profoundly sociable theory oflanguage, which grasps
the literary text as discourse rather than langue, refusing purely textual (or
"organically contextual") notions of meaning for an insistence that meanings
are inscribed in practical social life before they come to be distilled into
poetry. The literary text for Empson is no organicistic mystery but a social
enunciation capable of rational paraphrase, open to the routine sympathies
and engagements of its readers, turning around terms that crystallize whole
social grammars or practical logics of sense.
The Empsonian reader is always an active interpreter: ambiguity
itself is defined as any verbal nuance that "gives room for alternative re-
actions to the same piece oflanguage, " 2 and the act of reading depends upon
certain tacit social understandings, certain "vague rich intimate" apprehen-
sions carried in collective social practice. Interpretation rests upon the hu-
manist-rationalist assumption that the human mind, however baffled, com-
plex, and divided, is essentially "sane"; to interpret is to make as large-
minded, generous allowance as one can for the way a particular mind, how-
ever self-broodingly idiosyncratic, is striving to work through and encom-
pass its own conflicts, which can never be wholly inscrutable precisely be-
cause they inhere in a shared social medium-language itself-inherently
patient of public intelligibility. If criticism is a mug's game, it is because
such conflicts, "life" being the multiple, amorphous affair it is, will never
endure definitive formulation, never submit to the boundaries of a single
sense. But this "pastoral" sense of the loose, incongruous character ofhistory
dignifies, rather than tragically defeats, human reason, providing it with the
most recalcitrant materials on which to exercise its powers and arrive at
the most fulfilling type of (in)adequation. The "aristocratic" refinements of
complex analysis, that is to say, are at once at odds with and enhanced by
the basic, unfinished stuff on which critical acumen goes to work-just as
that "common" stuff at once ironizes the critical gesture itself and, in being
revealed by it as in truth inexhaustibly subtle, comes to be on terms with
it. Empson, like the Freud by whom he is nervously fascinated, is the kind
of rationalist who constantly allows reason to press up against its own strin-
gent limits without for a moment ceasing to trust in its force. In this sense
he fits awkwardly into the straw-target category of rationalism ideologically
requisite for the fashionable irrationalisms of our own time.
Responding to a question about his attitude toward Leavis and
New Criticism, Raymond Williams makes an acute comment on the politics
of English criticism:
I said to people here at Cambridge: in the thirties you
were passing severely limiting judgments on Milton
and relatively favorable judgments on the metaphys-
ical poets, which in effect redrew the map of 17th-
century literature in England. Now you were, of course,
622
Terry Eagleton
making literary judgments-your supporting quota-
tions and analysis prove it, but you were also asking
about ways of living through a political and cultural
crisis of national dimensions. On the one side, you
have a man who totally committed himself to a par-
ticular side and cause, who temporarily suspended what
you call literature, but in fact not writing, in that con-
flict. On the other, you have a kind of writing which
is highly intelligent and elaborate, that is a way of
holding divergent attitudes toward struggle or toward
experience together in the mind at the same time. These
are two possibilities for any highly conscious person
in a period of crisis-a kind of commitment which
involves certain difficulties, certain naiveties, certain
styles; and another kind of consciousness, whose com-
plexities are a way of living with the crisis without
being openly part of it. I said that when you were
making your judgments about these poets, you were
not only arguing about their literary practice, you were
arguing about your own at that time. 3
The dilemma outlined by Williams here-one between a highly specialized
mode of critical intelligence, which in foregrounding ironic complexity evades
certain necessarily univocal social commitments, and a plainer, committed
writing that is prepared to sacrifice such ambivalences in the cause of po-
litical responsibility-is a modern version of the contradictions which, as I
have argued elsewhere, fissure the English critical institution throughout
much of its history. 4 Criticism has lurched between a "professional" so-
phistication that sequesters it from collective social life and a political in-
tervention into the life that, at its best (as with Milton), lends it a substantive
function, and at its worst (as with Arnold) degenerates into an ineffectually
"amateur" liberal humanism.
Williams, one suspects, would place Empson's work firmly on
the second side ofhis antithesis, and there is much truth in such a judgment.
But this would overlook the ironies of pastoral, which, while conscious of
the socially determined distance between the language of developed con-
sciousness and a common Lebenswelt, nevertheless seeks a basis of dialogue
between them. If Empson's pastoral model is transferred, as it would seem
to ask to be, from the anodyne artifice of a courtly drama to the problem
of the critical intellectual in modern bourgeois society, it can be made to
yield up significances akin rather than alien to Williams's own political case.
The author of Seven Types of Ambiguity, that supposed classic of New
Criticism, is also the author of Milton's God, a work quite prepared to
negotiate its way in most un-Eliotic or un-Leavisian fashion through the
twists and turns of Milton's religious ideology, powered as it is by a fero-
ciously debunking Voltairean humanism but steadfast in its acknowledg-
ment of Milton's magnificence. One can trace, indeed, in the radically di-
vided character of Paradise Lost-its rational humanism and religious
transcendentalism-a veritable allegory ofEmpson's own critical battles with
literary reaction. Empson the ironist and ambiguist is, after all, the critic
who writes in Milton's God that he feels he can well understand the God
623
Lost from the inside, having been a propaganda specialist himself during
the Second World War. The insult is directed against the Christian God,
not against propaganda or political rhetoric.
Empson's criticism, that is to say, offers a partial deconstruction
ofWilliams's polarity. That the deconstruction is only partial is surely plain:
he is obviously not a "committed" critic in the style of a Milton or a
Williams. But those features of his critical approach that look most lemon-
squeezingly Wimsattian are in fact nothing of the sort; his relentless un-
raveling of finer and finer shades of verbal meaning is no aridly evasive
enterprise of the kind Williams is right to denounce, but is itself a political
position, inscribed by a whole range of militantly humanistic beliefs-trust
in the intelligibility and sense-making capacities of the mind even at its
most divided; a dogged refusal of symbolistic mystifications; a recognition
of conflicts and indeterminacies-which are a necessary, if not sufficient,
condition of any more politically radical criticism. Christopher Norris, in
his excellent study of Empson, describes his pastoral as "lift[ing] the sub-
tleties of poetic argument into a larger, essentially social air"; 5 but while
this is true, "ambiguities" for Empson were in a way this all along, not
sealed structures of New Critical ambivalence but interpretative struggles
and enigmas consequent upon language's ineradicable sociality and correl-
ative roughness, its multipurpose functioning in practical life, its intrinsic
openness to alternative social histories and tonalities. Poetry is not, for
Empson, as for New Criticism and some contemporary deconstruction, the
privileged locus of ambiguity or indeterminacy; all language is indetermi-
nate, and this, precisely, is how it is fruitful and productive. Empson's
Cambridge is also the Cambridge of Wittgenstein, who reminds us in the
Blue and Brown Books that "we are unable clearly to circumscribe the con-
cepts we use; not because we don't know their real definition, but because
there is no 'real' definition to them." 6 Those who seem suddenly to have
discovered that the essence of "literary" language lies in its indeterminacy
have obviously not been listening for some years to how the people around
them actually talk.
Empson's ambiguities, moreover, have never been purely rhe-
torical affairs. They root down into conflicts of impulse and allegiance, in
what seems to him the mixed, contradictory character of social being itself,
in the friction of competing ideologies and social valuations. Paul de Man
is not wrong to claim that Empson's work thus manifests a "deep division
of Being itself'; he is mistaken, rather, in appearing to assimilate Empson's
category of"contradictory meanings" (the seventh type of ambiguity) to his
own model of semantic deadlock (Empson, in fact, writes breezily that "any
contradiction is likely to have some sensible interpretations") 7 and in ap-
propriating the English critic's esentially social notions of conflict to his
own ontologizing impulse. Summarizing Empson's famous account of Mar-
vell's The Garden, in which the mind, having first discovered a delightful
unity with Nature, then moves to transcend and annihilate it, de Man in-
forms us with enviable authority that "the pastoral theme is, in fact, the
only poetic theme, that it is poetry itself." 8 What he means is that pastoral
enacts just that ironic dissociation of consciousness from its objects, which
is for him the properly demystified condition of all literature. Pastoral as-
suages de Man's early-Sartrean horror of "inauthenticity" and "bad faith,"
that dismal state in which the etre pour soi cravenly congeals into the etre
624
Terry Eagleton
en soi. ''What is the pastoral convention, then," he asks, "if not the eternal
separation between the mind that distinguishes, negates, legislates, and the
originary simplicity of the natural?" To which the only answer, even on de
Man's own account, is: a good deal more. A few lines earlier de Man notes
that in Marvell's poem the thought that annihilates Nature is "green"; in
the very act of dissociation, an equable correspondence between conscious-
ness and the world is ironically reintroduced by this softly intrusive modifier,
along with the sense, in Empson's words, of a "humble, permanent, un-
developed nature which sustains everything, and to which everything must
return." De Man actually quotes this phrase, but he does not allow it to
qualify his own Sartrean dogma of eternal alienation; he seizes the moment
of pastoral that best fits his own denial of all productive interchange between
consciousness and its surroundings and then redefines the whole genre-
and, for good measure, poetry itself-solely in these terms.
It is amusingly typical of de Man that he should find even pastoral
depressing, and for reasons quite other than Williams's. Marvell, himself,
as Empson sees, has no such puritanical inhibitions: the wit and courage of
his poem here lie in its refusal to absolutize even the moment ofthe mind's
annihilating transcendence, confident and humorous enough in its own fic-
tions to be able to reinvoke and indulge the notion of harmonious liaison
between Nature and mind even at this point of mystical fading and dis-
solution of the real. De Man's attempt to appropriate both Marvell and
Empson, in short, presses him into self-contradiction: he acknowledges the
greenness of the thought but then instantly erases its significance, for pastoral
is not only a demonstration of the division between mind and Nature but
also, across that acknowledged rift, a continuous sportive interplay in which
each puts the other into question. Fulfilling correspondences between both
terms can be delightedly pursued once the myth of any full identity between
them has been dismantled. De Man's doctrine of eternal separation, for him
the absolute truth of the human condition, is for the pastoralist no more
than one truth among several, an ironic reminder not to take one's own
fictions too seriously, which then therapeutically clears the way for a fruitful
alliance with the sensuous world. It is Empson, or Marvell, who is the
deconstructionist here, and de Man is the full-blown metaphysician.
De Man's puritanical fear of entanglement in the world of ma-
terial process, so different from Marvell's deliciously masochistic yearning
to be chained by brambles and nailed through by briars, finds a paradoxical
echo in the very Marxism de Man (as we shall see in a moment) is out to
worst. Few words have rung more ominously in Marxist ears than "natural,"
and we have all long since learned to rehearse the proper objections to it
with Pavlovian precision. Having learned that lesson, however, it is surely
time to move on rather than remain, like de Man, fixated in the moment
of bleak recognition that aardvarks are not people, repeating that traumatic
moment compulsively. Once the consolations of identity have been un-
masked as mythical (and pastoral, wrenched by a certain reading, can con-
tribute to that end), we are liberated to inquire what fertile pacts and al-
legiances between Nature and humanity might in fact be generated, as the
ecology movement has for some time been inquiring. The work of Sebas-
tiano Timpanaro, Raymond Williams, and Norman Geras, not to speak of
the drama and prefaces of Edward Bond, 9 does not cancel the important
caveats of historicist Marxism on this score, but at its best takes us through
625
and beyond them, to the point where the concepts of Nature and human
nature are not merely to be dismissed as ideological fictions but are to be
theoretically reconstructed. Pastoral asserts that some conditions and styles
of feeling are more natural than others, and provided we do not absolutize
the term, there is no reason why it should not remain, as it has long tra-
ditionally been, an integral part of radical social criticism. There seems
something strangely self-thwarting about a culturalist or historicist Marxism
that sternly forbids itself to describe as "unnatural" a wholly reclusive life
or a society that finds sunshine disgusting.
The political implications of de Man's misreading of Empson are
ominous: if the ironies of pastoral are allegorical of the critic's relation to
society, or indeed of the relation of all intellectual to manual labor, then it
is the uncrossable gulf between them that de Man wishes to reaffirm. This
is one reason why his reflections on Empson culminate abruptly, though
not wholly unpredictably, in an assault on Marxism, which is, of course,
for de Man (if not for 90 percent of Marxists) a poetic dream of utter
reconciliation between world and mind. Insofar as Empson himself criticizes
this drive as "premature" in his chapter on proletarian literature, he has
laid himself wide open to such enlistment; but one cannot imagine that he
would support the tragic philosophy that is de Man's only alternative to
the loss of the impossible. "The problem of separation," de Man writes,
"inheres in Being, which means that social forms of separation derive from
ontological and metaphysical attitudes. For poetry, the divide exists for-
ever."'0 It is very hard to see why, ifthe idea of some total identity between
Nature and society is plainly absurd, the absence of it should be considered
somehow tragic. Many human beings would quite like to live forever, but
not all of them find it tragic that they will not. Some people feel repulsed
and alienated by staring at the roots of trees, while others just sit down and
have a picnic. The nonidentity of consciousness and being is a fact, which
may be construed tragically or not depending on how far you are still secretly
in thrall with a vision of unity. The sharpest difference between de Man
and Empson on this point is that for Empson the noncoincidence of mind
and world, the sophisticated and the simple, is not in itself tragic at all,
though it may from time to time involve tragedy. It is true that, in his
remark that the poet is never at one with his or her public, Empson suggests
a transhistorical estrangement upon which de Man can then pounce, turning
the point for good measure against the early Marxian Barthes; but for Emp-
son, the writer's lack of identity with an audience is simply a fact, not the
basis of some melancholic ontology. For de Man it is an unquestioned good
that consciousness should keep free of its objects, that the critic refuse all
definitive identifications; for Empson, the typically pastoral attitude is a
more ambiguous one: "I (the artist/critic/intellectual) am in one way better
(than the worker/peasant), in another way not as good." Or, as he puts it
more accurately elsewhere: "Some people are more delicate and complex
than others, and . . . if such people can keep this distinction from doing
harm it is a good thing, though a small thing by comparison with our
common humanity."''
The fact that in a given society some individuals have the means
and opportunity to be more cultured than others is not to be guiltily re-
pressed; this, indeed, would be the Sartrean bad faith or false identification
whereby intellectuals seek to empty themselves into the etre en soi of the
626
Terry Eagleton
masses. Part ofthe implicit courage of Some Versions of Pastoral, one feels,
is exactly its ironic resistance to the romantic versions of this thirties-style
thesis, which was powerfully in the political air and from which the opening
chapter on proletarian literature immediately takes its distance. But this is
not to leave oneself with no option but romantic alienation, endorsing the
eternal isolation ofthe refined critic and the unchangeable lowliness of the
common people. Some Versions of Pastoral begins with a brilliant critique
of Gray's Elegy, which demonstrates just how the poem's imagery tries to
trick us into accepting the obscurity of the rural poor as somehow inevitable.
Though distinctions of sophistication and simplicity exist, Empson's crucial,
most un-de Manian point is that they are a poor thing in contrast with our
"common humanity." Pastoral, in manifesting such distinctions, is more
than a ruling-class conspiracy because it also reveals them as continually
ironized and encompassed by a wider ambience, a general sustaining Nature
as it were, which transcends them in its importance. What makes us uniquely
different individuals, as Derek Parfit argues in his Reasons and Persons, is
just not important enough a basis on which to build an ethics-or, one might
add, a politics. 12 Pastoral knows a moment of (potentially tragic) separation
of mind from world, the cultivated from the simple, self-reflexivity from
spontaneity; but it includes this moment within a richer, more complex
relationship in which it is recognized that the intellectual must be taught
by the masses, that the mind is, after all, a part of Nature and not just its
other, that the rich are poorer as well as richer than the common people,
and that even the intellectuals-hard though it sometimes is to credit them-
share a common humanity with others, which ultimately overrides whatever
demarcates the two. The critic who recognizes all this is the critic as clown,
and one of his several names in our time is William Empson. Paul de Man,
for his part, inherits from Nietzsche a notion of action as mindless spon-
taneity (practice as "pure forgetting"), which however qualified (de Man
goes on to deconstruct that "pure") puts it eternally at odds with the com-
plexities of theory. 13 It is a nineteenth-century irrationalist current that
emerges at its most disreputable in such writers as Conrad and leaves its
mark on the work of Althusser.
De Man's epistemology of dissociated spirit most certainly entails
a politics of intellectual elitism. Among the objects of consciousness are, of
course, mass movements and political commitments, and modem bour-
geois-liberal critics can attain some negative authenticity only in that ironic
gesture by which, in separating themselves from such empirical engage-
ments, they name them all as ineradicably inauthentic. "The ironic language
splits the subject into an empirical self that exists in a state ofinauthenticity
and a self that exists only in the form of a language that asserts the knowledge
of this inauthenticity." 14 In one sense, the intellectual has been discredited:
he or she can no longer speak an authentic discourse to a society that has
no particular desire to know about Holderlin. In another sense, such an
intellectual retains much of his or her traditional authority-retains, indeed,
much of the classicalform of relationship between liberal intelligentsia and
society as a whole, and so is able to deliver an authoritative message. That
message, however, is now wholly empty and negative: it consists of the
ceaseless act of naming the inauthenticity of all empirical engagements. In
a way, the form of the intellectual's relation to modem society-the act of
rigorous self-separation-has become the content of the enunciation. That
627
the intellectual should still be honored but should really have nothing to
say is the material basis of de Man's metaphysical dislocation of mind and
being. It is not difficult to see how this doctrine grew up in the United States
of America. The intellectual's own discourse is inevitably contaminated by
inauthenticity (even Yale is situated in New Haven), constantly threatening
to congeal into the reified beliefs of the unreflexive masses and constantly
recovering itself only in the blank space it keeps establishing between itself
and such entanglements. Thus, when the intellectual's own discourse speaks,
it is untrue; and when it is true it must be silent. Meaning and being are
ceaselessly at odds, and it is easy to see why this Lacanian doctrine has an
appeal when one is trying to teach Kleist in Reagan's America. But if the
intellectual's own discourse is inauthentic, it is also because his or her ide-
ological interests are, on the whole, at one with the very society his or her
ironic self-distancing seeks to shut out. Only by the form of the intellectual's
statements can such interests be momentarily transcended; ..irony" is the
device whereby the modern bourgeois critic can at once collude with and
privately disown the ideological imperatives of the modern state.
This is not the case with Empson's mode of irony. Whereas de
Man is the patrician who ironizes the ideological doxa of the peasant, Emp-
son views the matter in a kind of Bakhtinian reversal: it is the canny sense
of the peasant that must keep the ideologizing clerk in check. In a deeply
Wittgensteinian gesture, the intellectual's fatal penchant to ride hobbyhorses
(a saddening feature, it must be confessed, of the later Empson himself)
must be prised open to the therapeutic influence of how language is prac-
tically used, exposed to the resources of that collective social wisdom crys-
tallized in its key terms (.. complex words"). It is, as it were, the common
people, or at least common readers, who live ambiguously, innately sus-
picious of ideological formalisms that would prematurely synthesize such
inconclusiveness; and Empson, as critic, is the spokesperson of this ..good
sense." Pastoral is a form of the people not because it is written or read by
them, or because it figures them other than in absurdly or offensively stylized
ways, but because it has about it a kind of .. productive looseness" (Chris-
topher Norris), which is the structural mark of this state of ideological
conflict and division. The phrase .. productive looseness" has a Brechtian
ring to it, and the connection seems less surprising once we remember the
two men's fascination with John Gay's Beggar's Opera . .. Putting the com-
plex into the simple" is, after all, a snap enough definition of Brecht's plurnpes
Denken. Looked at in one light, Empson's liberal humanism, his constant
striving to give what credit he can to beliefs (such as Milton's) that are
deeply repugnant to him, involves an ironic provisionality of attitude not
far from de Man's. Both critics can, in this sense, plausibly be construed as
baffled, somewhat self-agonizing bourgeois liberals. But there is also a sense
in which Empson's ironies carry him to a point closer to the sensibility of
a Brecht, for whom irony denotes the necessarily unfinished, processual,
contradictory nature of historical affairs, a fact usually more obvious to the
ruled than the rulers. There is even a possible link through to Brecht in
what Empson learned from his Far Eastern experience: what he reads as
the tolerant, ironic magnanimity of the Buddha is very close to the .. Chinese"
Brecht's sense of the need to maintain a kind of cheerful impassive equipoise
in the difficult business of negotiating contradictions.
628
Terry Eagleton
Contradictions for Brecht were not only sometimes intolerable
but also, as he once said with reference to Hegel, a "joke." The jokiness of
both Brecht and Empson-the one self-consciously plebeian, the other icon-
oclastically English-strikes a quite different social tone from the high Eu-
ropean humorlessness of de Man. Empson writes in Some Versions of Pas-
toral of a Soviet performance of Hamlet (that most de Manian of dramas)
that the audience spontaneously decided was a farce. Such people, Empson
reflects, "may well hold out against the melancholy of old Russia, and for
them there may be dangerous implications in any tragedy, which other
people do not see." 15 I think Christopher Norris is right to suggest that
Empson may well have approved of such a response to the play. Tragedy,
for Empson, is a heroic mode associated with aristocratic absolutism and
ascetic self-renunciation, deeply at odds with his own ironic humanism; and
in this humanistic suspicion of tragedy he is again very close to Brecht. Like
Brecht, the alternative form Empson offers is not some crass triumphalism
but, as Norris argues of the quality of his "complex words" ("fool," "dog,"
"honest," and so on), "a down-to-earth quality of healthy scepticism which
. . . permits their users to build up a trust in human nature on a shared
knowledge of its needs and attendant weaknesses." 16 This, too, is a pastoral
mode of feeling: you must love and admire the "high" human qualities of
truth, beauty, virtue, and courage, but you must not be too downcast if
people fail to live up to them, or terrorize them with these ideals to a point
that makes their weaknesses painful to them. Tragedy moves within the
high-minded terrorism of such ideals; however "deep," it is arguably nar-
rower, more violent in its implacable expectations than the large-minded
plebeian wisdom that, without a breath of cynicism (the mere flip side of
such idealism) knows when not to ask too much of others. Empson's own
companionable literary style is antiheroic in this sense, designed not to
intimidate a reader; Milton's God pushes raciness and iconoclasm to the
very brink of academic indecorousness. Brecht's antitragic awareness that
there are always other possibilities parallels Empson's reading of the "Meta-
physical" poets as constantly entertaining further possible levels of meaning,
ironically including within a poem its acts of exclusion. Brecht's belief that
an effective play ought always to convey a sense of the (potentially contra-
dictory) meanings it excludes, the pressure of a further possible productivity,
is classically Empsonian.
The fact that there is always more productivity where that came
from should not be confused with the infinite regress of a certain mode of
deconstruction. For Empson, interpretation is certainly, in principle, inex-
haustible, and the limitation of the various types of ambiguity to a mere
seven is more a joke at the expense of magical numbers than a serious
taxonomy. That there is some continuity between Empson the liberal hu-
manist and the antihumanist deconstructionist is signaled in Norris's sum-
mary of his critical "method": "He seems constantly on the verge of defining
the complex implications, verbal or generic, which might satisfy, by some-
how pinning down, his sense of the poem's richness. Yet he constantly
relegates this purpose, detecting behind these provisional structures a series
of ironies and 'placing' attitudes which prevent their treatment as an in-
tegrating function of form." 17 This could clearly be said of Derrida or de
Man; indeed, the affinity is well enough mapped in Christopher Norris's
own evolution from a sympathetic critic of Empson to an exponent of
629
deconstruction. Yet such a trajectory tends also to impoverish Empson's
work, isolating him as the author of Seven Types ofAmbiguity and pruning
away (or conveniently repressing) the more "sociable," proto-political later
writing.
The shift from Seven Types of Ambiguity to The Structure of
Complex Words, from "Metaphysical" to "Augustan," "wit" to "sense,"
reflects a growing recognition on Empson's part that wit and ambiguity,
however idiosyncratically "brilliant," are nurtured by collective contexts of
tacit significances, as in that Popean "good sense" that marks the inscription
of social logics within individual "wit." All discourse for Empson is in-
scribed by such social rationalities, however much it may disrupt and trans-
gress them; and this is why he turns in Complex Words to a period (the
eighteenth century) in which the inherent sociableness of language, for all
its normative violence, is more clearly apparent than in the seventeenth-
century ofNew Criticism. His appeal here is to "common sense," but though
his work is shot through with the limitations of this most English of vices
(it lacks, for example, almost any concept of ideology); it also goes some
way toward refurbishing the concept. "Common sense" in Empson is often
enough his airy impatience with theory, a brisk plain-minded reliance on
"what the author probably meant"; if he is one of the few English critics
to have taken the pressure of Freud, he does so with notable unease and
discomfort. Yet at its best his writing demonstrates just how thin a line
there can be between such anemic commonsensicality and the richer Grams-
dan idea of proletarian "good sense," the routine practical wisdom of those
who, more intimate with the material world than their rulers, are less likely
to be mystified by high-sounding rhetoric. When Empson declares his pas-
toral faith that "the most refined desires are inherent in the plainest, and
would be false if they weren't," 18 he is very close to a kind of Bakhtinian
populism; indeed, the remark is made in the context of discussing one of
Shakespeare's clowns. For Empson, it is Swift who presses this deconstruc-
tion of body and spirit, savagery and sophistication, to an extreme limit-
significantly enough, a limit to which Empson cannot quite follow him.
Empson the rationalistic humanist really does feel that Swift is "blasphe-
mous," rattled as he is by this virulent insistence that every generous human
motivation can be rewritten in terms of a degrading vulgarity. For "Swift,"
here, one might well read "Freud." To attempt to "refunction" the works
of Empson in Brechtian spirit cannot be to overlook his egregious limits.
Empson is a self-ironizing upper-class liberal rationalist with an exasper-
atingly commonsensical stance, trapped in a largely tedious form of nine-
teenth-century atheism and sometimes dangerously sanguine, in typically
English style, about human decency. His trust in a "common human nature"
can be ideological in the most negative sense of the term and needs to be
carefully distinguished from the more positive, materialist senses of that
concept to which Marxism has recently begun to tum. What can be retrieved
for socialism from Empson's work by a certain tendentious reading must
be retrieved against the grain of these evident blindnesses.
To contrast Empson with a later middle-class critic like de Man
is, most crucially, to compare a prefascist liberal intellectual with a post-
fascist one. Two of Empson's most seminal works were written before the
full fury of European fascism had been unleashed; and we might well wonder
whether his belief in the essential sanity and generosity of the "human mind"
630
Terry Eagleton
is not in part dependent on that chronology. De Man, as I have argued
elsewhere, is most interestingly viewed in the light of a bitter "postideo-
logical" scepticism belonging to the postfascist epoch; 19 and Empson's buoy-
ant Enlightenment rationality is just what he is out to embarrass. IfMarxism
cannot accept either position as it stands, it remains true that Empson poses
for us the more serious challenge, at least in this sense: that he reminds us
forcibly, with what he himself might call a "pastoral flatness," of just what
complexity and ambiguity any program of social transformation must en-
compass, without regarding that transformative end as in any sense un-
worthy. At the same time it is part of Empson's courage, and evidence of
the seeds of socialism that can be detected in his work, that he finally refuses
the liberal fetishizing of difference and ambivalence that still serves the cause
of liberal oppression. To paraphrase his own version of pastoral, with a
materialist sense of "common humanity" in mind: some people are more
delicate and complex than others, and this need not matter; indeed, it is a
positive enrichment, provided such distinctions do no social harm. But the
most seductive subtleties, the most dazzling displays of heroism, virtue, and
intelligence, are a poor thing compared to our shared humanity; and when-
ever we are forced to choose, it is always better to choose the latter.
Notes
1 Raymond Williams, The Country and the City (London: Oxford University Press, 1973), p.
21.
2 William Empson. Seven Types of Amb1guity (New York: New Directions, 1947), p. 1.
3 Raymond Williams, Politics and Letters (New York: Schocken, 1979). p. 335.
4 See Terry Eagleton. The Function of Criticism (New York: Schocken, 1984).
5 Chnstopher Norris, William Empson and the Philosophy of Literary Criticism (Atlantic High-
lands, N.J.: Humanities Press. 1978), p 64.
6 Ludwig Wittgenstein, The Blue and Brown Books (New York: Harper and Row), p. 25.
7 Empson, Seven Types of Amb1gwty, p. 197.
8 Paul de Man, Blmdness and Insight (Minneapolis: University of Minnesota Press, 1983). p.
239.
9 See in particular Sebastiana Timpanaro. On Materialism (New York: Schocken, 1980). chap.
1; Norman Geras, Marx and Human Nature (New York: Schocken, 1983). See also Terry
Eagleton, "Nature and Violence: The Prefaces of Edward Bond," Critical Quarterly 26:1-2
( 1984). Perry Anderson has remarked that the question of Nature is one Marxism must
confront in the future; see In the Tracks of H1storical Materialism (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press. 1984). pp. 56-84.
10 de Man, p. 240.
11 William Empson, Some Versions of Pastoral (New York: New Directions, 1960). p. 23.
12 See Derek Parfit. Reasons and Persons (Oxford: Oxford University Press. 1984).
13 See Paul de Man, "Literary History and Literary Modernity," in Blindness and Insight.
14 de Man, p. 214.
15 Empson, Some Versions of Pastoral, p. 13.
16 Norris. p. 86.
17 Norris, pp 46-4 7.
18 Empson, Some Versions of Pastoral. p. 114.
19 Eagleton, The Function of Criticism, p. 101.
631
Michel Picheux
...On A Gagne': What Has Been Won, How, and for Whom7 .. 7
Concerning the Objects of the Statement: What Is Won, How, and for
Whom?
Let us consult the dictionary about the verb "to win," gagner.
We see it can be constructed:
a. with a live subject (an agent endowed with will, feeling, in-
tention, etc.)-to earn one's living, to earn so much per month; to win a
competition, to be the winner; to win a game of chance, to win the first
prize; to overtake (on land, in space or time) an opponent; to be promoted;
to reach a place; to win someone's sympathy, (men, allies, friends); or
b. with a lifeless subject (a thing, a process without any proper
will, feeling, or intention.) These "agents" become objects: heat, cold, en-
thusiam, sleep, illness, joy, sadness overtake us (take hold of me, of him,
of us.)
What part did each of these lexicosyntactic ways of functioning
play in the equivocal unity of the reverberated chant? "We won": joy of
victory is enunciated without an object, but objects are not far away-we
won the match, the game, the first set (before legislative elections); but at
the same time (see above), we won by chance, as the first prize is won when
no one dared to hope for it, and, of course, ground is gained over the
opponent, with the anticipation of places to be filled, above all the place
from which France is governed, the place of governmental and state power.
"The Left takes power in France" is a plausible paraphrase of the formula-
statement "We won" as an extension of the event. Assuming power: at last
something that may be shown as the object of the verb "to win."
636
Michel Picheux
It is not at all certain that the verb "to win, to take power" may
be explained univocally. 9 "Power" may in a way be considered as an ac-
quired object, the deserved fruits of a long effort, or as unexpected good
fortune; in any case, the symbolic first prize to be managed for the good of
everyone. In another way "power" may be seen as a resistant space to be
conquered in an ongoing struggle against the bastions of capitalism (which
did its best to prevent it and continues to resist). In still another way, power
is a performative act to be upheld (to do what was promised) or even a new
set of social relations to be constructed.
On a gagne: for two years, the equivocation of this formula has
troubled leftists in government posts as well as other layers of the population;
it troubles those who believe in it as well as those who do not, those who
are waiting for a large popular movement and those who are resigned to a
generalized apoliticism, officeholders and ordinary people. Therefore, there
are two distinct temptations: (1) to deny the ambiguity ofthe event of May
10, for instance, by bringing it down to the logically stabilized level of
political institutions (Yes or no, is the French Left in or not? If yes, then
let us be consistent with the will of the people.); (2) to deny the event as
such, by behaving as if the problems were the same as if the right wing were
in power (Nothing really happened. What has been won?). 10 Yielding to
either of these temptations would ultimately divide the two Lefts from each
other and surrender both to the opponent. If the right wing were to come
back into power in France, one would see-too late-what one has lost.
My intention in taking the event of May 10, 1981, as an example
has been to raise the question of the status of the discursivities that traverse
an event, interweaving propositions that seem logically stabilized and there-
fore may be univocally responded to (yes or no, X or Y) with those for-
mulations that are irredeemably equivocal. Discursive objects that seem to
be stable, that seem privileged by a relative logical independence in relation
to statements produced about them, exchange their trajectories with other
kinds of objects whose mode of existence is governed by the very way they
are spoken about. Is one type of object more "real" than another? Is there
an underlying space common to the deployment of such dissimilar objects?
Science, Structure, and Scholasticism
To suppose that, in certain circumstances at least, an object is
independent in relation to any discourse about that object is equally to
suppose that, in the interior of what appears to be the physical-human
universe (things, living beings, persons, events, processes), "there is some-
thing of the real." That is, there are points of impossibility determining
what cannot fail to be thus. The real is (the) impossibility ... that things
could be otherwise. Therefore, one does not discover the real; one bumps
into it, meets it, finds it.
Thus, the domain of mathematics and the natural sciences has
to do with the real, insofar as one can say of a mathematician or of a physicist
that he or she has found the solution to a problem that had remained up
to that point unsolved. Also, we say that a student, facing math or physics
homework, has solved such and such part of the problem, that he or she is
"right" (if "a bon'') on such and such a question, while as far as the rest is
concerned he or she is "lost" (if seche).
A very great number of material technologies that produce phys-
ical or biophysical transformations "have to do with" the real, in opposition
637
to the techniques of divination and interpretation. The point is to find, with
or without the aid of the natural sciences, the means of obtaining a result
in the most effective possible fashion, while taking into account the ex-
haustibility of nature~ the means to use natural processes, to instrumentalize
them, to direct them toward the sought-for effects. To this series is added
a multiplicity of techniques of the social management of individuals: they
are marked, identified, classified, compared, placed in order, in ranks and
tables. They are reassembled and separated according to defined criteria in
order to put them to work, to teach them, to give them dreams or hallu-
cinations, to protect them and maintain surveillance over them, to lead
them to war, to induce them to have children.
This administrative (juridical, economic, and political) space pre-
sents the appearance of a disjunctive logical constraint. It is "impossible"
that one is both a bachelor and married, that one has a diploma and does
not have a diploma, that one works and is unemployed, that one earns less
than x dollars per month and more than that sum, that one is both a civilian
and in the military, that one is elected to such and such a function and is
not, and so on. These spaces, through which the possessors of knowledge
are placed, the specialists and officials of diverse existing orders (all of them
functioning as agents and guarantors of these multiple operations), have a
very specific property: they essentially forbid interpretation. This interdic-
tion is implied by the ordered usage of logical propositions (true or false)
with disjunctive interrogations (Is the state of affairs A or not A?). Correl-
atively, this interdiction implies the refusal of certain marks of discursive
distance, 11 such as "in a sense," "if you like," "we might say," "to an extreme
degree," "properly speaking." In particular, these spaces imply the refusal
of all quotation marks of an interpretative nature that would displace the
categorization. For example, the statement "Such and such a person is very
military in civilian life" is prohibited, even though this statement, of course,
makes perfect sense.
In the discursive spaces designated above as logically stabilized,
a given speaking subject is supposed to know what is being talked about;
every statement produced in these spaces reflects structural properties that
are independent of the enunciation of the statement. These properties are
transparently inscribed in an adequate description ofthe universe, such that
this universe is discursively grasped in the spaces. The apparent unifying
factor of these discursive spaces is a series of logical-practical evidences at
a very general level, such as: the same object X cannot be at the same time
in two different places; the same object X cannot have at the same time
property P and property not P; the same event E cannot at the same time
have occurred and not have occurred; and so on. The logical homogeneity
that conditions the logically representable as a set of propositions capable
of being true or false is traversed by a series of equivocities (in particular
concerning such terms as Law, Rigor, Order, Principle, etc.), which covers
at the same time, like a patchwork, the domains of the exact sciences, tech-
nologies, and public services. 12
This "logical" cover (couverture) of the heterogeneous regions of
the real is too massive and systematic a phenomenon to be seen simply as
a deception, constructed piecemeal by some mystifying Prince: before this
false semblance (faux-semblant) of a natural and sociohistorical real, covered
by a network of logical propositions, everything happens as if it were not
638
Michel Picheux
in anyone's power totally to escape, even-and perhaps especially-those
who believe themselves not to be duped by it ("non-dupes"), as if this in-
evitable inclusion would come to be realized in one way or another.
If we put aside all explanations that are not explanations, insofar
as they are only the commentaries of this inclusion itself, there is perhaps
a crucial point to consider from the direction of the multiple exigencies of
everyday life. But to call this point into question supposes the suspension
of the position of the universal spectator as the source of logical homo-
geneity; it necessitates the interrogation of the "pragmatic" subject in the
Kantian sense, as well as in the contemporary sense. 13 The idea that these
logically stablilized spaces could be imposed from the exterior, like the
constraints placed on the pragmatic subject, through the sole power of people
of science, specialists, and administrators, becomes, once it is seriously con-
sidered, indefensible.
The pragmatic subject-that is to say, ordinary people faced with
the diverse exigencies oftheir lives-has itself an imperative need for logical
homogeneity, marked by the existence of a multiplicity of small, portable,
logical systems: from the management of everyday existence (for example,
in our civilization, wallet, keys, schedules, calendars, papers), to the great
decisions of social and private life (I decide to do such and such and not
something else, to respond to X and not to Y), to the whole sociotechnical
environment ofhousehold appliances (the series of objects that we acquire,
that we learn how to work, that we throw away or use, that we break or
repair or replace). In this space of equivocal necessity, in which are inter-
mingled things and persons, technical processes and moral decisions, in-
structions for use and political choices, any conversation (from the simplest
request for information to discussions, debates, and confrontations) is ca-
pable of putting into play a logical bipolarization of statable propositions-
with, from time to time, the insidious impression of a univocal simplifi-
cation, which could eventually be deadly for oneself and/or for others.
It does no good to deny this need (or desire) for the appearance
of homogeneity bearing logical disjunctions and categorizations: the uni-
versal need for a "semantically normal (i.e., normalized) world" begins with
the relation that we each maintain with our own body and our immediate
environment (beginning with the distribution of good and bad objects, ar-
chaically figured by the disjunction between food and excrement). Nor does
it do any good to deny that this need for boundaries coincides with the
construction of links between multiple "things to be known" (choses a sa-
voir): we say "things to be known" and "things ofknowledge"; we say "things
of beauty." These "things to be known" can be considered as reserves of
accumulated knowledge that we depend on, 14 machines of knowledge against
threats of any kind: the state and institutions functioning most often-at
least in our societies-as privileged poles of response to this need or demand.
Thus, such "things to be known" stand for things that might be
lacking for the happiness (and ultimately for the simple biological survival)
of the pragmatic subject; that is, anything that threatens him or her by the
very fact that it exists (the fact that it is part of the real, whatever grasp the
subject in question has of the structure of the real). It is not necessary to
have a phenomenological intuition, a hermeneutic grasp, or a spontaneous
apprehension of the essence of typhus to be affected by this malady; 15 in
fact, it is quite the contrary: there are "things to be known" (knowledges to
639
be socially managed and transmitted), that is, descriptions of situations,
symptoms, and acts (to be performed or avoided) associated with the mul-
tiple threats of the real for which ignorance of the law is no excuse-because
the real is without pity.
The project of a knowledge that would unify this multiplicity of
"things to be known" into a homogeneous representable structure, the idea
of a possible science ofthe structure ofthe real, capable of making it explicit,
outside of any false semblance, and of assuring the control over this real
without the risks of interpretation (therefore a scientific self-reading of the
real, without fault or lack)-this project obviously corresponds to an urgency
so vivid, so universally "human," tied (knotted) so well (around the same
stake of domination/resistance) to the interests of successive masters of this
world, as well as to those of the wretched of the earth, that the phantasm
of such an effective, manageable, and transmissible knowledge could not
fail historically to use any means to make itself materialize.
The promise of a royal science as conceptually rigorous as math-
ematics, as concretely effective as material technologies, as omnipresent as
philosophy and politics-how could humanity resist such a godsend?
-There was the moment of Aristotelian scholasticism that marked
the beginning of the deployment of the categories that structure language
and thought, fashioning the model and organon of any systematization:
disjunctive questions en utrum ("either ... or") considering divinity, the
sex of angels, celestial and terrestrial bodies, plants and animals, all things
known and unknown .... How many catechisms have been structured by
the networks of such scholastic questions and responses?
-There is the modem-contemporary moment of positive rigor
which has appeared in the historical context of the constitution of physics,
chemistry, and biology as sciences, a moment associated with the emergence
of a new form of Law (organized into a set ofpropositions), as well as with
a rebirth of mathematical thought. The result is a new organon, constructed
in opposition to Aristotelianism and based on a reference to the exact sci-
ences, beginning in its tum to homogenize the real, from mathematical logic
to social and administrative spaces, from the experimental hypothetical-
deductive method to the "techniques of the proof."
-And, last but not least, there is the moment of marxist ontology,
pretending for itself to produce the dialectical laws of history and matter;
another organon, partially resembling the two preceding organa and in any
case sharing with them the desire for omnipotence: "the theory of Marx is
all powerful because it is true" (Lenin). As a whole, the workers' movements
have visibly been unable to resist this extraordinary gift of a new unified
philosophy capable of institutionalizing itself efficiently as a critical/orga-
nizational component of the state (whether the existing state or the state to
come). And the basic apparatus of marxist dialectical ontology (with Capital
as the absolute weapon: "the most powerful missile ever thrown at the head
of the bourgeoisie") has shown itself to be capable-like all knowledges of
this unified and homogeneous appearance-of justifying anything in the
name of urgency. 16
Neo-positivism and marxism thus form the major episteme of our time,
entangled in a partially contradictory manner around the stake of the human
640
Michel Picheux
and social sciences, with the question of history at the center, that is, the
question of the possible forms of existence of a science of history.
The point here is not to decide whether or not Capital and the
research that has derived from Capital have produced what I have called
"things to be known." Even for the fiercest adversaries of marxism, the
process of capitalist exploitation, for example, incontestably constitutes a
"thing to be known," and the owners of capital have learned to use it as
much as, and perhaps better than, those they exploit. 17 The same goes for
class struggle and several other "things to be known." The question is, rather,
to determine if the "things to be known" that have emerged from marxism
are capable or not of being organized into a coherent scientific space, in-
tegrated into a systematic montage of concepts, such as the productive forces,
relations of production, social-economic formations, social formations, in-
frastructure and ideological, juridical and political superstructures, state
power, and so on, in the sense that, for example, the Galilean discovery was
capable of constituting the coherent scientific matrix of physics, in the cur-
rent sense of the term. 18
The moment of the Galilean rupture opened the possibility of a
construction of the physical real as a process, following the track of the
impossible proper to this real through the ordered relations combining the
construction of conceptual writings and experimental devices (thus em-
ploying a part of the register of material technologies evoked above). Ac-
cordingly, the first instruments (inclined planes, winches, etc.) used by Gal-
ilean physics were inevitably imported from pre-Galilean technological
spaces; and it is in the development itself of physics that the aforementioned
instruments were transformed, in order to be adapted to the intrinsic ne-
cessities of Galilean physics, with, as a retroactive effect, the indefinitely
enlarged production of industrialized technical objects associated with a
new technical-social division of labor ("scientists," engineers, and techni-
cians), which made physics appear also as a "social science." 19
The intellectual consequences of the Galilean discontinuity are
marked by the fact that for no physicist today is Aristotle a colleague or
even the first physicist: Aristotle is simply a great philosopher. Another
mark of this discontinuity is that Galilean and post-Galilean physics do not
interpret the real-even if, of course, the movement they initiate, the con-
struction of the physical real as process, incessantly becomes the object of
multiple interpretations.
The question I am posing here is that of knowing if Marx may
or may not be considered the Galileo of the "continent ofhistory." 20 Is there
an impossible specific to history, marking structurally that which constitutes
the real? Is there an ordered relationship between the formulation of con-
cepts and the construction of instruments capable of grasping the real? And
can we discern, with the emergence of Marx's thought, a discontinuity such
that the historical real ceases to be the object of divergent interpretations
in order to be constituted in its tum as a process (for example, a "process
without subject or end[s]," according to the famous formula of Althusser)?
The fact ofthe "crisis of marxism" is today sufficiently acknowl-
edged. I can be brief and say that everything leads us to think that the
epistemological discontinuity associated with Marx's discovery has become
extremely precarious and problematic. Marx is neither the first historian
nor the first economist, in the sense that Galileo could be the first physicist:
641
Thucydides, who is apparently not a colleague for the contemporary prac-
titioners of historiography, 21 is without doubt a historian before as well as
after Marx. All we can suppose is that eventually Thucydides would not be
read in the same manner, according to whether or not the reading takes
into account the work of Marx (that is to say, in fact, such and such a
reading of such and such a text signed by Marx, or by Marx and Engels,
etc.). But can we not say exactly the same thing about any great thought
that has emerged out of history? Failing to be the founder of a science of
history, let us say that Marx would be a very great philosopher, as important
as Aristotle.
What would have (and to a certain extent has) happened is that
Marx would be considered the first marxist theoretician, in spite of the
famous phrase with which he rejected the categorizing adjective derived
from his proper name that certain of his contemporaries had already coined
in his lifetime. And the fact that Marx thus refused to recognize himself in
the initial effects associated with the social-historical "reception" of his work
has almost always been understood as a denegation, signifying, in fact, ••I,
Karl Marx, am effectively a marxist, but not in the sense in which it is
commonly understood." It seems to me that the aristocratic thematic of the
"good" reading as opposed to "bad" (banal or fallacious) readings, of the
correct interpretation always held in reserve under erroneous interpreta-
tions, of the truth as a telos of a potentially infinite process of rectification,
begins at this precise point.
The scholastic effects of the division of reading (exoteric/esoteric
reading, Marx read by X/Marx read by Y, etc.), of which marxism had been
the site from the very beginning, with a quasi-indefinite postponement of
the moment of the decisive experience would not be especially surprising.
The impossible proper to the structure of the historical real-that is, the
specific real considered by marxist theory-is probably literally ungraspable
in the "applications" of the aforementioned theory. The same aporetic point
appears in another way: the question of "instruments." If we consider (as
was the case for a century for a not-negligible part of humanity) marxism
as the science of history put into practice by the proletariat, we must admit
that the practitioners of the science in question were constrained to "bor-
row" from the existing (and therefore pre-marxist) social-historical world a
whole series of instruments (institutions, or "apparatuses," forms of orga-
nization and practices, etc.) in order for this science-practice to be consti-
tuted simultaneously as a space of knowledge and a means of intervening
in history.
Insofar as it is a question of intervening in history by obeying
its law (which incidentally presupposes that the "things to be known" con-
cerning history, society, and politics have the structure of laws of the sci-
entific-Galilean type), it is clear that, like the inclined planes and winches
of Galileo, the first "instruments" utilized have been, up to this point,
dissimilar to their new "scientific" goals, inadequate to their transforma-
tional function, in a word, crude (only inveterate utopians can believe that
it is possible to construct ex nihilo such social-political instruments by mag-
ically denying the weight of the past). But the crucial problem is that the
development of the applications of marxism as a science-practice, the new
instruments or apparatuses constructed under its scientific auspices, con-
tinue to resemble, grosso modo, earlier structures-sometimes with aggra-
642
Michel Picheux
vations that are more than accidental: in particular, the same patchwork,
the same false appearance oflogical homogeneity, telescoping the discursive
stability proper to the natural sciences, to the material technologies and to
procedures of administrative management and control, has not ceased to
dominate the different variants of marxism. In other words, to speak bru-
tally, the instruments have not followed theory in its "applications," which
can also be understood as an indication that the science-practice in question
has not (yet?) been correctly applied.
To speak this way is, again, to suppose a "true" marxism in
reserve, a marxism introuvable, 22 that is, basically, to repeat Marx's own
denegation of the interpretation ofhis work; it is to be identified with Marx's
gesture, in what is most defensive about it. So, let us stop protecting Marx
and protecting ourselves through him. Let us stop supposing that the "things
to be known" concerning the social-historical real form a structural system,
analogous to the conceptual-experimental coherence of the Galilean sys-
tem. 23 And let us try to comprehend what this systematic phantasm implies
as a kind of link to "specialists" of all kinds and to the institutions and
state apparatuses that employ them, not in order to place ourselves out of
play, or out of state (!), but so we may think the problem outside of a marxist
denial of interpretation, that is, by facing the fact that history is a discipline
of interpretation and not a physics of a new type.
To Read, To Describe, To Interpret
To raise the question of the existence of a real specific to the
disciplines of interpretation requires that the non-logically stable not be
considered a priori as a lack, or simple hole, in the real. This assumes that-
"the real" understood in various ways-there could exist a real other than
that already evoked, as well as another kind of knowledge that is not re-
ducible to the order of "things to be known" or to a network of such things.
Thus, we have a real that is constitutively foreign to logical univocation
and a knowledge that is not transmitted, learned, or taught but nevertheless
exists in the production of effects.
The intellectual movement that was named "structuralism" (as
it developed, in particular, in France in the sixties, around linguistics, an-
thropology, philosophy, politics, and psychoanalysis) may be considered,
from this point of view, an antipositivist attempt to take into account the
real that thought "bumps into" at the intersection of language and history.
New reading practices (symptomatic, archaeological, etc.) applied to textual
monuments, and initially to the Great Texts (cf. Reading Capital), have
emerged from this movement. The principle on which these readings are
based consists, as we know, in disengaging what is being said "here" (at a
precise place in a text)-said in such a way and no other-from what is being
said elsewhere and in another way, in order to be able to "hear" the presence
of the "unsaid" within what is said.
Assuming that "any fact is already an interpretation" (an anti-
positivist reference to Nietzsche), structuralist approaches made it a point
to describe the textual discursive constructions in their material imbrication.
And paradoxically, they, in this manner, set aside the production of inter-
pretations (of representations of contents, of Vorstellungen) in favor of de-
scription per se (Darstellung) of these constructions. It was in this way that
structuralist approaches expressed their refusal to be constituted as a "royal
643
science" of the structure of the real. Nonetheless, we will see in a moment
how they were able, in their tum, to be seduced by this phantasm, only to
end up appearing as a new "royal science." But first it is necessary to stress
the fact that in the names of Marx, Freud, and Saussure a new theoretical
foundation, politically heterogeneous, took shape, leading to a critical con-
struction that shattered the literary evidence of"lived" authenticity, as well
as the "scientific" certitudes of positivist functionalism.
I recall how, at the beginning of Reading Capital, Althusser marked
the encounter of these three fields: "Only since Freud have we begun to
suspect what listening and hence what speaking (and keeping silence) means
(veut dire); that this 'meaning' (vouloir-dire) of speaking and listening dis-
closes, beneath the innocence of speech and hearing, the specifiable depth
of a hidden level, the 'meaning' of the discourse of unconscious-that level
whose effects and formal conditions are thought by modem linguistics." 24
The subversive effect of the trilogy Marx-Freud-Saussure was an intellectual
challenge that held out the promise of a cultural revolution that would call
into question the evidence of the human order as a strictly biosocial order.
To restore something of the specific work of the letter, the symbol,
and the trace was to begin to open up a fault within the compact block of
pedagogies, industrial and biomedical technologies, and moralizing hu-
manisms or religions. It was to call into question the direct articulation of
the biological and the social (an articulation that excluded the symbolic and
the signifier from the real). It was an attack on the individual and the
collective narcissism of human consciousness (c£ Spinoza in his time), an
attack on the eternal negotiation of the "self' (as master/slave of its action,
speech, and thought) in its relation to the other self. In a word, the struc-
turalist cultural revolution never ceased to attack the psychological register
(and the psychologies-of the "self," of "consciousness," of "behavior," or
of the "epistemic" subject). This attack was not engendered by the hatred
of humanity that was often attributed to structuralism. It was only the
consequence of the recognition of a structural fact proper to the human
order: that of symbolic castration.
But at the same time, this antinarcissistic movement (whose po-
litical and cultural effects have obviously not been exhausted) turned toward
a new form of theoretical narcissism-a narcissism of structure. This the-
oretical narcissism may be marked in the structuralist tendency to reinscribe
its "readings" in the unified space of a conceptual logic. Thus, the suspension
of interpretation (associated with the descriptive gestures of the reading of
textual constructions) topples over into a sort of structural overinterpre-
tation of the montage as the effect of the whole: this overinterpretation used
the "theoretical" level as a kind of metalanguage, organized in a network
of paradigms. Structuralist overinterpretation then functions as a translating
device, transposing "common empirical statements" into "conceptual struc-
tural statements." The mode of functioning of structural analysis (and in
particular of what could be called structural materialism or political struc-
turalism) remains secretly governed by the general model of interpretative
equivalence. To schematize this, take the empirical statement PI (for ex-
ample, "The face of existing socialism is distorted"): ... PI, in fact, means
nothing else but ... theoretically comes to say that ... in other words ...
that is to say ... the theoretical statement P2 (for example, "Bourgeois
ideology dominates marxist theory"). It is above all this state of theoretical
644
Michel Picheux
overhang, the allure of a discourse without a subject simulating mathe-
matical processes, that conferred on structuralist approaches the appearance
of a new "royal science," denying, as usual, its own interpretative position.
The paradox of the early 1980s is that the bogging down ofFrench
political structuralism, its breakdown as a "royal science" (that nevertheless
continues to produce effects, notably in Latin America), coincides with the
growing acknowledgment of the works of Levi-Strauss, Lacan, Barthes, Der-
rida, and Foucault in the Anglo-Saxon countries-in England, West Ger-
many, as well as in the United States. By a strange seesaw effect, at the
precise moment that America discovers structuralism, the French intelli-
gentsia "turns the page" by developing a massive ressentiment ofthe theories
suspected of having spoken in the name of the masses, while producing a
long series of inefficient symbolic acts and unhappy political performatives.
This ressentiment is the effect of a profound movement "from below," a
sort of ideological backlash necessitating reflection, and must not be con-
fused with the cowardly relief of many French intellectuals who react by
discovering retroactively that "theory" has "intimidated" them.
The· biggest strength of this critical reexamination is that it calls
into question the theoretical "heights" of political structuralism, the am-
bition to construct a relation to the state (eventually, its identification with
the state-and especially with the party-state of the revolution). This back-
lash has forced us to look toward what is happening "below," in the infra-
ecstatic space that constitutes the ordinary of the masses, especially in a
period of crisis. It is becoming increasingly obvious that-in history, soci-
ology, and literary studies-we must learn to listen to this often silent speech
enclosed within the urgency of survival. We must do more than read (or
reread) the Great Works (of science, law, and the state). We must hear the
articulations embedded in the "ordinary way" ofmeaning. 25 But at the same
time, the risks of this movement are quite clear, especially the risk of fol-
lowing the greatest ideological slope, of conceiving the "ordinary way of
meaning" as a natural psychobiological process inscribed in a logically sta-
bilized discursivity. Hence, the risk of a tremendous regression toward pos-
itivism and the philosophies of consciousness.
A meeting such as this could be an opportunity to evade some
ofthese risks, if we can determine the stakes involved and situate the major
points of encounter. As far as I am concerned (but I am expressing a point
of view here that is not mine alone: it is a working position that is developing
in France today), I will point out the strong interest of a theoretical and
procedural rapprochement between practices of "ordinary language analy-
sis" (within the antipositivistic perspective that may be drawn from Witt-
genstein's work) and "reading" practices derived from structuralist ap-
proaches. 26 Taken seriously (i.e., other than as a mere "cultural exchange"),
this rapprochement involves, in a concrete manner, ways of working on the
discursive materialities implied in ideological rituals, philosophical dis-
courses, political statements, and aesthetic and cultural forms, through their
relations to everday life, to "the ordinary" of meaning. This project can
only become consistent if it prudently avoids any present or future "royal
science" (either positivism or marxist ontologies).
This work pattern imposes a certain number of necessities that
must be explained in detail and that I can only mention briefly in closing.
The first necessity consists in giving priority to descriptions of discursive
645
materialities. According to this perspective, description is not a phenome-
nological or hermeneutical apprehension in which it indiscernibly becomes
interpretation; such a conception of description implies, on the contrary,
the recognition of the specific real on which it leans: the real of langue (cf.
J. C. Milner, especially in L'amour de Ia langue). And I say Ia langue, that
is, neither language, speech, discourse, text, nor conversational interaction
but rather what has been put forward by linguists as the condition for ex-
istence (in principle), in the form of the existence of the Symbolic as Ja-
kobson and Lacan understood it.
Certain recent tendencies in linguistics are rather encouraging
from this point of view. Beyond Harrisian distributionalism and Chom-
skyan generativism, trends have emerged that question the primacy of log-
ical proposition as well as the limitations imposed on linguistic analysis as
sentence analysis. Thus, linguistic research might begin to free itself from
its obsession with ambiguity (meant as the logic of "either ... or") in order
to reach what is proper to langue through the role of equivocity, ellipsis,
lack, and so on. This play of differences, alternations, and contradictions
cannot be seen as the softening of some logical hard core: the equivocation,
the "constitutive heterogeneity" (J. Authier) oflangue corresponds to Mil-
ner's "declarations of faith" 27 : "Nothing of poetry is foreign to Langue";
and "No language can be completely thought out without integrating the
possibility of its poetry." This imposes on linguistic research the construc-
tion of procedures (the modes of questioning facts and the forms of rea-
soning) capable of explicitly approaching the linguistic fact of equivocity as
a structural fact implied by the symbolic order; that is, the necessity of
working up to the point at which logical representations (inscribed in the
"normal world") cease to be consistent. This is also the argument Francois
Gadet and I developed in La langue introuvable.
The object of linguistics, that which is proper to langue, thus
appears to be traversed by a discursive division between two spaces: that
ofthe manipulation of stabilized significations, normalized by a pedagogical
hygiene of thought, and that of the transformation of meaning escaping
from all a priori assignable norms, the work of meaning on meaning, grasped
in an indefinite "rebirth" of interpretations. The frontier between the two
fields is difficult to determine in that there exists a whole intermediate zone
of discursive processes (related to the juridical, to the administrative, and
to the conventions of daily life) oscillating around it. And it is in this in-
termediary discursive region that the logical properties of objects cease to
function: objects both have and do not have such and such a property;
events both have and have not occurred according to the discursive con-
structions within which the statements that support these objects and events
are found to be inscribed. 28 The fluctuating and paradoxical character of the
ordinary register of meaning appears to have almost completely escaped the
philosophical perception of the structuralist movement. This register has
been the object of a theoretical aversion that has enclosed it globally in the
inferno of the dominant ideology and practical empiricism. It has been
considered as the blind point of a pure reproduction of meaning. 29
In doing so, the structuralists were giving credence to the idea
that the process of transformation internal to symbolic and ideological spaces
is an exceptional process: the solitary, heroic moment of theory and poetry
(Marx-Mallarme) as the "extraordinary" work of the signifier. This aristo-
646
Michel Pecheux
cratic conception, giving itself, de facto, a monopoly on the second field
(that oflogically nonstabilized discursivities), remained the prisoner-even
in its "proletarian" reversal-of the old elitist certitude that the dominated
masses never invent anything because they are too absorbed in the logic of
everyday life. Ultimately, the proletariat, the masses, the people, have such
a vital need for logically stabilized universes that the play of the symbolic
order does not concern them at all! On this precise point, the theoretical-
poetic position of the structuralist movement is insupportable. 30 And in
failing to discern how humor and poetry are not the "Sunday of thought,"
but belong to the fundamental elasticity of political and theoretical intel-
ligence, this movement had already given in to the populist argument of
urgency, since it implicitly shared its essential presupposition: the proletariat
has no (time for the luxury of the) unconscious!
From what precedes, it follows that any description (it does not
change anything whether it is a description of objects or events, or a de-
scription of a discursive-textual construction, as long as we hold firmly that
"there is no metalanguage") is intrinsically exposed to the equivocity of
langue: any utterance is intrinsically able to become other than itself, to
split discursively from its meaning, to be diverted toward another (except
if the prohibition of interpretation proper to the logically stable is applied
to it). Any utterance or sequence of utterances is thus linguistically describ-
able as a series (lexico-syntactically determined) of possible points of di-
version, leaving room for interpretation. It is in this space that discourse
analysis claims to work.
It is here that one finds, once again, the matter of disciplines of
interpretation: because there is something of the "other" in societies and in
history, a link (identification or transference) corresponding to this "other"
proper to discursivity is possible, that is, a relation that opens up the pos-
sibility of interpretation. And it is because this link exists that historical
filiation can be organized into memories and social relations into networks
of signifiers. Hence the fact that the "things to be known" mentioned before
are never visible from above like the historical transcendentals of the ep-
isteme in Foucault's sense. They are always entangled in memory networks
that lead to identificatory filiations and never to a learning through inter-
action: the transference is in no way an "interaction," and the historical
filiations in which individuals are inscribed are by no means "learning ma-
chines."
From this perspective, the main point is to determine in the
practice of discourse analysis the place and time of interpretation in relation
to description. To say it is not a question of two successive phases, but
rather of an alternation or a pulsation, does not imply that description and
interpretation are condemned to lose themselves in the indescernible. On
the other hand, to say that any description opens onto interpretation is not
necessarily to assume that it opens onto "anything." The description of an
utterance or a sequence necessarily involves (through the detection of empty
syntactical places, ellipses, initiation of negations and interrogation, of var-
ious forms of indirect discourse) some "other" discourse as the virtual space
of a reading of the utterance or sequence. And it is this discursive otherness
as virtual presence within the describable materiality of the sequence that
marks from within this materiality the insistence of the other as the law of
social space and historical memory, and thus as the very principle of the
647
social-historical real, a fact that justifies the use of the term "discipline of
interpretation" a propos of disciplines working within this register.
The crucial point is that, within the transferential spaces of iden-
tification, constituting a contradictory plurality ofhistorical filiations (through
speech, images, stories, discourses, texts, etc.), the "things to be known"
coexist with objects about which no one can be sure of "knowing what one
is talking about" for the very good reason that these objects inscribed within
a filiation are by no means the products of learning-and this happens in
the secrecy of the private sphere of the family as well as at the "public"
level of institutions and state apparatuses. The phantasm of "royal science"
is precisely what comes to deny-at all levels-this equivocity by giving the
illusion that one may always know what one is talking about-that is, if you
understand what I mean-by denying the act of interpretation at the very
moment it occurs.
This point leads to the final question of discursivity as structure
or event. From what precedes, one may say that the act that consists in
inscribing a given discourse in a series, in incorporating it in a corpus, always
risks absorbing the event of this discourse into the structure of the series
insofar as this series tends to function as a historical transcendental reading
grid or anticipatory memory of the discourse in question. The notion of
"discursive formation" borrowed from Foucault has too often drifted toward
the ideas of a discursive machine of subjection fitted with an internal semi-
otic structure and therefore bound to be repetitive. At the limit, this struc-
tural conception of discursivity would lead to an obliteration of the event
through its absorption in anticipatory overinterpretation.
One should not pretend that any discourse would be a miraculous
aerolite, independent of networks of memory and the social trajectories
within which it erupts. But the fact that should be stressed here is that a
discourse, by its very existence, marks the possibility of a destructuring-
restructuring of these networks and trajectories. Any given discourse is the
potential sign of a movement within the sociohistorical filiations of iden-
tification, inasmuch as it constitutes, at the same time, a result of these
filiations and the work (more or less conscious, deliberate, and constructed
or not, but all the same traversed by unconscious determination) of dis-
placement within their space: there is no completely "successful" identifi-
cation; that is, there is no sociohistoricallink that is not affected in any way
by an "infelicity" in the performative sense of the term-in these circum-
stances, by a "tragic error" about the other as object of identification. This
may even be one of the reasons why such things as societies and history
exist instead of merely a chaotic juxtaposition (or a perfect supra-organic
integration) of human animals in interaction.
The working position that I evoke here in reference to discourse
analysis by no means implies the possibility of some calculation of the
displacements of filiation or of the conditions of factual felicity or infelicity.
It merely supposes that, through ordered descriptions of discursive con-
structions, it is possible to detect moments of interpretation as acts that
emerge in the form of explicit viewpoints recognized as such; that is, as
effects of identifications that are assumed and not denied. Before boundless
interpretations in which the interpreter acts as an absolute point, without
any other or real, it is for me a matter of ethics and politics: a question of
responsibility.
648
Michel Picheux
Notes
649
constructions are found to be writing itself. The real of the material technologies partially
overlaps wiih the real of the natural sciences insofar as these technologies constitute an
indispensable element in experimentation. At the same time, the massive use of technical
objects surpasses the real of natural science: the relation to logical disjunction turns away
from magical gestures (with their rites, taboos, and prohibitions). Concerning the real of the
managerial sciences, which often presents itself as a technical real of a particular type (the
"social technologies"). it is fundamentally a prohibition even if it is based, especially in
industrialized societies. on the real of the technologies, as well as that of the sciences of
nature, find1ng there the means to manage both the immense register of production and the
register of destruction.
13 "The practical law. derived from the motive of happiness, I call pragmatical (rule of prudence)"
(Kant, Cntique of Pure Reason).
14 For work on the art of memory, cf. F. Yates. The Art of Memory (London, 1966).
15 Once the barn is set on fire. the conflagration spreads according to the structure of the
building and its openings, according to the nature and disposition of the objects and materials
that the building contains. to the direction of the wind, and so on, not according to the desire
of the arsonist (for revenge, etc.).
16 "To JUStify" is not the same things as "to produce." Scholasticism did not produce the
Inquisition; marxism did not engender the Gulag; nee-positivism did not invent voluntary
servitude or the desire for universal scientific domination. But the capacity of such philo-
sophical systems for JUStification is incontestible.
17 It little matters. in passing, that these knowledges are denied: everyone takes them into
account, just as a pedestnan crossing the street takes the cars into account in order to avoid
being hit. even 1f he or she is a professed philosophical idealist!
18 Cf. the discontinuist perspective inaugurated by the work of Alexandre Koyre in opposition
to the continuism of Duhem.
19 Jean-Marc Levy-Leblond. L 'esprit de set (Pans: Fayard, 1981 ).
20 This quest1on received an explicitly affirmative response in the framework of "historical struc-
turalism" from Althusser's early work. which posed historical materialism as "the science of
history."
21 I am alluding here to a recent art1cle by h1storian N1cole Loraux. "Thucydide n 'est pas un
collegue, " Ouaderni d1 stona 12, 1980. pp 51 -81 .
22 This expression takes up the title of a book by D. Lindenberg, Le marxisme introuvable (Paris,
1975). wh1ch surveys some of the historical avatars of this game of hide-and-seek between
the "scientific marxism" of the university and "vulgar marxism" (which produces catechisms
for mass consumption). What is called "Anglo-American neo-marxism" is largely, in 1ts pres-
ent state. an academic phenomenon (linked in large part to the collapse of European political
structuralism), that is, a marxism "without organs," except intellectual organs-which is not
to say that with the help of the "pragmatic" spirit of Anglo-American culture, this phenom-
enon will be Without repercussions in the cultural, ideological. and political fields. and that it
does not hold some surprises for those who are celebrating "the end of marxism!"
23 An expression like "the logic of capital" refers to a real about which there are "things to be
known." But 1s 1t conceivable to respond with a "yes" or "no" to total questions such as.
Is the current French government attacking the logic of capital? or even, Have we in the
exact sense of the term "seized power"? See Jacques Mandrin, Le socialisme et Ia France.
24 L. Althusser, Reading Capital (London: New Left Books, 1979). p. 16.
25 Cf. Michel de Certeau, L 'invention du quotidien (Paris: 10/18, UGE, 1980).
26 For more on current developments in discourse analysis in France, see the review Mots (4:6)
and the collection Materia/ites discoursives (m part1cular. J. J. Courtine and J.-M. Maradin,
"Que/ objet pour !'analyse de discours," and A. Lecomte, "La frontiere absente'}.
27 Jean-Claude Milner, Ordre et raisons de langue (Paris: Seuil, 1983). p. 336.
28 Cf. earlier remarks concerning the possible associable referents of the statement On a gagne.
We might develop Similar remarks about such expressions as "the will of the people,"
"freedom" (of thought or of the market), "austerity" versus "rigor," and so on.
29 This problem constitutes one of the weak points of the Althusserian reflection on the ideo-
logical state apparatus, as well as of the initial applications of this reflection in the domain
of discourse analysis m France.
30 A hatred of the ordinary gives rise to an anti-intellectual cult of this same ordinary: a certain
esoteric structuralism nourished the hatred of philosophy expressed, for example, in the
sociology of Pierre Bourdieu.
650
Hugo Achugar
660
Hugo Achugar
American poetry reinserts itself into the aesthetic hegemony. This joint
social enunciation of projects, in either its explicit or implicit versions, in
the last three decades has provoked a resemanticization ofbooks of poems.
Consequently, the aesthetic-ideological norm to which it responds (and which
is proposed to the Hispanic American reader) acquires a rigidity and co-
herence more orthodox than what seems to occur in isolated books.
The contemporary Hispanic American book of poems seduces,
convinces, indoctrinates, and conquers anonymous readers through an ar-
ticulation of the poetic system that does not always succeed in foregrounding
the peculiarities of heterogeneous discourses. In this sense, the book of
poems does not succeed in escaping the sociohistorical enunciating situation.
Yet this failure reveals it to be a social act within the real (i.e., not symbolic)
struggle for what Marti has called "Nuestra America."
Notes
1 I use "book of poems" as a translation for the Spanish word poemario, which emphasizes
the notion of wholeness.
2 I could also mention other than Hispanic American authors who have written on poetic
production, such as Heidegger, Pfeiffer, Cohen, Della Volpe, Thompson, Adorno, Friedrich,
Riffaterre, and Easthope. These authors and the Spanish Americans Reyes and Portuondo
speak at two levels: ( 1) considering the poem as a self-sufficient or independent entity, and
(2) at the level of the general poetic discourse (i.e., a precise poet's complete work or the
poetic language), as different from the colloquial, narrative, or scientific language.
3 See Raquel Chang Rodriguez, "Epistola inedita de Pedro Carvajal, poeta de Ia Academia
Antartica," Revista de critica literaria Latinoamericana, 3 ( 1976).
4 The term is from Volosinov's 1/linguaggio come pratica soc1ale (Bari: Dedali Libri, 1980). in
wh1ch he uses the notion of situazione di enonziazione. For a more complete discussion of
the notion of "situation," see Claude Germain, The Concept of Situation in Linguistics (Ot-
tawa: University of Ottawa Press, 1979).
5 I have used the term "basic speaker" (hablante basico) before, in ldeologias v estructuras
narrativas en Jose Donoso: 1950-70 (Caracas: Celarg, 1979). At that time, I referred to
Booth's "implied author" and to similar notions proposed by Jan Mukarovsky and Miroslav
Cervenka. In Latin America the same notion has been used by Antonio CorneJo Polar, Nelson
Osorio, and lately by Jav1er Lasarte, who has proposed the use of "basic enunciator" (en-
unciador bilsico).
6 It could also be said, considering the heterogeneity of a discourse or its polyphony, that the
book of poems offers a multiplicity of not always coincidental perspectives.
7 Even the chronological organization, apparently innocent and naive, of the book of poems is
a special case of syntax and never its denial. In the event of poesia permutante (permutating
poetry). which Cortazar includes in Ultimo round, we might talk about a heterodox syntax.
Its own condition of "violation of pattern" syntax allows us to discover a peculiar syntactic
project. See Ultimo round (Mexico: Siglo XXI, 1972). pp. 272-73.
8 It is this syntactic order, for instance, that bestows a special significance on the introductory
poem or group of poems and becomes a sort of "reading art." Whether its function is to
train the reader or to design a particular cultural-ideological unit this syntactic order will
function within the book of poems as the "rule" to be developed or deconstructed. In this
view we could even talk about .. catalytic poems," borrowing Barthes' s terminology, perhaps
drawing attention to the function of the final poem or group of poems, which often provide
a syntactic closure to the book of poems.
9 See Umberto Eco, Trattato generale di semiotica (Milano: Bompiani. 1975); Thomas Lewis,
"Notes toward a Theory of Literary Referent" PMLA. 94:3 (1979). pp. 459-75.
10 Although it is not explicitly described, this work does take into account the characteristics
of a popular poetic system (e.g., songs, children's literature, rural traditions. and workers'
poems) where it proposes notions of poetry effective within the social totality of the enun-
ciating situation in which the learned system makes itself.
11 Cf. Edoardo Sanguinetti, Vanguardia, ideologia v lenguaje (Caracas: Monte Avila, 1969). p.
13.
661
12 Ala1stair Fowler. "Genre and the Literary Canon," NLH, 11: 1 ( 1979). p. 98.
13 Marta Traba, "La cultura de Ia Resistencia," Ltteratura v praxis en Amenca Latina (Caracas:
Monte Avila, 1974).
14 Fowler, p. 98.
15 This situation was not free from the particular developments of the productive apparatuses
of the nations as well as of their national literatures.
16 One could mention Atlantida, Claridad, Revista de Occidente, Porrua, Espasa Calpe, Sur,
Emece, Zig-Zag, Tor, Nasctmento v Ercilla. Losada deserves to be pointed out as particularly
open-minded, in both ideological and aesthetic terms.
17 The statistical data place the hegemonic period of the Argentinian publishing houses in the
forties. During 1950, 50 percent of the Latin American market was supported by Argentina,
a status that would drastically change by 1972 "when its participation becomes 15%." See
Argentina, Brasil, Mexico (Bogota: Cerlai-UNESCO. 1980). pp. 7-8.
18 The importance of the publishing work in this period becomes evident in the fact that pub-
lishers held conferences in 1946 (Santiago, Chile). 1948 (Buenos A1res). and 1964 (Mexico)
to create cohesion and organization in support of the "principle of copyright of books in the
Spanish language for countries that speak that language" (Argentina, Brasil. Mexico, p. 35).
While this was an anti-imperialist defense. 1t was brought about by a kind of Hispanic "Monroe
doctrine" of culture that eliminated transnational competition. Competition remained relative
since some of the major publishers. such as Espasa-Calpe, had parent companies in Madrid.
Buenos Aires, and Mexico.
19 The surrealist axis, Buenos Aires-Mexico-Santiago, also had its part, though less important.
20 I could also mention Area, La Rosa Blindada, Galerna, Joaquin Mortiz, Techo de Ia Ballena,
and Marcha from Montevideo.
21 Santiago Luppoli asserts that "the systematic study of the current poets becomes more
difficult every time, since the logical task-ranging them according to their stylistic, ideological,
and renewal patterns-Is almost unapproachable.·· See Handbook of Latin American Studies:
Humanities. no. 36 (Gamsv1lle: University of Florida Press, 1974). p. 411.
662
Darko Suvin
1.1
Before getting into the inevitably somewhat special-
ized arguments, I want to discuss their intertext, which I suggest in my title
by way of the possibilities lurking within both "people" and "(re)present."
This intertext, or practical context, is situated at the interface between fic-
tional and other ways of viewing, interpreting, and constructing reality.
1.2
"People" (gens, Leute) means, of course, something
like women plus men plus children; it does not denote THE people (le peuple,
das Volk). This essay will focus on the images of people rather than on the
interests ofthe people that can be found (re)presented in fiction. Nonetheless,
these overlapping connotations are an important signal, for the way people
are presented in literature will intimately codetermine what interests that
literature might re-present. The stakes, therefore, are very high-both for
Marxian critics dealing with culture and for the fate of fiction itself. This
subject is a privileged way of entering into and indicating an answer to these
radical democratic and socialist questions: Is fiction more than opium for
663
(the) people? Is it also-as this usually truncated text of Marx continues-
the heart of a heartless world? Is fiction only ideology or also Utopia and/
or cognition? Is there, then, a cognitive (and thus politically usable and
ethically justifiable) reason for a radical critic to investigate fiction-be it
Shakespeare or "Dallas," Homer or science fiction, Proust or Piercy, comic
strips or Brecht-especially when that will involve a halfway conscientious
critic in the indispensable mediations of the meta-meta-discourses of mod-
ern criticism, thus leaving less time for more direct radical action?
Many radicals throughout the years have come, with reluctance
or enthusiasm, to share with pragmatists and philistines the conclusion that
there is NO such reason, that a radical cultural critic is an oxymoron of the
order of fiery ice or planned disorder. Nikolai Chernyshevsky, the leader of
Russian revolutionary populism, said somewhere (the image was to recur
in the Soviet debates) that sausages came before Shakespeare. From a vulgar
materialist (bourgeois as well as "socialist") point of view, this is undeniable:
people cannot exist without eating; they can exist without fiction.
Yet, can they? In the depths of the 1930s depression, did not
Hollywood thrive on perverting the pennies of millions of jobless people
into profits from soap-opera movies? Does not every halfway intelligent
regime in economic-political difficulties buttress itself through the most pop-
ular forms of fiction at the same time (if not before) it tries political solu-
tions? The genres vary: in Elizabethan times it was theater, street ballads,
or preachings (even technically speaking these are largely fictional); in the
nineteenth century, popular novels; today, TV. The orientation remains
constant. The biblical author had better food imagery than Chernyshevsky:
not by bread alone but also by fictional images-which explain why bread
is or is not there, why pie in the sky will come by and by-liveth man and
woman.
Thus, to continue with examples from revolutionary leaders, it
was not only Che Guevara who might have thought that machine guns were
more important than speeches, nor only Mao Tse-tung that working in
peoples' actions (in the sense that a sculptor works in marble) was more
important than working in poems. Many pragmatists with less flair for
insurrection or liberating politics take such an attitude unthinkingly. Let
me call this operative attitude (or gesture, in Brecht's sense of Gestus) by
the name of, arguably, the greatest nineteenth-century poet, also a Com-
munard, who very early on abandoned poem writing for gunrunning: it is
the Rimbaud Syndrome. I do not maintain that Che or Mao took the wrong
decisions for themselves-that would be ignorant and presumptuous. But I
do maintain that when the Rimbaud Syndrome is adopted as a norm im-
posed on all possible future Rimbauds, it is pernicious. All of us who have
worked within movements aspiring to radical democracy and economic
justice, including movements claiming Marxist ascendancies, remember well
how our eccentric involvement with not immediately operative sign sys-
tems-in particular with fiction-met in general with two responses: either
with hostility, or, in the case of our most well meaning and shrewd comrades
outside the cultural (wordsmithing, picture making, and similar) trades, with
the pitying smile of forbearance for childish pursuits. (Indeed, I seem to
detect some echoes of the Rimbaud Syndrome in this conference, where
according to my count one can find one and one-third session out of thirteen,
or 10 percent, devoted to fictional communication.)
664
Darko Suvin
Yet kulturshchiks (the Russian term from such debates) have a
good deal of historical irony to fall back upon. Thus, Chemyshevsky's main
positive influence was not in his failed revolutionary action but in his writ-
ings, in particular in a fictional text called What Is to Be Done? (1865),
which forty years later inspired a young man called Volodya Ulyanov to
write a nonfictional text of the same title, setting out the theory of a future
Leninist party (hardly an ineffective text). Ten years after the second What
Is to Be Done? its author, then already V. I. Lenin, would interrupt his
possibly most important and certainly most utopian piece of wordsmithing
(called The State and the Revolution) with a concluding statement that it is
better to make a revolution than write about it. What I am arguing is not
that he was wrong but that he was (necessarily) oversimplifying: that without
Chemyshevsky's fiction as well as Chemyshevsky's organizational tradition
(which led to Ulyanov's elder brother being executed by tsarism) many
central features of the united theory and practice of Leninism would not
have existed in the same form. And one thing a good look at fiction and
art in general-which fuses conceptualization with sensuality-can teach us
is that phenomena only exist in given forms: not to exist in a given way
means not to exist.
Let me go on with the historical record, to Che Guevara and
Mao Zedong. I cannot even hint at the richness of their lives' work, but I
wish to isolate one important lesson to be drawn from them: what survives
after a generation. A large part of what survives from such lives are narrative
images, agents with actions. Che is in this domain surviving as something
like a Marxist version of an Arthurian or Spenserian Knight of Justice,
giving his life for the cause, a revolutionary Christ-like intercessor for the
oppressed. This image is so potent that even Hollywood felt compelled to
attempt co-opting and neutralizing it. Similarly, Mao is increasingly becom-
ing a twofold narrative agent: the writer of certain kinds of texts and an
imaginary type within global political discourse (the leader of the Long
March, the speaker at Yenan, the swimmer in the Yangtze, etc.). It is not
that the practice or praxis of fiction is better than, but merely that it is
indispensable for and indispensably allied with, the praxis of revolutionary
change. Indeed, fiction or narrative (in the wide sense of telling a story with
agents and space/time, which englobes equally what the old theories called
epic, lyric, and dramatic fiction) is inextricably enmeshed with all social
practice. If any ideology or movement pretends to kick narrative and images
borrowed from fiction out the front door, they will return by the cellar
window. Surely it would be better to do knowingly what you have to do
anyway; for only thus, as Hegel said, do you truly do that. Furthermore,
only thus can what you do be consciously controlled and corrected.
1.3
This is not to deny that the Rimbaud Syndrome remains a very
important and open, particular historical (as different from general theo-
retical) question. But it, too, is an important question because, before the
gunrunning, Rimbaud had an unsurpassed way with words, in his case
organized into verse images and narratives.
It might have become apparent that my title conceals some basic
choices. Along with the connotational resonance between people (plural)
and the people (collective singular), another, more polarized choice is whether
665
either is being-is to be-" re-presented" or "represented," or indeed simply
••presented."
Re-presenting I take to refer to a supposed copying from or re-
flection of a supposedly otherwise known external reality. Two minutes'
thought suffices to render this untenable in any literal form, so it is quickly
provided with a codicil to the effect that a subjective prism is interposed
between the objective reality and the image of (the) people. Then it turns
out that a norm for the rightness of that prismatic refraction must be found
in order to obviate the possible multiplicity of prisms (say, avant-gardist or
mystical as against "realistic") and that the normative prism is that of the
ruling ideology-be it socialist-realism or the awful capitalist-realism we can
see in the halls of any U.S. university in the form of paintings of presidents
and board chairmen. This, in short, is a static, conformist, Philistine theory
of artistic mimesis, banal and without much interest.
However, if people are represented in fiction as a selection, con-
densation, and displacement of surface empirical events and the ruling ide-
ological way of seeing them, if they are seen as in a partially steerable
daydream, then representation or mimesis is not to be understood as simple
copying. No doubt, any thinking is based on models. But representation in
fiction is then a process of taking model images of people from nonfictional
ways of understanding and of reconstructing social reality into a process
that (in ideal cases) develops roughly as follows: The new images go about
subverting the heretofore received fictional norms of agential structuring,
but as this is happening, the images themselves are in turn modified in and
by some autonomous principles of fictional structuring. All of this together
enables the resulting views of relationships among people, elaborated by the
restructured piece of fiction, to return into our understanding of reality or
ideology with a cognitive increment. This better understanding permits what
Brecht called interventionary, effective, or engaged thinking (in the technical
sense of meshing or being in gear). For Brecht, an image or model of a
person can be drawn up, into which might be inserted attitudes that the
person observed might not have found by him/herself: "but these imputed
ways of behavior do not remain the observer's illusions; they turn to real-
ities: the image has become productive, it can change the person modelled,
it contains (realizable) proposals. To make such an image means to love"
(Brecht, 20: 170). The great Brechtian, and indeed Marxian, theme of a pro-
ductive or creative eros has been formulated before and better than in all
the privatized jouissances.
Indeed, at this point the mimetic ambiguity of "representing"
(which dominates present-day views) should probably be abandoned for the
more productive and communicative two-way duplicity of "presenting":
presenting images taken from outside fiction as propositions or formative
hypotheses for a narrative, but also presenting images transmogrified within
fiction as proposals to the pragmatic world. Even in the best case of "re-
alism," representing suggests standing in for something that already exists,
as a democratic binding mandate represents the opinions of the mandate-
givers. Presenting may in the best, Brechtian case suggest instead erotic
increment and plasticity. The roundabout route of art and fiction could thus
hide a long-range operativity, intervention, or use value after all. That it
does so, and that a horizon can be indicated within which it does so, is the
argument of my essay. For if it does not, if people cannot be represented
666
Darko Suvin
in fiction, a great part of the humanist and radical passion that is inalienably
allied to a need of changing people's lives, of modifying the relationships
among people, would be irrelevant to fiction, and fiction would indeed be
irrelevant to it. To expand a remark of Brecht's about drama: if people do
not fit (let me add what Brecht presupposed: in however autonomous ways)
into the worlds of fiction, then fiction does not fit into the world of people.
1.4
Perhaps I could cap my introductory argument by two axioms
and their respective corollaries.
First axiom: We need a materialist approach. Our matter is in
this case social discourse provisionally fixed in texts that interact with frames
of acceptance and nonacceptance (ideologies). Therefore, any hypothesis to
be tried out has to be verifiable through ensembles oftexts in interaction with
"reading" frames. This verifiability implies (a) that there exists both a pos-
sibility of falsification and a need for a readiness to alter the hypothesis;
and (b) (an application of Occam's razor) that the explainability ofthe text
by means of the initial hypothesis is either equal or superior to the explain-
ability by means of any previous, insufficiently materialist hypothesis. In
short, hypotheses and text-ensembles-cum-reading-frames are partners or
use values.
First corollary: An anecedote has it that Matisse once showed a
painting of his to a visitor, who exclaimed he/she had never seen a woman
like that, to which the painter answered: "It is not a woman, it is a picture."
The material pertinent to re-presenting people in fiction (and all texts) is
not people but words, sentences, and what they imply in interaction with
reading frames. More particularly, this material is (some equivalent of) a
nominal syntagma with a given place in the story-just as the pertinent
materials in Matisse's painting are colors and lines with a place inside a
frame. Paradoxically, all the lessons of Russian formalism, without which
we cannot begin making sense of fiction, belong here under the heading of
materialism (albeit a partial and inconsistent, not yet a dialectical one).
Formalism is the A and B of any integrally materialist approach to art, from
which we should then proceed to C, D, and so on.
Second axiom: We need a dialectical approach. If social discourse
is provisionally fixed in texts that interact with reading frames or ideologies,
then all texts are incomplete products that freeze an ongoing intertextual
process. Such textual and metatextual dialogues form unceasing strategies
of discourse between large human groups within a society. Therefore, no
text can be even correctly read without filling in the concavities it designs
by its own convexity, without taking into account the significant presup-
positions present within the textual positions. In matters pertinent to the re-
presentation of people in fiction, these presuppositions are attitudes toward
people that are possible at the historical moment of the text's freezing. In
the first axiom and corollary, materialism means the central position of a
material consisting of words and propositions combined in "transphrastic"
(more than sentence-length) text-ensembles; in this second axiom dialectic
means socially, ideologically precise historical differentiation.
Second corollary: The narrative agents of fiction (to be defined
more closely in part 3) will be re-creations not of actual or imaginary people
but of given historically possible attitudes toward animate and active en-
667
tities. Just as in painting, where such attitudes are subject to the possibilities
of color, line, and their disposition in two-dimensional space pretending to
a third dimension, so in fiction the transposition of extraliterary attitudes
will be shaped not only by given ideological interests but also by longue
duree rules of language material, textual coherence, as well as fictional and
general ideological conventions. Longue duree does not mean ahistorical:
it just complicates our materialist analysis with welcome historical dialectics
of culture. In strange and imperfectly understood ways, Homer's sun still
shines on us. Paradoxically, images of people can be modified out of all
empirical or naked-eye recognition-for example, into gods, talking animals,
allegorical notions or disembodied narrative voices-yet still remain fabular
transpositions and re-creations of possible relationships between people.
These image clusters or agential constellations can be both decoded and
transposed back into relationships between historical people (in significant
cases, with an increment in understanding and a possibility of intervening
into them).
1.5
In order to pass to my argument about a theory of narrative
agents, I shall attempt to draw some conclusions from this first part. It
seems to me that we are faced with two main alternatives for envisaging
the presentation of people. Individualist atomism talks about the individ-
ual's mysterious essence, by definition not to be further analyzed; it is a
competitive mystification. Structuralist collectivism talks about abolishing
personality and substituting for it a camera eye; it is a static mystification.
The first, or subject-bound, mystification implies the liberalism of the "free-
enterprise" market; the second, or object-bound, mystification implies the
technocracy of state-capitalist intervention and multinational corporations.
Both finally see society as a stable, vertical class system, this layered stability
being its fundamental condition and supreme value ("law and order"). If
we instead posit the historical and axiological priority of a dynamic and
open horizontal system (which can then accommodate dynamic stability
and of which even temporary closures are special cases), a system in which
meaning is not preexistent and located either in individual(ist) atoms or in
the nodes of a structural(ist) grid but constituted in the interaction of the
general and the singular-then we can begin instituting a materialist and
dialectical discourse about narrative agents.
It seems necessary, therefore, to proceed along two lines. First,
we must induce from historical evidence the possible forms of narrative
agents and therefore of agential analysis. This means we must reconsider
at least two approaches that have pioneered a sophisticated analysis of fic-
tional agents: (a) the biblical and the Lukacsian notions of types; (b) the
Greimasian notion of actants. I shall here be able only briefly to discuss
Greimas's and Lukacs's approaches. Second, we must put these analytic
tools into practice and see whether they illuminate it. In the following ar-
gument, drama will be used as an example of all narrative. However, in
principle most descriptions and discussions in this essay (e.g., the sum-
marizing table in sect. 3.1) should be applicable to the theory ofnondramatic
narrations, too.
1.6
I shall conclude this first, introductory part with an operative
definition and a division of my further argument. Narrative agents can be
668
Darko Suvin
in a first approximation defined as all nouns or nominal syntagmas that
can be imagined as independent entities potentially able (in contrast to the
objects) to carry out independent action in a narrative's imaginary universe
or possible world. However many central questions this still begs, its mixture
of intuitive and verifiable elements seems sufficient for a first approach. The
necessary linguistic and semiotic elements in this definition function within
a "possible world" whose structures are largely borrowed from practical life.
In other words, when not modified by new propositions, the presuppositions
of dominant ideological ways of understanding everyday reality are retained
in narratives. Narrative agents therefore both derive their traits from ad-
jectivized cultural commonplaces and value judgments (such as brave, mi-
serly, amorous) and structure the traits differently from empirical practice
for the purposes of a better cognitive overview.
The study of narrative agents is seriously underdeveloped and
labors under two grave disadvantages. First, it is still largely naively im-
pressionistic and positivistic. In the 1920s the very well informed Bakhtin
noted bitterly that this field was in "a complete chaos": "character, type,
personnage, story hero, the famed classification of scenic emplois: the lover
(lyrical, dramatical), the reasoner, the simpleton, etc.-all such classifications
and determinations of the geroi [Bakhtin's term for something like a nar-
rative agent] are given no common basis or common denominator, nor is
there a unified principle extant for their reasoned ordering. Usually the
classifications are uncritically contaminated to boot.... " More than half a
century later, Chatman's synthetic survey of structuralist narrative analysis
quotes with approval a lament about the scandalous blanks in even a theory
of surface-level agents (the characters), a lament that maintains that the
latest advance in this field was E. M. Forster's distinctions from 1928, no-
tably between round and flat characters. 2 Indeed, the illusionistic confusion
of narrative agents and people from everyday life is still very much with
us.
Second, in the last twenty-five years there has appeared a sym-
metrical obverse of positivistic empiricism, the abstract apriorism of de-
ducing agents from eternal psychobiological structures sundered from social
history. Given that among the most interesting developments in cultural
studies today is a sociohistorical semiotics, in parts 2 and 3 I sketch a critique
of both ahistorical semiotics and asemiotic history and offer my own pro-
posals for a socioformal theory of agential analysis centered on the key
category of "type," as well as for some possibilities of its application to
textual agents in general, including in part 4 characters (principally in drama).
This might lead, in part 5, to some provisional answers to the question
posed in my title.
669
2.1
Barthes defined apophantic semiotics as a semiotics that denies
the necessity and possibility of "attributing to the sign positive, fixed, a-
historical, a-corporeal, in brief: scientific characteristics." Though the rest
of part 2 may explain his skepticism toward certain kinds of "science," I
would prefer to his sweeping farewell to scientism and metalanguage a more
nuanced approach, which would still keep those terms on condition that
they were subverted from within in order to approach the horizon he de-
sires-that is, on condition that the apophantic science and metalanguage
acknowledge and respect their own sociohistorical constitution, in the dou-
ble sense of sociohistorical coming into being and sociohistorical function-
ing. This condition could reconcile our technical needs, involving metalevels
and formalized analysis, and Barthes's salutary warning that "all relation-
ships of exteriority between one language and another are, a Ia longue,
untenable.... " 3 Respecting the intimately sociohistorical character of all
semiotics means acknowledging that in language any meaning of a term is
a matter of historical semantics and pragmatics, and in nonverbal com-
munication it is another variant of, as Eco put it, a "cultural unit." In
agential analysis this means returning to the Aristotelian-Proppian orien-
tation and inducing from what Marc Angenot calls "such historical ideal-
types as are the genres and the discursive traditions [within] the general
economy of social discourse." To indulge instead in supposedly pure de-
duction and ahistorical universalism leads to a glossocracy that offers little
result and that, moreover, is homologous to the technocracies of contem-
porary monopoly capitalism and monopoly pseudosocialism. Adapting Levi-
Strauss, it can be said that simply to understand the meaning of a term one
must permutate it in the context of all the discourses pertinent to it. 4 The
sociohistorical discourses constitute at the very least one large pertinent
group; freezing them out of the permutating process produces an impov-
erishment of great ideological significance but no scholarly justification.
As I noted in a study written in 1980 (to which I refer the reader
for a fuller discussion of all matters in part 2), the analysis of narrative
agents was relatively little developed by structuralism and the structuralisant
semiotics and narratology. 5 Apart from the forgotten Bakhtin, systematic
work in agential analysis began only in the wake of Levi-Strauss, with the
works of Greimas and the Communications authors. It is their problems
that will be considered in this section, and I shall limit myself to the dilem-
mas and aporias of their basic ideological premise, glossocratic universalism,
only in the domain of the number and nature ofagential levels in narratology
(including dramaturgy). Since this was most authoritatively developed by
A. J. Greimas, I shall concentrate on the part of his work that provides a
generally recognized framework for most later structuralism dealing with
narrative agents. I shall first briefly argue for a different articulation of the
deepest level of narrative functions (the actants) and then at greater length
for a different, "pragmatic" nature and hierarchy of the other levels.
2.2
Aristotle and Propp had, in their different ways, both distin-
guished two levels of agents (ethos vs. pratton, or dramatis persona vs.
function, respectively). The first of them is to be read off immediately from
the surface elements of the text; the second is not but is to be found by
670
Darko Suvin
further analysis (it is usually called metatextual). They also stressed that
this second, more general and abstract level was the strategically more im-
portant one. Propp concentrated in his functions on actions, which only
secondarily define six or seven "spheres of action" by as many main agents:
hero, villain, donor or provider, helper, sought-for person (and her father),
dispatcher or mandator, false hero. Obviously, this is both too much and
too little: false hero and villain are both antagonists, the term "hero" con-
taminates narrative function and ethical approval (e.g., Tartuffe is thenar-
rative but not at all the axiological "hero" of Moliere's play), the "sought-
for" agent can instead of a princess be any value (e.g., the Grail), and so
on. Just as interestingly, though discussing the opposite pole of individualist
dramaturgy of the last four centuries in Paris, Souriau worked out six "dra-
maturgic functions." Somewhat confusingly he identified them with as-
trological signs, which he fortunately disambiguated by adding clear defi-
nitions and persuasive examples. His six functions were the Thematic Force,
the Value or Wished-for Good, the Beneficiary (of that Good), the Adver-
sary, the Arbiter (who attributes the Good), and the Helper, who is always
a ''redoubling" of one of the first five functions. Both Propp and Souriau
were also perfectly clear about the possibility of distributing participation
in metatextual agents among several textual ones, as well as about the ob-
verse possibility: thus, whether the magical object given to a hero be one
horse or a ring out of which issue three youths, this will always represent
the Helper's "sphere of action" (Propp, pp. 19-20, 79); the Adversary may
be single or divided into eight, as in Moliere's Les Facheux (Souriau, pp.
95-100). Greimas's first attempt in Semantique structurale did not go much
beyond reactualizing (be it said in his praise) the multilevel agential analysis
of Propp and Souriau into the two levels of actants and acteurs.
It should be clear that Propp's Morphology of the Folktale is not
a synthesis but a halfway house between his scrupulous and brilliant his-
torical induction and a pioneering formalizing deduction. (Propp's later
works then established a more convincing balance, unfortunately not ex-
plicitly applied to narrative agents.) The attendant weaknesses were noted
by Levi-Strauss and Greimas, who rightly attempted a more consistent for-
malization. But in the process, Greimas, at least, lost sight of Propp's strengths
based in historical feedback and misused him by transferring the debate
onto the domain of universalist syntax, a dubious advantage. Greimas pro-
posed a basic scheme of agential functions applicable to all narratives, which
he divided into Subject, Object, Addressor, Addressee, Helper, and Oppo-
nent (sujet, objet, destinateur, destinataire, adjuvant, opposant). His pseu-
dosyntactic terminology and organization of this deepest level of agential
functions "offers little evidence how this model [of actants] would work in
practice ... " (Culler, p. 234). The most useful course is, then, a return to
a nonindividualist widening and grounding ofSouriau's narrative functions.
I propose to translate his articulation into the more historical and theater-
based vocabulary of the independent functions of Protagonist, Antagonist,
Value, Mandator, Beneficiary, and the dependent function of Satellite. 6
Greimas's breakthrough came in his essay "La structure des ac-
tants du recit. " 7 The existence and narratological status of the two levels
he called actant and acteur are from that time on generally accepted in
agential theory (so that this essay will take them for granted, while not
treating exhaustively their outstanding problems, from ontological basis to
671
predicative articulation). In between them, he tentatively and without sys-
tematic explanation added a third level called roles, defined as "elementary
actantial units which correspond to coherent functional fields" ("unites ac-
tantielles elementaires correspondant aux champs fonctionnels coher-
ents")-for example, pere or pretre. 8 Greimas's final refinement on the agen-
tial theory came in the essay "Les actants, les acteurs et les figures," where
he worked out eight roles actantiels. I have analyzed in great detail (Suvin,
"Per una teoria," pp. 91-92) the resulting unclear oscillation between binary
and ternary typologies, culminating in the Greimas-Courtes attempt to sys-
tematize such contradictions. 9 Greimas's first approach had in 1966 been
accompanied by engaging modesty-bearing disclaimers such as "Cette in-
terpretation vaut ce qu'ele vaut" (This interpretation is given for what it's
worth). He also acknowledged that his actants were "extrapolated from
French Syntax," which fifty pages later became "extrapolated from the syn-
tactic structure" ("extra-polees en partant de la syntaxe francaise"-
"!'extrapolation de la structure syntaxique," Semantique structurale, pp.
134, 185). In his essay from Semantique narrative et textuel/e, this had
already advanced to "a structure . . . that appears more and more able to
account for the organization of the human imagination ... " ("La structure
actantielle apparait de plus en plus comme etant susceptible de rendre compte
de }'organisation de l'imaginaire humain ... ")! His latter ending-and that
of many followers-forgets the beginning.
What is the basis of such hesitations and contradictions? It would
be both ungracious and silly to seek it in personal incompetence: Levi-
Strauss, too, hesitates between affirming with equal imperturbability two
opposite and contradictory positions. On the one hand, he says, there exist
some "universal laws which make up the unconscious activity ofthe mind,"
while on the other hand, "the physical universe [is a] projection of the social
universe": as far as the linguistic model in general is concerned, the error
of formalism lies in forgetting "that there is no language whose vocabulary
can be deduced from the syntax." Perhaps Levi-Strauss's corollary that "to
tackle first the grammar and to leave the vocabulary for later means to
condemn oneself never to create anything but an anemic grammar and a
vocabulary that used anecdotes in place of definitions" should be subject
to some clarification ofthe level of analysis envisaged; nonetheless, I would
agree with the particular application he then proceeds to make, namely, this
interlocking is indissoluble in narrative entities such as myths and tales,
where grammar and vocabulary do not even operate on distinct levels (as
he acknowledges they do in language) but "adhere to each other on their
whole surface and completely overlap," so that in narrative texts everything
is simultaneously both syntax and vocabulary. 10 It is, at any rate, obvious
that overarching ideological causes must be sought for such fundamental
epistemological oscillations in such leading theoreticians.
2.3
In order to get at such causes, a metatheoretical detour is una-
voidable, for it is only the ideologies of technocracy that believe they can
formalize their own truth, can lift themselves up by their own bootstraps
without paying the price of a dependence on a hierarchically superior system
or context (an epistemological version of their belief in quick economic-
political fixes that take into account neither transcendental values nor the
672
Darko Suvin
deeper demands of practice). 11 This is the meaning of Greimas's agnostic
stance, that whether we think the semantic organization of meaning(s) is
inscribed into social reality, or whether we postulate such an organization
for heuristic purposes, the practical consequences will be the same (" ... soit
qu'il existe une structure semantique organisant l'univers du sens, soit qu'une
telle structure est postulee en vue de !'investigation de l'univers seman-
tique.... Les consequences pratiques seront les memes.... "). This allows
him to conclude that, in any case, the investigator will find given "universes"
for investigation. Even in that essay, dealing with the relation of semiotics
and natural sciences, Greimas systematically avoids committing himself as
to whether such a "universe of meaning" is one of discourse only or of
other practices too-for example, it is unclear whether "semantic" in this
passage, as in his whole essay, refers to natural or formal languages. It is at
this price that Greimas's investigation proceeds to construct formal models
supposedly in conformity with such an unexplained "preexisting structure"
(Du sens, p. 39). This is not a stance that necessarily arises from semiotics:
Peirce, who thought that both our interests and our experience of objects
were extrasemiotic, would have denied it.
Since all happens within language anyway, Greimas is implying
that the "world of meaning" is going to be linguistic-here, "semantic"-in
any case. Yet this is a technocratic blanking out of some fundamentals of
his model-discipline, for nowhere is the existence of hierarchical levels of
analysis clearer than in linguistics, where the formal or syntactic meaning
of any element (e.g., a phoneme) is its function as an integral meaning of
a superior level (e.g., a morpheme). By that token, then, the question im-
mediately arises, What is the hierarchically superior level to the uppermost
linguistic level, that of the sentence? When they do not refuse to answer,
most linguists concede this is the (or a) pragmatic level of extralinguistic
reality. 12 Only the semantic-pragmatic meaning is usable and to be used in
the sense that is current outside of specialized linguistic usage. Greimas's
famous title, Du sens (On Meaning), plays with this ambiguity. So far as I
can see, he never explicitly argues that syntactic meaning is to be substituted
for semantic meaning beyond the sentence-that is, in narratives. However,
his whole proceeding presupposes this hidden theoretical claim, which nec-
essarily turns out to be untenable in practice.
It may be becoming apparent, then, that the root of the Grei-
masian contradictions is to be found in the orthodox structuralist glosso-
cracy, best expressed by his reliance on the very peculiar Hjelmslevian lin-
guistics as his epistemology. Greimas takes Hjelmslev as his authority for
founding the actantial model in the syntactic structure of natural languages,
equated with the organization of human imagination. 13 This is cognitively
improper, in the above bad sense of an ideological sleight-of-hand, for a
formal system is defined by its signs not having any independent meaning
outside the system, so that in order to speak about anything it must be in
a second moment interpreted in the sense of finding a meaning for its signs.
If the system then claims to be "wholly independent of any prior theory, it
is in fact constructed ad hoc. Thus, if the logician subsequently pretends to
search for its interpretation, he is as one who is asked a riddle for which
he already knows the answer, and who delights in feigning ignorance!" 14
Greimas's typical proceeding is a structuralist bricolage in fundamentals,
followed by a relentless scientistic and combinatory logic in consequences:
673
a proceeding vaunted by his followers as elasticity and broadmindedness.
The other way around, firm foundations and elastic applications, would
have been much more sympathetic. Yet whenever he is analyzing actual
narrative texts, Greimas finds-to my mind not too surprisingly-that de-
ductive and universalist syntax is an insufficient fundament, and he hastens
to supplement it with semantics: a crack through which the social history
of peoples' relationships with each other and with the world of things, kicked
out of the main door, partially and inconsistently oozes back by a cellar
window. In his first book, Greimas started out by hesitating between what
he then called the "syntactic actants proper" and "semantic actants," even
connecting the actants with a Freudian investment of desire. In Du sens,
his analyses of a group ofLithuanian folktales required a Proppian recourse
to the specific social semantics and, indeed, pragmatics of authority. And
in his final development of actants, while allotting them an entirely syntactic
nature, he stressed the semantic (or at least mixed) nature of the acteurs
and the roles thematiques. 15
Thus, the ideological horizon of glossocracy contradicts actual
scholarly necessity. I believe this obscurely felt contradiction is the key to
Greimas's shifting, overlapping, uneconomic, and often confusing cate-
gories, which becloud his undoubted flair for spotting strategic Gordian
knots and his pioneering boldness (only in view of which are further at-
tempts-such as this critique-becoming possible). It seems, therefore, im-
perative to say, today, that if we are to have a viable agential theory, the
hesitation between universalist syntax and shamefaced semantics-cum-prag-
matics is to be resolved in favor of sociohistorical contextuality and inter-
textuality in (say) Bakhtin's and Mukarovsky's, and sometimes Levi-Strauss's
and Barthes's, "marxist" sense of a dialogic tension between the worldviews
of specific societal groups. It is high time to recognize Hjelmslev's rigidly
deductive approach as simply a misleading analogy and to depose it from
the narratological hegemony it has illicitly enjoyed. 16 While the conceptual
rigor of linguistics is an admirable example, when sundered from social
verisimilitude and historical semantics, it easily leads to "a rigorous irre-
levance" (Culler, p. 257).
2.4
One witty way of clinching the necessity of an integration of
formalized linguistics or semiotics with investigation into socialized actions
might be to note that the integration has become increasingly recognized
as unavoidable in linguistics itself. It has taken the name of pragmatics,
defined already by Charles Morris as the domain of relationships between
the signs and their interpreters, which clarifies the conditions under which
something is taken as a sign. From Peirce, G. H. Mead, and Karl Buhler,
through BakhtinjVoloshinov, Morris, Carnap, and the Warsaw school, to
(say) R. M. Martin, Leo Apostel, and John R. Searle, pragmatics has slowly
been growing into an independent discipline on a par with syntactics (the
domain of relationships between the signs and their formally possible com-
binations) and semantics (in this sense, the domain of relations between
the signs and the entities they designate). Moreover, there are, since the late
1950s, strong arguments that pragmatics is a constitutive and indeed en-
globing complement of both semantics and syntactics. The basic-and, to
any materialist, unexceptionable-argument for it has been suggested in
674
Darko Suvin
section 2.3: an object or event (word, text, shape, color, change, etc.) becomes
a sign only in a signifying situation; it has no "natural" meaning outside of
it. This situation is constituted by the relation between signs and their users.
A user can take something to be a sign only as it is spatiotemporally concrete
and localized and as it relates to the user's disposition toward potential
action; both the concrete localization and the user's disposition are always
sociohistorical. Furthermore, they postulate a reality organized not only
around signs but also around subjects, in the double sense of a psycho-
physical personality and a socialized, collectively representative subject. The
entry of potentially acting subjects reintroduces acceptance and choice, tem-
poral genesis and mutation, and a possibility of dialectical negation into the
frozen constraints of syntax (in fact, by the most orthodox structuralist
standards, only such dynamics can make the-temporary-stability of any
structure meaningful). It also regrounds semantics: even in language, "one
cannot tell the meaning of most words without observing how the word is
used, and what effects it seems to have on our behavior." All words have
a pragmatic value based on an implicit classification "that follows the kind
of interest which they evoke [in the subject], the advantages or inconven-
iences, pleasures or sufferings, which they suggest." 17 Thus, each and every
semantic presupposition is also a pragmatic one (though the contrary does
not obtain).
The signifying situation as the basic cell of pragmatics is clearly
the theoretical locus of the hierarchically superior system that must finally
allot significations and validate all other investigations into signs (including
natural languages). Or, at the very least, pragmatics is the mediation between
semiotics and an even more general theory of action or practice. Only prag-
matics is able to take into account the situation of the text producers and
its social addresses, 18 as well as the whole spread of their relationships within
given cognitive (epistemological and ideological) presuppositions, conven-
tions, economical and institutional frames, and so on. And only a semantic-
pragmatic decision about pertinent presuppositions and levels of reading
can make sense of an at-all-complex text (from, say, a proverb or parable),
whose presuppositions, levels, and connotations would otherwise be prac-
tically infinite. Realizing much of this, the early Levi-Strauss (structuralism
with a somewhat uneasy conscience) claimed his method could exhaust all
the pertinent presuppositions because his texts-the myths-came from a
supposedly less complex, "cold" (tribal) society in which the presuppositions
were presumed to be frozen and finite (which I doubt, too). These pragmatic
presuppositions about the signs' possible uses by their users, then, neces-
sarily inscribe historical reality, as understood by the users, between the
lines of any text (in the widest sense). Semiotics is either informed by an
open historicity or it is, on its own methodical terms, truncated.
Equally, the sciences are, no doubt, texts (though not purely ver-
bal ones), but the book of science is also-for all its partial autonomy-an
interpretation of the book of nature, which is the presupposition of all
scientific propositions. Furthermore, what exactly are the pertinent cate-
gories that constitute any object of investigation (in the widest sense, in-
cluding a whole discipline) in the first place? This delimitation, which con-
stitutes not only the cognizable domain but also the possible ways of
envisaging and cognizing it, cannot be established from the object alone but
only from its interaction with the social subject whose pragmatic point of
675
view or approach is defining the pertinence and by that token constructing
the object's cognitive identity. 19 To return to the terms oflogics, linguistics
cannot be its own epistemology, because no natural language can be wholly
formalized without incurring semantic contradictions-as Greimas inevit-
ably does, on a theoretical level, when he is not being fuzzy. Therefore,
linguistics cannot and does not provide the criteria valid for every type of
cognition but, on the contrary, needs itselfto be justified by an epistemology
external to it.
Thus, for any pursuit of systematic knowledge, as semiotics, the
formal logic of syntax is clearly indispensable. But it is not sufficient, for if
the analysis of a text must be begun, it cannot be concluded by an under-
standing of its syntax. This does not mean that for given, clearly delimited
exercises syntactic rules could not be treated as an autonomous object of
cognition. But it means that "a well definable (autonomous) syntax is only
the syntax of syntactic categories as a purely formal syntax." 20 A syntactically
valid analytic system cannot be used to prove anything about an empirical
object unless and until the system is related to a semantic interpretation
and a pragmatic situation, as was demonstrated in the case of Greimas's
actants used to explain narration.
2.5
In conclusion, then, if (and insofar as) Greimas's system of ac-
tants is taken as a claim for full interpretative validity with a solid episte-
mological basis, one would have to apply to it Piaget's evaluation of the
philosophical school that (through Hjelmslev) underpins it: logical positiv-
ism. "Logical Positivism has committed the imprudence of transforming
method into doctrine, in other words of wanting to codify formalizing anal-
ysis and of making it co-responsible for a dogmatism ... " (Piaget, p. 84).
I would not go quite so far-as do a number of critics, for example, Tim-
panaro-as to call Greimas's method objective idealism, since it does not
quite Claim that the categories of the given sign-system determine what there
is but "only how anything is." I would, rather, call it a medium-rare semiotic
idealism-a cross between agnosticism and thoroughgoing idealism. 21 Of
course, no idealism or-to give it a historically suggestive name-medieval
realism can account for changes in our cognition of the world (never mind
changes in an external world). Greimas's attempt is simply one of the most
developed-and the dominant one in agential analysis-to investigate the
meanings of a text by means of a text "linguistics," "grammar," or "syntax"
(all of which are, in fact, shamefacedly founded on the quite exceptional
digital model of phonetics). This seems to me, in all cases, a dangerously
ambiguous metaphor, and in the worst case it is a positive guarantee of
wrong theorizing. The only safe course is to avoid both the thing and the
name. 22
Nonetheless, I have suggested the presence of some undoubtedly
stimulating aspects in Greimas-mainly those taking off from Propp. Grei-
mas addressed the crucial dilemma in studying narratives, namely, into
which system a text must be integrated in order to become meaningful (i.e.,
such that an interpreter may explain it). Positivism had answered this by
putting its object simply into a quantitatively larger set of texts (an author's
opus, a genre tradition, etc.). Structuralism was right to react against this
in the direction of qualitatively different levels of analysis, but structuralism
676
Darko Suvin
was wrong-as is all scholastic realism-in radically sundering deductive and
formal cognition (a self-sufficient, closed system of signs) from experiential
cognition based on reference to the extrasignific reality of social bodies. 23
In cultural studies, structuralism's answer-to apply to the investigated text
a "grammar of narration"-explains texts in terms of a universal structure
of the human (or, in Greimas, Indo-European?) mind, as evidenced in lan-
guage. In a nicely sterile Hegelian antithesis, both positivism and structur-
alism bypass the actual historical situations in culture, its pragmatic hier-
archy. Cultural texts may be analyzed into cognitive levels only by seeing
how those levels are intimately molded by precise societal values and ten-
sions.
Greimas's multilevel schema of agents should, therefore, be sep-
arated out of his unacceptable system and then reworked in a way that
incorporates the semantic and pragmatic dimension, namely, societal his-
tory and mutability. It should then become possible to use this reworked
form within the epistemic axioms of my part 1, within a need for observing
material practice as well as the dialectical interrelations that obtain between
the synchronic and the diachronic, structure and history, subject and object.
True, no historical situation is fully formalizable, but it can (and I believe
must) be investigated through a series of formalizations open to practice
and focusing on strategic stages frozen for synchronic investigation. Thus,
I will present a sketch of such a sociohistorical semiotics of narrative agents:
a study of sign, necessarily, but signs given meaning by choices within
societal histories. No doubt, the sociohistorical concreteness of my proposed
new system will have to be inversely proportional to the area it is designed
to cover. But it will use semiotics in the proper epistemological hierarchy
dominated by relationships of people in signifying situations and not by
glossocracy: "It is essential that one does not confuse the systematic order
in semiotics: syntactics-semantics-pragmatics, with the epistemological or-
der of the dimensions of semiosis: pragmatic-semantic-syntactic dimen-
sion. The pragmatic dimension of semiosis is epistemologically of primary
importance.... the pragmatic aspects always appear at the beginning and
at the end of the study of semiosis. " 24
3. For Sociohistorical Semiotics of Narrative Agents: A Proposal
(with Types as the Key Level)
3.1
I cannot provide here a lengthy inventory of extant narratological
contributions to a clear definition and delimitation of the third, intermediate
level of agential analysis. Besides Aristotle, Propp, Souriau, Bakhtin, and
Levi-Strauss, one should reevaluate the use of agents in the Marxian tra-
dition, from The Eighteenth Brumaireto Brecht and Benjamin. 25 One should
also sift and integrate the contributions of structuralists (Barthes, Todorov,
Greimas, Rastier, Hamon, Chatman, etc.) and of some other precursors.
The structuralists are perhaps best represented by Alexandrescu's book on
Faulkner, situating between personnages and actants a level of roles: in
677
Faulkner's opus (itself a concrete refashioning of a historical and history-
oriented genre), Alexandrescu found the roles of Indian, black, mulatto,
farmer, aristocrat, Yankee, businessman, and intellectual (and I think other
"roles" could be found, too). However, since my present concern is to help
build a theory of narrative agents, I cannot here give a detailed overview
of work in this field. I shall content myself with acknowledging that I used
hints from the older authors mentioned in part 2, as well as from those in
the preceding two paragraphs, and also from Simmel, the Russian formalists
(Eikhenbaum, Balukhatii, etc.), Ubersfeld, and Doutrepont, in order to pro-
pose Table 1.26
I should stress that the agential levels are cumulative and not
exclusive. The two basic ones-actants and types-are to be found in every
fictional text, while the uppermost one-characters-may or may not be
present in any given text (this depends on the historical epoch and literary
genre). Where characters are present, "each is a type but also at the same
time a definite individual, a 'this one,' as old man Hegel expresses it. ... " 27
This points to the key function ofthe second, or intermediate, level of types,
on which I shall now focus.
I suggested in part 2 that different scholars have used various,
sometimes confusing terms: figure, role, and emploi in Vol'kenshtein; role
or role pur in Souriau; "basic characters" in Eco's discussion of James Bond
(p. 85); role and role actantiel in Greimas (if I have understood him and
when he uses them); role in Alexandrescu and (much less usefully) in Bre-
mond; role forme/ in Rastier; emploi in Hamon (p. 106); role and personnage-
type in Ubersfeld (pp. 113-14, 131, 150). Perhaps the actual term used is
not of primary importance if the level is clearly delimited and articulated,
but it is of some importance: language speaks us as much as we speak it.
Thus, I would not favor "role" in French or English because it invites
confusion both with an actor's role in the theater and with the sociological
theory of role playing. 28 "Type,'' however, is both suitably Anglo-French
and able to draw sustenance from a confrontation with its wide use in literary
criticism and in the theater tradition, which (in English more than in French)
draws on such associations as "type of role,'' "typecast,'' "stock types,'' and
so on.
3.2
It seems necessary to confront here Lukacs's pioneering use, sym-
metrically inverse to the formalists and structuralists, ofterms such as "typ-
ical character." I have sufficient space here only for a first sketch of the
splendors and miseries in his approach to narrative agents. I shall use for
that purpose mainly his early Theory of the Novel, the essay on "intellectual
physiognomy,'' and, as his crowning achievement, The Historical Novel and
the essays on Balzac. 29
The Theory of the Novel may not be thought fair game, since
Lukacs himself declares in his 1962 preface that its writer's world view "tended
toward a fusion of 'left-wing' ethics and 'right-wing' gnoseology (ontology
etc.)" (p. 16). I would add to this a right-wing or bourgeois aesthetics fixated
on eighteenth- and nineteenth-century "realism,'' from Cervantes to Thomas
Mann, and evident in his lifelong, sincere hatred of Dada, photomontage,
Brechtian dramaturgy, and so on. A deep interest in Baroque drama or
novel, as in Benjamin and Bakhtin, is beyond Lukacs's ken-not to mention
678
Table 1.
4.1
I can only briefly suggest here a program of at least book-length
research needed to verify the usefulness of a historical-cultural theory of
narrative agents. If the hypothesis developed earlier is correct, the answer
to the question, Which agential level is to be found on the surface of a text
and which is to be found in the presuppositions or depths of a text (i.e.,
what is textual and what is metatextual)? is neither single nor eternal. It is
not given once and for all by the structure of the human brain or unconscious 39
and/or by a universal syntax; on the contrary, it is a changing answer, based
on dominant aspects of sociohistorical relationships among people-both
the relationships of which and to which that text speaks. Such changes
happen, no doubt, within a longue duree measured in epochs, yet they are
nonetheless part of the major "geological" shifts in human relations. One
clear instance of such a wholly new (in principle) narrative level is the rise
of the individualist character in the period between Boccaccio, Shakespeare,
Cervantes, and Moliere, in whose works its coming into being can be pal-
pably traced.
Of course, this does not mean that agents with conflicting and
sufficiently numerous traits (i.e., characters) cannot be found before or out-
side the European fourteenth or sixteenth century. Basic epistemological
shifts in a culture and in social practice come neither overnight nor out of
686
Darko Suvin
nowhere. If we knew more about different cultures, we could speak with
more confidence about controversial matters such as a possible antique or
Hellenic individualism arising somewhere between Aeschylus and Euri-
pides. I shall have to leave this aside, as it is for my theoretical purposes
indifferent whether to postulate the rise and coming into existence of bour-
geois individualism only or of several individualisms that came and went
(though I would be inclined to argue with Aristotle that in most Hellenic
plays there is no character, only ethos, a Hellenic variant of type under the
sign of constant categories from moral philosophy, physiology, etc.). 40 I shall
similarly leave aside the non-European cultures-though I am again hard
put to find characters in the dramaturgies of Noh, the Peking Opera, the
Javanese wayang-topeng (where the principal actors cannot even speak), or
the classical Chinese novel. 41 But in European art, from the Middle Ages
on, it seems clear that the deviation from universalia toward individuality
"is a comparatively recent development." 42 Character in the individualist
sense was born together with the bourgeoisie, capitalist money economy,
economic rationality, atomization, quantification, and reification of human
relationships, including equality before the law, and the whole well-known
historical cluster accompanying the rise of this new episteme. Character is
the fictional equivalent of private property in the process of production and
circulation, of independent individuals in the market "who are the posses-
sors of commodities [and who] place themselves in relation to one another
as persons whose will resides in these objects."43
Historical semantics can prove that this is precisely the time when
the modern meanings of key terms such as individual, personality or char-
acter, and subject arose. In English, "individual" originally meant the op-
posite of what it does after the sixteenth-seventeenth-century watershed,
namely, an indivisible unity or community in multiplicity (e.g., the Christian
Trinity), or "the individual Catholicke Church" (as Milton was still writing
at this late date). The singular noun "individual" emancipated itself from
explicit and subordinate relation "to the group of which it was, so to say,
the ultimate indivisible division" only in the late eighteenth century-a
characteristic example of the new usage being in Adam Smith's political
economy! The fully fledged ideology of "individualism" emerged, then, in
the nineteenth century and was recorded in the English translation of
Tocqueville, who characterizes it as "a novel expression, to which a novel
idea has given birth." Similarly, the use of "character" for fictional agents
dates from the mid-eighteenth century; earlier, if applied to people at all,
it had meant their more or less fixed nature, their reputation, or the fixed
type and literary genre popularized by Theophrastus, La Bruyere, and Over-
bury. Finally, "subjective" also changed into its opposite: for the Schoolmen
it meant "as things are in themselves," that is, according to their substance.
It is "especially from Descartes" that "subject" came to mean the opposite,
that is, the thinking, isolated self. Correspondingly, "objective" metamor-
phosed from the meaning "as things are not in themselves" to "as things
are in themselves," beheld by but deduced as independent of the thinking
self. In English, the use of "subject" in grammar came in the seventeenth
century, and of "object" in the eighteenth century. The modern philosoph-
ical distinction "subject-object" (tacitly imported into the earlier syntactic
use by Greimas et al.) developed, of course, in and after classical German
philosophy. 44
687
To verify this in terms of dramaturgic agents (see Table 1): the
kind or category of behavior-though not necessarily the concrete behavior
itself-of a type (as explained in part 3, e.g., a miles g/oriosus or a La Bruyere
caractere) is wholly predictable. As different from type, a character must
possess more than, say, half a dozen traits, of which at least two are even-
tually found to be contradictory or otherwise incompatible. Thus, in a char-
acter even the kind of behavior is not wholly predictable. In that sense, this
character or personnage-personne is an upstart and newfangled kind of agent.
It is limited not only by epoch but also by genre 45-for example, the psy-
chological novel and piece bien faite as against fairy tale, paraliterature, and
most of the avant-garde ofthe last century (which in this hypothesis is the
beginning of the postindividualist epoch).
I should make clear that none of my arguments have spoken to
the historical necessity or value of the rise of individualistic character. My
provisional opinion-on a huge subject that requires more investigation
willing to admit and, if warranted, compensate for its initial ideological
bias-is that the rise of the character as an agential level (just as the rise of
its economic and social analogues and bearers, the market and the bourgeoi-
sie) has brought both great advantages and great limitations. The advantages
were principally apparent during the ascending historical phase, in Europe,
say, up to Balzac, George Eliot, and Tolstoy. In that phase, the character
was the agential formulation of the freedom to break through the consensual
constraints of hierarchically frozen social types and dogmatic normative
systems-connected with despotic monarchism and a stagnant subsistence
economy-toward larger horizons of life. The multiplication of traits and
their conflictuality, the illusion of agential "roundness" and "three-dimen-
sionality," connoted that human agents and actions were not explained,
foreseen, and fixed. Their richness allowed these freshly conceived agents
to slip through the insufficient-clumsy and restrictive-net of old univer-
sa/ia. In particular, the highly significant chronotopic analogues to this new
structure of agents should also be investigated: where the types were timeless
and set against a fixed background, so that they pretended to eternal and
ubiquitous validity, a character can and does evolve in time and environ-
ment. But all such aspects tum into their contraries with the contraction
and exhaustion of individualism in our century. On the one hand, the price
of its particular kind of freedom begins to weigh more heavily than its
achievements as the bourgeoisie shifts from personal competition to ficti-
tious corporative "individualities"; on the other hand, this shift, as well as
the failure (so far) of radical alternatives to bourgeois rule, threatens all
freedom (in the sense of enlarging possibilities of life), bringing about new
monopolistic and stereotype-producing networks-the Leviathans of states,
corporations, armies, culture industry, and so on. 46
4.2
Let me then take, at the end, the trajectory of one typologically
and probably historically coherent sequence, whose extreme ends would be
the allegorical figure of Avarice (in a hypothetical morality play) and a
realistic miser, say Balzac's Gobseck. The two traits of Avarice (the hom-
onymous predicate and its Stellenwert in the system of sins) expand in a
Renaissance or post-Renaissance type into roughly half a dozen: the type
Pantalone can be characterized by the traits "merchant," "old," "male,"
688
Darko Suvin
"Venetian," "amorous," and "miserly." Without that last predicate and
trait, there would be no Pantalone; that is what dooms his amorous ventures
to failure and makes him a permanent butt. Equally, however, it is the new
fusion of this trait with the unambiguous class identification of Venetian
merchant that makes for both a recognizable and a popular hyperbole of
"a precise historical function, as a representative of an industrious bourgeoi-
sie"-"the satire of commercial power" (together with homologous satires
of the military power in the Capitano and of sterile learning in the Dottore)Y
The biological age of Pantalone is highly significative: the fact that there is
no type of the young merchant before bourgeois drama (though well-known
in everyday life, and even in prose fiction from the Novellino and Boccaccio
on) shows that the physical coding is an ideological hyperbole, a plebeian
(and possibly also aristocratic) adverse judgment on the vitality of a new
class, episteme, way of behaving-in short, of a new type. One step further
and we are at Moliere's Harpagon, who has a similar ideological profile but
is already part of the way from type to character (though not quite a con-
tradictory character), probably by way of contamination of several types.
The watershed toward character is passed in Shylock, precisely in his speech
"Hath not a Jew eyes? ... " (III.i): there is no type, I think, that can see
itself simultaneously through the eyes of antagonists and through its own
interiority, since this provides a union of contradictory traits par excellence.
Though Shylock may for long stretches be a type, he is no longer only or
primarily such (the same would hold for Richard III as against the Medieval
Vice). Finally, the usurers and misers of realism, such as Gobseck, draw
their strength from the interplay of characterological richness and the steel
backbone of the old type, never totally buried under the surface of indi-
vidualistic character.
Indeed, it is remarkable that characters-verbally bound up with
a proper name-can revert to social type and tum their name into a common
or generic noun simply by adding an article or a suffix. Moliere's Tartuffe
became "les Tartuffes" in his first placet to the King (August 1664); Don
Juan turns into "donjuanism" or Les Don Juans de village (title of a play)
as readily as Tartuffe does into "a tartuffe" or into "tartufferie. "48 This
measures the oftentimes small distance between the character and type levels
in much literature since Moliere: in dramaturgy, it is enough to mention
the melodrama (that matrix of all romantic plays), the vaudeville, or even
the boulevard comedy whose art consists precisely in pasting the newest
traits of the marketplace on the good old masks-a Commedia dell'arte
inverted, so to speak. As for modem drama, say from Jarry and Chekhov
to Brecht and Genet, one could show that part of its strength consists in
ironically violating those same type expectations hidden behind the char-
acters (e.g., in Brecht's Mutter Courage und ihre Kinder the miles gloriosus
for Eilif, the ingenue for K.attrin, the niais, benet, or simpleton for Swiss
Cheese, and, of course, the miserly merchant for Courage herself).
5. In Lieu of Conclusion
In parts 2-4 of this essay I have argued two points. First, that to
understand narrative agents it is necessary to take into account the inter-
action within each dramatis persona between the three levels of actantial
function, sociohistorical way of categorizing people or type, and often also
the particular-individual but no less sociohistorical-characterization. In
689
this "spatial-form" (i.e., paradigmatic) textual interaction, hegemonies will
shift between the three levels according to given historical periods (as well
as given analytic goals). 49 Second, I have argued that the most formalizing
analysis can become precise, instead of formalistic, if and only if it enters
into a feedback relation to the sociohistorical actuality of the field under
scrutiny. That is why, instead of a "pure" technocratic and idealistic birth
of agential theory (or, indeed, semiotics) from the spirit of syntax, I pleaded
in part 2 for this relation. To speak from within semiotics, such a feedback
is, after all, built into its foundations-in Aristotle, in Propp, and at least
theoretically even in Levi-Strauss, as well as in the best practitioners such
as the latter Barthes and Eco. This could add the dialectics of historic mut-
ability to the mechanistic atomism of the formalists or the computerized
statics of the structuralists and neutralize their respective metaphysics.
However, there is more than a particular (much less fashionable)
method of narrative and cultural analysis at stake here. As I argued in part
1, the reply to my title question is hugely important, and I hope my ar-
gumentation may lead toward two complementary conclusions: First, em-
pirical individuals, people in the bourgeois individualist sense, cannot be
represented in fiction; they necessarily become, on the one hand, exempla
(Auden's paragons) and, on the other hand, shifting nodes of narration.
Second, pertinent and crucial relationships among people-not atomic or
pointlike but as a rule dyadic or differential-nonetheless can be represented
in fiction; in fact, fiction consists in their representation and reformulation,
which allows the reader to pleasurably verify old and dream up new alter-
native relationships, to re-articulate (in both senses of the word) human
relationships to the world of people and things. As Aristotle argued in Pol-
itics (1.2), humans necessarily live in communities (polis); they are "political
animals." Thus, all central human relations are, in this widest sense, polit-
ical, and significant fictional re-presentation of relations among people rear-
ticulates our political relationships.
Notes
I trust the current cultural theories discussed in this part of the essay are readily identifiable.
Therefore, I will use as few references as possible for the general intertext, here and else-
where. lndispensible titles and quotes will be footnoted at the first mention and after that
referred to by author's name and page number in parenthesis within the body of the essay.
In another essay, "On Metaphoricity and Narrativity in Fiction," Sub-Stance 48( 1986): 51-
67, I argue that the chronotope is, in fact, specific only to narrative texts as opposed to
metaphorical ones. For part 1, the classical discussion of re-presentation 1s in Henri Wallon.
De l'acte a Ia pensee (Paris: Flam marion, 1970), especially pp. 162-67; I am also abundantly
using Bertolt Brecht, Gesammelte Werke, vols. 15-20 (Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 1973). I am
bound to note that the Social Sciences and Humanities Research Council of Canada has,
from 1981 to 1984, consistently refused to fund research connected with this paper.
2 Mikhail M. Bakhtin, "Avtor i gero1 v estet1chesko1 deiatelnosti," in Estetika slovesnogo tvor-
chestva (Moscow: lskusstvo. 1979), pp. 10-11; Seymour Chatman, Story and Discourse
(Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press. 1978), pp. 107-8, where three other laments rangmg
from 1936 to 1966 are also quoted; E. M. Forster, Aspects of the Novel ( 1928; Har-
mondsworth, U.K.: Penguin, 1962). Translations from Bakhtin (as from all other non-English
texts. unless they are cited from English titles) are mine.
3 Roland Barthes, Lecon inaugurale (Paris: College de France, 1977). pp. 35-36. The other
quotes in this paragraph are from Umberto Eco, A Theory of Semiotics (Bloomington: Indiana
Universtiy Press, 1977), pp. 66-68 pass1m; Marc Angenot, "La notion d'actant comme
categone genologique," paper presented at CSRA meeting, Montreal, May 1980. I am
deeply indebted to discussions w1th Angenot, as well as to remarks, md1cations. and obJec-
690
Darko Suvin
tions of William Dodd, Irwin Gopnik, Cary Nelson, Maria-Luisa Nunes, Patrick Parrinder, Patrice
Pavis, and Maria Vittoria Tessitore.
4 Claude Levi-Strauss, "La structure et Ia forme," in Anthropologie structurale deux (Paris:
Pion, 1973). p. 162, trans. by C. Jacobson and B. G. Schoepf as Structural Anthropology
(New York: Basic Books, 1976).
5 Darko Suvin, "Per una teoria dell'analisi agenziale," Versus 30( 1981 ): 87-109. in particular
pp. 87-94. Cf. Achim Eschbach and Wendelin Rader, Semiotik-Bibliographie I (Frankfurt:
Antoren-und Verlagsgesellschaft Syndikat, 1976). and Jonathan Culler's judgment in Struc-
turalist Poetics (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1975). p. 230. True, as always we
can refer to Aristotle (Poetics, 1449b-1450a, 1451 b, in the edition by L. Golden and 0. B.
Hardison, Jr. [Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall, 1968]; and ct. his Ethics and Rhetorics);
to Vladimir Propp, Morphology of the Folktale (Austin: University of Texas Press, 1974).
chaps., 2, 6; and to Brecht (see note 1). See also Etienne Souriau, Les deux cent mille
situations dramatiques (Paris: Flammarion, 1950). pp. 65-81; and for some hints in
Vol'kenshtein, Bogatyrev, and Frye, see note 8.
6 A major problem here is the initiating, overarching, or "transcendental" actant that Greimas
calls destinateur(see the critique by Culler, pp. 233-34) and Souriau calls balance (=Arbiter);
the Proppian denomination of Mandator seems to work better than either of these but has
to be verified by further inductive analyses.
7 The four main works on actants by Greimas to be focused upon are: "Reflexions sur les
modeles actantiels," in Semantique structurale (Paris: Larousse, 1966); "La structure des
actants du recit," in Du sens (Paris: Editions du Seuil, 1970)-cf. for agents especially pp,
254ft.; "Les actants. les acteurs et les figures," in Claude Chabrol, ed., Semiotique narrative
et textuelle (Paris: Larousse, 1973); and, with Joseph Courtes, Semiotique (Paris: Hachette,
1979). For other works of his, see notes 9 and 22.
8 Greimas had already, in Semantique structurale (p. 188). hinted at a third agential category
and level in his account of psychocriticism (e.g., Baudelaire's porteur de chimere). Possibly,
he based the introduction of this third level on a few hints in Souriau's role and role pur (pp.
69, 71 ), but more probably on analytic necessity. Ct. also a few hints about such a possible
level, called respectively figure and emploi, type, and stock type, in Vladimir Vol'kenshtein,
Dramaturgiia ( 1923, Moskva: Sovetskii pisatel', 1960), pp. 106, 111-12, 124-25; Petr
Bogatyrev, "Les signes du theatre," Poetique 5( 1971 ): 524 (first published in 1938); and
Northrop Frye, Anatomy of Critic1sm (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press, 1957), pp.
172ft.
9 Ct. for the two incompatible types of roles actantiels the Greimas essay in Chabrol, pp. 165-
66, 167, and for roles thematiques, pp. 171-75; for agents assigned to discours versus
recit in Du sens. pp. 255-56; and for Greimas-Courtes (e.g., entries for actant, acteur, role
thematique). The differentiations between collective and individual as well as paradigmatic
and syntagmatic actant in Greimas's Semiotique et sciences sociales (Paris: Editions du Seuil,
1976) do not seem either illuminating or pertinent to the present essay. Claude Bremond,
Logique du recit (Paris: Editions due Seuil, 1973) attempted to inventory all the principal
"narrative roles·' into eternal agents. such as protecteur and frustrateur, or patients. such
as beneficiaire and victime.
10 First quote by Levi-Strauss, Anthropologie structurale (Paris: Pion. 1958). p. 75; quotes in
following sentences: ibid., p. 201, and Anthropologie structurale deux, pp. 168-69, 172.
11 I will summarize and apply in the following two sections only some of the most basic and
pertinent issues of extremely complex and largely unfinished epistemological debates. The
handiest brief discussions of preconditions for knowledge may be found in Jean Piaget, ed.,
Logique et connaissance scientifique (Paris, 1967). in particular the essays by Piaget. Jean-
Biaise Grize, Leo Apostel, and Jean Ladriere. Since Greimas claims for his approach the
authority of a formal system, one could also apply to him the strictures of Kurt Godel, "Ueber
formal unenthscheidbare Satze ... , " Monatshefte f. Mathematik u. Physik 38( 1931 ): 173-
98 (in English: On Formally Undecidable Propositions of Principia Mathematica and Related
Systems [Edinburgh: Oliver and Boyd, 1962]); and of Alfred Tarski, "Der Wahrheitsbegriff
in den formalisierten Sprachen," StudJa philosophica 1(1935): 261-405; "On Undecidable
Statements in Enlarged Systems of Logic and the Concept of Truth," Journal of Symbolic
Logic 4( 1939); and Introduction to Logic and to the Methodology of Deductive Sciences
(New York: Oxford University Press, 1949). that such a system can only be validated by
another, higher and more potent system (in Marxism: practice). I will here simplify by giving
Greimas the benefit of the doubt that his approach may rather be used as a model; but if
so, claims made for it have to be scaled down sharply.
12 Ct., e.g., Emile Benveniste, "Les niveaux de I' analyse linguistique," Proceedings of the Ninth
International Congress of Linguistics (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1962). pp.
266-93. The followers of "text linguistics" would deny this, but I do not think they have
proved their case.
691
13 See Semantique structurale, pp. 133, 185, and Du sens, pp. 162 passim. Cf., however,
even from the standpoint of Brondal·s linguistic philosophy, the critique of Greimas's tacit
transmogrification of the concept of actant in Svend Erik Larsen, "Le concept d'actant:
Gre1mas et Brondal,'' Journal Canadien de Recherche Semiotique 3(1975): 16-35, esp. pp.
24-26.
14 Grize, "Historique," in Piaget, p. 169.
15 Greimas, Semantique structurale, pp. 130, 185ft.; Du sens, p. 257; "Les actants, les acteurs
et les figures," pp. 169-76. Similar hesitations can be found in many others, not excluding
the interesting Franc;:ois Rastier, Essais de semiotique discursive (Tours: Marne, 1973), pp.
95-96, 173, 214, or even Barthes. Culler, pp. 76-94, is, I believe, getting at the same
problem in his persuasive cntlque of Greimas's "structural semantics"; further on (pp. 213-
14, 233-34) Culler 1s JUStly severe about Greimas's arbitrary classifications and tentative
speculations elevated into methodology. Cf. also the critique of Greimas's inconsistent syn-
tactic-cum-semantic terminology in K. Bartoszynski, "0 badaniach ukladow fabularnych," in
H. Markiewicz and J. Slawinski, eds., Problemy metodologiczne wspolczesnego literaturoz-
nawstwa (Krakow: Wydawn. Literackie, 1976), p. 181, and of Greim as's "occultation of the
enunciating subject" m Timothy J. Reiss, "Semiology and Its Discontents: Saussure and
Greimas," Canadian Journal of Research in Semiotics 5(1977): 85-97. A general critique
of the ahistorical structuralist "syntacticism" ism Paul Ricoeur, Le confilt des interpretations
(Paris: Editions du Seuil 1969), pp. 31-63; and cf. Ricoeur, "La grammaire generative de
Greimas," Documents [de recherche du groupe de linguistique] 15( 1980); and two further
sociohistorically oriented critiques in Henri Lefebvre's beautiful L 'ideologie structuraliste (Paris:
Editions du Seuil, 1975) and Pierre Bourdieu's Outline of a Theory of Practice (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1977). Let me not fail to note that an engaging bricolage-type
modesty coexists strangely in Greimas with blind H]elmslevian dogmatism in fundamentals,
on which I unfortunately have to focus.
16 Cesare Segre, Semiotics and Literary Criticism, trans. J. Meddemmen (The Hague: Mouton,
1973), p. 67, puts 1t more politely: "Clearly Hjelmslev's highly suggestive scheme is not up
to the complexity of literary models"; he notes that valid semiotic criticism should not be
limited to a mere defining of matrices. Segre passes the same judgments on Greimas's
actants in his entry "Narrazione/narrativita," in Enciclopedia Einaudi, vol. 9 (Torino, 19BO),
p. 696. But Hjelmslev's dichotomy between "pure form" and social substance is very dubious
within linguistics itself. Perhaps the most famous critique in that discipline is by Andre Mar-
tinet, "Au sujet des Fondements de theorie linguistique de L. HJelmslev," Bulletin de Ia
Soci{ne de Linguistique de Paris 42, fasc. 1( 1946): 19-43; it has been often repeated in
French linguistics. Prieto notes that Hjelmslev's abstract formalization is an "illusion sym-
metrical and inverse" to naive empiricism (Pertinence [see note 19], p. 125; cf. pp. 66-69,
122-26). Claude Chabrol discusses incisively HJelmslev's "dizzying failure" in "De Ia semio-
tlque en question,'' m Claude Chabrol and Louis Marin, eds , Le recit evangelique (Paris:
Aubier Montaigne, 1974), pp. 193-200, 205-9; he notes also that Hjelmslev's claim about
the translatability of all other "languages" into natural language was based on unclear con-
cepts and has since been falsified by all attempts to find linguistic forms in music, body
gesture and movement, fine arts, and so on. For a general argument on the cognate uni-
versalism in analytical philosophy and Whorfian linguistics, see Ferruccio Rossi-Landi, Se-
miotica e 1deologia (Milano: V. Bompiani, 1972), pp. 154ft.; and for objections more directly
pertinent to Greimas's domain, see Barthes's critiques of the basic syntactic dyad subject-
predicate and the "logic" of actions if taken outside the cultural conditions in SIZ (Paris,
1970), pp. 82-83, 88-89, 209-10 pass1m, as well as cntiques of Bremond and Greimas in
Culler, pp. 208-11 and note 15, and in Rastier, pp. 218-21.
17 First quote: John C Condon, Semantics and Communication (New York: Macmillan, 1975),
p. 3; second quote: Albert Carnoy, La science du mot (Louvain: Ed1tions Universitas, 1927),
p. 43. One of the great pioneers of pragmatics is Bakhtin, for whom situation implies the
space and time as well as the object or theme of utterance and the evaluative relation of
the interlocutors to that utterance and its context-ct., e.g., BakhtinNoloshinov's "Stylistics
of Artistic Discourse" (1930), forthcoming in Wlad Godzich, ed., Writings of the Circle of
Bakhtin (University of Minnesota Press); and also Marxism and the Philosophy of Language
(New York: Seminar Press, 1973) and Estetika (see note 2).
18 On that concept see Darko Suvin, "The Social Addresses of Victorian Fiction," Literature
and History 1( 1982): 11-40, with large bibliography.
19 I am following here the fundamental approach by Luis J. Prieto. Cf. "Entwurf einer allgemeinen
Semiologie," Ztschr. f. Semiotik 1( 1970): 261, and Pertinence et pratique (Paris: Editions
de Minuit, 1975), pp. 147-50 passim, attempting to pursue the epistemological implications
of Marx's Theses on Feuerbach (though I disagree with some points in Prieto, e.g., his stark
Althusserian break between natural and human sciences, between subject and object of
cognition).
20 Janos Petofi, cited m Achim Eschbach, Pragmasemiotik und Theater (Tubingen: Narr, 1979),
p. 69.
692
Darko Suvin
21 Sebastiana Timpanaro, "Structuralism and Its Successors," 1n On Materialism (London: NLB,
1975); cf. also the general argument of David Savan, "Towards a Refutation of Semiotic
Idealism," Semiotic Inquiry 3(1983): 6.
22 I cannot enter here into Greimas's evolution after the peak of h1s actantial theory in the
1970s. I should mention that parallel to the development of linguistic pragmatics he has
been attempting to somewhat mend his fences but without basically changing his approach.
In his study of a "passion" ("De Ia colere," Documents [du groupe de recherches semio-
linguistiques de 1'E.H.E.S.S.] 27( 1981). the subtitle of "semantique lexicale" seems to me
crucial. To paraphrase calif Omar, it raises a dilemma in both of whose horns it is untenable.
Either the "lexical" is contained in semantics, since in a way all meanings of words are also
lexical, and it is redundant; or it is not so contained, and it is an oxymoron on the order of
Brecht's "planned disorder," where the adJective purports to redefine the noun, so that
meanings of words are henceforth to be understood only as lexical and not also as referential,
extrasemiotic in Peirce's sense. Thus, the familiar oscillation between agnosticism and Ide-
alism is retained and applied to new domains. Similar IS Greimas's interest 1n the per se not
uninteresting attempts at the study of modalities, which amount to a recuperation of ideo-
logical studies in a dehistoricized fashion; cf. the latest propositions I know of in his interview
with Hans-George Ruprecht. "Ouvertures metasemiotiques," Semiotic Inquiry 4( 1984): 1-
23. His conclusion is that pragmatics. and even "somatic passions," might perhaps be
admitted if it stays within (his kind of) sem1Dt1cs.
23 One of structuralism's most important epistemological precursors and shapers (by way of
logical positivism) is Ernst Mach. If my argument about the usable versus useless faces of
structuralism is correct. then-for all of Mach's lack of clarity and sometimes sheer agnos-
ticism-Lenin overreacted in Materialism and Empiriocrit1cism (and especially, in the heat of
what was centrally a political battle, against Bogdanov. a thinker to be reevaluated). Today,
in view of both political and Ideological developments during the intervening eighty years. it
is impossible to bypass the clarifications of epistemology from Mach and Russell on. However,
as my critique indicates. I think these can be accepted only on condition that (as Lenin also
insisted) they be refunctioned within a materialist and dialectical horizon. I have approached
this huge problem, attempting to use Gramsci, Bloch, Timpanaro, and Habermas, in "On
Two Notions of 'Science' in Marxism," in Tom Henighan. ed., Brave New Universe (Ottawa,
1980). pp. 27-43. For developed epistemological considerations. ct. Piaget, especially his
brilliant essay "Les methodes de l'epistemologie."
24 Doede Nauta, The Meaning of Information (The Hague: Mouton, 1970). p. 42.
25 For this different and unduly neglected tradition. which seems to begin with Marx's Eighteenth
Brumaire, see Hans Gerth and C. Wright Mills, Character and Social Structure (New York:
Harcourt Brace, 1953); Jutta Matzner, "Der Begriff der Charaktermaske bei Karl Marx,"
Soziale Welt 15(1964): 130ff.; Eduard Urbanek, "Roles, Masks and Characters," in Peter
Berger, ed., Marxism and Sociology (New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1969); and the
essays by John Coombes and Stanley Mitchell in Francis Barker et. al., eds., Literature,
Society, and the Socwlogy of Literature: 1848 (Colchester: University of Essex, 1977).
26 See notes 5, 8, 15, 16, 48; see also Georg Simmel, Soziologie (Munchen: Duncker and
Humblot. 1923); Sarin Alexandrescu, Logique du personnage; Roland Barthes, "Introduction
a !'analyse structurale des rec1ts," Communications 8( 1966; Pans: Editions du Seuil, 1981 ):
7-33. and S/Z; Philippe Hamon, "Pour un statut semiologique du personnage," Litterature
6(1972): 86-110; Tzvetan Todorov. "Personnage," in Oswald Ducrot and Tzvetan Todorov,
eds., Dictionnaire encyclopedique des sciences du langage (Paris: Editions du Seuil, 1972).
pp. 286-92, and Poetique de Ia prose (Paris: EditiOns du Seuil, 1971 ); Anne Ubersfeld, Lire
le theatre (Paris, 1977). Cf. Umberto Eco, "James Bond: Une combinatoire narrative,"
Communications 8 ( 1966): 83-99.
27 Friedrich Engels, letter to Minna Kautsky, Nov. 26, 1885, in Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels,
Ueber Kunst und Literatur ([East] Berlin: Henschelverlag, 1953). p. 120. Cf. Lidi1a Ginzburg,
"0 strukture literaturnogo personazha," in lskusstvo slova [Festschrift D. D. Blag01] (Moskva,
1973), pp. 376-88, and 0 psikhologicheskoi proze (Leningrad: VKP, 1971), for the most
sophisticated approach to the relations between type and character that I have found (un-
fortunately, too late for this study). After my hypothesis of the three agential levels had been
given as a lecture at several conferences and universities, Patrice Pavis kindly sent me proofs
of his Dictionnaire du theatre (Paris: Editions Sociales, 1980). where he (s.v. "actantlel
[modele]") briefly 1ndicates his own "Theorie des niveaux d'existence du personnage." Pavis
postulates the existence of four agential levels, the two middle ones being actants and
characters; between them, he somewhat tentatively but very interestingly postulates a "ni-
veau intermediaire" of roles defined as "entites figurat1ves, animees, mais generales et
exemplaires (ex: le fanaron, le pere noble, le traitre)." I am delighted with this convergence-
it recurs apropos our evaluation of Brecht's key theoretical concept of Gestus, which Pavis
deals with at more length in "On Brecht's Not1on of Gestus," Languages of the Stage (New
York, 1982). pp. 39-49-and only wish he would develop this insight at more length and
into a full analytic level having the same rights as his other two. Pavis's deepest level of
693
"structures elementaires de Ia signification" seems to me an unnecessary reverence toward
Greimas; his fourth level pertains to staging, which seems to me another metalanguage
altogether.
28 However, a developed narratological theory of agents will have to seriously confront this
theory, both to point out its serious deficiencies and to see what elements may still be usable.
Its principal sources are Ralph Linton. The Cultural Background of Personality (New York: D.-
Appleton-Century, 1945) and The Study of Man (New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts, 1964);
G. H. Mead. Mind, Self and Society (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1934); Jacob L.
Moreno. Who Shall Survive? (Beacon, NY.: Beacon House, 1953); and Georg Simmel (see
note 26). Cf. also Michael Banton, Roles (London: Tavistock, 1965); Erv1ng Goffman, En-
counters (Indianapolis: Bobbs-Merrill, 1961) and other titles to Frame Analysis (New York:
Harper and Row, 1974); Georges Gurvitch, ed., La vocation actuelle de Ia sociologie, vol.
1 (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France, 1957); Marcel Mauss, Sociologie et anthropologie
(Pans: Presses Universitaires de France, 1950); J. Milton Yinger, Toward a Field Theory of
Behavior (New York: McGraw-Hill, 1965). See also Bruce J. Biddle and Edwin J. Thomas,
eds., Role Theory (New York: Wiley, 1966); Hans Joas, Die gegenwartige Lage der soziol-
ogischen Rollentheorie (Frankfurt: Athenaum-Verlag, 1973); and Anne-Marie Rocheblave-
Spenle, La notion de role en psychologie sociale (Paris: Presses Universitaires de France,
1962). For interesting critiques, cf. Dieter Claessens, Rolle und Macht (Munchen: Juventa-
Verlag, 1970); Uta Gerhardt, "Toward a Critical Analysis of Role," Social Problems 27( 1980):
556-67; and Frigga Haug, Kritik der Rollentheorie (Frankfurt: Fischer Taschenbuch Verlag,
1972). I am grateful to my master's student Hanneke van Schaik for bringing some of these
titles to my attention.
For attempts at bridging social and theater roles, see much of the Burns book;
see also Jean Duvignaud, L 'Acteur(Paris: Gallimard, 1965), pp. 12-20; Anne-Marie Gourdon,
"Role social et role theatral," Travail theatral 10(1973): 76-86; Uri Rapp, Handeln und
Zuschauen (Neuwied, 1973); and Bruce Wilshire, Role Playing and Identity (Bloomington:
lnd1ana University Press, 1982).
Another whole field to be surveyed is that of an analytic philosophy of action;
cf. for a first introduction Robert W. Binkley et. al., eds., Agent, Action and Reason (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1971), with an extensive bibliography on pp. 169-99; and R. Tanaka,
"Action and Meamng in Literary Theory," Journal of Literary Semantics 1( 1972): 41-56.
29 Georg Lukacs, Die Theorie des Romans (Neuwied: Luchterhand, 1965); "The Intellectual
Physiognomy in Characterization," in Writer and Critic and Other Essays, ed. Arthur D. Kahn
(New York: Grosset and Dunlap, 1971 ); The Historical Novei(Harmondsworth, U.K.: Penguin,
1969); Balzac und der franzosische Rea!Jsmus (Berlin: Aufbau-Verlag, 1952); cf. also the
splendid "Zur Soziologie des modernen Dramas," Archiv f. Soz1alwiss. u. Soz1alpol. 38(1914):
303ft., so far as I know not yet fully published in English. The title of The Specificity of
Aesthetics testifies to Lukacs's interesting attempts at delving deeper into that crucial subject.
though I think still on the same "right" ontological basis of subject versus object, form versus
content, and so on.
30 Cf. Darko Suvin, "Looking Backward at Lukacs," To Brecht and Beyond (Brighton and Totowa,
N.J., 1984). pp. 75-79.
31 Draft of Engels's letter to Miss Harkness of Apr. 1888, in Karl Marx and Friedrich Engels,
Ueber Kunst und Literatur, ed. Michael Lifschitz (Berlin: Henschelverlag, 1953), p. 122.
However, I believe that at the back of Lukacs's mind is Simmel's discussion of all individuals
being also types (e.g., Soziologie, pp. 24-28). and probably some Russian nineteenth-century
criticism (for this last point I am indebted to discussions with Regine Robin, Le realisme
socialiste. forthcoming from Payot, Paris).
32 William Whewell, The Philosophy of Inductive Sciences (London: J. W Parker, 1840), 1:476-
77, quoted approvingly in T. H. Huxley, Man's Place in Nature, and Other Essays (London,
1906). p. 272; emphasis is mine. Appropriately, it was Whewell who coined the typifying
term "sc1entist." Very sim1lar is Balzac's definition in his preface to Une tenebreuse affaire:
"Un type ... est un personnage qui resume en lui-meme les traits caracteristiques de tous
ceux qui lui ressemblent plus ou moins, il est le modele du genre" (paraphrased in present-
day terms: A type is a narrative agent who blends characteristic traits of all characters of the
same category; he is the model of his genus).
33 E. H. Gombrich, Art and Illusion, Bollingen Series XXV-5 (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University
Press, 1972), p. 301.
34 Gombrich, p. 90; see also the psychological theories of Bruner and Postman as summarized
by Floyd H. Allport, Theories of Perception and the Concept of Structure (New York and
London, 1955), pp. 376ft., and with further bibliography; also the well-known works of Jean
Piaget and S. L. Vygotsky on perception.
35 Gombrich, p. 73. When applied to dramatis personae. any such approach necessarily issues
in discussions of typification as allegory; cf. the stimulating remarks of Fredric Jameson,
694
Darko Suvin
Marxism and Form (Princeton, N.J.: Princeton University Press. 1971 ). pp. 398-400. and
The Political Unconscious (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press 1981 ). pp. 160-64 passim.
36 Keir Elam, The Semiotics of Theatre and Drama (London: Methuen, 1980). p. 8.
37 This whole matter of masks and masking warrants special invest1gat1on as. I thmk, a theo-
retically crucial point in agential analysis.
38 Ju. M. Lotman and B. A. UspenskiJ, "'lntroduzione ... in Ricerche semiotiche (Torino. 1973).
p. xxvi.
39 As Levi-Strauss often also seems to believe; cf .. e.g., Anthropologie structurale, pp. 67.
106-not to speak of Chomsky's approving reference to the .. assumption that linguistic and
mental processes are virtually identical"' 1n Cartesian LinguistiCS (New York: Harper and Row.
1966). p. 31.
40 Aristotle, Poetics (see note 5. also the editor's comments on pp. 124-26, 202); ct. also
Rhetorics 11.12-17 on types by age and status. and Politics 1.2 on the polis versus the single
person. as well as Chatman. pp. 108-9, and Gombnch, p. 142. on types in Greek art.
41 Ct. Darke Suvin. "'On F1ction as Anthropology: Agential Analysis, Types. and the Classical
Chinese Novel, .. in J. Hall. ed .. Proceedings of the 1983 Conference on Literature and
Anthropology, University of Hong Kong Press (forthcoming).
42 Gombrich, p. 148, and esp. pp. 148-52. V. M. Zhirmunsk1i, Sravnite/'noe /iteraturovedenie-
Vostok i Zapad (Leningrad: Nauka. 1979). is one of the latest major scholars who notes how
1n both medieval and oral literature "'the typical dominates ... over the individual"' as creativity
is enclosed within literary genres that are bearers "'not of an individual and Idiosyncratic but
of a socially typical world view and style"' (pp. 161-62). The protagonist's behavior. too. is
here determined by norms of etat. mundane ritual. etiquette (p. 170)
43 Karl Marx. Capital, vol. 1 (New York: Vintage. 1977). p. 178. See Marx's whole key argument
on commodity fetishism. in which-very interestingly for further discussion of relations be-
tween agents and objects in fiction-he adds that reification of human relations is the obverse
of a personification of things. Cf. also Lukacs. History and Class Consciousness (Cambridge.
Mass.: Harvard University Press. 1971)
44 All the examples and quotes of historical semantics in th1s paragraph come from Raymond
Williams. Keywords (London: NLB. 1976). s.v. "'Individual ... "'Personality"' (for references
to "'character"'). and "'Subjective ... See also on the (bourgeo1s) legal framework as enforcing
individuality instead of a "'person-in-role"' or of "'role-slices ... Gottman, Encounters. p. 142;
and for the opinion that the subject/object division has been imported 1nto linguistic theory
from formal logic, the inventor of the term "'actant"' himself, Lucien Tesniere, Elements de
syntaxe structurale (Paris: C. Klincksieck. 1959). pp. 103-5.
45 Barthes. "'Introduction ... p. 16: "'une forme purement historique. restreinte a certains genres
(il est vrai les mieux conn us de nous) ..... ; ct. also the longer discussions in S!Z, pp. 141-
42, 153-54, 183-84. Propp has some very similar h1nts. On character requiring a number
of possibly contradictory traits, I am expanding from Chatman, pp. 121-22, who is indebted
to Forster (whose discussions derive in turn-just as Lukacs's do-from Hegel's Aesthetics,
perhaps the major source on individuality 1n art). Some of the most fascinating discussions
on the sense of the Self before individualism (both in tribal soc1et1es and in the Latin concepts
of res and persona) are to be found in Mauss. pp. 232-79, 337-62.
46 On culture industry, the pioneering text is Theodor Adorno and Max Horkheimer's vigorous
(if one-sided) Dialectics of Enlightenment (London: Continuum. 1979); see in particular, for
the evacuation of individuality. pp. 154-56. 84-86. 144.
47 Vito Pandolfi. II teatro del Rinascimento e Ia Commedia deii'Arte (Roma: Lerici, 1969). pp.
176. 180. Pantalone is. of course. a Commedia de/l'arte Maschera. and as such a type by
theatrical convention physically overcoded into a narrow range of looks and behaviors. Finally,
in the eighteenth century the bourgeoisie hit back and changed the nature of dramaturgic
agents: "'In the Commedia de/l'arte poor Pantalone was [ridiculed and deluded]; but in my
character Comedies I restored the reputation of this good figure. who represents an honest
Merchant of my Nation ... reported Goldoni; he therefore changed a dell'arte scenario with
a "'libertine. stupid, and ridiculous"' Pantalone into "'a moral comedy ... instructive for those
who are seduced by Interest or fnendship to entrust their cap1tal to suspect persons .
called The Bankruptcy"'; Carlo Goldoni. II teatro comico-Memorie ita/fane (Milano: Marsilio.
1982). pp. 189, 218.
48 My discussion of the onomastics of type uses the naive but rich work by Georges Doutrepont.
Les types populaires de Ia litterature franc;aise (Bruxelles. s a ) I am Indebted to John Ripley
and Charles Shattuck for counsels on English "'stock characters"' or theater types. It should
be noted that naming is a privileged p01nt of entry into discussions about individualistic fiction.
too; see. e.g., Barthes SIZ. pp, 74-75, 101-2. 196-97; Todorov. "'Personnage.'' with further
bibliography; Ju. M. Lotman and B. A. UspenskiJ, "'Myth-Name-Culture,"' in Daniel P.
695
Lucid. ed., Soviet Semiotics (Baltimore, Md.: Johns Hopkins University Press. 1977). pp.
233-52; and the disagreements a propos the eighteenth century between ian Watt, The
Rise of the Novel (London: Chatto and Wind us, 195 7). pp. 18ft .. and Joan Rockwell. Fact
in F1ction (London: Routledge and Kegan Paul. 1974). pp. 105ft.. as well as Wolfgang lser's
discussions of Fielding in Der implizite Leser (Munich: W. Fink. 1972) and "Die Wirklichkeit
der Fikt1on.'' 1n Rainer Warning, ed .. Rezeptionsasthetik (Munich: W. Fink. 1975). pp. 308ft.
49 Furthermore, when our understanding wishes. as IS proper. to embrace the temporally var-
iable agent1al system of any text or macrotext (ensemble of texts). agential hegemonies will
shift not only paradigmatically but also syntagmatically. In this essay I do not discuss syn-
tagmatic interaction. which is both more frequently studied then and yet logically posterior
to the paradigmatic interaction. and which can best be shown in estenso by applications to
particular texts.
696
Michele Barrett
Notes
I would like to thank Cora Kaplan and Mary Mcintosh for their help with this paper; also John
Tagg for his work in making more of Max Raphael's writings available in English.
712
Michele Barrett
Janet Wolff. Aesthetics and the Sociology of Art (London: Allen and Unwin, 1983). pp. 18-
19.
2 Terry Eagleton, Literary Theory (Oxford: Blackwell, 1983). p. 2.
3 Ronald Frankenberg. "Styles of Marxism; Styles of Criticism. Wuthering Heights: A Case
Study," Sociological Review Monograph, no. 26 (1978).
4 Terry Lovell. Pictures of Real1ty: Aesthetics. Politics, Pleasure (London: British Film Institute,
1980)
5 Roland Barthes, The Pleasure of the Text. trans. Richard M1ller (London: Cape, 1976).
6 Fredric Jameson, "Pleasure: A Political Issue," Formations of Pleasure (London: Routledge
and Kegan Paul, 1983).
7 Claire Pajaczkowska. "Structure and Pleasure," Block, no. 9 (1983). p. 13.
8 Peter Fuller, Art and Psychoanalysis (London: Writers and Readers Publishing Cooperative,
1980)
9 Max Raphael, The Demands of Art, trans. Norbert Guterman (London: Routledge and Kegan
Paul. 1968). p. 207. Hereafter cited in the text as DA.
10 I d1scuss this in "Feminism and the Definition of Cultural Politics," in Feminism, Culture and
Politics. ed. R. Brunt and C Rowan (London: Lawrence and Wishart, 1983).
11 See, for example, Heinnch Wolfflin, Classic Art (Oxford: Phaidon, 1980): "There is a con-
ception of art-history which sees nothing more in art than a 'translation of life' (Taire) into
pictorial terms. and which attempts to interpret every style as an expression of the prevailing
mood of the age Who would wish to deny that th1s is a fruitful way of looking at the matter?
Yet it takes us only so far-as far. one might say, as the point at which art beg1ns" (p. 287).
12 Max Raphael was born in Prussia 1n 1889 and educated in Germany. He lived in various
cities. including Paris, and in 1941 settled in New York, dying there in 1952. Much of his
work has been published posthumously and some of it is still not available in English. The
maJor works available are The Demands of Art; Proudhon, Marx, Picasso: Three Studies in
the Sociology of Art (trans. lnge Marcuse, ed. John Tagg [London: Lawrence and Wishart,
1980; New York: Humanities. 1980]). The latter contains a bibliography of Raphael's pub-
lished and unpublished work, compiled by John Tagg. My exposition is drawn largely from
The Demands of Art. wh1ch deals principally with aesthetic questions. Proudhon, Marx,
P1casso is more theoretical and sociological in 1ts focus.
13 Heinrich Wolfflm, Principles of Art History (New York: Dover, 1950). p. 226.
14 Raphael. Proudhon, Marx, Picasso, p. 83. Hereafter cited in the text as PMP.
15 An English translation of the relevant part of Raphael's Arbeiter, Kunst und Kunstler(Frankturt:
Fischer Verlag, 1975) by Anna Bostock appears under the title "Workers and the Historical
Heritage of Art," 1n On Art and Society, a supplement of Women and Art, Summer/Fall 1972
(New York).
16 John Tagg, "The Method of Criticism and Its Object in Max Raphael's Theory of Art," Block,
no. 2 (Spring 1980).
17 Raphael writes in The Demands of Art, "Were Picasso to prov1de an allegorical key to Guer-
nica. 1t would still be true that what he produced is ineffectual as propaganda and dubious
as a work of art" (p. 153).
18 Lukacs's view that in modernism "man IS reduced to a sequence of unrelated experiential
fragments" 1s summarized in "The Ideology of Modernism," The Meaning of Contemporary
Realism (London: Merlin, 1972)
19 See, for example. Anton Ehrenzweig, The Psycho-analysis of Artistic Vision and Heanng (New
York: Braziller. 1965). Ehrenzweig compares Cezanne's challenge to the convention of con-
stant peripheral v1sion with Picasso's challenge to that of constant localization.
20 Quoted in Tagg, "The Method of Criticism," p. 6.
21 Lovell, Pictures of Reality, chaps. 4, 5.
22 Terry Eagleton, "Poetry, Pleasure and Politics," Formations of Pleasure (London: Routledge
and Kegan Paul, 1983). p. 64
713
Fengzhen Wang
Notes
721
4 Marx. Engels. Lenin. and Stalin. On Literature and Art (Beijing: People's Literature Publishing
House, 1980). p. 101.
5 lb1d. p. 40.
6 Lukacs, Studies m European Realism (New York: Grosset and Dunlap, 1964). p. 21.
7 Marx et al., On Literature and Art, p. 130.
8 Marx. "Preface." p. 390.
9 Marx. Theses on Feuerbach.
722
Notes on Contributors
Hugo Achugar
Hugo Achugar was born in Montevideo, Uruguay, in 1944,
and received a Ph.D. in Latin American literature from the University of Pittsburgh.
He has taught at the Catholic University of Andreas Vello (Venezuela), the Central
University of Venezuela, and is currently at Northwestern University. He is the
author of more than ten books, including Textos para decir maria (1976) and Los
mariposas tropicales ( 1985).
Jack L. Amariglio
Jack L. Amariglio was born in Brooklyn, New York, in 1951.
For many years he was involved in community organizing in the working-class,
ethnically diverse neighborhood in which he grew up. He received his B.A. in history
from the City College of New York in 1973, his Ph.D. in economics from the
University of Massachusetts in 1984, and is currently teaching economics at Franklin
and Marshall College in Lancaster, Pennsylvania. He has published on the philos-
ophy and methodology of economics, economic history, economic anthropology,
and Marxist social theory, and is presently writing a book on different historical
forms of "primitive communism" in the pre-twentieth-century United States.
Perry Anderson
Perry Anderson was born Francis Rory Peregrine Anderson
in London in 1938 and was educated at Eton College and Oxford University, where
he received a B.A. in French and Russian literature. After serving for almost twenty
years as the editor of New Left Review, he remains the primary voice on the editorial
committee. He has done research and taught at the Maison des Sciences de L'Homme
(Paris), the University of Manchester, and the Central University ofVenezuela. His
books include Passages from Antiquity to Feudalism ( 197 4), Lineages ofthe Absolutist
State (1974), Considerations on Western Marxism (1976), Arguments within English
Marxism ( 1980), and In the Tracks ofHistorical Materialism ( 1984). His many essays
include several important ones published in NLR: "Components of the National
Culture," "The Antinomies of Antonio Gramsci," and "Trotsky's Interpretation of
Stalinism."
Stanley Aronowitz
Stanley Aronowitz was born in New York City in 1933 and
received his Ph.D. from the Union Graduate School. In the sixties he was a labor
and community organizer and coedited Studies in the Left; in the seventies he co-
founded the New American Movement (NAM). He is the author of many books,
including False Promises: The Shaping of American Working-Class Consciousness
(1973), The Crisis in Historical Materialism (1981), and Working-Class Hero: A New
Strategy for Labor (1983). His articles have appeared in The Nation, Village Voice,
and the Los Angeles Times, as well as numerous academic journals. He is currently
professor of sociology at the Graduate Center of the City University of New York
and the Center for Worker Education and is coeditor of Social Text.
Etienne Balibar
Etienne Balibar was born in Avallon (Yonne), France, in
1942 and studied at the Ecole Normale Superieure and the Sorbonne (with Jean
Hyppolite and Georges Canguilhem). He worked with Louis Althusser for many
years, coauthoring Reading Capital, and has taught at the University of Algiers, the
Sorbonne, and presently at the University of Paris; he has also taught in the Neth-
erlands, Cuba, and Mexico. After coorganizing the movement Pour L'union dans
les Luttes from 1978 to 1981, he was excluded from the Communist party for criti-
cizing its position on the question of immigrant workers in France. He has published
723
numerous books and articles, including Sur Ia dictature du proletariat (1976) and,
most recently, Spinoza, philosophie politique (1985).
Michele Barrett
Michele Barrett was born near London in 1949 and studied
sociology at the Universities of Durham and Sussex. She coedited Ideology and
Cultural Production (1979), edited Virginia Woolf: Women and Writing (1980),
authored Women's Oppression Today (1980), and coauthored The Anti-Social Fam-
ily (1982). Since 1977 she has taught sociology at the City University of London.
She is a member of the editorial collective of Feminist Review.
lain Chambers
lain Chambers was born near Manchester, England, in 1949,
and brought up near Bristol. He studied history and American studies at the Uni-
versity of Keele and did research at the Centre for Contemporary Cultural Studies
of the University of Birmingham. He is the author of Urban Rhythms (1985) and
Popular Culture: The Metropolitan Experience (1986) and currently teaches at the
University of Naples and publishes widely in both English and Italian.
Christine Delphy
Christine Delphy is a research fellow at the Centre National
de la Recherche Scientifique. She was a cofounder, with Simone de Beauvoir, of the
journal Questions Feministes and remains an editor of Nouvelles Questions Fem-
inistes. Her publications include The Main Enemy ( 1977) and Close to Horne: A
Materialist Analysis of Women's Oppression (1984).
Terry Eagleton
Terry Eagleton was born in Salford, England, in 1943. Ed-
ucated at Cambridge University, he currently teaches at Wadham College, Oxford.
He is the author of nine books, including Myths of Power: A Marxist Study of the
Brontes (1976), Criticism and Ideology (1976), Walter Benjamin, Or Towards a
Revolutionary Criticism (1981 ), and Literary Theory (1983). Most recently some of
his essays have been collected in Against the Grain ( 1986).
A. Belden Fields
A. Belden Fields was born in Chicago in 1937 and attended
the University of Illinois (A.B., 1960) and Yale University (M.A., Ph.D.). He teaches
political science at the University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign. His books in-
clude Student Politics in France: A Study of the Union Nationale des Etudiants de
France ( 1970) and Trotskyism and Maoism: Studies of Theory and Practice in France
and the United States ( 1983).
Jean Franco
Jean Franco was born in Durkinfield, England, in 1924 and
teaches in the department of Spanish and Portuguese at Columbia University. She
received a B.A. and M.A. in history from the University of Manchester and a second
B.A. and a Ph.D. in Spanish from the University of London. She has taught at
London, Essex, and Stanford universities and is a founding editor of Tabloid and a
member of the editorial collective of Social Text. She has published numerous articles
and books, including The Modern Culture of Latin America: Society and the Artist
(1967) and Cesar Vallejo: The Dialectics ofPoetry and Silence(l976). She is currently
working on a book on the relations between high, mass, and popular culture in Latin
America.
Simon Frith
Simon Frith was born in England in 1946 and received his
B.A. from Oxford University and his M.A. and Ph.D. in sociology from the Uni-
724
versity of California at Berkeley. A leading scholar on popular music, he teaches at
Warwick University. He is also a leading rock critic, frequently writing for Rolling
Stone, Village Voice, New Society, and other popular magazines. He served for four
years as rock critic for the Sunday Times (London) and is currently writing for The
Guardian. A founding member and for many years the chair of the British branch
of the International Association for the Study of Popular Music, his books on pop
music include The Sociology ofRock ( 1978) and Sound Effects ( 1981 ). He is currently
working on a book on the "art school connection" in British popular music.
Sue Golding
Sue Golding was born in New York in 1954 and has studied
at the University of Maryland (B.A.), Cambridge University, and the University of
Essex. She is completing her Ph.D. in politics at the University of Toronto and has
written on the concept of democracy in Gramsci's Prison Notebooks. She teaches
political science at Trent University and is a longtime activist in gay and feminist
politics, especially in struggles for sexual freedom.
Lawrence Grossberg
Lawrence Grossberg was born in New York City in 1947
and attended the University of Rochester, the Centre for Contemporary Cultural
Studies of the University of Birmingham, and the University of Illinois at Urbana-
Champaign, from which he received his Ph.D. in communications in 1976. He spent
a number of years traveling and performing in Europe in an itinerant anarchist
theater commune. The author of many articles in the areas of contemporary phi-
losophy and literary theory, cultural studies, philosophy of communication, and
popular music, he has served as assistant director of the Unit for Criticism and
Interpretive Theory at the University of Illinois and was the assistant director of
the summer program Marxism and the Interpretation of Culture. He is currently
completing a book with Stuart Hall and Jennifer Daryl Slack entitled Cultural Studies
and is also working on a book about postmodernism, cultural studies, and popular
culture called Another Boring Day in Paradise.
Stuart Hall
Stuart Hall was born in Kingston, Jamaica, in 1932 and
attended Oxford University as both a Rhodes Scholar and a Jamaica Scholar. A
founding member of the New Left Club and the first editor of New Left Review, he
also helped shape the Centre for Contemporary Cultural Studies at the University
of Birmingham, as a research associate and, from 1969 to 1979, as its director, and
is currently professor of sociology at the Open University. He has been active in a
variety of political struggles and is regarded by many as a leading spokesperson for
the British Left. Coeditor of many volumes of the Centre's research (e.g., Culture,
Media, Language [1980]), numerous Open University readers (e.g., Politics and Ide-
ology [1986]), and a number of books on the New Right and the state of the Left
(e.g., The Politics ofThatcherism [ 1983]), he also coauthored The Popular Arts ( 1964),
Policing the Crisis: Mugging, the State, and Law and Order (1978), and Cultural
Studies (forthcoming). His essays are currently being collected in a number of vol-
umes, including Reproducing Ideologies.
Eugene W. Holland
Eugene W. Holland was born in Princeton, N.J., in 1953 and
received his Ph.D. in French from the University of California at San Diego. He
has taught at Rice University, the University of Iowa, and currently in the depart-
ments of romance languages and humanities at Ohio State University. He has written
articles on nineteenth-century French literature and critical theory, including "The
Suppression of Politics in the Institution of Psychoanalysis" and "Narcissism from
Baudelaire to Sartre."
725
Fredric Jameson
Fredric Jameson was born in 1934 and has come to be re-
garded as perhaps the leading Marxist literary critic in the United States. Since
receiving his B.A. from Haverford College and his Ph.D. in French from Yale Uni-
versity, he has taught at Harvard and Yale universities, the University of California
at San Diego and at Santa Cruz, and currently at Duke University. He is coeditor
of Social Text and the author of many articles and books, including Sartre: The
Origins of a Style (1961), Marxism and Form (1971), The Prison-House ofLanguage
( 1972), Fabies of Aggression ( 1979), and The Political Unconscious ( 1981).
Ernesto Laclau
Emesto Laclau was born in Argentina in 1935 and was ed-
ucated at the University of Buenos Aires and Oxford University. He teaches in the
department of government of the University of Essex and in the department of
history at the University of Chicago. He is the author of Politics and Ideology in
Marxist Theory (1977) and coauthor, with Chantal Mouffe, of Hegemony and So-
cialist Strategy: Towards a Radical Democratic Politics (1985).
Henri Lefebvre
Henri Lefebvre was born in 1901 in Hegetman, Gascony,
and studied with Maurice Blonde! at the university in Aix-en-Provence and with
Leon Brunschvicg at the Sorbonne. He was, and remains, one of the most influential
figures in modem French Marxist theory. In the twenties, he cofounded the Philo-
sophies Group, which was initially closely allied with the surrealists. After joining
the PCF in 1928, the group began publishing La Revue Marxiste, which is often
described as the first serious French journal of Marxist theory. In the thirties, he
cotranslated the first selections of Marx's 1844 Manuscripts into French. He served
in the Resistance during the Second World War, and as a leading member of the
anti-Stalinist group within the PCF, he published an internal dissident journal, Voies
Nouvelles. In 1958 he was expelled from the party and became the moving force
behind the dissident Marxist journal Arguments. He has taught at the universities
of Strasbourg, Paris at Nan terre, and the Ecole Pratique des Hautes Etudes and has
published many books, ranging from his early readings of the more humanistic Marx
(e.g., Dialectical Materialism [ 1968], to his analysis of the events of 1968 (The Ex-
plosion [ 1969]), to his highly influential Everyday Life in the Modern World (1971).
Lefebvre currently lives in Paris and continues to write.
Julia Lesage
Julia Lesage is cofounder and editor of Jump Cut: A Review
of Contemporary Cinema, as well as the author of A Research Guide to Jean-Luc
Godard (1979). She has taught film theory, criticism, and production at many uni-
versities, including Northwestern, the University of Illinois at Chicago, Indiana Uni-
versity, and the Pontifical Catholic University (Lima, Peru). She has lectured and
published widely on a broad range of topics in contemporary cinematic theory and
practice, Marxism, and feminism.
Catharine MacKinnon
Catharine MacKinnon was born in 1947, attended Smith
College, and received her M.Phil. and J.D. (1977) from Yale University. She has
been active, as a scholar and lawyer, in many key court battles around issues of
gender, particularly in the areas of sex discrimination, sexual harassment, and por-
nography. Her first book, Sexual Harassment of Working Women: A Case of Sex
Discrimination (1979), helped to establish and define sexual harassment as a legal
injury. More recently, she has been a visible leader and spokesperson for the anti-
pornography movement. In addition, she has published a number of articles in
feminist theory (e.g., "Feminism, Marxism, Method and the State") which have
726
placed her at the center of current theoretical debates. Her new book, Feminism
Unmodified, will be published shortly. She has taught at the law schools of the
University of Minnesota and Harvard and Yale universities and is currently a vis-
iting scholar at Stanford University Law School.
Armand Mattelart
Armand Mattelart was born in Belgium in 1936 and received
his doctorate in law and political economy from the University of Louvain. From
1962 to 1973 he taught at the university in Santiago, Chile, where he worked closely
with the Allende government in the attempt to create new initiatives in popular
communication. Between 1975 and 1983 he was a professor at the University of
Paris, VII and VIII. He has carried out frequent missions for the governments of
France, Belgium, and Mozambique, and for the United Nations, in the area of
communications policy. Founder and coeditor of the journal. Comunicacion y Cui-
lura, which moved from Chile to Argentina and then to Mexico (in 1977), he is
currently professor of information sciences and communication and head of the
department at the University of Upper Brittany (Rennes II). He is the author of
many articles and books, including (with Ariel Dorfman) How to Read Donald Duck
(1975), Multinational Corporations and the Control of Culture (1979), Mass Media,
Ideologies and the Revolutionary Movement (1980), Transnationals and the Third
World: The Struggle for Culture (1983), and Communication and Information Tech-
nologies: Freedom of Choice for Latin America? ( 1984).
Michele Mattelart
Michele Mattelart was born in France in 1941 and studied
at the Sorbonne and the University of Paris. She is presently doing research at the
Centre National de la Recherche Scientifique in Paris. From 1963 to 1973 she lived
in Chile, teaching at the Catholic University of Chile and helping to found a center
for national study. During Allende's rule she was involved with both the national
television service and publishing for youth. Frequent trips and official missions since
then have maintained her close ties with Latin America. She has written many articles
and books, including La cultura de Ia opresion femenina (1977), Women and the
Cultural Industries ( 1981), and (with A. Mattelart and X. Delcourt) La culture contre
Ia democratie? (1985).
Franco Moretti
Franco Moretti was born in Italy in 1949 and is professor
ofEnglish literature at the University of Salerno. He is editor of the journals Calibano
and Quaderni Piacentini, has edited an anthology of criticism on T. S. Eliot ( 197 5),
and has written a study of English left-wing intellectuals in the thirties (1976). His
book, Signs Takenfor Wonder, was published in 1983.
Chantal Mouffe
Chantal Mouffe was born in 1943 in Baulet, Belgium, and
attended the Catholic University ofLouvain (B.A.), the University of Paris, and the
University of Essex (M.A.). She has taught at the National University of Colombia
and City University of London and is currently teaching at Westfield College of the
University of London and writing for various popular periodicals (e.g., The Guard-
ian, New Statesman, El Pais). She has written extensively on problems of ideology
and hegemony and has edited a collection of essays, Gramsci and Marxist Theory
(1979). Most recently, she coauthored Hegemony and Socialist Strategy: Towards a
Radical Democratic Politics (1985).
Oskar Negt
Oskar Negt was born in Konigsberg (now Kaliningrad) in
1934. He has studied and taught at the Universitat Frankfurt am Main, where he
727
was closely associated with the Frankfurt school of critical theory. He is currently
professor of sociology at the University of Hannover and has published numerous
articles and books, including Struckturbeziehungen Zwischen den Gesellschafislehren
Comtes und Hegel (1964), Universitat und Arbeiterbewegung(1968), and (with Alex-
ander Kluge) Offentlichket und Erfarhrung zur Organisationsanalyse (1972).
Cary Nelson
Cary Nelson was born in Philadelphia in 1946. Educated at
Antioch College and the University of Rochester, he is currently professor of English
and founding director of the Unit for Criticism and Interpretive Theory at the
University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign. The author of The Incarnate Word:
Literature as Verbal Space (1973) and Our Last First Poets: Vision and History in
Contemporary American Poetry (1981) and the editor of several books, including
Theory in the Classroom ( 1986), he is presently completing Reading Criticism: The
Literary and Institutional Status of Critical Discourse, chapters of which have ap-
peared in numerous books and journals, and Modern American Poetry and Literary
History.
Paul Patton
Paul Patton was born in Australia in 1950 and studied phi-
losophy at the University of Sydney, where he participated in the struggle for the
introduction of a women's studies course, which eventually led to the splitting in
two of the philosophy department. After receiving an M.A., he completed a Doctorat
d'Universite at the University of Paris at Vincennes in 1979. Since returning to
Australia he has taught social theory, epistemology, and the philosophy of science
at Macquarie and Griffith universities and the University of Sydney and is currently
at the University of New South Wales. A member of the Intervention Collective,
he has published essays and edited collections on, as well as translating, the work
of various contemporary French theorists, especially Foucault, Deleuze, and Baud-
rinard.
Michel Picheux
Michel Pecheux was born in France in 1938 and studied
philosophy under Louis Althusser at the Ecole Normale Superieure, participating in
Althusser's famous course for scientists (1967-68), out of which came Sur l'histoire
des sciences. His later works, including Language, Semantics and Ideology (1982)
and La langue introuvable, critically extend the theory of ideology in light of recent
developments in linguistic, psychoanalytic, and Marxist theory. Until his death in
1983 he was research director at the Centre National de Recherche Scientifique.
Gajo Petrovic
Gajo Petrovic has long had a prominent place in philosophy
in Yugoslavia and in the development of a humanistic "neo-Marxist" alternative
to orthodox Marxism in Eastern Europe. Born in the town ofKarlovac in 1927, he
was educated at the University of Zagreb (Ph.D. 1956), where he subsequently was
appointed to the philosophy faculty and for many years has been professor of phi-
losophy. The course of his philosophical development and career is reflected in the
changing nature of the books he has written. His first book, a study of the thought
of the orthodox Marxist Russian philosopher Plekhanov (The Philosophical Views
of G. V. Plekhanov, 1957), was followed seven years later by two books on matters
central to the Western analytic tradition (From Locke to Ayer and Logic, both 1964).
Petrovic then began publishing a series of books reinterpreting Marx's thought along
humanistic lines, departing markedly from the orthodox ("Stalinist") tradition: Phi-
losophy and Marxism (1965), Why Praxis? (1972), and Philosophy and Revolution
(1979). These books and other writings from the mid-1960s onward brought him to
the attention of philosophers in the West and established him as an important
728
contemporary interpreter of Marx. He also served as editor-in-chief of the journal
Praxis, in which a remarkable group of like-minded Yugoslav philosophers found
their voice and gained wide attention through their vigorous and bold contributions
to a new human-centered understanding of Marxism. During the first part of this
period, Petrovic and his colleagues focused their criticisms on the theory and practice
of Stalinist Marxism, valorized the Yugoslav alternative, and enjoyed the favor of
the political authorities in Yugoslavia. As they became disenchanted with and in-
creasingly critical ofYugoslav institutions and practices, however, they lost this favor
and eventually became the target ofharsh political criticism and repressive measures.
At various times they were forbidden to teach and publish in Yugoslavia; the regime
also sought to deprive them of their academic positons and to bring about their
exile. Petrovic led the resistance to these pressures, and he and his colleagues some-
how managed to weather the storm, refusing either to abandon their philosophical
and critical course or to quit their positions and their country. His and their position
remains a difficult and tenuous one; but, with his colleagues, Petrovic continues to
teach and write in Yugoslavia and to contribute to the further development of
Marxist philosophy.
Fred Pfeil
Fred Pfeil was born in 1949 in Port Allegany, Pennsylvania,
"a white rural factory town." He "escaped to Amherst College, there to receive equal
doses of Civilization and Snobbery" and to work with Tillie Olsen, his first mentor
as a fiction writer. While working on a master's degree in creative writing at Stanford
University, he labored in a variety of"mainly bottom-line jobs" and was employed
by the Navy to teach sailors aboard the USS Agerholm in the Pacific. He has taught
English at Stephens College in Missouri and currently teaches in the departments
of English and twentieth-century studies at Oregon State University at Corvallis. He
was a member of NAM and is currently active in Central America solidarity work
and the construction of the Rainbow Coalition. Since 1982 he has been coeditor of
The Minnesota Review, a "journal of committed writing." He has written a number
of essays on literature, criticism, and music, in addition to a large body of fictional
work. His novel, Goodman 2020, was published in 1986, and a collection of his
short stories is due out shortly. He is presently working on a documentary novel
about the relationships between patterns of masculinity and corporate capitalism in
late-nineteenth-century America.
Stephen A. Resnick
Stephen A. Resnick was born in 1938 and received his Ph.D.
in economics from M.I.T. in 1964. He has taught at Yale University and City College
of New York and currently teaches economics at the University of Massachusetts
at Amherst. He has published on such topics as imperialism, international trade and
the European Common Market, and economic history. A cofounder, in 1983, of the
Association for Economic and Social Analysis, his books include Colonial Devel-
opment: An Econometric Study (with Thomas Birnberg, 1975) and Marxist Theory:
Epistemology, Class, Enterprise and State (with Richard Wolff, forthcoming). He
has also coedited Rethinking Marxism: Struggles in Marxist Theory (1986).
729
Mass Media upon It: A Latin American Perspective (1977), and Cuba: Diez anos de
revo/ucion ( 1969).
Andrew T. I. Ross
Andrew T. I. Ross was born in 1956 and educated in Scot-
land, where he spent some time working in the North Sea oil fields. After doing
doctoral research at the University of Kent, Indiana University, and the University
of California at Berkeley (receiving his Ph.D. in English and American literature
from the University of Kent at Canterbury), he worked at Illinois State University
and is currently teaching English at Princeton University. A member of the editorial
collective of Social Text, he has published on a wide range of topics, including
cultural theory, sexual politics, psychoanalysis, television, modem literature, and
literary criticism. The author of The Failure of Modernism: Symptoms ofAmerican
Poetry (1986), he is also the cotranslator of Jacques Aumont's Montage Eisenstein
( 1986) and is currently working on a study of intellectuals and mass culture.
Michael Ryan
Michael Ryan was born in Ireland in 1951 and received a
B.A., M.A., and Ph.D. from the University oflowa. He has taught at the University
of Virginia and currently at Northeastern University and is the author of Marxism
and Deconstruction: A Critical Articulation (1982) and coauthor (with Douglas Kell-
ner) of The Politics and Ideology of Contemporary American Film. He is also the
cotranslator of Antonio Negri's Marx beyond Marx (1984).
Richard Schacht
Richard Schacht was born in Racine, Wisconsin, in 1941,
and received a B.A. from Harvard University, an M.A. and Ph.D. in philosophy
from Princeton University, and did postgraduate work at Tiibingen University. He
is currently professor and chair of the philosophy department at the University of
Illinois at Urbana-Champaign and has published widely in European philosophy
since Kant, philosophical anthropology, social theory, value theory, and the philos-
ophy of art. His books include Alienation ( 1970), Hegel and After: Studies in Con-
tinental Philosophy between Kant and Sartre ( 1975), Nietzsche ( 1983), and Classical
Modern Philosophers: Descartes to Kant (1984). He is currently working on a book
on human nature.
730
Darko R. Suvin
Darko R. Suvin was born in 1930 in Zagreb, Yugosalvia,
and studied at the University of Bristol, the Sorbonne, and Yale University, in
addition to receiving a B.A., M.S., and Ph.D. from Zagreb University. He is ex-
tremely active in many organizations concerned with both theater and science fiction
(e.g., he served as coeditor of Science Fiction Studies from 1973 to 1981) and is
currently professor of English and comparative literature at McGill University and
vice-president of the International Brecht Society. He has edited numerous volumes
on Brecht and science fiction, and in addition to his many academic contributions
he writes theater criticism. He has published many books on a diverse range of
topics, most recently Metamorphoses of Science Fiction: On the Poetics and History
of a Literary Genre (1979), Victorian Science Fiction in the U.K.: The Discourses of
Knowledge and of Power (1983), and To Brecht and Beyond: Soundings in Modern
Dramaturgy (1984).
Fengzhen Wang
Fengzhen Wang, an editor, critic, and translator, was born
in 1942 to a farmer's family in north China. His early schooling, "directed in ac-
cordance with the mottos 'carefully read and write, do physical exercises every morn-
ing,'" included studies at Lincheng High School and Peking University. Wang's
talent for literature was exhibited in high school when he won the local award for
poetry in 1958. From 1968 to 1977 he worked as a businessman and interpreter in
a foreign trade company in Beijing. Since 1978 he has been an editor of World
Literature, a leading magazine in China for translations of foreign literary works
and critical essays, and a lecturer at the Institute of Foreign Literature of the Chinese
Academy of Social Sciences. "During the Cultural Revolution I was sent to a farm
to do physical labor for a year, which enriched my experience of life. With the
difficulties facing intellectuals at that time, I managed to get some science fiction
books to read and later became a well-known critic in that field." Since the end of
the Cultural Revolution he has written essays on foreign writers such as John Keats,
Thomas Hardy, Joseph Conrad, and Nathaniel Hawthorne, as well as on the practice
of Western literary criticism. He has translated the works of Rene Wellek, Northrop
Frye, Erskine Caldwell, John Wain, and others, and has compiled a number of
anthologies of English and American stories and critical essays. He has been a visiting
scholar at UCLA and is now working on a book about his visit to the United States,
as well as on a brief history of Western literary criticism.
Cornel West
Cornel West was born in 1953 and received a B.A. from
Harvard University and an M.A. and Ph.D. (1980) in philosophy from Princeton
University. He has taught at the Union Theological Seminary and is currently teach-
ing the philosophy of religion at the Divinity School of Yale University. He is a
member of the editorial collective of Social Text and has been involved for many
years in Afro-American and socialist politics. The author of Prophesy Deliverance!
An Afro-American Revolutionary Christianity (1982), he has written extensively on
the relations of Afro-American experience, theology, and Marxism, as well as on
contemporary hermeneutic and Marxist philosophy.
Richard D. Wolff
Richard D. Wolff was born in 1942 and attended Harvard
University and Stanford University, receiving his Ph.D. in economics from Yale
University in 1969. He has taught at Yale University and City College ofNew York
and currently teaches economics at the University of Massachusetts at Amherst. He
has published widely on such topics as colonialism in Africa, imperialism, and the
theory of economic crises. He has also been active in the U.S. labor movement and
socialist community organizations since the 1960s. In 1974 he published The Eco-
731
nomics ofColonialism: Britain and Kenya, 1870-1930. His recent work with coauthor
Stephen Resnick on certain basic theoretical problems in the Marxist tradition cul-
minated in the forthcoming Marxist Theory: Epistemology, Class, Enterprise and
State. He has also coedited Rethinking Marxism: Struggles in Marxist Theory (1976)
and was a cofounder of the Association for Economic and Social Analysis.
732
Index
733
Dante (Dante Alighieri). 83 tory of Primitive Christian-
Darwin, Charles. 177 ity," 186-88, 193-94;
Daughtry, Rev. Herbert. 26n, 28n Dialectics of Nature, 173.
Davagnino. Miguel. 454 174-77, 178; History of
Davis. Mike, 290-91 Natural Creation. 177-
Day, Jen. 374 80; "Juridical Socialism,"
Debord, Guy, 352, 411 183-86; Ludwig Feuer-
Debray, Regis, 329 bac~ 180-83, 192-93.
Debs. Eugene. 19 See also Marx, Karl. and
Deleuze. Gilles. 25, 28-29n, 123-24. Friedrich Engels
129.138,151.285, Engels. Stephanie, 396
308; "Intellectuals and Enzensberger. Hans Magnus. 363,
Power," 272-80, 282- 378n
83, 286, 289-90 Ewald. Francois. 129
Deleuze. Gilles. and Felix Guattari, 28n;
Anti-Oedipus. 126-27. Fa non. Frantz. 17. 426-28. 503-4,
137. 273-74, 279. 514-15
310n, 312n,405-8, Ferguson. Adam. 167
410-11.414-15. 415n; Feuerbach. Ludwig, 164, 168. 235
Mille Plateaux, 124, Feyerabend. Paul. 135-36n. 138-39,
127-28. 135n; "Rhi- 264. 529, 532, 538
zome," 125. 127, 132 Fink, Eugene. 248n
Delphy, Christine. 135n, 539, 540-41 FitzGerald. Edward. 306
de Man. Paul. 624-31 Flaubert. Gustave. 342
Denby, Edwin, 386 Forman, James, 19-20, 26n
Derrett. J. M .. 298 Forster. E. M .. 669
Derrida, Jacques. 17-18, 23, 25, 52, Foucault, Michel, 11,17-18,23,25,
138,271,284.297, 27n. 28n. 51-53, 56.
308, 309n, 310n, 379n, 68,70-71, 123-24.
413-14,499n, 523. 125. 128. 132-33, 138,
629; Of Grammatology, 143-46, 147-49. 151.
291-94, 311n; "Struc- 226. 285, 292. 294,
ture, Sign, and Play in the 308.349.392-93.414.
Discourse of the Human 415n,489, 504,523.
Sciences," 254 64 7; The Archaeology of
Descartes. Rene. 113 Knowledge, 51-53,
Dewey, John, 529-30, 531. 539 492-95, 500n; Discipline
Dews. Peter. 313n and Punish, 52. 126-27,
DiBianco. Doug, 338 129.132-33; TheHis-
Dickens. Charles. 718 torv of Sexuality, 52; "In-
Dilthey, Wilhelm. 205-6n tellectuals and Power,"
Dinnerstein, Dorothy, i09, 393, 395. 272-80, 282-83, 286.
403n 289-90; Power/Knowl-
Donoso. Jose. 51 0-11 edge, 274, 280-81.
Dovjenko. Alexandr P.. 435 285, 290-91, 298,
Du Bois, W. E. B.. 17 309n
Durkheim, Emile, 52-53. 71 Fowler. Alaistair, 656
Dworkin, Andrea. 118. 120 Fox-Genovese. Elizabeth, 295
Dyer. Richard. 613 Frankenberg, Ronald, 699
Fraser, Nancy, 138, 358
Eagleton. Terry, 291. 377. 698 Friedrich, Hugo, 655
Eastman, Max. 29n Freud, Sigmund. 50, 76, 78, 84,
Eco. Umberto. 690 108-9, 204n, 205n,
Eisenstein, Sergej M .. 364 228, 234, 252-53.
Elser. Jon, 255 296-97. 309n,424
Empson. William. 619-31 Fromm. Erich, 224-25
Engels. Friedrich. 6, 76, 85, 86, 162. Frye, Northrop, 684, 685
205n. 206n, 207n. Fuentes. Carlos. 51 0
208n. 223-24. 232. Fuller. Peter. 700
242-44, 717; Anti-DOh-
ring, 172-77, 198, 574; Galbraith. J. K.. 431
"Contribution to the His- Gamble, Andrew. 39
734
Gandhi, Mahatma, 302 196,201,211,213,
Garcia, Ricardo, 456 221, 228, 252
Garcia Marquez, Gabriel, 508, 510, Heidegger, Martin, 87, 207n
511-12 Heisenberg, Werner, 113, 525, 533
Garvey, Marcus, 20 Hejinian, Lyn, 373, 377
Genovese, Eugene, 28n Henley, Nancy, 421
Gems, Norman, 331,625 Henry, Paul. 49
Geschwender, James A., 21 Herr, Michael, 351
Giddens, Anthony, 156n Herzog, Werner, 504
Ginsberg, Allen, 364 Hindess, Barry, and Paul Hirst, 149,
Glass, Philip, 382, 401 n; and Godfrey 151,253, 311n, 354,
Reggio, 398-99 489
Glucksman, Andre, 128 Hjelmslev, L., 673, 674
Godard, Jean-Luc, 328-29 Hobbes, Thomas, 59, 164
Godoy, Alvaro, 453 Hook, Sidney, 522-23
Godwin, William, 95 Hooks, Rev. Benjamin, 28n
Goethe, Johann von, 83, 319, 341- Horkheimer, Max, 367, 526-27
42, 343 Husser!, Edmund, 538
Goldmann, Lucien, 248n
Gombrich, Ernst. 684-85 lnglehart, Ronald, 149
Gorz, Andre, 519-20, 521
Graff, Gerald, 381 Jackson, Jesse, 28n, 425
Graham, Loren, 528 Jacoby, Russell, 124
Gramsci, Antonio, 5, 24-25, 33, 38, Jakobson, Roman, 377, 646
47, 53-57, 59, 63, 69- Jameson, Fredric, 31 On, 311-1 2n,
70, 99, 102-3, 103-4, 327, 372, 377, 382,
184, 190, 191, 192, 385,387-88,391,397,
201, 206n, 207n, 246, 402-3n,403n, 700
252, 283, 326, 332, Jay, Peter, 47
366, 477, 499n, 538; Jefferson, Thomas, 59
The Modern Prince, 55; Joseph, Sir Keith, 38, 46-47, 62
Prison Notebooks, 3; Joyce, James, 79,339,342-44,362
Ouaderni, 543-58, 558-
62n Kafka, Franz, 339
Greimas, A. J., 670, 671-77, 691n, Kamenka, Eugene, 566
693n Kane, P. V., 300-304
Grlic, Danko, 239 Kangraga, Milan, 239
Grossberg, Larry, 615 Kant, Immanuel, 164, 168, 202, 211,
Guattari, Felix. See Deleuze, Gilles, and 216-17, 255, 572
Felix Guattari Kautsky, Karl, 175, 183-86
Guevara, Che, 664-65 Kedrov, B., 206n
Guha, Ranajit. 283-85, 288 Kenner, Hugh, 362, 378n
Kern berg, Otto, 41 0
Habermas, Jlirgen, 145-49, 213, Kerouac, Jack, 137
248n, 523-24, 526, Keynes, John Maynard, 76
527-28, 534; Legitima- Kierkegaard, S0ren, 343
tion Crisis, 145-46, 148; Kilson, Martin, 21
"New Social Move- King, Martin Luther, Jr., 155
ments," 146-49, 150, Kirk, Richard, 20
151-53, 154 Klein, Melanie, 391-92
Haeckel, Ernst, 177 Kofman, Sarah, 296
Hall, Stuart, 28n, 96, 120, 135n, Kohut. Heinz, 41 0
358-59,477 Korsch, Karl, 3, 5
Harryman, Carla, 374 Kramer, Hilton, 381
Hartsock, Nancy, 506-7, 51 2 Krauss, Rosalind, 387, 40 1-2n
Hassan, lhab, 359 Kuhn, Thomas, 524, 528-29, 532
Hayek, Friedrich A., 97, 100
Haywood, Harry, 19 Labriola, A., 246
Heath, Edward, 37-38 Lacan, Jacques, 48-49, 49-51, 67-
Heath, Stephen, 477 68, 90, 132, 255, 389,
Hebdige, Dick, 4 71, 612 390, 392, 395, 402-3n,
Hegel, G. W. F., 78, 85, 86, 87, 164, 406, 410, 424, 482,
177, 178, 181, 193, 646
735
Laclau, Ernesto, 25, 49, 56, 66, 134, 84-87,99, 106, 126,
149-50, 151,360,538. 12 9' 14 1' 160' 16 7'
540, 612, 614-15 173. 204n. 208n, 209n.
Lasch, Christopher. 395, 397, 403n, 213-14,215-16,217,
405-6, 410-12 218,220-21,227,
Lassalle, Ferdinand, 78, 223 229-31, 234n, 235,
Lautreamont. Le Comte de, 340 241-44,245-47, 268,
Le Bon. Gustave, 207n 271,279,285, 295-96,
Lefebure. A., 591 309n. 310n, 330-31.
Lefebvre. Henri. 5, 6, 246, 351. 607 334, 336, 368, 372,
Leibn1tz, Gottfried Wilhelm von. 253, 394, 406, 424, 522,
255 565, 567-73, 576, 577,
Le Nain. Louis, 708 642, 717; Capital. 162,
Lenin, V. I., 76, 85, 86, 160, 184, 175-76, 191-92, 194,
190,191,200-201, 222-23, 230, 231'
207n, 211, 212,243, 232-33, 408, 500n.
247, 251-52, 349, 366, 51 9. 641 ; The Critique of
665 the Gotha Program. 76,
Levi-Strauss, Claude. 67. 291, 384- 78,185. 197; The Eigh-
85, 672 teenth Brumaire of Louis
Lewontin, Richard C.. 499n Bonaparte. 42, 162,
Llosa, Mario Vargas. 509-1 0 222,276-78,285,411,
Loria, A., 560n 677; Grundrisse, 162,
Lorde, Audre. 31 233, 322, 330-31'
Lovell. Terry, 699, 711 495-96; Preface to A
Lowery, Rev. Joseph, 28n Contribution to the Cri-
Lukacs, Georg, 3, 3-4. 4-5, 5. 43, tique of Political Economy,
83, 114, 202, 219, 246, 551; Theses on Feuer-
323-24, 335, 337, 366, bach, 549-50, 554. 555
377, 409, 499, 520, Marx, Karl, and Friedrich Engels, 2-3,
535n, 678-83, 717, 76, 189-91, 194-203,
718-19 204n. 205n, 208n, 211,
Luxemburg, Rosa, 3. 26n, 80. 244- 212-13, 223, 225,
50 227-28, 232. 719; The
Lynch, Kevin, 353 Communist Manifesto,
43, 166, 167, 170-72,
Lyotard. Jean-Franc;:ois. 300
205n, 231,318,320-
22, 416n, 681; Eco-
Macaulay, Thomas Babington. 282
nomic and Philosophical
MacCabe, Colin. 345
Manuscnpts, 3, 13n.
MacDiarmid, Hugh, 362
141 ; The German Ideol-
Mach, Ernst, 693n ogy, 41-42, 43-45, 46,
Macherey, Pierre. 286-87, 377 161, 163-70, 172, 174,
Machiavelli, Niccolo, 164, 181. 546 180-81, 197, 204n,
Macmillan, Harold, 36 372, 536n
Mclaren, Malcolm, 465-66 Masaryk, Thomas, 249
MacPherson, C. B., 102 Mathieu, Mireille, 434
Mallet, Serge, 248n. 521 Matisse, Henri, 667
Malraux, Andre, 431 Mayakofsky, Vladimir, 365
Mandel, Ernest. 4, 350 Mayer, Arno, 324-25
Mann, Thomas, 76,341 Menger, Anton, 183
Mao Zedong (Mao Tse-tung). 190, Miege, Bernard, 594
202,211,664,665, Miller, J. Hillis, 414
715-16 Miller, Jacques-Aiain, 280
Marcuse, Herbert, 92, 117, 248n. Mitterand, Franc;:ois, 431, 581-82,
367, 368, 379n, 527- 585-86, 604-5n
28, 530 Montesquieu, Baron de, 330
Mariategui, Jose Carlos, 27n Moore, Barrington, 31
Marquez, Enrique, 455 Moore, Charles, 413
Marsh, Dave, 462 Moretti, Franco, 328, 335
Marvell, Andrew, 625 Morris, Charles, 674
Ma~. Karl, 11, 45, 68,72-73,75, Mouffe, Chantal, 138, 149-51, 152,
76, 77-79, 80, 82, 83, 360
736
Nandy, Ashis, 300 Rodriguez, Silvio, 449-50
Negri. Tony, 208n, 416 Rorty, Richard, 28-29n
Negt, Oskar, 9, 205n Rose, Peter, 137
Neruda. Pablo, 652, 655, 658 Rosselson, Leon, 473-74
Newton-Smith, W., 532, 537n Rousseau, Jean-Jacques, 104, 182,
Nietzsche, Friedrich, 76, 130, 235, 330
406, 568, 578, 627 Rubin, Gayle, 265-66, 402n
Norris, Christopher, 624. 628, 629 Russel, Charles, 387
Nozick, Robert, 152 Russell, Bertrand, 252, 253
Russolo, Luigi, 607-8
Offe. Claus, 93 Ryan, Michael, 137, 416n
O'Hara, Frank, 372
Oilman, Bertell, 566 Sahlins, Marshall, 489
Olson. Charles, 363 Said, Edward, 280, 283, 292, 306
Omvedt, Gail, 311 n Sanguinetti, E.. 655
Oppen, George, 361-63, 378n Sartre, Jean-Paul, 6, 145, 391, 405,
Owens, Craig, 384,387, 401n 415n
Saussure, Ferdinand de, 7, 49, 499n
Pacheco, Jose Emilio, 658 Schiller, Jon, 389, 392, 403n
Pajaczkowska, Claire, 700 Schmitt, Carl, 341, 343
Palloix, Christian, 535n Schumpeter, Joseph, 76
Palomares, Gabino, 454, 457 Scola, Ettore, 440
Parfit, Derek, 627 Segre, Cesare, 692n
Passeron, J. C., 602 Sennett, Richard, 340
Patterson, Orlando, 28n, 31 Shastri, Mahamahopadhyaya Harapra-
Patton, Paul, 70, 151-54 sad, 282
Pavis, Patrice, 693-94n Shklovsky, Viktor, 371-72
Paz, Octavia, 506, 652, 655, 657 Silliman, Ron, 369, 372, 379n, 380n
Pecheux, Michel, 49, 208n Simmel, Georg, 340, 535n
Peery, Nelson, 19, 26n Smith, Adam, 46, 166
Peirce, Charles Sanders, 524 Snowden, Frank, 30
Peralta, Eduardo, 457-58 Sohn-Rethel, Alfred, 248n
Perelman, Bob, 374 Solzhenitsyn, Aleksandr, 337
Perloff. Marjorie, 381, 400n Sontag, Susan, 431
Petrovic. Gajo, 334 Souriau, Etienne, 671
Piaget, Jean, 145 Souza, Chico Mario de, 454, 457
Picasso, Pablo, 652, 707-8 Sowell, Thomas. 21
Plato. 78 Spinoza, Benedict, 204n, 253
Plekhanov, G. V., 202, 243, 247, Spivak, Gayatri Chakravorty, 10-11,
251, 253, 716 110,111,113,117,
Poggioli, Renata, 41 2 423-24
Polsby, Nelson W., 156n Stalin, Joseph, 4, 20, 76
Ponge, Francis, 363 Stein, Gertrude, 375
Popper, Karl, 215, 529 Stendhal, 345
Poulantzas, Nicos, 42, 69, 489 Stevens, Wallace, 414
Pound, Ezra, 361, 362, 363 Stirner, Max, 164
Powell, Anthony, 326, 337 Surkin, Marvin, and Dan Georgakis,
Powell, Enoch, 38 351-52
Propp, Vladimir, 670-71 Suvin, Darko, 346, 348, 359
Swift, Jonathan, 630
Rank, Otto, 31
Raphael, Max, 702-12, 713n Tagore, Rabindranath, 301
Rasu~.Jed, 370, 379n Thatcher, Margaret, 36, 38, 40, 47,
Raulet, Gerard, 135n 60, 62, 65, 98
Reagan, Ronald, 65, 98, 154, 462. Thompson, E. P. (Edward), 6; The Pov-
628 erty of Theory, 35
Reich, Wilhelm, 71-72, 228, 274 Thompson, Edward: Suttee, 282, 301,
Rey, P.-P., 489 305-6
Reyes, Alfonso, 505 Thurley, Geoffrey, 363
Ricardo, David, 68, 552 Timpanaro, Sebastiana, 625
Richardson, Samuel, 506 Tocqueville, Alexis de, 89, 94, 101
Rimbaud, Arthur, 665 Tolstoy, Leo, 83
737
Tourraine, Alain, 98 Williamson, Judith, 389-91, 402-3n
Trotsky, Leon, 251 Willis Ellen, 117-19, 120, 121
Tucker, Robert, 566 Wilson, Harold, 36-37
Tzara, Tristan, 76 Wilson, Robert, and Philip Glass, 384,
397-98, 399
Vallejo, Caesar, 508, 652-53 Wilson, William Julius, 21
Van Eyck, Aldo, 356 Wing, Bob, 20-21
Vian, Boris, 434
Wiseman, Frederick, 143
Vico, Giambattista, 544-45, 558n
Wittgenstein, Ludwig, 254, 669
Volosinov, V. N., 45, 669
Wollstonecraft, Mary, 95
Wainwright, Hilary, 130
Washington, Harold, 425 Xun, Lu, 720
Watten, Barrett, 361, 373, 375-76
Weber, Max, 234, 409
Yeats, William Butler, 345
Welles, Orson, 443n
West, Cornel, 337, 360
Wickham, Gary, 52 Zaid, Gabriel, 657
Wilde, Oscar, 698 Zhdanov, Andrei, 716
Williams, Raymond, 6, 382-83, 400- Zueqin, Cao, 720
401n, 621-24, 625 Zukofsky, Louis, 363, 364-65
738