Ruse, M. Charles Darwin's Theory of Evolution An Analys
Ruse, M. Charles Darwin's Theory of Evolution An Analys
Ruse, M. Charles Darwin's Theory of Evolution An Analys
An Analysis
MICHAEL RUSE
Departmen t of Philosophy
University of Guelph
Guelph, Ontario
NATURAL SELECTION
Journal of the History ofBtology, vol. 8, no. 2 (Fall 1975), pp. 219-241.
Copyright © 1975 by D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht-Holland.
MICHAEL RUSE
220
Charles Darwin's Theory of Evolution: An Analysis
some way to each being in the great and complex battle of life,
should sometimes occur in the course of thousands o f generations?
If such do occur, can we doubt (remembering that many more in-
dividuals are born than can possibly survive) that individuals having
any advantage, however slight, over others, would have the best
chance o f surviving and of procreating their kind? On the other
hand, we may feel sure that any variation in the least degree injur-
ious would be rigidly destroyed. This preservation of favourable
variations and the rejection of injurious variations, I call Natural
Selection. 6
221
MICHAEL RUSE
222
Charles Darwin's Theory of Evolution: An Analysis
223
MICHAEL RUSE
DOMESTIC ORGANISMS
224
Charles Darwin's Theory of Evolution: An Analysis
225
MICHAEL RUSE
What I shall argue is that the first two chapters of the Orion were
important for Darwin just as much for the support they gave to his
theory as for their illustration of his thought processes, enabling the
new reader more easily to grasp the contentious points of the theory. 14
Furthermore, I shall argue that this support, although part of Darwin's
theory, was not linked deductively with the rest of the theory, and that
hence, in an least one place in the Or/gin, Darwin's method of inference
was analogical or, more generally, inductive. In other words, I shall
suggest that grave doubt must be thrown on the supposed overall hypo-
thetico-deductive nature of Darwin's theory (even if we ignore the
point I made previously about the nonlawlike nature of some Darwin's
premises).
That Darwin's discussions of artificial selection and of variation in the
wild do have a justificatory role in his thought emerges clearly f~om his
arguments toward natural selection. Consider for a moment Darwin's
claims about the existence of favorable and injurious variations, which,
as we have seen, occur as premises in Darwin's arguments to natural
selection. What evidence did Darwin give for the claims? He wrote:
"Let it be borne in mind how infinitely complex and close-fitting are
the mutual relations of all organic beings to each other and to their
physical conditions of life. Can it, then, be thought improbable, seeing
that variations useful to man have undoubtedly occured, that other
variations useful in some way to each being in the great and complex
battle of life, should sometimes occur in the course of thousands of
generation? ''is Obviously, at this point Darwin was supporting his
premises by an analogical argument. But what is this argument? It goes
something like this.
14. See also M. Ruse, "The Value of Analogical Models in Science," Dialogue,
12 (1973), 243-253.
15. Darwin, Origin, p. 80.
226
Charles Darwin's Theory of Evolution: An Analysis
227
MICHAEL RUSE
throw out the argument to natural selection as well? And so, for the
sake of a philosophical thesis, Darwin's theory starts to reduce down to
a bare statement o f the principle o f natural selection. If we are to avoid
this, and I think we should, then I think we must learn to live with
Darwin's arguments for different kinds o f variation.
The other face-saving move for the hypothetico-deductive theorist is
to try to convert Darwin's analogical argument into a deductive argu-
ment. There are two difficulties with this move. In the first place, I am
not sure just what kind o f general premise would suffice to make
Darwin's argument deductive - at least I am not sure of any premise
which has any vague hope of being b o t h true and factual. One seems to
need a premise like "Whenever one has a group o f organisms, some o f
t h e m will have some variations which are in some sense useful to some-
one, possibly themselves or possibly someone else." This woolly state-
ment is a much weaker reed than anything on which Darwin in fact
rested his case. And this brings me to the second difficulty. Other than
for the sake o f saving the hypothetico-deductive thesis, why should one
convert Darwin's argument into a deductive one? There is no evidence
that Darwin really thought deductively - i n d e e d we all often argue
analogically without in any sense presupposing general premises which
would make our arguments deductive. I may buy a second pair o f shoes
from a store because m y first pair wore very well without at all suppos-
ing that every pair of shoes from the store wears well (or that every pair
of a more limited kind wears well). Darwin did not give us a deductive
argument, there is no evidence that he intended to give us a deductive
argument (although he thought his conclusion was well taken, as we
often do in the case o f analogical arguments) - i n d e e d , he tells us
explicitly in his correspondence that he is using an analogical argu-
ment 16 - therefore I see no reason to make his argument deductive. At
this point, the hypothetico,deductive model does not fit.
We come now to that part o f the Origin, much the largest part, which
comes after the demonstration o f the existence o f natural selection.
Here Darwin showed how the continued (evolutionary) effects of
natural selection could be used to solve problems in geology, paleon-
16_ "In fact the belief in Natural Selection must at present be grounded
entirely on general considerations [including] the analogy of change under domes-
tication by man's selection." Letter to G. Bentham, in F. Darwin, ed., Life and
Letters of Charles Darwin (London: Murray, 1887), III, 25.
228
Charles Darwin's Theory of Evolution: An Analysis
229
MICHAEL RUSE
other words, the relative proportion of fast and slow wolves would
remain constant.
I am not saying that this would ever actually be the case for wolves; is
but the point is that were Darwin offering us deductive arguments or, at
least, were he offering us valid deductive arguments, then if his premises
were true, his conclusion would have to be true. My counter-example
shows this not to be the case. Of course, it might be claimed that my
choosing this example is a little unfair, since at the point at which
Darwin gave this argument he could hardly appeal to the laws of
heredity: the illustration about the evolution of wolves occurs in the
fourth chapter; but it is not until the fifth chapter that Darwin dealt in
any detail with the laws o f heredity, specifically, with the laws govern-
ing the introduction of new variation. Perhaps only after this could we
expect Darwin to work with deductive rigor.
However, this defense of Darwin really does not solve very much. In
the first place, it does not alter the fact that the passage I am consider-
ing does not contain a deductively rigorous argument. In the second
place, even a hasty perusal of Darwin's fifth chapter ("Laws of Varia-
tion") shows that it is hardly likely to bring us to a precise exemplifica-
tion of the hypothetico-deductive model. Essentially, the chapter con-
tains information about a collection of things which Darwin thought
might lead to the introduction of new heritable variation. In this collec-
tion there are, for example, the effects of changes in the conditions of
life affecting the reproductive systems of organisms, the effects of the
conditions of life directly impinging on organisms, and the effects o f
use and disuse. Rather than leading one to think that Darwin's argu-
ments are close to being put on a firm deductive basis, this discussion, if
anything, directs one's thoughts in the opposite direction. Admittedly,
in his later work, The Variation o f Animals and Plants Under Domes-
tication, 19 Darwin did try to work out some coherent theory of
heredity ("pangenesis')~ but he never put this theory into the later
editions of the Origin ; and in any case, even if one draws on the theory
18. Such "balanced" situations do actually occur, of course, even if not in the
particular case of wolf-fleetness. The maintenance of the sickle-cell gene in
African populations living in malarial districts is the classic example. I discuss this
case in some detail in The Philosophy of Biology and in "Some Thoughts on
Programmes for Improving Mankind" in Proceeding~ of the Fifth Conference on
Value Inquiry (New York: Gordon and Breech, 1900).
19_ London: Murray, 1868.
230
Charles Darwin's Theory of Evolution: An Analysis
Fig. 1. Fig. 2.
23. See, for example, the two chapters on geographical distribution in the
Origin_
232
Charles Darwin's Theory of Evolution: An Analysis
233
MICHAEL RUSE
from his reliance on nonlaws in his core arguments, few if any of his
arguments were rigorously deductive. Nevertheless, Darwin did rely on
some laws, and in his core arguments he got close to the deductive
ideal. Hence, if our analysis is not to diverge from what Darwin himself
would have wanted to claim, it seems proper to think of the arguments
following his demonstration of natural selection as being in a rather
loose sense sketches of hypothetico-deductive argumentsY
There is, however, one large qualification that I would want to make
to this conclusion. This resolves around the use Darwin made of the
analogy from artificial selection. We have seen how Darwin argued
analogically from the existence o f variations favorable or otherwise to
man's wishes to the existence o f variations favorable or injurious to
their possessors in the struggle for existence. At that point, Darwin's
theory did not fit the hypothetico-deductive pattern. Moreover,
not only is it difficult to see how it could be made to fit the pattern, but
since Darwin himself specifically referred to the link between the
artificial world and the natural world as an analogy, there is little reason
to think, on the basis of Darwin's own intentions, that at that point
Darwin's theory should fit the hypothetico-deductive pattern. However,
after the chapters in the Origin in which Darwin proved the existence of
natural selection, we continue to get repeated mentions of artificial
selection, and again I think we get violations of the hypothetico-deduc-
tive pattern. Let me explain how this comes about.
When discussing topics in the Origin after the introduction of natural
selection (and after his discussion of the laws o f variation), Darwin
referred constantly to the conclusions he drew about the struggle for
existence and natural selection. But it was clearly not the case that
when working in (what I might call) the "lower-level disciplines"
- m o r p h o l o g y , embryology, taxonomy, and so o n - Darwin relied
exclusively on conclusions drawn from his core arguments. The lower-
level disciplines, of course, contained assumptions derived from sources
other than the core, some of these being peculiar to one particular
discipline, and some being shared by more than one. Darwin gave many
illustrations of such lower-level (i.e., non-core) assumptions. For
example, in his discussions of geographical distribution, while
explaining the nature o f the inhabitants of archipelagos, he relied on
234
Charles Darwin's Theory of Evolution: An Analysis
Fanciers select their horses, dogs, and pigeons, for breeding, when
they are nearly grown up: they are indifferent whether the desired
qualities and structures have been acquired earlier or later in life, if
the full-grown animal possesses them. And the cases just given, more
especially that of pigeons, seem to show that the characteristic
differences which give value to each breed, and which have been
accumulated by man's selection, have not generally first appeared at
an early period of life, and have been inherited by the offspring at a
corresponding not early period. 3°
235
MICHAEL RUSE
Then, having made his point in the domestic world, Darwin argued that
an analogous situation holds in a state of nature.
Now, clearly, we have here no deductive link between the way in
which variation appears in domestic organisms and the way in which it
appears in wild organisms, and given the fact that at this point in the
Origin Darwin did indeed refer to the link as being an analogy, it might
with reason be argued that no deductive argument was intended and
that a deductive interpretation is inappropriate. And this could well
also be true of the other (frequent) passages where Darwin invoked the
domestic-organism analogy. Thus one might argue that although a large
part of Darwin's theory is hypothetico-deductive (in a sketched form),
this structure is, as it were, intermeshed with a great many analogical
threads running from domestic organisms to wild organisms.
Of course, as before, the hard-line hypothetico-deductive theorist will
have a reply to an argument like this. He will probably argue that even
the frequent references to domestic organisms need not point to a
failure of his model. He will suggest that what we find is that Darwin
used examples drawn from domestic organisms to justify general claims
about all organisms, which he then applied deductively to wild
organisms. But it will also be argued that no hypothetico-deductive
theorist would want to deny that in justifying his general claims the
scientist (when not deriving the claims from more general claims) can-
not work deductively - t h e scientist must work inductively from
specific examples. The hypothetico-deductive thesis, its supporter will
claim, is about the theory proper and begins only when one has one's
general statements.
The trouble with this argument, I think, is precisely what was wrong
with the argument when it was used against the inclusion in Darwin's
theory of the analogical inference from one kind of variation (variations
in domestic organisms and useful to man) to another kind of variation
(variations in wild organisms and useful to the possessors). Apart from
the question of the truth of the assumption that one can in fact find
satisfactory general premises covering both domestic and wild
organisms, one does seem rather to be defending the hypothetico-
deductive thesis, not on its own merits, but by legislation. What fits the
hypothetico-deductive model is part of the theory, what does not fit
the model is not part of the theory. Thus, when Darwin justified his
claims deductively, this was part of his theory; but when he justified his
claims analogically, this was not part of the theory. However, unless
one decides a priori that the only real parts of scientific theories are
deductions from laws (in which case it is not that surprising that one
236
Charles Darwin's Theory of Evolution: An Analysis
237
MICHAEL RUSE
238
Charles Darwin's Theory of Evolution: An Analyses
239
MICHAEL RUSE
240
Charles Darwin's Theory of Evolution: An Analysis
Lower- Level
d sc p nes
Fig. 3.
241