Lecture 6 Discourse Analysis and Pragmatics
Lecture 6 Discourse Analysis and Pragmatics
Lecture 6 Discourse Analysis and Pragmatics
1. Pragmatics
Concerning the relationship with other subjects in the area of linguistics,
pragmatics was once called the waste-basket of semantics. Semantics
studies what the words mean by themselves without considering the
context, whereas a word or sentence will have different meanings in
different situations. Therefore, this discipline leaves an unsolved problem
and pragmatics is the approach to deal with that problem.
2. Scope of Pragmatics
1) Person Deixis
Person deixis is used to point to people. It clearly operates a basic three-part
division, exemplified by the pronouns for first person (I), second person
(you), and third person (he, she, or it). In many languages, these deictic
categories of speaker, addressee, and other(s) are elaborated with makers
of relative social status (for example, addressee with higher status versus
addressee with lower status). Expressions, which indicate higher status are
described as honorifics.
2) Spatial Deixis
3) Temporal Deixis
b. Presupposition
1) Potential presupposition
2) Existential presupposition
3) Factive presupposition
5) Structural presupposition
6) Non-factive presupposition
7) Counterfactual presupposition
It says that speakers should be truthful. They should not say something that
they think or believe is false, or make statement for which they have no
d. Implicature
Grice (1975: 24) says that implicature is what a speaker can imply, suggest,
or mean as distinct from what he/she literally says. It is an implied message
that is based on the interpretation of the language use and its context of
communication. He points out that there are two kinds of implicature,
namely, conventional and conversational implicature.
1) Conventional Implicature
2) Conversational Implicature
It is another level at which speaker’s meaning can differ from what is said,
depends on the context of conversation. In conversational implicature,
meaning is conveyed not so much by what is said, but by the fact that it is
said. The cooperative principle and the maxims take part when the
conversational implicature arises. There are four kinds of conversational
e. Speech Acts
The term speech act was coined by Austin (1962) and developed by Searle
(1969). Austin defines speech acts as acts performed in saying something.
Further, he identifies three distinct levels of action beyond the act of
utterance. He distinguishes the act of saying something, what one does in
saying it, and what one does by saying it, and dubs these a locutionary, an
illocutionary, and a perlocutionary act.
Another definition comes from Nunan. “Speech acts are simply things
people do through language-for example, apologizing, complaining,
instructing, agreeing, and warning” (1993: 65). In line with Nunan’s
statement, Yule (1996: 47) says “Actions performed via utterances are
generally called speech acts”. Both agree that speech act is an utterance
that replaces an action for particular purpose in certain situation.
Some linguists have different classifications of speech act. There are three
classifications of speech act based on Austin (1962), Searle (1969) and Leech
(1983).
Austin (1962: 101) identifies three distinct levels of action beyond the act of
utterance, they are:
i) Locutionary Act
(1) Verdictives
(3) Commisives
Commisives are typified by promising or otherwise undertaking; they
commit the hearer to do something, but include also declaration or
announcements of intention, which are not promise, and also rather vague
things which can be called espousal, as for example siding with.
(4) Behabitives
(5) Expositives
Expositives are difficult to define. They make plain how utterances fit into
the course of an argument or conversation, how words are use, or in
general are expository. The examples are ‘I reply’, ‘I concede’, ‘I illustrate’, ‘I
assume’, and ‘I postulate’.
Searle (2005: 23-24) starts with the notion that when a person speaks,
he/she performs three different acts, i.e. utterance acts, propositional
acts, and illocutionary acts. Utterance acts consist simply of uttering strings
of words. Meanwhile, propositional acts and illocutionary acts consist
characteristically of uttering words in sentences in certain context, under
certain condition, and with certain intention. Searle classifies the
illocutionary acts based on varied criteria as the following:
i) Assertive or Representative
Searle (2005: 12) says that the purpose of the members of this class is to
commit the speaker (in varying degrees) to something’s being the case, to
the truth of the expressed proposition. It describes states or events in the
world such as an assertion, a description, a claim, a statement of fact, a
report, and a conclusion. Therefore, testing an assertive can be done by
simply questioning whether it can be categorized as true or false. Kreidler
(1998: 183) adds in the assertive function speakers and writers use
language to tell what they know or believe; assertive language is
PROF. DR. BUSHRA NI’MA RASHID
8
concerned with facts. The purpose is to inform. By performing an assertive
or representative, the speaker makes the words fit the world (belief). For
examples:
The two examples represent the world’s events as what the speaker
believes. Example (1) implies the speaker’s assertion that the British queen’s
name is Elizabeth. In example (2) the speaker asserts that he/she believes
that the earth is flat.
ii) Directive
iii) Commissive
Searle (2005: 14) suggests that commissive refers to an illocutionary act
whose point is to commit the speaker(again in varying degrees) to some
future course of action, such as promising, offering, threatening, refusing,
vowing, and volunteering. Yule (1996: 54) and Leech (1996: 105-107) add it
expresses what the speaker intends. Further, Kreidler (1998: 192) explains
PROF. DR. BUSHRA NI’MA RASHID
9
that commissive verbs are illustrated by agree, ask, offer, refuse, swear, all
with following infinitives. A commissive predicate is one that can be used to
commit oneself (or refuse to commit oneself) to some future action. The
subject of the sentence is therefore most likely to be I or we. The examples
are as follows:
(1) We’ll be right back.
(2) I’m gonna love you till the end.
iv) Expressive
Expressive includes acts in which the words are to express the
psychological state specified in the sincerity condition about a state of
affairs specified in the propositional content (Searle, 2005: 15). In other
word, it refers to a speech act in which the speaker expresses his/her
feeling and attitude about something. It can be a statement of pleasure,
pain, like, dislike, joy and sorrow. He adds the paradigms of expressive
verbs are thank, congratulate, apologize, regret, deplore, and welcome.
In line with Searle, Yule (1996: 53) states that this class is a kind of speech
acts that states what the speaker feels. It can be a statement of pleasure,
pain, like, dislike, joy or sorrow. The examples are:
v) Declaration
Its successful performance brings about the correspondence between the
propositional content and reality, successful performance guarantees that
the propositional content corresponds to the world; the direction of fit is
words-to- world. Searle (2005:17) gives examples that
“If I successfully perform the act of appointing you chairman, then you are
chairman; if I successfully perform the act of nominating you as candidate, then
you are a candidate; if I successfully perform the act of declaring a state of war,
Yule (1996: 53) and Cutting (2002: 16), simplify Searle’s long explanation by
saying that declaration is a kind of speech acts that changes the world via
utterance. The speaker has to have a special institutional role, in a specific
context, in order to perform a declaration appropriately. Leech (1996: 105-
107) adds that declaration are the illocution whose successful performance
brings about the correspondence between propositional content and reality.
Christening or baptizing, declaring war, abdicating, resigning, dismissing,
naming, and excommunicating are the examples of declaration. Some
examples of utterances classified as declarations are:
Examples (1) and (2) bring about the change in reality and they are more than
just statements. Example (1) can be used to perform the act of ending the
employment and example (2) can be used to perform the end of the game.
i) Competitive
The illocutionary goal competes with the social goal. The function of this type
of speech act is for showing politeness in the form of negative parameter. The
point is to reduce the discord implicit in the competition between what the
speaker wants to achieve and what is ‘good manner’. The examples of this
speech acts are ordering, asking, demanding, begging, and requesting.
ii) Convivial
The illocutionary goal deals with social goal. On the contrary with the previous
category, the convivial type is intrinsically courteous. It means that politeness
here is in the positive form of seeking opportunities for comity. The examples
iii) Collaborative
The illocutionary goal is different from the social goal. In this function, both
politeness and impoliteness are relevant. It can be found in most of written
discourse. The examples of this category are asserting, reporting, announcing,
and instructing.
iv) Conflictive
The illocutionary goal conflicts with the social goal. Similar to the
collaborative function, politeness does not need to be questioned for the
terms in this illocutionary function are used to cause offence or hurt the
feeling of the hearer. The examples of the conflictive function are threatening,
accusing, cursing, and reprimanding.
However, notoriously, not all cases of meaning are simple because the
speaker’s utterance meaning and the sentence meaning come apart in
various ways. One important class of such cases is that in which the speaker
utters a sentence, means what he says, but also means something more. For
example, a speaker may utter the sentence “I want you to do it.” by way of
requesting the hearer to do something. The utterance is incidentally meant as
a statement, but it is also meant primarily as a request, a request made by way
of making a statement. Another example is someone says, “Can you reach the
Searle (2005: 31) argues that indirect speech acts are cases in which one
illocutionary act is performed indirectly by way of performing another.
Therefore, there is an indirect relationship between a surface structure and
function. A declarative sentence can be used to make a command, an
interrogative to make a request, etc.
In line with Searle’s opinion, Cutting (2002: 19) explains that someone using an
indirect speech act wants to communicate a different meaning from the
apparent surface meaning; the form and the function are not directly
connected. Hence, a declarative form such as “I was going to get another
one”, or “You could get me a tuna and sweetcorn one” might have the
function of a request or order.
4) Speech Events
The basic unit of analysis in verbal interaction is speech event. In performing
indirect request, one can treat that performance in two ways. One may
simply utter a single speech act in a single utterance and one may utter some
utterances without performing a single speech act clearly, but it allows the
hearer to react as if the request has been made. In the first condition, for
example, when S is asking H to do X by performing only a single speech act in a
single utterance “Will you do X?”. In the second condition, S is asking H if the
precondition for doing X is in place for making a request result. Then, to
understand this, i.e. studying how to get more than what is communicated
through the speech, analysis of speech event is needed.
3. Context
Context is an important concept in pragmatic analysis because pragmatics
focuses on the meaning of words in context or interaction and how the
persons involved in the interaction communicate more information than the
word they use. This statement is in line with Finegan et al.’s explanation. They
(1997: 345) state that the essential element in the interpretation of an
utterance is the context in which it is uttered. It is the obvious case of
pragmatics as the study of contextual meaning. Therefore, analyzing the
meaning of an utterance cannot ignore the context since the meaning of an
utterance will be different if the context is different. It will establish the
interpretation of the utterance.
Yule (1996: 21) mentions that context simply means the physical environment
in which a word is used. Meanwhile, Mey (1993: 39-40) states that context is
more than a matter of reference and of understanding what things are about.
It gives a deeper meaning to utterances. The utterance “It is a long time since
we visited your mother.”, when uttered at the living room by a married
couple, has a totally different meaning from if it is uttered by a husband and
wife while they are standing in front of the hippopotamus enclosure at the
zoo, in which it can be considered as a joke.
a. Context of situation
Further, Hymes (1974: 55-60) puts forward several concepts for describing the
context of situation. For convenience, he uses the word SPEAKING as an
acronym for the various factors he deems to be relevant.
3) (E) End
5) (K) Key
Key refers to the cues that establish the tone, manner, or in which a particular
message is conveyed: light-hearted, serious, precise, sarcastic, and so on. Key
6) (I) Instrumentalities
Instrumentalities basically refer to the choice of channel and the actual forms
of speech employed, such as the language, dialect, code, or register that is
chosen. The choice of channel itself can be oral, written, or telegraphic.
8) (G) Genre
Genre refers to the clearly demarcated types of utterance, such as poem,
proverb, riddles, sermon, prayer, lecturer, and editorial.