The Constructivist Turn in International Relations Theory: Jeffrey T. Checkel

Download as doc, pdf, or txt
Download as doc, pdf, or txt
You are on page 1of 19

Review Article

The Constructivist Turn in International Relations


Theory
Jeffrey T. Checkel *

Martha Finnemore. National Interests in International Society . Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell


University Press, 1996, 149 pages.

Peter Katzenstein, ed. The Culture of National Security: Norms and Identity in World
Politics . New York: Columbia University Press, 1996, 562 pages.

Audie Klotz. Norms in International Relations: The Struggle against Apartheid . Ithaca, N.Y.:
Cornell University Press, 1995, 183 pages.

For the past decade a central locus of contention within international relations has been the
neorealist-neoliberal debate. This exchange has been fruitful and cumulative, allowing
proponents of the two research programs to sharpen arguments while simultaneously shedding
light on key issues of world politics, for example, the conditions under which relative or absolute
gains-seeking behavior occurs. 1

By and large, the constructivists under review would concur with such a characterization. Their
critique of neorealists and neoliberals concerns not what these scholars do and say but what they
ignore: the content and sources of state interests and the social fabric of world politics. Reaching
back to earlier theoretical traditions (the English school, [End Page 324] some versions of
liberalism) and reaching out to new disciplinary foundations (sociology), constructivists seek to
expand theoretical discourse.

Regarding both the books under review and constructivism more generally, this essay advances
three claims. First, I argue that constructivism has succeeded in broadening the theoretical
contours of IR. By exploring issues of identity and interest bracketed by neoliberalism and
neorealism, constructivists have demonstrated that their sociological approach leads to new and
meaningful interpretations of international politics. Moreover, constructivists have rescued the
exploration of identity from postmodernists. By arguing for its importance using methods accepted
by the majority of scholars, they have been able to challenge mainstream analysts on their own
ground. Second and more critically, I show that constructivism lacks a theory of agency. As a
result, it overemphasizes the role of social structures and norms at the expense of the agents
who help create and change them in the first place.

Third, I argue that constructivism remains a method more than anything else. The central
challenge for these scholars is theory development. Having demonstrated that social construction
matters, they must now address when, how, and why it occurs, clearly specifying the actors and
mechanisms bringing about change, the scope conditions under which they operate, and how
they vary across countries. To accomplish this task, constructivists must integrate their insights
and assumptions with middle-range theory. Otherwise, the empirical ad hocism that plagues their
current work will remain.

The essay is organized as follows. It begins by defining constructivism and its approach to the
study of global politics. Next, it considers the empirical contribution of constructivists, focusing on
the three books under review. Finally, the review explores several issues constructivists must
address if they are to mount a sustained challenge to their competitors in contemporary IR.

The Social Construction of International Politics


The constructivist critique of neorealism and neoliberalism reaches well beyond the level-of-
analysis argument of either Image I (individual) or Image II (domestic politics) theorists.
Constructivism is concerned not with levels per se but with underlying conceptions of how the
social and political world works. It is not a theory but an approach to social inquiry based on two
assumptions: (1) the environment in which agents/states take action is social as well as material;
and (2) this setting can provide agents/states with understandings of their interests (it can [End
Page 325] "constitute" them). Put differently, these scholars question the materialism and
methodological individualism upon which much contemporary IR scholarship has been built.

The first assumption reflects a view that material structures, beyond certain biological necessities,
are given meaning only by the social context through which they are interpreted. Consider
nuclear weapons--the ultimate material capability. Constructivists argue that it is not such
weapons themselves that matter. After all, the United States worries very little about the large
quantity of nuclear weapons held by the British; however, the possibility that North Korea might
come into possession of even one or two generates tremendous concern. 2

The second assumption addresses the basic nature of human agents and states, in particular,
their relation to broader structural environments. Constructivists emphasize a process of
interaction between agents and structures; the ontology is one of mutual constitution, where
neither unit of analysis--agents or structures--is reduced to the other and made "ontologically
primitive." This opens up what for most theorists is the black box of interest and identity formation;
state interests emerge from and are endogenous to interaction with structures. 3

Constructivists thus question the methodological individualism that underpins both neoliberalism
and neorealism. This agent-centered view asserts that all social phenomena are explicable in
ways that involve only individual agents and their goals and actions; the starting point of the
analysis is actors (states) with given properties. Ontologically, the result is to reduce one unit of
analysis--structures--to the other--agents. 4

Also implicit in many constructivist accounts is a model of human and state behavior where rule-
governed action and logics of appropriateness prevail. Such logics involve reasoning by analogy
and metaphor and are not about ends and means. Under them, agents ask "What kind of
situation is this?" and "What should I do now?"--with norms helping to supply the answers. Norms
therefore constitute states/agents, providing them with understandings of their interests. 5 [End
Page 326]

Scholars of rational choice, by contrast, use a behavioral model based on utility maximization:
when confronted with various options, an agent picks the one that best serves its objectives and
interests. Much rational choice research ("thick" rationalism) also makes assumptions about the
content of these interests, typically that they are material goods such as power or wealth. State
(agent) interests are given a priori and exogenously. Norms and social structures at most
constrain the choices and behavior of self-interested states, which operate according to a logic of
consequences (means-ends calculations). 6

It is important to note that constructivists do not reject science or causal explanation; their quarrel
with mainstream theories is ontological, not epistemological. The last point is key, for it suggests
that constructivism has the potential to bridge the still vast divide separating the majority of IR
theorists from postmodernists. With the latter, constructivists share many substantive concerns
(role of identity and discourse, say) and a similar ontological stance; with the former, they share a
largely common epistemology. Constructivists thus occupy a middle ground between rational
choice theorists and postmodern scholars. 7

To illuminate these differences between constructivists and other schools, it is helpful to explore
their understanding of central terms. Consider "norms," a concept that has gained much currency
in IR scholarship over the past decade. While realists see norms as lacking causal force,
neoliberal regime theory argues that they play an influential rule in certain issue-areas. However,
even for neoliberals, norms are still a superstructure built on a material base: they serve a
regulative function, helping actors with given interests maximize utility. Agents (states) create
structures (norms and institutions). 8 For constructivists, by contrast, norms are collective
understandings that make behavioral claims on [End Page 327] actors. Their effects reach
deeper: they constitute actor identities and interests and do not simply regulate behavior. As
explanatory variables, their status moves from intervening to independent (Finnemore, chaps. 3,
4; Klotz, chap. 6, for example). Norms are no longer a superstructure on a material base; rather,
they help to create and define that base. For constructivists, agents (states) and structures
(global norms) are interacting; they are mutually constituted. 9

Taken together, these moves by constructivists--their questioning of methodological individualism


and materialism, along with a continuing commitment to the scientific enterprise--have brought a
breath of fresh air to thinking about world politics, in ways accessible to nearly all scholars. A key
issue, however, is whether such new perspectives allow these researchers to explain important
international puzzles
and phenomena and thereby demonstrate the empirical value of their approach.

Puzzles and Anomalies in World Politics: The Constructivist


Contribution
The books under review seek to make empirical contributions in three areas: the role of
international institutions and organizations (Finnemore); international security (Katzenstein
volume); and the effects of international norms (Klotz). To evaluate their success, it is necessary
to establish a baseline for comparison.

On international institutions, the dominant school for well over a decade has been neoliberal
institutionalism. Since the publication of Keohane's After Hegemony, these scholars have shown
increasing sophistication in exploring the conditions under which institutions are created in the
first place and the various roles they play in world politics. 10

Partly out of a concern for theoretical parsimony, neoliberal institutionalists have purposely
bracketed several issues, including the sources of state interests, which are given by assumption.
These scholars also grant only a limited role to institutions, considering them to be the creation of
self-interested states that at most constrain choices and strategies. [End Page 328] Virtually
ignored is the possibility that the effects of institutions reach deeper, to the level of interests and
identity.

The baseline for the second issue-area--international security--is difficult to establish with
precision, given the turbulence stirred up within this subfield by the end of the cold war. Certainly
realism and rationalism have been and remain dominant here, but scholars have refined their
analyses by paying more attention to domestic politics.

Important studies have enriched our understanding of security by exploring the role of ideology
and threat perception, coalition politics, cognitive variables, and perceptions. While some accuse
these scholars of smuggling into their analyses sociological and cultural variables emphasized by
constructivists, they are nonetheless still united in a common commitment to rationalism and
materialism. On the former, key actors (elite decision makers or groups within the state) make
cost/benefit calculations and choose strategies designed to maximize certain interests; on the
latter, perceptual, ideational, and cultural factors are ultimately parasitic on a material base. 11

Research on international norms, the third area addressed by the books under review, has been
heavily influenced by regime analysis. These scholars have typically demonstrated that regime
norms constrain the behavior of states; they are an explanatory variable that intervenes between
underlying power distributions and outcomes. 12

Work on epistemic communities and, more recently, on transnational policy networks has brought
research on international regimes closer to the insights offered by constructivists. It does so by
suggesting that regime norms have deeper cognitive effects. Studies of this sort are arguably still
a minor current within regime theory; they are also beset by a number of problems. Moreover,
these scholars, especially those working on epistemic communities, embrace a largely agent-
centered view, where state decision makers calculate and reason in response to a changing
material environment. 13 [End Page 329]

Constructing National Interests

With this background, the task is to assess the contribution of the constructivists, beginning with
the book by Finnemore. She questions two assumptions upon which most work on international
institutions and IR more generally rests: the definition of state interests and rational means-ends
calculations as the dominant mode of human interaction (p. x). In ontological terms, she seeks to
move scholarship away from agent-oriented approaches (neoliberalism, for example) by paying
more attention to the structure side of the agent-structure debate (p. 7).

In an excellent opening chapter, Finnemore argues that a constructivist logic of appropriateness


is just as plausible a predictor of human and state behavior as the rationalists' logic of
consequences. When one makes actor and state interests the dependent variable, as she does,
such logics of appropriateness can be key in determining their content. From where do such
logics come? Systemic norms propagated by international organizations are one possible
answer; they provide states with direction and goals for action.

The core of the book is three case studies of how international institutions (and, in one case, an
international nongovernmental organization) were able to reconstitute state interests. These not
only make for fascinating reading, but they also offer fresh insights into how institutions matter in
world politics. They are also carefully argued, typically using two streams of evidence: (1)
correlations between the emergence of new systemic norms and changes in state interests and
practice; and (2) analysis of discourse to see if actions are justified in ways consistent with the
values and rules embedded in the norms. These data, along with attention to alternative
explanations, allow Finnemore to build a plausible case.

Her study of the United Nations Educational, Scientific and Cultural Organization (UNESCO) is
representative. Finnemore's puzzle is to explain why so many countries--developing and
developed--created similarly stuctured science policy bureaucracies in a relatively brief period.
She begins with a rigorous consideration of alternative explanations for their creation, for
example, that they were established at the behest of powerful domestic constituencies. After
testing these quantitatively and finding them lacking, Finnemore advances her own norms-based
argument.

She starts at the international level, documenting how a norm prescribing the creation of national
science units initially took hold at UNESCO and was later consolidated there. On the latter, part of
the evidence is a careful study of the changing discourse within UNESCO [End Page 330] and
among its member states. In particular, she notes how, over time, the notion that such units were
needed took on a prescriptive status and came to be taken for granted. 14

Finnemore then turns to the state level, establishing correlations between the norms promoted by
UNESCO and the creation of science bureaucracies by a number of states. To move beyond
correlations, however, she considers several cases (Lebanon, East Africa) in more detail,
analyzing the personal and organizational pathways through which the UNESCO norms diffused
to these states. While the evidence here is a bit weaker (Finnemore conducted no fieldwork in the
respective countries), it is nonetheless sufficient to allow her to make a plausible case that the
norms were causally important for the change in science policy. Put differently, norms embodying
certain logics of appropriateness had provided states with a new understanding of their interests
(chap. 2).

Analysis of this sort moves one beyond the understanding of institutions provided by neoliberal
institutionalists in at least two ways. First, by endogenizing interest formation, Finnemore sheds
much- needed light on a crucial issue ignored by neoliberals: how states come to define their
interests in certain ways. International organizations can teach states to value certain goals:
national science bureaucracies in the case of UNESCO and poverty alleviation as a policy
objective in the case of the World Bank. Finnemore carefully argues that these new interests
arose in the absence of domestic constituencies or powerful countries favoring them. Instead,
they were diffused to states by systemic norms, from the outside, as it were. Materialist and
rationalist explanations cannot account for such value and behavioral change.

Second, the book demonstrates that international organizations are not empty vessels that simply
reduce transaction costs, as portrayed by neoliberals. They are purposive entities that are able, in
some cases, to trump states and their power. Indeed, Finnemore's rich source material at the
international level gives her cases a sense of dynamism and history in the making that is typically
absent from neoliberal accounts of institutions. She has thus provided a theoretically informed
and empirically substantiated argument for how institutions not only constrain but also constitute
states and their interests, solving what is a puzzle for other theorists. 15 [End Page 331]

The book also fills a gap in constructivism: failure to tell us why certain norms arise at particular
times. Finnemore provides an answer by exploring the role of moral entrepreneurs: committed
individuals who happen to be in the right place at the right time to instill their beliefs in larger
global social structures (pp. 24-28, chap. 4, pp. 137-39). 16

Finnemore's account is not without weaknesses, however. Most important, it is not clear what one
does with her argument, with so much resting on contingencies and idiosyncratic variables. While
Finnemore has demonstrated that social construction is causally important, she has failed to
specify systematically when, how, and why this occurs. To be fair, one book cannot do everything.
All the same, the critical next step should be the development of a specifically constructivist
theory of international institutions, one that would elaborate such scope conditions.

A second weakness is the degree to which Finnemore's analysis is consistent with


constructivism's mutual constitution of agents and structures. Now, exactly how one
operationalizes mutual constitution is a dilemma for all empirical constructivists. Finnemore's
solution is a bracketing strategy, where she first brackets agency and then, structures; her case
studies are broadly faithful to this approach (pp. 24-25, chaps. 2-4).

The problem is the wrong choice of agents: the entrepreneurs who are responsible for the
creation of norms in the first place. To analyze the process of mutual constitution that led to a
change of national interests within particular states (her dependent variable), the agents she
should be exploring, especially given her emphasis on global norms as the structures, are groups
and individuals in those same states. If Finnemore had focused on these agents, it would have
led her to explore several important issues, for example, the feedback effects of state (agent)
behavior on the norms themselves.

A final difficulty is unavoidable given Finnemore's emphasis on systemic social structures: the
neglect of domestic politics. A question that immediately comes to mind when reading her
analysis is why norms diffuse differentially, that is, why they have so much greater impact in some
countries than in others. Through what mechanisms do global norms work their effects
domestically? Finnemore alludes to these issues at several points but provides no clear answers
(pp. 125, 137). This is odd, since it is the constructivists, with their attention to practice and
interaction, who should be keying upon process and mechanisms. 17 [End Page 332]

Culture and Security

In a curious way, the Katzenstein volume is both very ambitious and very cautious. The former is
seen in its willingness to question, from a sociological perspective, the very microeconomic
disciplinary foundations of IR, and to do so on empirical issues that realists will recognize as their
own. At the same time, Katzenstein and his contributors do not advance an alternative theory of
national security; in contrast to many of the better edited volumes, this one does not even provide
a common theoretical framework used by all contributors. 18

It does offer extraordinarily fresh thinking about security, however, along with richly detailed case
studies. Among the familiar security questions explored in a new way are the proliferation of
conventional weaponry, the role of deterrence in the nonuse of nuclear and chemical weapons,
the sources of military doctrine, the Soviet cold war endgame, and alliance dynamics in both the
North Atlantic and the Middle East.

Chapter 1 (Katzenstein) and especially chapter 2 (Jepperson, Wendt, and Katzenstein) should be
required reading in any graduate seminar on security or IR more generally. This is not because
Katzenstein et al. have decisively trumped mainstream theorists or because they have everything
right. Rather, the essays are extremely helpful in explaining how the theoretical schools
(neorealism, neoliberalism, constructivism) differ and why it matters (chap. 1) and for making
sense of a sociological approach to national security (chap. 2). Moreover, these scholars are
interested in dialogue; the goal is not to demonize existing approaches but to note their
limitations. 19

The volume's sociological approach to national security involves relaxing the two core
assumptions of neorealism and neoliberalism, which are (1) that the environment of states can be
conceived solely in terms of physical capabilities and (2) that institutions and structures only
constrain the behavior of states with fixed interests. Relaxing the first assumption opens the
possibility of social structures being causally important in world politics, while relaxing the second
suggests that the effects of these structures may reach beyond behavioral constraint to identity
and interest formation. In other words, just like Finnemore, this is a challenge to the materialism
and methodological individualism that dominate the discourse in mainstream IR (Katzenstein, 16-
17). [End Page 333]

Given this stance, the volume needs to address two key questions: (1) the content and properties
of the social structures having such profound effects on agents; and (2) the causal mechanisms
through which these structures have their affects. The social structures doing the explanatory
work are norms and, to a lesser extent, culture. The former are defined as collective expectations
about proper behavior for a given identity (Jepperson, Wendt, and Katzenstein, 54). That this is
the same definition as used by Finnemore and Klotz is one indicator, among others, that a
constructivist research program is beginning to consolidate itself in IR. 20
The presence of these normative structures is established through a variety of well-established
and standard methodological techniques, for example, interview data, qualitative content analysis
of primary sources, statistical studies. The research strategy is broadly similar to Finnemore's:
document the presence of the social structures; note a correlation between these and new state
interests; examine changing discourse as further evidence of these normative effects; and, finally,
strengthen the case by considering alternative explanations, usually drawn from neorealist and
neoliberal theories.

Risse-Kappen's chapter on the North Atlantic Treaty Organization is a good example of the
general approach. His puzzle is to explain NATO's initial formation and endurance--events that
are anomalous, he argues, from the standpoint of both traditional and more sophisticated realist
theories of alliances. In the first part of his essay Risse-Kappen discusses these likely alternative
explanations and carefully documents their shortcomings.

Next, he develops his own liberal constructivist approach, where the norms that govern the
domestic decision-making process within liberal systems come to regulate the interactions among
democracies in international institutions such as NATO. Democracies, Risse-Kappen argues,
"externalize their internal norms when cooperating with each other. Power asymmetries will be
mediated by norms of democratic decision-making among equals emphasizing persuasion,
compromise and the non-use of force or coercive power." He then deduces four different ways
such norms will influence the interaction process among democratic allies (pp. 268-71). 21 [End
Page 334]

Risse-Kappen illustrates the argument by showing how the interests in play, both in the formation
of NATO and during several key crises (Suez 1956, Cuba 1962), were shaped by the democratic
normative context in which they evolved. In other words, the interests of states and alliance
decision makers (the agents) were being constituted by these democratic norms (the structures).
His evidence is carefully culled from secondary and, especially, primary sources, for example, the
U.S. government's Foreign Relations of the United States series and materials in the National
Security Archive. This allows him to dissect the decision-making process, showing how norms
affected the preferences and interests of various alliance partners. 22

The essay by Risse-Kappen is not at all atypical for the Katzenstein volume, which contains a
number of carefully argued studies documenting the impact of norms. Unfortunately, the volume
is much weaker at theorizing the causal mechanisms that give these social structures such
powerful constitutive effects. This is a fair criticism to make, as the authors clearly commit
themselves to a largely causal epistemology (Katzenstein, 4-5, 7; Jepperson, Wendt, and
Katzenstein, 52-53, 65-68). However, as Katzenstein himself admits in the book's concluding
essay, structural theories such as sociological institutionalism, which is accorded a central role in
the volume, neglect important processes that translate structural effects (pp. 512-13). 23

One result is that the role of agency, while highlighted empirically in many of the chapters, is
neglected theoretically. The volume short-circuits one loop in the constructivist method: the causal
arrows flow primarily from structures to agents. Mutual constitution, however, implies they also
flow from agents to structures. Some constructivists might object that such sequential (structures
to agents then agents to structures) causal language misconstrues the essence of their ontology:
the simultaneous, mutual constitution of agents and structures. However, the empirical application
of mutual constitution by these scholars follows precisely the sequential logic outlined here. 24

Despite such shortcomings, this is a very important volume. Its commitment to causal analysis
and standard methodologies contributes to a productive dialogue with neorealists and neoliberals;
for the most part, these scholars are all talking the same language. In addition, the case [End
Page 335] studies (chaps. 3-11) offer new and meaningful insights. For some authors, this means
demonstrating that particular security outcomes can be explained only when realist analyses are
supplemented with constructivist approaches (Herman's chapter on Soviet foreign policy under
Gorbachev; Risse-Kappen's essay on NATO).

Other contributors, however, go a step further and argue that their constructivist approach
supplants rationalist and materialist accounts. For example, in a superbly argued essay, Alastair
Johnston shows that the persistence of China's realpolitik over several centuries can be
understood only in terms of a constructivist explanation that subsumes structural realism
(Katzenstein, chap. 7).

Finally, in an innovation rare in any edited volume, Katzenstein has included an essay (chap. 12
by Kowert and Legro) that reflects critically on the book as a whole. This excellent chapter
provides the sense of cumulation and summary that is missing when one reads across the
various contributions. It achieves this not by championing the constructivist cause but by critically
evaluating the volume's shortcomings. For developing a more coherent constructivist research
program, this is precisely what is needed. Katzenstein et al. are to be applauded for including
such a chapter.

Global Norms and the Demise of Apartheid

The puzzle Audie Klotz seeks to explain is why a large number of international organizations and
states adopted sanctions against the Apartheid regime in South Africa despite strategic and
economic interests that had fostered strong ties with it in the past. Klotz argues that the
emergence of a global norm of racial equality is at the heart of the explanation: it led states to
redefine interests even though they had material incentives not to do so. This demonstrates a
constitutive role for norms, she argues, where they affect state identity and do not simply regulate
behavior (chaps. 1-2).

The case studies on the United States, Britain, and Zimbabwe (chaps. 6-8) make for especially
fascinating reading. Klotz's extensive empirical research and attention to domestic politics allow
her to explore how this global norm first reached the national level and the effects it then had on
the interests of various groups and individuals. In contrast to Finnemore and many contributors to
the Katzenstein volume, Klotz offers much more process-level evidence on how norms actually
reconstituted state interests.

The book thus fills in important gaps in both regime theory and constructivism. Concerning the
former, Klotz demonstrates in a nicely [End Page 336] argued section that neoliberal regime
analysis shortchanges the role norms play in international politics. This is not to argue that the
neoliberals have it all wrong (Klotz does not say this); rather, their view of norms as constraints on
states, as opposed to constituting them, is only half the story. Empirically, she shows how this
theoretical move can actually be carried out (pp. 13-33). In an important sense, Klotz is
empiricizing the abstract critiques of regime theory advanced by Friedrich Kratochwil and John
Ruggie over the past decade. 25

The author is also to be commended for flagging an issue that constructivist research must
address. As Klotz puts it: "The crucial question is then how a contested norm . . . becomes
institutionalized, both globally and domestically" (pp. 24-25). Indeed, after reading enough of this
work, one senses that there are all too many norms floating around "out there" that somehow
insinuate themselves "in here," that is, in the domestic arena. (While Finnemore furthers our
understanding of how norm institutionalization works in international institutions, she neglects the
question of domestic diffusion mechanisms and processes.)

Klotz addresses this issue by elaborating three transmission mechanisms that link norms and
policy choice: community and identity; reputation and communication; and discourse and
institutions. While these are ultimately underspecified (one would want to know what mechanisms
under what conditions are likely to be at work in a particular national setting), this is nonetheless a
foundation upon which other scholars should build. By elaborating causal mechanisms that
specify diffusion pathways, constructivists will move away from the correlational analyses too
often evident in their work; process tracing of this sort is a method whose time has come for
constructivism.

Three weaknesses limit the impact of Klotz's book, however. First, the ontology is not one of
mutual constitution, not even in its bracketing form--comments to the contrary notwithstanding
(Klotz, 168-69, 172). Instead, like both Finnemore and many of the Katzenstein case studies, this
is a study of how social structures, a global norm of racial equality, reconstituted agents.

Second, the analysis is too often correlational (pp. 158-61, for example). In part, this results from
a failure to specify more systematically the causal mechanisms operating at the domestic level
(Klotz, 24-33). However, it is also an artifact of the source material, which is primarily secondary.
Given the arguments that Klotz wishes to make about the [End Page 337] effects of global norms
on various groups within states, archival, memoir, or interview data would seem essential.

For the congressional representatives in her U.S. study, to take one case, it matters tremendously
for the argument whether their views, in the presence of the global norm, were changing because
they feared adverse electoral consequences (the rationalists' means-ends calculations) or
because they learned new values and beliefs (the constructivists' logic of appropriateness) (Klotz,
chap. 6). Klotz's correlations tell us that the views were changing but not why this occurred; the
necessary process tracing is never fully carried out in the substantive chapters.

Third, the theory-building potential inherent in the book's ambitious cross-national design goes
unrealized. Klotz presents no theory that might predict her results or explain similar dynamics in
other countries, if one wished to extend the study. This is unfortunate: in the end, one is still left
wondering why regimes and norms have such powerful constitutive effects in some states but not
in others. 26

Summary

Two conclusions follow from the above. Most important, constructivists have convincingly shown
the empirical value of their approach, providing new and meaningful interpretations on a range of
issues of central concern to students of world politics. At the same time, constructivist theorizing
is in a state of disarray. These researchers, much like the rational choice scholars they criticize,
have made too rapid a leap from ontology and methods to empirics, to the neglect of theory
development. This matters tremendously. As a central architect of constructivism has recently put
it: "If parsimony is over-rated as a theoretical virtue . . . cumulation is surely underappreciated."
And cumulation, it might be added, if it is to be efficient and productive, requires theory. 27

Agency, Theory Building, and the Constructivist Enterprise


My purpose in this last section is twofold. I begin by highlighting three issues that should be easy
for constructivists to fix. Two, more difficult [End Page 338] questions are then explored: the role
of agency and the need for theory. Without more sustained attention to agency, these scholars
will find themselves unable to explain where their powerful social structures (norms) come from in
the first place and, equally important, why and how they change over time. Without theory,
especially at the domestic level, constructivists will not be able to explain in a systematic way how
social construction actually occurs or why it varies cross nationally.

The Three Easy Fixes


Constructivists need, first, to pay greater attention to research design. As noted, much of the
empirical work examines single countries or issues. Cross-national or longitudinal designs would
help reduce the problem of overdetermination that is evident in many constructivist analyses,
where social structures, usually norms, are invoked as one of several causal variables with little
or no insight given on how much of the outcome they explain (Katzenstein, chaps. 4, 8, 10; and
Klotz, 114, 162, passim). It would also be useful to consider cases when the "dog doesn't bark,"
that is, where state identity/interests, in the presence of a norm, do not change. 28

Second, these scholars should give equal attention to the bad things in world politics that are
socially constructed. There is a tendency in the recent work to consider only ethically good
norms, such as those imposing a stigma on the use of nuclear or chemical weapons, those that
helped bring the cold war to an end, or the global norms that facilitated the demise of Apartheid.
Some constructivists are aware of this problem (Finnemore, 6, 31-32; Kowert and Legro, in
Katzenstein 485-86), but future work must address it. It will not only protect these scholars from
getting caricatured as peaceniks by theoretical opponents, but it will also direct their attention to
important unexplored issues such as the role of social construction in ethnic conflict and war. 29
[End Page 339]

Third, constructivists must take greater care in defining key terms, for example,
institutionalization. This word is invoked in nearly every analysis of norms (Finnemore, 126;
Katzenstein, 56, 96-97, 129, 143, 161, 472, 484; Klotz, 24-26), but the reader is given no
explanation of what the process entails. In what institutions--or individuals--do norms reside?
Must norms be internalized first by individuals through a socialization and learning process? If so,
constructivists should pay greater attention to developing the often implicit cognitive models in
their analyses. Or, does institutionalization occur at a higher level of aggregation, through
bureaucratic and legal processes that affect society as a whole. If this is the level under
examination, constructivists could benefit from the insights of historical institutionalists and of
those in the ideas literature who have studied such dynamics. 30

The Challenges Ahead

Ontology and theory building are the central challenges for constructivists.

Bringing Agency Back In

This move is necessary if mutual constitution is to be taken seriously as a way of thinking about
the social world. I appreciate the reasoning of some that a neglect of agency is legitimate, at
present, as a corrective to the extreme agent orientation of most mainstream IR (Finnemore,
chap. 1). Moreover, it has proved very difficult to apply mutual constitution in empirical research.

All the same, constructivists should want to avoid the charge that they are reducing one unit of
analysis--agents (states, decision makers)--to the other--structures (norms). One result of this
reduction is a failure to explore how norms arise in the first place (and the role of agency and
power in this process), and how, through interactions with particular agents, norms change over
time. 31

An example clarifies the importance of the last point. Post-cold war Europe has witnessed the
emergence of norms advancing more inclusive conceptions of national membership (citizenship
laws, rights of national [End Page 340] minorities). Promoted initially by nongovernmental actors
and more recently by the Strasbourg-based Council of Europe, the content of these norms has
now been modified significantly as a result of Russia's instrumental exploitation of them in a bid to
reassert its dominance among the former Soviet states. The constructivists' normative structures
are themselves being reshaped by the activities of purposeful agents. 32
Three reasons explain why agency has fallen through the ontological cracks for constructivists.
First, many constructivists rely upon the insights of sociological institutionalism for their thinking
about the social world. Those insights, however, are based upon a particular branch of
organization theory that systematically excludes questions of agency, interest, and power. 33

Second, because of their focus on collectively held, intersubjective understandings (norms), most
constructivists, not surprisingly, are less interested in questions of individual agency. Yet the
evolutionary development of norms suggests that, at some early point in their life histories, they
may not be collective in any meaningful sense; particular individuals (Finnemore's moral
entrepreneurs, for example) may play key roles at early stages. Thus, social construction at the
level of agents is--or rather, should be--a relevant concern for these scholars. 34

Finally, Wendt, who has been so influential in developing constructivism, has explicitly bracketed
individual agency as a factor to be explained by mutual constitution. For Wendt, a key distinction
is between the corporate and social identity of states, with the former deemphasized because "its
roots [are] in domestic politics." Since he assumes a unitary state, corporate identity includes and
subsumes that of the individual. The result is that social construction at the level of individual
agents or, more generally, at any domestic level is neglected. While several theorists have
criticized Wendt for this stance, no clear understanding of how to rectify it has emerged. 35 [End
Page 341]

It is ironic that constructivists therefore find themselves in a predicament all too familiar to rational
choice scholars: their ontology has led them to neglect key issues. The agent-centered approach
of rational choice provides a clear perspective on the microfoundations of human behavior, but
much less clarity on how this connects with the broader institutional and social context. The
dilemma then is how to get from microfoundations to outcomes. 36

Constructivists, despite their arguments about mutually constituting agents and structures, have
advanced a structure-centered approach in their empirical work. Moreover, Wendt's theoretical
stance has led to a neglect of domestic agency. The result is that constructivism, while good at
the macrofoundations of behavior and identity (norms, social context), is very weak on the
microlevel. It fails to explore systematically how norms connect with agents. 37

Social Construction and Theory Building

To explore such connections, constructivists will need to engage in theory development. At


present, constructivism is, like rational choice, nothing more than a method. It leads one to ask
certain questions and make certain assumptions. However, constructivists should surely want
more. In fact, in the volumes under review, there is a persistent call precisely for greater
specification of constructivism (Finnemore, 130-31; Kowert and Legro, in Katzenstein, 469-83;
Klotz, 26-33). 38

The missing element is substantive, middle-range theory, which would provide constructivists with
a set (or better, competing sets) of research questions and hypotheses that could be tested in
various cross-national and longitudinal studies. The need for theory is especially evident at the
domestic level, where the constructivist "norm" is empirical ad hocism with all sorts of implicit
models of domestic politics and key actors being invoked. 39 [End Page 342]

If constructivists are to theorize at the domestic level, they will need to address three issues. How
deep within a policy does one need to go with a constructivist analysis? How is such an analysis
actually carried out? Under what conditions is a constructivist approach, as opposed to a
rationalist one, even necessary to explain the effects of social structures?
Progress on the first issue requires specification of political actors, that is, some model of
domestic politics within the state. There are all sorts of domestic frameworks available (pluralist,
institutional, and so on), but these are well known and need not be discussed. Rather, I wish to
suggest that constructivists have already uncovered abundant evidence that the state-level
penetration of international social structures varies cross nationally. The how deep question
clearly matters. 40

A few examples will clarify the point. Although Finnemore is not explicit on this score, one can
infer from her empirical chapters that normative effects are limited to state bureaucrats
(Finnemore, chaps. 2, 4). In the Katzenstein volume, some authors find norms held broadly within
a polity (Berger on postwar Germany and Japan), while others see their effects confined to
political and academic elites (Herman on the USSR) or to state decision makers (Risse-Kappen
on NATO; Katzenstein, chaps. 9, 8, 10). Klotz's cross-national design uncovers evidence of
normative effects at the level of political elites in one instance (the U.S.); in her British case,
however, such influences are partly blocked by deeper, historically constructed national
discourses (Klotz, chaps. 6, 7).

To make sense of and explain such diversity, constructivists will need to theorize the varying
processes through which social construction occurs. The insights gained from Klotz's partial move
in this direction indicate its importance. Here, constructivism would benefit greatly from utilizing
methods developed by IR scholars seeking to place greater emphasis on process. 41

Having established that social construction occurs at various levels within the state, the second
question can be addressed: how does one conduct such an analysis? For present purposes,
assume three domestic levels: society, state institutions, and individual decision makers.
Furthermore, due to space limitations, consider only the individual level. What does it mean to
explore the social construction of individual decision makers? Theoretically, it is to explore how
social structures interact [End Page 343] with and fundamentally affect the identities of these
agents, how certain logics of appropriateness come to govern their behavior.

For constructivists, this means being able to explain how the interests and identities of particular
agents, in the presence of norms, change--or, equally important, do not change over time.
Despite its centrality, this issue, which directly addresses the cognitive microfoundations of
constructivism, has not received the attention it should, especially in the empirical literature.
However, a review of this work suggests three possibilities.

One is a learning argument drawn from cognitive psychology. Just such a dynamic is implicit in
Finnemore's book, where agents (state elites), through exposure to norms, are taught new
identities and interests. Because interests are changing, one can infer that this is a constructivist
claim about complex, rather than simple, learning. (In the latter, new information allows actors to
pursue given interests more effectively; it can be accommodated within a rationalist framework.) 42

The problem for such arguments is that when one introduces the reality and friction of domestic
politics, complex learning typically breaks down. Absent such processes, one is back in the
rationalists' world of simple learning. This politics-learning tension is well established both
theoretically and empirically, with the basic insight being that learning becomes less likely as the
circle of actors grows. 43

Symbolic interactionist theory in sociology provides a second possible way to probe these
constructivist microfoundations. Here, individual identities and interests are formed through a
process of interaction, with two mechanisms being key: imitation and social learning. Since
imitation does not involve interaction (and, thus, mutual constitution), it is the social learning
dynamic that plays a more central role in the constructivist accounts. Social learning, much like
the cognitive/individual sort just discussed, can be simple or complex, but given the constructivist
emphasis on identity change, the focus is again on the latter. Specifically, complex social learning
occurs when identities and interests are learned in response to how actors are treated by
significant others. 44 [End Page 344]

While intriguing, this line of reasoning has not yet been integrated with empirical research. When
and if this occurs, the same problem as discussed above will confront constructivists: how to
maintain complex learning in settings where the static created by domestic politics hinders it.

Social psychology provides a final possible tool for exploring social construction at the individual
level. Here, the theoretical foundations are provided by Turner's self-categorization theory, where
the focus is on individual-group interactions. For constructivists, the key process in Turner's work
is depersonalization, for this is how individual identities and interests change through interaction
with a larger social group. 45

Unfortunately, this process is so context dependent and unclear (does depersonalization occur
through social learning? through coercion?), it is not at all certain how constructivists might
integrate its insights into their work. Nor surprisingly, when these scholars have used variants of
self-categorization theory, it has led to unresolved theoretical disputes, as well as to sloppy
empirical work. 46

The criticisms and questions raised above should not be viewed as dismissive. In addressing an
issue of central importance--how to connect social structures to agents--these scholars are
building much-needed bridges to other literatures. In fairness to constructivists, scholars of
rational choice have been harshly criticized in similar ways for their attempts at the reverse
process: connecting their sparse microfoundations to broader social and normative structures. 47

These last comments lead directly to the third question constructivism needs to address more
systematically at the domestic level: when is such an approach, as opposed to a rationalist one,
even necessary to explain the effects of social structures? Because most of the constructivist
work to date has been method driven, these scholars have failed to appreciate that the domestic
effects of norms are at times best captured and explained by rational choice. 48

Klotz's U.S. study, for example, suggests that global norms were not so much transforming the
identities of congressional representatives as [End Page 345] creating constraints on their
behavior (Klotz, chap. 6). In other words, one is back in the rationalist's world of means-ends
calculations (in this instance, a political survival calculus of how best to secure reelection). Now,
Klotz, as well as many contributors to the Katzenstein volume, does recognize that norms can
have instrumental effects such as these. Nonetheless, one would want clear indicators of when
one dynamic or the other is likely to prevail. The challenge, then, is to develop scope conditions.
49

One is temporal. This is the division-of-labor argument briefly mentioned in the Katzenstein
volume (Jepperson, Wendt, and Katzenstein, 70; Kowert and Legro, 490-91). Constructivism
might be best at explaining identity and interest formation, but as some later time, when interests
were stable, rationalism might be the right method. Such a solution would have the benefit of
making everyone happy: there would be a legitimate place and time for all approaches. However,
the devil is in the details. Empirically, how does one know a priori when a state is likely to be in a
period of identity formation, where constructivism is appropriate, as opposed to a time when
identities and interests are already fixed?

A second scope condition is a density-of-interactions argument, which has been applied primarily
to international bargaining. At some stage in this process, actors may switch from the rationalists'
consequential, means-ends logic to a situation in which their preferences are in genuine flux and
open to change through persuasion and communication. However, the key question is how one
predicts such a switch. What needs to happen and when? Cognitive uncertainty by individual
negotiators? The establishment, through communication and speech, of some level of collective
trust among them? Lacking this specification, the same problems arise as with the division-of-
labor argument. 50

A final scope condition explores the role of domestic institutions. "Institution," in this case, refers
to the bureaucracies, organizations, and groups that channel and define policy-making within
states. In the three books under review, one sees two very different normative effects at the
domestic level. In some instances, decision makers and elites are [End Page 346] essentially
taught (Finnemore) or learn (Herman, in Katzenstein, chap. 8) new beliefs and values in the
absence of any obvious domestic pressures; that is, new (constructivist) logics of appropriateness
come to govern their behavior. At other times, norms do not have individual effects; instead, they
mobilize domestic groups that pressure elites to change policy in ways consistent with the norms
(for example, Klotz, chap. 6). That is, normative effects are operating through (rationalist) means-
ends calculations.

Perhaps this variation is explained and predicted by differences in political institutions across
states. In liberal polities such as the U.S., where decision makers have little autonomy from
societal groups, the rationalists' instrumental logic more often captures the domestic effect of
systemic social structures. In states with greater autonomy and insulation from society (say, the
former USSR), constructivist logics may more often capture the unit-level affects of norms. 51

Conclusions
An IBM ad in a recent issue of the shows a well-heeled executive holding his head and shaking it
in despair: "Oh no, another paradigm shift," he laments. The good news for IR theorists is they
face no such threat from the constructivists reviewed in this essay. However, this attests not to
their failures but to the nature of their goals: dialogue, a widening of disciplinary foundations, and
a commitment to causal analysis. These scholars are out not to colonize and deconstruct IR but
to revitalize and expand its conceptual lenses.

That one can make so many critical observations about this work suggests, paradoxically, its
achievements. The publication of the books discussed here, along with the work of scholars such
as Wendt, Ruggie, and Kratochwil, has for the first time given constructivism a critical mass of
research that is both theoretical and empirical. This allows a reviewer to probe for lacunae and
tensions, as well as synergies in it.

At this point, instead of summarizing, a broader issue needs to be raised: what kind of
constructivism do we want? Some constructivists might feel this review "mainstreams" them too
much. The criticisms on research design, better specification of key terms, developing middle-
range [End Page 347] theory, taking domestic politics and agency seriously, after all, sound like a
primer for building a more coherent research program.

There are two reasons for constructivists to move in this direction. First, judging by many
comments to this effect, it is the direction in which they wish to move. Their emphasis on dialogue
and causal analysis suggests a fairly standard concern with building a rigorous and coherent
body of research that speaks to and plays off other literatures within IR.

Second, in its present form, it is not clear what one does with constructivism. How could
Finnemore's insights be applied to other international institutions--NATO, for example? Why do
the transnational norms, which figure so prominently in Klotz's study, have seemingly no impact in
contemporary China? Answers to such puzzles will come only when constructivists specify more
clearly the actors--structures and agents--and causal mechanisms bringing about change, the
scope conditions under which they operate and how they vary cross nationally. Absent this
theorizing, the "what do we do with it" question will remain.

Jeffrey T. Checkel is Senior Researcher and Coordinator, Research on European Identity


Change, arena (Advanced Research on the Europeanization of the Nation State), University of
Oslo. He is the author of Ideas and International Political Change: Soviet/Russian Behavior and
the End of the Cold War (1997). His current project is a cross-national study exploring the relation
between norms and identity change in contemporary Germany, Ukraine, and Russia.

* Earlier versions of this essay were presented at the 1996 annual convention of the American
Political Science Association, and at the workship on "Structural Change in International Politics,"
sponsored by the German Political Science Association, February 1997. For comments, I thank
Andrew Cortell, Aaron Hoffman, Jeff Legro, Thomas Risse, and Alex Wendt. The financial support
of the Alexander von Humboldt-Stiftung and German Marshall Fund is gratefully acknowledged.

Notes
1 See Robert Keohane, After Hegemony: Cooperation and Discord in the World Political
Economy (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1984); David Baldwin, ed., Neorealism and
Neoliberalism: The Contemporary Debate (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993); Robert
Powell, "Anarchy in International Relations Theory: The Neorealist-Neoliberal Debate (Review
Article)," International Organization 48 (Spring 1994); and "Promises, Promises: Can Institutions
Deliver?" International Security 20 (Summer 1995).

2 Alexander Wendt, "Constructing International Politics," International Security 20 (Summer


1995), 73.

3 For an excellent discussion of this black box for neoliberals and neorealists written by a theorist
sympathetic to their enterprise, see Powell (fn. 1), 317-24.

4 On neoliberalism's methodological individualism, see Volker Rittberger, Andreas Hasenclever,


and Peter Mayer, "Interests, Power, Knowledge: The Study of International Regimes," Mershon
International Studies Review 40 (October 1996), 183-87. For that of neorealism, see Alexander
Wendt, "The Agent-Structure Problem in International Relations Theory," International
Organization 41 (Summer 1987), 340-44.

5 On logics of appropriateness, see James March and Johan Olsen, Rediscovering Institutions:
The Organizational Basis of Politics (New York: Free Press, 1989).

6 On the last point, see Barry Weingast, "A Rational Choice Perspective on the Role of Ideas:
Shared Belief Systems and State Sovereignty in International Cooperation," Politics and Society
23 (December 1995); and Dennis Chong, "Rational Choice Theory's Mysterious Rivals," in Jeffrey
Friedman, ed., The Rational Choice Controversy: Economic Models of Politics Reconsidered
(New Haven: Yale University Press, 1996). Useful introductions to rational choice are Jon Elster,
"The Market and the Forum," in Elster, ed., Foundations of Social Choice Theory (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1986); James Morrow, Game Theory for Political Scientists
(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1994), chap. 2; and Donald Green and Ian Shapiro,
Pathologies of Rational Choice Theory: A Critique of Applications in Political Science (New
Haven: Yale University Press, 1994), chap. 2.

7 See, among others, Alexander Wendt, Social Theory of International Politics (New York:
Cambridge University Press, forthcoming), chaps. 1-2. There is a good bit of confusion regarding
these central tenets of constructivism; see, for example, John Mearsheimer, "The False Promise
of International Institutions," International Security 19 (Winter 1994-95), 37-47.

8 For example, Stephen Krasner, ed., International Regimes (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University
Press, 1983). My comparisons here are limited to mainstream ir, since it has been vastly more
influential than postmodern work in shaping the field.

9 Strictly speaking, my discussion of norms as intervening or independent variables is not correct,


as constitutive effects (A enables or makes possible B) are not captured by standard causal
terminology (A causes B). See Wendt (fn. 2), 72. In practice, however, empirical constructivists
use the terms interchangeably; see, for example, Mlada Bukovansky, "American Identity and
Neutral Rights: From Independence to the War of 1812," International Organization 51 (Spring
1997).

10 See, among others, Keohane (fn. 1); Lisa Martin, Coercive Cooperation: Explaining
Multilateral Economic Sanctions (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1992); and Beth A.
Simmons, "Why Innovate? Founding the Bank for International Settlements," World Politics 45
(April 1993).

11 See, among others, Stephen Walt, The Origins of Alliances (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University
Press, 1987); Jack Snyder, Myths of Empire: Domestic Politics and International Ambition (Ithaca,
N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1991); and William Wohlforth, "Realism and the End of the Cold
War," International Security 19 (Winter 1994-95).

12 Mark Zacher, Governing Global Networks: International Regimes for Transportation and
Communications (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1996), for example. An excellent,
synthetic review of the regime literature is Rittberger, Hasenclever, and Mayer (fn. 4).

13 See Peter Haas, Saving the Mediterranean: The Politics of International Environmental
Cooperation (New York: Columbia University Press, 1990); and Kathryn Sikkink, "Human Rights,
Principled Issue-Networks and Sovereignty in Latin America," International Organization 47
(Summer 1993). For critiques, see Checkel, Ideas and International Political Change:
Soviet/Russian Behavior and the End of the Cold War (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1997),
chaps. 1, 7; and Helen Milner, "International Theories of Cooperation: Strengths and
Weaknesses," World Politics 44 (April 1992).

14 The documentation and data come chiefly from archives at unesco's Paris headquarters.

15 For a similar argument, see David Strang and Patricia Mei Yin Chang, "The International Labor
Organization and the Welfare State: Institutional Effects on National Welfare Spending, 1960-80,"
International Organization 47 (Spring 1993).

16 On moral entrepreneurs and the development of norms, see also Ann Florini, "The Evolution of
International Norms," International Studies Quarterly 40 (September 1996).

17 Indeed, Wendt himself stresses the importance of mechanisms and process in causal
constructivist theorizing. Wendt (fn. 7), chap. 2, 91-96.

18 In addition to the edited volume, Katzenstein has published a monograph that makes many
similar sociological claims. See Peter Katzenstein, Cultural Norms and National Security: Police
and Military in Postwar Japan (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1996).

19 See also ibid., chap. 2.


20 Definitional congruence in key concepts of a research program is often seen as a sign of its
growing maturity. See Milner (fn. 13).

21 Students of the democratic peace literature will recognize this as a constructivist extension of
their domestic norms argument. See Zeev Maoz and Bruce Russett, "Normative and Structural
Causes of the Democratic Peace," American Political Science Review 87 (September 1993).

22 Risse-Kappen has elaborated these arguments in a separate monograph; Risse-Kappen,


Cooperation among Democracies: The European Influence on U.S. Foreign Policy (Princeton:
Princeton University Press, 1995).

23 In his own book, Katzenstein pays much greater attention to mapping such processes,
although a lack of explicit theorizing about them is still evident. Katzenstein (fn. 18), chaps. 3-6.

24 See Finnemore's bracketing strategy (p. 25); Wendt (fn. 4), 364-65; and fn. 9 above.

25 Friedrich Kratochwil and John Ruggie, "International Organization: A State of the Art on an Art
of the State," International Organization 40 (Autumn 1986); and Friedrich Kratochwil, Rules,
Norms and Decisions: On the Conditions of Practical and Legal Reasoning in International
Relations and Domestic Affairs (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1989).

26 By "theory" I mean middle-range theory and its development, which should be the goal of
problem-driven empirical research. See, for example, Thomas Risse-Kappen, ed., Bringing
Transnational Relations Back In: Non-State Actors, Domestic Structures and International
Institutions (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1995).

27 For the quote, see Wendt (fn. 7), chap. 1, 15. A central message of one recent and influential
critique of rational choice is precisely its neglect of theory development, particularly of the middle-
range sort. See Green and Shapiro (fn. 6), 188; and idem, "Pathologies Revisited; Reflections on
Our Critics," in Friedman (fn. 6).

28 On the last point, Klotz's cross-national focus is an important step in this direction. For
additional constructivist research utilizing single-country/issue designs, see Ray Koslowski and
Friedrich Kratochwil, "Understanding Change in International Politics: The Soviet Empire's
Demise and the International System," International Organization 48 (Spring 1994); Richard
Price, "A Genealogy of the Chemical Weapons Taboo," International Organization 49 (Winter
1995); Thomas Biersteker and Cynthia Weber, eds., State Sovereignty as Social Construct (New
York: Cambridge University Press, 1996); Bukovansky (fn. 9); Nina Tannenwald, "The Nuclear
Taboo: The Normative Basis of Deterrence" (Manuscript, Watson Institute for International
Studies, Brown University, April 1996); and Jutta Weldes, "Constructing National Interests,"
European Journal of International Relations 2 (September 1996).

29 On the last point, see Lars-Erik Cederman, "From Primordialism to Constructivism: The Quest
for Flexible Models of Ethnic Conflict" (Paper presented at the annual meeting of the American
Political Science Association, San Francisco, September 1996). A particularly egregious example
of the caricaturing is Mearsheimer (fn. 7).

30 See Frank Longstreth et al., Structuring Politics: Historical Institutionalism in Comparative


Analysis (New York: Cambridge University Press, 1992); and Judith Goldstein, Ideas, Interests
and American Trade Policy (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1993). Not surprisingly, it is
Katzenstein, the comparativist, who has offered the most careful constructivist account of
domestic norm institutionalization. See Katzenstein (fn. 18), chaps. 1-3, 5, 7.
31 Dessler's transformative model of international structure should be especially relevant to
constructivists as they rethink the role of agency in their analyses. See David Dessler, "What's at
Stake in the Agent-Structure Debate?" International Organization 43 (Summer 1989).

32 Checkel, "Norms, Institutions and National Identity in Contemporary Europe" (Manuscript,


October 1997).

33 See Paul DiMaggio, "Interest and Agency in Institutional Theory," in Lynne Zucker, ed.,
Institutional Patterns and Organizations: Culture and Environment (Cambridge: Ballinger
Publishing, 1988); Paul DiMaggio and Walter Powell, eds., The New Institutionalism in
Organizational Analysis (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1991), chaps. 1, 4; Frank Dobbin,
"Cultural Models of Organization: The Social Construction of Rational Organizing Principles," in
Diana Crane, ed., The Sociology of Culture: Emerging Theoretical Perspectives (Cambridge:
Blackwell Publishers, 1994).

34 See also the discussion of norm reproduction in Florini (fn. 16), 374-75, 377-80.

35 Alexander Wendt, "Collective Identity Formation and the International State," American
Political Science Review 88 (June 1994); and, for the quote, idem, "Identity and Structural
Change in International Politics," in Friedrich Kratochwil and Yosef Lapid, eds., The Return of
Culture and Identity in IR Theory (London: Lynne Rienner, 1996), 50-51. For critiques, see Sujuta
Pasic, "Culturing International Relations Theory: A Call for Extension," in Kratochwil and Lapid,
87-90; and Cederman (fn. 29), 13-19.

36 Rational choice institutionalism represents an effort to address this dilemma. See Norman
Schofield, "Rational Choice and Political Economy," in Friedman (fn. 6), 192-93, 207-8; and Peter
Hall and Rosemary Taylor, "Political Science and the Three New Institutionalisms," Political
Studies 44 (December 1996), 958-62.

37 On the micro versus the macrofoundations of behavior and identity and the tensions between
the two, see "Symposium: The Role of Theory in Comparative Politics," World Politics 48
(October 1995), 13-15.

38 After earlier confusion, Wendt also now argues that constructivism is not a theory. Wendt (fn.
7), chap. 1.

39 All the books reviewed are strongest, theoretically, at the systems level, in large part because
they draw upon an already well developed sociological literature that is systemic in orientation.
See Martha Finnemore, "Norms, Culture and World Politics: Insights from Sociology's
Institutionalism," International Organization 50 (Spring 1996).

40 Milner's (fn. 13) advice to mainstream ir theorists on how to conceptualize domestic politics is
relevant here as well.

41 Peter Evans, ed., Double-Edged Diplomacy: International Bargaining and Domestic Politics
(Berkeley: University of California Press, 1993); Haas (fn. 13); Sikkink (fn. 13); and Risse-Kappen
(fn. 26), among others.

42 Personal communication, Martha Finnemore, September 1996. See also Thomas Risse-
Kappen, "Democratic Peace--Warlike Democracies? A Social Constructivist Interpretation of the
Liberal Argument," European Journal of International Relations 1 (December 1995). On the
learning literature more generally, see Jack Levy, "Learning and Foreign Policy: Sweeping a
Conceptual Minefield (Review Article)," International Organization 48 (Spring 1994).
43 On the learning theory--politics connection, see Richard Anderson, "Why Competitive Politics
Inhibits Learning in Soviet Foreign Policy," in George Breslauer and Philip Tetlock, eds., Learning
in U.S. and Soviet Foreign Policy (Boulder, Colo.: Westview Press, 1991).

44 See Wendt (fn. 7), chap. 7; and idem, "Anarchy Is What States Make of It: The Social
Construction of Power Politics," International Organization 46 (Spring 1992). Symbolic
interactionist theory has been developed primarily at the individual level, which is why I discuss it
here. Wendt, unconvincingly in my view, argues that it can be applied at the level of (unitary)
states as well.

45 See John Turner, Rediscovering the Social Group: A Self-Categorization Theory (Oxford: Basil
Blackwell, 1987), chap. 3; and Penelope Oakes et al., eds., Stereotyping and Social Reality
(Oxford: Blackwell, 1994), chaps. 1, 4.

46 On the former, compare Jonathan Mercer, "Anarchy and Identity," International Organization
49 (Spring 1995); and Wendt (fn. 7), chap 7. For the sloppy empirical work, see Glenn Chafetz,
"The Political Psychology of the Nuclear Nonproliferation Regime," Journal of Politics 57 (August
1995).

47 For example, Robert Lane, "What Rational Choice Explains," in Friedman (fn. 6).

48 For details, see Checkel, "International Norms and Domestic Politics: Bridging the Rationalist-
Constructivist Divide," European Journal of International Relations 3 (December 1997).

49 For other constructivist accounts portraying similar rationalist logics, see Price and
Tannenwald, in Katzenstein, 138, 148-50; and Bukovansky (fn. 9), 21-51. Very similar questions
of scope and domain are now being asked by several rational choice analysts. See the
discussion of "segmented universalism," in Green and Shapiro (fn. 6), 192-93, 204; Michael
Taylor, "When Rationality Fails," in Friedman (fn. 6), 230-33; and Powell (fn. 1), 324.

50 Thomas Risse, "The Cold War's Endgame and German Unification" (A Review Essay),
International Security 21 (Spring 1997). This constructivist conception of communication thus
extends well beyond the rationalists' "cheap talk." For an excellent discussion, see James
Johnson, "Is Talk Really Cheap: Prompting Conversation between Critical Theory and Rational
Choice," American Political Science Review 87 (March 1993).

51 For a full theoretical elaboration, see Checkel, "Between Norms and Power: Identity Politics in
the New Europe" (Book manuscript in progress), chap. 2. Recent work on the role of international
norms in U.S. policy-making is consistent with the argument made here. See Andrew Cortell and
James Davis, "How Do International Institutions Matter? The Domestic Impact of International
Rules and Norms," International Studies Quarterly 40 (December 1996).

You might also like