Checkel 1998 - The Constructive Turn in IR Theory
Checkel 1998 - The Constructive Turn in IR Theory
Checkel 1998 - The Constructive Turn in IR Theory
http://journals.cambridge.org/WPO
Jeffrey T. Checkel
* Earlier versions of this essay were presented at the 1996 annual convention of the American Po-
litical Science Association, and at the workship on "Structural Change in International Politics," spon-
sored by the German Political Science Association, February 1997. For comments, I thank Andrew
Cortell, Aaron Hoffman, Jeff Legro, Thomas Risse, and Alex Wendt. The financial support of the
Alexander von Humboldt-Stiftung and German Marshall Fund is gratefully acknowledged.
1
See Robert Keohane, After Hegemony: Cooperation and Discord in the World Political Economy
(Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1984); David Baldwin, ed., Neorea/ism and Neoliberalism: The
Contemporary Debate (New York: Columbia University Press, 1993); Robert Powell, "Anarchy in In-
ternational Relations Theory: The Neorealist-Neoliberal Debate (Review Article)," International Or-
ganization 48 (Spring 1994); and "Promises, Promises: Can Institutions Deliver?" International Security
20 (Summer 1995).
6
On the last point, see Barry Weingast, "A Rational Choice Perspective on the Role of Ideas:
Shared Belief Systems and State Sovereignty in International Cooperation," Politics and Society 23
(December 1995); and Dennis Chong, "Rational Choice Theory's Mysterious Rivals," in Jeffrey Fried-
man, ed., The Rational Choice Controversy: Economic Models of Politics Reconsidered (New Haven: Yale
University Press, 1996). Useful introductions to rational choice are Jon Elster, "The Market and the
Forum," in Elster, ed., Foundations of Social Choice Theory (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press,
1986); James Morrow, Game Theory for Political Scientists (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1994),
chap. 2; and Donald Green and Ian Shapiro, Pathologies ofRational Choice Theory: A Critique of Appli-
cations in Political Science (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1994), chap. 2.
7
See, among others, Alexander Wendt, Social Theory of International Politics (New York: Cambridge
University Press, forthcoming), chaps. 1-2. There is a good bit of confusion regarding these central
tenets of constructivism; see, for example, John Mearsheimer, "The False Promise of International In-
stitutions," International Security 19 (Winter 1994-95), 37-47.
8
For example, Stephen Krasner, ed., International Regimes (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press,
1983). My comparisons here are limited to mainstream IR, since it has been vastly more influential than
postmodern work in shaping the field.
328 WORLD POLITICS
actors. Their effects reach deeper: they constitute actor identities and
interests and do not simply regulate behavior. As explanatory variables,
their status moves from intervening to independent (Finnemore, chaps.
3,4; Klotz, chap. 6, for example). Norms are no longer a superstructure
on a material base; rather, they help to create and define that base. For
constructivists, agents (states) and structures (global norms) are inter-
acting; they are mutually constituted.9
Taken together, these moves by constructivists—their questioning of
methodological individualism and materialism, along with a continu-
ing commitment to the scientific enterprise—have brought a breath of
fresh air to thinking about world politics, in ways accessible to nearly
all scholars. A key issue, however, is whether such new perspectives
allow these researchers to explain important international puzzles
and phenomena and thereby demonstrate the empirical value of their
approach.
" T h e documentation and data come chiefly from archives at UNESCO's Paris headquarters.
15
For a similar argument, see David Strang and Patricia Mei Yin Chang, "The International Labor
Organization and the Welfare State: Institutional Effects on National Welfare Spending, 1960-80,"
International Organization 47 (Spring 1993).
332 WORLD POLITICS
The book also fills a gap in constructivism: failure to tell us why cer-
tain norms arise at particular times. Finnemore provides an answer by
exploring the role of moral entrepreneurs: committed individuals who
happen to be in the right place at the right time to instill their beliefs in
larger global social structures (pp. 24-28, chap. 4, pp. 137-39). 16
Finnemore's account is not without weaknesses, however. Most im-
portant, it is not clear what one does with her argument, with so much
resting on contingencies and idiosyncratic variables. While Finnemore
has demonstrated that social construction is causally important, she has
failed to specify systematically when, how, and why this occurs. To be
fair, one book cannot do everything. All the same, the critical next step
should be the development of a specifically constructivist theory of in-
ternational institutions, one that would elaborate such scope conditions.
A second weakness is the degree to which Finnemore's analysis is con-
sistent with constructivism's mutual constitution of agents and structures.
Now, exactly how one operationalizes mutual constitution is a dilemma
for all empirical constructivists. Finnemore's solution is a bracketing
strategy, where she first brackets agency and then, structures; her case
studies are broadly faithful to this approach (pp. 24-25, chaps. 2-4).
The problem is the wrong choice of agents: the entrepreneurs who
are responsible for the creation of norms in the first place. To analyze
the process of mutual constitution that led to a change of national in-
terests within particular states (her dependent variable), the agents she
should be exploring, especially given her emphasis on global norms as
the structures, are groups and individuals in those same states. If
Finnemore had focused on these agents, it would have led her to ex-
plore several important issues, for example, the feedback effects of state
(agent) behavior on the norms themselves.
A final difficulty is unavoidable given Finnemore's emphasis on sys-
temic social structures: the neglect of domestic politics. A question that
immediately comes to mind when reading her analysis is why norms
diffuse differentially, that is, why they have so much greater impact in
some countries than in others. Through what mechanisms do global
norms work their effects domestically? Finnemore alludes to these is-
sues at several points but provides no clear answers (pp. 125,137). This
is odd, since it is the constructivists, with their attention to practice and
interaction, who should be keying upon process and mechanisms.17
16
On moral entrepreneurs and the development of norms, see also Ann Florini, "The Evolution of
International Norms," International Studies Quarterly 40 (September 1996).
17
Indeed, Wendt himself stresses the importance of mechanisms and process in causal construc-
tivist theorizing, Wendt (fn. 7), chap. 2,91-96.
C O N S T R U C T I V I S T TURN IN IR T H E O R Y 333
18
In addition to the edited volume, Katzenstein has published a monograph that makes many sim-
ilar sociological claims. See Peter Katzenstein, Cultural Norms and National Security: Police and Military
in PostwarJapan (Ithaca, N.Y.: Cornell University Press, 1996).
" See also ibid., chap. 2.
334 WORLD POLITICS
Given this stance, the volume needs to address two key questions:
(1) the content and properties of the social structures having such pro-
found effects on agents; and (2) the causal mechanisms through which
these structures have their affects. The social structures doing the ex-
planatory work are norms and, to a lesser extent, culture. The former
are defined as collective expectations about proper behavior for a given
identity (Jepperson, Wendt, and Katzenstein, 54). That this is the same
definition as used by Finnemore and Klotz is one indicator, among oth-
ers, that a constructivist research program is beginning to consolidate
itself in IR.20
The presence of these normative structures is established through a
variety of well-established and standard methodological techniques, for
example, interview data, qualitative content analysis of primary sources,
statistical studies. The research strategy is broadly similar to Finne-
more's: document the presence of the social structures; note a correla-
tion between these and new state interests; examine changing discourse
as further evidence of these normative effects; and,finally,strengthen
the case by considering alternative explanations, usually drawn from
neorealist and neoliberal theories.
Risse-Kappen's chapter on the North Atlantic Treaty Organization
is a good example of the general approach. His puzzle is to explain
NATO's initial formation and endurance—events that are anomalous, he
argues, from the standpoint of both traditional and more sophisticated
realist theories of alliances. In the first part of his essay Risse-Kappen
discusses these likely alternative explanations and carefully documents
their shortcomings.
Next, he develops his own liberal constructivist approach, where the
norms that govern the domestic decision-making process within liberal
systems come to regulate the interactions among democracies in inter-
national institutions such as NATO. Democracies, Risse-Kappen argues,
"externalize their internal norms when cooperating with each other.
Power asymmetries will be mediated by norms of democratic decision-
making among equals emphasizing persuasion, compromise and the
non-use of force or coercive power." He then deduces four different
ways such norms will influence the interaction process among demo-
cratic allies (pp. 268-71).21
20
Definitional congruence in key concepts of a research program is often seen as a sign of its grow-
ing maturity. See Milner (fh. 13).
21
Students of the democratic peace literature will recognize this as a constructivist extension of their
domestic norms argument. See Zeev Maoz and Bruce Russett, "Normative and Structural Causes of
the Democratic Peace," American Political Science Review 87 (September 1993).
CONSTRUCTIVIST TURN IN IR THEORY 335
Risse-Kappen illustrates the argument by showing how the interests
in play, both in the formation of NATO and during several key crises
(Suez 1956, Cuba 1962), were shaped by the democratic normative
context in which they evolved. In other words, the interests of states
and alliance decision makers (the agents) were being constituted by
these democratic norms (the structures). His evidence is carefully culled
from secondary and, especially, primary sources, for example, the U.S.
government's Foreign Relations of the United States series and materials
in the National Security Archive. This allows him to dissect the deci-
sion-making process, snowing how norms affected the preferences and
interests of various alliance partners.22
The essay by Risse-Kappen is not at all atypical for the Katzenstein
volume, which contains a number of carefully argued studies docu-
menting the impact of norms. Unfortunately, the volume is much
weaker at theorizing the causal mechanisms that give these social struc-
tures such powerful constitutive effects. This is a fair criticism to make,
as the authors clearly commit themselves to a largely causal epistemol-
ogy (Katzenstein, 4-5, 7; Jepperson, Wendt, and Katzenstein, 52-53,
65-68). However, as Katzenstein himself admits in the book's conclud-
ing essay, structural theories such as sociological institutionalism, which
is accorded a central role in the volume, neglect important processes
that translate structural effects (pp. 512—13).23
One result is that the role of agency, while highlighted empirically in
many of the chapters, is neglected theoretically. The volume short-cir-
cuits one loop in the constructivist method: the causal arrows flow pri-
marily from structures to agents. Mutual constitution, however, implies
they also flow from agents to structures. Some constructivists might
object that such sequential (structures to agents then agents to struc-
tures) causal language misconstrues the essence of their ontology: the
simultaneous, mutual constitution of agents and structures. However,
the empirical application of mutual constitution by these scholars fol-
lows precisely the sequential logic outlined here.24
Despite such shortcomings, this is a very important volume. Its com-
mitment to causal analysis and standard methodologies contributes to a
productive dialogue with neorealists and neoliberals; for the most part,
these scholars are all talking the same language. In addition, the case
22
Risse-Kappen has elaborated these arguments in a separate monograph; Risse-Kappen, Coopera-
tion among Democracies: The European Influence on U.S. Foreign Policy (Princeton: Princeton University
Press, 1995).
23
In his own book, Katzenstein pays much greater attention to mapping such processes, although a
lack of explicit theorizing about them is still evident. Katzenstein (fh. 18), chaps. 3-6.
24
See Finnemore's bracketing strategy (p. 25); Wendt (fh. 4), 364-65; and fh. 9 above.
336 WORLD POLITICS
studies (chaps. 3-11) offer new and meaningful insights. For some au-
thors, this means demonstrating that particular security outcomes can
be explained only when realist analyses are supplemented with con-
structivist approaches (Hermans chapter on Soviet foreign policy under
Gorbachev; Risse-Kappen's essay on NATO).
Other contributors, however, go a step further and argue that their
constructivist approach supplants rationalist and materialist accounts.
For example, in a superbly argued essay, Alastair Johnston shows that
the persistence of China's realpolitik over several centuries can be un-
derstood only in terms of a constructivist explanation that subsumes
structural realism (Katzenstein, chap. 7).
Finally, in an innovation rare in any edited volume, Katzenstein has
included an essay (chap. 12 by Kowert and Legro) that reflects critically
on the book as a whole. This excellent chapter provides the sense of
cumulation and summary that is missing when one reads across the
various contributions. It achieves this not by championing the con-
structivist cause but by critically evaluating the volume's shortcomings.
For developing a more coherent constructivist research program, this is
precisely what is needed. Katzenstein et al. are to be applauded for in-
cluding such a chapter.
has been developed primarily at the individual level, which is why I discuss it here. Wendt, uncon-
vincingly in my view, argues that it can be applied at the level of (unitary) states as well.
<s
See John Turner, Rediscovering the Social Group: A Self-Categorization Theory (Oxford: Basil Black-
well, 1987), chap. 3; and Penelope Oakes et al., eds., Stereotyping and Social Reality (Oxford: Blackwell,
1994), chaps. 1,4.
* On the former, compare Jonathan Mercer, "Anarchy and Identity," International Organization 49
(Spring 1995); and Wendt (fn. 7), chap 7. For the sloppy empirical work, see Glenn Chafetz, "The Po-
litical Psychology of the Nuclear Nonproliferation Regime," Journal of Politics 57 (August 1995).
47
For example, Robert Lane, "What Rational Choice Explains," in Friedman (fn. 6).
48
For details, see Checkel, "International Norms and Domestic Politics: Bridging the Rationalist-
Constructivist Divide," European Journal of International Relations 3 (December 1997).
346 WORLD POLITICS
creating constraints on their behavior (Klotz, chap. 6). In other words, one
is back in the rationalist s world of means-ends calculations (in this in-
stance, a political survival calculus of how best to secure reelection). Now,
Klotz, as well as many contributors to the Katzenstein volume, does rec-
ognize that norms can have instrumental effects such as these. Nonethe-
less, one would want clear indicators of when one dynamic or the other is
likely to prevail. The challenge, then, is to develop scope conditions.49
One is temporal. This is the division-of-labor argument briefly men-
tioned in the Katzenstein volume (Jepperson, Wendt, and Katzenstein,
70; Kowert and Legro, 490-91). Constructivism might be best at ex-
plaining identity and interest formation, but as some later time, when
interests were stable, rationalism might be the right method. Such a so-
lution would have the benefit of making everyone happy: there would
be a legitimate place and time for all approaches. However, the devil
is in the details. Empirically, how does one know a priori when a state
is likely to be in a period of identity formation, where constructivism is
appropriate, as opposed to a time when identities and interests are al-
ready fixed?
A second scope condition is a density-of-interactions argument,
which has been applied primarily to international bargaining. At some
stage in this process, actors may switch from the rationalists' conse-
quential, means-ends logic to a situation in which their preferences are
in genuine flux and open to change through persuasion and communi-
cation. However, the key question is how one predicts such a switch.
What needs to happen and when? Cognitive uncertainty by individual
negotiators? The establishment, through communication and speech,
of some level of collective trust among them? Lacking this specifica-
tion, the same problems arise as with the division-of-labor argument.50
A final scope condition explores the role of domestic institutions.
"Institution," in this case, refers to the bureaucracies, organizations, and
groups that channel and define policy-making within states. In the
three books under review, one sees two very different normative effects
at the domestic level. In some instances, decision makers and elites are
49
For other constructivist accounts portraying similar rationalist logics, see Price and Tannenwald,
in Katzenstein, 138,148-50; and Bukovansky (fn. 9), 21-51. Very similar questions of scope and do-
main are now being asked by several rational choice analysts. See the discussion of "segmented univer-
salism," in Green and Shapiro (fn. 6), 192—93, 204; Michael Taylor, "When Rationality Fails," in
Friedman (fn. 6), 230-33; and Powell (fn. 1), 324.
50
Thomas Risse, "The Cold War's Endgame and German Unification" (A Review Essay), Interna-
tional Security 21 (Spring 1997). This constructivist conception of communication thus extends well
beyond the rationalists' "cheap talk." For an excellent discussion, see James Johnson, "Is Talk Really
Cheap: Prompting Conversation between Critical Theory and Rational Choice," American Political
Science Review 87 (March 1993).
CONSTRUCTIVIST TURN IN IR THEORY 347
essentially taught (Finnemore) or learn (Herman, in Katzenstein, chap.
8) new beliefs and values in the absence of any obvious domestic pres-
sures; that is, new (constructivist) logics of appropriateness come to
govern their behavior. At other times, norms do not have individual ef-
fects; instead, they mobilize domestic groups that pressure elites to
change policy in ways consistent with the norms (for example, Klotz,
chap. 6). That is, normative effects are operating through (rationalist)
means-ends calculations.
Perhaps this variation is explained and predicted by differences in
political institutions across states. In liberal polities such as the U.S.,
where decision makers have little autonomy from societal groups, the
rationalists' instrumental logic more often captures the domestic effect
of systemic social structures. In states with greater autonomy and insu-
lation from society (say, the former USSR), constructivist logics may
more often capture the unit-level affects of norms.51
CONCLUSIONS
51
For a full theoretical elaboration, see Checkel, "Between Norms and Power: Identity Politics in
the New Europe" (Book manuscript in progress), chap. 2. Recent work on the role of international
norms in U.S. policy-making is consistent with the argument made here. See Andrew Cortell and
James Davis, "How Do International Institutions Matter? The Domestic Impact of International
Rules and Norms," International Studies Quarterly 40 (December 1996).
348 WORLD POLITICS
range theory, taking domestic politics and agency seriously, after all,
sound like a primer for building a more coherent research program.
There are two reasons for constructivists to move in this direction.
First, judging by many comments to this effect, it is the direction in
which they wish to move. Their emphasis on dialogue and causal analy-
sis suggests a fairly standard concern with building a rigorous and co-
herent body of research that speaks to and plays off other literatures
within IR.
Second, in its present form, it is not clear what one does with con-
structivism. How could Finnemore's insights be applied to other inter-
national institutions—NATO, for example? Why do the transnational
norms, which figure so prominently in Klotz's study, have seemingly no
impact in contemporary China? Answers to such puzzles will come only
when constructivists specify more clearly the actors—structures and
agents—and causal mechanisms bringing about change, the scope condi-
tions under which they operate and how they vary cross nationally. Ab-
sent this theorizing, the "what do we do with it" question will remain.