Callon, M., Law, J. (1982) - On Interests and Their Transformation - Enrolment and Enrolment. Social Studies of Science, Vol. 12, No. 4, Theme Section - Laboratory Studies (Nov), Pp. 615-625
Callon, M., Law, J. (1982) - On Interests and Their Transformation - Enrolment and Enrolment. Social Studies of Science, Vol. 12, No. 4, Theme Section - Laboratory Studies (Nov), Pp. 615-625
Callon, M., Law, J. (1982) - On Interests and Their Transformation - Enrolment and Enrolment. Social Studies of Science, Vol. 12, No. 4, Theme Section - Laboratory Studies (Nov), Pp. 615-625
Your use of the JSTOR archive indicates your acceptance of JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use, available at
http://www.jstor.org/page/info/about/policies/terms.jsp. JSTOR's Terms and Conditions of Use provides, in part, that unless
you have obtained prior permission, you may not download an entire issue of a journal or multiple copies of articles, and you
may use content in the JSTOR archive only for your personal, non-commercial use.
Please contact the publisher regarding any further use of this work. Publisher contact information may be obtained at
http://www.jstor.org/action/showPublisher?publisherCode=sageltd.
Each copy of any part of a JSTOR transmission must contain the same copyright notice that appears on the screen or printed
page of such transmission.
JSTOR is a not-for-profit service that helps scholars, researchers, and students discover, use, and build upon a wide range of
content in a trusted digital archive. We use information technology and tools to increase productivity and facilitate new forms
of scholarship. For more information about JSTOR, please contact [email protected].
Sage Publications, Ltd. is collaborating with JSTOR to digitize, preserve and extend access to Social Studies of
Science.
http://www.jstor.org
NOTES AND LETTERS
* ABSTRACT
A way of treating interests which differs from those of both Woolgar and Barnes
is here recommended. This third 'enrolment' or 'networking' theory approach
notes that actors attempt to enlist one another in a variety of different ways,
including the transformation of imputed interests. Some of the strategies
adopted in this process are considered. Overall, it is suggested that interests
should not be imputed to actors as background causes of action, but rather that
they should be seen as attempts to define and enforce contingent forms of social
order on the part of actors themselves.
Social Studies of Science (SAGE, London and Beverly Hills), Vol. 12 (1982), 615-25
616 Social Studies of Science
that there can be nothing final about this (and all other) ex-
planatory attempts. On the other hand, there is the
ethnomethodological preoccupation with the essential reflexivity of
discourse, and, accordingly, in this context, with the methods by
which interest explanations are mounted such that they achieve the
status of being descriptions of putative, externally existing, in-
fluences on knowledge. Woolgar actually considers how MacKen-
zie imputed interests in the course of his study of the different ap-
proaches adopted by Pearson and Yule to the correlation of
nominal variables, but it seems clear from his text that the imputa-
tion of interests by scientists themselves would be an equally ap-
propriate focus of study. Perhaps it is a pity that he did not adopt
the latter course which might have resulted in a less acrimonious
debate, for at least one thing is clear to us (as it is to Barnes): the
two approaches are directed by different (dare we say it?) interests
and are, at least in some respects, accordingly incommensurable.
In this Note we want to avoid a commentary on the relative
merits of these two positions. Our aim is, rather, to suggest that
there is (at least) a third way of considering the 'problem of in-
terests'. We will attempt, in the short space available, to indicate
the promise of this third 'enrolment' or 'networking' theory,3 by
showing how it can be utilized for a simple empirical case. We will
not attempt to explore it fully or to argue its superiority to existing,
well-established views.
Imputing Interests
... we could have chosen all sorts of polymers to do this experiment with, but
having chosen one that other people have done things with will in fact make it
much easier to get it published. You can start by saying 'so and so has said this,
etc., etc., and it's interesting to find out whether DIVEMA does so and so.' 6
Transforming Interests
Our referees have advised me not to accept your paper for publication on two
grounds. Firstly, that your study is only of limited relevance to cancer and
secondly, from a scientific standpoint, 'not enough attention has been paid to
the possible limitations of the assay systems employed and, in view of this fact,
the conclusions drawn may prove somewhat premature'.14
Watt: I think we thought [this paper] was distinctly weaker [than a later one]. It
lacked interest. That was the trouble...
Dover: It was sound but very dull. There was nothing interesting. There was
nothing that would compel anyone to read it, if you like, whereas the extra infor-
mation that we've collected is [of] interest.15
* NOTES
Jon Harwood, Bruno Latour and Rob Williams all contributed, in one way or
another, to the writing of this paper. We thank them - and, of course, the long-
suffering Chinatown scientists.
14. The first paragraph of a letter of rejection from Cancer Quarterly dated 10
February 1979.
15. Tape-recorded interview, 28 January 1981, tape 1A/141.
16. We qualify this suggestion because the Chinatown team had always doubted
that the DIVEMA results would be positive and thus very interesting: see Williams
and Law, op. cit. note 4, 298.
17. We are happy to report that this later paper has been accepted.
18. We are aware that there is a great deal more to be said about this success,
though this cannot be properly outlined here. Broadly, however, we would approach
the matter by noting that Chinatown's interests (a product of enrolment by
previously encountered others, and consequential self-definition) led them to accept
a rejection letter of this kind, however unwelcome, as the last word. Effectively
Chinatown was left resourceless in this interaction. Other resources (for example,
the use of violence), were almost literally unthinkable in the context of the 'facts'
and 'interests' generated by Chinatown.
19. See Law and Williams, op. cit. note 3.
20. See Callon, op. cit. note 3; and Michel Callon, Jean-Pierre Courtial, William
Turner and Serge Bauin, 'From Translation to Network: An Introduction to Co-
Word Analysis', Social Science Information, forthcoming (1983).
21. Bruno Latour, 'Give Me a Laboratory and I will Raise the World', in Karin
D. Knorr-Cetina and Michael Mulkay (eds), Science Observed (London: SAGE
Publications, forthcoming).
22. Though much of his work is important in this respect, see in particular, Andy
Pickering, 'The Role of Interests in High Energy Physics: the Choice between
Charm and Colour', in Knorr et al. (eds), op. cit. note 8, 107-38; and also Pickering,
'Exemplars and Analogies: A Comment on Crane's Study of Kuhnian Paradigms in
High Energy Physics', Social Studies of Science, Vol. 10 (1980), 497-502.
23. For further argument on the irrelevance of the 'macro' and the 'micro', see
Michel Callon and Bruno Latour, 'Unscrewing the Big Leviathan: How Actors
Macro-structure Reality and How Sociologists Help them to Do So', in Karin D.
Knorr and Aaron Cicourel (eds), Advances in Social Theory and Methodology:
Toward an Integration of Micro- and Macro-Sociologies (London: Routledge and
Kegan Paul, 1981), 277-303.
24. Woolgar, op. cit. note 1, 373.
25. It might be argued that given a choice between conformity and the guillotine,
it was in the 'interests' of the person presented with the option to opt for
conformity. We have no strong objection to such an extension of the term, but on
balance it seems to be a somewhat unhelpful redescription.
Notes & Letters: Callon & Law: Enrolment 625