Ferraris - Manifesto of New Realism
Ferraris - Manifesto of New Realism
Ferraris - Manifesto of New Realism
Maurizio Ferraris
10 9 8 7 6 5 4 3 2 1
Suppose there is a black rock on an island, and
that its inhabitants have come to believe—through
elaborated experiences and an intensive use of per-
suasion—that the rock is white. Yet the rock would
be black, and the inhabitants nothing but idiots.
—Paolo Bozzi (1930–2003)
CONTENTS
Prologue xiii
Notes 85
Index 101
vii
FOREWORD
GRAHAM HARMAN
ix
x Foreword
Notes
xiii
xiv Prologue
xvii
ONE
REALITISM
The Postmodern Attack on Reality
Ironization
Desublimation
Deobjectification
If, nevertheless, we look for the sufficient reason and the politi-
cal engine of ironization and desublimation we find deobjecti-
fication: that is, the idea that objectivity, reality, and truth are
a bad thing and even that ignorance is a good thing. Also in
Realitism 13
But the area where skepticism and the farewell to truth have
shown their most aggressive side is politics.32 Here, postmodern
deobjectification was, exemplarily, the underlying philosophy
of the Bush government, which theorized that reality was sim-
ply the belief of “reality-based communities”—that is, unwary
people who do not know how things go. This praxis found
its most concise expression in the response by one of Bush’s
consultants to the journalist Ron Suskind: “We’re an empire
now, and when we act, we create our own reality. And while
you’re studying that reality—judiciously, as you will—we’ll act
again, creating other new realities, which you can study too.”33
An arrogant absurdity, of course. Yet, eight years before that
the philosopher and sociologist Jean Baudrillard had claimed
that the Gulf War was nothing but a TV fiction,34 playing (like
Feyerabend) the role of the useful skeptic in favor of a cause
that was certainly not his own.
the world for what it is. Thirty years of history taught us the
opposite.
As I mentioned in the prologue, what I call “new realism”
is therefore the common name of a transformation that hit
contemporary philosophical culture and that was developed in
many directions. First of all, the end of the linguistic turn and
the stronger realist inclination of philosophers that, while not
adhering to postmodernist positions, had previously been more
sensitive to the reasons of constructivism and the modeling
role of conceptual schemes upon experience. Think of Hilary
Putnam’s passage from “internal realism” to “commonsense
realism,”39 or of the claim of the importance of experience
with respect to conceptual schemes in Umberto Eco,40 or again
of the development of a “speculative realism” by the younger
generations of philosophers.41 Another way in which the turn
took place is the return to perception, which was traditionally
neglected by philosophical transcendentalism culminating in
postmodernism. Typically, the fact that aesthetics returned to be
considered not as a philosophy of illusion but as a philosophy
of perception42 revealed a new openness toward the external
world, namely, a real that lies beyond conceptual schemes and
that is independent from them—just as it is impossible for us to
correct optical illusions or change the color of the objects sur-
rounding us by mere reflection. A third significant element of
the realistic transformation is what I would call the ontological
turn, namely, the fact that both in analytic and in continental
philosophy there has been an increasing recovery of ontology as
the science of being43 and of the multiplicity of objects, which—
from perception to society—constitute a research area that is
not necessarily subordinated to natural science. With the return
of ontology, therefore, there is the overcoming of the prevailing
philosophical attitude ever since Kant, who had bid ontology
farewell by claiming that philosophy had to cease dealing with
Realitism 19
obtain the “Emancipation” that lends its name to the last chap-
ter, it will thus be necessary to resort to Enlightenment, which,
as Kant put it, is “sapere aude!” and marks “man’s emergence
from his self-incurred immaturity.”48 Enlightenment, today, still
requires a stand and faith in mankind, which is not a fallen race
in need of redemption but an animal species that evolves and
that, in its progress, was endowed with reason.
TWO
REALISM
Things That Have Existed
Since the Beginning of the World
23
24 Manifesto of New Realism
Epistemology Ontology
Amendable Unamendable
What can be corrected What cannot be corrected
Internal World External World
(= internal to conceptual schemes) (= external to conceptual schemes)
Science Experience
Linguistic Not necessarily linguistic
Historical Not historical
Free Unamendable
Infinite Finite
Teleological Not necessarily teleological
Positivism?
RECONSTRUCTION
Why Criticism Starts from Reality
45
46 Manifesto of New Realism
Army entered Auschwitz and saw the “shame the Germans did
not know.” Sure, you may decide to introduce a discontinuity,
but the price would be very high, because if you cut at any
point the wire that leads from the snow to the Holocaust, then
any denial becomes possible. If this is the case, the “very dif-
ferent” something appealed to by those who argue that tables
and chairs are devoid of philosophical relevance is connected
to the world of tables and chairs by a robust and continuous
wire, which cannot be broken—otherwise one will fall into
meaninglessness or irresponsibility.
Deconstruction
Criticism
Reconstruction
EMANCIPATION
Unexamined Life Has No Value
65
66 Manifesto of New Realism
Dialectic
Certainty
Should we trust it? There are bad mothers, both in the literal
sense and figuratively; there are deceivers and manipulators,
both in the name of reason and in the name of faith. Moreover,
certainty (and sensible experience itself proves it) can be deceit-
ful. So, I can have hallucinations, or my mother might not be
my mother, or even—as happened to the boys of the Hitler-
jugend—my certainty and my fundamental reliance could be
named Adolf Hitler. So, certainty alone is not enough: it needs
truth, that is, knowledge. Here, rather than with the experience
of the reliance on the mother, we are confronted with a differ-
ent movement, namely, with man’s emergence from childhood
and with the “dare to know” brought forward by Enlighten-
ment. In fact, no one denies that in the light of reliance, cer-
tainty, and dependence, one can live and die—maybe even very
well. And of course Oedipus would have lived better had he
not found out the truth. Yet, these practical or rather “eude-
monistic” motives (to use an old-fashioned expression) do not
exempt us from a consideration: living in certainty, for what we
have said so far, is not living in truth. And we should note that
it is in the name of truth that the promise of certainty—maybe
the ‘‘worship, rejoice, be silent” with which a great philoso-
pher, Antonio Rosmini, ended his earthly life—gives peace. But
it is also true that peace, as Kafka said, “would be of a kind
desirable only for one’s ashes.”21
Enlightenment
Liberation
Prologue
85
86 Notes to Chapter 1
Chapter 1. Realitism
Chapter 2. Realism
18. From this point of view, as for my research, the text to start
from is Analogon rationis (Milan: Pratica filosofica, 1994).
For a comprehensive presentation of the role of perception
in my perspective, I refer the reader to the afterword of
the new edition of my Estetica razionale (Milan: Raffaello
Cortina, 2011 [1997]), 573–586.
19. Maurizio Ferraris, “Metzger, Kant, and the Perception of
Causality,” in Johan C. Marek and Maria E. Reicher, eds.,
Erfahrung und Analyse (Wien: ÖBV & HPT, 2005), 297–
309. The closeness of Metzger’s concept of “encountered”
and my concept of “unamendable” has been underlined by
Giovanni Bruno Vicario, Psicologia generale: I fondamenti
(Rome and Bari: Laterza, 2001), 101. I also refer the reader
to Vicario’s analyses for a presentation of the concept of
“reality” in psychology.
20. See Paolo Bozzi, Fisica ingenua (Milan: Garzanti, 1990);
Paolo Bozzi, Scritti sul realismo (Milan: Mimesis, 2007) (I
argue more extensively what I am saying here in the intro-
duction to that volume, 11–20; for the ontological impli-
cations, I refer the reader to my “Ontologia come Fisica
ingenua,” Rivista di estetica n.s., 6 [1998]: 133–143).
21. And as I articulated in Il mondo esterno, 198–201.
22. See ibid., 89 ff., to which I refer the reader for a complete
phenomenology.
23. For a more detailed analysis, see ibid., 193–201.
Chapter 3. Reconstruction
Chapter 4. Emancipation