Oran YOUNG, International Cooperation (Building Regimes For Natural Resources and The Environment)
Oran YOUNG, International Cooperation (Building Regimes For Natural Resources and The Environment)
Oran YOUNG, International Cooperation (Building Regimes For Natural Resources and The Environment)
9
International Regimes in Theory
10
Chapter One
International Regimes:
An Institutional Perspective
12
International Regimes
!3
International Regimes in Theory
6. Among other things, this fact explains why those endeavoring to elicit compliance
with the lights and rules of international regimes often turn to domestic courts. See
Richard A. Falk, The Role of Domestic Courts in the International Legal Order (Syracuse:
Syracuse University Press, 1964).
7. See also Mark W. Zacher, Trade Gaps, Analytical Gaps: Regime Analysis and
International Commodity Trade Regulation,” International Organization 41 (1987), 173-
H
International Regimes
10. In real-world situations, those involved in regime formation virtually never operate
behind a Rawlsian “veil of ignorance.” See John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge:
Harvard University Press, 1971), chap. 3.
11. Though this is not the place to address problems of operationalization in detail, a
few comments on the empirical analysis of rights and rules are in order here. Empirically,
rights and rules can be approached either in terms of the expectations shared by the
members of a given group or in terms of observable regularities in the behavior of the
group’s members. As the two approaches are not mutually exclusive, it may well be
instructive to make use of both in the effort to pin down rights and rules empirically. This
suggests that there is no necessary connection between the rights and rules actually
operative in a social environment and the statements regarding rights and rules contained
in formal documents such as treaties or conventions, though it may still prove useful to
turn to such documents for an easily accessible approximation of the substantive compo¬
nent of specific institutional arrangements. For some additional observations pertaining to
these issues see Axelrod, “An Evolutionary Approach to Norms.”
12. On the idea of bundles of rights see Charles A. Reich, “The New Property,” Yale Law
Journal 73 (1964), 733-787.
z5
International Regimes in Theory
13. Consult, among others, Eirik Furubotn and Svetozar Pejovich, “Property Rights
and Economic Theory: A Survey of Recent Literature,” Journal of Economic Literature 10
(1972), 1137-1162.
14. The result may be described as a system of “restricted” common property: see J. H.
Dales, Pollution, Property, and Prices (Toronto: University of Toronto Press, 1968), 61—65.
15. My use of the concept “rules” differs somewhat from that prevalent in recent
contributions to jurisprudence. Compare H. L. A. Hart, The Concept of Law (Oxford:
Oxford University Press, 1961), and Ronald Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously (Cambridge:
Harvard University Press, 1977), especially chaps. 2 and 3.
International Regimes
16. See G. H. von Wright, Norms and Actions (New York: Humanities Press, 1963).
17. On liability rules and their significance compare R. H. Coase, “The Problem of
Social Cost,” Journal of Law and Economics 3 (i960), 1—44, and Guido Calabresi and
A. Douglas Melamed, “Property Rules, Liability Rules, and Inalienability: One View of the
Cathedral,” Harvard Law Review 85 (1972), 1089—1128.
18.I use the term regulation in a sense somewhat different from that used in discussions
of public regulation of private industries. For a clear example of this usage see George
Stigler, The Citizen and the State: Essays on Regulation (Chicago: University of Chicago Press,
1975)-
19. Incentive systems can also be used to raise or disburse revenues. Their primary
purpose, however, is to structure the behavior of identifiable groups of actors.
n
International Regimes in Theory
society than of the more centralized systems that are common at the
national level. Yet international regimes accompanied by explicit orga¬
nizations can and sometimes do employ these devices. The International
Monetary Fund, for example, has promulgated extensive regulations
pertaining to the drawing rights of individual members, and the pro¬
posed International Seabed Authority would be able to regulate produc¬
tion of manganese nodules to implement more general rules concerning
such matters as the impact of deep-seabed mining on the world nickel
market.20
20. See, for example, Robert Z. Aliber, The International Money Game (New York: Basic
Books, 1976).
21. For a general analysis of social choice see A. K. Sen, Collective Choice and Social
Welfare (San Francisco: W. H. Freeman, 1970).
22. Problems of social choice pertaining to the selection and reform of international
regimes per se are discussed in chapters 4 and 9 below.
International Regimes
23. The classic study, which focuses on voting systems, is Kenneth Arrow, Social Choice
and Individual Values, 2d ed. (New York: Wiley, 1963).
24. Oran R. Young, “Anarchy and Social Choice: Reflections on the International
Polity,” World Politics 30 (1978), 241—263.
19
International Regimes in Theory
Implementation
25. That is, reality seldom approximates the condition of “perfect compliance” dis¬
cussed in Rawls, A Theory of Justice, 351.
26. For a similar observation about institutional arrangements at the domestic level see
A. Myrick Freeman, “Environmental Management as a Regulatory Process,” Resources
for the Future Discussion Paper D-4, (Washington, D.C., January 1977).
27. For an intriguing empirical example see Abram Chayes, “An Enquiry into the
Workings of Arms Control Agreements,” Harvard Law Review 85 (1975), 905-969.
20
International Regimes
Clarifying Observations
28. Oran R. Young, Compliance and. Public Authority: A Theory with International Applica¬
tions (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1979), especially chaps. 4 and 5.
29. For empirical examples consult Lucy Mair, Primitive Government (Bloomington:
Indiana University Press, 1977), especially chap. 1.
30. Ronald S. Tauber, “The Enforcement of IATA Agreements,” Harvard International
Law Journal 10 (1969), 1—33.
31. International regimes, like other social institutions, will ordinarily exhibit the at¬
tributes of collective goods (that is, nonexcludability and jointness of supply) to a relatively
high degree. For a cla'ssic account of the problems of supplying collective goods see
Mancur Olson, Jr., The Logic of Collective Action (Cambridge: Harvard University Press,
i965)-
32. For a variety of examples see William T. Burke, Richard Legatski, and William W.
Woodhead, National and International Law Enforcement in the Ocean (Seattle: University of
Washington Press, 1975).
21
International Regimes in Theory
cases can simply be treated as null regimes. The arrangements for high-
seas fishing prevailing prior to World War II, for instance, might be
described as a regime based on unrestricted common property and the
procedure known as the “law of capture,” rather than as a situation
lacking any operative regime.33 But this line of reasoning is seriously
flawed. Some activities arise de novo in the absence of prior experience
(for example, international satellite broadcasting or deep-seabed min¬
ing). In such cases, we would have to develop some fiction about latent
or tacit regimes to avoid the conclusion that there are situations in which
no regime is present. Further, existing regimes sometimes break down,
leaving a confused and inchoate situation (for example, international
trade and finance in the aftermath of the Great Depression and World
War II).34 Here, too, the concept would have to be stretched excessively
to assert the continued existence of a regime. What is more, avoiding the
temptation to assume the presence of some regime in every specifiable
activity will facilitate later discussions of the origins of regimes and of
regime transformation.
In analyzing international regimes, there is also a tendency to focus on
highly coherent and internally consistent constructs. Yet real-world re¬
gimes are often unsystematic and ambiguous, incorporating elements
derived from several analytic constructs or ideal types. This is sometimes
the result of misunderstandings on the part of those who make decisions
about the creation of regimes. Much of the ambiguity, however, arises
from two other factors. The development of an international regime
frequently involves intense bargaining that leads to critical compromises
among the interested parties. The hard bargaining that characterized
the hammering out of a regime to govern deep-seabed mining illustrates
this phenomenon. Additionally, international regimes generally evolve
and change over time in response to various economic and political
pressures. This is true even of regimes formulated initially in some
comprehensive constitutional contract. With the passage of time, re¬
gimes generally acquire new features and become less consistent inter¬
nally. The point of these remarks is neither to criticize existing regimes
nor to argue that ideal types are unimportant in examinations of the
development of international institutions. But a failure to bear in mind
the distinction between ideal types and reality is bound to lead to confu¬
sion.35
33. Francis T. Christy and Anthony Scott, The Common Wealth in Ocean Fisheries (Bal¬
timore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1965).
34. Charles P. Kindleberger, The World in Depression, 1929-1939 (Berkeley: University
of California Press, 1973).
35. On the relationship between ideal types and reality, with special reference to the
22
International Regimes
Regimes in Operation
Varieties of Regimes
theory of games, see Anatol Rapoport, Two-Person Game Theory (Ann Arbor: University of
Michigan Press, 1966), 186-214.
36. For a succinct and lucid account of such conditions see Robert Haveman, The
Economics of the Public Sector (New York: Wiley, 1976), 22—27.
23
International Regimes in Theory
its rights and rules. At one extreme is the case of unlimited laissez-faire,
in which actors are completely free to do as they please without even the
constraints of a system of property or use rights.37 At the other extreme
are arrangements featuring central planning and pervasive rules gov¬
erning the actions of individual members. Between these extremes lies a
wide range of mixed cases that are differentiable in terms of the extent
to which they include rights and rules restricting the autonomy of
individual members. Though international regimes tend to be less re¬
strictive than institutional arrangements in domestic society, they rarely
approximate the extreme of unlimited laissez-faire.
Some writers have fallen into the habit of equating regimes with the
agreements in terms of which the regimes are often expressed or cod¬
ified.38 In practice, however, international regimes vary greatly in the
extent to which they are expressed in formal agreements, treaties, or
conventions. The current regime for Antarctica is formalized to a far
greater degree than the neutralization arrangements for Switzerland.
As in domestic society, moreover, it is common for informal understand¬
ings to arise within the framework established by the formal structure of
an international regime. Such understandings may serve either to pro¬
vide interpretations of ambiguous aspects of the formal arrangements
(for example, the notion of optimum yield in conjunction with marine
fisheries) or to supplement formal arrangements by dealing with issues
they fail to cover (for example, the treatment of nuclear technology
under the terms of the partial nuclear test-ban regime). Though it may
be helpful, formalization is clearly not a necessary condition for the
effective operation of international regimes.39 There are informal re¬
gimes that have been generally successful, and there are formal arrange¬
ments that have produced unimpressive results (for example, several of
the commodity agreements).40
Regimes are directed to the extent that they exert pressure on their
members to act in conformity with some clear-cut social or collective
37. As an extreme type, this category is empirically empty. But a regime for some
natural resource with no private property rights, no liability rules, and allocation based on
the principle known as the “law of capture” would approach the extreme case.
38. See, for example, Arthur A. Stein, “Coordination and Collaboration: Regimes in an
Anarchic World,” 115—140 in Krasner, International Regimes.
39- As well, formalization is not a sufficient condition for the effective operation of
international regimes. In this connection, note also that any definitional convention that
equates regimes with the existence of formalized agreements cuts off efforts to analyze
relationships betwen institutional arrangements and the formalization of such arrange¬
ments in treaties or conventions.
40. United Nations, International Compensation for Fluctuations in Commodity Trade (New
York; 1961), and Zacher, “T rade Gaps.”
24
International Regimes
Organizations
41. P. A. Larkin, “An Epitaph for the Concept of Maximum Sustained Yield," Transac¬
tions of the American Fisheries Society 106 (1977), 1 — 11.
42. On economic approaches to such trade-offs see Richard Zeckhauser and Elmer
Shaefer, “Public Policy and Normative Economic Theory,” 27-101 in Raymond A. Bauer
and Kenneth J. Gergen, eds., The Study of Policy Formation (New York: Free Press, 1968).
43. Mair, Primitive Government.
25
International Regimes in Theory
44. See Haveman, Economics of the Public Sector, 21, for a description of markets in
precisely these terms.
45- See Richard A. lalk and Richard Barnet, eds.. Security in Disarmament (Princeton:
Princeton University Press, 1965).
46. Simon Lyster, International Wildlife Law (Cambridge: Grotius Publications, 1985),
chap. 1 2.
26
International Regimes
Policy Instruments
47. See, for example, Brown et al., Regimes for the Ocean, and Michael Hardy, “The
Implications of Alternative Solutions for Regulating the Exploitation of Seabed Minerals,”
International Organization 31 (1977), 313—342.
27
International Regimes in Theory
opening and closing of harvest areas are standard issues involving policy
instruments. Adjustments of exchange rates or the issuance of broadcast
licenses are common policy instruments in other regimes.48
At the international level, a key consideration concerns the extent to
which the use of policy instruments requires the existence of organiza¬
tions. It is possible, for example, to redefine the contents of collections of
rights and rules at occasional assemblies of the members of a regime; it
may even be possible to do so as a result of unilateral actions on the part
of some members of a regime to which others subsequently conform on
a de facto basis. Policy instruments of this sort have an obvious appeal in
highly decentralized settings like international society. This appeal may
account for the current tendency to respond to problems relating to
international maritime regimes by redrawing jurisdictional boundaries
(that is, shifting areas or activities from the domain of international
common property toward the domain of national public property)
rather than by agreeing to well-defined rules for the use of common
property at the international level.49 States can pursue jurisdictional
changes unilaterally and without turning to the forums provided by
international organizations. The administration of use rules for com¬
mon-property resources, by contrast, is apt to require the establishment
of organizations, though the results may be more equitable than those
arising from shifts in jurisdictional boundaries.50
Nonetheless, policy instruments suitable for use by organizations are
by no means absent from the realm of international regimes. The Inter¬
national Whaling Commission has the authority to adjust annual harvest
quotas for individual species of great whales. The International Mone¬
tary Fund can lay down specific conditions in granting loans to countries
experiencing balance-of-payments problems. The International Coffee
Agreement allows for the allocation of export shares among its mem¬
bers. And the proposed International Seabed Authority would be able to
make use of a relatively complex system of licenses to regulate the
production of manganese nodules from the deep seabed. The ability of
these organizations to operate autonomously in using such instruments
48. For further discussion see Giandomenico Majone, “Choice among Policy Instru¬
ments for Pollution Control,” Policy Analysis 2 (1976), 589—613.
49. Changes in regimes for marine fisheries arising from unilateral extensions of juris¬
diction on the part of coastal states exemplify this prospect. In the case of the United
States, the transition was accomplished through the passage of the Fishery Conservation
and Management Act of 1976. For further discussion see Oran R. Young, “The Political
Economy of Fish: The Fishery Conservation and Management Act of 1976,” Ocean De¬
velopment and International Law 10 (1982), 199—273.
50. For a case in point see the discussion of the regime for deep-seabed mining in
chapter 5 below.
28
International Regimes
Conclusion
1. Institutional character. What are the principal rights, rules, and social choice
procedures of the regime? How do they structure the behavior of individ¬
ual actors to produce a stream of collective outcomes?
2. Jurisdictional boundaries. What is the coverage of the regime in terms of
functional scope, areal domain, and membership? Is this coverage appro¬
priate under the prevailing conditions?
3. Conditions for operation. What conditions are necessary for the regime to
work at all? Under what conditions will the operation of the regime yield
particularly desirable results (for example, economic efficiency, distribu¬
tive justice, ecological balance)?
4. Consequences of operation. What sorts of outcomes (either individual or col¬
lective) can the regime be expected to produce? What are the appropriate
criteria for evaluating these outcomes?
5. Regime dynamics. How did the regime come into existence, and what is the
51. Bart S. Fisher, “Enforcing Export Quota Agreements: The Case of Coffee,” Har¬
vard International Law Journal 12 (1971), 401—435.
52. It is not necessary to subscribe to Marxian precepts to realize that domestic as well as
international regimes are sometimes influenced greatly by pressures from actors who are,
in principle, subject to regulation under the terms of these regimes. This is, in fact, the
central insight of the “capture” theory of regulation.
29
International Regimes in Theory
3<>
Chapter Two
4. Duncan Black, The Theory of Committees and Elections (Cambridge: Cambridge Uni¬
versity Press, 1958), and Douglas W. Rae, The Political Consequences of Electoral Laws (New
Haven: Yale University Press, 1971).
5. Robert Haveman and Kenyon A. Knopf, The Market System, 3d ed. (Santa Barbara:
Wiley, 1978).
6. A. Irving Hallowell, “ The Nature and Function of Property as a Social Institution,”
journal of Legal and Political Sociology 1 (1943), 115—138.
7- Note that this tells us nothing about the degree to which the consequences that
inst itutions produce are just, fair, or otherwise desirable.
52
Patterns of International Cooperation
8. Hedley Bull, The Anarchical Society: A Study of Order in World Politics (New York:
Columbia University Press, 1977). For an account of the operation of the states system
with respect to natural resources see Richard B. Bilder, “International Law and Natural
Resources Policies,” Natural Resources Journal 20 (1980), 451-486.
9. For an institutional perspective on the public order of the oceans consult Myres S.
McDougal and William T. Burke, The Public Order of the Oceans (New Haven: Yale Univer¬
sity Press, 1962).
10. Robert O. Keohane and Joseph S. Nye, Power and Interdependence: World Politics in
Transition (Boston: Little, Brown, 1977).
11. Hedley Bull, “War and International Order,” in Alan James, ed., The Bases of
International Order (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1973), 116—132; Quincy Wright, A
Study of War (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1942); and Michael Howard, War in
European History (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1976).
12. For a more general account of the role of organizations in international society see
Harold K. Jacobson, Networks of Interdependence: International Organizations and the Global
Political System (New York: Knopf, 1979).
35
International Regimes in Theory
The regime for the Svalbard Archipelago was established under the
terms of the treaty of 9 February 1920 relating to Spitsbergen.13 The
archipelago is a collection of islands located some 600 miles northwest of
the north coast of Norway and covering 62,400 square kilometers (about
the size of Belgium and the Netherlands combined). The treaty, which
now has forty signatories including both the United States and the
Soviet Union, originated in the larger settlement of issues at the end of
World War I. In essence, the regime articulated in the treaty of 1920,
which entered into force in 1925, couples a recognition of Norwegian
sovereignty over the archipelago with a series of commitments on the
part of Norway to respect all previously established rights in the area, to
allow nationals of all the signatories equal access to exploit the natural
resources of the archipelago, and to maintain the archipelago in a
demilitarized state. Legally, therefore, the Svalbard Archipelago is a
part of Norway. But the Norwegian government does not have the
authority to exclude others from using its resources including both
minerals and fish, and Norway has an international obligation to pre¬
vent the use of it for warlike purposes.
The Spitsbergen treaty does not establish a specialized organization to
administer the Svalbard regime. Rather, the government of Norway
handles all administrative functions for the area. As 0streng says,
“Svalbard is administered by a Governor, who combines the functions of
district judge and revenue officer.”14 Similarly, “the Commissioner of
Mines is responsible for ensuring the observance of the Mining Code,
which applies to all nationalities in Svalbard.”15 There have been dis¬
agreements from time to time regarding the application of Norwegian
regulations to the Russian mining operations located at Barentsburg
and Pyramiden as well as the rules that would govern efforts to extract
natural resources from the continental shelves surrounding Svalbard.
But no one has proposed the creation of a separate organization for the
administration of the regime.
As a second example, consider the regime for renewable resources
set forth in the provisions of the convention of 11 September 1980 on
the Conservation of Antarctic Marine Living Resources (the Southern
Ocean convention).16 This convention, intended to complement the
Antarctic Treaty of 1959, now includes sixteen Contracting Parties and
13. For a general account see Willy 0streng, Politics in High Latitudes: The Svalbard
Archipelago (London: C. Hurst, 1977).
14. Ibid., 3.
15. Ibid.
16. James N. Barnes, “The Emerging Antarctic Living Resources Convention,” Proceed¬
ings of the American Society of International Law, 1979, 272—292.
34
Patterns of International Cooperation
17. For relevant background see the papers in parts 3, 4, and 5 of Bernard H. Oxman,
David D. Caron, and Charles L. O. Buderi, eds., Law of the Sea: U.S. Policy Dilemma (San
Francisco: ICS Press, 1983).
35
International Regimes in Theory
36
Patterns of International Cooperation
Organization
Yes No
Civil International
Yes
Society Anarchy
Regime
Freestanding International
No
Organization State of Nature
International Anarchy
18. Daniel Guerin, Anarchism (New York: Monthly Review Press, 1970).
19. Robert Nozick, Anarchy, State, and Utopia (New York: Basic Books, 1974).
37
International Regimes in Theory
20. On the distinction between negative freedom or “freedom from” and positive
freedom or “freedom to,” see Isaiah Berlin, Four Essays on Liberty (Oxford: Oxford Univer¬
sity Press, 1969).
21. See Charles Wolf, Jr., “A Theory of Nonmarket Failure: Framework for Implemen¬
tation AnalysisJournal of Law and Economics 22 (1979), 107—139.
22. Bull, The Anarchical Society.
23. For a well-known example see Grenville Clark and Louis B. Sohn, World Peace
through World lmu) (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1958).
Patterns of International Cooperation
24. For a thoughtful account of the supply of international public goods in the absence
of central organizations see Charles P. Kindleberger, “International Public Goods without
International Government,” American Economic Review 76 (1986), 1 — 13.
25. For a discussion of zonal arrangements with particular reference to natural re¬
sources see Oran R. Young, Resource Management at the International Level (London and
New York: Pinter and Nichols, 1977), especially chap. 5.
26. For an account that looks upon the enclosure movement with favor see Ross D.
Eckert, The Enclosure of Ocean Resources (Stanford: Hoover Institution Press, 1979).
27. On the events culminating in the advent of EEZs consult Ann L. Hollick, U.S.
Foreign Policy and the Law of the Sea (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1981).
39
International Regimes in Theory
28. For relevant background see Charles Lipson, “The Transformation of Trade: The
Sources and Effects of Regime Change,” in Krasner, International Regimes, 233—271.
29. Eckert, Enclosure of Ocean Resources, chap. 8.
30. For further discussion of such ideas consult Francis T. Christy, Jr., “Property Rights
in the World Ocean,” Natural Resources Journal 15 (1975), 695-712, and Seyom Brown,
Nina W. Cornell, Larry L. Fabian, and Edith Brown Weiss, Regimes for the Ocean, Outer
Space, and Weather (Washington, D.C.: Brookings, 1977).
31. Caldwell, International Environmental Policy, chap. 5.
40
Patterns of International Cooperation
32. Philip W. Quigg, A Pole Apart: The Emerging Issue of Antarctica (New York: McGraw-
Hill, 1983).
33. Simon Lyster, International Wildlife Law (Cambridge: Grotius Publications), chaps.
12 and 13.
34. Caldwell, International Environmental Policy, 189—192.
41
International Regimes in Theory
35. For a more general discussion of principles of equitable distribution of the world's
wealth and natural resources see Oscar Schachter, Sharing the World’s Resources (New York:
Columbia University Press, 1977).
36. The Red Data Book, published and periodically updated by the IUCN, has acquired
considerable influence in international efforts to protect endangered species.
37. Abram Chayes, “An Enquiry into the Workings of Arms Control Agreements,”
Harvard Law Review 85 (1972), 905—969.
42
Patterns of International Cooperation
43
International Regimes in Theory
44
Patterns of International Cooperation
Civil Society
40. For a range of perspectives on such matters consult Per Magnus Wijkman, “Manag¬
ing the Global Commons,” International Organization 36 (1982), 511—536; Marvin S. So-
roos, “The Commons in the Sky: The Radio Spectrum and Geosynchronous Orbit as
Issues in Global Policy,” International Organization 36 (1982), 665—677; and the special
issue on “Managing International Commons,” ofJournal of International Affairs 31 (Spring-
Summer 1977).
45
International Regimes in Theory
46
Patterns of International Cooperation
47
International Regimes in Theory
45. For a characteristic formulation see Robert H. Haveman, The Economics of the Public
Sector, 2d ed. (Santa Barbara: Wiley, 1976), especially pt. 2.
46. Wolf, “A Theory of Nonmarket Failure.” For an intriguing argument that focuses
on the growing rigidities of aging organizations see Mancur Olson, Jr., The Rise and Decline
of Nations (New Haven: Yale University Press, 1982).
47. See also the elegant argument presented in Albert Hirschman, Shifting Involvements:
Private Interest and Public Action (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1982).
48. On the concept of hegemony consult Robert O. Keohane, After Hegemony: Discord
and Collaboration in the World Political Economy (Princeton: Princeton University Press,
1984), chap. 3. For an account that explicitly adopts the perspective of the hegemon see
4$
Patterns of International Cooperation
regimes offers some support for this point of view.49 A major theme of
colonial history, after all, is the preference of imperial powers for net¬
works of bilateral relations in which individual colonies interact on a
superordinate/subordinate basis with imperial powers but have little
opportunity to interact with each other. The essential attraction of such
arrangements is that they facilitate the efforts of imperial powers to
maintain control by isolating colonial leaders and minimizing oppor¬
tunities for colonies to band together in opposition to the policies of
imperial states. Naturally enough, such networks of bilateral relations
do not generate significant roles for central organizations. Yet it is worth
noting that even colonial regimes sometimes give rise to central organi¬
zations. Perhaps the classic example, though certainly not the only case
in point, is the British Commonwealth of Nations.50 The Common¬
wealth evolved after World War I as a means of holding together a
colonial regime in the face of progressive erosion in the physical and
moral dominance of Great Britain as an imperial state. Operating orga¬
nizationally through the Commonwealth Secretariat, it served to co-opt
numerous leaders of individual colonies into the colonial order by giving
them stakes in the perpetuation of the system. The struggles of many
Indian leaders in the 1940s over participation in the Commonwealth as
well as the continuing ties of states like Canada and New Zealand to the
Commonwealth attest to the remarkable effectiveness of this arrange¬
ment and the organization to which it gave rise.
When we turn to other sorts of imposed regimes, the attractions of
central organizations loom even larger. In some cases, organizations
appeal to hegemons seeking to distract attention from their dominant
positions and to engender widespread feelings of legitimacy regarding
the institutional arrangements they create. The IMF originated in this
sort of environment. The United States (or perhaps the United States in
consort with Great Britain) dominated the process of creating the post¬
war international monetary regime.51 Yet the United States chose to
deemphasize its hegemonic role in this context, a fact that made the
creation of an organization like the IMF appealing. An interesting varia¬
tion on this theme involves the establishment in 1948 of the Organiza-
Arthur A. Stein, “The Hegemon’s Dilemma: Great Britain, the United States, and the
International Economic Order,” International Organization 38 (1984), 355—386.
49. For an informative account of the imperial mentality see A. P. Thornton, The
Imperial Idea and Its Enemies (Garden City: Doubleday, 1968).
50. Hedley Bull, “What is the Commonwealth?” in International Political Communities
(Garden City: Doubleday, 1966), 457-468.
51. Richard N. Gardner, Sterling-Dollar Diplomacy in Current Perspective (New York:
Columbia University Press, 1980).
49
International Regimes in Theory
52. Michael Marrese, “CMEA: Effective but Cumbersome Political Economy,” Intema-
tional Organization 40 (1986), 287-327.
53- Andrzej Korbonski, “COMECON: The Evolution of COMECON,” in International
Political Communities, 351—403.
54. See also Mancur Olson, Jr., and Richard Zeckhauser, “An Economic Theory of
Alliances,’’ Review of Economics and Statistics 48 (ig66), 266—279.
Patterns of International Cooperation
55. Robert Axelrod, The Evolution of Cooperation (New York: Basic Books, 1984), and
Friedrich A. Hayek, The Political Order of a Free People, vol. 3 of Law, Legislation, and Liberty
(Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1979).
56. Ibid., 3.
57. For a rich descriptive account of this process in the case of the North Atlantic
fisheries see William Warner, Distant Water (Boston: Little, Brown, 1983).
58. Charles B. Heck, “Collective Arrangements for Managing Ocean Fisheries,” Inter¬
national Organization 29 (1975), 711—743.
59. Vincent A. Mahler, “The Political Economy of North-South Commodity Bargain¬
ing: The Case of the International Sugar Agreement,” International Organization 38 (1984),
International Regimes in Theory
Freestanding Organizations
7°9~73G Robert H. Bates and Da-Hsiang Donald Lien, “On the Operations of the
International Coffee Agreement,” International Organization 39 (1985), 553—559; and
Mark W. Zacher, “Trade Gaps, Analytical Gaps: Regime Analysis and International Com¬
modity I rade Regulation,” International Organization 41 (1987), 173—202.
52
Patterns of International Cooperation
60. On the role of SCAR see James H. Zumberge, “The Antarctic Treaty as a Scientific
Mechanism: The Scientific Committee on Antarctic Research and the Antarctic Treaty
System,” in Polar Research Board, Antarctic Treaty System: An Assessment (Washington, D.C.:
National Academy Press, 1986), 153—168.
53
International Regimes in Theory
instance, has become a major forum for those desiring to promote the
package of alterations in the prevailing international economic order
that is known collectively as the new international economic order. More
concretely, the United Nations Environment Programme, which was
created in the wake of the 1982 Stockholm Conference on the Human
Environment but which is not actually linked to an existing regime, has
played a remarkably effective role in promoting the development of
geographically defined regimes that focus on pollution control under
the terms of its Regional Seas Programme61 as well as in facilitating the
negotiation of a more general regime to protect stratospheric ozone.
The International Maritime Organization has provided an important
forum for the development of an evolving regime that deals with the
pollution of the sea from ships. This regime rests on an interlocking set
of international conventions that culminated in the provisions of the
1978 International Convention on the Prevention of Pollution from
Ships.62 Similar observations are in order regarding the role of the
International Atomic Energy Agency in encouraging the negotiation of
an international regime to cope with the problems associated with radi¬
oactive fallout. The Antarctic and Southern Ocean Coalition, a non¬
governmental organization, has succeeded in playing a part both in
protecting the existing regime for Antarctica and in devising supple¬
mental regimes for marine living resources and minerals in the Antarc¬
tic region. Though it is true that regimes emerge spontaneously under
some conditions, conscious efforts to create institutional arrangements
are frequently protracted and difficult. As a result, freestanding organi¬
zations often become not only sources of innovative ideas for those
negotiating regimes but also pressure groups and even negotiating
forums in the lengthy processes involved in the creation of negotiated
regimes. In such cases, freestanding organizations constitute an advance
guard that endeavors to move international society toward the develop¬
ment of a richer texture of institutional arrangements.63
54
Patterns of International Cooperation
regimes they were associated with to become, in effect, freestanding organizations. Some
of the regional fisheries organizations appear to be heading in this direction.
64. Bull, The Anarchical Society.
65. See the collection of essays on polar politics published in International Journal 39
(Autumn 1984).
66. Edith Brown Weiss, “International Responses to Weather Modification,” Interna¬
tional Organization 29 (1975), 805—826, and Brown et al., Regimes for the Ocean.
55
International Regimes in Theory
67. For an account stressing the significance of this perspective see Kratochwil and
Ruggie, “International Organization.”
68. See also the observations in Jan Tinbergen, “Alternative Forms of International
Cooperation: Comparing Their Efficiency,” International Social Science Journal 30 (1978).
223-237.
56
Patterns of International Cooperation
right. Rather, they are more or less well suited to the institutional
arrangements with which they are associated. It follows that policy¬
makers should design organizations to maximize their effectiveness and
minimize their negative by-products in connection with the provisions
of specific institutions or regimes.
4. Policymakers should avoid falling prey to intellectual fashions in thinking
about the linkages between institutions and organizations. Throughout much
of the postwar period, observers treated international anarchy as in¬
ferior to civil society. Today, we are witnessing a marked increase of
emphasis on nonmarket failures leading to minimalist views regarding
roles for organizations at the international level, not to mention govern¬
ments at the domestic level. Yet neither of these intellectual fashions
offers a trustworthy guide for policymakers concerned with institutional
design. There is no substitute for starting with a systematic assessment of
the relative merits of alternative institutional arrangements and pro¬
ceeding to devise organizations (if any) to meet the requirements of the
specific institutional arrangements selected.
57
Chapter Three
1. I his perspective is exemplified with particular clarity in the public choice literature.
See, for example, James M. Buchanan and Gordon Tullock, The Calculus of Consent (Ann
Arbor: University of Michigan Press, 1962). And for an account that probes the underpin¬
nings of this perspective consult Geoffrey Brennan and James N. Buchanan, The Reason of
Rules: Constitutional Political Economy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985).
2. Susan Strange, "Cave! hie dragones: A Critique of Regime Analysis,” in Stephen I).
Krasner, ed.. International Regimes (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1983), 337—354.
The Power of Institutions
3. For an account that stresses these structural considerations see Kenneth N. Waltz,
Theory of International Politics (Reading: Addison-Wesley, 1979).
4. Hedley Bull, The Anarchical Society (New York: Columbia University Press, 1977).
5. For a sophisticated discussion see Anthony D’Amato, “What ‘Counts’ as Law?” in
Nicholas Greenwood Onuf, ed., Lawmaking in the Global Community (Durham: Carolina
Academic Press, 1982), 83-107.
6. Kenneth N. Waltz, “Reflections on ‘Theory of International Politics’: A Response to
My Critics,” in Robert O. Keohane, ed., Neorealism and Its Critics (New York: Columbia
University Press, 1986), 322-345.
7. Emile Durkheim, The Division of Labor in Society (New York: Free Press, 1983/1964).
8. Even so, some observers have taken to stressing the rising level of interdependence
at the international level. See, for example, Robert O. Keohane and Joseph S. Nye, Power
and Interdependence: World Politics in Transition (Boston: Little, Brown, 1977).
59
International Regimes in Theory
60
The Power of Institutions
Keohane, After Hegemony: Cooperation and Discord in the World Political Economy (Princeton:
Princeton University Press, 1984).
15. Inis L. Claude, Jr., Power and International Relations (New York: Random House,
1962).
61
International Regimes in Theory
19. See also Keohane and Nye, Power and Interdependence, especially pt. 2.
62
The Power of Institutions
63
International Regimes in Theory
Antarctic Treaty of 1959 (that is, the Antarctic club) certainly played a
leadership role in the creation of the current international regime for
Antarctica.25 In much the same way, the United States and a few other
like-minded members of international society undoubtedly took the lead
in devising the regime governing international trade in endangered
species, which is now formalized in the 1973 Convention on Interna¬
tional Trade in Endangered Species of Fauna and Flora.26
Yet it is misleading to direct attention primarily to these exceptional
situations. In the typical case, international institutions are extremely
difficult to get rid of, or even to adjust in a conscious fashion to changing
circumstances. Interestingly, existing regimes or institutional arrange¬
ments often prove highly resistant even to assaults spearheaded by one
or more of the great powers. Common-property regimes for renewable
resources, for example, are remarkably difficult to change at the inter¬
national level. Even the enclosure movement, which has brought many
resources within the exclusive management authority of coastal states,
has done little to eliminate the common-property character of regimes
for marine fisheries and other renewable resources of marine regions.27
The obvious importance, under contemporary conditions, of moving
toward regimes based on an ecosystems approach or at least a multi¬
species approach at the international level has so far made little headway
against the persistent tendency to develop separate regimes for individ¬
ual species, such as polar bears, fur seals, or halibut.28 The efforts of
those endeavoring to make significant changes in the existing interna¬
tional economic order, such as the various reforms often lumped to¬
gether under the general rubric of a new international economic order,
have met with remarkable resistance despite the fact that the reform
movement probably includes a majority of the members of international
society.29 To be more specific, the Soviet Union failed completely in its
attempt to promote major changes in the international regime govern¬
ing the Svalbard Archipelago during the 1940s.30 Similarly, the efforts
of a large coalition of states to reform the prevailing international re-
25. Philip W. Quigg, A Pole Apart (New York: McGraw Hill, 1983).
26. Lynton Keith Caldwell, International Environmental Policy (Durham: Duke Univer¬
sity Press, 1984), especially 189-192, and Simon Lyster, International Wildlife Law (Cam¬
bridge: Grotius Publications, 1985), chap. 12.
27. Oran R. Young, “The Political Economy of Fish: The Fishery Conservation and
Management Act of 1976,” Ocean Development and International Law 10 (1982), 199—273.
28. For an account of efforts to promote an ecosystems approach see Caldwell. Interna¬
tional Environmental Policy, chaps. 7 and 8.
29. Marvin S. Soroos, Beyond Sovereignty: The Challenge of Global Policy (Columbia: Uni¬
versity of South Carolina Press, 1986), chap. 6.
30. Willy Ostreng, Politics at High Latitudes (London: C. Hurst, 1977), especially chap. 6.
64
The Power of Institutions
gime for Antarctica have met with so much opposition from the mem¬
bers of the Antarctic club that some of the reformers (for example,
India) have decided to join the club rather than to continue pushing for
changes from the outside.31
Perhaps even more striking is the resistance of many international in¬
stitutions to change even when the prevailing arrangements are not only
inefficient but also exceedingly difficult to justify on ethical grounds.
The international food regime, which is based on a system of distribution
through world markets (in other words, of withholding food from those
who lack the money to pay for it), has played a major role in bringing
about the current situation in which millions of people are malnour¬
ished, in some cases to the point of starvation, despite the fact that global
food production is entirely adequate to feed all the world’s people. And
no serious prospects for reforming this regime are in sight at the present
time.32 While some efforts are now being made to protect living re¬
sources in the face of a rising tide of extinctions of species, those who
have tried can attest to the difficulties encountered in efforts to restruc¬
ture institutional arrangements in this area, particularly when it comes to
arrangements for noncommercial species such as oceanic birds, por¬
poises, or sea lions.33 Much the same can be said of the relatively un¬
restricted common-property regimes currently in place for the inter¬
national atmospheric commons. While evidence mounts concerning
threats to the world’s climate system associated with the buildup of
carbon dioxide in the atmosphere or the depletion of ozone in the
stratosphere, efforts to devise new institutional arrangements at the
international level to cope with these problems are still in their infancy.34
There are several clear-cut reasons why international institutions, like
domestic institutions, are generally difficult to get rid of or to replace
with more appropriate alternatives. Above all, efforts to reform institu¬
tional arrangements on an intentional or planned basis almost always
entail processes of collective choice. The image of a dominant state or a
hegemon playing the role of lawgiver is severely distorted. Even under
the extraordinary conditions that prevailed in the aftermath of World
31. Deborah Shapley, The Seventh Continent: Antarctica in a Resource Age (Washington,
D.C.: Resources for the Future, 1986).
32. See also Raymond F. Hopkins and Donald J. Puchala, “Perspectives on the Interna¬
tional Relations of Food,” International Organization 32 (1978), 581—616.
33. On the problem of disappearing species see Norman Myers, The Sinking Ark: A New
Look at the Problem of Disappearing Species (New York: Pergamon, 1979).
34. The ozone agreement concluded in Montreal in September 1987 is certainly a
significant step. Already, however, a consensus is emerging on the proposition that this
agreement does not go far enough toward controlling the production and emission of
chlorofluorocarbons.
65
International Regimes in Theory
War II, the United States had to negotiate with several other major
players to achieve consensus on the monetary regime set forth in the
Bretton Woods agreement. Likewise, the United States found itself
forced to make substantial concessions regarding the international-trade
regime after the collapse of arrangements laid out in the Havana Charter
and the failure to reach consensus on the proposed International Trade
Organization.35 Under more typical conditions, such as those prevailing
today, it is clear that regime formation almost invariably gives rise to
extremely complex processes of collective choice, which will often fail to
produce clear-cut agreement on new or revised institutional arrange¬
ments. Witness recent efforts to devise suitable institutional arrange¬
ments to govern deep-seabed mining, international broadcasting via
satellite, threats to the international climate system, or exploratory ac¬
tivities aimed at assessing the mineral potential of Antarctica.36
The fact that the development of international institutions typically
involves complex collective-choice processes has several important im¬
plications for any effort to understand the significance of institutions as
determinants of collective outcomes at the international level. In many
cases, existing arrangements have vigorous defenders who stand to lose
as a result of institutional change, even if the existing arrangements are
unattractive from the point of view of certain conceptions of the com¬
mon good. It is no cause for surprise, for example, to find the United
States staunchly supporting the existing economic order in many specific
areas, the members of the Antarctic club defending the current regime
for Antarctica, or countries where major polluting industries are based
resisting changes in international environmental regimes designed to
control the long-range transport problems associated with acid deposi¬
tion or Arctic haze.37 What is more, even in cases where all parties
acknowledge the inadequacy of existing institutional arrangements (for
example, international regimes designed to maintain biological diversity
by protecting endangered species), complications arising from collec¬
tive-choice processes can pose severe impediments to institutional re¬
form. In virtually every case, several distinct options are available to
those concerned with the replacement of existing institutional arrange¬
ments. And it is rare that the preferences of the relevant members of
international society fail to differ substantially with regard to these
options. The resultant processes of bargaining over the relative attrac-
66
The Power of Institutions
38. James K. Sebenius, “Negotiation Arithmetic: Adding and Subtracting Issues and
Parties,” International Organization 37 (1983), 281—316.
39. For an insightful development of this proposition see Friedrich A. Hayek, The
Political Order of a Free People, vol. 3 of Law, Legislation, and Liberty (Chicago: University of
Chicago Press, 1979).
40. Soroos, Beyond Sovereignty, especially chap. 3.
41. Caldwell, International Environmental Policy, and R. Michael M’Gonigle and Mark W.
Zacher, Pollution, Politics, and International Law (Berkeley: University of California Press,
1979)-
67
International Regimes in Theory
42. Ross D. Eckert, The Enclosure of Ocean Resources (Stanford: Hoover Institution Press.
*979)-
43. See the discussion of burden sharing in Mancur Olson, Jr., and Richard Zeckhauser,
“An Economic Theory of Alliances,” Review of Economics and Statistics 48 (1966), 266—279.
68
The Power of Institutions
69
International Regimes in Theory
i 950s and 1960s, have gradually come around to the conclusion that it is
expedient to join the club and conform to the principal rights and rules
of an array of prevailing international institutions.47
Under the circumstances, it seems entirely reasonable to treat institu¬
tional arrangements as important constraints on the behavior of individ¬
ual actors in international society, just as we do in thinking about domes¬
tic society. To be sure, institutions are not actors in their own right
(though the organizations created to administer institutions may some¬
times acquire the attributes of actors). Some analysts have jumped
quickly from this observation to the conclusion that institutions cannot
be significant determinants of collective outcomes in international so¬
ciety.48 But this is surely incorrect. It is not necessary to be an actor to
operate as a determinant of collective behavior at the international or
any other level. To think otherwise would require a wholesale revision of
our understanding of the role of markets, electoral systems, structures of
property rights, and so forth in domestic societies, not to mention our
understanding of the impact of systemic or structural factors at the
international level.49
47. On the case of the Soviet Union in the 1920s and 1930s see F. P. Walters, A History of
the League of Nations (London: Oxford LJniversity Press, i960), especially chap. 30.
48. James N. Rosenau, “Hegemons, Regimes, and Habit-driven Actors,” International
Organization 40 (1986), 849—894.
49. Waltz, “Reflections.”
70
The Power of Institutions
50. But note that some of those who think in contractarian terms assume perfect
compliance for purely analytic reasons. For a case in point see John Rawls, A Theory of
Justice (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1971).
51. Oran R. Young, Compliance and Public Authority: A Theory with International Applica¬
tions (Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1979), chap. 7.
52. It is worth noting, however, that the rights and rules of social institutions are not of
equal importance to the survival of specific institutional arrangements. That is, levels of
violation that we tolerate with respect to some rights and rules might well seem intolerable
with respect to others.
53. See also the discussion in Roger Fisher, Improving Compliance with International Law
(Charlottesville: University Press of Virginia, 1981).
54. Young, Compliance and Public Authority.
55. For an insightful discussion of the emergence of norms of cooperation see Robert
Axelrod, The Evolution of Cooperation (New York: Basic Books, 1984).
71
International Regimes in Theory
Decision Variables
56. Political ideology certainly plays a role in structuring thought in this realm. Specifi¬
cally, there is a definite link between conservatism and the tendency to stress enforcement
as a critical factor in compliance decisions.
57. See also the insights laid out in Michael Taylor, Anarchy and Cooperation (New York:
Wiley, 1976).
58. Olson and Zeckhauser, “An Economic Theory of Alliances.”
72
The Power of Institutions
59. Kenneth Dam, The GATT: Law and International Economic Organization (New York:
Midway Reprint, 1977).
60. See also Lance N. Antrim and James K. Sebenius, “Incentives for Ocean Mining
under the Convention,” in Oxman, Caron, and Buderi, Law of the Sea, 79—99.
61. Waltz, “Reflections.”
62. For a sophisticated account, which develops a helpful vocabulary for identifying
different types of retaliation, see Axelrod, Evolution of Cooperation.
63. The United States, for example, has cut the fishing quotas of Japan, Norway, and
the Soviet Union within the American Fishery Conservation Zone for this reason.
75
International Regimes in Theory
74
The Power of Institutions
66. See also the analysis of order in international society developed in Friedrich V.
Kratochwil, International Order and Foreign Policy (Boulder: Westview Press, 1978).
67. Robert O. Keohane, “Reciprocity in International Relations,” International Organiza¬
tion 40 (1986), 1-27.
68. For a seminal account consult Thomas C. Schelling, The Strategy of Conflict (Cam¬
bridge: Harvard University Press, i960).
69. Leigh S. Ratiner, “The Costs of American Rigidity,” in Oxman, Caron, and Buderi,
Law of the Sea, 27—42.
75
International Regimes in Theory
70. For a general account of the literature on conformity see C. A. Kiesler and Sara B.
Kiesler, Conformity (Reading: Addison-Wesley, iq6g).
76
The Power of Institutions
Collective-Choice Considerations
71. For a discussion emphasizing linkages between international regimes and the do¬
mestic politics of the members see Stephan Haggard and Beth A. Simmons, “Theories of
International RegimesInternational Organization 41 (1987), 491—517.
72. For a well-known account of bureaucratic politics consult Graham T. Allison, Es¬
sence of Decision (Boston: Little, Brown, 1971), especially chap. 5.
73. For the details of a variety of international regimes dealing with wildlife see Lyster,
International Wildlife Law.
74. For a seminal discussion of the analysis of governments as arenas for collective
decision making rather than as unitary actors see Anthony Downs, An Economic Theory of
Democracy (New York: Harper and Row, 1957), chap. 15.
77
International Regimes in Theory
75. Peter Haas, “Do Regimes Matter? A Study of Evolving Pollution Control Policies for
the Mediterranean Sea,” paper presented at the 1987 annual meetings of the Interna¬
tional Studies Association.
76. On the case of the Great Lakes see the essays in Alternatives 1 3 (August/September
1986), a special issue entitled “Saving the Great Lakes.” On CITES, consult Lvster.
International Wildlife Law, chap. 1 2.
77. On the sources of this situation, with special reference to the United States, see
Eckert, Enclosure of Ocean Resources, especially chap. 8, and James L. Malone, “Who Needs
the Sea Treaty?” Foreign Policy 54 (1984), 44—63.
78. for a general account of standard operating procedures consult Allison, Essence of
Decision, especially chap. 3.
7*
The Power of Institutions
have noted, agencies are ordinarily confronted with such a large volume
of issues that they cannot begin to deal with the actions expected of them
on a case-by-case basis. Accordingly, they must devise highly simplified
decision rules to avoid becoming overwhelmed by the volume of their
business. In fact, most agencies deal with the great majority of the issues
that come their way through the routine application of such decision
rules in the form of standard operating procedures. It follows that
agencies charged with handling national responses to the requirements
of international regimes are likely to comply with these requirements on
a routine basis to the extent that compliance acquires the status of a
standard operating procedure. There is a good deal of evidence to
suggest that this basis of compliance has come to play an important role
in ensuring high levels of compliance even in cases of highly politicized
international regimes such as those involving arms-control arrange¬
ments.79 It should come as no surprise, therefore, that compliance often
becomes almost entirely routinized in connection with institutional ar¬
rangements that are less sensitive in political terms, like the regime
governing the use of the electromagnetic spectrum or the regime deal¬
ing with marine living resources in the Antarctic region. Of course, this
basis of compliance only becomes more compelling when responsible
agencies come to rely on a metanorm or higher-order standard operat¬
ing procedure that calls on decision-makers to use specific standard
operating procedures routinely in handling their workload.80
What can we conclude from this discussion of the bases of compliance
in international society? Briefly, the absence of authorized enforcement
mechanisms does not justify the conclusion that the members of interna¬
tional society can simply ignore institutional dictates whenever they
seem inconvenient or troublesome. In fact, we can identify a number of
distinct bases of compliance at the international level, and there are
good reasons to expect these considerations to exert effective pressure
on most members of international society to comply with the dictates of
institutional arrangements most of the time. Without doubt, violations
of the rights and rules of international institutions can and will occur
from time to time. But there is nothing remarkable about this. The
occurrence of similar violations in domestic society does not cast doubt
on our assumption that institutional arrangements are significant deter¬
minants of collective outcomes at the domestic level. The fact that
79. See Abram Chayes, “An Enquiry into the Workings of Arms Control Agreements,”
Harvard Law Review 85 (1972), 905-969, and Fisher, Improving Compliance, chap. 7.
80. For a suggestive discussion of metanorms see Robert Axelrod, “An Evolutionary
Approach to Norms,” American Political Science Review 80 (1986), 1100—1102.
79
International Regimes in Theory
violations occur from time to time is not incompatible with the proposi¬
tion that the dictates of institutional arrangements operate as major
constraints on the behavior of individual actors in social systems. And
there is no evidence to suggest that compliance levels are, for the most
part, lower in international society than they are in domestic societies.
Conclusion
80
Chapter Four
i. See also A. Irving Hallowell, “The Nature and Function of Property as a Social
Institution,” Journal of Legal and Political Sociology 1 (1943), 115—138.
81
International Regimes in Theory
2. For a suggestive account of the nature and role of social conventions see Russell
Hardin, “The Emergence of Norms,” Ethics 90 (1980), 575-587. and Collective Action
(Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1982), chaps. 11-14.
3. This view has much in common with the philosophical tenets of legal positivism as
contrasted with natural law. See the well-known exchange between H. L. A. Hart. “Positiv¬
ism and the Separation of Law and Morals, Hamard Law Review 71 (1958), 593—629, and
Lon L. Fuller, “Positivism and Fidelity to Law: A Reply to Professor Hart,” Harvard Law
Review 71(1958), 630-671.
82
Regime Dynamics
83
International Regimes in Theory
Regime Formation
Developmental Sequences
6. See also Geoffrey Brennan and James M. Buchanan, The Reason of Rules: Constitu¬
tional Political Economy (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1985). And for an anal¬
ysis of strategies available to individual actors seeking to promote changes in prevailing
institutions consult Victor P. Goldberg, “Institutional Change and the Quasi-Invisible
Hand,” Journal of Law and Economics 17 (1974). 461-492.
7. See, among others, Hardin, Collective Action; Mancur Olson, Jr., The Logic of Collec-
84
Regime Dynamics
many men but . . . not the result of human design.”8 Such regimes are
distinguished by the facts that they do not involve conscious coordina¬
tion among participants, do not require explicit consent on the part of
subjects or prospective subjects, and are highly resistant to efforts at
social engineering. Though the terms “self-generating” and “spontane¬
ous” are attributable to Hayek, Lewis covers some of the same ground in
his study of social conventions, Schelling evidently has a similar phe¬
nomenon in mind in his discussion of interactive behavior, and Axelrod
points to analogous processes in the evolution of cooperation.9 In fact,
there are several realms in which the expectations of subjects regularly
converge to a remarkable degree in the absence of conscious design or
even consciousness. Natural markets are an important case in point well-
known to social scientists, and similar processes are at work in many
balance-of-power situations at the international level. Spontaneous ar¬
rangements relating to such things as language systems and social mores
are even more striking in this regard. As those who have tried can attest,
it is extraordinarily difficult to create an effective language by design.
Yet large groups of individuals are perfectly capable of converging on
relatively complex linguistic conventions and of using them proficiently
without high levels of consciousness.
The processes through which spontaneous arrangements arise are
not well-understood.10 Surely, the propositions of sociobiology are not
sufficient to provide a satisfactory account of the formation of institu¬
tional arrangements that take such diverse forms and change so rapidly.
And social psychology offers no comprehensive theoretical account of
interactive learning relevant to the emergence of social conventions.* 11
There are intriguing hints concerning such processes, however, in re¬
cent work on the convergence of expectations and the evolution of
cooperation. Thus, Schelling’s account of tacit bargaining has high¬
lighted the role of what he terms focal points or salient solutions in coordi¬
nating the behavior of interdependent actors in the absence of explicit
communication.12 Perhaps even more suggestive in this context is the
live Action (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1965); and Garrett Hardin and John
Baden, eds., Managing the Commons (San Francisco: W. H. Freeman, 1977).
8. Friedrich A. Hayek, Rules and Order, vol. 1 of Law, Legislation, and Liberty (Chicago:
University of Chicago Press, 1973), 37.
9. David K. Lewis, Convention: A Philosophical Study (Cambridge: Harvard University
Press, 1969); Thomas C. Schelling, Micromotives and Macrobehavior (New York: Norton,
1978); and Robert Axelrod, The Evolution of Cooperation (New York: Basic Books, 1984).
10. For some suggestive observations, however, see Hardin, Collective Action, chaps. 11 —
14.
11. But consider the research on the norm of reciprocity reviewed in Kenneth J.
Gergen, The Psychology of Behavior Exchange (Reading: Addison-Wesley, 1969).
12. Schelling, Strategy of Conflict, especially chap. 4.
85
International Regimes in Theory
13. Robert Axelrod, “An Evolutionary Approach to Norms,” American Political Science
Review 80 (1986), 1095-1111.
14. On learned behavior pertaining to institutional arrangements see also Ernst B.
Haas, “Words Can Hurt You; or, Who Said What to Whom about Regimes,” 23-59 *n
Stephen D. Krasner, ed., International Regimes (Ithaca: Cornell University Press, 1983).
15. Axelrod, “An Evolutionary Approach to Norms,” 1008—1009.
16. But note that such institutions may rely on effective, if informal, social pressures.
For a general discussion of social pressure consult C. A. Kiesler and Sara B. Kiesler,
Conformity (Reading: Addison-Wesley, 1969).
17. For a general account of constitutional contracts see James M. Buchanan, The Limits
of Liberty (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1975), especially chap. 4.
86
Regime Dynamics
18. This insight is, of course, examined extensively in the neofunctionalist literature on
regional integration. See, for example, the essays in Leon Lindberg and Stuart Scheingold,
eds., Regional Integration: Theory and Practice (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1971).
19. For a review of the major theories of bargaining see Oran R. Young, ed. and
contributor, Bargaining: Formal Theories of Negotiation (Urbana: University of Illinois Press,
1975)-
20. On the game-theoretic models consult R. Duncan Luce and Howard Raiffa, Games
and Decisions (New York: Wiley, 1957). The microeconomic models are reviewed in Young,
Bargaining, pt. 2.
International Regimes in Theory
21. For a discussion of these problems in the context of international bargaining see
Oran R. Young, The Politics of Force: Bargaining daring International Crises (Princeton:
Princeton University Press, 1968).
22. See also Robert Gilpin, The Political Economy of International Relations (Princeton:
Princeton University Press, 1987).
23. A. P. Thornton, Doctrines of Imperialism (New York: Wiley, 1965).
24. Charles P. Kindleberger, “Dominance and Leadership in the International Econ¬
omy,” International Studies Quarterly 25 (1981), 242—254; “International Public Goods
without International Government,” American Economic Review 7b (198b), 1 — 13; and “Hi¬
erarchy versus Inertial Cooperation,” International Organization 40 (198b), 841-847.
88
Regime Dynamics
25. See also Gilpin, Political Economy of International Relations, and “The Politics of
Transnational Economic Relations,” International Organization 25 (1971), 398—419.
26. For a review of efforts to conceptualize power in international society consult
David A. Baldwin, “Power Analysis and World Politics,” World Politics 31 (1979), 161 — 194.
27. For an insightful discussion of the role of habits of obedience see H. L. A. Hart, The
Concept of Law (Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1961), 49-64.
28. Consult Michael Hechter, Internal Colonialism (Berkeley: University of California
Press, 1975).
29. For a richly illustrated account emphasizing the role of structural factors see Ste¬
phen D. Krasner, Structural Conflict: The Third World against Global Liberalism (Berkeley:
University of California Press, 1985).
International Regimes in Theory
the oceans during the 1970s and 1980s when regimes for marine re¬
sources typically took the form of imposed or spontaneous arrange¬
ments in the past? Why have we come to rely increasingly on negotiated
regimes for various commodities when spontaneous arrangements (for
example, natural or unregulated markets) would have seemed perfectly
adequate in the past? The first thing to notice in reflecting on these
questions is that the three developmental sequences I have identified are
not mutually exclusive under real-world conditions. An imposed or
spontaneous regime, for example, is sometimes codified or legitimated
in a formal, constitutional contract; the 1958 Geneva Convention on the
Continental Shelf clearly illustrates this phenomenon. The promulga¬
tion of a negotiated regime will have little effect unless its precepts and
requirements are absorbed into the routine behavior of the participants.
Efforts to translate the terms of regional-fisheries arrangements into
day-to-day management systems, for example, indicate clearly how diffi¬
cult it can be to implement negotiated arrangements in international
society.30 By the same token, imposed regimes are sometimes increas¬
ingly accepted as legitimate with the passage of time, with the result that
it becomes less necessary for dominant actors to coerce others into
conforming with their requirements. A transition of this sort may well
have occurred in recent years in the management authority of adjacent
coastal states over marine fisheries. It follows that any attempt to classify
actual international regimes rigidly in terms of the three developmental
sequences is apt to distort reality and to produce confusion rather than
enhance understanding.
Nonetheless, we are still faced with the problem of identifying the
factors that lead to the predominance of one developmental sequence or
another. There is, in my judgment, a pronounced tendency to exagger¬
ate the role of negotiated regimes in contrast to imposed or spontaneous
regimes at the international level. Such an emphasis on negotiated
arrangements appeals to the conceptions of rational choice and con¬
scious institutional design that pervade the contemporary literature on
public policy and public choice. Additionally, a focus on spontaneous
regimes seems to imply an organic conception of society, an orientation
that is often associated with illiberal political views.31 Yet it is hard to
escape the conclusion that spontaneous regimes are of critical impor-
go
Regime Dynamics
32. For evaluations of this “hegemonic stability” perspective see Robert O. Keohane,
After Hegemony: Cooperation and Discord in the World Political Economy (Princeton: Princeton
University Press, 1984), and Duncan Snidal, “The Limits of Hegemonic Stability Theory,”
International Organization 39 (1985), 579—614.
33. For a sophisticated treatment of the distinguishing features of international society
see Hedley Bull, The Anarchical Society (New York: Columbia University Press, 1977).
34. Oran R. Young, “Interdependencies in World Politics,” International Journal 24
(1969), 726-750.
91
International Regimes in Theory
92
Regime Dynamics
ism in a variety of ways. My emphasis here is on the idea that social systems have properties,
such as centralization, interdependence, or complexity, that are attributes of the systems
per se rather than of their constituent members. For further discussion see Kenneth N.
Waltz, Theory of International Relations (Reading: Addison-Wesley, 1979).
42. For a suggestive, though overly optimistic, account of these virtues see Flayek, Rules
and Order, chap. 2.
43. Though the neoconservative movement has recently stressed this point, it is worth
noting that it has long been a major theme in the literature of anarchism. See, for example,
Daniel Guerin, Anarchism: From Theory to Practice (New York: Monthly Review Press, 1970).
44. See also Gilpin, Political Economy of International Relations.
93
International Regimes in Theory
nant actors are often oriented more toward rent-seeking behavior than
toward the pursuit of allocative efficiency—as the history of mercantil¬
ism attests. What is more, imposed regimes may become expensive to
maintain, unless the hegemon or leadership group succeeds in inducing
subordinate actors to accept the arrangements as legitimate.45
Of course, it is true that spontaneous regimes may yield outcomes that
are difficult to justify in terms of any reputable standard of equity.
Unregulated markets certainly exemplify this observation under a wide
range of conditions. Unfortunately, however, negotiated regimes and,
especially, imposed regimes cannot be counted on to yield outcomes that
are more attractive on this account. This proposition is obviously true of
imposed arrangements, which are designed to advance the interests of
one or a few dominant actors. But it is noteworthy that negotiated
regimes offer no guarantee of outcomes that are more defensible in
terms of equity. Bargains struck may be heavily affected by an unequal
distribution of bargaining strength, and it is often hard to foresee the
consequences likely to flow from complex institutional arrangements in
any case. Even if a negotiated regime is equitable in principle, moreover,
there is usually considerable scope for implementing it in ways that
differ greatly with respect to equity.46
By contrast, the situation strikes me as markedly different when we
turn from the question of outcomes to a consideration of the stability of
international regimes or the capacity of institutional arrangements to
adjust to a changing environment in an orderly fashion.47 It is here that
spontaneous regimes often run into more or less severe problems. As
the cases of language systems and moral codes suggest, these arrange¬
ments are particularly well suited to relatively settled social environ¬
ments. The convergence of expectations through spontaneous pro¬
cesses takes time, especially in situations where a multiplicity of opinion
leaders can be expected to direct attention toward divergent focal points
concerning behavioral standards. Rapid social change, therefore, typ¬
ically erodes spontaneous regimes without creating conditions condu¬
cive to the formation of new arrangements.
Imposed regimes and negotiated regimes, on the other hand, or¬
dinarily stand up better in the face of social change. A flexible hegemon
45. For a rich account of the erosion of the legitimacy of British imperialism see A. P.
Thornton, The Imperial Idea and Its Enemies: A Study in British Power (Garden City: Anchor
Books, 1968).
46. I his problem is largely abstracted away by writers like Rawls who assume perfect
compliance with the principles of justice accepted by actors in the original position. See
John Rawls, A Theory of Justice (Cambridge: Harvard University Press, 1971). 351.
47. See also Oran R. Young, “On the Performance of the International Polity,” British
Journal of International Studies 4 (1978), 191—208.
94
Regime Dynamics
Regime Transformation
48. See Keohane, After Hegemony, for an extended assessment of this argument.
49. M. J. Peterson, “Antarctica: The Last Great Land Rush on Earth,” International
Organization 34 (1980), 377-403.
95
International Regimes in Theory
Patterns of Change
50. Compare the well-known query posed by philosophers: How many Chevrolet parts
added to a Ford automobile would it take to transform the vehicle from a Ford into a
Chevrolet?
51. For a more general discussion of the problems posed by conflicts among rights
consult Ronald Dworkin, Taking Rights Seriously (Cambridge: Harvard University Press,
t977), especially chap. 4.
52. For an illustration, see Immanuel M. Wallerstein, The Capitalist World Economy (New
York: Cambridge University Press, 1979).
53- See the essays included in William R. Thompson, ed., Contending Approaches to World
System Analysis (Beverly Hills: Sage Publications, 1983).
96
Regime Dynamics
54. For a seminal analysis consult H. Scott Gordon, “The Economic Theory of a
Common Property Resource: The Fishery,” Journal of Political Economy 62 (1954), 124-
l42-
55. For an accessible discussion of the stability conditions associated with equilibrium
models see Anatol Rapoport, Fights, Games, and Debates (Ann Arbor: University of Michi¬
gan Press, i960), pt. 1.
56. See also the more general account of reaction-process models in Kenneth Boulding,
Conflict and Defense (New York: Harper and Row, 1962), especially chap. 2.
57. On the nature of dialectical reasoning see John Mepham and David H. Rubin, eds.,
Issues in Marxist Philosophy, vol. 1 (Atlantic Highlands, N.J.: Humanities Press, 1979)-
58. For a thoughtful discussion of the nature of dialectical laws see Bertell Oilman,
Alienation: Marx’s Theory of Man in Capitalist Society, 2d ed. (New York: Cambridge Univer¬
sity Press, 1976).
59. See also Richard A. Falk, This Endangered Planet (New York: Random House, 1971).
60. See also Michael B. Nicholson, Formal Theories of International Relations (Cambridge:
Cambridge University Press, 1989), chap. 8.
97
International Regimes in Theory
61. Reinhold Niebuhr, The Structure of Nations and Empires (New York: Scribner’s, 1959).
62. Gilpin, Political Economy of International Relations, chap. 4.
63. In short, regimes are seldom developed under conditions approximating the Rawls-
ian “veil ol ignorance.” See Rawls, A Theory of Justice, for an account of these conditions.
64. See also Joseph S. Nye, Jr., “Ocean Rule-making from a World Perspective,” 221-
244 in Ocean Policy Project, Perspectives on Ocean Policy (Washington, D.C., 1974).
65. For a critical review see David A. Baldwin, “Money and Power,” Journal\of Politics 33
(1970, 578—614.
Regime Dynamics
66. For an account that even raises questions about the decline of American influence
see Susan Strange, “The Persistent Myth of Lost Hegemony,” International Organization 41
(1987k 55!-574-
67. See also Baldwin, “Power Analysis.”
68. To illustrate, compare the ideas set forth in Johan Galtung, “A Structural Theory of
Imperialism,"Journal of Peace Research 2 (1971), 81 —118, with those outlined in Robert O.
Keohane and Joseph S. Nye, Jr., Power and Interdependence (Boston: Little, Brown, 1977).
69. For a sweeping view of Western history that stresses the role of technological change
see William H. McNeil, The Rise of the West (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1963).
For a more specific argument relating technological change to many contemporary en¬
vironmental problems see Barry Commoner, The Closing Circle (New York: Knopf, 1971).
70. See also Seyom Brown, Nina W. Cornell, Larry Fabian, and Edith Brown Weiss,
Regimes for the Ocean, Outer Space, and Weather (Washington, D.C.: Brookings, 1977)’
99
International Regimes in Theory
Paths to Transformation
especially chaps. 11-13, anc^ Gregory C. Staples, “T he New World Satellite Order: A
Report from Geneva,” American Journal of International Law 80 (1986), 699—720.
71. On the natural resources of the Southern Ocean see G. L. Kesteven, “The Southern
Ocean,” 467-499 in Elisabeth Mann Borgese and Norton Ginsburg, eds.. Ocean Yearbook, 1
(Ghicago: University of Chicago Press, 1978).
72. See also Lester B. Lave, Technological Change: Its Conception and Measurement (En¬
glewood Cliffs: Prentice-Hall, 1966).
IOO
Regime Dynamics
73. For non-Marxian analyses of this type see G. W. F. Hegel, The Philosophy of History,
trans. by J. Sibree (New York: Dover, 1956), and Oswald Spengler, The Decline of the West,
abr. trans. by Charles F. Atkinson (New York: Knopf, 1962).
74. For a thoughtful account of this type see Ernst B. Haas, “Why Collaborate? Issue
Linkage and International Regimes,” World Politics 32 (1980), 357-405.
IOI
International Regimes in Theory
75. See Falk, This Endangered Planet, for an analysis reflecting this point of view.
76. For a general treatment of these issues see Thomas S. Kuhn, The Structure of Scientific
Revolutions, 2d ed. (Chicago: University of Chicago Press, 1970). For an analysis of similar
issues with particular reference to international politics consult Graham Allison, The
Essence of Decision (Boston: Little, Brown, 1971).
77. See the observations on this phenomenon developed in Wolffs critique of Rawls:
Robert Paul Wolff, Understanding Rauds (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1977).
78. For an account that stresses the view that constitutional contracts are, in any case,
little more than interpretations arising from a flow of authoritative decisions see Myres S.
McDougal and Associates, Studies in World Public Order (New Haven: Yale University Press,
i960).
102
Regime Dynamics
Conclusion