What Is Comparative Politics
What Is Comparative Politics
What Is Comparative Politics
net/publication/272567191
CITATION READS
1 83,310
1 author:
Timothy Lim
California State University, Los Angeles
35 PUBLICATIONS 217 CITATIONS
SEE PROFILE
Some of the authors of this publication are also working on these related projects:
The Policy and Politics of Ethnic “Return” Migration: A Comparative Examination of South Korea’s Diaspora Engagement
Policy View project
The Policy and Politics of Ethnic “Return” Migration: An Examination of South Korea’s Diaspora Engagement Policy View
project
All content following this page was uploaded by Timothy Lim on 22 February 2015.
Timothy Lim
Copyright © 2010
ISBN: 978-1-58826-744-3 pb
Contents
List of Figures ix
Preface xi
v
00_Lim_FM.qxd 6/16/10 2:14 PM Page vi
vi Contents
Contents vii
Glossary 311
Selected Bibliography 337
Index 355
About the Book 369
01_Lim_Ch01.qxd 6/16/10 3:06 PM Page 1
1
Introduction
What Is Comparative Politics?
Let us begin this book with a few basic, but very big questions:
There are, of course, many answers to these questions. Some answers may
sound very persuasive, whereas others may seem far less convincing, even ab-
surd. On the first question, for example, the controversial director Michael
Moore argued in his Oscar-winning 2002 film Bowling for Columbine that the
high level of gun violence in the United States is largely due to a “culture of
fear” that has been created and constantly reproduced through policies and prac-
tices that exacerbate insecurity throughout US society. This culture of fear,
Moore suggested, pushes Americans to resolve problems and interpersonal con-
flict through violence, a reaction that, in turn, creates a self-confirming cycle:
fear begets violence, which begets more fear, which begets even more violence,
and so on. A culture of fear may not explain everything we need to know about
gun violence in the United States, but according to Moore, it is almost certainly
1
01_Lim_Ch01.qxd 6/16/10 3:06 PM Page 2
2 Introduction
6 Introduction
the world was colonized by western powers. As such, those societies without
a sovereign state were, almost automatically, considered unworthy of study.
Their histories, their cultures, their peoples, their methods of governing, and
so on were simply dismissed (by scholars in the United States and other west-
ern countries) for lack of political sovereignty.
Predictably, then, issues that are now considered especially important to
researchers in comparative politics and to other comparative social scientists
(“comparativists” for short), such as economic development and democrati-
zation, were also largely ignored by early students of comparative politics in
the United States. These issues were not considered pressing or worthy of
study, because the West had already “solved” them. In other words, non-
democratic and economically “backward” countries were treated as aberra-
tions or immature versions of the West and of the United States specifically,
“rather than as political systems with distinct characteristics . . . worthy of ex-
amination on their own merits” (Zahariadis 1997, p. 7). The tendency for po-
litical scientists in the United States to ignore most of the rest of the world
(even much of western Europe), moreover, rested on the immodest assump-
tion that the United States simply had little or nothing to learn from anyone
else. From this perspective, it is far easier to understand why comparative pol-
itics remained so narrowly defined for the first half of the twentieth century.
“The reasons,” as Wiarda (1991) nicely put it,
go to the heart of the American experience, to the deeply held belief that the
United States is different [from] and superior to European and all other na-
tions, the widespread conviction at the popular level that the United States
had little to learn from the rest of the world, the near-universal belief of
Americans in the superiority of their institutions and their attitudes that the
rest of the world must learn from the United States and never the other way
around. Hence political science as it developed as a discipline in the United
States was predominantly the study of American politics, for that is where
the overwhelming emphasis and interest lay. . . . Those who studied and
wrote about comparative politics were generally believed to have little to
offer intellectually to other areas of the discipline. (emphasis added; p. 12)
peoples so that the military-strategic interests of the United States could be bet-
ter protected. Certainly, in terms of funding and official support, there is little
doubt this was true. As Bruce Cumings (1997), a prominent area specialist on
Korea, pointed out, the first effort to create a systematic base of knowledge
about “foreign” countries (from the perspective of the United States) was car-
ried out by the Office of Strategic Services (OSS), the forerunner of the Cen-
tral Intelligence Agency (CIA). According to Cumings, in 1941, OSS director
William “Wild Bill” Donovan established the rationale for employing the na-
tion’s best expertise to collect and analyze all information and data that might
bear upon national security. Once this rationale became policy, the future of
comparative and area studies in the United States brightened considerably.3
The war not only broadened the perspective of the United States with re-
gard to the list of countries that mattered but also with regard to the issues that
mattered. In particular, the rise of fascism and militarism in Germany, Japan,
and Italy and the rise of communism (and Stalinism) in Russia and, later,
China, had a profound impact on the field of comparative politics and politi-
cal science as a whole (Wiarda 1991). For good reason, scholars, policymak-
ers, and others wanted to understand these political phenomena, which dif-
fered so much from the democratic and capitalist paths followed by the United
States and most Western European countries. They especially wanted to un-
derstand not only how and why fascist or totalitarian rule emerged and de-
veloped but also how and why it seemed to thrive in certain places (especially
to the extent that it represented a serious and real threat to the democracies of
the West). The question was how to best accomplish this understanding. For
an increasing number of scholars and policymakers, the answer was to be
found in a more sophisticated approach to comparative study. One of the lead-
ing advocates of this view was Roy Macridis (1955), who, in the mid-1950s,
strongly criticized traditional comparative politics as being overly parochial
(with its near-exclusive focus on Western Europe), too descriptive (as op-
posed to analytical), exceedingly formalistic, atheoretical, and even noncom-
parative. Macridis’s critique helped lay the basis for a sea change in the field.
8 Introduction
The terms “South,” “Third World,” the “developing world” (or developing
countries), and “less developed countries” (LDCs) are often used inter-
changeably to refer to those parts of the world except for Western Europe,
North America (Canada and the United States), Australia, New Zealand,
Japan, and the former communist “bloc.” During the Cold War era, so-called
Third World countries were distinguished from “Second World” countries
largely based on political ideology and military power; thus, the Second
World comprised the communist or socialist regimes, including the Soviet
Union and its satellite states (it is not clear, however, whether other commu-
nist states—such as China, Vietnam, North Korea, and others—were in-
cluded). Today, of course, the former Soviet Union and its erstwhile “satel-
lites” no longer exist. They have been replaced by Russia and a plethora of
newly independent states, located primarily in Eastern Europe and Central
Asia. For this reason, the concept of the Second World has essentially disap-
peared (although, even during the Cold War era, the term was rarely used).
So where have these countries gone? Into the Third World, or some-
place else? This is not a trivial question, for there is considerable debate
over the issue of what terminology to use. For many researchers, the con-
cept of the Third World not only has become an anachronism but was sus-
pect from the very beginning in that it implied inferiority—as did the term
“less developed countries.” Instead, many preferred the more neutral term
“South.” This term, too, is problematic, given that countries such as Aus-
tralia and New Zealand are situated in the Southern Hemisphere, whereas
most countries of Asia, many countries of Africa, and even some countries
of South America are located in the Northern Hemisphere. More recently,
others have proposed a whole new set of terms. Advocates of neoliberalism,
for example, like the term “emerging markets”; not surprisingly, that term
has not been embraced by everyone. One interesting alternative has been
proposed by Titus Alexander (1996), who argued that the most appropriate
term is “majority world.” This term, noted Alexander, is descriptively accu-
rate but does not imply any degree of homogeneity among the huge number
of countries that compose the majority world—an important point consid-
ering the “huge social, economic and political differences within and be-
tween all countries” (p. ix). Moreover, “majority” world does not contain
any connotation of inferiority, backwardness, or subordination.
would now have to treat as relatively independent players in world affairs. Sig-
nificantly, it was not just any countries and regions that were included: “Japan
got favored placement as a success story of development, and China got obses-
sive attention as a pathological example of abortive development” (Cumings
1997). Latin and South American countries also became important foci of at-
tention for scholars and policymakers (starting in the 1960s), as did South
01_Lim_Ch01.qxd 6/16/10 3:06 PM Page 9
Korea, Taiwan, and a few other countries that showed “promise.” Much of the
research during this time, moreover, was driven by the desire to understand and
confront the appeal of and potential challenge posed by communism. In this re-
gard, it is no coincidence that one of the most influential academic books of the
1950s and 1960s was W. W. Rostow’s The Stages of Economic Growth: A Non-
Communist Manifesto (1960). Although not strictly a work of comparative pol-
itics, Rostow’s anticommunist sentiments were shared by the foremost scholars
of comparative political development of the time, including the likes of Gabriel
Almond, James Coleman, and Lucien Pye (Wiarda 1991, p. 14).
This bit of history, it is important to understand, is still relevant. It tells
us, quite clearly, that outwardly objective fields of study are not immune to a
host of subjective, generally hidden—but sometimes quite open—social and
political forces. (See Figure 1.3 for a contemporary example.) And what is
true of the past is almost assuredly true of the present. This means that we al-
10 Introduction
ways need to be careful, and even a little skeptical, of the knowledge that is
produced in any context. This does not mean that all of today’s scholarship,
even more, the scholarship of the 1940s and 1950s, is irredeemably tainted
and illegitimate. It is not (although some parts may certainly be). Instead, we
should never assume it is entirely or even mostly “objective” or free of polit-
ical, cultural, or social bias.
This said, since the 1960s, the field has continued to change. Definitions
of the field, too, have changed. Today, in fact, the definition of comparative
politics, except in a very broad or generic sense,4 is characterized as much by
divergence as by consensus. (For a sampling of current definitions of com-
parative politics, see Figure 1.4.) This is one reason why the bulk of this chap-
ter is devoted to the question, what is comparative politics? Unless you can
To answer the question upon which this section is based, it is extremely use-
ful to recognize that comparative politics is not the only field in political sci-
ence that focuses on countries or states as the primary units of analysis.
Scholars in international relations, as I noted above, are also intimately con-
cerned with countries or, more accurately, states. But, as I also noted, inter-
national relations is typically more interested in relations between and among
states—that is, with their interactions in an international system. Even though
this has not precluded IR scholars from looking at what happens inside states
or countries, a good deal of research in the field has tended to treat states as
undifferentiated wholes, which is to say that IR scholars (especially those as-
sociated with the dominant research school in IR, realism or neorealism) as-
sume that states are functionally alike when interacting with other states. This
is a critical assumption, largely because it suggests that it is possible to ex-
plain the behavior of states or countries without a careful examination of their
“internal workings.” The reasoning behind this assumption stems from the be-
lief that the international system is anarchic, so that each and every state is
forced to behave in similar ways regardless of its internal makeup or its do-
mestic politics. The logic here is both simple and compelling: in an anarchic
(as opposed to hierarchic) system, states must compete with other states for
security, power, and influence. They must do so precisely because there is no
ultimate rule maker and rule enforcer for the system as a whole. Lacking an
ultimate authority, individual states (or actors) are forced to take matters into
their own hands, so to speak. Each state must, in other words, do those things
that ensure its own long-term survival. This generally means, among other
things, building a strong army, developing a network of mutually beneficial
military-strategic alliances, maintaining a diplomatic corps, gathering intelli-
gence, and engaging in military conflict when necessary.
In this view, the internal (political) makeup of a country is relatively unim-
portant in terms of explaining or predicting its external behavior. Thus, for ex-
01_Lim_Ch01.qxd 6/16/10 3:06 PM Page 12
12 Introduction
Zahariadis is correct, but his observations do not go far enough. The division
of labor between comparative politics and IR has resulted not only in differ-
ent orientations and research interests but also in a belief that there is a real
and fundamental difference between domestic and international politics.
What Is Politics?
Traditionally (that is, prior to World War II), comparative politics mainly in-
volved describing the basic features of political systems. Most research in
comparative politics, moreover, operated on the premise that politics referred
exclusively to the formal political system, that is, to the concrete institutions
01_Lim_Ch01.qxd 6/16/10 3:06 PM Page 14
14 Introduction
of government (such as the parliament, the congress, and the bureaucracy) and
to the constitutional and judicial rules that helped governments function. Ac-
cordingly, early studies tended to be little more than factual and generally su-
perficial accounts of how particular institutions of government operated and
were organized or how certain laws were written and then passed. Such ac-
counts may be useful and even necessary, but they can only tell a small part
of what we need to know about politics. Even those political processes and ac-
tors closely associated with the formal political system—such as political par-
ties, elections, and foreign and domestic decisionmaking—were left out of
these early studies. Politics, in short, was conceived of in very narrow terms.
Losing Focus?
There are many political scientists who would disagree with this broad con-
ception of politics. We are already familiar with the basic argument. To repeat:
overly broad definitions force us to lose focus; that is, because there are no neat
boundaries telling us what is and what is not included in the scope of the def-
inition, we are studying both everything and nothing. Zahariadis (1997), for
01_Lim_Ch01.qxd 6/16/10 3:06 PM Page 16
16 Introduction
Employees/
population 1.4 million 28.7 million 4.2 million 9.0 million
Sales/GDP-PPP
(in billions US$) $374.5a $593.4 $115.7 $11.5
Per capita sales/
GDP (in US$) $267,500 $23,834 $27,060 $1,316
Growth rate
(3-year average,
2006–2008) 10.03% 3.6% 1.75% 2.6%
International sales/
exports (in
billions US$) $90.6b $311.1 $29.5 $0.49
Imports (in
billions US$) N/A $92.4 $31.1 $2.1
Sources: Figures for Wal-Mart are all based on the 2008 fiscal year (“Wal-Mart 2008
Annual Report,” http://walmartstores.com/sites/AnnualReport/2008/). GDP-PPP figures
for Saudi Arabia, New Zealand, and Haiti are from the International Monetary Fund,
World Economic Outlook Database (April 2009), www.imf.org/external/pubs/ft/weo/
2009/01/weodata/index.aspx. All other data are from the CIA World Factbook, www.cia
.gov/library/publications/the-world-factbook.
Notes: GDP = gross domestic product; PPP = purchasing power parity; N/A = figures
not available.
a. Includes sales from Sam’s Club and Wal-Mart International. Sales for Wal-Mart
only were $239.5 billion.
b. Figure is included in total sales.
In thinking about what it means to compare, let’s first consider what one re-
searcher has to say: “Thinking without comparison is unthinkable. And, in the
absence of comparison, so is all scientific thought and scientific research”
(Swanson 1971, p. 141; cited in Ragin 1987, p. 1). This scholar is telling us that
in all social sciences, researchers, scholars, and students are invariably en-
gaged in making some sort of comparison. If this is so (and it is fair to say that
it is), then there is very little that sets comparative politics apart—on the sur-
face, at least—from other fields of study. This is to say that the comparative
01_Lim_Ch01.qxd 6/16/10 3:06 PM Page 18
18 Introduction
strategies used by “comparativists” are not, in principle, different from the com-
parative strategies used by other political scientists or by sociologists, econo-
mists, and so on. But it does not mean that no differences exist: arguably, one
practice that sets comparative politics apart from other fields is the explicit and
direct focus on the comparative method—as opposed to simply “comparing.”7
The comparative method, as I will discuss in detail in the following chap-
ter, is a distinctive mode of comparative analysis. According to Ragin (1987),
it entails two main predispositions. First, it involves a bias toward (although
certainly not an exclusive focus on) qualitative analysis, which means that
comparativists tend to look at cases as wholes and to compare whole cases
with each other. Thus the tendency for comparativists is to talk of comparing
Germany to Japan or the United States to Canada. This may not seem to be an
important point, but it has significant implications, one of which is that com-
parativists tend to eschew—or at least, put less priority on—quantitative
analysis, also known as statistical or variable-centered analysis (Ragin
1987, pp. 2–3). In the social sciences, especially over the past few years, this
orientation away from quantitative and toward qualitative analysis definitely
sets comparativists apart from other social scientists. Even within compara-
tive politics, however, this is beginning to change. The second predisposition
among comparativists is to value interpretation and context (pp. 2–3). This
means, in part, that comparativists (of all theoretical orientations, I might add)
begin with the assumption that “history matters.” Saying that history matters,
I should caution, is much more than pointing out a few significant historical
events or figures in an analysis; instead, it involves showing exactly how his-
torical processes and practices, as well as long-established institutional
arrangements, impact and shape the contemporary environment in which de-
cisions are made, events unfold, and struggles for power occur. It means, in
other words, demonstrating a meaningful continuity between the past and the
present. This is not easy to do, but for a comparativist using “history,” it is
often an essential task. (See Figure 1.6.)
Although understanding the predisposition of comparativists is impor-
tant, this still doesn’t tell us what it means to compare—a question that may
seem easy to answer, but in fact is not. Just pointing out or describing differ-
ences and similarities between any two countries, for example, is not by any
account the be-all and end-all of comparative analysis. Indeed, if you stay
strictly at the level of superficial description—for example, China has a Con-
fucian heritage, whereas the United States does not; both France and Russia
experienced social revolutions—you will never genuinely engage in com-
parative analysis, no matter how accurate your observations may be. And
you’re even less likely to tell your audience anything meaningful or insight-
ful about political phenomena. Comparing, then, involves much more than
making observations about two or more entities. Just what else is involved in
comparative analysis is the topic of our next chapter, so I will reserve the re-
01_Lim_Ch01.qxd 6/16/10 3:06 PM Page 19
Good historical analysis must show how past events and processes connect
with and shape contemporary events and processes. Just “talking about” his-
tory is never enough.
Why Compare?
20 Introduction
sons, doing comparative politics requires that you be aware of your reason
and rationale for making a comparison. Figure 1.7 provides a summary of the
three general purposes of comparing.
General Purpose
22 Introduction
What Is Comparable?
Comparing Cases
What we can compare, I should stress, is definitely not limited to countries
(more on this in Chapter 2). Nor is it necessarily limited to comparable data
from two or more countries. Such a restriction, for example, would automati-
cally exclude comparatively oriented but single-country (or single-unit) case
studies, including such classic comparative studies as Alexis de Tocqueville’s
Democracy in America ([1835] 1998) and Emile Durkheim’s Elementary
Forms of the Religious Life ([1915] 1961) (both cited in Ragin [1987, p. 4]).
As Ragin explained it, “Many area specialists [i.e., researchers who concen-
01_Lim_Ch01.qxd 6/16/10 3:06 PM Page 23
Earlier I noted that comparativists tend to look at cases as wholes and to com-
pare whole cases with each other. There are important advantages to this prac-
tice, the first and most important of which, perhaps, is that it enables re-
searchers to deal with complex causality (or causal complexity). At one
level, complex causality is an easy-to-grasp concept. After all, there is little
doubt that much of what happens in the “real world” is an amalgam of eco-
nomic, cultural, institutional, political, social, and even psychological
processes and forces. Not only do all these processes and forces exist inde-
pendently (at least to some extent), but they interact in complicated, difficult-
01_Lim_Ch01.qxd 6/16/10 3:06 PM Page 24
24 Introduction
The point to remember is that other methods of inquiry (such as the experi-
mental method and statistical analysis) cannot, in general, adequately deal
with complex causality. Comparative (case-oriented) analysis, by contrast, is
especially—perhaps uniquely—suited for dealing with the peculiar complex-
ity of social phenomena (Rueschemeyer 1991). Why? Quite simply because
comparative analysis, to repeat a point made above, can and often does deal
with cases as a whole—meaning that a full range of factors can be considered
at once within particular historical contexts (which themselves vary over
time). This is especially apparent with regard to “deviant” or anomalous
cases. Comparative analysis can help explain why, for example, some rela-
tively poor countries—such as India, Mauritania, and Costa Rica—are demo-
cratic, when statistically based studies would predict just the opposite.9 To ac-
count for such anomalous cases (as many comparativists might argue), we
need to look very closely at the particular configuration of social, cultural, and
political forces in these individual countries and understand how, from a his-
torical perspective, these configurations emerged and developed. We also
01_Lim_Ch01.qxd 6/16/10 3:06 PM Page 25
need to understand how external forces and relationships interacted with the
domestic environment to produce the specific results that they did. None of
this is likely to be achieved, to repeat, without considering the whole context
of each individual case.
A second, strongly related advantage is that comparative analysis (espe-
cially when carried out in a qualitative as opposed to quantitative manner) al-
lows the researcher to better understand or explain the relationship between and
among factors. Quantitative or statistical research, by contrast, does a very good
job in showing that relationships exist (for example, that capitalist development
is related to democratization) but does not generally do a good job at telling us
what the nature or underlying dynamic of this relationship is. To use a metaphor
from aviation, we might say that quantitative analysis shows a strong correla-
tion between engine failure and plane crashes, but it typically does not tell us
the exact reasons (or the chain of causal events leading to the crash—since not
all engine problems, even very similar ones, lead to the same outcome, and vice
versa). To find out the reasons planes crash, therefore, investigators almost al-
ways have to look inside the black box or flight data recorder (see Figure 1.8).10
They have to analyze the myriad factors—some of which will undoubtedly be
unique to individual flights—to determine the cause of any particular crash.
Even this may not be enough: quite frequently, investigators have to literally re-
assemble the fragments of the destroyed plane to determine the chain of causal
events. To be sure, the cause is sometimes obvious and does not require inten-
sive investigation, but more often than not, the incident as a whole needs to be
examined in order to develop a complete explanation.
Factor X ■ Outcome Y
Example: Example:
Capitalist growth Democracy
26 Introduction
By Way of a Conclusion:
Method and Theory in Comparative Politics
The metaphor of the black box is instructive, but we should be careful not to
take it too far, for comparative analysis is more than just opening up the black
box and analyzing its contents. It also involves—as might already be apparent
from my discussion of the two types of comparative research strategies—a
process of a priori conceptualization. At the most basic level, this simply
means that the selection of cases to investigate should not be purely random or
arbitrary but should be guided by certain criteria, some of which derive from
the particular research design we choose. Yet before we even get to the re-
search design, important choices have to be made regarding the factors (or
variables) we consider significant in the first place. These choices are guided
by theory. In Chapter 3, I talk much more about theory. For now, then, let me
highlight one general point: theory has a bad reputation among students. Part
of the blame, I think, falls on professors who do not help students understand
why theory is not only important but is something none of us can do without
(whether in an academic discipline or in everyday life). As I will make clear,
we all theorize about the world, all the time. Yet just because we all theorize
does not mean we all do it equally well—this is especially true for those of you
who operate on the assumption that theories have nothing to do with the “real
world,” or that one can explain or understand anything simply by appealing to
the “facts.” One way to rectify this problem is to simply become more self-
conscious and explicit about theory/theorizing; this has the added benefit, I
might add, of helping you become a more disciplined, critical, and analytic
thinker. Thinking theoretically about comparative politics, in this regard, has
value well beyond the confines of this particular subfield. The same can be said
about thinking comparatively, which is the topic of our next chapter.
To sum up, doing comparative politics requires, minimally, a clear-eyed
understanding of what comparative politics is, of what it means to compare,
and of the importance and necessity of theory. There is, of course, more to
doing comparative politics than just these three requirements, but they consti-
tute an essential foundation upon which everything else will stand.
Questions
States? What were the problems that characterized the early development of
comparative politics as a field of study?
3. Why did the scope and definition of comparative politics change after
World War II? Did these changes lead to a “better” or more objective defini-
tion of comparative politics?
4. What are the differences between international relations and compar-
ative politics as fields of study? Why is it important to be aware of and un-
derstand these differences?
5. What does it mean to say that international relations, in general, has
adopted an “outside-in” approach, while comparative politics, in general, has
adopted an “inside-out” approach? Is one approach better than the other?
6. What definition of comparative politics is recommended in the chap-
ter? How does it differ from other definitions of the field?
7. What are the key implications of a process-oriented definition of pol-
itics in terms of (1) whom we see as significant actors; (2) what we consider
to be a political issue; and (3) where we understand politics to occur?
8. Does the economic size of a corporation such as Wal-Mart make it a
significant “political” actor? Do the decisions made and implemented by Wal-
Mart have important political consequences and implications?
9. What are the three goals of comparing? How do these goals differ in
terms of doing comparative analysis?
10. Are “apples and oranges” comparable? More generally, are units of
analysis that appear quite different from one another—say, Haiti and Japan—
comparable? Or, is it only permissible to compare units that are essentially
similar to one another?
11. What are the key advantages of the comparative method?
12. What is the “black box of explanation” and how does it relate to com-
parative analysis?
Notes
1. Terms that appear in boldface type are defined in the Glossary (see p. 311).
2. This seems an obvious point about which most scholars would agree. Yet the dis-
tinction between American and comparative politics still exists in the United States. There
are, of course, plenty of reasons for this, one of which is that it is “natural” for people to
see their own country or society as separate and distinct from other places. Nonetheless,
there is no solid justification for the distinction. As Sigelman and Gadbois (1983) nicely
put it, “the traditional distinction between American and comparative politics is . . . intel-
lectually indefensible. . . . Comparison presupposes multiple objects of analysis . . . one
compares something to or with something else” (cited in Sartori 1994, p. 14).
3. For an interesting discussion of the relationship between US government sup-
port and the development of area studies (specifically in relation to Asia) in the United
States, see Selden (1997).
01_Lim_Ch01.qxd 6/16/10 3:06 PM Page 28
28 Introduction