Philosophical Perspectives On Suicide: Kant, Schopenhauer, Nietzsche, and Wittgenstein 1st Ed. 2020 Edition Paolo Stellino

Download as pdf or txt
Download as pdf or txt
You are on page 1of 39

Philosophical Perspectives on Suicide:

Kant, Schopenhauer, Nietzsche, and


Wittgenstein 1st ed. 2020 Edition Paolo
Stellino
Visit to download the full and correct content document:
https://ebookmass.com/product/philosophical-perspectives-on-suicide-kant-schopenh
auer-nietzsche-and-wittgenstein-1st-ed-2020-edition-paolo-stellino/
More products digital (pdf, epub, mobi) instant
download maybe you interests ...

Essays on Schopenhauer and Nietzsche: Values and the


Will of Life Christopher Janaway

https://ebookmass.com/product/essays-on-schopenhauer-and-
nietzsche-values-and-the-will-of-life-christopher-janaway/

Philosophical Perspectives on Land Reform in Southern


Africa 1st ed. Edition Erasmus Masitera

https://ebookmass.com/product/philosophical-perspectives-on-land-
reform-in-southern-africa-1st-ed-edition-erasmus-masitera/

Suicide through a Peacebuilding Lens 1st ed. 2020


Edition Katerina Standish

https://ebookmass.com/product/suicide-through-a-peacebuilding-
lens-1st-ed-2020-edition-katerina-standish/

Martyrdom, Self-Sacrifice, and Self-Immolation:


Religious Perspectives on Suicide Margo Kitts

https://ebookmass.com/product/martyrdom-self-sacrifice-and-self-
immolation-religious-perspectives-on-suicide-margo-kitts/
Collingwood on Philosophical Methodology 1st ed.
Edition Karim Dharamsi

https://ebookmass.com/product/collingwood-on-philosophical-
methodology-1st-ed-edition-karim-dharamsi/

Bad Words: Philosophical Perspectives On Slurs David


Sosa

https://ebookmass.com/product/bad-words-philosophical-
perspectives-on-slurs-david-sosa/

Kafka’s The Trial: Philosophical Perspectives Espen


Hammer (Ed.)

https://ebookmass.com/product/kafkas-the-trial-philosophical-
perspectives-espen-hammer-ed/

Wittgenstein on Realism and Idealism David R. Cerbone

https://ebookmass.com/product/wittgenstein-on-realism-and-
idealism-david-r-cerbone/

Suicide Tourism: Understanding the Legal,


Philosophical, and Socio-Political Dimensions Daniel
Sperling

https://ebookmass.com/product/suicide-tourism-understanding-the-
legal-philosophical-and-socio-political-dimensions-daniel-
sperling/
Philosophical
Perspectives
on Suicide
Kant, Schopenhauer,
Nietzsche, and Wittgenstein

Paolo Stellino
Philosophical Perspectives on Suicide
Paolo Stellino

Philosophical
Perspectives on
Suicide
Kant, Schopenhauer, Nietzsche,
and Wittgenstein
Paolo Stellino
Nova Institute of Philosophy
Universidade Nova de Lisboa
LISBOA, Portugal

ISBN 978-3-030-53936-8    ISBN 978-3-030-53937-5 (eBook)


https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-53937-5

© The Editor(s) (if applicable) and The Author(s), under exclusive license to Springer Nature
Switzerland AG 2020
This work is subject to copyright. All rights are solely and exclusively licensed by the Publisher, whether
the whole or part of the material is concerned, specifically the rights of translation, reprinting, reuse of
illustrations, recitation, broadcasting, reproduction on microfilms or in any other physical way, and
transmission or information storage and retrieval, electronic adaptation, computer software, or by similar
or dissimilar methodology now known or hereafter developed.
The use of general descriptive names, registered names, trademarks, service marks, etc. in this publication
does not imply, even in the absence of a specific statement, that such names are exempt from the relevant
protective laws and regulations and therefore free for general use.
The publisher, the authors, and the editors are safe to assume that the advice and information in this book
are believed to be true and accurate at the date of publication. Neither the publisher nor the authors or
the editors give a warranty, expressed or implied, with respect to the material contained herein or for any
errors or omissions that may have been made. The publisher remains neutral with regard to jurisdictional
claims in published maps and institutional affiliations.

This Palgrave Macmillan imprint is published by the registered company Springer Nature Switzerland AG.
The registered company address is: Gewerbestrasse 11, 6330 Cham, Switzerland
Preface

According to Baruch Spinoza, “a free person thinks about death less than
anything, and his wisdom is a meditation not on death but on life”
(Ethics, IV, 67). Writing a book on the philosophy of suicide does not
necessarily mean to meditate on death. This is what I tried to explain—
often with no success—to all those friends and colleagues that in recent
years kept asking me why I had chosen to work on such a gloomy subject.
Of course, I could have reminded them of Camus’ well-known opening
words of The Myth of Sisyphus: “There is but one truly serious philosophi-
cal problem and that is suicide.” But the fact is that whereas I am not
persuaded by Camus’ claim, I am truly convinced that meditating on
suicide means, to a great extent, meditating on fundamental questions
that directly concern life, not death. Among others, these questions are:
How do we conceive our obligations to society, friends, and family?
Which is the set of moral values according to which we choose to orien-
tate our life? Which is the value that we give to our autonomy and free-
dom? Is this value non-negotiable? And how do we conceive dignity? Is it
a “property” that, in specific situations, can be undermined or
deteriorated?
I began to take interest in these questions almost fifteen years ago
when, almost accidentally, I attended a session of the seminar of the
Bioethics Research Group of the University of Valencia. At the time, I
was still a PhD student and the subject of my dissertation (on Nietzsche
v
vi Preface

and Dostoevsky) had little to do with bioethics. Juan Carlos Siurana


Aparisi, the director of the research group, drew my attention to the fact
that Nietzsche’s stance on suicide was almost unexplored by bioethicists.
I began looking for Nietzsche’s remarks on suicide in his writings and
posthumous fragments. What struck me immediately was Nietzsche’s
joyous and almost poetical conception of free death. The possibility of
conceiving death differently, that is, as a festival was something new for me.
I left Spain in 2010. At the time, I had two main concerns: to find a
post-doc position and to work on the English translation of my disserta-
tion. I temporarily set aside my interest on the topic of suicide and
devoted myself completely to Nietzsche and Dostoevsky. It was an inter-
national conference on Kant and Nietzsche, held in 2012 in Lisbon, that
gave me the occasion to work again on the philosophy of suicide. From
that moment, suicide has been, somewhat intermittently, one of my main
topics of research. The idea of writing this book occurred to me some
years later, when I noticed that there was a fil rouge that linked Kant’s,
Schopenhauer’s, Nietzsche’s, and Wittgenstein’s views of suicide. I will
motivate my choice to place these four philosophical perspectives on sui-
cide side by side in the Introduction, so that there is no need to dwell on
it here.
Some chapters of this book are based on material previously published
in P. Stellino, “Nietzsche on Suicide”, Nietzsche-Studien, 42 (2013):
151–177, and in P. Stellino, “Kant and Nietzsche on Suicide”, Philosophical
Inquiry, 39/2 (2015): 79–104. Although in both cases I heavily reworked
their content for this book, I would like to thank both journals for per-
mission to revise and reuse these publications.
My research particularly benefited from the works of three specialists
on the philosophy of suicide: Margaret P. Battin, Héctor Wittwer, and
Michael Cholbi. Wittwer’s book Selbsttötung als philosophisches Problem:
Über die Rationalität und Moralität des Suizids particularly helped me at
the initial stage of my research to understand the complexities of the dif-
ferent arguments that are put forward in the debate concerning the ratio-
nality and morality of suicide.

LisbonPaolo Stellino
23 April 2020
Acknowledgements

I owe a great debt to the following friends and colleagues who read single
chapters of this book and provided me with extremely valuable feedback:
Roberta Pasquarè and Lorena Cebolla Sanahuja (chapter on Kant),
Christopher Janaway and Vilmar Debona (chapter on Schopenhauer),
Marta Faustino and Maria Cristina Fornari (chapter on Nietzsche), and
Vicente Sanfélix Vidarte and Modesto Gómez Alonso (chapter on
Wittgenstein). I am also most grateful to the anonymous reviewer for
providing very useful critical and constructive comments on the entire
manuscript.
I would like to thank Brendan George and Lauriane Piette, from
Palgrave Macmillan, and Charanya Manoharan, from Springer, for their
help and support. I would also like to thank João Constâncio for kindly
supporting my work since the first day I arrived in Lisbon. I should also
mention that this book would not have been possible without the sup-
port of the Portuguese Fundação para a Ciência e a Tecnologia (FCT).
A part of this book was written during my stay in Montpellier. I would
like to thank Pascal Nouvel for welcoming me at the Centre d’Éthique
Contemporaine. A special thought goes to Nadia El Eter and Guillaume
Bagnolini, who shared with me the daily routine at the Centre.
A word of gratitude goes to all the friends who, inside and outside
academia, near and far, have accompanied me during this journey. I can-
not help mentioning Maria Cristina Fornari, Luca Lupo, and Pietro
vii
viii Acknowledgements

Gori. In particular, I shared with Pietro all the ups and downs of the
academic life as well as the experience of building a new life in a new
country with our respective families.
Finally, I am deeply thankful to my family for their constant support,
and to Audrey for her love and for sharing her life with me (despite the
fact that I am a philosopher). E lucevan le stelle…
Contents

1 Introduction: Bringing Kant, Schopenhauer, Nietzsche,


and Wittgenstein Together  1
References  9

2 Immanuel Kant: The Moral Duty of Self-­Preservation 11


2.1 Contextualizing Kant’s Prohibition of Suicide  11
2.2 Arguments from the Lectures on Ethics  23
2.3 Arguments from the Published Writings  40
2.4 Concluding Remarks  64
References 66

3 Arthur Schopenhauer: The Metaphysical Futility of Suicide 71


3.1 Schopenhauer’s Critique of Religious and Philosophical
Arguments against Suicide  78
3.2 Schopenhauer’s Metaphysical Worldview  90
3.3 The Futility of Suicide 100
3.4 Concluding Remarks 117
References118

ix
x Contents

4 Friedrich Nietzsche: A Free Death at the Right Time123


4.1 Voluntary versus Involuntary Death 131
4.2 Free Death and Quick Death 143
4.3 Meaninglessness and Suicide 155
4.4 Concluding Remarks 173
References174

5 Ludwig Wittgenstein: Suicide as the Elementary Sin179


5.1 The Sources 189
5.2 Wittgenstein’s View of Ethics 199
5.3 Wittgenstein’s Remarks on Suicide 208
5.4 Concluding Remarks 221
References223

6 Conclusion: What Kant, Schopenhauer, Nietzsche, and


Wittgenstein Can Teach Us About Suicide227
References240

Index243
About the author

Paolo Stellino is Researcher at the Nova Institute of Philosophy, New


University of Lisbon, Portugal. His main fields of research interest are the
history of nineteenth- and twentieth-century philosophy, ethics, and phi-
losophy of cinema. He has published many articles in international peer-­
reviewed journals and has authored several book chapters. He is the
author of the book Nietzsche and Dostoevsky: On the Verge of Nihilism (2015).

xi
Abbreviations

Kant
References to Kant’s writings are cited according to the volume and page
number of the Academy Edition (Kants gesammelte Schriften).
A Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View
CPR Critique of Pure Reason [1781 cited as A/1787 cited as B]
CPrR Critique of Practical Reason
LE Lectures on Ethics
G Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals
MM The Metaphysics of Morals
NF Notes and Fragments
R Religion within the Boundaries of Mere Reason

Schopenhauer
References to Schopenhauer’s writings are cited according to the follow-
ing abbreviations and the page number of the editions listed in the
bibliography.

BM On the Basis of Morals


MR Manuscript Remains in Four Volumes
PP (I & II) Parerga and Paralipomena
WWR (I & II) The World as Will and Representation

xiii
xiv Abbreviations

Nietzsche
References to Nietzsche’s works are cited by abbreviation, chapter (when
applicable) and section number. For the sake of brevity, the chapter might
be identified only by a key word (for instance, Clever instead of Why I Am
so Clever). Nietzsche’s posthumous fragments are cited by year, group,
and fragment number according to the standard Colli and Montinari
edition. Nietzsche’s letters are quoted using the symbol # plus the stan-
dard reference number of the letter.

A The Anti-Christ
BGE Beyond Good and Evil
BT The Birth of Tragedy
EH Ecce Homo
GM On the Genealogy of Morality
GS The Gay Science
HH Human, All Too Human
HL On the Use and Disadvantage of History for Life
L Letters
NW Nietzsche contra Wagner
PF Posthumous Fragments
SE Schopenhauer as Educator
TI Twilight of the Idols
WS The Wanderer and His Shadow
Z Thus Spoke Zarathustra

Wittgenstein
Quotes from the Tractatus are cited by reference to the number of the
section. Quotes from the Notebooks and the Geheime Tagebücher are cited
by reference to the day of the entry.

CV Culture and Value


GT Geheime Tagebücher. 1914–1916
LE Lecture on Ethics
NB Notebooks. 1914–1916
TLP Tractatus Logico-Philosophicus
1
Introduction: Bringing Kant,
Schopenhauer, Nietzsche,
and Wittgenstein Together

In Ancient Greece death was seen as an exit door that led “from here to
yonder”, as Socrates puts in Plato’s Phaedo (117c/Plato 1997), that is,
from life on earth to the afterlife. One of the key philosophical questions
concerning death was whether man had the right to open the door. In an
earlier passage from the same dialogue, Socrates explains to Cebes that
“we men are in a kind of prison, and that one must not free oneself or run
away” (Phaedo, 62b)—at least, not “before a god has indicated some
necessity to do so” (Phaedo, 62c). Some centuries afterwards Epictetus,
the Stoic philosopher, expressed a different opinion. Life should be pre-
served as long as it is beneficial, but if it becomes unbearable, one can give
it up. As he writes in a well-known passage from the Discourses, “[h]as
some one made a smoke in the house? If he has made a moderate amount
of smoke I shall stay; if too much, I go outside. For one ought to remem-
ber and hold fast to this, that the door stands open” (Discourses I, XXV,
18/Epictetus 1956).
Since antiquity, the arguments put forward by philosophers have
become more solid and sophisticated. Nevertheless, the main question to
be answered remains the same: do we have a right to voluntarily put an
end to our life? This question can be essentially declined in two different,

© The Author(s) 2020 1


P. Stellino, Philosophical Perspectives on Suicide,
https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-53937-5_1
2 P. Stellino

but strictly related, questions: (1) is suicide morally permitted? and (2)
can suicide be considered (at least in certain situations) a rational act? An
analytic approach to this question is typical of recent, contemporary phi-
losophy of suicide, which is now treated as an independent branch of
philosophy. With few exceptions (like St. Thomas Aquinas and Hume),
past philosophers have considered the question of the morality and/or
rationality of suicide in a rather fragmentary way, so that their arguments
in favour or against suicide, often to be found in detached passages of
different works, must be pieced together in order to get a general view. As
will be shown, this is precisely the case with the four philosophers consid-
ered in this book.
Nowadays, there are several valuable studies that offer an overview of
the several philosophical (and religious) arguments that can be put for-
ward in support or against one’s right to commit suicide. The works of
Cosculluela (1995), Battin (1996), Wittwer (2003), and Cholbi (2011)
are good examples of this. The scope of these studies is often introduc-
tory. This means that, in presenting the several arguments pro and con
they gain in comprehensiveness, but inevitably lack in depth.1 The aim of
this book is to address some of the same questions that these studies
address. To this end, however, a different approach is followed. Attention
is focused on four modern perspectives, which can be considered as rep-
resenting or illustrating four different views of suicide. Putting forward
seven different arguments against suicide and defending a strict prohibi-
tion of this act, Kant is a representative of the anti-libertarian view.
Schopenhauer also essentially opposes suicide, but he does it as a conse-
quence of his metaphysical view of the world, which is thoroughly pes-
simistic. His stance exemplarily shows that a pessimistic worldview does
not necessarily go hand in hand with a pro-attitude towards suicide.
Contrary to Kant, Nietzsche is rather favourable to voluntary death, at
least in certain specific situations. His stance, reminiscent of the Stoics’,
can be thus considered as representative of the libertarian view. Finally,
Wittgenstein considers suicide from the standpoint of his mystical–reli-
gious worldview, conceiving it as the elementary sin. Addressing these

1
Due to its length, Wittwer’s study combines, to a certain extent, comprehensiveness and depth.
1 Introduction: Bringing Kant, Schopenhauer, Nietzsche… 3

different but, as will be shown, complementary positions, this book pro-


vides an unusual way of understanding the phenomenon of suicide in an
integrated way. The book of course does not pretend to have an exhaus-
tive character on the immense topic it touches upon, but what it lacks in
comprehensiveness it gains in depth.
The reason to consider Kant’s, Schopenhauer’s, Nietzsche’s, and
Wittgenstein’s views of suicide in the same book also derives from the fact
that, as mentioned in the Preface, there is a fil rouge that links these views
together. In the Appendix to the first volume of the World as Will and
Representation, Schopenhauer clearly acknowledges that “however differ-
ent the content of my line of reasoning is from that of Kant, it has clearly
been very heavily influenced by Kantian ideas, it necessarily presupposes
them, and takes them as its point of departure” (WWR I: 443/
Schopenhauer 2010). When it comes to morality and its grounding,
however, Schopenhauer’s view is “diametrically opposed to Kant’s in its
essential points” (BM: 122/Schopenhauer 2009). This can be clearly seen
in Schopenhauer’s negative evaluation of Kant’s view of suicide.
Schopenhauer is very critical of the way in which Kant approaches sui-
cide and several pages of his prize essay On the Basis of Morals are devoted
to criticizing some of the arguments put forward by the latter.
Nietzsche’s relation to Schopenhauer recalls, to a certain extent,
Schopenhauer’s relation to Kant. Nietzsche was deeply influenced by
Schopenhauer (“my great teacher”, he called him in the Preface to the
Genealogy of Morality; GM, Preface, 5/Nietzsche 2006) and this influence
is not limited to the former’s early philosophy, as is often believed. At the
same time, however, Nietzsche was a profound critic of Schopenhauer’s
life-denying philosophy. Thus Nietzsche partly elaborates his view of sui-
cide in opposition to his teacher’s, and, more in general, to pessimistic
attitudes to life. Indeed, due to the influence of Schopenhauer’s thought,
pessimistic philosophies were à la mode in the second half of the nine-
teenth century and Nietzsche knew them well. Furthermore, as men-
tioned, Nietzsche’s view is also antithetical to Kant’s—although this
antithesis is not the result of Nietzsche’s direct confrontation with Kant’s
arguments against suicide, but it rather depends on Nietzsche’s more gen-
eral critique of his moral theory.
If Schopenhauer criticizes Kant’s view of suicide, and if Nietzsche
opposes Schopenhauer’s (directly) and Kant’s (indirectly) approaches to
4 P. Stellino

suicide, Wittgenstein’s most important remarks on suicide date from the


early period, that is, at a time when his philosophy was strongly influ-
enced by Schopenhauer’s metaphysics (which takes Kant’s transcendental
idealism as starting point, as mentioned). Given that Schopenhauer
exerted a major influence on the early Wittgenstein’s understanding of
the world and of ethics, it is not surprising to see that this influence also
extends to the latter’s view of suicide. In passing, it should be also men-
tioned that although it is not possible to know whether Wittgenstein was
familiar with Nietzsche’s remarks on suicide, it is a fact that in 1914
Wittgenstein bought the eighth volume of Nietzsches Werke (GT 8.12.14/
Wittgenstein 1992), which contained several texts from 1888.
Wittgenstein was most interested in Nietzsche’s The Anti-Christ. In his
Wittgenstein biography, Ray Monk comments on Wittgenstein’s interest
in Nietzsche as follows: “More stimulating was a writer whose view could
not have been more antithetical to the Tolstoyan Christianity that
Wittgenstein had come to embrace: Friedrich Nietzsche” (Monk 1991:
121). In reality, Wittgenstein’s interest in Nietzsche can be easily
explained. Indeed, although it is true that The Anti-Christ was a virulent
attack upon the Christian religion and that Wittgenstein was “deeply
affected” by Nietzsche’s hostility against Christianity (GT 8.12.14),
Nietzsche’s work was strongly influenced by Tolstoy’s view of Christianity
(Llinares Chover 2010). As will be shown, precisely this view contributed
to an important extent to shape Wittgenstein’s view of suicide.
As one can see, there is a clear connection between Kant’s,
Schopenhauer’s, Nietzsche’s, and Wittgenstein’s views of suicide. This
connection, however, does not constitute the only reason for this book.
Another reason is that, with the exception of Kant, the other three phi-
losophers considered here are often ignored in the field of philosophy of
suicide. This lack of attention seems to be motivated by reasons that are
different in each case. Schopenhauer’s opposition to suicide may be
regarded as unappealing since it presupposes his peculiar and, by now,
outdated metaphysics of the will. However, Schopenhauer is among the
philosophers who gave most importance to the topic of suicide (like
Hume, he dedicated a specific essay to suicide) and in his writings one
can find interesting considerations of various nature on this subject.
These considerations go far beyond his argument for the futility of
1 Introduction: Bringing Kant, Schopenhauer, Nietzsche… 5

suicide based on metaphysical grounds and Schopenhauer’s approach to


suicide is highly worthy of attention for the broadness of its scope and for
being ahead of his time, among other reasons. One of the aims of this
book is thus to revaluate Schopenhauer’s view of suicide and bring it to
the attention of contemporary scholars.
In the field of philosophy of suicide Nietzsche has received even less
attention than Schopenhauer. This may come as a surprise if one consid-
ers that his published writings contain several remarks on suicide and
that a speech from the first part of Thus Spoke Zarathustra is significantly
entitled On Free Death. This lack of attention can be differently accounted
for. One reason might be the fragmentary and unsystematic character of
Nietzsche’s approach to suicide. Another reason might be the strong rhe-
torical component of the texts in which he presents his view. As will be
shown, however, although Nietzsche tends to appeal to emotions instead
of defending his position with proper arguments, he nonetheless gives his
readers reasons that support his argumentation, and these reasons can be
scrutinized and examined just in the same way as Kant’s, Schopenhauer’s,
and Wittgenstein’s arguments can be. A third reason that might explain
why Nietzsche’s view of suicide is often ignored in secondary literature on
philosophy of suicide is the fact that, along with the notion of free death,
he also defends a quick death for all those who cling to life out of cow-
ardice and fear, and refuse to take a timely leave from it. Without denying
that considered from a contemporary perspective this latter notion
appears unsettling, one should resist here the temptation of decontextual-
izing Nietzsche’s words and reading them through the distorting prism of
our historical perspective. In any case, the notions of free and quick death
can and should be kept separated, so as to judge Nietzsche’s arguments in
favour of voluntary death without any bias.
Of the four philosophers considered in this study, Wittgenstein is the
one who has received less attention in the field of philosophy of suicide.
To my knowledge, the only in-depth study on Wittgenstein’s view of
suicide is the very recent paper by Gómez Alonso (2018) which, however,
mainly (although not uniquely) focuses the attention on the relation
between Wittgenstein’s early view of suicide and Schopenhauer’s meta-
physics of the will. This lack of attention may be explained by the fact
that Wittgenstein’s remarks on suicide are very few in number and that in
6 P. Stellino

order to grasp their meaning it is necessary to understand some of the


very complex and difficult notions that he introduces in his Tractatus
Logico-Philosophicus. Once this difficult step is overcome, however,
Wittgenstein’s view of suicide appears very insightful and directly linked
to some of the most profound thinkers of the nineteenth century such as
Tolstoy, Dostoevsky, Kierkegaard, and James, among others.
Unlike Schopenhauer’s, Nietzsche’s, and Wittgenstein’s views of sui-
cide, Kant’s view has been the subject of countless studies—as the
extended bibliography of the second chapter of this book clearly shows.
This should not be surprising, given that Kant’s moral theory has exerted
and continues to exert such an extraordinary influence on contemporary
bioethics and applied ethics. Even in this case, however, some clarifica-
tions are needed. First, although there are several informative studies on
Kant’s view of suicide, to my knowledge, there is no comprehensive study
in English on this subject. The only paper that presents an overview of
Kant’s several arguments against suicide is Wittwer’s (2001). However,
this paper is almost twenty years old (although the analysis developed in
it is still compelling) and is written in German, being therefore not easily
accessible to the anglophone audience. Second, existing literature usually
tends to focus the attention on Kant’s arguments from the published
writings, ignoring the arguments put forward in the Lectures on Ethics.
Almost no attention has been paid, for instance, to Kant’s freedom argu-
ment in the Collins lectures (see Sect. 2.2.3), according to which suicide
would imply a self-contradiction of freedom. This is very surprising, con-
sidering that a similar line of argumentation is sometimes advanced
within the context of the contemporary debate on assisted suicide. The
aim of the first chapter of this book is thus to provide a comprehensive
study of Kant’s view of suicide and an in-depth examination of all his
arguments against suicide. Third and finally, recent literature in English
on this subject tends to question the conventional reading of Kant as a
philosopher who categorically prohibits suicide. Some scholars even
argue that, in certain situations, Kant’s moral philosophy can be read as
justifying not only a right, but even a duty to suicide. As I will show in
the following chapter, these readings are often based on misunderstand-
ings deriving either from incomplete information or from a lack of philo-
logical accuracy.
1 Introduction: Bringing Kant, Schopenhauer, Nietzsche… 7

The methodology followed in this study primarily consists in a close


and attentive reading of the primary sources (published writings, Nachlass,
lectures, diaries, and letters). When necessary, attention is given to the
German original. The main aim is to provide a complete overview of
Kant’s, Schopenhauer’s, Nietzsche’s, and Wittgenstein’s views of suicide.
As far as possible, each stance is presented as a unitary whole. On the
other hand, however, chronological differences are taken into account.
Kant’s arguments from the Collins lectures (pre-critical period), for
instance, are distinguished from the arguments that can be found in the
published writings. At the same time, correspondences between the for-
mer and the latter are nevertheless emphasized. With the help of the rel-
evant bibliography on the subject, the arguments in favour of or against
suicide put forward by the four philosophers considered in this study are
explained, contextualized (when necessary), examined, and critically
assessed. The approach of this book is thus not so much historical as
philosophical in nature.
This book is constituted of four main chapters and a conclusion. To
each philosopher’s view of suicide is devoted one, single chapter. The fol-
lowing is a brief overview of the content of each chapter. Chapter 2 pro-
vides an in-depth examination of Kant’s arguments against suicide. After
a contextualization of Kant’s prohibition of suicide (§2.1), following
Wittwer (2001), I identify seven different arguments against the moral
permissibility of suicide: three from the Lectures on Ethics (§2.2) and four
from the published writings (§2.3). For each of them, I present the argu-
ment (and possible variations), point out strengths and flaws, and discuss
possible objections and counter-objections, taking into consideration the
abundant bibliography on the subject. I conclude that, against a recent
trend in secondary literature, which tends to read Kant as justifying not
only a right, but even a duty to suicide, Kant does not allow for any
exception to his strict prohibition of suicide.
Chapter 3 provides a full and complete analysis of Schopenhauer’s
view of suicide. Drawing on the limited secondary literature on this sub-
ject (essentially, Fox (1980), Birnbacher (1985), Jacquette (1999, 2000),
and Janaway (2017)), I first focus on Schopenhauer’s dismissal of previ-
ous religious and philosophical arguments against this act, giving particu-
lar attention to his critique of Kant’s arguments (§3.1). Subsequently, I
Another random document with
no related content on Scribd:
sash, First-floor, §61, p28
-sash hardware, §55, p77
sash, Second-floor, §61, p29
Windows, Cost of window frames and, §60, p63
Wire brads, §55, p9
gauge, §55, p4
glass, §55, p161; §64, p54
nails, §55, p2
nails, Special, §55, p8
nails, Table of sizes of, §55, p7
Wiring, Cost of electric, §61, p41
Wood screws, §55, p11
screws, Table of sizes of, §55, p13
Wooden door knobs, §55, p71
floors, Table of labor cost of laying, §60, p44

Y
Yale master-key lock, §55, p52

Footnotes:
[1] In place of the mortise turnbuckle any of the following hardware can be used:
Casement fasts or locks; Cremorne bolts, locking top, bottom, and center; or,
Espagnolette bars, either rim or mortise.
[2] The block F is taken as a triangle. The block G is a semicircle, and its area is
found, as will be noticed, by finding the area of a circle and dividing it by 2.
[3] The block F is taken as a triangle. The block G is a semicircle, and its area is
found, as will be noticed, by finding the area of a circle and dividing it by 2.
[4] Lengths scaled along center line of walls.
[5] Lengths scaled along center line of walls.
[6] External measurements with no deduction for openings.
[7] Although these are made continuous, to carry the base, or ground sill,
independent piers, under the porch columns might be substituted, at a
somewhat less cost.
[8] Although these are made continuous, to carry the base, or ground sill,
independent piers, under the porch columns might be substituted, at a
somewhat less cost.
[9] The walls between the base sill and the water-table are faced with ashlar,
which extends around the main walls to the porches, and all porch piers are built
of ashlar.
[10] One joist will be left over here, but this cannot easily be helped.
[11] In the attic plan, which shows the lines of the roof, the lines of the dormers
are omitted so as to make the important hips and valleys more prominent.
[12] Where studs over 20 feet are required, it is sometimes more economical to
use two short studs, inserting a plate over the first-story studs and resting the
feet of the second-story studs thereon.
[13] This value would appear high if compared with Table VI, Estimating and
Calculating Quantities, Part 1, but this table represents ideal conditions, where
there are no delays, mistakes, legitimate office expenses, nor foreman's time
included.
[14] Usually a man can lay more than 700 shingles per day, but the roof under
consideration is very much cut up.
[15] The cost of this hemlock is $1 cheaper per thousand than that used in the
framing, since shorter lengths may be employed.
[16] The prices given include the cost of labor.
[17] The prices of doors do not include hardware, which item will be found in the
hardware bill, but they include putting on the hardware.
[18] This door opens to the balcony.
Transcriber’s Notes:

The cover image was created by the transcriber, and is in the public domain.
The illustrations have been moved so that they do not break up paragraphs and so
that they are next to the text they illustrate.
Typographical and punctuation errors have been silently corrected.
*** END OF THE PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK HARDWARE,
ESTIMATING, AND MILL DESIGN ***

Updated editions will replace the previous one—the old editions will
be renamed.

Creating the works from print editions not protected by U.S.


copyright law means that no one owns a United States copyright in
these works, so the Foundation (and you!) can copy and distribute it
in the United States without permission and without paying copyright
royalties. Special rules, set forth in the General Terms of Use part of
this license, apply to copying and distributing Project Gutenberg™
electronic works to protect the PROJECT GUTENBERG™ concept
and trademark. Project Gutenberg is a registered trademark, and
may not be used if you charge for an eBook, except by following the
terms of the trademark license, including paying royalties for use of
the Project Gutenberg trademark. If you do not charge anything for
copies of this eBook, complying with the trademark license is very
easy. You may use this eBook for nearly any purpose such as
creation of derivative works, reports, performances and research.
Project Gutenberg eBooks may be modified and printed and given
away—you may do practically ANYTHING in the United States with
eBooks not protected by U.S. copyright law. Redistribution is subject
to the trademark license, especially commercial redistribution.

START: FULL LICENSE


THE FULL PROJECT GUTENBERG LICENSE
PLEASE READ THIS BEFORE YOU DISTRIBUTE OR USE THIS WORK

To protect the Project Gutenberg™ mission of promoting the free


distribution of electronic works, by using or distributing this work (or
any other work associated in any way with the phrase “Project
Gutenberg”), you agree to comply with all the terms of the Full
Project Gutenberg™ License available with this file or online at
www.gutenberg.org/license.

Section 1. General Terms of Use and


Redistributing Project Gutenberg™
electronic works
1.A. By reading or using any part of this Project Gutenberg™
electronic work, you indicate that you have read, understand, agree
to and accept all the terms of this license and intellectual property
(trademark/copyright) agreement. If you do not agree to abide by all
the terms of this agreement, you must cease using and return or
destroy all copies of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works in your
possession. If you paid a fee for obtaining a copy of or access to a
Project Gutenberg™ electronic work and you do not agree to be
bound by the terms of this agreement, you may obtain a refund from
the person or entity to whom you paid the fee as set forth in
paragraph 1.E.8.

1.B. “Project Gutenberg” is a registered trademark. It may only be


used on or associated in any way with an electronic work by people
who agree to be bound by the terms of this agreement. There are a
few things that you can do with most Project Gutenberg™ electronic
works even without complying with the full terms of this agreement.
See paragraph 1.C below. There are a lot of things you can do with
Project Gutenberg™ electronic works if you follow the terms of this
agreement and help preserve free future access to Project
Gutenberg™ electronic works. See paragraph 1.E below.
1.C. The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation (“the
Foundation” or PGLAF), owns a compilation copyright in the
collection of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works. Nearly all the
individual works in the collection are in the public domain in the
United States. If an individual work is unprotected by copyright law in
the United States and you are located in the United States, we do
not claim a right to prevent you from copying, distributing,
performing, displaying or creating derivative works based on the
work as long as all references to Project Gutenberg are removed. Of
course, we hope that you will support the Project Gutenberg™
mission of promoting free access to electronic works by freely
sharing Project Gutenberg™ works in compliance with the terms of
this agreement for keeping the Project Gutenberg™ name
associated with the work. You can easily comply with the terms of
this agreement by keeping this work in the same format with its
attached full Project Gutenberg™ License when you share it without
charge with others.

1.D. The copyright laws of the place where you are located also
govern what you can do with this work. Copyright laws in most
countries are in a constant state of change. If you are outside the
United States, check the laws of your country in addition to the terms
of this agreement before downloading, copying, displaying,
performing, distributing or creating derivative works based on this
work or any other Project Gutenberg™ work. The Foundation makes
no representations concerning the copyright status of any work in
any country other than the United States.

1.E. Unless you have removed all references to Project Gutenberg:

1.E.1. The following sentence, with active links to, or other


immediate access to, the full Project Gutenberg™ License must
appear prominently whenever any copy of a Project Gutenberg™
work (any work on which the phrase “Project Gutenberg” appears, or
with which the phrase “Project Gutenberg” is associated) is
accessed, displayed, performed, viewed, copied or distributed:
This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere in the United
States and most other parts of the world at no cost and with
almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away
or re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License
included with this eBook or online at www.gutenberg.org. If you
are not located in the United States, you will have to check the
laws of the country where you are located before using this
eBook.

1.E.2. If an individual Project Gutenberg™ electronic work is derived


from texts not protected by U.S. copyright law (does not contain a
notice indicating that it is posted with permission of the copyright
holder), the work can be copied and distributed to anyone in the
United States without paying any fees or charges. If you are
redistributing or providing access to a work with the phrase “Project
Gutenberg” associated with or appearing on the work, you must
comply either with the requirements of paragraphs 1.E.1 through
1.E.7 or obtain permission for the use of the work and the Project
Gutenberg™ trademark as set forth in paragraphs 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.

1.E.3. If an individual Project Gutenberg™ electronic work is posted


with the permission of the copyright holder, your use and distribution
must comply with both paragraphs 1.E.1 through 1.E.7 and any
additional terms imposed by the copyright holder. Additional terms
will be linked to the Project Gutenberg™ License for all works posted
with the permission of the copyright holder found at the beginning of
this work.

1.E.4. Do not unlink or detach or remove the full Project


Gutenberg™ License terms from this work, or any files containing a
part of this work or any other work associated with Project
Gutenberg™.

1.E.5. Do not copy, display, perform, distribute or redistribute this


electronic work, or any part of this electronic work, without
prominently displaying the sentence set forth in paragraph 1.E.1 with
active links or immediate access to the full terms of the Project
Gutenberg™ License.
1.E.6. You may convert to and distribute this work in any binary,
compressed, marked up, nonproprietary or proprietary form,
including any word processing or hypertext form. However, if you
provide access to or distribute copies of a Project Gutenberg™ work
in a format other than “Plain Vanilla ASCII” or other format used in
the official version posted on the official Project Gutenberg™ website
(www.gutenberg.org), you must, at no additional cost, fee or expense
to the user, provide a copy, a means of exporting a copy, or a means
of obtaining a copy upon request, of the work in its original “Plain
Vanilla ASCII” or other form. Any alternate format must include the
full Project Gutenberg™ License as specified in paragraph 1.E.1.

1.E.7. Do not charge a fee for access to, viewing, displaying,


performing, copying or distributing any Project Gutenberg™ works
unless you comply with paragraph 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.

1.E.8. You may charge a reasonable fee for copies of or providing


access to or distributing Project Gutenberg™ electronic works
provided that:

• You pay a royalty fee of 20% of the gross profits you derive from
the use of Project Gutenberg™ works calculated using the
method you already use to calculate your applicable taxes. The
fee is owed to the owner of the Project Gutenberg™ trademark,
but he has agreed to donate royalties under this paragraph to
the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation. Royalty
payments must be paid within 60 days following each date on
which you prepare (or are legally required to prepare) your
periodic tax returns. Royalty payments should be clearly marked
as such and sent to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation at the address specified in Section 4, “Information
about donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation.”

• You provide a full refund of any money paid by a user who


notifies you in writing (or by e-mail) within 30 days of receipt that
s/he does not agree to the terms of the full Project Gutenberg™
License. You must require such a user to return or destroy all
copies of the works possessed in a physical medium and
discontinue all use of and all access to other copies of Project
Gutenberg™ works.

• You provide, in accordance with paragraph 1.F.3, a full refund of


any money paid for a work or a replacement copy, if a defect in
the electronic work is discovered and reported to you within 90
days of receipt of the work.

• You comply with all other terms of this agreement for free
distribution of Project Gutenberg™ works.

1.E.9. If you wish to charge a fee or distribute a Project Gutenberg™


electronic work or group of works on different terms than are set
forth in this agreement, you must obtain permission in writing from
the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation, the manager of
the Project Gutenberg™ trademark. Contact the Foundation as set
forth in Section 3 below.

1.F.

1.F.1. Project Gutenberg volunteers and employees expend


considerable effort to identify, do copyright research on, transcribe
and proofread works not protected by U.S. copyright law in creating
the Project Gutenberg™ collection. Despite these efforts, Project
Gutenberg™ electronic works, and the medium on which they may
be stored, may contain “Defects,” such as, but not limited to,
incomplete, inaccurate or corrupt data, transcription errors, a
copyright or other intellectual property infringement, a defective or
damaged disk or other medium, a computer virus, or computer
codes that damage or cannot be read by your equipment.

1.F.2. LIMITED WARRANTY, DISCLAIMER OF DAMAGES - Except


for the “Right of Replacement or Refund” described in paragraph
1.F.3, the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation, the owner
of the Project Gutenberg™ trademark, and any other party
distributing a Project Gutenberg™ electronic work under this
agreement, disclaim all liability to you for damages, costs and
expenses, including legal fees. YOU AGREE THAT YOU HAVE NO
REMEDIES FOR NEGLIGENCE, STRICT LIABILITY, BREACH OF
WARRANTY OR BREACH OF CONTRACT EXCEPT THOSE
PROVIDED IN PARAGRAPH 1.F.3. YOU AGREE THAT THE
FOUNDATION, THE TRADEMARK OWNER, AND ANY
DISTRIBUTOR UNDER THIS AGREEMENT WILL NOT BE LIABLE
TO YOU FOR ACTUAL, DIRECT, INDIRECT, CONSEQUENTIAL,
PUNITIVE OR INCIDENTAL DAMAGES EVEN IF YOU GIVE
NOTICE OF THE POSSIBILITY OF SUCH DAMAGE.

1.F.3. LIMITED RIGHT OF REPLACEMENT OR REFUND - If you


discover a defect in this electronic work within 90 days of receiving it,
you can receive a refund of the money (if any) you paid for it by
sending a written explanation to the person you received the work
from. If you received the work on a physical medium, you must
return the medium with your written explanation. The person or entity
that provided you with the defective work may elect to provide a
replacement copy in lieu of a refund. If you received the work
electronically, the person or entity providing it to you may choose to
give you a second opportunity to receive the work electronically in
lieu of a refund. If the second copy is also defective, you may
demand a refund in writing without further opportunities to fix the
problem.

1.F.4. Except for the limited right of replacement or refund set forth in
paragraph 1.F.3, this work is provided to you ‘AS-IS’, WITH NO
OTHER WARRANTIES OF ANY KIND, EXPRESS OR IMPLIED,
INCLUDING BUT NOT LIMITED TO WARRANTIES OF
MERCHANTABILITY OR FITNESS FOR ANY PURPOSE.

1.F.5. Some states do not allow disclaimers of certain implied


warranties or the exclusion or limitation of certain types of damages.
If any disclaimer or limitation set forth in this agreement violates the
law of the state applicable to this agreement, the agreement shall be
interpreted to make the maximum disclaimer or limitation permitted
by the applicable state law. The invalidity or unenforceability of any
provision of this agreement shall not void the remaining provisions.
1.F.6. INDEMNITY - You agree to indemnify and hold the
Foundation, the trademark owner, any agent or employee of the
Foundation, anyone providing copies of Project Gutenberg™
electronic works in accordance with this agreement, and any
volunteers associated with the production, promotion and distribution
of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works, harmless from all liability,
costs and expenses, including legal fees, that arise directly or
indirectly from any of the following which you do or cause to occur:
(a) distribution of this or any Project Gutenberg™ work, (b)
alteration, modification, or additions or deletions to any Project
Gutenberg™ work, and (c) any Defect you cause.

Section 2. Information about the Mission of


Project Gutenberg™
Project Gutenberg™ is synonymous with the free distribution of
electronic works in formats readable by the widest variety of
computers including obsolete, old, middle-aged and new computers.
It exists because of the efforts of hundreds of volunteers and
donations from people in all walks of life.

Volunteers and financial support to provide volunteers with the


assistance they need are critical to reaching Project Gutenberg™’s
goals and ensuring that the Project Gutenberg™ collection will
remain freely available for generations to come. In 2001, the Project
Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation was created to provide a
secure and permanent future for Project Gutenberg™ and future
generations. To learn more about the Project Gutenberg Literary
Archive Foundation and how your efforts and donations can help,
see Sections 3 and 4 and the Foundation information page at
www.gutenberg.org.

Section 3. Information about the Project


Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation
The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation is a non-profit
501(c)(3) educational corporation organized under the laws of the
state of Mississippi and granted tax exempt status by the Internal
Revenue Service. The Foundation’s EIN or federal tax identification
number is 64-6221541. Contributions to the Project Gutenberg
Literary Archive Foundation are tax deductible to the full extent
permitted by U.S. federal laws and your state’s laws.

The Foundation’s business office is located at 809 North 1500 West,


Salt Lake City, UT 84116, (801) 596-1887. Email contact links and up
to date contact information can be found at the Foundation’s website
and official page at www.gutenberg.org/contact

Section 4. Information about Donations to


the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation
Project Gutenberg™ depends upon and cannot survive without
widespread public support and donations to carry out its mission of
increasing the number of public domain and licensed works that can
be freely distributed in machine-readable form accessible by the
widest array of equipment including outdated equipment. Many small
donations ($1 to $5,000) are particularly important to maintaining tax
exempt status with the IRS.

The Foundation is committed to complying with the laws regulating


charities and charitable donations in all 50 states of the United
States. Compliance requirements are not uniform and it takes a
considerable effort, much paperwork and many fees to meet and
keep up with these requirements. We do not solicit donations in
locations where we have not received written confirmation of
compliance. To SEND DONATIONS or determine the status of
compliance for any particular state visit www.gutenberg.org/donate.

While we cannot and do not solicit contributions from states where


we have not met the solicitation requirements, we know of no
prohibition against accepting unsolicited donations from donors in
such states who approach us with offers to donate.

International donations are gratefully accepted, but we cannot make


any statements concerning tax treatment of donations received from
outside the United States. U.S. laws alone swamp our small staff.

Please check the Project Gutenberg web pages for current donation
methods and addresses. Donations are accepted in a number of
other ways including checks, online payments and credit card
donations. To donate, please visit: www.gutenberg.org/donate.

Section 5. General Information About Project


Gutenberg™ electronic works
Professor Michael S. Hart was the originator of the Project
Gutenberg™ concept of a library of electronic works that could be
freely shared with anyone. For forty years, he produced and
distributed Project Gutenberg™ eBooks with only a loose network of
volunteer support.

Project Gutenberg™ eBooks are often created from several printed


editions, all of which are confirmed as not protected by copyright in
the U.S. unless a copyright notice is included. Thus, we do not
necessarily keep eBooks in compliance with any particular paper
edition.

Most people start at our website which has the main PG search
facility: www.gutenberg.org.

This website includes information about Project Gutenberg™,


including how to make donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary
Archive Foundation, how to help produce our new eBooks, and how
to subscribe to our email newsletter to hear about new eBooks.

You might also like